Oikeiosis
Oikeiosis
Oikeiosis
Benajamin Straumann
But among the traits characteristic of man is an impelling desire for society [appetitus soci-
etatis], that is, for the social life – not of any and every sort, but peaceful, and organized
according to the measure of his intelligence, with those who are of his own kind; this
desire the Stoics called oikeiosis.1
I will argue in the present paper that what Grotius presented in the 1625
edition of De iure belli ac pacis as appetitus societatis, and later identified with
oikeiosis, corresponds essentially to the Stoic notion of oikeiosis as put for-
1 De iure belli ac pacis prol. 6: Inter haec autem quae homini sunt propria, est appetitus societatis,
id est communitatis, non qualiscunque, sed tranquillae et pro sui intellectus modo ordinatae cum his
qui sui sunt generis: quam oikeiosin Stoici appellabant. The edition used is B. J. A. de Kanter-
van Hettinga Tromp (ed.), Hugonis Grotii De iure belli ac pacis libri tres, Lugduni Batavorum
1939, reprint Aalen 1993, with additional notes by R. Feenstra and C. E. Persenaire (referred
to as IBP below). The translation is taken from Hugo Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pacis Libri
Tres, trans. F. W. Kelsey, ed. J. B. Scott, Oxford 1925 (The Classics of International Law 3,
vol. 2). Some of the translations, however, have on occasion been modified for the sake of
clarity or accuracy.
2 The view that oikeiosis was not originally a Stoic doctrine, but rather one that can be
shown to have been present in the Peripatos, was put forward by Arnim in 1926 and again by
Dirlmeier. This view is based mainly on the presentation of oikeiosis by Arius Didymus in
Stobaeus, where it is referred to as a part of Peripatetic ethics. Arnim and Dirlmeier regarded
this description as an authentic reflection of Theophrastus’ moral philosophy, see J. von
Arnim, Arius Didymus’ Abriss der peripatetischen Ethik, Vienna-Leipzig 1926 (Akademie der
Wissenschaften in Wien, philosophisch-historische Klasse, Sitzungsbericht 204, 3), 131ff.,
157-161 and F. Dirlmeier, Die Oikeiosis-Lehre Theophrasts, Leipzig 1937, 20ff., 67-72. Max
Pohlenz opposed this view in 1940; according to Pohlenz, the presentation of oikeiosis by
Arius Didymus represents an integration of the true Stoic doctrine of oikeiosis into Peripatetic
ethics attributable to the Academic eclectic Antiochus of Askalon. Thus Theophrastus, as the
source, is eliminated. Brink came to a similar conclusion in 1956 when he claimed Stoic
rather than Peripatetic origins for the doctrine of oikeiosis; see M. Pohlenz, Grundfragen der
stoischen Philosophie, Göttingen 1940 (Abhandlungen der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu
Göttingen, Philosophisch-historische Klasse 3, 26), 1-81 and C. O. Brink, ‘Oikeiosis and
oikeiotes: Theophrastus and Zeno on Nature in Moral Theory’, Phronesis 1 (1955-56), 123-
145.
3 On this issue see Pohlenz, Grundfragen ; Brink, ‘Oikeiosis’; S.G. Pembroke, ‘Oikeiosis’, in
Problems in Stoicism, ed. A.A. Long, London 1971, 114-149; G. Striker, ‘The Role of oikeiosis
in Stoic Ethics’, in Striker, Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics, Cambridge 1996,
281-297; T. Engberg-Pedersen, The Stoic Theory of Oikeiosis, Aarhus 1990.
4 From Striker, ‘The Role’, 281. Cf. Pembroke, ‘Oikeiosis’, 116.
5 See Pembroke, ‘Oikeiosis’, 121, where different kinds of oikeiosis are discussed.
that these two different views correspond to two distinct functions of oikeio-
sis in Stoic philosophy. The first function is to support the Stoic conception
of telos, while the second provides the justification for the notion of justice in
Stoic teaching on virtue,6 although to some extent the second function is
dependent on the first (the teleological) function.
At first sight, Grotius’s appetitus societatis would appear to contain ele-
ments of both uses. The term appetitus brings in the aspect of individual
impulse contained in the first (teleological) use, while societas, as the object
of this impulse, refers more to a notion of oikeiosis as recognition and appre-
ciation of the way in which the societas humani generis belongs to the individ-
ual human being. In his influential description of Grotius’s natural law
approach, Richard Tuck stresses the importance of the impulse for self-
preservation as the basis of this system. He describes Grotius’s refutation of
Carneades’s skepticism7 using the principle of self-preservation as ‘Grotius’s
most powerful and original idea’.8 This alleged originality of Grotius is
founded on a view already put forward by Jean Barbeyrac at the beginning of
the 18th century, in a historic treatise on the development of moral philoso-
phy. Barbeyrac claimed that no arguments against Carneades and his skepti-
cism had been developed during either the classical or medieval periods.
‘According to Barbeyrac, the writers of antiquity and the Middle Ages all
failed to produce an adequate scientific ethics; the Stoics and Cicero [...]
came nearest, but even they were deficient in a number of crucial aspects.’ 9
Tuck himself adheres to Barbeyrac’s view. Not only does he see Grotius’s
6 Striker, ‘The Role’, 282. See also L. Winkel, ‘Die stoische oikeiosis-Lehre und Ulpians
Definition der Gerechtigkeit’, Zeitschrift der Savigny-Stiftung für Rechtsgeschichte romani-
stische Abteilung 105 (1988), 669-679.
7 Grotius identified the Academic skeptic Carneades – as presented in Cicero’s De re
publica – as the main spokesman of a branch of skepticism that contests the existence of any
natural law. Cicero had already used Carneades as the representative of certain skeptic views
that had previously constituted part of the Sophist repertoire, and Grotius was familiar with
the passage in De re publica from Lactantius, Divinae institutiones 5, 16, 3. He discusses
Carneades’s case for skepticism in IBP prol. 5.
8 Richard Tuck, ‘The “Modern” Theory of Natural Law’, in The Languages of Political
Theory in Early-Modern Europe, ed. A. Pagden, Cambridge 1987, 113. There have been some
challenges to this position in the literature. An essay by Shaver rightly makes the point that
Grotius’s case against Carneades’s skepticism is based less on the principle of self-preserva-
tion and rather more on the social nature of human beings, although Shaver does not address
the classical dimension of this argument. See R. Shaver, ‘Grotius on Scepticism and Self-
Interest’, Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 78 (1996), 27-47.
9 Tuck, ‘The “Modern” Theory’, 107.
system of natural law as a Humanist refutation of Academic skepticism
based, ultimately, on the principle of self-preservation, but he also agrees
with Barbeyrac in regarding this refutation as a revolutionary and specifi-
cally modern argument first presented by Grotius.10
In the discussions that follow it will be argued that this is not the case and
that, on the contrary, Grotius accepted the arguments put forward by Cicero
against Carneades’s criticism of natural law and made use of them. The rea-
son why Cicero’s arguments in favor of a natural law lent themselves to Gro-
tius was that both Cicero’s and Grotius’s doctrines of natural law originally
stem from an attempt to legally defend imperial expansion. In Cicero’s case,
natural law in De republica served as the main argument not against moral
skepticism in general, but against the attacks mounted by Carneades against
the Roman just war doctrine. Grotius, in De iure praedae, drew upon this
Ciceronian tradition, not in order to refute the second order skepticism of
early modern skeptics such as Montaigne or Charron, as Tuck holds, but, in
a context arguably similar to Cicero’s, in mounting his natural law defense of
Dutch military expansion in the East Indies.11 Moreover, the Ciceronian
arguments substantiating the natural law were not limited to the principle of
self-preservation; neither did Grotius limit them in this way. Rather they
were arguments starting from the Stoic notion of oikeiosis in favor of a vir-
tue-based natural law that allowed, however, for being formulated in a sys-
tem of allegedly natural, universal legal rules. I will begin by outlining the
10 Tuck, ‘The “Modern” Theory’, 109-115. Tuck rightly emphasises the Humanist charac-
ter of Grotius’s writing. However he also contrasts it with the writers of the scholasticism of
the school of Salamanca – a disparity that was scarcely perceived by Grotius himself; see IBP
prol. 53, 55, where the late scholars Covarruvias and Vazquez, together with the Humanists
Bodin and Hotman, are cited as representatives of that group of Roman law scholars, qui
humaniores literas cum legum studio conjunxerunt. We should also qualify Tuck’s additional
claim that Grotius, with his Humanist background, was reacting to the challenge of Human-
ist skepticism as propounded by Montaigne and Charron by being the first to present
Carneades as the ‘principal spokesperson’ of this skepticism, and founding his natural law
system on a refutation of Carneades’s arguments. In 1554, Theodor Beza had already identi-
fied Carneades in a theological context as a possible opponent of Calvinist doctrine, while,
within the context of international law, the Spanish lawyer Ayala had subsequently touched
on the dialogue between Laelius and Philus presented in Cicero’s De re publica. Ayala –
whom Grotius describes as a predecessor in the Prolegomena – mentions the debate in his
Praefatio de Jure Belli of 1582, where he expresses the view that Laelius presented a convinc-
ing case against Carneades and in favour of the need for justice in a state. See, on Theodor
Beza, R. Popkin, The History of Scepticism. From Savonarola to Bayle, revised and expanded
edition Oxford 2003, 11.
11 As I will try to argue in detail elsewhere.
various different kinds of oikeiosis in order to obtain a reliable picture of the
context in which Grotius developed his idea of appetitus societatis.12
12 The legal historian Laurens Winkel has published a very useful article on the classical ori-
gins of Grotius’s concept of appetitus societatis, although he focuses mainly on terminological
problems (based on the notes to prol. 6 added by Grotius to the 1642 edition and thereafter)
rather than concepts: L. Winkel, ‘Les origines antiques de l’appetitus societatis de Grotius’,
Legal History Review 68/3 (2000), 393-403. According to Winkel the term appetitus societatis
is not a modern Humanist translation of oikeiosis, since this term can be found in Cicero and
Seneca: Winkel, ‘Origines’, 399-400. However it seems more likely that Grotius’s source was
Vázquez’s Controversiarum illustrium usuque frequentium libri tres (1564), where the naturalis
appetitus societatis is regarded as Peripatetic doctrine (praefatio nn. 121-122.). In addition, Jon
Miller has recently published an article on the Stoic influence on Grotius: J. Miller, ‘Stoics,
Grotius, and Spinoza on Moral Deliberation’, in Hellenistic and Early Modern Philosophy, ed.
J. Miller/B. Inwood, Cambridge 2003, 116-140.
13 In IBP 1, 2, 1, 1. See below, p. 12, at n. 44.
14 See M. Pohlenz, Die Stoa, vol. 1, Göttingen 1959, 113. Zeno was convinced that Epicurus
had used the right methods. Zeno, argues Pohlenz, was the first to address the philosophical
problem of how the first impulse developed in human beings in view of their rational nature,
answering it with the concept of oikeiosis. See also Pohlenz, Grundfragen, 40, where Pohlenz
attributes the Stoic attempt to begin the presentation of oikeiosis in the earliest stages of
human development after birth to the influence of Epicurus. On the Epicurean version of
oikeiosis, where desire is seen as proton oikeion, see Jacques Brunschwig, ‘The Cradle Argu-
ment in Epicureanism and Stoicism’, in The Norms of Nature: Studies in Hellenistic Ethics, ed.
M. Schofield/G. Striker, Cambridge 1986, 115-116.
living beings observed in a later stage of development might already be cor-
rupt, and could therefore no longer be used to exemplify the effects of
nature.15 Cato’s presentation of the Stoic conception of oikeiosis also takes
the moment of birth as its point of departure.
It is the view of those whose system I adopt, that immediately upon birth (for that is the
proper place to start from) a living creature feels an attachment for itself [ipsum sibi conci-
liari], and an impulse to preserve itself [commendari ad se conservandum] and to feel affec-
tion for its own constitution and for those things which tend to preserve that constitution;
while on the other hand it conceives an antipathy to destruction and to those things which
appear to threaten destruction.16
perceive and understand. These are the objects which living beings naturally
pursue. However, with respect to human beings these are not merely objects
that are in accordance with nature (ta kata physin). They are the primary
objects in accordance with nature (ta prota kata physin) – the principia natu-
ralia that are pursued first of all (res, quae primae appetuntur). Grotius was
well aware of this distinction.20 It was a differentiation that, once again,
served to distinguish animals and children, on the one hand, from older
human beings on the other. Because of this distinction, the things in accord-
ance with nature that were pursued by people of a greater age could be char-
acterised differently.21 Cato had undertaken to demonstrate that virtue alone
was the summum bonum and that, therefore, the wise man needed to make a
selection from amongst the things that were in accordance with nature. For
this reason it was necessary for him to show that a shift from the prota kata
physin aimed at self-preservation to the true Stoic telos of honestum was plau-
sible. In this process, as Striker rightly comments, a change takes place:
Consideration of a ‘normal development’ towards increasing rational capaci-
ties (in line with the increasing development of the logos) gives way to con-
sideration of a ‘moral development’.22
After the section of De finibus described above, Cato goes on to present the
process by which the object of oikeiosis shifts from the primary things in
accordance with nature and from self-preservation to the Stoic telos. For-
mally, based on the criteria established by Aristotelian ethics23 and in
accordance with the other Hellenistic schools, the Stoic tradition under-
stood telos to be that which is done for its own sake, and for which every-
19 Cicero, De finibus 3, 16f.: id ita esse sic probant, quod ante, quam voluptas aut dolor attigerit,
salutaria appetant parvi aspernenturque contraria, quod non fieret, nisi statum suum diligerent,
interitum timerent. fieri autem non posset ut appeterent aliquid, nisi sensum haberent sui eoque se
diligerent. ex quo intellegi debet principium ductum esse a se diligendo. in principiis autem naturali-
bus plerique Stoici non putant voluptatem esse ponendam.
20 Grotius was aware of the formulation ta prota kata physin and also cited it, as shown
below.
21 See SVF 3, 140-146; 181, on things in accordance with nature. According to Pohlenz, Die
Stoa, vol. 2, Göttingen 1959ff., 66, Zeno created the term ta prota kata physin as an addition
to the existing doctrine on things kata physin. Cf. also Pohlenz, Grundfragen, 13.
22 Striker, ‘The Role’, 289.
23 Aristotle, Ethica Nicomachea 1, 1097a15ff.; cf. T. Irwin, ‘Stoic and Aristotelian concep-
tions of happiness’, in Schofield/Striker The Norms, 206ff.
thing else is done.24 When it came to the semantic content of the term,
however, the Stoics understood telos to be ‘life in accordance with nature’.25
As opposed to the other schools of philosophy, it was this life in accordance
with nature that was the sole object of oikeiosis in Stoic ethics. In the devel-
opment that Cato describes in De finibus, Gisela Striker sees the explanation
of why this shift from self-preservation to a life in accordance with nature, as
the exclusive object of oikeiosis, can be regarded as plausible: “What seems to
be needed is an argument to show that man’s interest should at a certain
point in life shift from self-preservation or even self-perfection to an exclu-
sive interest in observing and following nature.”26
Cato’s argument can be outlined as follows: The initial human oikeiosis
(conciliatio) is directed towards things that are in accordance with nature (ea,
quae sunt secundum naturam). However as soon as man gains insight and
understanding (ennoia, notio) and is able to recognise the order and harmony
of things and actions, he gives clear preference to harmony (concordia). By
applying his perception and reason (ratio) he ultimately realises that this
harmony – because it is the Stoic homologia (translated by Cicero as conveni-
entia) – is in fact the supreme human good (summum bonum), to be praised
and sought for its own sake. It is in the Stoic homologia that this good
(bonum) – virtue (honestum) itself, the only component of good to which eve-
rything else must be related – is to be found. Although virtue does not
develop until a later stage, it is in fact the only quality worth striving for.
The primary things in accordance with nature (quae sunt prima naturae) are
not regarded as worthwhile in this sense.27
Here we see Cato providing an explanation of the way in which the object
of oikeiosis shifts as man uses his reason. Scholars differ on whether this pas-
sage represents an argument in favour of the Stoic thesis that life in accord-
ance with nature is the summum bonum for mankind or whether the text
merely attempts to make plausible the shift in the object of oikeiosis during
the course of human development.28 However it is clear that the Stoic notion
of oikeiosis – as presented to us in the third book of Cicero’s De finibus – has
been extended beyond the idea of self-preservation to take in a life in accor-
dance with nature, and, moreover, that this extension is somehow attributa-
ble to ratio. As outlined below, this was the model adopted by Grotius, a
model we might describe as a kind of dual or two-stage oikeiosis.
An additional aspect that was extremely important for the way in which
Grotius used these ideas is related to the Stoic identification of the summum
bonum – life in accordance with nature – with virtue (honestum). In order to
prove Cato’s claim as outlined above, that virtue is worth pursuing for its
own sake, it must first be shown that virtue fulfils the criteria for the sum-
mum bonum, in other words, that virtue and virtuous conduct correspond to,
or are predetermined by, human nature. Cicero demonstrates this with an
additional version of the doctrine of oikeiosis that sees oikeiosis as the founda-
tion of honestum. “[I]n order to show that nature prescribes virtuous behav-
iour, the Stoics would have to show that such behaviour is natural for man.
And this is, I think, what they tried to do with their second appeal to oikei-
ôsis, thus making it the foundation of justice, and indeed of the other virtues
as well.”29 It is this Ciceronian doctrine of oikeiosis that was adopted by Gro-
tius.
28 See Engberg-Pedersen, The Stoic Theory, 81-97, for the view that Cicero’s De finibus 3, 21
represents an argument in favour of the Stoic telos. Engberg-Pedersen discusses Striker’s
arguments in ‘The Role’, 289-293, where she maintains that Cicero, in De finibus 3, 21, sim-
ply assumes that life in accordance with nature is the yardstick for human action. However
even Striker admits that the ‘vague phrase’ cognitione et ratione collegit is a slight indication –
at least – that there may be an argument here. See Striker, ‘The Role’, 290-291.
29 Striker, ‘The Role’, 294.
cism probably only concerned the internal justice of a state, in De republica
Carneades was made to attack the morality of Roman imperial conquest and
rule. This attack was then repudiated by another participant to the dialogue,
providing the first extant philosophical justification of the Roman empire,30
a justification presented in Stoic terms, using the idea of oikeiosis and natural
law to mount a legal defense of Roman imperialism. Cicero’s sequel to De
republica, De legibus, starts where the argument in De republica had left off,
with the doctrine of natural law and justice. It is important to see that this
was the tradition Grotius was drawing upon in substantiating his doctrine of
natural law and, ultimately, of just war. Cicero’s answer to criticism directed
against the Roman just war doctrine, arguing in Stoic terms from oikeiosis to
the existence of natural law, clearly lent itself to Grotius, whose natural law
system had had its starting point, in De iure praedae, in the legal defense of
Dutch commercial imperialism in the East Indies.
30 For the relation between Cicero and the original Carneadean debate, see J.E.G. Zetzel,
‘Natural Law and Poetic Justice: A Carneadean Debate in Cicero and Virgil’, Classical Philol-
ogy 91, 1 (1996), 297-319.
31 IBP 1, 3, 8, 1, note 1; 1, 3, 12, 1; 2, 19, 2, 1f.; 2, 21, 19, note 3. Grotius’s library in 1618
contained two copies of Cicero’s works, see P.C. Molhuysen, ‘De bibliotheek van Hugo de
Groot in 1618’, Mededeelingen der Nederlandsche Akademie van Wetenschapen, Nieuwe Reeks,
Deel 6, 61f., nos. 271, 307.
32 In De legibus, Carneades’s Academy is required to maintain silence right from the start;
Cicero, De legibus 1, 39: Perturbatricem autem harum omnium rerum Academiam, hanc ab Arce-
sila et Carneade recentem, exoremus, ut sileat.
basis of utility is uprooted by that same utility: if nature will not confirm jus-
tice, all the virtues will be eliminated.33
No argument in favour of a natural law system based on the doctrine of
oikeiosis is presented here. Instead, the reader is clearly confronted with the
daunting consequences of any alternative to a natural law system of this
kind. According to Cicero, justice is either natural or it loses its status as the
yardstick for all written laws. It cannot be based on advantage. Any attempt
to base arguments in favour of iustitia on utilitas – or at any rate, on utilitas
alone – is condemned to failure since this kind of notion of justice would
inevitably be undermined by the criterion of advantage.34
In Cicero’s De republica, Carneades had found himself faced with the
same alternative, prompting him to locate utilitas within the sphere of the
natural and deny that any kind of natural justice or natural law was possible.
In this way iustitia was reduced to mere obedience to positive laws and took
on a decidedly convention-like character. Thus, in order to avoid the conse-
quences outlined in the passage cited – i.e. the overturning of virtues – an
argument for the natural character of iustitia was needed. An argument of
this kind can be found in De finibus, where the doctrine of oikeiosis, until
then focused on individuals and their actions alone, is extended in an altruis-
tic fashion and used to describe the social nature of mankind.35 The social
nature of the human race in general (communis humani generis societas) is
33 Cicero, De legibus 1, 42-43: Quodsi iustitia est obtemperatio scriptis legibus institutisque popu-
lorum, et si, ut eidem dicunt, utilitate omnia metienda sunt, negleget leges easque perrumpet, si
poterit is, qui sibi eam rem fructuosam putabit fore. Ita fit, ut nulla sit omnino iustitia, si neque
natura est, eaque quae propter utilitatem constituitur, utilitate illa convellitur, utque si natura con-
firmatura ius non erit, virtutes omnes tollantur. The translation is taken from Marcus Tullius
Cicero, On the Commonwealth; and, On the Laws, ed. and trans. J. E. G. Zetzel, Cambridge
1999. The final line of the text is uncertain: Dyck reads Atque si natura confirmatum ius non
erit, tollantur <...necesse est>, thus choosing not to insert the words virtutes omnes; Striker
reads <iustitia omnis> tolla{n}tur; see A.R. Dyck, A Commentary on Cicero, De Legibus, Ann
Arbor 2004, 187-188.
34 See Dyck, A Commentary, 187.
35 Engberg-Pedersen, The Stoic Theory, 122-123: ‘Till now the doctrine of oikeiosis has been
silent on a person’s relations with others. [...] So how does one get from the love of self which
is at the centre of oikeiosis in its first version, and has remained so in actual fact (though only
accidentally) after one has reached the final insight, to some form of genuine care for others?
It is this basic step away from natural self-centredness that the Stoics attempt to elucidate
when they bring in oikeiosis for the second time.’
derived from the love that parents have for their children.36 This gives rise
to oikeiosis (commendatio) between human beings,37 a move that severs any
earlier link with self-preservation.
We may presume that this second step in oikeiosis – hominum inter homines
commendatio – is also understood to be the result of mankind’s rational
nature, even if it is not explicitly argued here. However, the importance of
ratio is explicitly noted in the first book of De officiis, which describes the
transition from the self-preservation impulse to the social nature of man-
kind, stressing the differentiation between humans and animals that was so
characteristic for the Stoa.38
Nature causes human beings to feel they are part of fellow humankind
through the power of their rational faculties, and this makes honestum and
36 Cicero, De finibus 3, 62. M. Schofield, ‘Two Stoic Approaches to Justice’, in Justice and
Generosity: Studies in Hellenistic Social and Political Philosophy, ed. A. Laks/M. Schofield,
Cambridge 1995, 198-199 does not regard this passage as a real argument for the natural char-
acter of justice. For him it is more of a preparation for an argument of this kind, and the tran-
sition to iustitia, he believes, was probably not fully developed in ancient Stoic sources. ‘I
offer the hypothesis that, as so often, Zeno gave no explicit account of the matter. Hence, I
suggest, later Stoics were forced – again, as often – to offer their own divergent explanations,
bereft of any authoritative guidance from the founder of the school.’ Various explanations of
the transition from oikeiosis as inter homines commendatio to justice had been attempted in the
first and third books of Cicero’s De officiis, based on Panaitios (off. 1) and Antipater (off. 3).
37 Cicero, De finibus 3, 63: ex hoc nascitur ut etiam communis hominum inter homines naturalis
sit commendatio, ut oporteat hominem ab homine ob id ipsum, quod homo sit, non alienum videri.
Cf., also, the excerpts from Hierocles in Stobaeus 4, 671, 7-673, 11.
38 Cicero, De officiis 1, 11f.: Principio generi animantium omni est a natura tributum, ut se,
vitam corpusque tueatur, declinet ea, quae nocitura videantur [...]. Sed inter hominem et beluam
hoc maxime interest, quod haec tantum, quantum sensu movetur, ad id solum, quod adest quodque
praesens est, se accomodat, paulum admodum sentiens praeteritum aut futurum. Homo autem, quod
rationis est particeps, per quam consequentia cernit, causas rerum videt earumque praegressus et
quasi antecessiones non ignorat, similitudines comparat rebusque praesentibus adiungit atque adnec-
tit futuras, facile totius vitae cursum videt ad eamque degendam praeparat res necessarias.
Eademque natura vi rationis hominem conciliat homini [...]. This passage was not included in
the collection by Long/Sedley (The Hellenistic philosophers, 2 vols., Cambridge 1987, from
here on abbreviated as LS) and is not discussed in the relevant monograph by Engberg-Ped-
ersen, The Stoic Theory, hence Engberg-Pedersen’s view (125) that ‘The Stoics nowhere
make clear the precise role of rationality in bringing about this result [...].’ The fact that the
function of reason was critical is evident, not least in the anonymous commentary on Plato’s
Theaitetos, which according to LS I, S. 353 provides (probably Academic) criticism of the
Stoic position. The anonymous commentator concedes the Stoic argument of a natural and
simultaneously rational oikeiosis with respect to one’s ‘neighbour’ – but believes a dinstinction
should be made between different degrees of oikeiosis.
virtuous conduct appear natural. In the same way virtue is shown to corre-
spond to Stoic requirements with respect to the summum bonum. The use of
the vis rationis must be seen as a new element in the Stoic doctrine of oikei-
osis, with the concept of ratio being understood in the authentic Stoic tradi-
tion as the human capacity for anticipation, conclusion and comparison.39
Reason is seen – following Stoic tradition – as the specific difference to the
animal world, and is used to justify the social nature of mankind, for which
the rational capabilities of anticipation, conclusion and comparison are pre-
requisites.40
Referring explicitly to the third book of Cicero’s De finibus and its Stoic
sources, Grotius clearly adopted this idea of a transition from the self-pres-
ervation impulse – as the first object of oikeiosis – to honestum as the superior
good, preferable to mere self-preservation:
Marcus Tullius Cicero, both in the third book of his treatise On Ends and
in other places, following Stoic writings learnedly argues that there are cer-
tain primary things in accordance with nature [prima naturae] – ‘first accord-
ing to nature’ [ta prota kata physin], as the Greeks phrased it – and certain
other principles which are later manifest buth which are to be preferred over
those first principles.41
Grotius probably came across the Stoic formulation ta prota kata physin
in either Aulus Gellius or Stobaeus (he compiled an edition of the latter’s
works42), since in Cicero it appears only in Latin.43 After discussing Cato’s
explanation in De finibus, which begins with birth, the doctrine of oikeiosis,
and the primary things in accordance with nature,44 Grotius turns to the role
of honestum, using the two-stage oikeiosis model familiar to him from Cicero.
Ratio is given an important role, but one that differs slightly from the corre-
sponding passage in De finibus, making evident the use Grotius made also of
Cicero’s De legibus:
But after these things have received due consideration [Cicero contin-
ues], there follows a notion of the conformity [convenientia] of things with
reason, which is superior to the body. Now this conformity, in which moral
goodness [honestum] becomes the paramount object, ought to be accounted
of higher import than the things to which alone instinct first directed itself,
because the primary things in accordance with nature [prima naturae] com-
mend us to right reason [recta ratio], and right reason ought to be more dear
to us than those things through whose instrumentality we have been brought
to it. Since this is true and without other demonstration would easily receive
the assent of all who are endowed with uncorrupted judgement [sanum iudi-
cium], it follows that in investigating according to natural law it is necessary
first to see what is consistent with those fundamental principles of nature,
and then to come to that which, though of later origin, is nevertheless more
worthy – that which ought not only to be grasped, if it appear, but to be
sought out by every effort.45
This presentation is obviously based essentially on the explanation para-
phrased above, which also saw the application of reason as the crucial devel-
44 IBP 1, 2, 1, 1: Prima naturae vocat, quod simulatque natum est animal, ipsum sibi conciliatur
et commendatur ad se conservandum, atque ad suum statum, et ad ea quae conservantia sunt eius
status, diligenda: alienatur autem ab interitu iisque rebus, quae interitum videantur afferre. Hinc
etiam ait fieri, ut nemo sit, quin cum utrumvis liceat, aptas malit et integras omnes partes corporis,
quam easdem usu imminutas aut detortas habere: primumque esse officium, ut se quis conservet in
naturae statu, deinceps ut ea teneat, quae secundum naturam sint, pellatque contraria. This pas-
sage is largely based on the third book of Cicero’s De finibus; here passages are reproduced
almost word by word from Cicero’s De finibus 3, 16; 3, 17 and 3, 20.
45 IBP 1, 2, 1, 2: At post haec cognita sequi notionem convenientiae rerum cum ipsa ratione quae
corpore est potior; atque eam convenientiam, in qua honestum sit propositum, pluris faciendam,
quam ad quae sola primum animi appetitio ferebatur; quia prima naturae commendent nos quidem
rectae rationi, sed ipsa recta ratio carior nobis esse debeat quam illa sint a quibus ad hanc venerimus.
Haec cum vera sint et ab omnibus, qui iudicio sano sunt praediti, facile sine alia demonstratione
assensum impetrent; sequitur in examinando iure naturae primum videndum quid illis naturae initiis
congruat, deinde veniendum ad illud, quod quanquam post oritur, dignius tamen est; neque sumen-
dum tantum, si detur, sed omni modo expetendum. Cf. Ulp. Dig. 1, 1, 10, where the honeste vivere
is named among the praecepta iuris. Grotius’s concept, however, is clearly based on Cicero’s
detailed account of the Stoic honestum.
opment. In the third book of De finibus Cato had explained the shift in the
object of oikeiosis away from the primary things in accordance with nature,
and away from self-preservation towards the Stoic telos,46 and Grotius clearly
took this passage as his source when justifying the hierarchical relationship
between self-preservation and the superior quality of honestum. The latter was a
product of human reason and the insight derived through the use of this fac-
ulty. However, in the quoted passage Grotius differed from Cato in apply-
ing the two stages of the Stoic doctrine of oikeiosis to his discussion of
natural law. By contrast, Cicero’s Cato did not discuss ius naturae since,
although he maintained that there was a link between virtue (honestum) and
the Stoic summum bonum (as shown in the section on the Stoic notion of telos
above), he was unable to show that virtue fulfilled the criteria required for
the Stoic summum bonum. In other words, he could not demonstrate that vir-
tue and virtuous conduct corresponded to human nature or were derived
from it. While in De finibus the purpose of reason was to recognise the sum-
mum bonum and to identify it with life in accordance with nature, Grotius,
going beyond this identification, created a direct link between honestum (and
with it justice) and human nature, via recta ratio, in a way strongly reminis-
cent of, and most probably taken from, the pertinent passages in Cicero’s De
legibus.47
In his article entitled Two Stoic Approaches to Justice, Malcolm Schofield
differentiates between an ‘ethical’ on the one hand and a ‘metaphysical’ or
‘theological’ argument on the other in favour of justice on the part of the
Stoa. He sees the doctrine of oikeiosis as serving the ethical argument.48
However, even for the texts that Schofield uses to support his argument this
46 Cicero, De finibus 3, 21: prima est enim conciliatio hominis ad ea, quae sunt secundum natu-
ram. simul autem cepit intellegentiam vel notionem potius, quam appellant ennoian illi, viditque
rerum agendarum ordinem et, ut ita dicam, concordiam, multo eam pluris aestimavit quam omnia
illa, quae prima dilexerat. atque ita cognitione et ratione collegit, ut statueret in eo collocatum sum-
mum illud hominis per se laudandum et expetendum bonum, quod cum positum sit in eo, quod homo-
logian Stoici, nos appellemus convenientiam, si placet, – cum igitur in eo sit id bonum, quo omnia
referenda sint, honeste facta ipsumque honestum, quod solum in bonis ducitur, quamquam post
oritur, tamen id solum vi sua et dignitate expetendum est; eorum autem, quae sunt prima naturae,
propter se nihil est expetendum.
47 Cicero, De legibus 1, 22f.
48 See Schofield, ‘Two Stoic Approaches’, 194, where the first book of De legibus serves as
an example for Stoic ‘metaphysical’ arguments in favour of justice, and De finibus 3, 62ff.
(supported by De officiis 1, 11f. and 3, 19-28) for their ‘ethical’ arguments.
kind of distinction is unnecessary.49 In the case of Grotius (who uses preci-
sely these texts), we can definitely exclude any clear differentiation of this
kind, particularly in view of the fact that Grotius imposes ‘metaphysical’
preconditions for his ‘ethical’ justification of natural justice using the Stoic
doctrine of oikeiosis. This is particularly obvious in the passage quoted
immediately above, where Grotius appears to equate Stoic honestum, and
with it justice, with recta ratio. While it is clear that there are different views
amongst historians of philosophy with regard to the Stoics and the use made
of the doctrine of oikeiosis, Grotius’s reading of the various sources and in
particular his reading of the relevant texts in Cicero appears consistent: in
Grotius’s works oikeiosis and the ‘metaphysical’ argument in favour of
justice are elements of one and the same conception of natural justice.
Grotius argues that virtue (honestum) lies in the agreement (or harmony:
convenientia) of things with reason, an agreement that is superior to the
body. This agreement, according to Grotius, is of higher value than those
things which, initially, are the sole things towards which our impulse is
directed (by which he means the impulse towards self-preservation). These
primary things in accordance with nature (prima naturae) commend us to
right reason (recta ratio), which then becomes more precious to us than the
primary things in accordance with nature themselves. Since this is true, and
is accepted by all people endowed with uncorrupted judgement (qui iudicio
sano sunt praediti), without the need for any further evidence (demonstratio),
it follows that, when investigating according to natural law (in examinando
iure naturae), it is necessary to begin by considering the things that corre-
spond to the (primary) principles of nature, and then to proceed to consider
those that are of higher value (dignius), even though they do not develop
until later. The latter should not merely be used if they happen to appear;
they should be sought out by every effort (omni modo expetendum).50
49 The basic problem in Schofield’s argument appears to lie in the fact that the approach to
iustitia, the doctrine of oikeiosis, which Schofield describes as ‘ethical’ rather than ‘metaphys-
ical’, is founded on important anthropological conditions in the area of metaphysics and
therefore excludes clear differentiation of this kind. This is clearly shown in the way in which
Grotius uses and mixes the two approaches. However, even in some of the sources cited by
Schofield, the two approaches are occasionally found together, inevitably resulting in contra-
dictions in his line of argument. For instance, in one place he asserts with respect to the first
book of De legibus, which serves as his example for the ‘metaphysical approach’, that the con-
cept of nature is being used here in a manner equivalent to ‘objective reality’ and that human
nature is irrelevant in this context (Schofield, ‘Two Stoic Approaches’, 205), while elsewhere
he states that ‘the nature of man’ is the subject of the first book of De legibus (191).
50 IBP 1, 2, 1, 2.
Grotius’s formulation of Cicero’s convenientia certainly appears some-
what idiosyncratic, even if in principle it correctly reflects the Stoic formu-
lation of the harmony between ratio and nature. That said, his description of
a notion of virtue that is somehow included in this harmony, as well as the
hierarchical relationship between the prima naturae and honestum does in fact
correspond to the model presented by Cicero. The requirement of uncor-
rupted judgement also corresponds to the established Hellenistic criteria
found in Cicero51 and needs to be seen in the context of the Stoic concept
mentioned by Cicero (ennoia), which is, “what natural and therefore veridi-
cal thinking on a point would be like if reasoning were not subject to the
usual (but unnatural) processes of corruption”.52
51 The field required for consensus had already been restricted through the reference to the
corrupt nature of judgement.
52 D. Obbink, ‘ “What all men believe – must be true”: common conceptions and consensio
omnium in Aristotle and Hellenistic Philosophy’, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 10
(1992), 223.
53 Such as self-preservation, health or wealth; see Diogenes Laertius 7, 101ff. (= LS 58 A).
from the point of view of nature health is preferable to illness, because of the
natural impulse to self-preservation).54 As opposed to the absolute value
proper to virtue, the value of preferable indifferent things remained depen-
dent upon circumstances (for instance, it might in certain situations be cor-
rect to risk the objective, natural value of health in the interests of
maintaining the good).
Grotius seems not to adopt the orthodox Stoic description of honestum as
the solum bonum, and seemingly abandons the fundamental distinction
between virtue, as the sole good, and the preferable indifferent things. Yet
he does not renounce the Stoic hierarchical relationship between honestum
and the preferable indifferent things (including the prima naturae and the
impulse to self-preservation). When conducting an examination under natu-
ral law, he maintains that the first step is to consider that which corresponds
to the preferable indifferent things, in other words the prima naturae. Hav-
ing done this, however, one must according to Grotius move on to the more
highly valued honestum.55 In slightly softening the fundamental orthodox
Stoic distinction between virtue and the preferable indifferent things, Gro-
tius also abandons another major Stoic distinction, that between the Stoic
wise man (sapiens) and the rest of humanity, the unwise (insipientes). How-
ever Grotius’s view deviates only marginally from that of the Roman Stoics
– he adopts indeed very much Cicero’s rendering of the Stoic doctrine. Just
as Cicero’s Cato appears to counter Aristo’s extreme position, when he allo-
cates a high status to preferable indifferent things on the grounds that the
whole living world would fall into disorder (confunderetur omnis vita) with-
out a certain amount of differentiation between the adiaphora,56 Grotius also
distinguishes between indifferent things that may be regarded as more or
less appropriate. As we shall see, Grotius probably believed that this Roma-
nized Stoic doctrine, as passed down by Cicero, was actually Stoic doctrine
tout court.
54 According to Plutarch, Chrysippus was forced to admit that the preferable indifferent
things overlapped with those things described as ‘good’ in conventional language; see Plu-
tarch, De Stoicorum repugnantiis 1048a (= LS 58 H). Aristo’s Stoic criticisms addressed this
convergence, rejecting any distinction between preferable and unacceptable indifferent things
on the grounds that a distinction of this kind was tantamount to setting preferable indifferent
things at the same level as the good; see Sextus Empiricus, Adversus mathematicos 11, 64ff. (=
LS 58 F).
55 IBP 1, 2, 1, 2.
56 Cicero, De finibus 3, 50.
In orthodox Stoic ethics, as opposed to the Ciceronian account Grotius
adopted, the wise man was the only person capable of arriving at telos and
leading a life in eudaimonia – in harmony with nature. He was the only per-
son capable of leading a virtuous life and attaining the summum bonum
because he acted according to the right moral principles. Unlike a normal
human being – insipiens – the Stoic sapiens was capable of more than just car-
rying out appropriate actions (kathekonta), in other words, actions that can
be justified through reason and that pursue the preferable indifferent things
such as self-preservation. The Stoic wise man acted in a perfectly appropri-
ate manner because his ‘right actions’ (katorthomata) pursued the good, were
morally right and were founded not merely on reason (ratio), as are the
appropriate actions of other human beings, but on ‘right reason’, recta ratio
(orthos logos), in which the wise man participated along with the Gods.57 In
early Stoic philosophy this recta ratio of the wise man was regarded as being
identical to natural law, which demanded perfectly appropriate or right
actions (katorthomata). The wise man, per definitionem, was the only human
capable of performing these.58 In Zeno’s early Stoic political philosophy this
resulted in an ideal society consisting solely of sapientes and Gods.59 This
must have been an entirely Utopian society, since the Stoic wise man was
such a rare phenomenon.60 It served the purpose of providing a philosophi-
cal defence of the idea of natural justice and was not intended as a feasible
political programme.61 The only law in force in Zeno’s Utopia was natural
57 See Stobaeus 2, 93, 14ff. (= SVF 3, 500 = LS 59 K); 2, 96, 18-97, 5 (= SVF 3, 501 = LS
59 M).
58 In ‘Natural Law and Natural Right in Post-Aristotelian Philosophy. The Stoics and
Their Critics’, Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt II 36.7, ed. W. Haase, Berlin 1994,
4829-4834, P. Mitsis disputes the view that, under the early Stoa, natural law prescribes
katorthomata alone. This view is put forward by P.A. Vander Waerdt, ‘Philosophical Influ-
ence on Roman Jurisprudence? The Case of Stoicism and Natural Law’, in Aufstieg und Nie-
dergang der römischen Welt II 36.7, ed. W. Haase, Berlin 1994, 4854-4856. However Mitsis
does admit that ‘only the wise man completely understands nature’s injunctions and [...] can
interpret the laws and act as a lawgiver. His reason and nature’s law are isomorphic’ (Mitsis,
‘Natural Law’, 4831, note 46).
59 Diogenes Laertius 7, 33; 7, 122ff.; 7, 131.
60 Only one or two examples of a sapiens can be cited; Alexander von Aphrodisias, De fato
199, 14-22.
61 See the convincing argument presented in P.A. Vander Waerdt, ‘Politics and Philosophy
in Stoicism. A Discussion of A. Erskine, The Hellenistic Stoa: Political Thought and Action’,
Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 9 (1991), 185-211. Plutarch describes Zeno’s Utopian
society as a philosophical dream; Plutarch, De Alexandri magni fortuna aut virtute 329a-b (=
LS 67 A).
law, in other words recta ratio, in which the only participants were Gods and
wise men. Thus, in this early Stoic approach, natural law appears to have
been limited to wise men.
Scholars differ on whether, or when precisely Stoic philosophy aban-
doned Zeno’s Utopian ideas in favour of a political philosophy devoted to
specific issues and institutions, as evidenced above all in Cicero’s De repub-
lica, De legibus and De officiis.62 However it is clear that from the time of Cic-
ero, at the latest, there are cohesive sources on Stoic doctrine in the fields of
ethics and political philosophy that go beyond a description of the state of a
Utopian society made up of sapientes and Gods, endeavouring to clarify the
practical implications of Stoic ethics for normal people, in other words for
insipientes. Such a practical approach necessarily entailed a more rule-ori-
ented and less agent-centered ethical outlook. In addition to widening the
field of application of Stoic natural law by extending recta ratio to the insipi-
entes, it can be shown that Cicero was also interested in the substantive con-
tent of the actual rules of natural law. This cannot be said of the early Stoa,
at least not on the basis of the fragmentary evidence available to us, and must
most probably be attributed to specific Roman concerns that were crucial to
Grotius, too, especially the aforementioned treatment of Roman imperialism
in the third book of Cicero’s De republica.63
Whatever our view of the early Stoa in this respect, it is likely that, from
Diogenes of Babylon onwards, natural law took the form of a para-legal sys-
tem of general abstract norms, rather than residing in the particularist inter-
62 Paul Vander Waerdt identifies a transformation of this kind and sees – mainly based on
Cicero, De legibus 3, 13f. – Diogenes of Babylon as the critical figure who modified the politi-
cal philosophy of the early Stoics, adapting it to the rival Academic and Peripatetic political
philosophies; see Vander Waerdt, ‘Politics and Philosophy’, 205-210. However, M.
Schofield, The Stoic Idea of the City, Cambridge 1991, 93-103, does not regard Zeno’s ‘repub-
licanism’ as a theory of natural law, maintaing that Chrysippus was the first thinker to pro-
duce a theory of natural law by extending Zeno’s society of wise men to encompass a society
of rational living beings. This view equates natural law with normative reason; see Schofield,
The Stoic Idea, 67-74. These discussions do not touch on the question of what the actual sub-
stantive provisions of natural law might be.
63 See also the Roman examples of kathekonta kata peristasin in time of war, in Cicero’s De
officiis 34-40. Academic and Peripatetic philosophical influences might as well have played a
role, see Vander Waerdt, ‘Politics and Philosophy’, 204f.
nal disposition of the Stoic wise man with respect to specific situations:64
“By Cicero’s time, however, the Stoic theory had been revised in such a way
that conduct in accordance with natural law was now held to be attainable by
moral progressors; accordingly, the strict early Stoic standard that only
katorthomata, actions performed by an agent who possesses the sage’s right
reason, accord with natural law is now relaxed, and the basis is laid for the
conception in which natural law is specifiable in a code of moral rules.”65
This means, with respect to Grotius, that he was able to draw on Cicero’s
model when he extended the normative scope of recta ratio, thereby univer-
salising the application of natural law. As we shall show below, Grotius cer-
tainly admits preferable indifferent things (prima naturae) alongside virtue
(honestum) as criteria in examinando iure naturae. Thus at first sight he
appears to attach a certain moral relevance to the former – contrary to the
orthodox Stoic position. However, upon more detailed examination, this
64 Vander Waerdt, for instance, notes a reorientation in the Stoic doctrine of natural law. He
argues that the early Stoa did not believe that natural law or the wise man’s recta ratio consti-
tuted any universal normative rules with substantive content, but rather dispositions relating
to the intentions of the wise man. It was not until the time of the younger Stoa that natural
law consisted of general abstract norms established on the model of legal rules and furnished
with substantive content. Natural law, he writes, is ‘constituted by the sage’s rational disposi-
tion, not by a code of rules or legislation’. For this reason it is ‘a dispositional rather than rule-
following model of natural law’, Vander Waerdt, ‘Zeno’s Republic and the Origins of Natural
Law’, in The Socratic Movement, ed. P.A. Vander Waerdt, Ithaca 1994, 287. Cf. also Vander
Waerdt, ‘Philosophical Influence’, 4854f. This view is opposed by Phillip Mitsis, in particu-
lar, who postulates universal rules following the model of legal norms even in the natural law
ideas of the early Stoa. Based on the beginning of Chrysippus’s Peri Nomou, as passed down
to us in Marcian’s Corpus iuris civilis (Marcian inst. 1 = LS 67 R), Mitsis, in ‘The Stoics and
Aquinas on Virtue and Natural Law’, The Studia Philonica Annual 15 (2003), 42, argues
‘Chrysippus does not claim that natural law prescribes to animals whose nature is political
how and how not they should perform actions or with what sorts of inner attitudes. He main-
tains that natural law prescribes what they should and should not do.’ Cf. also Mitsis, ‘Natu-
ral Law’, 4835-4841. Although Mitsis’s argument is certainly convincing, it should be noted
that we do not have any early Stoic sources corroborating the substantive content of these
natural law norms; for this reason the precise content of Chrysippus’s norms remain unclear.
Not until the time of Cicero do we find statements relating to the content of natural law
norms (for example, from Diogenes of Babylon, whose statements have been passed on by
Cicero, see Cicero, De officiis 3, 51-57). Vander Waerdt, ‘Philosophical Influence’, 4854,
appears to contest the Stoic origins and the natural law character of these statements (as well
as the moral norms discussed by Seneca in Epistulae 94-95) when he states that ‘no Stoic
account of the precepts of natural law has survived’.
65 Vander Waerdt, ‘Philosophical Influence’, 4855. Vander Waerdt regards Antiochus as the
source of this change in Stoic theory.
conclusion proves to be incorrect. Indeed, it becomes clear that Grotius’s
stand with regard to virtue, and with it justice, is founded on a reception of
Cicero’s doctrine of oikeiosis as described above, and is eminently Stoic in
character. For Grotius, virtue holds a superordinate position and – in the
case of competing rules – represents a clear barrier in the Stoic sense against
actions that pursue the prima naturae.
From this text it is clear that, like the Stoics, Grotius associates the primary
natural things with the impulse to self-preservation. According to Grotius,
both the purpose of war – the preservation of life and limb – and the reten-
tion or acquisition of things useful for life are completely in accordance with
the primary natural things. The need to use force does not run counter to
the primary things in accordance with nature, since this is the very reason
why all living beings have been endowed with enough physical strength to
defend themselves. Clearly Grotius includes war amongst the Stoic kathek-
onta (or appropriate actions) that pursue things in accordance with nature
such as health (for Grotius the vitae membrorumque conservatio) or, of
slightly lower ranking, property67 (for Grotius the rerum ad vitam utilium
aut retentio aut acquisitio). Although irrelevant with respect to the good,
these primary things in accordance with nature are still preferable to other
indifferent things (proegmena adiaphora).
The inclusion of war amongst appropriate actions in the Stoic sense
(kathekonta) is also supported by the authorities cited by Grotius, which
obviously consist of non-Stoics. In his quotation from Xenophon’s Cyrupai-
deia, as in the quotations from Ovid, Horace, Lucretius, Galen and Aristo-
tle, human beings are compared to animals and equated with them when it
comes to warlike actions. Since war pursues self-preservation and thus the
prima naturae of oikeiosis, in other words objects that all living beings natu-
rally pursue, it belongs to the category of actions that are in accordance also
with the nature of human beings, and indeed of all living beings: cum ani-
mantibus singulis vires sint a natura attributae. Grotius’s idea of war as an
action not limited merely to human beings, and in accordance with the
nature of the living being carrying out the action, is absolutely in line with
the criteria for the Stoic kathekon.68
Nevertheless, as a Stoic kathekon, war is in accordance with natural law for
Grotius only to the extent that it does not contradict natural law, and this is
where the crucial Stoic differentiation between human beings and other liv-
ing beings comes in; although the reason why it does not contradict natural
law is because it does not belong to natural law in its proper sense. With
66 IBP 1, 2, 1, 4: Inter prima naturae nihil est quod bello repugnet, imo omnia potius ei favent.
nam et finis belli, vitae membrorumque conservatio, et rerum ad vitam utilium aut retentio aut
acquisitio, illis primis naturae maxime convenit: et vi ad eam rem si opus sit uti, nihil habet a primis
naturae dissentaneum, cum animantibus singulis vires ideo sint a natura attributae, ut sibi tuendis
iuvandisque sufficiant. Xenophon: [...] omnia animantium genera pugnam norunt aliquam, quam
non aliunde quam a natura didicerunt.
67 Diogenes Laertius 7, 101ff., on the proegmena adiaphora.
68 See the Stoic definition of kathekon in Stobaeus 2, 85, 13-2, 86, 4 (= SVF 3, 494 = LS 59
B). Even plants can carry out kathekonta, see Diogenes Laertius 7, 107.
respect to war as kathekon, Grotius states that certain things non proprie, sed
reductive are said to belong to natural law merely because there is no contra-
diction between them and natural law.69 However, the only actions that are
truly in accordance with natural law are those actions that correspond to
honestum and this, in its turn, means they must be prescribed by recta ratio.
Initially, war as a kathekon, as a means of self-preservation, is irrelevant with
respect to honestum since recta ratio, in other words natural law in its real
sense, makes no statement with respect to adiaphora, to which self-preserva-
tion undoubtedly belongs. This also corresponds precisely to the Stoic doc-
trine of the category of appropriate actions (kathekonta) which, if we
consider the actions carried out only by human beings, comprises those
actions that, as perfectly appropriate or right actions (katorthomata) consti-
tute a special case of kathekonta. These are morally right actions associated
with virtue (honestum), which can be performed only by Stoic wise men.
It is important to note the careful distinction made by Grotius in this
analysis of whether war is compatible with natural law. Like the Stoa, he dis-
tinguishes between actions that are relevant with respect to virtue (honestum)
and thus with respect to natural law in its true sense, on the one hand, and
morally irrelevant actions on the other. As regards natural law in its true
sense, Grotius regards war quite simply to be irrelevant, to the extent that it
pursues self-preservation, which is indifferent with respect to virtue. This is
evident in Grotius’s description of virtue and the relationship between hon-
estum and natural law that results from this notion of virtue.70 Grotius pre-
sents various different concepts of virtue (honestum). In some places it consists
of a single point, as it were, with even the slightest deviation from this point
resulting in wrong (vitium). In other places its scope is less restricted, and
69 IBP 1, 1, 10, 3: Ad iuris autem naturalis intellectum, notandum est, quaedam dici eius iuris non
proprie, sed ut scholae loqui amant, reductive, quibus ius naturale non repugnat, sicut iusta modo
diximus appellari ea quae iniustitia carent. Actions in accordance with the merely conventional
ius gentium would fit this characterization.
70 IBP 1, 2, 1, 3: Hoc ipsum vero, quod honestum dicimus, pro materiae diversitate, modo (ut ita
dicam) in puncto consistit, ut si vel minimum inde abeas, ad vitium deflectas; modo liberius habet
spatium, ita ut et fieri laudabiliter, et sine turpitudine omitti aut aliter fieri possit, ferme quomodo
ab hoc esse ad hoc non esse statim sit transitus; at inter aliter adversa, ut album et nigrum, reperire
est aliquid interpositum, sive mixtum, sive reductum utrinque. Et in hoc posteriori genere maxime
occupari solent leges tum divinae, tum humanae, id agendo, ut, quod per se laudabile tantum erat,
etiam deberi incipiat. Supra autem diximus, de iure naturae cum quaeritur, hoc quaeri, an fieri
aliquid possit non iniuste: iniustum autem id demum intelligi quod necessariam cum natura rationali
ac sociali habet repugnantiam.
an action may be carried out in a praiseworthy manner, omitted without
being unpraiseworthy, or even carried out in another manner. The rule of
law that is subject to the will concerns itself with this second notion of virtue
– honestum in its wider scope. This applies both to human laws and to laws
imposed by God, which are the legal sanctions for actions regarded as prai-
seworthy or virtuous in the second sense. Yet natural law, in its true sense,
relates to the first, more narrow conception of virtue – in other words,
honestum in the sense of a single ‘point’ where there is no transition between
virtue and wrong, as in the case of Stoic honestum.
With respect to war this means that, if war is to correspond to the nar-
rower conception of honestum and thus to natural law in its narrower sense, it
must also, in a second step, meet the criteria of recta ratio. War that is com-
patible with natural law in this narrower sense cannot be a kathekon alone,
but it must satisfy the repertoire of just causes for war as presented by Gro-
tius in the second book of De iure belli ac pacis. For the purposes of this arti-
cle it is sufficient to draw attention to the distinction that Grotius makes
between just actions in the broader sense and actions corresponding to natu-
ral law in the narrower sense, and to note the close relationship between this
distinction made by Grotius and the Stoic differentiation of kathekonta und
katorthomata. Only wars waged because of just causes are in accordance with
natural law in the narrow sense and may qualify as katorthomata, whereas
mere self-preservation does not suffice.
• 3. Conclusion
It could be shown in the present article that Grotius derived the Stoic pre-
suppositions for his universal natural law from Cicero’s description of the
doctrine of oikeiosis in the philosophical works De legibus, De finibus bonorum
et malorum and De officiis. Grotius, it is true, chose to call this originally
Stoic doctrine by the term appetitus societatis, avoiding Cicero’s translation
conciliatio, and identified the term only from the 1631 edition onwards with
the Greek technical term oikeiosis. But there cannot be any doubt as to the
concept’s Ciceronian pedigree. As in Cicero, the function of oikeiosis in Gro-
tius’s work is to provide the anthropological justification for a universal nat-
ural law that is no longer restricted to the Stoic wise man, as it was in
orthodox Stoic thought.
As Cicero’s successor, Grotius aligns individual human development
with a kind of two-stage oikeiosis process. This leads him to endow every
adult human being with recta or perfecta ratio, rather than restricting it to the
sapiens, as did the orthodox Stoics.71 Thus the authority for Grotius’s natu-
ral law in terms of form is Cicero and his recta ratio, while the substantive
content of the concept is the virtue of justice (honestum) defined in the nar-
row Stoic sense of the word.72 Therefore war, as an action whose purpose is
self-preservation, thus constituting a Stoic kathekon, does not in fact contra-
dict Grotius’s idea of natural law, since an action of this kind is irrelevant for
natural law in its narrower sense.
However, and more importantly, the question of whether a specific war is
compatible with natural law in the narrower sense must, according to Gro-
tius, be examined in accordance with recta ratio, which does not admit self-
preservation as a sufficient criterion. Although Grotius bases his system of
natural law norms developed in De iure belli ac pacis on anthropological pre-
suppositions, these are not predominantly the impulse to self-preservation,
but rather the anthropological characteristics outlined by the Stoics in their
doctrine of oikeiosis. They manifest themselves, above all, in mankind’s
social disposition that arises out of his essentially rational nature. Tuck’s
view that self-preservation is the foundation of Grotius’s natural law must
thus be contested.73 The only criterion taken into account under recta ratio is
the substantive one of justice. This means that, for Grotius, self-preserva-
tion is in accordance with natural law only to the extent that such self-pre-
servation is just.
71 Although Cicero’s definitions continue to equate natural law with the recta ratio of the
Stoic wise man (see Cicero, De legibus 1, 18f.; 2, 8), he removes all generic distinctions
between human beings: Itaque quaecumque est hominis definitio, una in omnis valet. Quod argu-
menti satis est nullam dissimilitudinem esse in genere. Cicero, De legibus 1, 29f. See Vander
Waerdt, ‘Philosophical Influence’, 4872, where he states, with respect to Cicero: ‘[...] natural
law is now the prescription not strictly of right reason, which only the sage possesses, but of
the rationality in which all human beings share.’
72 Certain actions, such as polygamy, do not contradict natural law in its true, narrow sense.
They contradict only the broader sense of honestum, which is the subject of positive law; see
IBP 1, 2, 1, 3.
73 See Tuck, ‘The “Modern” Theory’, 113.