COHEN - Reflections On Habermas On Democracy PDF
COHEN - Reflections On Habermas On Democracy PDF
COHEN - Reflections On Habermas On Democracy PDF
Reflections on Habermas on
Democracy
JOSHUA COHEN*
Abstract. Jrgen Habermas is a radical democrat. The source of that self-designation
is that his conception of democracywhat he calls discursive democracyis
founded on the ideal of a self-organizing community of free and equal citizens, coordinating their collective affairs through their common reason. The author discusses
three large challenges to this radical-democratic ideal of collective self-regulation:
1) What is the role of private autonomy in a radical-democratic view? 2) What role
does reason play in collective self-regulation? 3) What relevance might a radicaldemocratic outlook have for contemporary democracies? The author addresses these
questions by considering Habermas answers, and then presenting alternative
responses to them. The alternatives are also radical-democratic in inspiration, but
they draw on a richer set of normative-political ideas than Habermas wants to rely
on, and are more ambitious in their hopes for democratic practice.
I. Radical Democracy
Jrgen Habermas is a radical democrat (Habermas 1996a, xliiiii). The source
of that self-designation is that his conception of democracywhat he calls
discursive democracyis founded on the abstract ideal of a self-organizing community of free and equal citizens, coordinating their collective
affairs through their common reason (Habermas 1996a, 7). In this paper, I
discuss three large challenges to this radical-democratic ideal of collective
self-regulation:
1) What is the role of private autonomy in a radical-democratic view?
2) What role does reason play in collective self-regulation?
* I am grateful to Oliver Gerstenberg and Kenneth Baynes for discussion of the material in
section II, to Sebastiano Maffettone for making available a draft of his essay on Liberalism and
Its Critique, and to Leonardo Avritzer and Joshua Flaherty for extensive discussion of many
themes in this essay. I presented earlier versions at a Political Theory Workshop at Nuffield
College, Oxford, and to the McGill University Philosophy Department. I also wish to thank
Jrgen Habermas for comments on an earlier draft. My broader intellectual debt to Habermas
should be clear from virtually everything I have written. I am pleased to have this occasion for
expressing that debt.
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999, 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
386
Joshua Cohen
Habermas on Democracy
387
For this reason, Habermas understands his view as having important affinities with anarchist and
socialist ideas, once the normative core of those ideas is properly understood. Thats because
he supposes (correctly, I think) that the normative core is provided by the ideal of a free association among equals, guiding the exercise of their collective power through their common reason.
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999.
388
Joshua Cohen
not the distinction between a decision-making elite and others subject to the
decisions of that elite, and the consequent need to organize the exercise of
power by that elite, but the horizontal, communicative relation among equal
citizens; democracy establishes a framework for that relation and makes the
exercise of collective power sensitive to it.
Such a conception of democracy has two components. First, one must
describe the content of the abstract conception: What, more precisely, is it for
a political society to be a self-organizing community of free and equal citizens, and for the exercise of collective power to trace to the free communication of citizens? Assume as background that the conception is addressed
to a pluralistic society, whose members embrace competing philosophies of
life; a reflective culture, that self-consciously embraces a distinction between
the fact that a practice is socially accepted and the legitimacy of the practice
(between facticity and validity); a society whose complexity, size, and pluralism preclude social coordination through communication alone, as distinct
from market exchange and administrative power; and a society whose members engage in strategic action (Habermas 1996a, 25). What could popular
self-organization and self-government possibly amount to under these conditions? How could free communication among citizens play a regulative
role in the political life of such a society? Perhaps under these conditions the
ideal of a self-organizing community of free and equal citizens loses its
capacity to guide social and political arrangements. The first task, then, is to
address this concern: to show how a radically democratic republic might
even be conceived today (Habermas 1996b, 471).
Second, one needs to consider whether such a society is possible. Here we
take the content of the normative idealsay, of Habermas discourse model
of democracywhich is developed on the social-political assumptions just
noted, which include no unfavorable assumptions about power and human
motivation. And we ask: Can this ideal be realized, given the realities of contemporary power and human motivation? Or do sociological and psychological realism imply that we must reduce our normative expectations, and
adopt a more minimalist understanding of democracy, according to which
democracy is a system of competitive elections in which citizens chose who
will rule, rather than in any more substantial sense a system of self-rule?
Of the three questions that I propose to discuss in this essay, two fall under
the problem of content, the third under the problem of possibility.
1) I begin with the role of rights of private autonomy in a democratic constitution. The place of such rights in a radical democratic view is uncertain.
One might think that a radical democrat, concerned with the self-rule of
citizens, will make the protection of personal liberties dependent on how the
people choose to exercise their collective power. But a radical-democratic
view that cannot provide personal liberties with a secure basis will seem, to
that extent, unreasonable. In response to this concern, Habermas argues that
rights of private and public autonomy (rights of participation) are equally
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999.
Habermas on Democracy
389
390
Joshua Cohen
Habermas on Democracy
391
Habermas rejects the idea that either public or private autonomy is more
basic: The requirement of ensuring private autonomy cannot legitimately
be imposed on a people, but a legitimate legal order cannot fail to protect
private autonomy. Instead, he argues that civic and private autonomy are
co-originalequally fundamental: The universal right to equal liberties
may neither be imposed as a moral right that merely sets an external constraint on the sovereign legislator, nor be instrumentalized as a functional
prerequisite for the legislators aims (Habermas 1996a, 104). In Habermas
own explanation of co-originality, each form of autonomy is required to
explain the other; they are, as it were, co-originating, as well as co-original.
But the claim about co-origination is best understood as a theory about why
the two forms of autonomy are co-original, and not as identical to the thesis
of co-originality itself.2
More particularly, the notion of co-originality implies the following: A
democratic process of legitimate lawmaking must ensure a variety of equal
liberties to citizens, including both communicative-participatory liberties
and personal liberties. Providing both is constitutive of a process of legitimate law-making. So, for example, just as a process of legitimate law-making
cannot ensure rights of political participation, association, and expression
only for some, it cannot establish a system of legal rights in which the rights
of conscience, privacy, or bodily integrity required for personal independence in pursuing a private conception of the good are available only to
some citizens. Though the specific rights of private autonomy that receive
protection are not given by the principle itself, but need to be specified
through a democratic process, liberties of both kinds are constitutive of a
process of legitimate lawmaking.
The argument for this conclusion proceeds (schematically) as follows.3
2
Thus, Rawls agrees that both forms of autonomy are equally fundamental but argues for this
conclusion by connecting each to a fundamental aspect of the moral powers of citizens, rather
than by showing that each is in some way required by the other (see Rawls 1995; 1987, esp. secs.
5, 6). Dworkin (1996, 1926, esp. 256), too, endorses the idea that both forms of autonomy are
equally fundamental, arguing that (roughly) democracy fosters freedom only if the subjects of
the laws can also regard themselves as its authors. But to regard themselves as its authors, they
must identify with the political communityunderstand themselves as its moral members.
And they can understand themselves as moral members only if they preserve independent
judgment about the values that will govern their own individual lives and about the quality of
the communitys decisions. Personal liberties are, in turn, required for this requisite
independence. Dworkins account seems close to at least part of what Habermas identifies as
the intuitive idea behind his account of the mutually presupposing character of public and
private autonomy: That [. . .] citizens can make adequate use of their public autonomy only if,
on the basis of their equally protected private autonomy, they are sufficiently independent
(Habermas 1998a, 261, emph. added). Still, Rawls and Dworkin present explicitly normative
treatments of the importance of such individual independence, whereas Habermas theory aims
to derive the requirement of independence, and associated rights of private autonomy, from the
need to institutionalize popular sovereignty and democratic process through law. My own
discussion is also explicitly normative, and draws on the idea of respect for those who hold
views that are reasonable, politically speaking. See below, sec. III.
3
I am not confident that I have the argument right. I draw particularly on discussions in Habermas
1996a, 1998, and on discussions with Joshua Flaherty, Kenneth Baynes, and Oliver Gerstenberg.
392
Joshua Cohen
Step 1. Begin with the fact of law: that coordination and regulation under
modern conditions proceed through law. This is a basic fact of modern social
life, following from the functional requirements of a complex society, with
a considerable degree of decentralized decision-making.
Step 2. The rule of law leads to a scheme of minimal personal liberty. Two
aspects of the rule of law lead to this result. First, law is Janus-faced: Law
is a distinctive form of social coordination in that it permits individuals to
choose whether to comply for strategic or normative reasonsfrom fear of
sanctions or from respect for the laws legitimacythus assigning latitude
to act according to personal preferences. By leaving reasons for compliance
open to choice, and by rejecting the idea that individuals can be held
accountable for their reasons for compliance, legal regulation establishes a
minimal order of liberty, the liberty not to give an account of reasons for
conduct: Private autonomy extends as far as the legal subject does not have
to give others an account or give publicly acceptable reasons for her action
plans (Habermas 1996a, 120).
Moreover, it is a feature of a legal order that individuals are at liberty to
act as they wish unless the law prohibits it: Modern law as a whole implements the principle that whatever is not explicitly prohibited is permitted
(Habermas 1998a, 256). That is, individuals are to be free specifically from
coercive collective power unless it is used to enforce valid law.
I dont propose to focus on these claims about what is ingredient in the
rule of law as such, though I do want to draw attention to two limitations of
the scheme of liberty that follows from the rule of law. First, the claim is not
that legality as suchthe very existence of a legal codegives us a requirement of equality or a principle of equal subjective liberties, according to
which each person is entitled to the same liberties as others. Instead, the
existence of a legal code implies only that some individuals have some rights
of private autonomy. Furthermore, the rights of private autonomy that
emerge from the principle that whatever is not prohibited is permitted are
very weak in that there are no limits on what might be prohibited, or for
what reasons.
Step 3. Next, moving from legality as such to legitimate law, we introduce
a principle of legitimacy: The discourse principle, an interpretation of the
idea of impartiality, according to which practical norms, whether legal or
moral, are legitimate if and only if all possibly affected persons could agree to
them as participants in rational discourses (Habermas 1996a, 107). This
Principle explicates the claim to justifiability or rightness characteristic of the
Janus-faced law as such, one face of which looks to legitimacy.
I say that we introduce this principle, but the claim is that the discourse
principle explicates the claims to normative validity characteristic of the
(Janus-faced) law as such. If that is right, then the discourse principle is laws
own implicit standard of validity, and any implications that follow from
applying the discourse principle to the legal medium are implicit elements
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999.
Habermas on Democracy
393
of legality as such (though the connection between legality and those implications is not analytic).
Step 4. A legal code, which must establish some system of rights, can be
approved by all affected parties (approved by them through rational discourses) only if that code assigns equal liberties to each person, which
strengthens the assurance of personal autonomy; for only if the code
incorporates this equal liberty principle can the addressees of the legal code
also regard themselves as its authors:
Norms appearing in the form of law entitle actors to exercise their rights or liberties.
However, one cannot determine which of these laws are legitimate simply by looking
at the form of individual rights. Only by bringing in the discourse principle can one
show that each person is owed a right to the greatest possible measure of equal liberties
that are mutually compatible. (Habermas 1996a, 123)
The precise argument for this claim about how the discourse principle (the
requirement of impartiality) leads to equal liberties is not entirely clear,
though the basic idea is familiar, at least since Hobbes derivation of the
second law of nature: Assuming that individuals are legitimately concerned
to protect their own fundamental interests, we cannot expect universal agreement on the code unless it provides equal protection of personal liberty. Thus,
if law as such implies a minimal order of liberty, legitimate law requires a
stronger scheme of rights to liberty.
Step 5. To apply the discourse principle to lawusing it to judge the
acceptability of legal regulationsrequires that law be available as a medium
for collective regulation. But citizens can only apply the discourse principle
to law if that same legal order already ensures their rights of public autonomy: That is, they can only judge whether those affected could consent after
reasoned consideration if they have rights to reflect, to communicate, to
associate, and to bring their judgments to bear on proposed regulation. So,
we get a requirement of democracy, as the way in which the discourse principle is brought to bear on evaluating proposed laws.
So public autonomy requires private autonomy because public autonomy
requires a legal order, which order is legitimate only if it ensures equal
liberties; and private requires public, because the legal regulation of private
autonomy is legitimate only if it emerges from a discursive process that
ensure political rights. Thus we have co-originality.
The equal liberty principle that comes with legitimate law only gives us
the requirement that there be some system of equal liberties for all; it does not
give determinate content to that system. In particular, specifically liberal rights
to conscience, bodily integrity, privacy, property, etc.do not emerge simply
from the requirement that the legal code be specified through a process that
satisfies the discourse principle, but emerge instead (if they do) from the actual
exercise of civic autonomy under particular historical conditions: basic rights
must be interpreted and given concrete shape by a political legislature in response
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999.
394
Joshua Cohen
Habermas on Democracy
395
396
Joshua Cohen
Habermas on Democracy
397
398
Joshua Cohen
Habermas on Democracy
399
cast in terms of the value of public order, except in the most extreme
conditions. To be sure, not all citizens acknowledge the obligations in question. But even those who do not can see the weightiness of those reasons,
within the outlooks of other politically reasonable citizens.
As these two observations indicate, pressure for liberty comes from at
least two sources: The pluralism of philosophies of life among political reasonable citizens leads to the rejection of some bases of restriction as politically weightless; other bases of restriction will not be weightless, but insufficient
to outweigh the reasons that can be acknowledged, consistent with reasonable pluralism, as commending or commanding conduct. Taking these
two considerations together, we have the basis for a strong case for religious,
moral, and nonpolitical expressive liberties: Conduct in these areas is supported by strong (perhaps compelling) reasons, as when religious exercise is
a matter of obligation according to a persons reasonable religious outlook.
Moreover, standard reasons for restrictionreligious and sectarian moral
reasonswill often be weightless.
Given this deliberative rationale for personal liberties, we can see why
their protection would be constitutive of democracy, and how, therefore, we
get co-originality. For imposing regulations in the name of reasons that are
either weightless or of insufficient force to override reasonable demands is a
violation of the fundamental democratic idea that the authorization to
exercise state power must arise from the collective decisions of the equal
members of a society who are governed by that powerthat it must be
supported by reasons that can be shared by the set of politically reasonable
citizens over whom power is exercised. Decisions to regulate are not suitably
collective, for the addressees of the regulations cannot all be included in
their collective authorization.
400
Joshua Cohen
sphere is open-ended, the decision-making procedures are subject to conditions of deliberative-democratic legitimacy: for example, that decisions are
to be founded on reasons; that the processes are to be open and fair; that they
are to be free of coercion; and that results are to be determined by the better
argument (Habermas 1996a, 3056).
This discursive model of democratic process appears to be founded on an
hypothesis about the connection between idealized discourse and actual
democratic decision-making (understood as proceeding along both tracks).
The central idea is that democratic procedures should produce rational
outcomeswhere rational outcomes are those that would emerge from
idealized discourse. Suppose, then, that we think collective decision-making
as a form of problem solving: The production of legitimate law through
deliberative politics represents a problem-solving procedure that needs and
assimilates knowledge in order to program the regulation of conflicts and
the pursuit of collective goals (Habermas 1996a, 318). Then, a discursively
democratic process of decision-making provides grounds for expecting reasonable solutions to problems:
The democratic procedure is institutionalized in discourses and bargaining processes
(assumed to be fair) by employing forms of communication that promise that all
outcomes reached in conformity with the procedure are reasonable []. Deliberative
politics acquires its legitimating force from the discursive structure of an opinionand will-formation that can fulfill its socially integrative function only because citizens expects its results to have a reasonable quality. (Habermas 1996a, 304, 296)
More generally,
democratic procedure makes it possible for issues and contributions, information
and reasons to float freely; it secures a discursive character for political will-formation; and it thereby secures that fallibilist assumption that results issuing from proper
procedure are more or less reasonable. (Habermas 1996a, 448)
Habermas on Democracy
401
Thus the case for the two-track process is founded on the claim that it will
generate rational outcomes. And that claim is based on the interplay in discursive democracy between an open-ended exploration of problems and
possible solutions, which influences the premises of judgment and decisionmaking in the political system (Habermas 1996b, 4867), and a disciplined,
rational assessment of proposed solutions. This interplay between discovery
and justification supports the presumption that the results will conform to
idealized, discursive problem solving. Because the two phases of reasoning
in the actual process conform to idealized reasoning, the actual process will
generate results like those that idealized discourse would generate:
Thus the normative expectation of rational outcomes is grounded ultimately in the
interplay between institutionally structured political will-formation and spontaneous,
unsubverted circuits of communication in a public sphere that is not programmed to
reach decisions and thus is not organized. (Habermas 1996b, 485)
402
Joshua Cohen
(about the social bases of democratic governance), can be freed from the
pluralists own theory of politics as bargaining between and among groups
that represent well-defined interests. Those insights can be wedded instead
to a conception of politics in which reasoning about the basic terms of association plays a central role. But the marriage requires the idea of the informal,
discursive public sphere, in which all can freely participate, and which has
the capacity to influence opinion through argument, and thereby shape the
agenda of formal politics. This strikes me as a fundamental contribution to
democratic thought: a remarkable reconception, with redemptive promise.
2.
So much for Habermas view. Now I come to the pair of questions I identified earlier: Why should democracy be deliberative? And why should
deliberation be democratic?
First, then, why is it important for democracy to be deliberative? Why
should collective decision-making involve the giving of reasons of suitable
kinds, rather than simply a fair aggregation of citizen interests? One rationale,
already suggested, arises from concerns about the impartial justifiability of
(or, as Habermas puts it, the rationality of) outcomes: the concern captured
in Habermas discourse principle. Suppose we have a hypothetical test of
validity: Outcomes are justified only if they could be accepted by people
who give suitable weight to the reasonable objections of others, assuming
those others to be free and equal. Deliberative democracy, then, may seem a
natural way to achieve such impartially justified outcomes. For it is a form
of democracy that aims to mirror hypothetical conditions of good information, attentiveness to reasons, and regard for others as equals by requiring,
in particular, that the exercise of power be justified by appeal to considerations that others acknowledge as reasons, and assuming a shared commitment to such justification. Bargaining under fair background conditions may
also produce rational outcomes, but deliberation generates a stronger presumption because it requires attentiveness to reasons.
Rawls suggests this thought about the relationship between a hypotheticalcontractual notion of justice and actual political decision-making when he
remarks that his principle of participationrequiring fair political equality
transfers the requirement of equal standing that defines the original position
into the design of the constitution: we have an effective political procedure
that mirrors the fair representation of persons in the original position
(Rawls 1993, 330). Deliberative democracy might be seen as giving this idea
of connecting contractual and actual a Scanlonian twist. Scanlons contractualism (1998, chap. 5) presents an idealized model of moral reasoning
rather suggesting that rational choice under conditions of ignorance can
provide a substitute for such reasoning. Correspondingly, then, instead of
merely transferring a requirement of equal standing or fair representation,
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999.
Habermas on Democracy
403
They have such expectation because actual decision-making, under the conditions of the discursive model, approximates (in ways noted earlier) idealized
deliberation.
Still, the case for the importance of deliberation need not proceed solely in
terms of the requirements on a system of collective decision-making that is
to match the results that would be achieved were decision-making to be
ideally deliberative. The virtues of the deliberative view are also more intrinsic, and allied closely with its conception of binding collective choice, in
particular with the role in that conception of the idea of reasons acceptable
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999.
404
Joshua Cohen
Habermas on Democracy
405
406
Joshua Cohen
Habermas on Democracy
407
408
Joshua Cohen
Habermas on Democracy
409
410
Joshua Cohen
sensors, detect popular concerns that are off the public agenda, suggest
novel solutions to them, and perhaps influence legislation (and ultimately
administration). To demonstrate that possibility, it suffices to show that
under certain circumstances civil society can acquire influence in the public
sphere, have an effect on the parliamentary complex, [] and compel the
political system to switch over to the official circulation of power
(Habermas 1996a, 373). And to make this case, it suffices to show that in
a perceived crisis situation, the actors in civil society [] can assume a
surprisingly active and momentous role (Habermas 1996a, 380).
In saying that this conclusion isto use Michelmans worddispiriting, I
do not disparage at all the momentous role of the social movementsfor
example, feminist and environmentalthat Habermas here has in mind
(Habermas 1996a, 381). But the argument does make democracy, as reconceived, foreign to the settled institutional routines of a modern polity. Except
for the exceptional conditions in which associations break free from the
institutionalized circuit of power, so to speak, the system rules: a reconception with limited redemptive force.7
Before going further, a qualification is in order. The conclusions we should
draw from Habermas account of democratic possibilityhow dispiriting
we should find itdepend on which of two purposes we assign to the argument. On one construction, the aim is simply to show that the old-fashioned,
radical-democratic ideal of a self-governing association of free and equal
citizensauthors of the laws, not merely their addresseesstill can connect
to modern politics, thus turning back realist arguments for less demanding
accounts of democracy. Interpreted this way, the argument succeeds, even if
Habermas is only able to point to occasional disruptions of the normal
routines of institutionalized power. The disruptions suffice as proof of
possibility.
Suppose instead that the purpose of the two-track model, with its sharp
distinction between free-floating discourse in a network of autonomous
associations and institutional decision-making and exercise of power, is to
identify democracys most attractive possibilities. Then the view strikes me
as less compelling. Perhaps because he is principally concerned with the
issue of possibility, Habermas thinks it suffices to make the case for autonomous influence flowing from the periphery, under conditions of crisis. But
once that case is on hand, we can ask whether there are other forms of citizen
participation that would more fully achieve the radical democratic promise.
Those forms would need to meet three conditions: They must permit and
encourage inputs that reflect experiences and concerns that may not
occupy the current agenda (sensors, rooted in local experience and information); they must provide disciplined assessment of proposals through
7
In this respect, Habermas view bears some resemblance to Bruce Ackermans (1991) account
of dualist democracy, with its distinction between normal and constitutional politics.
Habermas on Democracy
411
For discussions of such experiments, see Meares and Kahan 1999; Luria and Rogers 1999;
Meier 2000; Sabel, Fung, and Karkkainen 2000.
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999.
412
Joshua Cohen
public agencies; they are not conventionally private in that they do exercise
problem-solving powers, and their governance works through discussion
among citizens rather than the assignment of ownership rights. Moreover,
they are attractive because they appear to foster two fundamental democratic valuesdeliberation and direct citizen participationwhile potentially
offering advantages as problem-solvers that programs conceived within the
limits of conventional representative democracies do not.
Stated without much detail or nuance, the fundamental idea comprises
the following three elements:
1) Local problem solving through directly-deliberative participation, which
is well-suited to bringing the relevant local knowledge and values to bear in
making decisions. Direct participation helps because participants can be
assumed to have relevant information about the local contours of the problem, and can relatively easily detect both deception by others and unintended consequences of past decisions. Deliberative participation helps
because it encourages the expression of differences in outlook, and the
provision of information more generally: The respect expressed through the
mutual reason-giving that defines deliberation reinforces a commitment to
such conversational norms as sincerity and to solving problems, rather than
to strategic angling for advantage (perhaps by providing misleading information); furthermore, if preferences over outcomes themselves are shaped
and even formed by discussion, and mutual reason-giving reduces disagreements among such preferences, then being truthful will also be good
strategy.
2) With an eye to addressing the narrowness commonly associated with
localism, an institutionalization of links among local unitsin particular, the
institutionalization of links that require separate deliberative units to consider
their own proposals against benchmarks provided by other units. Because
practical reasoning requires a search for best solutions, decision-makers
need to explore alternatives to current practice. A natural place to look for
promising alternativesincluding alternatives previously unimagined in
the local settingis in the experience of units facing analogous problems.
Thus alongside directly-deliberative decision-making we need deliberative
coordination: deliberation among units of decision-making directed both to
learning jointly from their several experiences, and improving the institutional possibilities for such learning. Extending deliberation across units
allows each group to see its viewpoints and proposals in light of alternatives
articulated by the others: in effect, it ensures that the exercise of practical
reason is both disciplined and imaginative.
3) Responsibility for ensuring that deliberation within and among units
meets these conditions, vested ultimately in authorizing and monitoring
agencieslegislatures, agencies, and courts. In contrast to the conventional division of deliberative labor, this responsibility, under conditions of
directly-deliberative polyarchy, is to be discharged by ensuring that the
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999.
Habermas on Democracy
413
414
Joshua Cohen
Habermas on Democracy
415
clarification it can attain. But even the most radical extension and deepening
of the public sphere will be of limited consequence precisely because the
technical demands, to which administration, parliament, and party must
respond, limit the direction that might issue from a more encompassing,
unrestricted discussion among citizens: Communicative power cannot supply a substitute for the systematic inner logic of public bureaucracies. Rather,
it achieves an impact on this logic in a siege-like manner (Habermas 1992;
1996b, 486). In the end, radical democracy on this conception serves more as
a series of remindersthat human communication need not be narrowly
technical, that unsolved problems remain outside the purview of conventional institutionsand a source of new ideas in periods of crisis, than a
program to redirect the ensemble of institutions to ensure a controlling role
for the communicative power of free and equal citizens. I see no compelling
reason for that self-limitation: We should not confuse a proof of possibility
with a redemption of promise.
MIT
Department of Political Science
E53-473
Cambridge, MA 02139
USA
References
Ackerman, Bruce. 1991. We, The People: Foundations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Barry, Brian. 1995. Justice as Impartiality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cohen, Joshua. 1998. Democracy and Liberty. In Deliberative Democracy. Ed. J. Elster.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cohen, Joshua, and Charles Sabel. 1997. Directly-Deliberative Polyarchy. European
Law Journal 3, 4: 31342.
Dorf, Michael, and Charles Sabel. 1998. Constitution of Democratic Experimentalism.
Columbia Law Review 98, 2: 267473.
Dworkin, Ronald. 1996. Freedoms Law. The Moral Reading of the American Constitution.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Gardbaum, Stephen. 1996. Rethinking Constitutional Federalism. Texas Law Review
74: 795838.
Habermas, Jrgen. 1990. Discourse Ethics: Notes on a Program of Philosophical
Justification. In J. Habermas, Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Trans.
C. Lenhardt, and S. Weber Nicholsen. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
. 1992. Further Reflections on the Public Sphere. In Habermas and the Public
Sphere. Ed. C. Calhoun. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
. 1996a. Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and
Democracy. Trans. W. Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
. 1996b. Appendix 1. Popular Sovereignty as Procedure. In J. Habermas,
Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy,
46390. Trans. W. Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Blackwell Publishers Ltd 1999.
416
Joshua Cohen
. 1998a. On the Internal Relation Between the Rule of Law and Democracy. In
J. Habermas, The Inclusion of the Other. Trans. C. Cronin, and P. De Greiff.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
. 1998b. Three Normative Models of Democracy. In J. Habermas, The Inclusion
of the Other. Trans. C. Cronin, and P. De Greiff. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Luria, Daniel, and Joel Rogers. 1999. Metro Futures. Ed. J. Cohen, and J. Rogers.
Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Meares, Tracey, and Dan Kahan. 1999. Urgent Times. Ed. J. Cohen, and J. Rogers.
Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Meier, Deborah. 2000. Schooling a Democracy. Ed. J. Cohen, and J. Rogers. Boston, MA:
Beacon Press (forthcoming).
Michelman, Frank. 1996. Democracy and Positive Liberty. Boston Review 21: 38.
Rawls, John. 1987. The Basic Liberties and Their Priority. The Tanner Lectures on Human
Values. Ed. S. McMurrin. Salt Lake City, UT: University of Utah Press.
. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.
. 1995. Reply to Habermas. Journal of Philosophy 92: 13280.
. 1999. The Idea of Public Reason Revisited. In J. Rawls, Collected Papers.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Sabel, Charles, Archon Fung, and Brad Karkkainen. 2000. Environmental Democracy.
Ed. J. Cohen, and J. Rogers. Boston, MA: Beacon Press (forthcoming).
Scanlon, Thomas M. 1998. What We Owe To Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.