Schlick 1936 Meaning and Verification
Schlick 1936 Meaning and Verification
Schlick 1936 Meaning and Verification
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Philosophical Review, Duke University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The Philosophical Review
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
XLV
Number
268
THE
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
MEANING AND VERIFICATION
I
seems to be an especially strange paradox that the question concerning the meaning of a proposition should constitute a serious
philosophical difficulty. For is it not the-very nature and purpose
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
understanding of sentences.
The source of these difficulties is to be found in the fact that
familiar with all the words occurring in it. But this is not sufficient. It will not lead to confusion or error as long as we remain
in the domain of everyday life by which our words have been
formed and to which they are adapted, but it will become fatal
the moment we try to think about abstract problems by means of
the same terms without carefully fixing their signification for the
new purpose. For every word has a definite signification only
England!' I should not know how to fulfill his wish; his phrase
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The 'grammatical' rules will partly consist of ordinary definitions, i.e., explanations of words by means of other words, partly
of what are called 'ostensive' definitions, i.e., explanations by
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
'because', 'immediate', 'chance', 'again', etc. In these cases we require the presence of certain complex situations, and the meaning
situations.
It is clear that in order to understand a verbal definition we must
know the signification of the explaining words beforehand, and
that the only explanation which can work without any previous
knowledge is the ostensive definition. We conclude that there is no
science. There has- never been any other way, and it would be a
grave error to suppose that we believe we have discovered a new
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
and being of the opinion that it really does not impose any re-
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
In the first place I should like to point out that when we say
that "a proposition has meaning only if it is verifiable" we are
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
be meaningful and true. You will observe that even then the
conclusion does not follow. For the first premiss assures us that
the issue has meaning if it can be verified; the verification does
not have to take place, and therefore it is quite irrelevant whether
it can take place in the future or in the present only. Apart from
this, the second premiss is, of course, nonsensical; for what fact
could possibly be described by the sentence 'verification can take
say that I can hear or feel bored only in the present moment?
And what could I mean by this? The particular nonsense involved
in such phrases will become clearer when we speak of the 'ego-
'verifiable here now'; much less does it mean 'being verified now'.
Perhaps it will be thought that the only way of making sure of
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
the verifiability of a proposition would consist in its actual verification. But we shall soon see that this is not the case.
future events did not really refer to the future at all but asserted
only the present existence of certain expectations (and, similarly,
speaking about the past would really mean speaking about present
memories). But it is certain that the author of that book does
not hold such a view now, and that it cannot be regarded as a
Thus I think that everybody-including the Consistent Empiricist-agrees that it would be nonsense to say, 'We can mean
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
this distinction does not entirely coincide with the one we have
been insisting upon just now.
* * *
ITI
contradict the laws of nature. This is, I think, the largest sense
in which we may speak of empirical possibility; we do not restrict
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
which the verification is carried out or prevented from being carried out. Many of those who refuse to accept our criterion of
meaning seem to imagine that the procedure of its application in
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
examples. The sentences, 'My friend died the day after tomorrow';
'The lady wore a dark red dress which was bright green'; 'The
campanile is i00 feet and I50 feet high'; 'The child was naked,
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
When we hear the words, 'A tower which is both ioo feet and
I50 feet high', the image of two towers of different heights may
The height of a tower cannot be i00 feet and i50 feet at the
same time; a child cannot be naked and dressed at the same timenot because we are unable to imagine it, but because our definitions
means that the rules of our language have not provided any use
for such combinations; they do not describe any fact. We could
may not imagine, if the word 'naked' (or 'red') occurs in its
description we have decided that the word 'dressed' (or 'green')
cannot be put in its place in the same description. If we do not
follow this rule it means that we want to introduce a new definition of the words, or that we don't mind using words without
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
accordance with the rules by which its terms are defined. The
only case in which verification is (logically) impossible is the
case where you have made it impossible by not setting any rules
for its verification. Grammatical rules are not found anywhere in
nature, but are made by man and are, in principle, arbitrary; so
is confined, there may be reason to lament our fate and the weakness of our physical and mental powers, but the problem could
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
"empirical-meaning requirement", and on the other hand we assert most emphatically that meaning and verifiability do not depend
on any empirical conditions whatever, but are determined by purely
logical possibilities. The opponent will object: if meaning is a
In reality there is no contradiction or difficulty. The word 'experience' is ambiguous. Firstly, it may be a name for any so-called
'immediate data'-which is a comparatively modern use of the
perience in the first sense of the word. No rule of expression presupposes any law or regularity in the world (which is the con-
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
form, 'this place is filled with matter', shall be called true or false.
The concept 'physical substance at a certain place' is defined by
our language in physics and geometry. Geometry itself is the grammar of our propositions about 'spatial' relations, and it is not very
difficult to see how assertions about physical properties and spatial
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
should say in general that verifiability of an assertion implies possibility of 'imagining' the asserted fact, this would be true only in a
restricted sense. It would not be true in so far as the possibility
is of the empirical kind, i.e., implying specific human capacities.
I do not think, for instance, that we can be accused of talking
logical grammar of the word 'to imagine'; these few remarks may
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
see that these two things have nothing in common. At this moment
I am trying in vain to imagine the shape of a capital G in German
fessor Lewis when he says about this hypothesis: "Our understanding of what would verify it has no lack of clarity." In
fact, I can easily imagine e.g. witnessing the funeral of my own
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
at all, that space must be defined in such a way that the impossibility of reaching it or of perceiving anything in it would
be merely empirical, so that some means of overcoming the difficulties could at least be described, although it might be beyond
human power to put them into use.
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
seems to be evident from the fact that Carnap, in his Der logische
Aufbau der Welt, states that the method of this book may be called
"methodological solipsism". Professor Lewis thinks, rightly, that
the egocentric or solipsistic principle is not implied by our general
principle of verifiability, and so he regards it as a second principle
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
experience is absolutely neutral or, as Wittgenstein has occasionally put it, that immediate data "have no owner". Since the
genuine positivist denies (with Mach etc.) that original experience
"has that quality or status, characteristic of all given experience,
the most important steps which philosophy must take towards the
clarification of its deepest problems.
empiricism.
How does the idealist or the solipsist arrive at the statement
that the world, as far as I know it, is 'my own idea', that ultimately
I know nothing but the 'content of my own consciousness'?
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The fact that all data are dependent upon 'my' body (particularly
those parts of it which are called 'sense-organs') induces us to
object which is perceived. Originally the perceiver is the senseorgan or the body to which it belongs, but since the body itselfincluding the nervous system-is also one of the perceived things,
the original view is soon 'corrected' by substituting for the per-
ceiver a new subject, which is called 'ego' or 'mind' or 'consciousness'. It is usually thought of as somehow residing in the body,
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
human bodies (or perhaps only one of them) as well as upon the
body M.
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
You will perhaps call my attention to the fact that the circumstances we have been describing are fictitious, that they do
not occur in our real world, so that in this world, unfortunately,
The idealist or solipsist who says, 'I can feel only my own pain',
or, more generally, 'I can be aware only of the data of my own
consciousness', believes that he is uttering a necessary, self-evident
truth which no possible experience can force him to sacrifice. He
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
described for our fictitious world; but, he will say, even if I feel
pain every time when another body 0 is hurt, I shall never say, 'I
fluous word which may just as well be omitted. 'I feel pain' and 'I
feel my pain' are, according to the solipsist's definition, to have
identical meaning; the word 'my', therefore, has no function in the
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The words 'I' and 'my', if we use them according to the solipsist's prescription, are absolutely empty, mere adornments of
speech. There would be no difference of meaning between the three
expressions, 'I feel my pain'; 'I feel pain'; and 'there is pain'.
Lichtenberg, the wonderful eighteenth-century physicist and philosopher, declared that Descartes had no right to start his philo-
sophy with the proposition 'I think', instead of saying 'it thinks'.
Just as there would be no sense in speaking of a white horse unless
it were logically possible that a horse might not be white, so no
sentence containing the words 'I' or 'my' would be meaningful unless we could replace them by 'he' or 'his' without speaking non-
verbally different formulations of this description. It is of fundamental importance to see that R and S are not two propositions,
but one and the same proposition in two different languages. The
solipsist, by rejecting the language of R and insisting upon the
language of S, has adopted a terminology which makes Q tautological, transforms it into T. Thus he has made it impossible to
verify or falsify his own statements; he himself has deprived them
of meaning. By refusing to avail himself of the opportunities
(which we showed him) to make the statement 'I can feel somebody else's pain' meaningful, he has at the same time lost the
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
body' any body in which I can feel pain. In our actual world these
two definitions apply to one and the same body, but that is' an
empirical fact which might be different. If the two definitions did
not coincide and if we adopted the second one we should need a
new word to distinguish the body M from other bodies in which
the owned object is empirical, not logical ('external', not 'internal'). Thus one could say 'Body M is the owner of this pain', or
'that pain is owned by the bodies M and 0'. The second proposition
can, perhaps, never be truthfully asserted in our actual world
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Thus we see that unless we choose to call our body the owner
or bearer of the data-which seems to be a rather misleading
perience' will either mean the simple empirical fact that all data
are in certain respects dependent on the state of the nervous system
of my body M, or it will be meaningless. Before this physiological
fact is discovered, experience is not 'my' experience at all, it is
sion of the same fact, and has meaning only if it refers to the
body. The concept of 'ego' is a construction put upon the same
fact, and we could easily imagine a world in which this concept
would not have been formed, where there would be no idea of an
After our last remarks it will be easy to deal with the so-called
problem concerning the existence of the external world. If, with
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
existence of living beings is no necessary condition for the existence of the rest of the world.
being?', and this question is answered in the negative by experience. The mistake of the solipsist or idealist consists in rejecting
the phrase 'if all living beings disappeared from the universe' for
the phrase 'if all minds disappeared from the universe'. I hope it
will not be thought that I have changed the meaning of the issue
by this substitution. I have avoided the word 'mind' because I take
it to signify the same as the words 'ego' or 'consciousness', which
empirical definition one may choose to give for 'mind'. I need only
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
verse without plants and animals and human bodies (including the
body M), and without the mental phenomena just referred to: it
would certainly be a 'world without minds' (for what else could
deserve this name?), but the laws of nature might be exactly the
the world, as the man in the street sees it, is perfectly correct; and
that the solution of the great philosophical issues consists in returning to this original world-view, after having shown that the
MORITZ SCHLICK
THE UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA
This content downloaded from 137.158.158.60 on Fri, 22 Jul 2016 11:04:08 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms