Geach, Peter (1954) - Form and Existence
Geach, Peter (1954) - Form and Existence
Geach, Peter (1954) - Form and Existence
Author(s): P. T. Geach
Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 55 (1954 - 1955), pp. 251-272
Published by: Wiley on behalf of The Aristotelian Society
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4544548
Accessed: 06-05-2015 16:36 UTC
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The Aristotelian Society and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
XI.-FORM
AND EXISTENCE.
By P. T. GEACH.
In this paper I shall discuss what Aquinas meant by
his term esse, or actusessendi,"act of existing ". Another
synonym that he uses-quo aliquid est, " that by which a
thing is (or: exists) "-suggests a convenient division of
the subject: we can first discuss Aquinas's philosophical
use of quo, " that by which ", and then consider which
sense of est, which sort of existential statements, may be
relevant to Aquinas's doctrine of esse. But we shall see that,
having got thus far, we cannot arrive at the meaning of
the whole phrase quoaliquidest, or the reasons for the way
Aquinas uses it, simply by combining our separate considerations about quoand est.
I.
Beginning with Aquinas's use of quo brings a great
immediate advantage. The predicate est," is " or " exists",
is at least a peculiar one, and many people would deny
that it is properly a predicate at all; but Aquinas uses quo
not only with est but also with unexceptionable predicates.
In this use, quofollowed by a noun- ubject and an (ordinary)
predicate is synonymous with the phrase formed by the
abstract noun answering to the predicate followed by the
genitive of the noun that was subject; quoSocratesalbusest
is synonymous with albedoSocratis,and so on. Either kind of
phrase is thus used in order to designate what Aquinas calls
Forms; to understand his use of quowe must exaniine his
notion of forms, which moreover is intimately connected
in other ways with his doctrne of esse.
For Aquinas, the real distinction between a form and
thesself-subsistent individual (suppositum)whose form it is
comes out in the logical distinction between subject and
2E
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
252
P.
T.
GEACH.
',
but the predicate " runs " from which this name is
formed; and " runs " and " thing that runs " are by no
means synonymous; the relation between their modisignificandi in fact raises over again the same problem as the
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
253
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
254
P.
T.
GEACH.
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
255
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
256
P. T. GEACH.
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
257
of
already gone wrong, for logically " the wisdom of Socrates "
does not split up into " the wisdom " and " of Socrates "
(sc. " that wisdom which is of Socrates ") but into " the
wisdom of. . . " and "Socrates ". What refers to a form is
" the wisdom of . . . ", not the whole phrase " the wisdom
of Socrates "; " the wisdom of . . . " needs to be completed
needs to be completed by a subject. " Of" is a logically inseparable part of the sign " the wisdom of . . . ", indicating
the need to put a name after this sign; and this need is
what makes the sign suitable to express a form, since a
form, as Aquinas says, is more properly termed entis than
ens. (Ia. q. 45 art. 4.) The linguistic oddity of the division
into " the wisdom of . . . " and " Socrates "-a
division
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
258
P. T. GEACH.
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
259
Socrates " without needing to understand the mythical relation of inherence. The term " wisdom ", like the term
" square root ", of itself demands a genitive to complete its
sense.
Again, in the sense of the word " form " that we have
so far used, what the phrase " the wisdom of Socrates"
designates is not a form simpliciter;but can legitimately be
said to be a form of Socrates, a form occurring in Socrates.
This too can be elucidated by our mathematical analogy.
Consider the square-root function: we cannot say that the
number 5 is that function or any other function: but we
can say that the number 5 is that function of the number 25.
So also the wisdom of Socrates is not a form simpliciterbut
is a form of or in Socrates. What designates a form is not
the whole phrase "the wisdom of Socrates ", but merely
"the wisdom of .
. "-although
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
260
P. T. GEACH.
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
261
God "-the square and the cube are quite distinct functions,
but " 1 " and "the square of I " and the " the cube of 1 " all
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
262
P. T. GEACH.
rather both. But now the individual red and the individual
square appear as distinct individual things, each with its
own distinct persistingidentity; there is no third individual,
non est ens. I do not
the red square; rubrumet quadratum
mean, of course, that there cannot be a red square object;
but then the persistent identity of this object will not
consist in any simple sensible character like redness or
squareness. It is because the philosophers' red square is
supposed to have no characteristics except a few simple
sensible ones that it falls to pieces under examination; for to
each such characterthere answersa distinct individual reality,
an individualized form-an individual extension, colour,
shape, etc.-and though these are united in one suppositum
x as the redness of x, the squarenessof x, etc., they are not
all one thing, the red patch; the red patch has no identity of
its own, nonest vereunumnecvereens.
These examples of individualizedformsmay be objectionable to some people as factitious philosophical examples.
But a wave, for example, is an identifiable individual that
can move locally (although Professor Prichard knew that
it was nonsense to say so); and this is certainly an
individualized form-it is that by which a certain body of
water is in a certain shape over part of its surface.
II.
"
The expression that by which the individual x is (or:
exists) " is senseless unless there is a sense in which " is "
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
263
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
264
P. T. GEACH.
not real) like Rover ". Here we are not pointing out any
trait that Cerberus has and Rover lacks; for it would be
nonsense to speak of the trait of being what thereis such a
thing as, and more nonsense to say that some things (e.g.,
Rover) have this trait, while other things (e.g., Cerberus)lack
it, and are thus things that there is no such thing as.
Logically our statement is about a difference not between
two dogs, Cerberus and Rover, but between the uses of two
words " Cerberus " and " Rover ".
The word
''
Rover "
the parent's reassuring " Cerberus does not exist ", and
how it is about the word " Cerberus", we cannot content
ourselves with writing " (The word) ' Cerberus ' does not
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
265
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
266
P. T. GEACH.
place I have cited, and says that the " existence " involved
in a true affirmative answer to it consists in the truth of an
affirmative predication (compositio). This is exactly right,
for " an F exists " is true if and only if " F " is truly predicable
of something or other. Moreover, the same logical status
is expresslyascribed to " God exists ", or " there is a God"
(Ia. q. 3 art. 4 ad 2 um); and Aquinas expresslydenies that
this statement relates to what he calls God's esse or actus
essendi. (This most important negative indication as to how
we must understandthe term essehas often been overlooked).
In " God exists " we are not predicating something of God,
but predicating the term " God " itself; " God exists"
means " something or other is God ". When we see this,
we can steer our way safely through all the shoals of the
17th-centuryontological argument. (Though it is commonly called by the same name, I think Anselm's argument is
essentially different; I shall not here discuss it.)
It is important that for Aquinas " God " is a descriptive,
predicable, term (nomennaturae-Frege's Begriffswort)and
not a logically proper name. Only because of this can the
question whether there is one God or many make sense;
just as the question whether there is one sun or many
makes sense only if " sun " is used to mean " heavenly
body of such-and-sucha nature ", not if it is a proper name
of this heavenly body. (Ia.q. 13 art. 9) Only because of
this can the heathen say his idol is God and the Christian
contradict him and both be using " God " in the same
sense; if " God " were a proper name, it would be a
logically impossible, not a lying, wicked, act, to predicate
it of stocks and stones. (Ia. q. 13 art. 10).
We now come on to C statements like "Joseph is not
and Simeon is not ". It would be quite absurd to say
that Jacob in uttering these words was not talking about
Joseph and Simeon but about the use of their names. Of
course he was talking about his sons; he was expressing a
fear that something had happened to them, that they were
dead. We have here a sense of " is " or " exists " that seems
to me to be certainly a genuine predicate of individuals;
the sense of " exist" in which one says that an individual
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
267
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
268
P. T. GEACH.
",
we consider
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
269
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
270
P. T. GEACH.
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
271
272
P.
T.
GEACH.
This content downloaded from 128.103.149.52 on Wed, 06 May 2015 16:36:56 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions