The Object of Art History
The Object of Art History
The Object of Art History
Author(s): David Freedberg, Oleg Grabar, Anne Higonnet, Cecelia F. Klein, Lisa Tickner and
Anthony Vidler
Source: The Art Bulletin, Vol. 76, No. 3 (Sep., 1994), pp. 394-410
Published by: College Art Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3046035
Accessed: 13-09-2016 05:55 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/3046035?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
College Art Association, Taylor & Francis, Ltd. are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to The Art Bulletin
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
of the American
of Art History
problematic.
"Art comes before gold and gems, the author before
These have been years in which art history has been
strug-declares the inscription on one of the plaques
everything,"
gling to redefine itself. Borrowing from a number
discifor of
a shrine
or altar commissioned by Henri of Blois from a
plines, it has not really succeeded in finding its own
Mosanvoice.
goldsmith in the third quarter of the twelfth century.
The tensions and confusions have been clear. But in what
Ever since a famous article by Meyer Schapiro, art historians
does the particular texture of art history consist? What
have
isbeen
it willing to admit that medieval images were
David Freedberg
admired and ranked for their artistic status as well as for their
beyond the rules of aesthetic evaluation, in ways that apAs so often, the development of a discipline has inter-proach more closely what we think of as ritual or cultic; or
sected with the politics of culture. Acknowledging the reli- that they may also arouse violent emotions and strong
passions. These are all phenomena that can be documented
gious and historical status of sacred objects within their
possession, museums have come to be increasingly willing tostraightforwardly enough. The value of understanding the
work of art (however so considered) in the context of the full
repatriate them to their original owners. Although their
range of images of the visual culture in which it is embedded
success has by no means been general, Hopi, Navajo, and
Pueblo peoples in this hemisphere, Maori and Aboriginehas been insisted upon often enough in recent years. But still
peoples in the other, have successfully reclaimed such worksthe questions remain: where does the distinct work of the art
for their original and intended contexts (or their closehistorian begin, and in what does it consist? One could, of
course, declare, as many now do, that one is simply a
equivalents). "Once returned, the sacred objects will again
historian or an ethnographer working with art; but surely
assume their religious functions within the Pueblo rather
is more to the task than that.
than being placed on display within a museum," declared there
a
recent press release by the Pueblo ofJemez, announcing the In the first place, I take it that there can be no history of
the object without a subject. However else defined, objects of
restitution of eighty-six ritual objects from the Smithsonian
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
because of our recognition of this fact and our consequent real that is both celebrated and fetishized in the image, even
drive to force them closer to a comprehensible reality that
about our desire for the real (or for avoiding it). Representation is always substitutional, and by its visuality tempts its
studied. So too are the ways in which not just the category but beholders with the possibility of restoring the rupture bethe very possibility of the unique have progressively disinte- tween what it is and what it promises to show.
grated.
By long practice art historians acquire a kind of experience
The problem, however, is that art historians continue to
in the analysis of visual things and their effects that is rarely if
give the impression of wanting to insulate and protect works
ever acquired in other fields. How it is acquired does not
of art from just the effects and interactions that we now so
seem so crucial to me, even though most of us are still likely
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
domain of the art historian and they form the raw material-turn to engage in the kinds of documentary and cont
researches whose disciplines we learn from other field
not the final result-of his or her investigations.
With aims such as these in mind, there seems to be little
These are some of the ways in which we as historians
reason to downgrade the worth of traditional art-historical and of images may begin to speak with authority
exercises such as the making of monographs and the problems and issues that cannot simply be resolved
application of the special skills and techniques of thatanalysis of contextual factors and the social construct
unfortunately named subdiscipline, connoisseurship. Of response and (say) the conditions of creativity. To
course, there is no doubt about the potential of such such analyses could as well have been done by other k
practices (monographs, the making of attributions, and sohistorians, and better. Frequently they have seem
on) for abuse; but the moral issues are consequential, not
The loss of prestige of the activities associated with the name description of the project-thus expanded well beyond
of connoisseurship has as much to do with a justifiable we call art-may seem ambitious; but if historians of a
revulsion at its elitist connotations as with a widespreadnot undertake it, who else will?
they are the perfect fiche, the bar-coded label which conta
decade which are (or can be made) part of our collective and
natural and physical sciences during their own classificati
individual visual experience and which often foster considerperiods is obvious. The main difference between Linnean
able pride of possession among individuals or communities.
Mendeleevian achievements and those of art historians is the
The multiplication of primarily taxonomic techniques
is as (or conclusion) of the categorical and typologica
assumption
amazing as the range of objects or built ensembles finiteness
to which of the natural world as opposed to the infinit
given
it in this essay, but the objective of a complet
chronology or codicology are just two of the more
orto
less
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
behavior (moving left or right, stopping, going, praying,cryis its pre-history, that is to say, everything that went into its
ing, laughing), by feeling various forms of pleasure or even
being whatever it was at the moment of its first appearance to
pain, and by evaluating or even judging whatever is perbe used or seen. It includes its techniques of manufacture,
user or observer, the "receiver" of the object. Many varialogically, rationally, and objectively, in the sense that such
and most of such conclusions are true or false
tions, at times incompatible ones, exist within this setstatements
of
impulses as well. There is the simpleminded but quite
within existing evidence and can be modified by new ev
dence.
common "I know what I like," with theoretically total
freedom of judgment and an implication of aesthetic anarThen there is a post-history. It begins with the first reaction
chy. As elaborated in some of Bakhtin's literary studies and
of the first person to see something or to use it. Abbot Suger
caricatured in Woody Allen's "Kugelmass machine," there is
or Salon and exhibition critics may have been affected by all
also a transformation of the observer by the object and then,
they knew or guessed about the pre-history of whatever they
eventually, the transmission of that transformation to the
saw, but their most significant response lay in their opinions
dently of each other. Many approaches-Gombrich's "matchimportant than the satisfaction of a need or yearning which I
ing and making," the binary opposites sought and never
will call, reluctantly, the aesthetic impulse. As it is usually not
identification of canons and types-require or imply someexpress their thoughts, pleasure, or emotions. The only
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
kinds of arguments, personal memories and associations. and subfields is beyond the capacity of most scholars and
Literary or political examples of all these strands are easy to critics who have not devoted themselves to that field.
Post-history is equally impossible to grasp as a whole. Only
provide, but they are only involved with "aesthetics" to the
extent that the absence of a reaction to seen artifacts would
But the new tastes in China and India (well over half of
emotional drives. It is at times expressed in poetic or
humanity) or the films and television series which are the
philosophically abstruse language, it is occasionally passing
and trendy, and it may simply restate in current termsprimary visual culture of 80 percent of humanity are hardly
well-known and well-honed truths. Its values are its immeautomatic parts of the intellectual or emotional makeup
On the whole, however, professional self-flagellation, exThe vehicles for scholarship or information about both
histories are also varied in kind. Pre-historians have devel-
historical endeavors?
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
profession over the decades to come, if we are to avoid thebe given to knowledge. In a world where more is available
On the Object
Anne Higonnet
Objects constitute my field. I differentiate my work from the
work of literary critics, historians, and philosophers (among
others) by my attention to material objects. If devotion to
objects has limited the scope and the importance of a field
AIW
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
question, the question of visual historical meaning, which I seamstresses by some famous artist in much the same way a
believe is never purely visual. Here the idea of the combina-historian uses photographs: to reinforce the conclusion of a
toire seems useful to me. Combinatoire translates from French
only very awkwardly as "combinator" or too familiarly as raphy has included some remarkably supple and innovative
"combination." In 1980, Michel de Certeau introduced his
essays,5 but they have been marginal within a formalist
theory of culture as "combinatoires d'operatzons,"3 while in photographic history that patterns itself on the history of
1975, Frederic Jameson, himself citing Charles Mauron and painting, and that ignores in photographs exactly those
Tzvetan Todorov, explained: "the combznatoire aims at reveal- factors of class and gender that would constitute Dans
ing, not the causes behind a given form, but rather thel'atelzer's
Any investigation of an image's historical meaning is very few historical studies of reciprocal relationships among
necessarily-I believe-an investigation into what has been image types. Which is to say that we have no clear or
called realism. What effect of the real does any image comprehensive histories of visual culture, let alone histories
produce, and how do visual and verbal modes of realism that mesh visual culture with social and literary history. The
interact? In what sense is any image a form of history, and method by which we could write the historical meaning, the
what place can its material factuality occupy in narratives realism, of an image like Dans l'atelier will have to be
written always after the fact? In contrast to a specificallyinvented.
It should already be clear that I believe such a project
literary realism, what interests me are the forms of realism
entails studying how the object that materializes a historical
moment unites the meanings so disparately treated by the
mode of realism always playing against, supplementing, fields of history and art history. The object forces us to see
complementing, or contradicting textual modes of realism. how meanings function at one moment in relation to each
What interests me are modes of realism that work not only other. It forces us to see how meanings act as functions of
produced by images, not merely considered as a question of
their subject matter's optical verisimilitude, but rather as a
through subject, but also through visual form and cultural each other, with no independent significance, as elements of
conditions of sight, modes of realism that imply a history notcombznatoires. In the combznatoire, no meaning can be prior to
just of subjects, but of visual culture. De Charly's photograph any other, privileged over any other. The only origin is the
realistic.
It would be easy to say that de Charly's Dans l'atelzer simply in S/Z, invoking images: "Thus realism ... consists not in
records how a visually underrepresented type-women work- copying reality, but in copying a (painted) copy of reality.""6
ers-really looked. This response would be the standard Neil Hertz identifies this regressive process as the "irreducesocial historian's. Yet social historians do not, in practice, able figurativeness of one's language," which he derives from
take photographs like Dans l'atelzer very seriously. By and Sigmund Freud's psychoanalytic concept of "repetition comlarge they consider images only to illustrate prior meanings. pulsion."7 Nonetheless, the object and its moment are
According to such a procedure, the social historian, having constituted by a particular intersection of these regressions.
investigated class and gender in mid-nineteenth-century The configuration of that intersection, the pattern formed by
France, would then invoke Dans l'atelier to show the appear- different vectors of meaning, their respective velocities, their
ances of a history that can be, has been, written already. If capacity to deflect or even absorb each other, together
Dans l'atelier is construed to show how seamstresses actually- constitute the combinatoire. That pattern determines the
really-looked, it could only be because their identity had combznatozre's function, temporarily. The very energy of the
been produced prior to the photograph. For most social elements that enter into it, and the transformation of those
historians, images do not produce meaning, and therefore energies by their mix, guarantee that the combznatozre can
neither last nor reproduce itself exactly, but rather concannot function as integral elements of history.
Art historians dismiss photographs like Dans l'atelzer in stantly mutates into unprecedented forms and functions.
their own way. The methods that have dominated art history
have no place for such images. De Charly is not a known images assembled into an album. The album was intended to
photographer, he belongs to no canon either on his own teach women the truth about themselves. Each page gave a
lesson about a reality of gender, class, and respectability that
merits or by association, and his picture is somewhat inert
formally: banal in its composition, light effects, and printing. underlay false values. De Charly relied primarily on photogBasically, Dans l'atelzer does not qualify as art. At best an art raphy's reality effect to convince his audience. He called the
historian would compare Dans l'atelzer to a painting of album Pirigrznatzons d'un objectzf, a title that when translated
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
into the English "Peregrinations of a Lens" loses the reso-them within a history of visual culture. I would also argue that
any essay with methodological intentions requires concentranance of "objective." Yet on every page of the album, the
tion on a few exceptional objects. In work with a broader
photograph that was going to reveal the truth visually has
been textually framed by explanatory captions above andscope, it would be preferable to deal with patterns of objects
evolving over time. The limited scope of an essay calls for
moral axioms below. Visual meanings were supposed to be
natural and self-evident, yet textual meanings are heresingle objects which carry within themselves, mise en abyme,
the signs of their own conditions. To recognize and value
invoked to speak the "truth."
Visual and textual meanings always together set the terms such objects, finally, requires an understanding of the object
as allegory. De Certeau wrote that his goal was to "make of
for realism's contracts, as they do, for instance, in de Charly's
album. If at any one moment either kind of meaning claims analysis a variant of its object."8 John Berger quoted Walter
to represent truth or nature or reality more effectively thanBenjamin quoting Goethe: "There is a delicate form of the
empirical which identifies itself so intimately with its object
the other, that claim will always, as in the case ofDans l'atelier,
that it thereby becomes theory."'
facilitate an ideological work whose unexpected conseFidelity to the material object forces a relational analysis of
quences will eventually require the intervention of its putaits references. Yet the recognition that those references are
tively more artificial semiotic counterpart. Nor can configura-
prescription, with an apposition of words unconnected gramAnne Higonnet is the author of two books on the Impressionist
matically.
Berthe Morisot and ofa dozen articles or book chapters on aspects of
It might be objected that Dans l'atelier is too exceptional an
object to sustain any argument larger than itself. I would first
4. Frederic Jameson, "Magical Narratives: Romance as Genre," New Lzterary Hzstory, no. 1,
into gender, class, and the place of the photographic medium in 19th-century visual culture,
Objects are nice. I've always liked them, especially dolls.as well as sentimental value, and as such they function in my
When I was a child I collected dolls, which I regarded as my home much like true works of art. I have even seen dolls just
own children. I treated them accordingly, tucking them in atlike mine on display in several museums.
night, combing their nylon hair with my own comb, dressing My own dolls, in fact, are now displayed next to a "real" art
them in little clothes my mother made them, feeding theobject, a recently commissioned wood carving of an ancestral
"youngest" with liquids that trickled out of a little hole at thekava kava figure from Rapa Nui (Easter Island) of the sort
center of the left buttock, where its approximation to that was hung from rafters in private homes except when
taken out and worn around the neck during ceremonial
cause embarrassment to adults. When my "babies" cried, asdances. Like the old kava kava statues collected by European
some were programmed to do, I tried to comfort them. I still sailors in the late eighteenth century, after which mine is
nature's design of the human body was not close enough to
have those dolls, but today metal stands support their inert patterned, my statue represents a naked, bent over, emacibodies on glass shelves in my living room, and plastic covers ated old man with erect phallus, grimacing mouth, bushy
keep off the dust that accumulates from lack of handling. I eyebrows, and glaring, shell-inlaid eyes. The figure's apparno longer talk to my dolls, nor do they "cry" for my attention.ent rage and misery are so immense that small children often
They have become, well, just objects, now of some financial cry out and back away when first confronted with it. I have
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
never thought of trying to calm or comfort this frighteningcently, usually figurative and naturalistic, creating another
figure, however, nor would I ever refer to it as a doll. And correlation-this time between "great art" and imagery.
although, on ancient Rapa Nui, its predecessor's loins wereUntil the mid-twentieth century, outside of architecture,
what we call "great art" has typically taken a figurative form
usually covered with a fiber garment, a feature that the carver
of my statue shrewdly omitted, I would never considerthat directly references, and so allegedly provides us with
dressing it myself. Unlike its predecessors, my kava kavaaccess to, its original meaning. "Significant form," then, has
figure does not need to be treated like a living human being come in our culture to imply forms that express the most
because in my culture, and thus for me, it represents a work important, most intellectual and spiritual values and ideas of
of art.
the day in a representational, figurative manner. When we
Art objects are nice. I've always loved them and for a long see an object that has been elaborately and carefully crafted
time, from childhood through my undergraduate years as a to reference imagistically a major concept or narrative in our
"studio" art major, I even made some. Today, as I've already culture, we assume that it provides us access to what was or is
indicated, I own a few artworks, and as an art historian, I most "significant" to the people of that place and period.
heritage, shifting instead toward fields formerly, and at best expressed through forms that are not (wo)manmade, are not
euphemistically, labeled as "primitive" and "non-Western."imagistic, and/or are not executed with the materials and
In my efforts to document and understand the visual cultures"care" that we expect of "great art." Examples are legion,
of these unfamiliar peoples, I frankly have found the Euro- but let me mention just a few. When Europeans first
American concept of the "art object" not only inadequatecontacted and subsequently settled in Tahiti in the eighand limiting, but at times positively misleading as well.teenth century, they collected a number of portable stone
According to conventional Western notions of art objects, for and wood figures called ti'z whose polished, carefully carved
example, traditional Rapa Nui kava kava figures, becauseplanes and angles have qualified them as "art" in at least
they were dressed and treated like living beings, bettersome European and North American museums. These carvresemble the dolls our children play with than the sculptureings, which constitute the largest figurative images from
that we display in our homes and museums. The damageancient Tahiti, could thus be seen as "clues" to, or "signs" of,
inflicted by such a semantic system can be enormous, for a what for Tahitians was once assigned the highest value. The
person lacking the critical ability to override such analogical assumption would seem to be supported by contemporary
errors may too easily conclude not only that eighteenth-travelers' reports to the effect that these figures originally
century Rapa Nui wood carvers were not "real artists"-that served as temporary receptacles for certain spirits who were
is, that the kava kava figures are not and never were "true" periodically invoked by religious practitioners. At the time of
works of art-but, far worse, that the behavior and thought contact, however, tz'i were of far less importance as religious
processes of all Rapa Nui people once were, and may evenobjects than another type of object that represented the
still be, childish. Similar conclusions, as is well known, have Tahitian war god, Oro. Oro, who was considered so sacred
been drawn for many colonized peoples over the centuriesthat he could not be portrayed in human form, was mani-
separating the modern Western world from the so-calledfested as a simple wood stick wrapped with braided sennit
into which red feathers were inserted. These "nonrepresenta"age of expansion."
There are many reasons why our concept of the art object tional representations" of Oro were placed inside huts at the
so often fails us when we step outside the Euro-Americancenter of sacred ceremonial precincts called marae, whereas
culture in which it was born, but the need for brevity here the figural tz'i so beloved of European and American collecpermits mention of only a few. Many of our difficulties stemtors were relegated to a relatively insignificant place at their
made (or at least [wo]man-modified) forms than with ourpressive sennit-and-feather representation of Oro, a form
notions of what makes these forms "significant." In Renais- that we would not regard as a work of art. But Oro
sance and post-Renaissance Europe, art objects were alwaysexemplifies yet another objection to Western art history's
assumed to constitute the most significant forms, and indeed cult of the object, for the materials that represented him were
the highest values and most "profound" concepts were used in an essentially natural, unworked, organic state. This
typically embodied by artworks. The frescoes in the Sistine choice of natural materials to embody the most sacred forces
Chapel are a good example. The most expensive, best-in the spiritual realm has been documented time and again
crafted, and most valuable works of art in the West, in otherthroughout the non-European world. In the Americas, for
words, traditionally have been expressions of what have beenexample, the most sacred objects and the most important
and/or are regarded (by those whose opinion has beensources of social and spiritual power were often unworked
crucial) as the most significant spiritual and political ideas ofmaterials drawn directly from nature. In the Great Plains of
their place and time. Artistic form implies the most signifi-what is now the United States, as throughout preconquest
Mesoamerica, godly essences and power objects in such
cant subject matter.
These expressions, moreover, were, until relatively re-forms as an eagle's claw, a buffalo tail, an obsidian mirror, or
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
examples far outstrips the space I can allot here, but a few
a group of thorns were kept wrapped in highly sacred cloth
or leather bundles. In like vein, the most sacred building inwill suffice. The Dayaks of what is now Malaysia and Kaliman-
seldom (wo)manmade, and therefore fall outside our usual substance. For in cases like these, as in so many instances of
definition of the art object on that ground alone. But what
makes it all the harder for the West to understand their value
to their owners is the fact that the materials represented wereAustralian aborigines painted with blood, when victorious
seldom those that we ourselves value. This matter of materi-
rarest, most expensive, most elaborately refined materials least partially resolved-by means of the natural world, of
that are most highly valued; gold and silver are excellent the body, themselves. The boundaries between "art" and
examples. But the issue is more complicated than this, for nature, object and subject, in other words, were perceived by
gold and silver, as we have seen, are metals and, as such,
these peoples as far more fluid and permeable than by
inorganic, and both require extensive processing if they are
to be useful to artists. Their value therefore lies in part in
substance.
thetic. The value, and thus the "significance" of the art object
those that are not directly derived from, and therefore do not
other parts of the world. In many places outside of the or capable of shifting. Among the ancient inhabitants of the
Euro-American sphere of influence, the favored media for Americas, for example, objects did not represent a fixed
artists are in fact objects found in nature, constituting reality defined in wordly terms, but rather were means of
elements of the landscape and the body. Far from distancing
meaningful form from natural substances and processes, and
thereby reducing it to a mere sign of its subject matter, these
artists reference the natural world metonymically through
their choice of materials. Once again the number of possible
reflecting and accessing a reality that was cognitively determined, and that thereby defied the integrity of empirically
determined categories. Thus for the prehispanic Inka, as for
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
certain of these rocks represented the ancestors themselves,tional Euro-American expectations of the object often co
clude that others "lack" artistic skill, they "lack" creativ
some of whom could actually come back to life, turning into
human beings capable of fighting a mutual enemy alongsidethey "lack" the ability to replicate natural appearances.
are or were, in other words, inferior. Since one of the ori
"real" men. The Aztecs, for their part, told how a local ruler
encountered, hanging on his kitchen wall, a mask that was functions, if not object(ive)s, of art history was precise
justify such denigration of conquered and colonized popu
audibly moaning. Convinced that the mask's moans portended war, which he did not wish for his people, the rulertions in order to facilitate their exploitation, I think it is
tore the mask from the wall and dashed it to the floor.
history's moral as well as intellectual obligation to redefin
In the examples discussed above there is no sharp division object. Art history needs to recognize, above all, tha
between the world of objects and human beings as subjects.
though objects are surely nice, they are not everything;
This is why inanimate forms can have "souls" and why some should never be the primary subject matter, the m
of them, like the Rapa Nui kava kava statues, must be treated objective of the discipline. The art object, as I've trie
like living beings. Among some rural Nahuatl speakers demonstrate, under the best of circumstances cannot alw
today, stones are still believed able to come to life at night to tell us what we really want or need to know about e
attack their owners. The form of an object, moreover, often significant form or the formulation of significance. By it
has been dictated to a person by a dream or vision, the ripped from its own historical, cognitive, and moral cont
nature of which, because it is a source of personal power, in fact, the object can be quite misleading.
It doesn't really matter, in other words, whether or not
must be kept secret. As the anthropologist Edmund Carpenter has noted, such forms, for this reason, may be encoded as dolls are works of art, nor does it matter whether or not
cryptic pictographs, or else kept well hidden, if not sooner or kava kava statue is a doll. What matters is that, together,
later destroyed. Some are simply never represented in can teach us something about the many ways, some diffe
material form at all. In this realm of what Carpenter calls and some remarkably similar, in which people the w
"invisible art," objects are seldom merely "signs" that can be over-including Euro-Americans-have conceived of
easily decoded and "read," for objects do not just refer to used objects. More important, they can shed light on
things; they themselves are, or are of, those things. In people construct meaning in their lives-on how they ne
semiotic parlance, there is a point at which they function as tiate the tensions between the material and the nonmateri
both the signifier and the signified. Such objects, moreover, between the worlds of form and formlessness. This, it se
do not automatically occupy a privileged place in the to me, is where the big questions tend to lie, and t
epistemological scheme of things, for they represent only therefore should be the real object of art history.
where "great" art objects typically represent the most signifi- research in Native American and Pacific Islands art. She specz
in the art of the Nahuatl-speaking Aztecs of prehispanic C
cant forms.
Because we bring to the study of other peoples our own Mexico and zs currently working on the rhetorical role of g
culture-bound, historically determined notions of what an art signs in Aztec art [Department of Art History, Universi
object is and should be, we often miss what is truly significant Calzfornza, Los Angeles, Calif. 90024].
ends of art history, who and what it'sfor (in the academy
market, the museums, the media, and the culture indus
generally) is a matter of argument rather than habit.
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ticating challenges to those objects. The discipline is now, as attention. Erwin Panofsky pointed out long ago that every-
Donald Preziosi puts it, more Roman than Greek, "like the
one's monuments are everyone else's documents and vice
versa.4 As Adrian Rifkin forces the issue in relation to
Pantheon ... a vast aggregate of materials, methods, proto-
cols, technologies, institutions, social ritual, and systems of Demoiselles d'Avignon, in what museum should it be put? In
circulation and inventory."2 But within this diversity some the museum of colonial oppression and liberation (its "prim
paradigmatic assumptions about the boundaries, objects,tivism"), the museum of gender formation (its siting, like th
and purposes of the field are clearly suffering from fatigue,
of so many of the canonical works of modernism, in t
and where that's the case any "new" or more properly criticalbrothel and its anxieties about venereal disease), or th
art history "kills only the dead."3
museum of social climbing (as the product of a provinc
To speak of "art" is to speak with a certain intensity of a Spaniard making a name for himself in the Parisian avantspecially valued but arbitrarily constructed category of hu- garde)? To put the question in this way is to caricature it,
man production. It could be argued that when the discipline he says, but also to highlight the naturalizing of "serie
emerged in its modern form "art" was (almost) still objects"
a
into fixed categories of attention."
consistent if honorific category. Most of the visual field was The art historian deals with physically surviving, intentio
taken up with buildings, crafted objects and surfaces, sculp-ally crafted, and (often) emotionally resonant objects, rath
tures, paintings, prints, and perhaps illustrated books that than the historian's documents and events. This offers the
we might recognize as conventional objects of art-historical illusion of continuity-of contact with a real and knowable
study. Even if this was once the case, it hasn't been so for
past-that can mask both the artifice of history and the
more than a century. Art has become a mandarin activity inradical instability of the object.
the age of mechanical (and electronic) reproduction. Daily The surviving object is not the "same" object. Physical
life is dominated by a kind of visual ecology of cinema,depradations will almost certainly have marked it, sometimes
television, photography, advertising, and printed ephemera in ways anticipated or even intended by its maker, but
of all kinds. This mass "visual culture" is the object of cultural
beyond reversal, and beyond any identifiably pristine state to
studies, another discipline-or inter- or antidiscipline-- which conservation can return it. More to the point, an object
welded together from component parts (in this case sociol- that encounters new sites, new audiences, and therefore new
ogy and literary and film studies). In effect, a division of labor
ways of seeing and talking about "art" is changed by those
took place. Art history, rooted in nineteenth-century distinc-encounters. The altarpiece leaves its liturgical context and
tions between "civilization" (a matter of social and technologi-enters the museum; the Mona Lisa, after three hundred
for which "culture" is to be understood in Raymond Wilethnographic collections to twentieth-century art museums,
liams's terms as "a whole way of life," has concentrated on
and Navajo blankets-tribal artifacts woven by women-are
mass and popular arts. There is no good reason for this: thatexhibited in American galleries as the works of anonymous
is, there is no reason why art history cannot extend beyond"masters" of innocent abstraction;7 so that the question to
its conventional (and conventionally valued) objects, though ask, as Nelson Goodman famously put it, is not so much
"What is Art?" but "When is Art?"8
it may have to revise its procedures; and no reason why
"cultural studies" analyses should not extend to high cultural Art history takes the object for granted as that which the
objects of study.
discipline explains, or interprets, or in some way accounts
Every discipline is constituted not only by its objects but byfor; but art history, which may have or borrow theories of
that to which it objects, disputing claims to the same epistemoagency, causation, social determination, or psychic investlogical territory and outlawing certain projects as somethingment, has no clear conception of the ontological and semielse (studies in patronage, perception, psychology, criticism,otic status of objects and their relation to language. As
or sociology). Art history objects-its inception depends on
Michael Baxandall has pointed out, unraveling a passage by
it-to any sense that "art" might be even at moments an
Kenneth Clark on Piero's Baptzsm of Christ, we tend to read as
unremarkable aspect of everyday life, or so fully imbricateda seamless description of an object an account made up (in
with other activities as to be the unnecessary or impossible this case) of "causal," "comparison," and "effect" words that
object of specialist inquiry. Art history requires not only a is really a description of its perceived effect.9
concept of art (and therefore of "not-art") that may or may Objects are always in circulation and embedded in disnot be consonant with the cultures it studies, but also a field
course, which is to say in shifting and overlapping systems of
of objects sufficiently unified and continuous to justify value
a
and meaning that don't pause at the "frame." It is the
"history"-a descriptive, explanatory, and interpretativeobject as "text," a more porous entity than the physical
narrative-and (now) a "museum," a special site of publicartifact, that is the object of study of all approaches centered
1. J. Wolff, Aesthetics and the Soczology ofA rt, London, 4. E. Panofsky, "The History of Art as a Humanistic 7. R. Parker and G. Pollock, Old Mistresses, London,
1983, 58.
2. D. Preziosi, Rethinking Art Hzstory, New Haven, Garden City, N.Y., 1955, 33.
1989, 34.
The New Art History, ed. A. L. Rees and F. Borzello,Taste," Journal of the Hzstory of Ideas, 1, 2, 1940,
207-24.
London, 1986, 19.
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
on the social production of meaning (including the iconoother, and psychoanalysis-the discourse that problematizes
graphic, the psychoanalytic, the semiotic, and the sociohistorigender-can slip back into the unproblematic gendering of
ground it historically can result in a conception of theof historical inquiry (a matter of evidence and reliable
witnesses);'14 on the subjective investments in '"judgment"
artwork as a transparent vehicle for (to be sure, social and
itself (which Freud described as a continuation of the original
historical) "meanings" conveyed to a passively consuming
spectator. There is a related, methodological difficulty hereprocesses of introjection and expulsion, by which the subject
in that artworks are explained in terms of the social context
takes things into itself or expels them according to what it
deems good or bad, pleasurable or unpleasurable);'5 and on
of their production and initial reception, and "context"-like semiosis-has no end outside the historian's narrative.10
what art and art history do for us. "Indeed, our love of the
The problem lies precisely in conceiving the object as a social aesthetic object is partly founded in our need to inquire of its
product of conscious agency, without reducing its explana- context or framework, which serves to epitomize our own
tion to an account of the artist's intentions or pathology, or ofstatus as the product of a framework. There can be no history
any particular zeitgeist, ideology, or set of social relationswithout a potential history of ourselves."'6
more, socially, discursively, and in terms of its affect, than a the signifying process to be ... identity rather than the art
bounded artifact-and obdurately an object in the sense that object or text.'17 This claim is rooted in psychoanalysis, but
it is not fully transparent to language and understanding."I If there is a parallel argument in the sociology of taste,
certain objects did not appear, for whatever reasons, reso-associated with Bourdieu,'8 to the effect that refined and
nant but silent or opaque to us, we should run out of things to discriminating discourse about a special category of valued
say and be done with them. If art history produces its objects objects ("art") simultaneously discriminates between catego(rather than simply discovering them), it never seems to do ries of (classed) consumer. An education in taste (an educaso to our final satisfaction. So we stay in business, sometimes tion in art history) is an investment in cultural capital. From
turning to new objects but mostly reworking what we have tothis perspective, otherwise divergent histories (formalist,
say about the old ones. We see this as a tribute to their semiotic, sociohistorical) share a common disregard for the
richness and complexity, but it's also a symptom of thecontribution of their object(s) to the production of subjectivinvestment we have in "art." Adrian Stokes said that art gives ity. And that includes our subjectivity, since there is certainly
us the sensation of having our cake and eating it ("without
destruction, surfeit, or waste-product").12 In talking about
The subject/object polarity so central to the Western and how you do it. The professional question is no longer a
epistemological tradition does not obtain in the same way in straight "What's your period?" There are classicists, medievalpsychoanalysis. Conventionally, an object is something pres- ists, and modernists, but also Islamicists and Africanists,
ent to the senses of an observing subject, something to which Marxists, feminists and deconstructionists. Most large and
action is directed, something external to consciousness. Inambitious departments, like zoos, aim to have one or two of
grammatical terms we can all be subjects or objects: subject to everything.
meaning (an object of reference) or the subject of meaning
(an active "I"). Psychoanalysis undermines commonsense but real case for sometimes writing history backwards."'9 Of
distinctions between object and subject and commonsense course, in a limited but real sense history is always written
identifications of objects with unitary "things". The Freudian backwards. All history, as Benedetto Croce put it, is a history
object is not opposed to subjective being, nor is it necessarily of the present. Historians have to a professional degree the
of projection and introjection, undermine any Cartesianobjects are the effects). Reasons are advanced as to why a
division between subject and other, ego and object. The work is as it is, as the consequence of a particular chain o
intellectual consequence of this is ultimately a parallel events. Once it has settled into an evolutionary narrative (still
undermining of any clear distinction between neutral, disin- the discipline's prevailing plot structure), it becomes difficult
terested, detached, and "objective" knowledge or truth on to conceive of the object or value it differently. Cezanne saw
the one hand and invested, idiosyncratic, empathetic, situ- the true path of art's evolution before the rest of us, and the
ated "subjectivity" on the other. "Object" doesn't appear inhistorian (slightly less prescient) secures that judgment in
the indices of art-history texts, even methodologically reflec- perpetuity. Hence Charles Harrison's caveat that it may be
tive ones, unless they are psychoanalytically oriented like,"salutary to conceive ofa possible world in which the grounds
say, The Crztical Wrztings ofAdrzan Stokes, which lists a variety ofjudgment never did change in Cezanne's favor, a history of
of compound forms including good-, bad-, internal-, mini- art in which he remained incompetent and unregarded" and
mum-, self-sufficient-, part-, and whole-object. Of course, a to consider another history, not of "triumphs of the will" bu
psychoanalytic approach can be used as reductively as any of"unredeemed incompetence" and "unpainted and unpaint-
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
able pictures," a history of "the wasted and the unauthenti- The overview-the totalizing God's eye view-combines
vision, distance, mastery, and the illusion of disembodiment
cated, the abandoned and the destroyed."20
It is not quite clear how we can have historical knowledge,at the cost of relegating other views to the margins (or the
plausible narratives. There is no one authoritative position ofinvolve embodiment, empathy, identification, and the capac
overview from which history is written or experienced. Theity to live comfortably with contingency and difference. A
Jane Gallop asks: "Might not one of the goals of what we so
best we can expect is a field of generous, intelligent, and
skeptical conversation about the past-which is to say, about ambiguously call 'women's studies' be to call into questio
representations from and of the past-adequate to itsthe oppressive effects of an epistemology based on the
encounter with the historically foreign object) "a preparedinterest in the history of works by women, in the gendered
gation," in Poststructuralzsm and the Questzon of His- New Lzterary Hzstory x, 1978-79, 464.
11. See N. Bryson, Art Bulletzn, LXXV, 2, 1993, tory,
337, ed. D. Attridge, G. Bennington, and R. Young,20. C. Harrison, "On the Surface of Painting,"
Cambridge, 1987, 126-36.
review of G. Didi-Huberman, Devant limage: QuesCrztzcal Inquzry, xv, 2, 1989, 299.
tzon posie aux fins de l'hzstoire de lart, Paris, 1990,15.
onS. Freud, "Negation" (1925), in Standard Edz- 21. Winnicott developed the concepts of goodthe claim that "the discipline's own mode of knowltzon of the Complete Psychologzcal Works of Szgmund enough mothering and the good-enough holding
edge (lucid, rational, explanatory) has historically
Freud, ed. James Strachey, London, 1961, xix, 235.environment in his work on the mother-child rela-
dialectically construed). Numerous intellectual strategies, events but the results," requires its own criteria. "A purely
from the Hegelian Zeitgeist to Riegl's Kunstwollen have been historical study," Panofsky concluded, "whether it proceeds
developed to overcome this division, one that Panofsky from the history of form or the history of content, never
characterized in his critical assessment of Riegl, as caught explains the work of art as a phenomenon except in terms of
between "art" and "history."I On the one hand, history, with other phenomena. Historical study does not draw on a
its emphasis on causes and effects, relations among different higher source of perception."2 An extreme case of this
kinds of knowledge, political and social as well as artistic, dilemma has traditionally been represented by architectural
explains the work of art by referring to external phenomena. history, with its spatially defined monuments resting uneasily
On the other hand, the art object, subject as art to internal on the shifting narrative ground of their temporal historicizaaesthetic criteria that establish it as unique, demands appre- tion.
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ence of 'the end of history.' "6 Here he takes his cue fro
problem might have been resolved. So much so that manyanthropologist Arnold Gehlen, who found the term use
critics have theorized the possibility of "the end of art sum up the mentality that followed postmodern disillu
history," as if the incursions of theory have made it impos- ment in the great nineteenth-century narratives of hist
sible, any more, to practice what from Vasari to Winckel-progress-the moment, as Gehlen says, when "prog
mann, Waagen to Wolfflin, Worringer to Warburg, Riegl to becomes routine."7 Vattimo sees such routinization in the
Panofsky was considered, in Panofsky's elegant definition, developments of technology and consumerism that wh
"art history as a humanistic discipline." By thus dissolvingcontinuously renewed, nevertheless stay the same:
history, it is thought, art history might attain a new status in
postmodernity as an interpretative, interdisciplinary, relativistic member of a group of domains all concerned with the
general question of "visual studies."
of Architecture?4 Now, admittedly, two of the publications development reinforced by the daily newspaper-now come
cited add a question mark after their disquieting titles, toto a halt. The "master" narrative, once a secularization of
soften the blow, so to speak; but overall a certain pessimism religious salvation, now fails, and multiple other possible
would appear to have overtaken the humanities in the latenarratives rise up. In this argument, Vattimo extends Gehlen
twentieth century. Thus Vattimo explores the connection he in order to "prove" postmodernism: "What legitimates
sees between nihilism and postmodernism that announces,post-modernist theories and makes them worthy of discusin his terms, the "dissolution of history"; the architects sion is the fact that their claim of a radical 'break' with
gathered in Vienna under the aegis of the radical group modernity does not seem unfounded as long as th
Coop Himmelblau proclaimed the "end of architecture" atobservations on the post-historical character of contem
least as we have known it since antiquity; and Belting (who, as rary existence are valid."'
This discussion of postmodernism and history would
an art historian, grudgingly admits that some form of art
history will inevitably continue) is convinced of the end "of entirely superfluous for us if it were not for the fact that
that conception of a universal and unified 'history of art'history is and always has been a discourse dependent on th
which has so long served . . both artist and art historian.'"" of history; from Vasari, through Winckelmann, to W61ffli
Now, while these recent varieties of the disease of ending and even Janson, art historians have modeled their narrat
do not, as we know, arrive without their own history in the forms and explanatory fictions on those of historians a
modern period-we think of the long tradition of endings philosophers of history. We would then expect, in a gener
from the 1830s including Hegel's own "end of art" and condition of posthistory, to find a state of post-art-histor
1 E. Panofsky, "The Concept of Artistic Volition,"3. H. Belting, The End of the Hzstory of Art?, trans.and Manifestos, ed. P Noever, Munich and Vienna,
1993.
trans. K.J. Northcott andJ Snyder, Crztzcal Inquiry,C. S. Wood, Chicago, 1987.
viii, 1, 1981, 18. (This essay was originally pub-4. G. Vattimo, The End of Modernity Nihilism and5. Belting (as in n. 3), ix.
lished as "Der Begriff des Kunstwollens," ZeztschrzftHermeneutics in Postmodern Culture, trans. and intro. 6. Vattimo (as in n. 4), 4.
fur Asthetik und allgemeine Kunstwissenschaft, xRv,J. R. Snyder, Baltimore, 1988; Coop Himmelblau, 7. A. Gehlen, cited by Vattimo (as in n. 4), 7
1920, 321-22.)
Z. Hadid, S. Holl, T. Mayne, E. O. Moss, C. Pin6s,
2. Ibid., 18.
and L. Woods, The End ofA rchitecture? Documents
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
part of his Lives called "history as the mirror of human diately see the "posthistoric" as a natural indeed, inevitable,
life"-has been dissolved and fragmented, apparently for outcome of historicist thought. At all events, it is possible t
reread art history as an academic discipline that has always
good.
Or so the postmodernists tell us. In fact, the story that I
have been telling from a reading of Vattimo and Belting is,
tions in the field, and many still bear the traces of their
former positions in "universal history." In other words, it is in
mutation.11
Thus, a fruitful first step to absorbing into art history the new
hitherto neglected, but now newly translated, essay "Perspective as Symbolic Form," in his Origin ofPerspectzve; MartinJa
has interrogated the French tradition of visual thought from
8. Ibid.
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Not only is it a question of rereading what has "not beenwork for us today, when the prototypical art historian is not
read" before, and reestablishing its place in a broader history
necessarily assumed to hunt regularly at weekends; but
of ideas and practices; it is also a question of entirely
Panofsky concludes with a more evocative example:
reconceptualizing the artistic objects-their spatial and environmental conditions. This task is not simply "revisionist"; It has rightly been said that theory, if not received at the
history itself changes its shapes and forms under such door of an empirical discipline, comes into the chimney
scrutiny. In a recent essay in Critical Inquiry, Carlo Ginzburg like a ghost and upsets the furniture. But it is no less true
theorist "to that between two neighbors who have the right Anthony
of
Vidler zs chair and professor of art history at the Unzve
of California, Los Angeles. His most recent book is The Arch
shooting over the same district, while one of them owns the
gun and the other all the ammunition."'13 Both parties, he tural Uncanny: Essays in the Modern Unhomely (19
concluded, would be well advised to realize this condition of [Department ofArt History, University of California, Los Ang
Calif 90024].
their partnership. Perhaps this metaphor does not quite
13. E. Panofsky, "The History of Art as a Humanistic Discipline" (1940), in Meaning in the Visual Arts
14. Ibid.
This content downloaded from 130.58.64.71 on Tue, 13 Sep 2016 05:55:15 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms