Kleinhaus - Leo Strauss On Thucydides

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 28

Piety, Universality, and History:

Leo Strauss on Thucydides


Emil A. Kleinhaus
Yale Law School

Having compiled his history of the Peloponnesian War before the


change in thought that was effected by Socrates occurred, Thucydides occupies no obvious place in Leo Strausss unique exposition of the history of political ideas.1 Nevertheless, Strauss made
three substantial statements about Thucydides. The first statement, a published lecture, predictably demotes Thucydides to the
subordinate status of a pre-Socratic.2 But Strausss more substantial statement on Thucydides, the concluding essay of The City and
Man, questions the lecture and indicates that Plato and Thucydides may supplement one another.3 The essay ultimately concludes not only that Thucydides work is compatible with Platos
and Aristotles but that the quest for the common sense understanding of political things which led us first to Aristotles Politics
leads us eventually to Thucydides War of the Peloponnesians and
the Athenians.4 Strauss, subverting the conventional pecking order, thus painted Thucydides not as a mere predecessor to Plato
1
There is only one oblique reference to Thucydides in Strausss early work
Natural Right and History. (Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1954], 120.)
2
Leo Strauss, The Rebirth of Classical Political Rationalism, Thucydides: The
Meaning of Political Philosophy, Thomas Pangle, ed. (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1989), 72.
3
Leo Strauss, The City and Man (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964),
140.
4
Ibid., 240.

68 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

and Aristotle but as a political philosopher in his own right whose


History marked the culmination rather than the origin of classical
political thought. In light of this judgment, it is not surprising that
Strausss last published essay, Preliminary Observations on the
Gods in Thucydides Work, consisted of an enigmatic piece
meant simply to modify some observations in the Thucydideschapter of The City and Man.5
Strausss mounting appreciation for Thucydides rested on his
conviction that Thucydides addressed two fundamental problems:
the problem of Athens and Jerusalem and the problem of history.
Strauss himself is often painted as unfriendly to religion and unambiguously hostile to a historical view of philosophy. But a close
reading of Strausss writings on Thucydides severely complicates
this picture. To reach this conclusion, a good deal of work is
needed. In regard to Athens and Jerusalem, Strausss statements
appear contradictory on their face. In his lecture Strauss emphasized the antagonism between Athens and Jerusalem and concluded that political history is of Greek, not of Hebrew, origin.6
But Strauss enigmatically ended his long essay on the Greek historian as follows: only by beginning at this point will we be open
to the full impact of the all-important question which is coeval
with philosophy although the philosophers do not frequently pronounce itthe question quid sit deus. Strauss is somewhat more
explicit though still maddeningly vague about Thucydides relevance to the problem of history. Strauss looks back to Thucydides
to find a pre-modern historical approach that can help navigate
around the problems that the new history, or historicism, has created. According to Strauss, since history has become a problem
for us, we must try to understand what is the precise character
of that Greek wisdom which issues in political history.7
By explicating Strausss original though imperfect reading of
Thucydides, according to which the History should be read as a
paean to the radically distinct forms of moderation that manifested themselves in Athens and Sparta, the essay will show how

5
Leo Strauss, Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy, Preliminary Observations on the Gods in Thucydides Work, Thomas Pangle, ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983), 89.
6
Strauss Thucydides, 73.
7
Ibid., 74.

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 69

Strausss
reputed
hostility to
historical view
of philosophy
overblown.

Strauss brought Thucydides into a larger discourse about both history and religion. In doing so it will attempt to reconcile the lecture and the essay while also incorporating into the analysis the
article on the gods in Thucydides. The essay will suggest that
Strausss reading of Thucydides fits neatly into the City and Man,
which unveils a uniform classical tradition of political philosophy
at the heart of which is a sober recognition of the limits of politics
and at the height of which is Thucydides. This Thucydides-centered interpretation of the City and Man, moreover, undermines
Strausss image as an uncompromising natural rights advocate.
Using the startling Preface to the City and Man as a guidepost, the
essay will hypothesize instead that, following Plato, Strauss conscientiously employed political speech to advance principles he
considered prudent, principles such as the power of ideas in the
political arena and the existence of just gods. At the same time,
however, following Thucydides, Strauss conveyed deep-seated
skepticism of the power of ideas in the political arena as well as
the existence of the gods outside of the political arena.
The Philosophic Historian
Thucydides project, according to Strauss, only resembled the
Thucydides
modern historians project. While Thucydides may have subjected
history dealt
his report to the most severe and detailed test possible, he also
with universal
inserts speeches, composed by him, into his narrative, which
truths.
say what was demanded of them.8 Moreover, contrary to the
modern historian, whose goal is to give an accurate answer to a
particular historical question, Thucydides conceived of his work
as a possession for all time.9 In Strausss view, Thucydides therefore cannot be understood as a historian alone, because his history does not deal only with particulars. Aristotle claimed that
poetry is more philosophic and more serious than history, for poetry states the universals.10 But Strausss Thucydides was a different type of historian. Since the Peloponnesian War, Thucydides
subject, was so great, it could be, in Thucydides judgment, the
source of universal truths.11
Strausss agreement with the generally held view that
8

Thucydides, I.22; Strauss, City and Man, 142.


Thucydides, I.22.
10
Aristotle, Poetics 1451a36-b11.
11
Strauss, City and Man, 155.
9

70 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

Thucydides was both a historian and a political philosopher is at


the core of his understanding of Thucydides. Strauss makes a
striking comparison between Thucydides and Plato: Plato too can
be said to have discovered in a singular eventin the singular life
of Socratesthe universal and thus to have become able to present
the universal through presenting the particular.12 The comparison, however, goes further. In regard to Platos Republic, Strauss
argues that one cannot separate the understanding of Platos
teaching from an understanding of the form in which it is presented.13 Platos position for Strauss lies between the lines of the
narrative because the narrative is a drama. Following Hobbes,
who asserted that in a good history the narrative doth secretly
instruct the reader, and more effectually than can ever be done by
precept, Strauss thus argues that Thucydides own world-view,
which is necessarily separate from the specific views articulated
in the political speeches, can be extracted by the careful reader.14
Power politics, therefore, despite its clear importance in the
speeches, is only one aspect of Thucydides vision, while what
one may call human or the humane constitutes an equally important aspect.15 The relation between these two forces, however,
can only be divined once one understands Thucydides independent teaching. In order to tease out that teaching, Strauss starts by
analyzing Thucydides stated opinions.
Strausss approach first leads to the conclusion that Thucydides
admired Sparta. In the archeology, Thucydides observed that
Sparta at a very early period obtained good laws, and enjoyed a
freedom from tyrants which was unbroken; it has possessed the
same form of government for more than four hundred years.16
Thucydides was enamored of Spartas moderation. In his praise
for Chios, Thucydides stated that, after the Spartans, the Chians
are the only people that I have known who knew how to be wise

12

Ibid., 143.
Strauss, Thucydides, 52.
14
Strauss, City and Man, 144. On this basis Strauss elsewhere dismisses
Webers reading of Thucydides according to which the Athenian envoys at Melos
simply state Thucydides view. According to Strauss, Weber did not pause to
wonder how Thucydides himself conceived of the dialogue. Strauss, Natural
Right and History, 58.
15
Strauss, City and Man, 144.
16
Thucydides, I.18.
13

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 71

Universal
presented
through the
particular.

in prosperity.17 Spartan moderation, according to Strausss reading, is inseparable from Spartan piety. The Spartans even stopped
military campaigns because of bad sacrifices.18 During the civil
war at Corcyra, which represented the height of immoderation for
Thucydides, religion was in honor with neither party, and it is
obvious to Strauss that Thucydides disapproves of breaches of
the divine law.19 Such breaches go hand in hand with civic decline, as is evidenced by the plague in Athens, when burial rights
were entirely upset and fear of gods or law of man there was
none.20
Staying with the explicit judgment approach, Strauss points to
perhaps the most enigmatic comment in the History, namely
Thucydides eulogy for Nicias: This or the like was the cause of
the death of a man who, of all the Hellenes in my time, least deserved such a fate, seeing that the whole course of his life had
been regulated with strict attention to virtue. 21 At this point,
Strauss accepts Thucydides at his word and concludes that, for
Thucydides, the connection between dedication, guided by law
and surely also by divine law, to virtue, between desert and fate,
points to the rule of just gods.22 Once Strauss attributes this view
to Thucydides, he can draw far-reaching conclusions about other
passages in the History. He can assert confidently that a tacit but
unmistakable connection exists between Pericles funeral oration,
which, though pronounced in obedience to a law, opens with a
blame of that very law, and the plague that ravaged Athens.23 Although Pericles is praised highly by Thucydides, that is only because Pericles saved democracy from itself.24 In fact, Thucydides
explicitly denied that Pericles regime was the best that Athens
could achieve when he praised the rule of the 5000 during the
twenty-first year of the war.25 Strauss argues further that a connection exists between the immoderate and impious Athenian position at Melos and the disastrous Sicilian Expedition. For
17

Ibid., VIII.24.
Ibid., V.55, V.116.
19
Strauss, The Gods, 96.
20
Thucydides, II.52-3.
21
Ibid., VII.86.
22
Strauss, City and Man, 150.
23
Ibid., 152.
24
Ibid., 153.
25
Thucydides, VIII.97.
18

72 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

Strausss first Thucydides, a sound regime is a moderate regime


dedicated to moderation.26 But that is not all. Piety demands that
the city must transcend itself. 27 That, according to Strauss,
would seem to be the most comprehensive instruction which
Thucydides silently conveys, the silent character of the conveyance being required by the chaste character of his piety.28 If this
is the case, the reason for Thucydides neglect of economic and
cultural matters is clearthat they were irrelevant to a pious man.
Strausss preliminary judgment is that, because of his devotion to
piety and moderation, Thucydides favored Sparta over Athens.
But Strauss backs away from that preliminary conclusion, because the very first explicit judgments in Thucydides narrative
contradict it. Thucydides declares that the Peloponnesian War was
the greatest movement and expresses his conviction regarding
the weakness of ancient times.29 These premises are essential for
his claim that it was the war, war writ large, a war which will
enable one to understand not only all past and future wars but
the past and future things simply.30 Strauss explores two dichotomies in the History: motion versus rest and Greekness versus barbarism. According to Strauss, Thucydides views the Peloponnesian War as the motion that succeeds the greatest rest and thus
the peak of Greekness. In studying that war, one sees the Greeks
at their peak in motion; one begins to see the descent. The peak of
Greekness is the peak of humanity.31
Strauss develops this point at great length because it is irreconcilable with a black-and-white preference for the Spartan manner. In fact, it is no different from the view of the Athenian statesman Pericles. In the funeral oration, Pericles proclaims that, if our
remote ancestors deserve praise, much more do our fathers. 32
Pericles goes on to praise his own generation in the highest terms.
Thucydides shared Pericles view, and therefore his praise of the
Spartans veneration for their ancestors, which is a key part of
their moderate temperament, must, according to Strauss, be recon26

Strauss, City and Man, 153.


Ibid.
28
Ibid.
29
Thucydides, I.1, I.3.
30
Strauss, City and Man, 155-6.
31
Ibid., I.57.
32
Thucydides, II.36.
27

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 73

Thucydides
surface
teaching
contradictory.

sidered. Thucydides had disdain for the most ancient antiquity.


As such, Thucydides argument in favor of Sparta, of moderation, of the divine lawimportant as it isis only part of his
teaching.33 Strausss explicit-judgment approach fails to yield a
conclusion because Thucydides surface teaching is contradictory.
In the first sections of his essay, Strauss does not deal with
Thucydides explicit comments about the gods. Yet these comments only strengthen Strausss argument against reading Thucydides as a knee-jerk supporter of Sparta. Thucydides, as we know,
admired the Spartans piety. Yet he himself proves remarkably impious. Regarding a dispute about the meaning of an oracle foretelling the plague, Thucydides asserted that the people made
their recollection fit in with their suffering. 34 Thucydides dismissed the Athenians faith in oracles flippantly: with this oracle
events were supposed to tally.35 Thucydides also dismissed the
Spartan demand that the Athenians cleanse themselves from the
pollution of Cylon as a pretext, as if no one else could have held
pious views because he did not. Strauss writes: The Spartan demand is no doubt ridiculous in the eyes of Thucydides.36 Thucydides did not share the piety of a Spartan even though he respected Sparta.
The Speeches: Right versus Compulsion
Since Thucydides explicit judgments do not convey a complete
or consistent argument, Strauss pushes his analysis further. The
speeches in Thucydides History offer many judgments. Yet the
speeches, according to Strauss, must be taken at least somewhat
seriously as historical documents. There is endless scholarly debate about the historicity of the speeches, most of which revolves
around Thucydides I.22.1.37 At least at the outset, Strauss adopts a
33

Ibid.
Thucydides, II.54.
35
Ibid.
36
Strauss, City and Man, 180.
37
According to the Crawley translation, I.22.1 reads as follows: With reference to the speeches in this history, some were delivered before the war began,
others while it was going on; some I heard myself, others I got from various quarters; it was in all cases difficult to carry them word for word in ones memory, so
my habit has been to make the speakers say what was in my opinion demanded
of them by the various occasions, of course adhering as closely as possible to the
general sense of what was really said.
Emphasizing Thucydides vague qualification, Werner Jaeger describes the
34

74 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

relatively trusting position, asserting that Thucydides decided to


write the speeches himself, keeping as close as possible to the gist
of what the speakers had said.38 Yet the wording of the speeches
is Thucydides own work.39 The speeches, in Strausss judgment,
are a particularly useful tool because they precede and succeed
actions, and can therefore be measured based on their accuracy
concerning previous deeds and their insight about future deeds.
By quoting the speeches, moreover, Thucydides established a clear
separation between his speech and the political speeches. By integrating the political speeches into the true and comprehensive
speech, Strauss contends, he makes visible the fundamental difference between the political speech and the true speech.40 The
speeches represent definite points of view that were appropriate
to political situations. Thucydides speech, on the other hand, was,
in Strausss view, impartial and comprehensive.
Strauss thus identified an approach to understanding Thucydides that goes beyond just studying his explicit judgments. The
speeches and the explicit judgments must be viewed together.
Strauss begins to implement his new approach by pointing to the
relationship between the very first speeches in the History. The
first speech, given by the Corcyreans in the hope of convincing the
Athenians to intervene in Epidamnus on their behalf, begins with
the word justice. The opposing speech, given by the Corinthians
in the hope of dissuading the Athenians from supporting Corcyra,
begins with the word necessity. According to Strauss, these two
opening words indicate the point of view from which Thucydides
looks at the Peloponnesian War.41
So what is the relationship between compulsion and right for
Thucydides? Strauss turns to Thucydides famous judgment that
the growth of the power of Athens, and the alarm which this inspeeches as the medium through which Thucydides expresses his political
ideas. (Werner Jaeger, Paideia: The Ideals of Greek Culture, trans. Glibert Highet,
vol.2 [Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1954], 391.) Donald Kagan, on the other hand,
stressing the second part of Thucydides I.22.1, concludes that we are obliged to
accept the essential authenticity of the speeches reported. (Donald Kagan, The
Speeches in Thucydides and the Mytilene Debate, Yale Classical Studies vol. 24
[Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975], 78.).
38
Strauss, City and Man, 164.
39
Ibid., 174.
40
Ibid., 166.
41
Ibid., 174.

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 75

Points of view
juxtaposed
against
comprehensive
judgments.

spired in Sparta, made war inevitable.42 The Athenians, in other


words, compelled the Spartans to fight. Were the Spartans compelled to violate right, however? To answer this question Strauss
must isolate Thucydides judgment of who broke the Thirty Years
Peace. At first glance, it seems clear that Athens did, because the
oracle promises support for the Spartan cause. But Thucydides
was not a believer in oracles, and, moreover, even the Spartans
themselves soon doubted the oracle, fearing that she had been
bribed. When they appeal to Athens to make peace after the disaster at Pylos, the Spartans admit that no one knows who broke
the peace. Thucydides then states unambiguously that the war began with the Spartan invasion of Attica. Finally, the Spartans
themselves come to believe that they had originally broken the
treaty, both on account of the attack of the Thebans on Plataea in
time of peace, and also of their refusal to listen to the Athenian
offer of arbitration . . . for this reason they thought they deserved
their misfortunes.43 Despite their initial confidence, the Spartans
for Strausss Thucydides were thus compelled to violate right.
No discussion of necessity in Thucydides would be complete,
however, without a consideration of what Strauss first called the
Athenian thesis.44 That thesis states that the powerful by necessity expand their empire to the farthest extent possible. In the
words of the Athenians, the strong by a necessary law of their
nature rule wherever they can.45 The thesis is stated in different
forms throughout the History, and it is unclear how Thucydides
judges that thesis. According to Strauss, however, the issue is decided in the dialogue between the Athenians and the Melians.46
The unparalleled significance that Strauss attaches to the Melian
Dialogue is obvious because Strauss paraphrases the dialogue in
its entirety. For Strauss, Thucydides conveys an implicit judgment
in the dialogue against the Melians: There is no debate in Thucydides work in which the Spartan or the Melian view defeats the
Athenian view.47 Even the Spartans will favor political expedience over right when necessary, as evidenced by their behavior at
42

Thucydides, I.23.
Ibid., VII.18.
44
Strauss, City and Man, 183.
45
Thucydides, V.104.
46
Strauss, City and Man, 184.
47
Ibid.
43

76 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

Plataea. Why then are the Spartans moderate? Strauss answers


that for Thucydides the Athenian thesis is not refuted by the facts
of Spartan moderation.Sparta was moderate because she had
grave troubles with her Helots.48 Strausss Thucydides thus reveals an unmistakably Athenian world-view even if he disapproves of Athens.
The Melian Dialogue and the Sicilian Expedition
If Thucydides does not share the Melian view of the gods,
which is that the gods reward the just and punish the unjust, what
is the connection between the Melian Dialogue and the Sicilian Expedition? Much has been made of that relationship, because the
juxtaposition of the dialogue, which shows Athens at the height
of her power, and the expedition, which ends with the Athenian
general Nicias virtually repeating the Melian view, is clearly deliberate.49 Strauss insists that the connection between the dialogue
and the expedition must be seen in light of Thucydides explicit
explanation of the expeditions failurethe emancipation of private interest in post-Periclean Athens.50 Yet the dialogue is about
public interest of the most extreme kind, namely the desire for empire. In fact, it mirrors Pericles last speech, in which he admits
that the empire is a tyranny while defending the empire on the
basis of the glory of the future.51 Strauss must somehow link
Thucydides judgment about private interest ruining the Sicilian
Expedition with the fiercely public-minded strain of thought that
runs through Pericles last speech and the dialogue. He argues:
Those who contend that there is a connection between the
Melian Dialogue and the Sicilian disaster must have in mind a
connection between the two events which Thucydides intimates
rather than sets forth explicitly by speaking of the emancipation
of private interest in post-Periclean Athens. The Melian Dialogue
shows nothing of such an emancipation. But it contains the most
unabashed denial occurring in Thucydides work of a divine law
which must be respected by the city or which moderates the citys
desire for having more. The Athenians on Melos, in contradis48

Ibid., 192.
For a discussion of various interpretations of the relation between the dialogue and the expedition, see Antony Andrewes, The Melian Dialogue and
Pericles Last Speech, Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society 6 [1960].
50
Strauss, City and Man, 193.
51
Thucydides, II.64.
49

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 77

tinction to Callicles or Thrasymachus, limit themselves indeed to


asserting the natural right of the stronger with regard to the cities; but are Callicles and Thrasymachus not more consistent than
they? Can one encourage, as even Pericles and precisely Pericles
does, the citys desire for having more than other cities without in the long run encouraging the individuals desire for having more than his fellow citizens?52
Tyranny in
public sphere
influences
private
behavior.

Strauss has thus established a direct relationship between the arguments presented by the envoys to Melos and the Athenian failure at Sicily and even the eventual civil war. As Clifford Orwin
puts it, the introduction of the Athenian thesis into domestic affairs proves disastrous.53 The justification for tyranny cannot be
bracketed and applied only in the public sphere, according to
Strauss, and the Athenians at Melos defend tyranny in strong language. During the Archidamian War, Pericles was able to subvert
Athenian democracy and maintain order, but after Pericles death,
the position articulated in the dialogue leads inevitably to the domestic strife that undermines the expedition. The Athenian thesis as expressed at Melos is self-mutilating.
But Strausss Thucydides cannot simply embrace Spartan moderation as the alternative to Athenian daring, because he shares
the Athenian view that fear compels cities to exert their power,
and he shows us that Spartan moderation itself is the result of
compulsion. Moreover, Thucydides mocks Spartan piety. Does that
mean that the self-defeating character of the Athenian thesis must
simply be endured? Strauss responds to this problem by exposing
a second connection between the Dialogue and the Expedition
through an analysis of the statesman Nicias, the the Athenian
who came closest to holding the Spartan or Melian view. 54
Thucydides, according to Strauss, exhibits the connection between
Nicias and the Spartans by describing many of Niciass deeds before recounting a single speech. Nicias, like his Spartan counterparts, lacked the ingenuity of Athenians like Cleon and Alcibiades,
and when he did speak, he favored a moderate policy aimed at
restoring peace with Sparta. Like a Spartan, Nicias cannot persuade his audience with words, and is ultimately left in sole command of the expedition he opposed. As the tide turns against Ath52

Strauss, City and Man, 193.


Clifford Orwin, The Humanity of Thucydides (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), 195
54
Strauss, City and Man, 200.
53

78 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

ens, Nicias begins to resemble the Melian opponents of Athens:


He is hopeful for the future because he has led a virtuous life.55
He tells his soldiers that if any of the gods was offended at our
expedition, we have already been amply punished, thus directly
contradicting the theology expressed by the Athenian envoys at
Melos. Nicias is tortured to death and his army is treated like animals by the vengeful Syracusans. Melian faith leads to disaster for
Nicias and Athens.
Why then does Thucydides call Nicias a man who, of all the
Hellenes of my time, least deserved such a fate, seeing that the
whole course of his life had been regulated with strict attention to
virtue?56 Strauss explains this notoriously tricky passage as follows:
Thucydides judgment on Nicias is imprecise, as precise as his
judgment on the Spartans according to which the Spartans above
all others succeeded in being moderate while prospering: both
judgments are made from the point of view of those on whom he
passes judgment. They are precise by being incomplete. His judgment of the Spartans does not reveal the cause of Spartan moderation and hence its true character. His judgment on Nicias does
not reveal the true character of the connection between the fate of
men and their morality. Nicias like the Spartans believed that the
fate of men or cities corresponds to their justice and piety, to the
practice of virtue as understood by old established custom. But
this correspondence rests entirely on hope, on unfounded or vain
hope.57

Strauss thus contends that Thucydides judgment of Nicias is the


judgment of the man who is being judged, and when it is taken in
context, it is hopelessly incomplete. Nicias perishes because he has
hope in gods that will not help him. Therefore, the view set forth
by the Athenians on Melos is true.58 The link between the Melian
view and Niciass view is the basis for a second connection between the dialogue and the expeditionnot indeed the gods, but
the human concern with the gods without which there cannot be
a free city, took terrible revenge on the Athenians.59 The Melian
thesis, as such, which is repeated by the Athenian Nicias, is as selfdestructive as the Athenian thesis. The human concern with the
55

Ibid., 207.
Thucydides., VII.86.
57
Strauss, City and Man, 208-9.
58
Ibid., 209.
59
Ibid.
56

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 79

divine in Athens, which manifested itself most strongly after the


Athens and
affair of the hermae, led the Athenians to choose the pious leader
Sparta at their Nicias to lead a campaign that only the impious Alcibiades could
extremes both
win. Men with blind faith chose a leader with blind faith who led
flawed.

the Athenians to become Melians. Ultimately, the two connections


between the Melian Dialogue and the Sicilian Expedition succeed
in undermining both the Athenian view and the Melian view as
they are expressed in the Dialogue. Strauss has reached the same
conclusion that he reached on the basis of explicit judgments
aloneAthens and Sparta at their extremes are both flawed. Yet
as we will see, while the first method yields only a contradiction,
the new approach will yield a specific conclusion.
Before proceeding with Strausss argument, it is worth pointing out a weakness in his method. Without the argument that
Thucydides adopts various perspectives to convey the thoughts of
actors, Strauss cannot reach the definite conclusions he does about
Thucydides. His argument about the eulogy is therefore of great
pragmatic value, but it is difficult to maintain consistently.
Thucydides eulogy for Nicias does require an explanation, since
it differs drastically from Thucydides other judgments about piety; nevertheless, how can Strauss choose which comments reflect
Thucydides true beliefs and which comments reflect the beliefs
of his characters? In most cases, Strauss takes Thucydides explicit
judgments, such as his judgment concerning the weakness of the
ancients, at face value. The method by which he chooses exceptions is highly selective, and it is based exclusively on the principle that Thucydides, like the Hebrew bible in the minds of rabbis, cannot ultimately contradict himself. Other scholars have
addressed the contradictions by raising the Thukydidesfrage, or
the question of composition. Thucydides scholars have devoted
themselves to judging when Thucydides wrote each section of the
History and explaining vastly different conclusions on that basis.
Clifford Orwin dismisses these scholars by noting that there was
never any consensus as to which passages to assign to each epoch. Following R. W. Connor as well as Strauss, Orwin contends
that these supposed blemishes are aspects of the works perfection.60 Strauss himself does not comment on the composition
question as a whole. In his last essay, however, Strauss does com60

Orwin, Humanity, 6.

80 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

ment on the contention that the peculiarity of Book VIII is due to


its incompleteness.61 Strauss answers: This is no more than a Strausss
plausible hypothesis. The peculiarity of Book VIII must be under- method partly
based on hope.
stood in the light of the peculiarity or peculiarities of the bulk of
62
the work. Strauss at least admits that the composition question
should be taken seriously, and that his own approach can be challenged with a plausible hypothesis. In some sense, Strauss, in
marked contrast to Thucydides own approach, chooses to understand the low in light of the high63 as he reads Thucydides, for he
refuses to believe that circumstance or chance determined what
Thucydides wrote. The argument of Strausss essay depends on
the assumption that the Thukydidesfrage can be ignored because all inconsistencies in Thucydides result from the historians
artistry. Strausss reinterpretations of explicit statements are certainly ingenious, but we should note that they are based on an interpretive choice that is partly made on the basis of hope.
The Nobility of Athens and Sparta
The Sicilian Expedition exposes the bankruptcy of both the
Athenian and the Melian world-views. Power cannot save the city
from itself and piety cannot save the city from its enemies. Does
Thucydides, then, disapprove of both Athens and Sparta? Strauss
acknowledges that he has yet to do justice to the truth intended
by the Spartan praise of moderation and the divine law, and admits that there are different kinds of compulsion that are relevant in the analysis of Athenian behavior.64 On the Athenian side,
Strauss contends that what compelled and compels her is not
merely fear and profit, but also something noble, honor; accordingly, she exercises her imperial rule in a juster, more restrained,
less greedy manner than her power would permit her to do.65
Pericles funeral speech, above all else, celebrates Athenian liberality even while praising the empire. It is only the Athenians who
fearless of consequences, confer their benefits not from calculation

61

Strauss, The Gods, 101.


Ibid.
63
Leo Strauss, Liberalism Ancient and Modern, Preface to Spinozas Critique of
Religion (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1968), 225.
64
Strauss, City and Man, 209-10.
65
Ibid., 211.
62

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 81

of expediency, but in the confidence of liberality.66 Thucydides,


according to Strauss, agrees with Pericles on this point, as evidenced by the contrast he sets up between the Athenian treatment
of the Mytilenians and the Spartan treatment of the Plataeans. The
Athenians are ultimately persuaded not to kill the Mytilenians by
an argument forwarded by an Athenian, namely Diodotus. That
argument is only about expediency because the Athenians in contradistinction to the Spartans assume that killing must serve a purpose other than the satisfaction of the desire for revenge.67 Spartan piety, on the other hand, does not lead to liberality. The
Spartans butchered the Plataeans despite the Plataean appeals to
justice simply because they could. No oracle or oath prevented
them from their horrific actions. Piety, as Thucydides shows, can
certainly lead to moderation, as evidenced by the Spartan restraint
against the helots at Ithome, who were supposedly protected by
an oracle. But Spartan piety, in contrast to Athenian liberality, is
rigid. The nobility of Athens, according to Strausss reading, lies
in her ability to be moderate within the confines of compulsion.
The need for honor, moreover, motivates Athens in a way that
it never motivates Sparta, and that honor even comes forth in the
context of the Sicilian expedition. The Sicilian expedition,
Strauss argues, undertaken against the will of Nicias, originated
in the nobility of her daringof her willingness to risk everything
for the sake of everlasting glory. The enemies of Athens have to
become in a manner Athenians in order to defeat her.68 They have
to devote themselves completely to their city just as Athenians do.
But Thucydides will not simply take one side in the conflict between Athens and Sparta. Athenian moderation results from liberality, and liberality disappears under duress. Honor is tenuous
as compared to fear and interest, and the Athenian treatment of
the Melians is not honorable. Spartan piety may be rigid, but at
least it is predictable. Moreover, Spartan piety and the moderate
life that proceeds from it thwart civil strife. There is surely a kind
of Athenian atrocity which has no parallel in Sparta: the Athenians savage rage against each other after the mutilation of the
Hermae and the profanation of the mysteries.69 Strauss expresses
66

Thucydides, II.40.
Strauss, City and Man, 215.
68
Ibid., 225.
69
Strauss, City and Man, 217.
67

82 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

Thucydides final view as follows: Sparta and Athens were worthy antagonists not only because they were the most powerful
Greek cities but because each was in its own way of outstanding
nobility.70 Despite the severe limitations placed on them by fear
and the civil strife that results from that fear, the Athenians are
noble because they crave honor and that craving leads to rare gestures of humanity that would be inconceivable to a Spartan. Moreover, that desire for honor leads them to show supreme daring
that could only be defeated with similar daring on the part of men
like Lysander. The Spartans, on the other hand, are noble because
they maintain a moderate but powerful regime, even if that regime
can be exceedingly brutal.
Thucydides: Political Philosopher
Thucydides is thus both a critic and an admirer of Athens and
also Sparta for Strauss, and Strauss isolates Thucydides political
philosophy by combining those aspects of Athens and Sparta that
Thucydides admires. In typically mind-boggling language, Strauss
concludes: It is hard but not altogether misleading to say that for
Thucydides the pious understanding or judgment is true for the
wrong reasons; not the gods but nature sets limits to what the city
can reasonably attempt. Moderation is conduct in accordance with
the nature of human things.71 Strausss Thucydides, as such, believes in Spartan moderation for Athenian reasons. He sees moderation as the highest political end not because of divine law but
because of the natural consequences of immoderate behavior,
namely civil strife and decline. Wisdom supports moderation. As
Strauss states: The virtue which can and must control political
life is moderation. In most cases moderation is produced by fear
of the gods and of divine law. But it is also produced by true wisdom. In fact, the ultimate justification for moderation is exclusively true wisdom.72 Thucydidean wisdom, which arises from
observation of the greatest motion, leads to the conclusion that
Spartan moderation is admirable but Spartan piety is misguided.
Moreover, Athenian honor, during the rare moments when it results in moderation, is also admirable, but Athenian recklessness
70

Ibid.
Ibid., 228-9.
72
Strauss, Thucydides, 90.
71

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 83

Moderation
supported on
prudential
grounds.

is not. Thucydides guarded praise of the regime of the 5000 is perfectly understandable in this light: mixed government, because of
the balance it achieves between the different forces in the city, is
moderate.
Thucydides conclusion about the ideal political regime, however, must be grounded in Thucydides broader narrative. The regime of the 5000 resulted from a rare and short-lived confluence
of many factors including chance. Likewise, the Spartan moderate
regime rested on the unique strain of ruling over the Helots. In
other words, as we already know, Thucydides recognized the predominance of compulsion and chance in political life. As such,
Thucydidean wisdom is not practical wisdom. His admiration for
moderation is tempered by an acknowledgment that all political
ideals are fragile. In fact, perhaps one aspect of Thucydides respect for moderation was that moderate policies seem to admit
that choice in politics is severely limited. Strauss realizes that
Thucydides is not a political idealist. According to Strauss, one is
led toward the deepest stratum in Thucydides thought when one
considers the tension between his explicit praise of Spartaof
Spartan moderationwhich is not matched by a praise of Athens
on the one hand, and on the other, the thesis of the archeology as
a wholea thesis which implies the certainty of progress and
therewith the praise of innovating Athens.73
Thucydides admired the Spartan regime, but that is only one
part of his world-view. Thucydides still admired Athens even
though he sees the Athenian political project as doomed. Strauss
explains his dualist position by assessing the legacy of Periclean
Athens. Periclean Athens hoped to achieve the glory through empire, but that hope was never accomplished. But Periclean Athens
still achieved a form of universality through the work of Thucydides, namely universality of wisdom. Thucydides work, which
is meant to be a possession for all time, tells us the truth about
the human condition in a way that can only be done by a daring
Athenian. Through understanding him we see that his wisdom
was made possible by the sun and by Athensby her power and
wealth, by her defective polity, by her spirit of daring innovation,
by her active doubt of the divine law.74 Thucydides begins his
73
74

Strauss, City and Man, 231.


Ibid., 231.

84 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

work by calling himself an Athenian, because his work is made


possible by his fundamental agreement with the Athenian manner. As Strauss puts it in the lecture, by understanding Thucydides history we see that Athens was the home of wisdom.75 In
an important way, Thucydides thus identified himself with Athens alone even as he embraced Sparta.
Strauss takes this point further, suggesting that Thucydides
project precludes intellectual history as a serious pursuit. Wisdom cannot be presented as a spectacle, in the way in which
battles and the like can be presented. Wisdom cannot be said. It
can only be done.76 In what seems to be a rare show of humor,
Strauss states this point in the lecture as follows: If someone were
to draw the conclusion that intellectual history is, strictly speaking, impossible, that intellectual history is an absurd attempt to
present descriptively what is by its nature incapable of being described, I would be forced to agree with that man. Fortunately for
us students of intellectual history, there is no such man.77 But
Strauss, adding an ironic twist to his essay, ascribes that exact
thought to Thucydides.
Thucydides is thus the prototypical Athenian whose work redeems Athens, and Thucydidean wisdom seems exclusively Athenian. Yet Strauss ultimately contests this conclusion, for he shows
that all wisdom is Spartan in the sense that Spartans do not dare
to rely on hope.
There is indeed a primary opposition between those (the Spartans, Nicias, the Melians) who merely wish to preserve the present
or available things and those (the Athenians) who are haunted by
the hope for immanifest future things. But on closer inspection
the former too prove to depend on such hope. In a language which
is not that of Thucydides, there is something reminding of religion in Athenian imperialism.78

All politics for Thucydides is fundamentally limited because it is


based on hope. The Spartans have to hope that the Helots will remain in their places. The Athenians have to hope that fortune will
favor them as they conquer foreign lands. Events like the plague
make clear that countless factors can obscure and destroy the best
75

Strauss, Thucydides, 91.


Strauss, City and Man, 231.
77
Strauss, Thucydides, 91.
78
Strauss, City and Man, 229.
76

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 85

Wisdom
cannot be
said. It
can only
be done.

plans. Thucydides wisdom, like Spartan political moderation in


its ideal form, transcends hope and allows for certainty. Thucydides wisdom, therefore, though based on Athenian daring, embraces the Spartan drive towards the absolute. Ultimately, for
Strauss, Thucydides wisdom, while exposing the Athenian-Spartan polarity, moves beyond that polarity. In political affairs,
Thucydides favors Spartan moderation based on Athenian wisdom, despite the fact that such a combination is probably impossible in the real world. Thucydides wisdom, however, aims at uncovering universal truths, not merely practical possibilities, and
that wisdom itself is both profoundly Athenian in its daring and
profoundly Spartan in its desire for absolutes.
The thrust of Thucydides argument, then, in Strausss judgment, is that politics has definite limits. Moderation is the highest
political virtue, but as we know from the case of Sparta, as well as
the case of the 5000, moderation only emerges amidst the right
combination of circumstances. But Strauss does not only claim that
Thucydides considered moderation to be the highest political end;
rather, Strauss calls moderation conduct in accordance with the
nature of human things. 79 Strauss therefore must prove that
Thucydides believes in human nature. He does this with
Diodotus famous speech opposing the annihilation of the
Mytilenians. By arguing for a moderate policy on the basis of expediency, Diodotus explicates a view that coheres remarkably with
the view that Strauss has attributed to Thucydides. Diodotus argues that capital punishment will not deter future rebels because,
as Strauss puts it, nomos is powerless against physis.80 According to Diodotus, it is impossible to prevent human nature from
doing what it has once set its mind upon, by force of law or by
any other deterrent whatsoever.81 Rebels, once they see a glimmer of hope, will rebel because they believe they can succeed.
Diodotus clearly believes in human nature. Strauss links
Diodotuss view to Thucydides by pointing to Thucydides description of the Athenian purification of Delos. According to
Strauss, Thucydides believes that, since the Athenians purified the
same island as Pisistratus did and reestablished an Ionian athletic
festival that had existed during Homers time on the island, hu79

Ibid.
Ibid., 234.
81
Thucydides, III.45.
80

86 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

mans will consistently react to similar situations in the same way.


That consistency results from human nature.
Despite its important role in Strausss argument, Strausss use
of Diodotuss speech, as well as his discussion about human nature as a whole, constitutes the least convincing part of the essay.
First, Strauss provides no clear basis for his argument that Thucydides considers Diodotuss speech an act of humanity which is
compatible with the survival of Athens and even of her empire.82
Surely Strauss cannot be arguing that, just because Thucydides despised Cleon, he necessarily admired his opponent. Second,
Strauss uses an indirect proof to show that Thucydides believed
in human nature while a direct proof would have been quite
simple. Thucydides refers to human nature throughout the History.
Yet Strauss privileges Diodotus speech because it alone fuses a
belief in human nature and an argument for moderation. Yet even
that speech insists that it is in mans nature to rebel against all
odds, which is totally immoderate. Nature in Thucydides, contrary to Strausss argument, sanctions immoderate action. The
Athenians, for example, justify their daring exploits by referring
to the law that the weaker should be subject to the stronger.83
For Thucydides and for some of his speakers, nature is problematic, because it compels men to do what they can without regard
to reason or justice. Strauss, by equating nature and moderation,
uses nature in a fundamentally un-Thucydidean way. Strausss argument only remains compatible with Thucydides text if moderation is defined as the highest political end, or the result of the wisdom of the philosophic historian. Strauss equates the natural with
the ideal, or with man at the peak of rationality. On the basis of
that definition, moderation can remain the crux of Thucydides
teaching. Nevertheless, Strausss failure to expound upon the difference between his definition and Thucydides remains a shortcoming of his essay.
Thucydides versus Plato
After concluding that Thucydides viewed moderation as the
natural political end, Strauss compares Thucydides with Plato.
Strauss, as we saw, ended his lecture by establishing a deep dis82
83

Strauss, City and Man, 232.


Thucydides, I.76.

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 87

Human
nature viewed
from different
perspectives.

tinction between the two Greek thinkers. The tentative difference


between Plato and Thucydides is exemplified by Platos explanation of the rise of Athenian democracy in the Laws. Plato traces
this profound change to the willful disregard of the ancestral laws
regarding music and theater, and he thus deliberately falsifies
history.84 He ignores the rise of the navy, which constitutes the
real reason for the democratization of Athens, because the true
account would show that the margin of choice in regard to regimes
is extremely limited.85 According to Strausss lecture, Plato, in
marked contrast to Thucydides, insisted on rejecting the absolute
preponderance of fatality over choice. Plato puts the emphasis
on human choice and Thucydides puts the emphasis on fatality.86 This minor difference in emphasis has crucial ramifications,
however. While the question of how to live is a grave practical
problem for Platos city, its answer is pre-determined for Thucydides. According to Strausss Thucydides, while the thinker can
fully understand political life, he cannot guide political life. For
Plato, on the other hand, all human life, even on the lowest
level, is directed toward philosophy, toward the highest . . . the
higher is stronger than the lower.87 How does Strauss account for
this difference? While Plato believes that rest is primary and unrest is derivative, thus allowing the maximum space for choice,
Thucydides sees Greekness, or rest, as derivative from barbarism,
or unrest, and therefore as extremely fragile. After the Socratic
revolution, which displaced Thucydides and other pre-Socratics,
political history became ancillary to philosophy. Xenophon, in
Strausss judgment, who in some sense succeeded both Socrates
and Thucydides, could not take Thucydides political history seriously because of his reverence for Socratic serenity.88
Strausss preliminary distinction between Thucydides and
Plato in the lecture can be placed in the context of Strausss
overarching project. In the Preface to Spinozas Critique of Religion, Strauss makes the following claim: It is safer to understand
the low in the light of the high than the high in the light of the
low.89 Strauss, showing conscious disdain for conventional inter84

Ibid.
Strauss, Thucydides, 98.
86
Ibid.
87
Ibid., 99-100.
88
Ibid., 102.
89
Strauss, Preface to Spinoza, 225.
85

88 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

pretations of the rise of Nazism, proceeds to offer an explanation


for that rise which emphasizes the power of ideas. Strauss blames
the radicalization and deepening of Rousseaus thought by German philosophy for the German bias against liberal democracy.
Elsewhere, he asserts that Neitzsche prepared a regime which, as
long as it lasted, made discredited democracy look again like the
golden age.90 Like Plato, Strauss distorts history in order to elevate intellectual choices to the highest level of relevance. Strauss
dismisses strong economic arguments for the rise of Nazism as
half-Marxist just as Plato dismisses the relationship between the
rise of the navy and the democratization of Athens as base.91
But Strauss abandons the preliminary distinction between
Thucydides and Plato in the essay.
It could appear that Plato in contradistinction to Thucydides
makes too little allowance for fatality as distinguished from choice.
In fact there is no fundamental difference in this respect between
the two thinkers. In the very context just referred to, Plato says
that it is chance rather than man or human wisdom or folly that
establishes regimes or which legislates.92

Plato, in Strausss judgment, despite his falsification of history in


The Laws, is fully cognizant of the fragility of the high as compared
to the low. In the lecture, Strauss already acknowledges that Plato
admits implicitly, and later on explicitly, that Thucydides estimate of the situation is correct.93 Strausss essay on the Republic
offers Strausss full interpretation of Platos political thought, and
90
Leo Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy and Other Studies (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1959), 55.
91
In that regard, it is worth comparing Strausss cerebral explanation of the
rise of Nazism with Martin Heideggers statements in the Rectoral Address.
Heidegger quotes Aeschylus character Prometheus: knowing is far weaker than
necessity. (Gnther Neske and Emil Kettering, Martin Heidegger and National Socialism: Questions and Answers, The self-assertion of the German University, intr.
Karsten Harries, trans. Lisa Harries [New York: Paragon House, 1983], 121.) According to Heidegger, all knowing about things has always already been surrendered to the predominance of destiny and fails before it(Ibid.). For Heidegger
the rise of Nazism was not a matter of choice. The young and the youngest
strength of the people, Heidegger states, which is already reaching beyond us,
has already decided the matter(Ibid., 124). Just as Plato apparently resists Thucydides explanation of the most consequential change in Athenian history because
it views the high in light of the low, Strauss resists Heideggers explanation of
the fall of Weimar.
92
Strauss, City and Man, 238.
93
Strauss, Thucydides, 98.

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 89

there is no space here for a full explication of Strausss argument.


Political
His ultimate insight is that the Republic, despite its external apaction subject pearance, ultimately champions the limits of politics. According
to essential
to Strauss, the Republic conveys the broadest and deepest analylimits.
94

sis of political idealism ever made. It appears then that the initial opposition between Thucydides and Plato does not hold up to
scrutiny, because Plato agreed with Thucydides broad-based conclusion that the city has essential limits.
The compromise between the two thinkers is not one-sided,
however. Just as Plato cedes to Thucydides that the low dominates
the high, Thucydides cedes to Plato that the high is reachable, at
least in the form of wisdom. Thucydides admits that philosophy
is a worthwhile pursuit. Plato adds indeed that within very narrow limits men have a choice between different regimes, Strauss
argues, but this is not denied by Thucydides.95 Although Thucydides never explicitly raises the question of what regime is best
in itself, he does comment on the best regime of his time in Athensnamely the regime of the 5000. Moreover, as we have seen,
he may offer subtle clues about the greater question of the best
regime in itself. According to Strauss, he prefers a mixture of
oligarchy and democracy to either of the pure forms but it is not
clear whether he would unqualifiedly prefer that mixture to an intelligent and virtuous tyranny.96
Strauss thus brings Thucydides and Plato into the same tradition of political philosophy. Plato shows us that choice is limited
in works that deal with how to make the greatest choice, namely
the choice between regimes. Thucydides, on the other hand, deals
with the question of the best regime in a history that exhibits,
above all else, the power of compulsion and chance. In contrast to
Strausss initial argument, the two men both concluded that philosophy is fragile and that idealism is dangerous.
In The City and Man, Strauss has therefore gradually led us to
the pre-modern thought of our western tradition, from which
liberal democracy, in contradistinction to communism and fascism, derives powerful support.97 Ultimately, Thucydides and
94

Strauss, City and Man, 127.


Ibid., 238.
96
Ibid.
97
Political Philosophy: Six Essays by Leo Strauss, The Three Waves of Modernity, ed. Hilail Gildin (Indianapolis and New York: Bobbs Merrill/Pegasus,
1975), 98.
95

90 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

Plato are part of the same traditiona tradition that questions idealism and idealizes moderation. In the introduction to the City and
Man, Strauss laments the decay of political philosophy into ideology.98 He expresses deep concern about a civilization so vulnerable to the attacks of fascism and communism, and concludes
that the modern liberal democratic project requires classical support. When The City and Man is viewed in its entirety, a classical
tradition emerges, and that tradition, which evinces a deep belief
in moderation and the natural limits of politics, pre-judges fascism
and communism.
Why then does Strausss lecture on Thucydides stop short of
articulating the unified conception of the classics that emerges in
The City and Man? One answer is that Strausss two statements are
simply inconsistent, and that might very well be true. But a reading that grounds Strausss own surface contradictions in the very
surface contradictions of the ancient political tradition that Strauss
himself isolated is more convincing. Early in the lecture Strauss
asserts that he is following Euripides maxim: I want what the
city needs.99 As we learn from the Preface to Spinoza, Strauss
believes that the modern regime still needs the preliminary if misguided distinction between Thucydides and Plato. Citizens need
to believe that the low can be understood in terms of the high if
they are to shun the low. Strauss was convinced that the students
who listened to Heidegger attribute the rise of Nazism to destiny
were less likely to resist it. The celebration of choice in Plato is
important, because it empowers people, allowing them to believe
that ideas have consequences and that individuals can make a
difference. In the lecture, Strauss distinguishes between political
speech, which is radically partial in its pursuit of what the city
needs, and Thucydidean speech, which describes the whole
without regard for real politics, and concludes with a rousing celebration of Socrates because of his faith in reason.100 The lecture
itself is therefore a political speech. But in an essay meant to uncover the lessons that Thucydides does not draw out, Strauss
rebuts the radically partial distinction between Thucydides and
Plato and reveals a unified classical tradition.101 The essay, in con98

Strauss, City and Man, 7.


Strauss, Thucydides, 73.
100
Ibid., 95.
101
Strauss, City and Man, 144. Strauss, Thucydides, 95.
99

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 91

trast to the lecture, is Thucydidean. Ultimately, it is only safer


to view the low in light of the high, but it is not necessarily wiser.
Strauss consciously reaches different conclusions in statements
with different purposes. In the lecture he is a speaker in Thucydides History. In the essay he imitates Thucydides himself.
History and Religion in Thucydides Moderate Regime
We can finally assess Thucydides contribution to our underStrausss
standing of the problem of history and the quarrel between Athhistoricist ens and Jerusalem. According to Strauss, Plato and Thucydides
sees only
each compromised on crucial points. Plato admitted that the
particulars.
philosophers existence in the city is usually futile at best and dangerous at worst. Thucydides, conversely, admitted that despite the
limitations on philosophy, there is a modicum of choice in human
affairs, as evidenced by the Athenian decision to spare the
Mytilenians. Under rare circumstances, the choice between different regimes can be informed by philosophers.
But the philosopher does not have to be useful. Thucydides
History represents a possession for all time because it rises to
the highest plain of wisdom, not because it informs statesmen
about matters of state. Strausss Thucydides teaches about universals by recounting particulars. He is a philosopher and a historian
at the same time, and that is why he speaks so powerfully to the
problem of history as Strauss perceives it. Thucydides History
represents the antithesis of Strausss historicism. While the historicistalbeit Strausss caricatured historicistclaims that there
are only particulars and that history engulfs philosophy,102 Thucydides claims that the universals become visible precisely through
the particulars. Strausss quarrel is therefore not with the modern
historian, who seeks to examine and recount particulars, but with
the historicist, who denies the existence of universals. By pointing to Thucydides, Strauss shows that the first historian did not
deny the possibility of philosophy.
Thucydides, in contrast to Strausss modern historicist, thus
believed that philosophy is possible. Yet he also believed that phi102
Historicism is for Strauss a denial of the universal. He does not recognize
the possibility of an historicism that does acknowledge universality and sees the
particular as potentially manifesting the universal. The latter philosophical positionwhich, ironically, has much in common with the position that Strauss approvingly attributes to Thucydideshas been called Value-Centered Historicism.

92 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

losophy is fragile and that the wisdom which leads to moderation


only arises amidst the most immoderate activity. The city is usually impervious to philosophy, so philosophy cannot save it. Moderation must result from compulsion or chance. Thucydides, however, expressed a basic agreement with the Athenians that fear,
interest, and honor naturally lead cities to be daring rather than
moderate. The only force in the History that led statesmen to make
moderate choices was piety. The relevant characteristic of piety for
Thucydides is that it is a form of compulsion. Thucydides, as we
know, did not sympathize with extreme piety of the sort expressed
by the Melians. But Thucydides recognized the instrumental relationship between piety and civil society. He observed that when
religion was in honor with neither party, then the moderate
part of the citizens perished between the two.103 In a pious city,
fear of gods necessarily restrains men, but in a plague-ridden
city, men become utterly careless of everything.104 Athens must
be forced by Jerusalem to practice moderation.
Strausss last essay, meanwhile, deals exclusively with the
theme of piety, and Strauss reaches the following conclusion: Political
Thucydides theologyif it is permitted to use this expression societies
need religion.
is located in the mean (in the Aristotelian sense) between that of
Nicias and that of the Athenian ambassadors on Melos.105 Niciass
theology leads to extreme folly and the Athenian ambassadors
theology leads to civil war. Thucydides theology, namely his understanding of the type of theology the city needs, is a restraining
force but not a crippling force. Against this backdrop, the abstruse
ending of The City and Man becomes clearer. Strauss praises
Thucydides because the theme of the divine is brought out more
clearly by Thucydides than by the philosophers.106 The fictional
natural city of the philosophers, for all its glory, is untenable no
matter how beautiful it may seem. The regime as it really exists
requires religion to achieve moderation; indeed, as we noticed
above, it is perhaps the only moderating force that is not utterly
susceptible to chance and contingency.
Strauss thus brings Thucydides into the larger discourse about
historicism and about Athens and Jerusalem. But why does
103
104
105
106

Thucydides, III.82.
Ibid., II.52-53.
Strauss, The Gods, 101.
Strauss, City and Man, 240.

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 93

Strauss believe that classical political philosophy presupposes the


articulation of this beginning of political understanding but it does
not exhibit it as Thucydides does in an unsurpassable, nay, unrivaled manner?107 Thucydides work marks the culmination rather
than the beginning of the classical tradition because it elucidates
the common sense understanding of politics without ignoring
the particulars from which that understanding arises. For Strausss
modern relativist, those particulars are important because there
are no universals. Strauss, however, knows that circumstance usually prevails, but shows that only Thucydides among the ancients
succeeded at describing particular circumstances while also taking up the search for universals, thus challenging the historicist
thesis that universals do not exist. Thucydides alone among the
Greek philosophers can speak powerfully to the modern problem
of history because Thucydides, like Strausss modern historicist,
regards the higher of the opposites, not as Socrates did, as stronger but as more vulnerable, more delicate than the lower. 108
Thucydides spoke what for Strauss is the modern historicists
language.
Thucydides unique treatment of religion is possibly even more
Tension
important for Strauss. Thucydides tells us about oracles earthbetween
quakes, and eclipses . . . in brief, all these things for which the
Athens and
modern scientific historian has no use or which annoy him, and to
Jerusalem
which classical political philosophy barely alludes because for it
source of
the concern with the divine has become identical with philosoWestern
vitality.
phy.109 Strauss himself, as evidenced from Progress and Return
as well as Philosophy and Law, was deeply concerned with the fate
of a society without religious conviction. Strauss believed that
Western Civilization derives its power from the tension between
reason and revelationit seems to me that this unresolved conflict is the secret of the vitality of Western Civilization.110 Thucydides also believed in both philosophy and theology. His own wisdom arose from his Athenian agnosticism, which allowed him
to look at the the greatest motion from outside of the confines
of piety. Yet he also recognized that when all men are like him,

107
108
109
110

Ibid., 240.
Strauss, What is Political Philosophy?, Kurt Riezler, 260.
Strauss, City and Man, 240.
Strauss, Rebirth, Progress or Return, 270.

94 Volume XIV, No. 1, 2001

Emil A. Kleinhaus

Corcyra emerges. Strausss essay Progress and Return expresses


much the same idea. The philosopher lives in a state above fear
as well as above hope, and the beginning of his wisdom is not, as
in the Bible, the fear of God, but rather the sense of wonder; Biblical man lives in fear and trembling as well as in hope. 111 The
philosophers sense of wonder, before it reaches the high plane of
Thucydidean wisdom, leads to the Sicilian expedition. Fear and
trembling, on the other hand, lead to upholding treaties.
In the final analysis, Strauss isolates Thucydides as the Greek
political thinker in The City and Man because the book serves a
greater purpose within Strausss overall project. Strauss has
claimed that a uniform classical tradition supports liberal democracy and that the fact-value distinction and its historicist corollary prove bankrupt when their classical roots are examined. The
City and Man as a whole exposes the unity of the classical tradition of political thought. The central theme of that tradition is
moderation and the natural limits of politics. But only Thucydides
deals head on with the relation between history and philosophy
as well as the tension between Athens and Jerusalem, which are
the two issues Strauss considers seminal. When Thucydides understated but crucial role in Strausss thought is fully exposed,
Strausss philosophy as a whole starts to appear differently.
Strauss falsified history like Plato in order to undermine what he
and Thucydides believed to be true, namely that the high is fragile compared to the low and religion is perhaps the only way to
restrain the low. Like Thucydides, however, Strauss was a historian who bridged the gap between history and philosophy by extracting the universal from the particular.

111

Ibid., 251.

Leo Strauss on Thucydides

HUMANITAS 95

You might also like