Bell - Racial Realism
Bell - Racial Realism
Bell - Racial Realism
LAW REVIEW
VOLUME 24
WINTER 1992
NUMBER 2
RACIAL REALISM
Derrick Bell*
HE struggle by black people to obtain freedom, justice, and dignity is as old as this nation. At times, great and inspiring leaders
rose out of desperate situations to give confidence and feelings of empowerment to the black community. Most of these leaders urged their
people to strive for racial equality. They were firmly wedded to the idea
that the courts and judiciary were the vehicle to better the social position of blacks. In spite of dramatic civil rights movements and periodic
victories in the legislatures, black Americans by no means are equal to
whites. Racial equality is, in fact, not a realistic goal. By constantly
aiming for a status that is unobtainable in a perilously racist America,
black Americans face frustration and despair. Over time, our persistent
quest for integration has hardened into self-defeating rigidity.
Black people need reform of our civil rights strategies as badly as
those in the law needed a new way to consider American jurisprudence
* Weld Professor of Law, Harvard University Law School. Visiting Professor, New York University Law School, 1991-92 school year. This is the text of a speech delivered at the University of
Connecticut School of Law, on September 20, 1991, as part of the Day, Berry & Howard Visiting
Scholar Program.
[Vol. 24:363
M. Friedman & Harry N. Scheiber eds., enlarged ed. 1988). Purcell calls the pre-Realist jurisprudence "a rigid and formalistic profession," and notes that even stalwart defenders of orthodoxy
acknowledged the massive confusion and self-contradiction that case law overload (case law being
the centerpiece of the formalists' common-law logic) had created. Id. at 361-62.
2. See Elizabeth Mensch, The History of Mainstream Legal Thought, in THE POLITICS OF
LAW 18-20 (David Kairys ed., 1990). A relatively precise characterization of the classical structure is given by Purcell: "The old legal theory claimed that reasoning proceeded syllogistically
from [mechanical] rules and precedents through the particular facts of a case to a clear decision."
Purcell, supra note 1,at 360. Many historians also refer to the classical structure as formalism.
Perhaps not as accurately as Purcell, Richard Posner defines "formalism" as a term that can be
used "simply to mean the use of logic in legal reasoning." Richard Posner, JurisprudentialResponses to Legal Realism, 73 CORNELL L. REV. 326, 326 (1988). Finally, Elizabeth Mensch calls
formalism's heavy emphasis on objective rights, rules, processes, and precedents "analogic refinement run rampant." Mensch, supra, at 18.
3. Purcell, supra note 1,at 362.
1992]
RACIAL REALISM
rigid ways of the past. More than their classical counterparts, they had
been influenced by the rapid spread of the scientific outlook and the
growth of social sciences. Such influence predisposed the Realists to
accept a critical and empirical attitude towards the law,4 in contrast to
the formalists who insisted that law was logically self-evident, objective, a priori valid, and internally consistent. The great majority of the
movement's pioneers had practical experience which strengthened their
awareness of the changing and subjective elements in the legal system.
This awareness flew in the face of the Langdellian conception of law as
unchanging truth and an autonomous system of rules."
The Realists took their cue from Oliver Wendell Holmes who
staged a fifty year battle against legalistic formalism. According to
Holmes's scientific and relativistic lines of attack, judges settled cases
not by deductive reasoning, but rather by reliance on value-laden, personal beliefs. To Holmes, such judges engineered socially desirable policies based on these beliefs which, like all moral values, were wholly
relative and determined by one's particular environment." Realist notions also were grounded in the views of the Progressives during the
1890s. Concerned with social welfare legislation and administrative
regulation, the Progressives criticized the conceptualization of property
rights being expounded by the United States Supreme Court.7 Creating
4. Empiricism is a crucial aspect of Racial Realism. By taking into consideration the abysmal
statistics regarding the social status of black Americans, their oppression is validated. See Infra
note 30 and accompanying text.
5. See id. at 361-63.
6. At this point it might be helpful to recognize an implicit distinction between the absence of
values and the impossibility of empirically demonstrable objective moral standards.Holmes's
relativism-that values are wholly determined by one's particular environment not existing somewhere "out there" for any impartial judge to discover and apply-has been called "cynical." See
id. at 361. Realists also embraced the notion that "there could be no such thing as a demonstrable
moral standard." Id. at 367. This kind of reasoning incurred the wrath of many. particularly as
the threat of war and Nazi totalitarianism made the defense of undeniable moral grounds for
democracy more urgent. Id. at 369.
Despite having earlier agreed that formal law overemphasized logical uniformity and often
frustrated the workings of justice, see id. at 361, Roscoe Pound called the Realists' take on morals
a breed of "philosophical nominalism," id. at 365, and at his most vitriolic, called Realism a
"give-it-up-philosophy." Id. at 369. Morris R. Cohen pointed to the antidemocratic implication of
a judicial theory that seemed to claim that judges' subjective decisions were the only law; Cohen
implied that the Realists were justifying judicial despotism when he declared, "To be ruled by a
judge is, to the extent that he is not bound by law, tyranny or despotism." Id. at 367.
In contemporary law, positivists fearful of unrestrained judicial power have attacked modern
strands of Realism, as have committed rights theorists, who reject the notion that enshrined rights
are mere interests to be balanced against all other interests. See Anita Allen, Legal Philosophy, in
LOOKING AT LAW SCHOOL
7.
"The Realist movement was part of the general twentieth-cntury revolt against formalism
[Vol. 24:363
a remedy based upon the finding of a property right was the Court's
way of subtly imposing personal and moral beliefs. Abstraction was the
method the Court used to accomplish its purpose. The Realists stressed
the function of law, however, rather than the abstract conceptualization of it.'
The Realists also had a profound impact by demonstrating the circularity of defining rights as "objective," which definition depended, in
large part, on a distinction between formalistically bounded spheres between public and private.9 Classical judges justified decisions by appealing to these spheres. For example, an opinion would justify finding
a defendant liable because she had invaded the (private) property
rights of the plaintiff. But such a justification, the Realists pointed out,
was inevitably circular because there would be such a private property
and conceptualism .... More specifically and politically, Realism was also a reaction against
Supreme Court decisions like Coppage, which had invalidated progressive regulatory legislation
favored even by many business leaders." See Mensch, supra note 2, at 21.
In Coppage v. Kansas, 236 U.S. 1 (1915), the Court refused to uphold a state statute outlawing yellow-dog contracts. The state argued that these contracts coerced workers to accept the
terms imposed by employers, rendering meaningless the formal law concept of freedom of contract. Although the Court did not deny the presence of unequal bargaining power, it reasoned that
the employees merely encountered economic coercion. Because the formal common-law definition
of duress that would have excused nonperformance of the contracts did not include economic
coercion, the workers were deemed to have freely exercised their choice. The Court would not
allow the State to invade the liberty rights of contracting parties. See Mensch, supra note 2, at
20.
8. See KERMIT L. HALL. THE MAGIC MIRROR: LAW IN AMERICAN HISTORY 269 (1989): see
also Purcell, supra note 1,at 361 ("Brandeis and Frankfurter argued that judges must consciously consider the probable social results of their decisions. Scientific studies of social needs and
problems, rather than syllogistic reasoning, should be the determining factor.").
There were also instrumentalist underpinnings to the Realists' conception of law:
Much of Realist scholarship was ... devoted to exposing the incoherence of established patterns of reasoning in judicial decisions. By undermining the inexorability of
such logic, the Realists hoped to reveal the "real" question in judicial decisions: why "the
court select[ed] ... one available premise rather than the other." This was the point in
Realist analysis where social science entered . . . . The "real" question in liberty of
contract cases was, therefore, not, "is there a liberty to contract in the due process
clause?," but "do industrial workers in fact have no bargaining power to choose the terms
of their employment?" This question was, the Realists believed, susceptible of empirical
analysis.
G. Edward White, From Realism to CriticalLegal Studies: A Truncated Intellectual History, 40
Sw. L.J. 819, 822-23 (1986) (citation omitted). See also Hall, supra, at 270 ("Realists ... rejected formalistic and deductive logic, which, they argued merely concealed a judge's prejudices
and preferences. The Realists indeed believed in general legal principles, but they insisted that the
traditional deference accorded to precedent was merely a screen that shielded the inherently conservative biases of most judges.").
9. See Fran Olsen, The Myth of State Intervention in the Family, 18 MICH. J.L. REF. 835
(1985).
19921
RACIAL REALISM
right if, and only if, the court found for the plaintiff or declared the
statute unconstitutional. The cited reasons for decisions were only results, and as such served to obscure the extent to which the state's enforcement power through the courts lay behind private property and
other rights claims.Y
Closely linked with the Realists' attack on the logic of rights theory was their attack on the logic of precedent." No two cases, the
Realists pointed out, are ever exactly alike. Hence a procedural rule
from a former case cannot simply be applied to a new case with a multitude of facts that vary from the former case. Rather, the judge has to
choose whether or not the ruling in the earlier case should be extended
to include the new case. Such a choice basically is about the relevancy
of facts, and decisions about relevancy are never logically compelled.
Decisions merely are subjective judgments made to reach a particular
result. Decisions about the relevance of distinguishing facts are valueladen and dependent upon a judge's own experiences."2
The imperatives of this Realist attack were at least two: first, to
clear the air of "beguiling but misleading conceptual categories"' 3 so
that thought could be redirected towards facts (rather than nonexistent
spheres of classism) and ethics. If social decisionmaking was inevitably
moral choice, policymakers needed some ethical basis upon which to
make their choices.1 4 And second, the Realists' critique suggested that
the whole liberal worldview of private rights and public sovereignty mediated by the rule of law needed to be exploded. The Realists argued
that a worldview premised upon the public and private spheres is an
attractive mirage that masks the reality of economic and political
power. 5 This two-pronged attack had profoundly threatening conse10.
11.
12.
of the
Power, 401 U.S. 424 (1971), in which blacks were deemed to have suffered discriminatory impact
when their employer required all workers to have a high school diploma and to pass a given
standardized test. The Court in Griggs used flexible reasoning in arriving at its decision, considering blacks' dismal access to education. Later decisions, however, prove that victories for blacks in
the courts regarding issues of affirmative action are, at best, sporadic.
13. Mensch, supra note 2, at 23.
14. See id.
15. Id. at 23-24. Implicit in the approach taken by the Realists is the notion that courts rendered decisions that were suspect because of their reliance on subjective and abstract concepts.
many early twentieth-century judicial decisions were "wrong." They [the decisions) were
[Vol. 24:363
1992]
RACIAL REALISM
[Vol. 24:363
the "right" result. Thus, cases such as Bakke should inspire many civil
rights lawyers to reexamine the potential of equality jurisprudence to
improve the lives of black Americans.
The protection of whites' race-based privilege, so evident in the
Bakke decision, has become a common theme in civil rights decisions,
particularly in many of those decided by an increasingly conservative
Supreme Court. The addition of Judge Clarence Thomas to that Court,
as the replacement for Justice Thurgood Marshall, is likely to add deep
insult to the continuing injury inflicted on civil rights advocates. The
cut is particularly unkind because the choice of a black like Clarence
Thomas replicates the slave masters' practice of elevating to overseer
and other positions of quasi-power those slaves willing to mimic the
masters' views, carry out orders, and by their presence provide a perverse legitimacy to the oppression they aided and approved.
For liberals in general, and black people in particular, the appointment of Clarence Thomas to the Supreme Court, his confirmation
hearings, and the nation's reaction to Professor Anita Hill's sexual harassment charges, all provide most ominous evidence that we are in a
period of racial rejection, a time when many whites can block out their
own justified fears about the future through increasingly blatant forms
of discrimination against blacks.2
The decline of black people is marked by a precipitous collapse in
our economic status and the frustration of our political hopes. An ultimate rebuff and symbol of our powerlessness is President Bush's elevation of one of us who is willing to denigrate and disparage all who look
like him to gain personal favor, position, and prestige.2 2 Here, historical
parallels contain a fearful symmetry. In 1895, Booker T. Washington,
another black man who had risen from the bottom-in Washington's
case that bottom was slavery itself-gained instant and lasting status in
white America by declaring, in his now famous Atlanta Compromise
speech, that black people should eschew racial equality and seek to
gain acceptance in the society by becoming useful through trades and
21. Thomas played on these fears when he invoked the image of a lynch mob to portray the
Senate inquiry. As one commentator has noted, "Any American with a sense of history under-
stood the connotations of Thomas's claim that he was a lynch victim, casting the fourteen white
men of the Senate Judiciary Committee as his lynch mob." Nell Irvin Painter, Who Was
Lynched?,
THE NATION,
577 (1991).
22. One critic of Black Conservatives states, "These black men tend to be high achievers who
may feel diminished by the notion they got where they are because of affirmative action ...
[They] are really trying to affirm that their status is the result of a fair fight." Julianne Malveaux,
Why Are the Black Conservatives All Men?, Ms., Mar./Apr. 1991, at 60, 60-61.
1992]
RACIAL REALISM
worsening state on characteristics that are far more the result of condition than color.
25. Clarence Thomas, no less than Booker T. Washington, could prove an unwitting double
agent. In his first civil rights decision, Justice Thomas voted with the conservative majority in a
voting rights case, Presley v. Etowah County Comm'n, 1992 U.S. Lexis 554 (Jan. 27, 1992). If
this voting pattern continues, Thomas will disappoint those blacks who supported him in the hope
that, once on the Court, he would drop the anti-civil rights views that propelled him there. In
addition, he could undermine the dwindling support for law-oriented civil rights groups and cause
blacks to turn to more militant leadership. Thus, as I suggested in an op-cd piece, Thomas, seemingly a black conservative, may prove to be a black revolutionary-despite himself. Derrick Bell.
A Radical Double Agent, N.Y. TiNtEs. Sept. 9, 1991, at AIS.
[Vol. 24:363
DERRICK
A.
1992]
RACIAL REALISM
[Vol. 24:363
than double that of U.S. whites and 50 percent higher than that of U.S. blacks generally. Black
men in Harlem are less likely to reach the age of 65 than men in Bangladesh. Colin McCord,
M.D. & Harold P. Freeman, M.D., Excess Mortality in Harlem, 322 NEw ENG. J. MED, 173
(1990). While the Harlem phenomenon is extreme, it is not unique. Of 353 health areas in New
York City, 54 also had twice as many deaths among people under the age of 65 as would be
expected if the death rates of U.S. whites applied. All but one of these areas of high mortality
were predominantly black or Hispanic.
The economist Dr. David Swinton has summarized the income and employment status of
black Americans. David H. Swinton, The Economic Status of African Americans: 'Permanent'
Poverty and Inequality, in THE STATE OF BLACK AMERICA 25 (1991). Both in absolute terms, and
in comparison to white Americans, blacks have high unemployment rates. As of November 1990,
the unemployment rate for black men was 11.5 percent, about 2.5 times the corresponding white
1992]
RACIAL REALISM
tort, and I do wish for revelations showing that any of the dreadful
data illustrating the plight of so many black people is false or misleading. But there is little effort to discredit the shocking disparities contained in these reports. Even so, the reports have little effect on policymakers or the society in general.
Statistics and studies reflect racial conditions that transformed the
"We Have a Dream" mentality of the 1960s into the trial by racial
ordeal so many blacks are suffering in the 1990s. The adverse psychological effects of nonexistent opportunity are worse than the economic
and social loss. As the writer, Maya Angelou, put it recently:
In these bloody days and frightful nights when an urban
warrior can find no face more despicable than his own, no ammunition more deadly than self-hate and no target more deserving of his true aim than his brother, we must wonder how we
came so late and lonely to this place.31
As a veteran of a civil rights era that is now over, I regret the need
to explain what went wrong. Clearly we need to examine what it was
about our reliance on racial remedies that may have prevented us from
recognizing that these legal rights could do little more than bring about
the cessation of one form of discriminatory conduct that soon appeared
in a more subtle though no less discriminatory form. The question is
whether this examination requires us to redefine goals of racial equality
and opportunity to which blacks have adhered for more than a century.
male rate of 4.6 percent. The slightly lower rate for black women, at 10.2 percent. was 2.3 times
the white rate. Black teenage unemployment was 35.8 percent, 2.6 times the white rate of 13.8
percent. Id. Again, these disparities have remained steady since 1970. although the degree of
inequality generally increased over time. Dr. Swinton cautions that the unemployment indicator
"does not take into account the lower participation, part-time workers or discouraged workers.
Therefore, this indicator understatesthe black unemployment disadvantage." Id. at 62 (emphasis
added).
Swinton explains that blacks also have low rates of employment, inferior occupational distributions, and low wages and earnings. Id. at 29. In 1989, black per capita income was S8,747, only
about 59 percent of white per capita income of S14,896. In the aggregate, the income of the
African-American population was S186 billion short of the income required for parity. This inequality has been within two percentage points of this figure every year since 1970, suggesting to
Dr. Swinton that "this degree of relative inequality appears to be a permanent feature of the
American economy." Id.
Statistically, blacks have low incomes and high poverty rates. In fact, in 1989, there were
about 9.3 million black persons living in poverty. Blacks were three times more likely to have
income below the poverty level than whites, a gap that has remained fairly steady since 1970. Id.
at 42.
31. Maya Angelou, I Dare to Hope, N.Y. TiMEs, Aug. 25, 1991. at EIS.
[Vol. 24:363
1992]
RACIAL REALISM
the North was more than ready to agree to a compromise that ill-served blacks. Among other
things, it promised Democrats both removal of remaining federal troops from the southern states
and freedom from intervention in "political affairs" in those states. See BELL, supra note 26. at
26-27.
34. The continuing burdens of discrimination are not limited to the poorest, black Americans.
A study conducted by black and white testers found that blacks were required to pay more for
new cars even when blacks and whites negotiated the car purchases in similar fashion. Ian Ayres.
Fair Driving: Gender and Race Discrimination in Retail Car Negotiations, 104 HARv L REv
817 (1991).
35. Blacks own little wealth and small amounts of business property. No significant progress is
being made to improve the status of blacks and to close the gaps. Thus, the disparities in measures
of economic status have persisted at roughly the same level for the last two decades, and many
indicators of inequality have even drifted upward during this period. Swinton. supra note 30. at
29-40.
[Vol. 24:363
19921
RACIAL REALISM
Mrs. MacDonald did not say she risked everything because she
hoped or expected to win out over the whites who, as she well knew,
held all the economic and political power, and the guns as well. Rather,
she recognized that-powerless as she was-she had and intended to
use courage and determination as weapons "to harass white folks." Her
fight, in itself, gave her strength and empowerment in a society that
relentlessly attempted to wear her down. Mrs. MacDonald did not even
hint that her harassment would topple whites' well-entrenched power.
Rather, her goal was defiance and its harassing effect was more potent
precisely because she placed herself in confrontation with her oppressors with full knowledge of their power and willingness to use it.
Mrs. MacDonald avoided discouragement and defeat because at
the point that she determined to resist her oppression, she was triumphant. Nothing the all-powerful whites could do to her would diminish
her triumph. Mrs. MacDonald understood twenty-five years ago the
theory that I am espousing in the 1990s for black leaders and civil
rights lawyers to adopt. If you remember her story, you will understand
my message.