Levi-Strauss Claude The Savage Mind
Levi-Strauss Claude The Savage Mind
Levi-Strauss Claude The Savage Mind
Editors:
THE SAVAGE
MIND
(La Pensee Sauvage)
Claude Levi- Strauss
WEID E N F E L D AND N I C O L S ON
5 W INSLEY STREET LONDON WI
To the Memory
of
Maurice Merleau-Ponty
. ,
CONTENTS
PREFACE
(i)
35
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
75
1 35
161
TIME REGAINED
217
245
BIBLIOGRAPHY
271
I ND EX
.(
i
I L L USTRAT I O NS
P REFACE
Small differences are noted . . . they have a name for every one of
the coniferous trees of the region ; in these cases differences are not con
spicuous. The ordinary individual among the whites does not distinguish
(them) . . . Indeed, it would be possible to translate a treatise on botany
into Tewa . . . (Robbins, Harrington and Freire-Marreco, pp. 9, 12).
Conklin quotes the following extract from his field notes to illus
trate the intimate contact between man and his environment which
the native is constantly imposing on the ethnologist:
At o6oo and in a light rain, Langba and I left Parina for Binli . . . At
Aresaas, Langba told me to cut off several 10 x so em. strips of bark from
an napla kilala tree (Albizzia procera (Roxb.) Benth.) for protection
agamst the leeches. By periodically rubbing the cambium side of the
strips of sapanceous (and poisonous : Quisumbling, 1 947, 148) bark over
our ankles and legs - already wet from the rain -soaked vegetation - we
produced a most effective leech-repellent lather of pink suds. At one spot
along the trail near Aypud, Langba stopped suddenly, jabbed his walking
stick sharply into the side of the trail and pulled up a small weed; tawag
kugum buladlad (Buchnera urticifolia R. Br.) which he told me he will use
as a lure . . . for a spring-spear boar trap. A few minutes later, and we
were going at a good pace, he stopped in a similar manner to dig up a
small terrestrial orchid (hardly noticeable beneath the other foliage)
known as liyamliyam (Epipogum roseum (D. Don.) Lindl.). This herb is
useful in the magical control of insect pests which destroy cultivated
plants. At Binli, Langha was careful not to damage those herbs when
searching through the contents of his palm leaf shoulder basket for apug
'slaked lime' and tabaku (Nicotiana tabacum L.) to offer in exchange for
other betel ingredients with the Binli folk. After an evaluative discussion
about the local forms of betel pepper (Piper betle L.) Langba got per
mission to cut sweet potato (Ipomoea batatas (L.) Poir.) vines of two
vegetatively distinguishable types, kamuti inaswang and kamuti lupaw
. . . In the camote patch, we cut twenty-five vine-tip sections (about
7 5 em. long) of each variety, and carefully wrapped them in the broad
fresh leaves of the cultivated saging saba (Musa sapientum compressa (Blco.
Teoforo) so that they would remain moist until we reached Langba's
place. Along the way we munched on a few stems of tubu minuma, a type
of sugar cane (Saccharum officinarum L.), stopped once to gather fallen
bunga area nuts (Areca catechu L.), and another time to pick and eat the
wild cherrylike fruits from some bugnay shrubs (Antidesma brunius (L.)
Spreng). We arrived at the Mararim by mid-afternoon having spent much
of our time on the trail discussing changes in the surrounding vegetation
in the last few decades! (Conklin I, pp. 1 5-17).
This knowledge and the linguistic means which it has at its dis
there are distinct terms
posal also extend to morphology. In
for all or ::t1most all the parts of
1;d mammals (Hendrsi:l
and Harrington, p. g). Forty tenns are employed in the morpho
logical description of the leaves of trees or plants,. and there are
fifteen distinct terms for the different parts of a maize plant.
The Hanug6o have more than a hl}ndred and fifty trms for the
parts and properties of_plants. These provide categories for the
7
., I
!
fact exactly the reverse of that which gives rise to works of art.
In the case of works of art, the starting point is a set of one or more
objects and one or more events which aesthetic creation unifies by
revealing a common structure. Myths travel the same road but
start from the other end. They use a structure to produce what is
itself an object consisting of a set of events (for all myths tell a
story). Art thus proceeds from a set (object + event) to the dis
covery of its structure. Myth starts from a structure by means of
which it constructs a set (object + event).
The first point tempts one to generalize the theory. The second
might seem to lead to a restriction of it. For we may ask whether
it is in fact the case that works of art are always an integration of
structure and event. This does not on the face of it seem to be
true for instance of the cedarwood Tlingit club, used to kill fish,
which I have in front of me on my bookshelf (Plate z). The artist
who carved it in the form of a sea monster intended the body of the
implement to be fused with the body of the animal and the handle
with its tail, and that the anatomical proportions, taken from a
fabulous creature, should be such that the object could be the cruel
animal slaying helpless victims, at the same time as an easily
handled, balanced and efficient fishing utensil. Everything about
this implement - which is also a superb work of art - seems to be a
matter of structure : its mythical symbolism as well as its practical
function. More accurately, the object, its function and its sym
bolism seem to be inextricably bound up with each other and to
form a closed system in which there is no place for events. The
monster's position, appearance and expression owe nothing to the
historical circumstances in which the artist saw it, in the flesh or in
a dream, or conceived the idea of it. It is rather as if its immutable
being were finally fixed in the wood whose fine grain allows the
reproduction of all its aspects and in the use for which its empirical
form seems to pre-determine it. And all this applies equally to the
other products of primitive art : an African statue or ')- Melanesian
mask . . . So it looks as if we have defined only one local and
historical form of aesthetic creation and not its fundamental pro
perties or those by means of which its intelligible relations with
other forms of creation can be described.
We have only to widen our explanation to overcome this diffi
culty. What, with reference to a picture of Clouet's, was provision
ally defined as an event or set of events now appears under a
broader heading : events in this sense are only one mode of the
contingent whose integration (perceived as necessary) into a struc
ture gives rise to the aesthetic emotion. This is so whatever the type
of art in question. Depending on the style, place and period the
contingent plays a part in three different ways or at three distinct
points in artistic creation (or in all of them). It may play a part in
the occasion for the work or in the execution of the work or in the
purpose for which it is intended. It is only in the first case that it
takes the form of an event properly speaking, that is, of conting
ency exterior and prior to the creative act. The artist perceives it
from without as an attitude, an expression, a light effect or a
situation, whose sensible and intellectual relations to the structure
of the object affected by these modalities he grasps and incorpor
ates in his work. But the contingent can also play an intrinsic part
in the course of execution itself, in the size or shape of the piece of
wood the sculptor lays hands on, in the direction and quality of its
grain, in the imperfections of his tools, in the resistance which his
materials or project offer to the work in the course of its accomplish
ment, in the unforeseeable incidents arising during work. Finally,
the contingent can be extrinsic as in the frst case but posterior,
instead of anterior, to the act of creation. This is the case whenever
the work is destined for a specific end, since the artist will construct
it with a view to its potential condition and successive uses in the
future and so will put himself, consciously or unconsciously, in the
place of the person for whose use it is intended.
The process of artistic creation therefore consists in trying to
communicate (within the immutable framework of a mutual con
frontation of structure and accident) either with the model or with
the materials or with the future user as the case may be, according
to which of these the artist particularly looks to for his directions
while he is at work . Each case roughly corresponds to a readily
identifiable form of art : the first to the plastic arts of the West, the
second to so-called primitive or early art and the third to the
applied arts. But it would be an oversimplification to take these
identifications very strictly. All forms of art allow all three aspects
and they are qnly distinguished from one another by the relative
proportion of each. Even the most academic of painters comes up
against problems of execution, for example. All the so-called primi
tive arts can be called applied in a double sense : first, because many
of their productions are technical objects and, secondly, because
z6
27
sides to reach the same score (Read, p. 429). This is treating a game
as a ritual.
The same can be said of the games which t<>;ok place among the
Fox Indians during adoption ceremonies. Their purpose was to
replace a dead relative by a living one and so to allow the fnal
departure of the soul of the deceased.* The main aim of funeral rites
among the Fox seems indeed to be to get rid of the dead and to
prevent them from avenging on the living their bitterness and their
regret that they are no longer among them. For native philosophy
resolutely sides with the living : 'Death is a hard thing. Sorrow is
especially hard'.
Death originated in the destruction by superna.tural powers of
the younger of two mythical brothers who are cultural heroes
among all the Algonkin. But it was not yet final. It was made so by
the elder brother when, in spite of his sorrow, he rejected the
ghost's request to be allowed to return to his place among the
living. Men must follow this example and be firm with the dead.
The living must make them understand that they have lost nothing
by dying since they regularly receive offerings of tobacco and food.
In return they are expected to compensate the living for the reality
of death which they recall to them and for the sorrow their demise
causes them by guaranteeing them long life, clothes and something
to eat. ' It is the dead who make food increase', a native informant
explains. 'They (the Indians) must coax them that way' (Michelson
I, pp. 369, 407).
Now, the adoption rites which are necessary to make the soul of
the deceased finally decide to go where it will take on the role of a
protecting spirit are normally accompanied by competitive sports,
games of skill or chance between teams which are constituted on
the basis of an ad hoc division into two sides, Tokan and Kicko.
It is said explicitly over and over again that it is the living and the
dead who are playing against each other. It is as if the living offered
the dead the consolation of a last match before finally being rid of
them. But, since the two teams are asymmetrical in what they
stand for, the outcome is inevitably determined in advance :
30
. This is how it is when they play ball. When the man for whom the
adoption-feast is held is a Tokana, the Tokanagi win the game. The
Kickoagi cannot win. And if it is a Kicko woman for whom the adoption* See below, p. 199 n.
31
feast is given, the Kickoagi win, as in turn the Tokanagi do not win
(Michelson I, p. 3 85).
And what is in fact the case? It is clear that it is only the living who
win in the great biological and social game which is constantly
taking place between the living and the dead. But, as all the North
American mythology confrms, to win a game is symbolically to
'kill' one's opponent ; this is depicted as really happening in in
numerable myths. By ruling that they should always win, the dead
are given the illusion that it is they who are really alive, and that
their opponents, having been 'killed' by them, are dead. Under the
guise of playing with the dead, one plays them false and commits
them. The formal structure of what might at first sight be taken
for a competitive game is in fact identical with that of a typical
ritual such as the Mitawit or Midewinin of these same Algonkin
peoples in which the initiates get symbolically killed by the dead
whose part is played by the initiated ; they feign death in order to
obtain a further lease of life. In both cases, death is brought in but
only to be duped.
Games thus appear to have a disjunctive effect : they end in the
establishment of a difference between individual players or teams
where originally there was no indication of inequality. And at the
end of the game they are distinguished into winners and losers.
Ritual, on the other hand, is the exact inverse; it conjoins, for it
brings about a union (one might even say communion in this con
text) or in any case an organic relation between two initially separ
ate groups, one ideally merging with the person of the officiant and
the other with the collectivity of the faithful. In the case of games
the symmetry is therefore preordained and it is of a structural kind
since it follows from the principle that the rules are the same for
both sides. Asymmetry is engendered : it follows inevitably from
the contingent nature of events, themselves due to intention, chance
or talent. The reverse is true of ritual. There is an asymmetry which
is postulated in advance between profane and sacred, faithful and
officiating, dead and living, initiated and uninitiated, etc., and the
'game' consists in making all the participants pass to the winning
side by means of events, the nature and ordering of which is
genuinely structural. Like science (though here again on both the
theoretical and the practical plane) the game produces events by
means of a structure ; and we can therefore understand why com
petitive games should flourish in our industrial societies. Rites
32
T H E SCIENCE OF T H E C ONCRETE
33
T H E L O G I C O F T O T E M I C C LA S S I F I C A T I O N S
Flippy was no fish, and when he looked at you with twinkling eyes from
a distance of less than two feet, you had to stifle the question as to whether
it was in fact an animal. So new, strange and extremely weird was this
creature, that one was tempted to consider it as some kind of bewitched
being. But the zoologist's brain kept on associating it with the cold fact,
painful in this connection, that it was known to science by the dull name,
Tursiops truncatus (Hediger, p. 1 38).
39
feet where maize will not ripen) further than it has perhaps ever
been done.
Over two hundred and fifty varieties are still distinguished in
native vocabulary and the figure was certainly higher in the past.
This taxonomy operates by using a term to designate the variety
and adding a qualifying adjective for each subvariety. Thus the
variety imilla 'girl' is subdivided either according to colour (black,
blue, white, red, blood-coloured) or according to other characteris
tics such as grassy, insipid, egg-shaped and so on. There are about
twenty-two main varieties which are subdivided in this way. In
addition, there is a general dichotomy between those which may
be eaten after simple cooking and those which can only be eaten
after being alternately frozen and fermented. A binomial taxonomy
also always uses criteria such as form (flat, thick, spiral, like cactus
leaf, lumpy, egg-shaped, in the shape of an ox tongue, etc.),
texture (mealy, elastic, sticky, etc.), or 'sex' (boy or girl) (La
Barre).
, It was a professional biologist who pointed out how many
errors and misunderstanding, some of which have only recently
been rectified, could have been avoided, had the older travellers
been content to rely on native taxonomies instead of improvising
entirely new ones. The result was that eleven different authors
between them applied the scientific name Canis azarae to three
distinct genera, eight species and nine different sub-species, or
again that a single v:ariety of the same species was referred to by
several different names. The Guarani of Argentine and Paraguay,
on the other hand, work methodically with names composed of
one, two or three terms. By this means they distinguish for
instance between large, small and medium felines : the dyagua ete
is the supreme example of the large feline, the mbarakadya ete of
the small wild cat. The mini (small) among the dyague (large)
correspond to the guasu (large) among the chivi, that is, the
medium-sized felines :
In the face of such accuracy and care one begins to wish that every
ethnologist were also a mineralogist, a botanist, a zoologist and
even an astronomer . . . For Reichard's comment about the Navaho
applies not only to the Australians and Sudanese but to all or
almost all native peoples :
44
45
/'
'
1 , ! ,I
'
"
so
also from a mythical point of view (the eagle being at the top of
the mythical hierarchy of birds).
Analysis of the ritual shows that it accords in every detail with
the hypothesis that there is a dualism between a celestial prey and
a subterranean hunter, which at the same time evokes the strongest
possible contrast between high and low in the sphere of hunting.
The extreme complexity of the rites which precede, accompany and
conclude an eagle hunt is the counterpart of the exceptional
position which eagle hunting occupies within a mythical typology
which makes it the concrete expression of the widest possilJle.
distance between a hunter and his game.
.
Some obscure features of the ritual become clear at the same
time, in particular the significance and meaning of the myths
which are told during hunting expeditions. They refer to cultural
heroes, capable of being transformed into arrows and masters of
the art of hunting with bows and arrows ; and therefore, in their
guise of wild cats and racoons, doubly inappropriate for the role
of bait in eagle hunting. Hunting w!th bows and arrows involves
the region or space immediately above the earth, that is, the .
atmospheric or middle sky : the hunter and his game meet in the
intermediate space. Eagle hunting, on the other hand, separates
them by giving them opposite positions : the hunter below the
ground and the game close to the empyrean sky.
Another striking feature of eagle hunting is that women have a
beneficial effect during their periods. This is contrary to the
belief held almost universally by hunting peoples, including the
Hidatsa themselves in the case of all except eagle hunting. What'
has just been said explains this detail also, when it is remembered
that in eagle hunting, conceived as the narrowing of a wide gulf
between hunter and game, mediation is effected, from the technical
point of view, by means of the bait, a piece of meat or small piece
of game, the bloodstained carcass of which is destined to rapid
decay. A first hunt to procure the bait is necessary in order for
the second hunt to take place. One hunt involves the shedding of
blood (by means of bows and arrows), the other does not (eagles
are strangled without any effusion of blood). The one hunt, which
consists in a close union of hunter and game, furnishes the means
of effecting a union between what is so distant that it looks
at first as if there is a gulf which cannot be bridged - except,_
precisely, by means of blood.
SI
53
1 J
!I
: !
54
55
s6
57
* And not only squirrels : 'The worst danger threatening pregnant women is
from animal :Vho live or are caught in any sort of hole (in the ground, in trees).
One can posttively speak of a horror vacui. If a pregnant woman eats an animal
o this kind, te child might also want to stay in its hole, "in the belly", and a
_
ts to b expected. Similarly the parents must not, during this
dtcult btrth
penod, take out any btrds' nests which have been built into the hollows of trees,
and one of my employees, who had made a woman pregnant, absolutely refused
to make me a model of a loaf of cassava, on the grounds that it would have to be
hollow' (Tessman, vol. 2, p. 1 93).
6o
61
of the term, but, as among the Bemba and the Ambo, joking
relationships link them in pairs. The reasoning behind this has,
from our point of view, the same interest. As I showed in an
earlier book and am continuing to establish here, so-called
totemism is in fact only a particular case of the general problem of
classification and one of many examples of the part which specific
terms often play in the working out of a social classification.
The following clans stand in a joking relationship to each other
among the Luapula : the Leopard and Goat clans because the
leopards eat goats, the Mushroom and Anthill clans because
mushrooms grow on anthills, the Mush and Goat clans because
men like meat in their mush, the Elephant and Clay clans because
women in the old days used to carve elephants' footprints in the
ground and use these natural shapes as receptacles instead of
fashioning pots. The Anthill clan is linked with the Snake clan
and also with the Grass clan because grass grows tall on anthills
and snakes hide there. The Iron clan jokes with all clans with
animal names because animals are killed by metal spears and
bullets. Reasoning of this kind allows the definition of a hierarchy
of clans : the Leopard clan is superior to the Goat clan, the Iron
clan to the animal clans and the Rain clan to the Iron clan because
rain rusts iron. Moreover the rain clan is superior to all the other
clans because animals would die without it, one cannot make mush
(a clan name) without it, clay (a clan name) cannot be worked
without it, and so on (Cunnison, pp. 62-5).
The Navaho give many different justifications of the virtues they
ascribe to medicinal plants and their modes of employing them :
the plant grows near a more important medicinal plant ; one of the
plant's organs looks like a part of the body ; the odour (or feel or
taste) of the plant is 'right' ; the plant makes water the 'right' colour ;
the plant is associated with an animal (as food, or in habitat, or by
contact) ; the knowledge was revealed by the gods ; its uses were
learnt from someone else without any explanation : the plant is
found near a tree struck by lightning ; it is good for a certain ailment
in that part of the body or an ailment with similar effects, etc.
(Vestal, p. 58). The terms used to differentiate plant names among
the Hanun6o belong to the following categories : leaf shape, colour,
habitat, size/dimension, sex, habit of growth, plant host, growing
time, taste, smell (Conklin I, p. 131).
These examples, together with those given earlier, make it clear
6z
that such systems of logic work on several axes at the same time. '
The relations which they set up between the terms are most
commonly based on contiguity (snake and anthill among the
Luapula and also the Toreya of South India)* or on resemblance
(red ants and cobras which, according to the Nuer, resemble each
other in 'colour'). In this they are not formally distinct from other
taxonomies, even modern ones, in which contiguity and resem
blance also play a fundamental part : contiguity for discovering
things which 'belong both structurally and functionally . . . to a
single system' and resemblance, which does not require member
shp of the same system and is based simply on the possession by
objects of one or more common characteristics , such as all being
'yellow or all smooth, or all with wings or all ten feet high (Simpson,
pp. 3-4).
But other types of relation intervene in the examples we have
just examined. Relations may be established, in effect, on either
the sensibl lev:l the bodily markings of the bee and the pythons)
or on the mtelhg1ble level (the function of construction common
to the bee and the carpenter) : the same animal, the bee, functions,
as it were, at different levels of abstraction in two cultures. Again,
the connection can be close or distant, synchronic or diachronic
(the relation between squirrels and cedars for instance on the one
hand, and that between pottery and elephants' footprints on the
oter), static (mush and goat) or dynamic (fire kills animals, rain
'lulls' fire ; the flowering of a plant indicates that it is time to
return to the village), etc.
It is probable that the number, nature and 'quality' of these
logical axes is not the same in every culture, and that cultures could
be classified into richer and poorer on the basis of the formal
properties of the systems of reference to which they appeal in the
construction of their classifications. However, even those which
are the least well endowed in this respect employ logics of several
dimensions, the listing, analysis and interpretation of which would
require a wealth of ethnographic and general information which
is all too often lacking.
* 'The members of the sept, at times of marriage, worship anthills, which are
of snakes' (Thurston, vol. VII, p. 176). Similarly in New Guinea :
certam types of plans, as well as the animals and plants parasitic on them, are
thought of as belongmg to the same mythical and totemic unit' (Wirz, vol. II,
p. 21).
he h?mes
64
red is the colour of life and fertility (C. M. N. White I, pp. 46-7).*
White represents the 'unstressed' situation in both cases, while
red - the chromatic pole of the opposition - is associated with
death in one case and with life in the other. In the Forrest River
district of Australia, members of a deceased person's own genera
tion paint themselves black and white and keep away from the
corpse while those of other generations do not paint themselves
and approach the corpse. 'Fhe opposition white/red is thus re
placed, without any change of semantic load, by an opposition
black + whitejO. Instead ofthe values given to white and red being
reversed, as in the previous case, the value of white (here associated
with black, a non-chromatic colour) remains constant, and it is the
content of the opposite pole which is reversed, changing from the
'super-colour' red to the total absence of colour. Finally, another
Australian tribe, the Bard, constructs its symbolism by means of
the opposition black/red. Black is the colour of mourning for even
generations (grandfather, Ego, grandson) and red the colour of
mourning for uneven generations (father, son), that is, those which
are not assimilated with the generation of the deceased (Elkin 4,
pp. 298 9). The opposition between two differently stressed terms
- life and death among the Luvale, ' someone else's death and "my"
death' in Australia - is thus expressed by pairs of elements taken
from the same symbolic chain ; absence of colour, black, white,
black + white, red (as the supreme presence of colour), etc.
The same fundamental opposition is found among the Fox, but
transposed from colour to sound. While the burial ceremony is in
progress 'those burying (the dead) talked to each other. But the
others did not say a thing to each other' (Michelson I, p. 41 1 ). The
opposition between speech and silence, between noise and the
absence of noise, corresponds to that between colour and the
absence of colour or between two chromatisms of different
degrees. These observations seem to make it possible to dispose of
theories making use of the concepts of ' archetypes' or a ' collective
unconscious'. It is only forms and not contents which can be
common. If there are common contents the reason must be sough
either in the objective properties of particular nature or artificial
entities or in diffusion and borrowing, in either case, that is,
outside the mind.
* As in China, where white is the colour of mourning and red the colour of
marriage.
, .
i
I
'
'!
,I
I, I
:
'
its parts like a motor with a feed-back device : governed (in both
senses of the word) by its previous harmony, it will direct the dis
cordant mechanism towards an equilibrium which will be at any
rate a compromise between the old state of affairs and the confusion
brought in from outside.
Whether they are historically correct or not, the traditional
legends of the Osage show that native thought itself may well
envisage this sort of interpretation, based on the hypothesis of a
structural adjustment of the historical process. When the ancestors
emerged from the bowels of the earth they were, according to
Osage tradition, divided into two groups, one peace-loving, vege
tarian and associated with the left side and the other warlike,
carnivorous and associated with the right. The two groups resolved
to ally themselves and to exchange their respective foods. In the
course of their wanderings, they met a third group, which was
ferocious and lived entirely on carrion, with whom they eventually
united. Each of the three groups was originally composed of seven
clans, making a total of twenty-one clans. In spite of the symmetry
of this three-clan division, the system was in disequilibrium since
the newcomers belonged to the side of war and there were fourteen
clans on one side and seven on the other. In order to remedy this
defect and to preserve the balance between the side of war and the
side of peace, the number of clans in one of the groups of warriors
was reduced to five and that in the other to two. Since then the
Osage camps, which are circular in shape with the entrance facing
east, consist of seven clans of peace occupying the northern half on
the left of the entrance and seven clans of war occupying the
southern half on the right of the entrance (J. 0. Dorsey I, 2). The
legend suggests twin processes. One is purely structural, passing
from a dual to a three-fold system and then returning to the earlier
dualism ; the other, both structural and historical at the same time,
consists in undoing the effects of an overthrow of the primitive
structure, resulting from historical events, or events thought of as
such : migrations, war, alliance. Now, the social organization of the
Osage, as it was to be seen . in the nineteenth century, in fact
integrated both aspects. Although they were each composed of the
same number of clans, the side of peace and the side of war were
in disequilibrium since one was simply 'sky' while the other, also
referred to as 'of the earth', consisted of two groups of clans
associated respectively with dry land and water. The system was
68
4-TSM
69
THE SAVAGE M I N D
The Osage would probably have used these two types of opposi
tion, one synchronic and the other diachronic, as a point of
departure. Instead of expecting to be able to choose between them
they would have accepted both on the same footing and would
have tried to work out a single scheme which allowed them to
combine the standpoint of structure with that of event.
Considerations of the same kind could undoubtedly provide an
7I
the aesthetic and the logical, and those who have tried to define
them in terms of only one or the other aspect have therefore
necessarily failed to understand their nature. Between the basic
absurdity Frazer attributed to primitive practices and beliefs and
the specious validation of them in terms of a supposed common
sense invoked by Malinowski, there is scope for a whole science
and a whole philosophy.
CHAPTER T H R E E
75
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
which was found, then the child may not even touch the tree on
which it grows. Ingestion or contact are regarded as a sort of
auto-cannibalism. The relation between the person and the object
is so close that the person possesses the characteristics of the object
with which he is identified. If, for example, it was an eel or sea
snake which was found, the child will, like these, be weak and
indolent, if a hermit crab, it will be hot-tempered ; or again, it will
be gentle and sweet-natured like the lizard, thoughtless, hasty and
intemperate like the rat or, if it was a wild apple which was found,
it will have a big belly the shape of an apple. These identifications
are also to be found at Motlav (the name of a part of Saddle Island)
(Rivers, p. 462). The connection between an individual on the one
hand and a plant, animal or object on the other is not general ; it
only affects some people. It is not hereditary and it does not involve
exogamous prohibitions between the men and women who happen
to be associated with creatures of the same species (Frazer vol. II,
pp. 8 1-3 , pp. 89-9 1 (quoting Rivers), and vol. IV, pp. 286-7).
Frazer regards these beliefs as the origin and explanation of those
found at Lifu in the Loyalty Islands and at Ulawa and Malaita in
the Solomon Islands. At Lifu a man before he dies sometimes
indicates the animal (or bird or butterfly) in whose form he will be
reincarnated. All his descendants are then forbidden to eat or kill
this animal. 'It is our ancestor', they say, and offerings are made to
it. Similarly Codrington observed that in the Solomon Islands
(Ulawa) the inhabitants refused to plant banana trees or eat
bananas because an important person, so he could be reincarnated
in them, had once forbidden it before his death.* In Central
Melanesia the origin of food taboos must therefore be sought in the
fanciful imaginations of particular ancestors. Frazer believed that
they were the indirect result and distant repercussions of the
cravings and sickly imaginings common among pregnant women.
He held that this psychological trait, which he elevated to the status
of a natural and universal phenomenon, was the ultimate origin of
all totemic beliefs and practices (Frazer, vol. II, pp. 106-7 et
passim).
The fact that the women of his period and circle of society
experienced cravings when they were pregnant and that the savage
Australian and Melanesian women also did so was enough to
convince Frazer of the universality and natural origin of the
phenomenon. He would have had otherwise to dissociate it from
nature and attribute it to culture, thus admitting that there could
in some way be direct, and so alarming, resemblances between late
nineteenth century European societies and those of the cannibals.
Now, apart from the fact that there is no evidence that pregnant
women the world over have crvings, their incidence has dimin
ished considerably in Europe in the last fifty years and they may
even have disappeared altogether in some sections of society. They
certainly occurred in Australia and Melanesia but in the form of an
institutional means of defining in advance certain aspects of the
status of persons or groups. And in Europe itself, it is unlikely that
the cravings of pregnant women will survive the disappearance of
a similar type of belief which fosters them - on the pretext of
referring to them - in order to diagnose (not predict) certain
physical or psychological peculiarities noticed after (not before) a
child's birth. Even if it were the case that the cravings of pregnant
women had a natural basis, this latter could not account for beliefs
and practices which, as we have seen, are far from being general
and which can take different forms in different societies.
Further, it is not clear what made Frazer give the 'sick fancies' of
pregnant women priority over those of old men at death's door,
except perhaps the fact that people must be born before they can
die. But by this reasoning all social institutions should have come
into existence in the course of a single generation. Finally, had the
system of Ulawa, Malaita and Lifu been derived from that of
Motlav, Mota and Aurora, the remains or survivals of the latter
should be found in the former. What is striking, however, is that the
two systems are exact counterparts of each other. There is nothing
to suggest that one is chronologically prior to the other. Their
relation is not that of an original to a derivative form. It is rather
that between forms symmetrically the reverse of each other, as if
system represented a transformation of the same group.
Instead of trying to discerg the priorities, let us think in terms of
groups and attempt to define their properties. We can summarize
these properties as a triple opposition : between birth and death on
the one hand, and between the individual or collective nature
either of a diagnosis or of a prohibition on the other. It is worth
* This fact is confirmed by Ivens, pp. 269-70, who puts forward a somewhat
different interpretation. However, he cites other prohibitions originating in
reincarnation of an ancestor. Cf. pp. 272, 468 and passim. Cf. also C. E. Fox for
beliefs of the same type at San Cristoval.
79
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
84
ss
l
THE SAVAGE MIND
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
laws. The greater our knowledge, the more obscure the overall
scheme. The dimensions multiply, and the growth of axes of
reference beyond a certain point paralyses intuitive methods : it
becoes impossible to visualize a system when its representation
.
reqmres a contmuum of more than three or four dimensions. But
the day may come when all the available documentation on Austra
lian tribes is tansfer ed to punched cards and with the help of a
* With the undoubted exception of the northern regions and these were not
witout contact with the rest of the continent. This is therefore only an approxi
matiOn.
88
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
rage in this closed world and the influence of fashion often para
mount, it is easy to understand the emergence of a sort of common
philosophical and sociological style along with methodically
studied variations on it, even the most minor of which were
pointed out for favourable or adverse comment. Each group was
no doubt actuated by the only apparently contradictory incentives
of being like others, as good as others, better than others and
different from others, that is, of constantly elaborating themes only
the general outlines of which were fixed by tradition and custom.
In short, in the field of social organization and religious thought,
the Australian communities behaved like the peasant societies of
Europe in their manner of dressing in the late eighteenth and early
nineteenth centuries. That each community had its own dress and
that this was composed of roughly the same elements for men and
women respectively was never called in question. It was in wealth
or ingenuity of detail alone that people tried to distinguish them
selves from, and to outdo, the neighbouring village. All women
wore coifs but they were different in different regions. In France
marriage rules of an endogamous kind were expressed in terms of
coifs ('Marry within the coif') just as Australian rules (of an
exogamous kind) were expressed in terms of sections or totemism.
Here, as elsewhere, among the Australian aborigines as in our own
peasant societies the combination of general conformity (which is
a feature of a closed world) with the particularism of the parish
results in culture being treated like themes and variations in music.
It is therefore conceivable that the favourable historical and geo
graphical conditions outlined have led to Australian cultures stand
ing in a relation of transformation with each other, possibly more
completely and systematically than those of other regions of the
world. But this external relation must not make us neglect the
same relation, this time internal, which exists, in a very much more
general fashion, between the different levels of a single culture.
As I have already suggested, ideas and beliefs of the .'totemic' type
particularly merit attention because, for the societies which have
constructed or adopted them, they constitute codes making it
possible to ensure, in the form of conceptual systems, the con
vertibility of messages appertaining to each level, even of those
which are so remote from each other that they apparently relate
solely to culture or solely to society, that is, to men's relations with
each other, on the one hand, or, on the other, to phenomena of a
1.'1
r',
,'
THE SAVAGE MIND
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
state of affairs. There are two seasons just as there are two sexes,
two societies, two degrees of culture (the 'high' - that of the
initiated - and the 'low' ; cf. Stanner I, p. 77 for this distinction).
On the natural plane, however, the good season is subordinate to
the bad, while on the social plane the relation between the corres
ponding terms is reversed. It is therefore necessary to decide how
to interpret the contradiction. If the good season is said to be male
on the grounds that it is superior to the bad season and that men
and the initiated are superior to women and the uninitiated (a
category to which women also belong) then not only power and
efficacy but sterility as well would have to be attributed to the
profane and female element. This would be doubly absurd since
social power belongs to men and natural fertility to women. The
other alternative is equally contradictory but its inconsistency can
at least be disguised by the double division of the whole society
into the two classes of men and women (now ritually as well as
naturally differentiated) and the group of men into the two classes
of old and young, initiated and uninitiated, according to the
principle that the uninitiated stand in the same relation to the inia
ted in the societyof men as women do to men within the society as
a whole. But in consequence men forego embodying the happy side
of existence for they cannot both rule and personify it. Irrevocably
committed to the role of gloomy owners 'of a happiness accessible
only through an intermediary, they fashion an image of themselves
on the model of their sages and old men ; and it is striking that two
types of people, women on the one hand and old men on the other,
constitute, as the means to and the masters of happiness respec
tively, the two poles of Australian society and that to attain full
masculinity young men must temporarily renounce the former and
lastingly submit to the latter.
The sexual privileges which old men enjoy, the control they
exercise . over an esoteric culture and sinister and mysterious
initiation rites are undoubtedly general features . of Australian
societies, and examples could also be found in other parts of the
world. I do not wish to claim that these phenomena are attributable
to what are obviously local natural conditions. In order to avoid
misunderstandings and in particular the charge of reviving an old
geographical determinism, this needs to be explained.
The first point is that natural conditions are not just passively
accepted. What is more they do not exist in their own righJ for
they are a function of the techniques and way of life of the people
who define and give them a meaning by developing them in a
particular direction. Nature is not in itself contradictory. It can
become so only in terms of some specific human activity which
takes part in it ; and the characteristics of the environment take on
a different meaning according to the particular historical and
technical form assumed in it by this or that type of activity. On
the other hand, even when raised to that human level which alone
can make them intelligible, man's relations with his natural
environment remain objects of thought : man never perceives them
passively ; having reduced them to concepts, he compounds them
in order to arrive at a system which is never determined in
advance : the same situation can always be systematized in various
ways. The mistake of Mannhardt and the Naturalist School was to
think that natural phenomena are what myths seek to explain, when
they are rather the medium through which myths try to explain
facts which are themselves not of a natural but a logical order.
The sense in which infrastructures are primary is this : first, man
is like a player who, as he takes his place at the table, picks up cards
which he has not invented, for the cardgame is a datum of history
and civilization. Second, each deal is the reult of a contingent
distribution of the cards, unknown to the players at the time. One
must accept the cards which one is given, but each society, like
each player, makes its interpretations in terms of several systems.
These may be common to them all or individual : rules of the game
or rules of tactics. And we are well aware that different players will
not play the same game with the same hand even though the rules
set limits on the games that can be played with any given one.
To explain the noticeable frequency of certain sociological
solutions, not attributable to particular objective conditions, appeal
must be made to form and not content. The substance of contra
dictions is much less important than the fact that they exist, and
it would be a remarkable coincidence if a harmonious synthesis of
the social and natural order were to be achieved at once. Now, the
form contradictions take varies very much less than their empirical
content. The poverty of religious thought can never be over
estimated. It accounts for the fact that men have so often had
recourse to the same means for solving problems whose concrete
elements may be very different but which share the feature of all
belonging to 'structures of contradiction'.
94
95
To return to the Murngin : one can see clearly how the system
of totemic symbols permits the unification of heterogeneous
semantic fields at the cost of contradictions which it is the function
.
'
of ritual to surmount by 'acting' them : the rainy season literally
engulfs the dry season as men 'possess' women, and the initiated
'swallow up' the uninitiated, as famine destroys plenty, etc. The
example of the Murngin is not however unique. There are sugges
tive indications of a 'coding' of a natural situation in totemic terms
in other parts of the world also. A specialist on the Ojibwa, reflect
ing on the symbolization of thunder as a bird which is so common
in North America, makes the following remark :
According to meteorological observations, the average number of days
with thunder begins with one in April, increases to a total of five in mid
summer (July) and then declines to one in October. And if a bird caledar
is consulted, the facts show that species wintering in the South begm to
appear in April and disappear for the most part not later than October . . .
The avian character of the Thunder Birds can be rationalized to some
degree with reference to natural facts and their observation (Hallowell, p.
32).
THE SAVAGE M I N D
skin symbolizes difficulty in the healing of the scar; the genet whose
spotted skin symbolizes leprosy ; the hare with his sharp teeth and
'hot' chillies which symbolize painful healing, etc. Female
initiates are subject to analogous prohibitions (C. M. N. White, I,
2).
These prohibitions have been mentioned because they are
specialized, well-defined and rationalized with precision. They can
readily be distinguished from totemic prohibitions within the
general category of eating prohibitions and contrasted with them.
But Tessman's list of the very large number of prohibitions of the
Fang of the Gabon includes examples of intermediate as well as
extreme types - which explains why the question of whether the
Fang are totemic has been so hotly contested even by those
believing in the concept of totemism.
The prohibitions which the Fang call by the general term beki
may apply to men or to women, to the initiated to the uninitiated,
to adolescents or adults, to households in which a child is expected
or to those in which it is not. The reasons given for them are more
over of very different kinds. The inside of elephants' tusks may not
be eaten because it is a soft and bitter substance. The trunk of the
elephant may not be eaten for fear of softening limbs, sheep and
goats lest they communicate their panting. Squirrels are forbidden
to pregnant women because they make childbirth difficult (cf.
above [p. 61]). Mice are specially forbidden to girls because they
shamelessly steal manioc while it is being washed and the girls
would run the risk of being 'stolen' in the same way. Mice are
however also more generally forbidden because they live near
homesteads and are regarded as members of the family. Some
birds are avoided for such reasons as their ugly cry or their physical
appearance. Children may not eat the larvae of dragonfly because
it might make them unable to hold their urine.
The idea of a dietetic experiment envisaged by Tessman has
recently been taken up by Fischer with respect to the natives of
Ponapy who believe that the violation of food taboos results in
physiological disorders very like allergies. Fischer shows that
allergic disorders often have a psychosomatic origin even among
ourselves : in many patients they result from the violation of a
taboo of a psychological or moral kind. This apparently natural
symptom derives, then, from a cultural diagnosis.
Among the Fang, of whose prohibitions I have mentioned only
98
' ,, 1
,,
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
r, , l
: I'
'
I ,
!I
I
'
, I
I I
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
1 02
1 03
;r
'!
'I
, ,
i I
Ii
1 04
I ,
:I
SYSTEMS OF TRANSFORMATIONS
t i.e. 'fry' and 'put in the pot', terms used to refer to seduction as well as
cooking (trans. note).
10 5
f. .
'i ;
S Y S T E M S OF T R A N S F O R MA T I O N S
the sexes and the union of eater and eaten is that they both effect a
conjunction by complementarity :
I I
I '
i
I
'
I
I
i l
I I
i l
1 06
i
, I
I 'I I
I I
Tikuna:
Elema:
non-exclusive
\
exclusive
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
'
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
'
'
prohibition (-)
'
cedible parts
and common
properties)
prerogative C+>
( inedible
parts and
distinctive
properties)
The fur, feathers, beak and teeth can be mine because they are that
in which the eponymous animal and I differ from each other : this
difference is assumed by man as an emblem and to assert his
symbolic relation with the animal. The parts which are edible and
so can be assimilated are the sign of genuine consubstantiality but
which, contrary to what one might suppose, it is the real aim of
the prohibition on eating them to deny. Ethnologists have made
the mistake of taking only this second aspect into account and this
has led them to conceive the relation between man and animal to
be of a single kind : identity, affinity or participation. Matters are in
fact infinitely more complex : there is an exchange of similarities
and differences between culture and nature, sometimes as amongst
animals on the one side and man on the other and sometimes as
between animals and men.
The differences between animals, which man can extract from
nature and transfer to culture (either by describing them in terms
of opposites and contrasts and thus conceptualizing them or by
taking over concrete, non-perishable parts : feathers, beaks, teeth
which equally constitutes an 'abstraction') are adopted as emblems
by groups of men in order to do away with their own resemblances.
And the same animals are rejected as food by the same group of
men, in other words the resemblance between man and animal
resulting from the fact that the former can assimilate the flesh of
I I
, ,
CHAPTER F O U R
T O TEM AND C A S T E
Both the exchange of women and the excha11ge of food are means
of securing or of displaying the interlocking of social groups with
one another. This being so, we can see why they may be found
either together or separately. They are procedures of the same type
and are indeed generally thought of as two aspects of the same
procedure. They may reinforce each other, both performing the
actual function, or one performing it and the other representing it
symbolically. Or they may be alternatives, a single one fulfilling the
whole function or if that is otherwise discharged, as it can be even
in the absence of both procedures, then the symbolic representation
of it :
If . . . a people combines exogamy with totemism, this is because it has
I'
II
I I
I1
I
108
I
' I
I
1,
109
who has known how to persuade his neighbours' yams to move and
stablish themselves in his garden. A man who has a good harvest
IS reckoned a lucky thief (Fortune z).
Beliefs of the same type were to be found even in France until
recently. In the middle ages there was a penalty of death for 'the
sorceress who defiled and injured crops ; who, by reciting the
psalm Super aspidem ambulabis, emptied the fields of their corn to
fill er o:wn grana with this goodly produce'. Not so long ago at
Cubjac m the Pengord a magical invocation was supposed to
asure the ferson sing it of a good crop of turnips : 'May our
.
neighbours be as big as millet seed, our relations' as big as grains
of corn and our own as big as the head of Fauve the ox !' (Rocal,
PP I 64-s).
part from the modicum of exogamy resulting from the pro
.
hibited degrees, European peasant societies practised strict local
endogamy. And it is significant that at Dobu extreme endo-agricul
ture can act as the symbolic compensation for lineage and village
exogamy which is practised with repugnance and even fear. In
spite of the fact that endogamy within the locality - which consists
of beween four an tweny villages - is generally assured, marriage
even mt the next village IS looked on as putting a man at the mercy
of assassms and sorcerers and he himself always regards his wife
as a powerful magician, ready to deceive him with her childhood
friends and to destroy him and his (Fortune 2). In a case like this
no-agriclture reinforces a latent tendency towards endogamy
If md :ed It doe not express symbolically the hostility to the
.
nwlllmgly. practised rules of a precarious exogamy. The situation
IS symmetncally the reverse of that prevailing in Australia where
food prohibitions and rules of exogamy reinforce one another as
'
we ve seen i more symbolic and clearly conceptual way in the
patnhneal societies (where the food prohibitions are flexible and
tend to be formulated in terms of moieties, that is, at a level which
is alrea?y abstract and lends itself o a binary coding by pairs of
.
.
oppositiOn) and m a more literal and concrete fashion in the
matrilineal societies (where the prohibitions are rigid and stated in
terms of clans which one might often be hesitant to regard as
members of systematic sets, given the determining part of demo
graphic and historic factors in their genesis).
Apart from these cases of positive or negative parallelism, there
are others in which reciprocity between social groups is expressed
III
t Rightly or wrongly, Radcliffe-Brown (J, pp. 32-3) treats the Nandi kinship
system as an Omaha system.
I I2
113
his own may not touch an emu. But if, on the other hand, he is in
company he is permitted and even supposed to kill it and offer it
to hunters of other clans. Conversely, when he is alone a man of
the Water clan may drink if he is thirsty but when he is with others
he must receive the water from a member of the other moiety,
preferably from a brother-in-law (Spencer and Gillen, pp.
I 59-6o). Among the Warramunga each totemic group is respons
ible for the increase and availability to other groups of a particular
plant or animal species : 'The members of one moiety . . . take
charge . . . of the ceremonies of the other moiety which are des
tined to secure the increase of their own food supply'. Among the
Walpari as well as the Warramunga the secondary totemic prohi
bitions (applying to the maternal totem) are waived if the food in
question is obtained through the agency of a man of the other
moiety. More generally and for any totem, there is a distinction
between the groups which never eat it (because it is their own
totem), those which eat it only if it is procured through the agency
of another group (as in the case of the maternal totems), and those
which eat it freely in any circumstances. Similarly in the case of
the sacred water-holes, women may never approach them, uniniti
ated men may approach but not drink from them, while some
groups drink from them on the condition that the water is given
to them by members of other groups who can themselves drink
freely from them (Spencer and Gillen, pp. I 64, I 67). This mutual
interdependence is already to be seen in marriage which, as
Radcliffe-Brown has shown in the case of Australia (but the same
could equally well be said of other clan societies such as the
Iroquois), was based on reciprocal gifts of vegetable food (fem
inine) and animal food (masculine) : the conjugal family in these
cases was like a miniature society with two castes.
There is thus less difference than would appear between
societies which, like some Australian tribes, assign a distinctive
magico-economic function to totemic groups and, for instance,
the Bororo of Central Brazil, among whom specialists are in charge
of the same function of 'liberating' the food production - whether
animal or vegetable - for the whole group (Colbacchini). This
leads one to doubt whether the opposition between .endogamous
castes and exogamous totemic groups is really radical. There seem
to be connections between these two extreme types, whose nature
species
+ species 2 + species 3 +
CULTURE :
group
+ group
+ group
3 +
. . . . . species n
. . . . group n
.
: '
NATURE :
species
+ species 2 + species 3 +
CULTURE :
group
+ group
2 + group
.....
species n
. . . . . group n
'
'
'
THE SAVAGE M I N D
sisters and daughters with them since it will tend to think of them
as being of a particular 'species'. Two images, one social and the
other natural, and each articulated separately, will be replaced by a
socio-natural image, single but fragmented :*
u6
I I
NATURE :
CULTURE :
species
species 2
species 3
group
group
group
species
group
I I7
uS
I
'I
!'
(the tribes of the plains and of the south west) and societies such
as the Natchez which afford one of the rare examples of genuine
castes known in North America.
We have thus established that in the two classical territories of
so-called totemism, the institutions defined with reference to this
misleading notion can either also be characterized from the point
of view of their function, as in Australia or, as in America, make
way for forms which are still conceived on the model of totemic
groups although they operate more like castes.
L et us now turn to India, also classical territory but of castes.
I shall try to show that through their influence institutions tradi
tionally thought of as totemic undergo a transformation exactly the
reverse of that in America : instead of castes conceived in terms of
a natural model we have here totemic groups conceived in terms
of a cultural model.
Most of the totemic names found among certain tribes in Bengal
derive from animals or plants. This is the case with some sixty
seven totems recorded among the Oraon of Chota Nagput with
the exception of iron which, as there is little point in proscribing
its consumption, is forbidden to come into contact with lips or
tongue. This prohibition is thus still formulated in terms that
make it approximate to an eating prohibition. Among the Munda
of the same region, the majority of the three hundred and forty
exogamous clans recorded have animal or plant totems, the
consumption of which is forbidden. Totems of a different kind are
however already noticeable : full moon, moonlight, rainbow,
months of the year, days of the week, copper bracelet, verandah,
umbrella, professions or castes such as that of basket-maker and
torch-bearer (Risley, vol. II and Appendix). Further west, the
forty-three names of the Bhil clans are divided into nineteen plant
and seventeen animal names and seven relate to objects : dagger,
broken pot, village, thorny stick, bracelet, ankle ring, piece of bread
(Koppers, pp. I 18-1 9)
It is towards the south that the reversal in the relation of natural
species and objects or manufactured goods becomes particularly
conspicuous. Few plants and scarcely any animals figure in the
names of the clans of the Devanga, a caste of weavers in the
Madras area. On the other hand, the following names are found :
buttermilk, cattle-pen, money, dam, house, collyrium, knife,
scissors, boat, lamp, cloths, female clothing, ropes for hanging pots,
1 20
I 2I
THE SAVAGE M I ND
the cultural plane. In the same way that women who are homo
geneous so far as nature is concerned are declared to be heterogeneous
from the point of view of culture, so natural species, which are
heterogeneous so far as nature is concerned are proclaimed to be
homogeneous from the point of view of culture : culture asserts
them all to be subject to the same type of beliefs and practices since
in the eyes of culture, they have the common feature that man has
the power to control and increase them. Consequently, men by
cultural means exchange women who perpetuate these same men
by natural means and they claim to perpetuate species by cultural
means and exchange them sub specie naturae : in the form of food
stuffs which are substitutable for each other since they all provide
nourishment and since, as with women also, a man can satisfy
himself by means of some foods and go without others in so far as
any women or any foods are equally suitable to achieve the ends
of procreation or subsistence.
1 24
128
1 29
130
'
AB
2
CD
3
EF
4
GH
13 1
5
IJ
6
KL
TOTEM A N D CASTE
Human beings however soon got tired of this monotonous ' diet',
so the son of the couple AB took the female product of CD and
so on for EF and G H etc. :
CDB
ABD
GHF
EFH
KLJ
IJL
Even then they were not satisfied and so the fisherman made war
on the hunter, the hunter on the farmer and the farmer on the
fisherman, and each appropriated the other's product. The result
was that from then on the fisherman ate flesh, the hunter the
products of the soil and the farmer fish :
ABDF
CDBH
EFHJ
GHFL
IJLB
KLJ D
I
, ,
CDBHL
EFHJB
GHFLD
LJLBF
KLJDH
CBHL
EHJB
GFLD
ILBF
KJDH
BHLA
HJBG
FLDE
LBFK
FJCB
HLAD
JBGF
BFKJ
DHIL
LADF
BGFL
DEHJ
FKJD
HILB
ADFJ
GFLD
EHJB
KJDH
ILBF
JDHI
LDEH
6-TSM
I33
CHAP TER F I VE
1 37
apparently the right and left hands rather than feet, but we have
already noticed the particular attention which the Osage pays to
the lower extremities). A Kaguru man uses his left hand for making
love and a woman her right hand (that is, the hands which are
impure for each sex respectively). The first payment which has to
be made to a healer, before treatment can begin, is made with the
right hand, the last with the left, etc. The nomadic Fulani of the
Sahel zone of the Niger, the Bororo of Africa, seem, like the Kaguru,
to associate the right side with men and - in the temporal order with what comes first, the left side with women and what comes
after.* Symmetrically, the masculine hierarchy goes from south to
north and the feminine from north to south, so that, in the camp,
the woman places her calabashes in order of decreasing size, with
the largest to the south, while a man fastens his calves in the reverse
order (Dupire).
To return to the Osage : the number thirteen, as we have seen, is
first of all the sum of the two social groups, right and left, north and
south, winter and summer ; thereafter it is specified concretely and
developed logically. In the image of the rising sun, in which the
beholder venerates the source of all life (thus facing east, which
means that the south is on his right and the north on his left), t the
number thirteen can symbolize the union of two terms : six and
seven, sky and land, etc. But when it relates to a star the solar sym
bolism is particularly attached to the sky moiety. Hence there come
to be other concrete specifications of the number thirteen, in this
case reserved to sub-groups of the other moiety : thirteen foot
prints of the black bear to represent the notable actions of the land
clans and thirteen willow trees to represent those of the water clans
(La Flesche 3 , p. 147).
Thirteen is thus the expression of a double human totality : collec
tive, since the tribe is made up of two asymmetrical moieties (quanti
tatively : one is single, the other divided ; and qualitatively : one in
Thus the quality and the unity of the two great divisions of the tribe
might be symbolized as a man or an animal, but the Hon' -ga great
division must always represent the right side of the man or animal and the
Tsi' -zhu the great division of the left. This idea of the duality and unity
of nature was not only reflected in the tribal organization but, in former
times, instilled in the minds of the people by certain personal habits, as
for instance members of the Hon' -ga great division when putting on their
moccasins put the moccasin on the right foot first, while members of the
Tsi' -zhu great division put the moccasin on the left foot first (La Flesche
3 . p . n s).
I want here to digress for a moment to point out that this meticulous
rigour in the practical application of a logical system is not an
isolated phenomenon. At Hawaii the death of a chief was marked
by violent manifestations of mourning. The participants wore their
loin cloths around their neck instead of loins. This vestimentary
inversion of high and low was accompanied by (and no doubt also
signified) sexual licence. The importance of the opposition between
high and low was expressed in a large number of prohibitions. A
receptacle containing food must not be covered by any object which
may have been walked on or sat on ; it was forbidden to sit on a
pillow or to use it as a footrest, to lay your head on a seat cushion, to
sit above anything containing food, or, for menstruating women,
to use as pads anything but material from old skirts worn below the
waist :
The old time Hawaiians used to talk often, when I was a small child, of
the terrible custom the Whites had of using a sheet sometimes to lie upon
and sometimes to lie under - they (the Whites) did not seem to know that
what belonged above (ma luna) should remain above and what belonged
below (ma lalo) should stay below . . .
In a hula school conducted by my cousin Ilala-ole-o-Ka'ahumanu,
one of the pupils thoughtlessly draped her skirt over her shoulder. The
hula master spoke sharply to her, saying 'What belongs above should stay
above, and what belongs below should stay below' (Ko luna, no luna no
ia; Ko lalo no lalo no ia). (Handy and Pukui, Part VI, p. 165, and Part
VII, pp. 3 1 6, 3 17).
"" The responsibility for this analysis, which is not given in the texts, is my
own.
144
1 45
. LES
CHT$; H U A i-ns
Humanized
N ature.
Sketch by
Grandville
rJl
"0
..
'+<
0
..
(\)
.D
el
..c:
..&
-<
"'
I
I
1.'
Society of Animals
Australian Churinga
1 49
151
;i
i ,
II
I55
'I
Not because 'lexical' and 'arbitrary' on the one hand and 'granunar'
and 'relative motivation' on the other, are always synonymous, but
because they have a common principle. The two extremes are like poles
between which the whole system moves, two opposing currents which
share the movement of language : the tendency to use the lexicological
instrument (the unmotivated sign) and the preference given to the gram
matical instrument (structural rules) (Saussure, pp. 133-4).
, ' ',,,
1 57
they invariably reasoned along these lines : trees and' the birds which made
which grew alongside
their nests in them were in the same moiety ;
creeks or in water-holes and swamps were in
same moiety as water,
fishes, water-fowl, lily-roots. 'Eaglehawk, p)ain turkey, everything that
flies all work together. Carpet snake [Python variegatus] and ground
goanna [Varanus Gould?] all work together
, :._ they travel together in olden
time' (Kelly, p. 465).
1 58
1 59
CHAPTER S I X
U N IVE R S AL I ZAT I O N A N D
PART I C U LARI ZAT I O N
\.
.
I:
!
1 60
1.
1 61
oint with the set of local logics inserted in it. This general logi
an be of a different order. It is then definable by the umber n
nature of the axes employed, by the rules of rns rrat :k;
it ossible to pass from one to another, an na y y .
a
inrtia of the system, that is, its greater or less receptiveness to
unmotivated factors.
The so-called totemic classifications, the berlefs and pracflCes1
connected with them, are only one aspect .or mode of thls. genera
systematic activity. From this point of VleW I have so far n
little more than develop and deepen some comments of a
Gennep's :
Every ordered society necessa .1y c1asses not only its human members,
but also the objects d creaturn of a: =t'=s according to their
i psychic character
external form, sometunes accor mg . .
griculture or in
istic,
sometimes
according
to
their
utihty
as
oo
f
d
. dustry, or for the producer or consumer N:i
g entitles us to
regard any one system of 1ass\
'fi t'on say the zoological system of
totemism or the cosmographIC sys Ior he occupational system (castes)
as prior to the others (Van Gennep, PP 345-6).
A footnote makes it clear that Van Gennep was fully conscious of
the boldness and novelty of this passage :
It will be seen that I do not accept Durkheim's vew (F_ormes, p . 3
f li g creatures (meludmg man) l
that the cosmic. classi'ficatiOn
own view the
material objects is a conseqenc of totemi m. In
special f;7t o::c l
I?Y is not e;en a
o
nuance
0 :=I!v = s!I:mponents: F?r
peoples without totemism alo posess a system f classification which m
thi case too. is ?ne of the pno::l: 0 their eneral system of
! r lay anlmagico-religius
social organizatiOn and as sue
institutions. Examples ar the on.ental stems Chinese and Persian
dualism, Assyro-Babyloman cosmograp sm, he so -called magical
system of sympathetic correspondences, etc.I
. of
Van Gennep's demonstration is inadequat, hoever, 1. splte
these sound views, for he continued to beheve m oemlsm s a
institutional reality. He no longer tried to make lt lto a c assl
ficatory system from which all others derived, but he stlll attempt.ed
to preserve a distinctiven.es for it coparable to that of a specJes
objectively identifiable. w1thm a genus
. ?f t temic k' hip is thus composed of three elements :
The notion
o
and cosmic, classificatory
sm l . i
?Y: !:l::Ii he c}t:71 goup to ceatures or. objects
tretically belonging to the group. What characterizes totemism . .
(I.e.).
vm
1 62
I
I
;I
il
'I
i
I
I!
i. :
I
'
'
I
I .
I
I'
1.
and somnolence from owls, pain in the joints from rattle-snakes, etc.
(Swanton, z) .
Similar beliefs are found among the Pima of Arizona. They attri
bute throat diseases to the badger, swellings, headaches and fever to
the bear, diseases of the throat and lungs to the deer, children's
diseases to the dog and coyote, stomach trouble to the gopher or
prairie-rat, ulcers to the jack-rabbit, constipation to the mouse,
nose-bleed to the ground-squirrel, haemorrhages to the hawk and
eagle, syphilitic sores to the vulture, children's fevers to the Gila
monster, rheumatism to the horned toad,* 'white fever to the lizard,
kidney and stomach troubles to the rattle-snake, ulcers and paralysis
to the turtle, internal pains to the butterfly, etc. (Russell).t Among
the Hopi, who are a day's march from the Pima, an analogous classi
fication is based on the organization into religious orders, each of
which can inflict a punishment in the form of a particular disease :
abdominal swelling, sore ears, horn-like swelling on the top of the
head, deafness, eczema on the upper part of the body, twisting and
twitching of the face and neck, soreness in the bronchial tubes, bad
knee (Voth 2, p. 1 09 n.). The problem of classifications could un
doubtedly be tackled from this angle and some curious resem
blances, symptomatic of logical connections which could be of
considerable importance, might be found between distant groups
(the association of the squirrel and nose-bleeding, for instance,
seems to recur in a large number of North American peoples).
The specific categories and the myths connected with them can
also serve to organize space, and the classificatory system is then
extended on a territorial and geographical basis. A classic example
is the totemic geography of the Aranda, but there are other people
equally exacting and subtle in this respect. In Aluridja territory a
rocky site measuring five miles round the base was recently dis
covered and described in which every accident of relief corresponds
to a phase of ritual in such a way that this natural rock illustrates the
structure of their myths and the order of the ceremonies for the
natives. Its north side is the side of the moiety of the sun and of the
* It may be noted, in support of the considerations adduced earlier (pp. 64-5)
that it is probably the same behaviour on the part of this animal which suggests
entirely different associations to the American Indians and the Chinese. The
Chinese ascribe aphrodisiac virtues to the flesh of the phrynosoma or to the wine
in which it has been macerated because the male holds on to the female so hard
during copulation that he does not let go even when caught.
t For closely related ideas among the Papago, cf. Densmore.
7-TSM
I,
II
ritual cycle Kerungera, its south side that of the moiety of the shade
and the ritual Arangulta. Thirty-eight points on the base of the
plateau are named and annotated (Harney).
North America also furnishes examples of mythical geography
and totemic topography, from Alaska to California as well as in the
south-west and north-east of the continent. In this respect the
Penobscot of Maine exemplify a general tendency on the part of the
northern Algonkin to interpret all the physiographic aspects of the
tribal territory in terms of the peregrinations of the civilizing hero
Gluskabe and other mythical personage or incidents. An elongated
rock is the hero's canoe, a streak of white rock represents the entrails
of the moose he killed, Kineo mountain is the overturned cooking
pot in which he cooked the meat, etc. (Speck 2, p. 7).
Again, in the Sudan, a mytho-geographical system has been dis
covered which covers the entire Niger valley, and thus extends over
more than the territory of any single group, and in which is trans
lated down to the minutest detail a conception of the relations
between different cultural and linguistic groups which is at once
diachronic and synchronic.
This last example shows that the systems of classification not
only permit the 'furnishing', as it were, of social time (by means of
myths) and of tribal space (with the help of a conceptualized topo
graphy). The filling in of the territorial framework is accompanied
by enlargement. In the same way that, on the logical plane, the
specific operator effects the transition to the concrete and individual
on the one hand and the abstract and systems of categories on the
other, so, on the sociological plane, totemic classifications make it
possible both to define the status of persons within a group and to
expand the group beyond its traditional confines.
Primitive societies have, and not without justification, been said
to treat the limits of their tribal group as the frontiers of humanity
and to regard everyone outside them as foreigners, that is, as dirty,
coarse sub-men or even non-men : dangerous beasts or ghosts. This
is often true, but what is overlooked when this is said is that one of
the essential functions of totemic classifications is to break down
this closing in of the group into itself and to promote an idea some
thing like that of a humanity without frontiers. There s evidence of
this phenomenon in all the classical areas of so-called totemic organ
ization. In a region in West Australia the clans and their totems 'are
grouped together into a number of what may be called inter-tribal
166
I have ascertained that in 167 cases (s6%) out of 300 names of common
totemic animals, the Western Aranda and the Loritja use the same or
similar terms ; and comparison of totemic plant names used by the
Western Aranda and Loritja shows that the same terms are found in both
languages to refer to 147 of the 220 species of plants which I recorded
(6iJ'o) (C. Strehlow, pp. 66--7).
All members with the same totem regarded themselves as related even
though of different villages or different tribes . . . When two strangers met
and found themselves to be of the same totem they immediately began to
trace their genealogy, . . . and the one became the cousin, the uncle, or
the grandfather of the other, although the grandfather might often be
the younger of the two. The ties of the totem were considered so strong
that if a quarrel should happen between a person with the same totem as a
bystander and a cousin or other near relative of the latter but with a
different mark, the bystander would side with the person with the same
totem whom perhaps he had never seen before (Kinietz, pp. 69-70).
This totemic universalization not only breaks down tribal frontiers
and creates the rudiments of an international society. It also some
times goes beyond the limits of humanity in a biological, and no
longer merely sociological, sense, when totemic names are applic
able to totemic animals. This occurs among the Australian tribes of
the Cape York Peninsula in the case of dogs* - also referred to as
'brothers' or 'sons' according to the group (Sharp, p. 70 ; Thomson)
- and among the Ioway and Winnebago Indians in the case of dogs
and horses (Skinner 3, p. 1 98).
* Among the Wik Munkan a dog is called Yatut 'extracting bones of . . . the
totem fish' if his master is of the Bone-fish clan, Owun 'illicit or stolen meeting'
if his master is of the Ghost clan (Thomson, pp. 161-2).
I have given a brief indication of how the meshes of the net can
stretch indefinitely in accordance with the dimensions and gener
ality of the field. It remains to be shown how they can also shrink
to filter and imprison reality but this time at the lower limit of the
system by extending its action beyond the threshold which one
would be inclined to assign to all classification, that beyond which
it is no longer possible to class, but only to name. These extreme
operations are in fact less widely separated than they might appear
and, when seen in the perspective of the systems we are studying,
they may even be superposed. Space is a society of particular places
as people are landmarks within the group. Places and individuals
alike are designated by proper names, which can be substituted for
each other in many circumstances common to many societies. The
Yurok of California provide one example among others of this
personified geography, where trails are conceived of as animated
beings, each house is named, and the names of places replace
personal names in current usage (Waterman).
An Aranda myth well expresses this feeling of correspondence
between geographical and biological individuation : the earliest
divine beings are shapeless, without limbs, and welded together
until the coming of the god Mangarkunjerkunja (the fly-catcher .
lizard), who proceeded to separate them and fashion them indivi- \
dually. At the same time (and is this not indeed the same thing ?) he
taught them the arts of civilization and the system of sections anJ
sub-sections. The eight sub-sections were originally divided into
two main groups : four land ones and four water ones. It was the god
who 'territorialized' them by allotting each site to a pair of sub
sections. Now, this individuation of territory corresponded to bio
logical individuation in another way as well, in that the totemic
mode of fertilizing the mother explains the anatomic differences
observable among children. Those with fine features were con
ceived by the operation of a ratapa, embryo-spirit ; those with large
features by magical projection of a rhomb into a woman's body ;
children with fair hair were direct reincarnations of totemic
ancestors (C. Strehlow). The Australian tribes of the Drysdale
River, in Northern Kimberley, divide all kinship relations, which
together compose the social 'body', into five categories named after
a part of the body or a muscle. Since a stranger must not be ques
tioned, he announces his kinship by moving the relevant muscle
(Hernandez, pp. 228-9). In this case, too, therefore, the total system
x68
If
(group a) . ; (grqup b) : : (bear species) : (eagle species)
then
(member of a) : (member y of b) : : (member l of bear) :
(member of eagle)
r
* Evrything, except the existence of what exists, which is not one of its
properties (cf. below, p. 255).
1 72
1 73
are most often found juxtaposed) the proper name refers to a partial
aspect of the animal or plant entity just as it corresponds to a partial
aspect of the individual being - in general, and in particular, in those
societies in which an individual receives a new name at every impor
tant point of his life. Neighbouring societies, moreover, employ the
same constructions for forming in some cases personal names
(borne by individual members of a clan group) and in others collec
tive names (borne by bands, lineages, or groups of lineages, that is,
sub-groups of a single clan).
Two parallel detotalizations are thus involved : of species into
parts of the body and attitudes, and of social segments into indivi
duals and roles. But just as the detotalization of the concept of a
species into particular species, of each species into its individual
members, and of each of these individuals into organs and parts of
the body could, as I tried to show with the help of a figurative model,
issue into a retotalization of the concrete parts into abstract parts
and of the abstract parts into a conceptualized individual, so here
the detotalization takes place in the form of retotalization. Kroeber's
observations about proper names among the Miwok of California
serve to provide a final example and at the same time open up a new
perspective :
The position seems to have been the same throughout Australia. 'By
knowing a native's name, if one knew the Aranda language well
enough, it would seem one would also know his or her totem by,
deduction' (Pink, p. 1 76). Another observation, relating to the
Murngin of Arnhem Land, echoes this one : 'The names of the
living are all taken from some part of the totemic complex and refer
directly or indirectly to the totem' (Warner, p. 390). The proper
names of the Wik Munkan also derive from their respective totems.
For instance, for men whose totem is the fish barramundi (Osteo
glossum), which they spear : the-barramundi-swims-in-water-and
sees-a-man, the barramundi-moves-its-tail-as-it-swims-around-its
eggs, the-b.-breathes, the-b.-has-its-eyes-open, the-b.-breaks-a
spear, the-b.-eats-mullet, etc. And for women whose totem is the
crab : the-crab-has-eggs, tide-takes-crabs-out-to-sea, the-crab
stops-down-hole-and-is-dug-out, etc. (McConnel, p. 1 84). The
tribes of the Drysdale River region have proper names derived from
clan appellations, as the author quoted above underlines : 'Proper
names . . . always bear relation to one's totem' (Hernandez).
It is clear that these individual appellations belong to the same
system as the collective appellations discussed above and that,
through the intermediary of the latter, one can, with the help of
transformations, pass from the horizon of individuation to that of
more general categories. Every clan or sub-clan possesses a quota of
names which only its own members can bear and, just as an indivi
dual is part of the group, so an individual name is 'part' of the
collective appellation, either in the sense that it may cover the whole
animal, and the individual names correspond to its parts or limbs,
or that the collective appellation may depend on an idea of the
animal conceived at the highest level of generality and the individual
appellations correspond to one of its predications in time or space :
Barking-dog, Angry-bison, or there may be a combination of both
procedures : Flashing-eyes-of-the-bear. The animal may be subject
or predicate in the relation so expressed : The-fish-moves-its-tail,
Tide-takes-crabs, etc. Whichever procedure is employed (and they
1 74
175
I'
use of the names of the dead which 'contaminate' any words with a
phonetic resemblance to these names. The Tiwi of the Melville and
Bathurst islands taboo not only the proper name 'Mulankina' but
also the word 'mulikina' which means : full, filled, enough (Hart).
This usage finds a parallel in that of the Yurok of California : 'When
Tegis died, the common word tsis, "woodpecker scalps", was not
uttered in the hearing of his relatives or by them' (Kroeber 2, p. 48). *
The Dobu islanders forbid the use of proper names between
individuals temporarily or permanently connected by a 'species' tie
through being companions on a voyage, eating together, or sharing
the favours of the same woman, as the case may be (Bateson).
Such facts have a double claim on our interest. In the first place,
they afford an indisputable analogy with food prohibitions, which
have been wrongly associated with totemism alone. In the same
way that at Mota a woman is 'contaminated' by a plant or animal, as
a result of which she gives birth to a child subject to the correspond
ing eating prohibition, and at Ulawa it is the dying man who 'con
taminates' by his incarnation in an animal or plant species which his
descendants are then forbidden to consume, so, by homophony, a
name 'contaminates' other words, the use of which then comes to be
forbidden. Secondly, this homophony defines a class of words, to
which the prohibition applies because they belong to the same
'species', and which thus acquires an ad hoc reality comparable to
that of animal or plant species. These 'species' of words 'stressed' by
the same prohibition bring together both proper names and common
names. And this is a further reason for suspecting that the difference
between the two types of words is not as great as we were near to
admitting at first.
1 76
1 77
The customs and procedures which I have just mentioned are not
found in all exotic societies nor even in all those which designate
their segments by animal and plant names. The Iroquois, who are
an instance of the latter, seem to have a system of proper names
entirely distinct from the system of clan appellations. Their names
most commonly consist of a verb with an incorporated noun or a
noun followed by an adjective : In-the-Centre-of-the-Sky, He
raises-the-Sky, Beyond-the-Sky, etc. ; Hanging-Flower, BeautifulFlower, Beyond-the-Flowers ; He-announces-Defeat (or Victory),
,
* There are other examples in Elmendorf and Kroeber 1 960, which was not
available to me at the time of writing this section.
I 8o
p and d?wn'. The s?n. of an opossum father is called 'Karingo' (the name of a
little sprmg), Myndtbambu : 'the opossum when his chest is slit up' and
Mynwhagala : 'opossum up the tree, now down', etc. (Kelly, p. 468).
181
'
der of
askmg them lS supphed wtth a substitute name whi
ch
mea
ns
liter
ally
'no name', 'without name' or 'the second born'.
There is a final difficu!ty, due to the large num
of categories of
arne. Amog te Wtk Munkan, the followiber
ng
tmgmsd : kish1p terms, niimp kimpan ; names must be dis
or ondit10 ; mcknames, niimpyann, literally ; 'namindicating status
as crawler (for someone partly paralysed) or 'the e nothing' . such
finally true proper names, niimJ: . Ony kinship left-handed' ; and
used as terms of address except m penods of mouterms are normally
rning when names
183
! 86
* Two terms among the Lacandons of Mexico, who speak the Mayan language.
They form names by the employment of a binome composed of an animal name
and an ordinal name (Tozzer, pp. 42-3 and 46-7).
,, .
Although I have called them 'personal names' they are really group
names and signify membership of, and solidarity with, a totemic group
(Thomson, p. 1 59).
These reservations are due to the fact that the list of names which
are the property and prerogative of each clan is often restricted and
that two people cannot bear the same name simultaneously. The
Iroquois have 'guardians' to whom they entrust the task of remem
bering the repertoire of clan names and who always know which
J88
names are available. When a child is born the ' guardian' is sum
moned to say which names are 'free'. Among the Yurok of Cali
fornia, a child can remain without a name for six or seven years,
until a relative's name becomes vacant through the death of its
bearer. On the other hand, the taboo on the dead man's name comes
to an end after a year if a young member of the lineage puts it back
into circulation.
Some names seem still more perplexing : these, like the ones given
in Africa to twins or to the first child to survive after a series of still
births, assign some individuals a place in a rigid and restricted taxo
nomic system. The Nuer reserve the names of birds which fly low,
such as guinea fowl, francolin, etc., for twins. In effect, they regard
twins as creatures of supernatural origin like birds (Evans-Pritchard
2, discussion in Levi-Strauss 6). The Kwakiutl of British Columbia
express an analogous belief in their association of twins with fish.
Thus the names Salmon-Head and Salmon-Tail are reserved for
children whose birth immediately precedes or succeeds that of
twins. Twins themselves are believed to be descended either from
olachan (if they have small hands) or from Oncorhynchus kisutch
(Silver-Salmon) or from Oncorhynchus nerka (Sockeye-Salmon).
The diagnosis is made by an old man who is himself a twin. In the
first case he names the male twin Making-Satiated and the female
twin Making-Satiated-Woman ; in the second case the names are
Only-One and Abalone-Woman respectively ; and in the third
Head-Worker and Head-Dancer (Boas 4, part I, pp. 684-93).
Among the Dogon of the Sudan there is a very strict method of
allotting proper names : each individual's position is plotted on the
basis of a genealogical and mythical model where each name is
linked with a sex, a lineage, and an order of birth and with the
qualitative structure of the group of siblings to which the individual
belongs : himself a twin, first- or second-born before or after twins,
boy born after one or two girls, or vice versa, boy born between two
girls or vice versa, etc. (Dieterlen 3).
Finally, one is often hesitant to regard as proper names the ordinal
names found among most of the Algonkin and Sioux, among the
Mixe (Radin 2), the Maya (Tozzer) and in the south of Asia (Bene
dict), etc. Let us confine ourselves to one example, that of the
Dakota, among whom the system is particularly developed, with the
following names corresponding to the order of birth of the first
seven girls and the first six boys :
1 89
Wino'ne
2. Ha'pe
3 Ha'psti
4 Wiha'ki
5 Hapo'nA
6. HapstinA
7 Wihake'da
1.
BOYS
Tcaske'
Hepo'
Hepi'
Watca'to
Hake'
Tatco'
CHAPTER SEVEN
(Wallis, p. 39).
The naming system of the Penan, who are nomads of the interior of
Borneo, enables us to give a more precise account of the relation
between the terms to which we should be inclined to reserve the
title of proper name and others which seem at first sight to be of a
different kind. Depending on his age and family situation, a Penan
may be designated by three sorts of terms : a personal name, a
teknonym ('father of so-and-so', 'mother of so..rand-so') and, finally,
what one feels like calling a necronym, which expresses the kinship
relation of a deceased relative to the subject : 'father dead', 'niece
dead', etc. The western Penan have no less than twenty-six distinct
necronyms, corresponding to the degree of kinship, relative age
of the deceased, sex and the order of birth of children up to the ninth.
The rules governing the use of these names are of surprising com
plexity. Simplifying a great deal, we can say that a child is known by
its proper name until one of his ascendants dies. If it is a grandfather
who dies, the child is then called Tupou. If his father's brother dies
he becomes Ilun and remains so until another relative dies. He then
receives a new name. A Penan may thus pass through a series of six
or seven or more necronyms before he marries and has children.
At the birth of their first child a father and mother adopt a
Teknonym expressing their relation to the child whose name forms
part of it. Thus : Tama Awing, Tinen Awing, 'father (or mother) of
Awing'. Shoitld the child die, the telmonym is replaced by a nec
ronym : 'Eldest child dead.' When the next child is born a new
teknonym takes the place of the necronym, and so on.
The position is further complicated by the special rules relating
to siblings. A child is called by his own name if all his brothers and
191
relation
present ( + ) or
absent (- ) :
opposition
between self
( + ) and other
( ):
-
NECRONYM
+
+
1 92
193
J '
is that they are 'dead' and that procreation is conceived not as the
addition of a new being to those who exist already but as the substi
tution of the one for the others.
cusom ?f fobidding the use of proper names during
. -h: Tiwi
mttiatwn
and chdd-btrth 1s also to be understood in this way :
1 94
The birth of a child is, to a native, a most mysterious affair and the
woman is regarded as being intimately in touch with the spirit world.
H ne her name as part of herself is invested with a ghostly character and
thts IS expressed by the tribe in treating her husband as if she did not
exist, as if she were dead in fact and for the time being no longer his wife.
.
_ m
She IS
touch with the spirits and the result will be a child for her
husband (Hart, pp. 288-9).
have, for the time being, been suspended in favour of their parents.
Proper names thus undergo a truly loical devaluation. They re
the mark of being 'unclassed' as candidates for a class, of bemg
temporarily obliged to define themselves either as unclassed (as in
the case of siblings resuming the use of their autonyms) or alter
natively by their relation to an unclassed person (like parents when
they assume a teknonym). When, however, death caues a breach in
the social fabric, the individual is, as it were drawn m. Thanks to
the necronym, which has an absolute logical priority over other
forms, his proper name, a mere place in the queue, is replaced ?Y a
position in the system, which from the mst general p mt of view,
can therefore be considered as formed of discrete quantified classes.
The proper name is the reverse of the necronym, of which the
teknonym in turn presents an inverted image. The case f the Pena
is to all appearances the opposite of that of the Algokm, Iro quos
and Yurok. Among the former a person must await a relative s
death to be rid of the name he bears, while often among the latter
he must await it to succeed to his name. But in fact there is as great a
logical devaluation of names in the latter case as there is in the
former :
The individual name is never used in either direct address or indirect
reference to relatives the relationship term doing service in all such cases.
Even when addressi g a non -relative, the individual name is very seldom
used the form of address consisting in a relationship term, according to
the r lative age of the speaker and the person addressed. Only when o
relatives are referred to in conversation is it customary to use the mdt
vidual name' which even then will not be used if the context plainly
indicates the person referred to (Goldenweiser, p. 367).
--
--
--
All sorts of beliefs have been invoked to explain the very common
prohibition on pronouncing the names of the dead. These beliefs
are real and well authenticated but the question is whether they
should be regarded as the origin of the custom, as one of the factors
which have contributed to reinforce it or perhaps even as one of its
consequences. If the explanations I have given are correct, the pro
hibition on the names of the dead is a structural property of certain
systems of naming. Proper names are either already class operators
of alternatively they provide a temporary solution for those awaiting
classification. They always represent classes at their most modest.
In the limiting case, as among the Penan, they are no more than the
means, temporarily unclassed, of forming classes or again, as it were,
bills drawn on the logical solvency of the system, that is on its
discounted capacity to supply the creditor with a class in due course.
Only newcomers, that is, the children who are born, raise a problem :
there they are. Any system which treats individuation as classifica
tion (and I have tried to show that this is always so) risks having its
structure called in question every time a new member is admitted.
There are two types of solution to this problem, and intermediate
forms between them. If the system in question consists of classes of
positions, it has only to command a reserve of unoccupied positions
sufficient to accommodate all the children born. The available
positions being always more numerous than the population, syn
chrony is protected against the vagaries of diachrony, at least in
theory. This is the Iroquois solution. The Yurok are less farsighted.
Among them, children have to wait their turn ; but as they are
nevertheless assured of being classified after a few years, they can
remain temporarily undifferentiated while awaiting a position in a
class, which the structure of the system guarantees them.
Everything is different when the system consists of classes of
relations. It is then no longer the case that one individual ceases to
exist and another replaces him in a position labelled by means of a
proper name which outlasts any particular person. For the relation
itself to become a class term, proper names, which present the terms
related as o many distinct entitles, have to be eliminated. The ulti
mate units of the system are no longer single member classes with a
train of successive living occupants, but classed relations between
who allows a man to live with her, has a lover or illegitimate children ; His father
was of -- ; Their late mother was -- ; Unmarried person of -- ; etc.
(Waterman, pp. 214-rS ; Kroeber in : Elmendorf and Kroeber, pp. 372-4, n. r ) .
8-TSM
1 97
the dead or even those who are so in effect (parents are described as
dead by contrast with the life they have created) and the living,
whether really living or in effect so (new born children who have a
proper name so that their parents may be defined in relation to them
until the real death of an ascendant allows them in turn to be
defined in relation to him). In these systems, the classes are thus
composed of different types of dynamic relations associating entries
and departures, while among the Iroquois and other societies of the
same sort, they are founded on a collection of static positions which
may be vacant or occupied.*
The prohibition on the names of the dead does not therefore raise
a separate problem for anthropology. A dead person loses his name
for the same reason that - among the Penan - a living person loses
his ; when the living Penan enters the system he assumes a nec
ronym, that is tc say, he becomes one of the terms in a relationship,
of which the other - since he is dead - no longer exists save in that
relation which defines a living person with reference to him. Finally,
for the same reason as the dead lose their names a mother and father
lose theirs also when they assume a teknonym, resolving in this way
(until the death of one of their children) the difficulty created for the
system by the procreation of a supernumerary member. The latter
must wait 'outside the door' as a named person until someone's
departure allows him to make his entrance. Then two beings of
whom one did not previously belong within the system and the
* Consequently, systems of relations, unlike systems of positions whose dis
continuous nature is evident, tend rather to be continuous. Another Penan usage
shows this clearly, although Needham (2), who also records it, rejects an explan
ation which in fact seems very plausible. The reciprocal terms 'grandparent'
and 'grandchild' replace the usual, closer terms for members of the same nuclear
family when one of the two persons involved is in mourning. Is not the point
that the person in mourning is looked upon as having moved over somewhat
towards death and so further away than he was from his closest relatives? Death
loosens the ties of kinship network. Needham is unwilling to allow this because
he regards what is in fact one problem as several : the mourner does not call a
son, daughter, nephew or niece or their spouse 'grandchild' because the same
mourning directly or indirectly affects them but quite simply by way of recipro
city. All the examples Needham, mentions confirm this except that of a young
child who suffers a slight mishap (has fallen down, received a blow or whose food
has been stolen by a dog) and is called on that occasion by the necronym
normally reserved for those who have lost a grandparent. But my account covers
this case also since the child is placed metaphorically in mourning by the damage
done to him and, due to his tender years, a slight injury to his well-being (actual
in the case of a fall or potential in that of a loss of food) is enough to drive him
back towards death.
199
The name Brassica rapa easily evokes the thought of a botanist classi
fying a number of specimens which to the lay mind are much alike, and
to one of which he gives the name Brassica rapa, just as a parent names
his baby. We have no such thought about the word turnip, and Brassica
rapa is simply the scientific name for the ordinary turnip. We may find
confirmatory support for regarding Brassica rapa as a proper name, or
at least as much more of a proper name than turnip, in the fact that we
do not say This is a Brassica rapa, or These are fine specimens of Brassica
rapa. In so saying we appeal to the name of any single example of the
type, whereas in speaking of a certain vegetable as a turnip, we appeal to
the similarity of that vegetable to others of its kind. The difference of
linguistic attitude is a mere nuance, but it is a real one. In the one instance
the sound of the name, what we usually describe as 'the name itself' , is
more in the foreground than in the other instance (Gardiner, p. 5 2).
200
: '
* It is very significant that even so limited and simple a series includes terms
from different logical sphere. 'Pierrot' can be a class indicator since one can say
'There are lhree pierrots on the balcony'. But 'Godard' is a term of address. As
the author of the article on this word in the Dictionary de Trevoux ( 1 732 ed.) so
excellently puts it : 'Godard is the name given to swans. When one calls them,
when one wants them to come, one says to them : " Godard, Godard, come
Godard, come. Here Godard". Jacquot and perhaps Margot seem to have an
intermediate role.' (Cf. Rolland, Faune, Vol. II on the human proper names
given to birds.)
t From the point of view of eternity, particular species of plants and animals
and simple substances are unique things of the same king as, for example, Sirius
or Napoleon (Brondal, p. 230).
201
206
207
* The opposition here comes out more clearly in the French where nickname
'sumom' is apposed to sub-name 'sous-nom' [trans. note].
T H E INDIVIDUAL A S A S P ECIES
210
That this is so seems even more certain when one notices that the
Tiwi system has striking analogies, on the human plane, with the
system _ in our own society, to which I drew attention in analysing
the vanous
ways of naming animals, where, it is hardly necessary to
say, fear of the dead plays no part. Among the Tiwi also, the system
rests on a sort of arbitrage, exercised by means of proper names,
b twee a syntagmatic chain (that of ordinary language) and a para
Igmatic set (the sacred language, which is essentially of this nature
smce te wor?s there become prgressively unfitted to form a syn
tagmatlc cham as they lose their meaning). In addition, proper
name_s _are metaporically connected with common nouns through
a positlve phonetic resemblance, while sacred words are metonym
ically _connected with proper names (as means or ends) through a
negative resemblance, based on the absence or poverty of semantic
content.
Even if one defines it, on the most general level, as consisting in
an exchange of wrds between the profane and the sacred language,
through the medmm of proper names, the Tiwi system clarifies
phenomena which minor aspects of our culture allowed us only to
do so much as broach. We are better able to understand how terms
like Brassica rapa which belong to a language 'sacred' in two respects
(being Latin a?d scientific) can have the character of proper names,
not, as Gardmer suggests and Hart seems prepared to admit,
because they are devoid of meaning but because, in spite of appear
ances, they are part of a whole system in which meaning is never
entirely lost. Were this not so, the sacred language of the Tiwi
would not be a language but a conglomeration of oral gestures.
Therecn, howevr beno _doubtthat even an obscure sacred langu
age retams potentlal meamng. I shall come back to this aspect of the
question later.
For the moment we must distinguish another type of 'sacred'
language which we employ, in the manner of the Tiwi, to introduce
proper names into ordinary language, even transforming the
common nouns from the domain in question into proper names.
Thu, as we have already seen, we use flower names as proper names
for gtrls, but we do not stop at this, since the inventiveness of horti
culturalists provides newly introduced flowers with proper names
taken over from human beings. This chasse-croise has some notable
peculiarities. The names we take from flowers and give (mainly to
persons of the female sex) are common nouns belonging to ordinary
2II
language (a girl may perhaps be called Rosa but definitely not Rosa
centifolia) ; those we give them in return, however, come from a
'sacred' language : a title is added to the patronym or christian name
and lends it a mysterious dignity. A new flower is not usually called
'Elizabeth', 'Doumer', or 'Brigitte' but ' Queen-Elizabeth', 'Presi
dent-Paul-Doumer', 'Madame-Brigitte-Bardot'.* Moreover, no
account is taken of the bearer's sex (in this case the grammatical
gender of the name of the flower) in naming it : a rose or a gladiolus
(feri:J.inine and masculine respectively in French) can be given either
a man's or a woman's name indifferently. This recalls one of the
rules for the attribution of 'umbilical' names among the Wik
Munkan.t
Now, these usages, whether also taken from our own culture or
from that of Australian islanders, clearly derive from the same group
as all those we have been considering ; we observe the same equiva
lence between metonymical and metaphorical relations which has
seemed to play the part of common denominator between them
from the start. The names we take over from flowers to make into
proper names have the force of metaphors : fair as a rose, modest
as a violet, etc. But the names drawn from 'sacred' language which
flowers receive in exchange have the force of metonymy, in two
ways : Brassica rapa removes the self-sufficiency of cabbage-turnip
to make it a species of a genus, part of a whole. The name 'Impera
trice-Eugenie', given to a new variety of flower, performs a converse
transformation, since it takes place at the level of the signifying
instead of at that of the signified : this time the flower is designated
by means of part of a whole ; not any Eugenie but a particular
Eugenie ; Eugenie de Montijo not before her marriage but after it ;
not a biological individual but a person in a determined social role,
etc.:j: One type of'sacred' name is thus 'metonymizing' and the other
* This tendency is already apparent in popular tradition which, when it
attributes human christian names to certain flowers, generally inserts them in a
phrase: 'Beau Nicolas' for the rose campion, 'Marie Cancale' for the comflower,
'Joseph Foireux' for the cowslip, etc. (Rolland, Flore, vol. II). Similarly in
English, the flower names : 'Jack in the Pulpit', 'Jack behind the Garden Gate',
etc.
t Cf. above, p. r 84.
t Note the inversion of the cycle as compared to the Tiwi system. Among
ourselves, the cycle goes from ordinary language to proper name, from proper
name to the 'sacred' language, to return finally to ordinary language. Ordinary
212
21 3
CHAPTER E I GH T
II
T IME RE GAINED
21 6
20
TIME REGAINED
TIME REGAINED
222
223
IS
TIME REGAINED
226
227
fulfilment of human
..........N
a
b
d
.........
then the Intichiuma recalls the affinity between A and B and b,
C and N and n, attesting that when, in the norm
e of events,
group b incorporates, by eating, species A, C, D,alEcours
.
.
.
N,
group
species B, C, D, E . . . N, and so on, what is in question
is an
exchange between social groups and an arbitrage between resem
lance and contiguity, not the replacement of one resemblance b
another resemblance nor one contiguity by another contiguityby
Sacrifice turns to comparison as a means of effacing differences.*
and in order to establish contiguity; the so-called
ic meals
institute contiguity, but only with a view to makitotem
ng
possi
ble a
comparison, the anticipated result of which is to confi
rm
differences.
The two systems are therefore opposed by
orientation,
metonymical in one case and metaphorical in thetheir
other
. But this
anti-symmetry leaves them still on the same plane, when
fact
they are on different levels from the epistemological point ofinview.
Totemic classifications have a doubly objective bash. There
really are natural species, and they do indeed form a disco
ntinuous
series ; and social segments for their part also exist. Totem
ism, or
so-called totemism, confines itself to conceiving a homology
structure between the two series, a perfectly legitimate hypothesisof
for social segments are instituted, and it is in the power of each,
society to render the hypothesis plausible by shapi its rules and
representations accordingly. The system of sacrificng
e, on the other
A
a,
c,
TIME REGAINED
228
9-TSM
mustard leaves and a branch of oak, gathered and cut on the way.
After this, they met the cock and then the warrior. The badger and
butterfly clan is so-called because its ancestors took with them a
man-badger whose acquaintance they had made a shrt time ?efore
they caught a butterfly to amuse a child ; but the child was ill and
it was Badger who cured him with simples. The ancestors of the
rabbit and tobacco clan found the plant and met the animal. Those
of the Patki clan took the names of lake, cloud, rain, snow, and fog
as a result of various incidents on their journey. Somewhere
between the actual site of Phoenix (Arizona) and the Little Colora
do the ancestors of the bear clan came upon a dead bear, whence
thir name but another band found the skin, from which small
rodents had taken the hair to line their holes. They made hide
straps out of the skin, and since then the hide strap and bear clans
have been associated. A third band took the name of the rodents
and was allied to the former clans (Voth 4, Parsons, pp. 26-30).
Let us now turn to South America. The Bororo say that the sun
and moon belong to the Badedgeba clan of the Cera moiety on
account of a dispute between a father and son, who both wanted to
appropriate the names of these heavenly bodies. A compromse
gave the father the names of Sun and Bah-of-the- un. T?bacco
belongs to the Paiwe clan because an Indian belongmg to It hap
pened by chance to discover its leaves in the innards of a fish he was
gutting in order to cook. The chief of the 'black' B_adedgeb clan
at one time possessed some black and some red birds
(Phzmosus
infuscatus and Ibis rubra respectively), but his colleagu : rd'
Babedgeba stole them from him and he had to agree to a divisiOn
according to colour (Colbacchini).
All these myths of origin of clan appellations are so similar that
it is unnecessary to cite examples from other parts of the world,
such as Africa where they also abound. What, then, are their com
mon characteristics ? In the first place, they all have in common a
brevity leaving room for none of those apparent digressions whih
often have a wealth of concealed meaning. A story reduced to Its
essential outlines has no surprises in store for the analyst. Secondly,
these myths are falsely aetiological (supposing that myth cold e
genuinely so) in as much as the kind of explanator;t _they gv_e IS
reducible to a scarcely modified statement of the Imtlal positwn;
from this point of view they appear redundant. Their role seems
to be demarcative, rather than aetiological; they do not really
230
TIME REGAINED
23 1
TIME REGAINED
The two series exist in time but under an atemporal regime, since,
being both real, they sail through time together, remaining such as
they were at the moment of separation. The original series is
always there, ready to serve as a system of reference for the inter
pretation and rectification of the changes taking place in the
derivative series. In theory, if not in practice, history is subordi
nated to system.
When, however, a society sides with history, classification into
finite groups becomes impossible because the derivative series,
instead of reproducing the original series, merges with it to form
a single series in which each term is derivative in relation to the
one preceding it and original in relation to the one coming after it.
Instead of a once-for-all homology between two series each finite
and discontinuous in its own right, a continuous evolution is postu
lated within a single series that accepts an unlimited number of
terms.
Some Polynesian mythologies are at the critical point where
diachrony irrevocably prevails over synchrony, making it impos
sible to interpret the human order as a fixed projection of the
natural order by which it is engendered ; it is prolongation, rather
than a reflection, of the natural order :
Fire and water married, and from them sprung the earth, rocks, trees,
and everything. The cuttle-fish fought with the fire and was beaten. The
fire fought with the rocks, and the rocks conquered. The large stones
fought with the small ones ; the small ones conquered. The small stones
fought with the grass, and the grass conquered. The trees fought with the
creepers, the trees were beaten and the creepers conquered. The creepers
rotted, swarmed with maggots, and from maggots they grew to be men
(G. Turner, pp. 6-7).
TIME REGAINED
The gurra ancestor hunts, kills, and eats bandicoots ; and his sons are
always engaged upon the same quest. The witchetty grub men of Lukara
spend every day of their lives in digging up grubs from the roots of
acacia trees . . . . The ragia (wild plum tree) ancestor lives on the ragia
berries which he is continually collecting into a large wooden vessel. The
crayfish ancestor is always building fresh weirs across the course of the
moving flood of water which he is pursuing ; and he is for'ever engaged in
spearing fish . . . if the myths gathered in the Northern Aranda area are
treated collectively, a full and very detailed account will be found of all
the occupations which are still practised in Central Australia. In his
myths we see the native at his daily task of hunting, fishing, gathering
vegetable food, cooking, and fashioning his implements. All occupations
originated with the totemic ancestors ; and here, too, the native follows
tradition blindly : he clings to the primitive weapons used by his fore
fathers, and no thought of improving them ever enter his mind (T. G. H.
Strehlow, pp. 34-5).
I select this in preference to all the other evidence to the same pur
pose available from other parts of the world because it emanates
from an ethnologist born and brought up among the natives,
speaking their language fluently and remaining deeply attached to
life and development'. After which he describes, in very pertinent fashion more
over, institutions whose object is, to use his own terms, to 'regroup' lineages
threatened with dispersion ; to 'allay' their crumbling ; to 'recall' their solidarity,
'establish' communication with the ancestors, 'prevent separated members of the
clan from becoming strangers to each other', furnish 'an instrument of protection
against conflicts', 'control' and 'master' antagonisms and subversions by means
of a 'minutely regulated' ritual which is 'a factor reinforcing social and political
structures'. One is easily in agreement with him (while, however, questioning
whether he is so with his own premises), that the institutions he began by deny
ing to have been founded on 'logical relations' and 'fixed structures' (p. 23)
demonstrate in fact the 'prevalence of traditional social logic' (p. 33), and that
'the classical system thus reveals, over a long period, a surprising capacity for
"assimilating" . . . ' (p. 34). The only surprising thing in all this is the author's
own surprise.
234
23 5
T I M E REGA I N E D
23 9
CHAPTER NINE
H I S T O RY AND D IALECT I C
247
inert matter it will be to discover that the latter has properties very
different fro those previously attributed to it. Levels of reduction
cannot therefore be classed as superior and inferior, for the level
taken as superior must, through the reduction, be expected to com
municate retro;1ctively some of its richness to the inferior level to
which it will have been assimilated. Scientific explanation consists
not in moving from the complex to the simple but in the replacement
of a less intelligible complexity by one which is more so.
Seen in this light, therefore, my self is no more opposed to others
than man is opposed to the world : the truths learnt through rna
are 'of the world', and they are important for this reason.* Thts
explains why I regard anthropology as the principle of all resarch,
while for Sartre it raises a problem in the shape of a constramt to
overcome or a resistance to reduce. And indeed what can one make
of peoples 'without history' when one has defined man in terms of
dialectic and dialectic in terms of history? Sometimes Sartre seems
tempted to distinguish two dialectics : the 'true' one which is sup
posed to be that of historical societies, and a repetitive, short-term
dialectic, which he grants so-called primitive societies whilst at the
same time placing it very near biology. This imperils his whole
system, for the bridge between man and nature wih he has taken
such pains to destroy would turn out to be surreptttwusly re-etab
lished through ethnography, which is indisputably a human sc1ence
and devotes itself to the study of these societies. Alternatively Sartre
resigns himself to putting a 'stunted and deformed' humanity n
man's side (p. 203), but not without implying that its lace m
humanity does not belong to it in its own right and is a functwn only
of its adoption by historical humanity : either because it has
begun to internalize the latter's history in the colonial cntext,
.
.
or because thanks to anthropology itself, htstoncal humamty has
given the blessing of meaning to an original humanity which was
*This even holds for mathematical truths of which a contemporary logician,
however, says that 'The characteristic of mathematical thought is that it does ot
convey truth about the external world' (Heyting, pp. 8-9). But mathema1al
_ the act1v1ty
thought at any rate reflects the free functioning of the mind, that 1s,
of the cells of the cerebral cortex, relatively emancipated from any external
.
constraint and obeying only its own laws. As the mind too is a thmg, the func
_ s : even pure
tioning of this thing teaches us something about the nature of thm
?
reflection is in the last analysis an internalization of the cosmos. It Illustrates the
structure of what lies outside in a symbolic form : 'Logic and logistics are
empirical sciences belonging to ethnography rather than psychology' (Beth,
p. 1 5 1 ).
without it. Either way the prodigious wealth and diversity of habits,
beliefs and customs is allowed to escape ; and it is forgotten that
each of the tens or hundreds of thousands of societies which have
existed side by side in the world or succeeded one another since
man's first appearance, has claimed that it contains the essence of
all the meaning and dignity of which human society is capable and,
reduced though it may have been to a small nomad band or a hamlet
lost in the depths of the forest, its claim has in its own eyes rested on
a moral certainty comparable to that which we can invoke in our
own case. But whether in their case or our own, a good deal of ego
centricity and naivety is necessary to believe that man has taken
refuge in a single one of the historical or geographical modes of his
existence, when the truth about man resides in the system of their
differences and common properties.
He who begins by steeping himself in the allegedly self-evident
truths of introspection never emerges from them. Knowledge of
men sometimes seems easier to those who allow themselves to be
caught up in the snare of personal identity. But they thus shut the
door on knowledge of man : written or unavowed 'confessions' form
the basis of all ethnographic research. Sartre in fact becomes the
prisoner of his Cogito : Descartes made it possible to attain univers
ality, but conditionally on remaining psychological and individual ;
by sociologizing the Cogito, Sartre merely exchanges one prison for
another. Each subject's group and period now take the place of time
less consciousness. Moreover, Sartre's view of the world and man
has the narrowness which has been traditionally credited to closed
societies. His insistence on tracing a distinction between the primi
tive and the civilized with the aid of gratuitous contrasts reflects, in
a scarcely more subtle form, the fundamental opposition he postu
lates between myself and others. Yet there is little difference
between the way in which this opposition is formulated in Sartre's
work and the way it would have been formulated by a Melanesian
savage, while the analysis of the practico-inert quite simply revives
the language of animism.*
Descartes, who wanted to found a physics, separated Man from
*It is precisely because all these aspects of the savage mind can be discovered
in Sartre's philosophy, that the latter is in my view unqualified to pass judgment
on it: he is prevented from doing so by the very fact of furnishing its equivalent.
To the anthropologist, on the contrary, this philosophy (like all the others) affords
a first-class ethnographic document, the study of which is essential to an under
standing of the mythology of our own time.
249
zso
252
253
the right one : superstructures are faulty acts which have 'made it'
socially. Hence it is vain to go to historical consciousness for the
truest meaning. What Sartre calls dialectical reason is only a recon
struction, by what he calls analytical reason, of hypothetical moves
about which it is impossible to know - unless one should perform
them without thinking them - whether they bear any relation at all to
what he tells us about them and which, if so, would be definable in
terms of analytical reason alone. And so we end up in the paradox
of a system which invokes the criterion of historical consciousness to
distinguish the 'primitive' from the 'civilized' but - contrary to its
claim - is itself ahistorical. It offers not a concrete image of history
but an abstract schema of men making history of such a kind that
it can manifest itself in the trend of their lives as a synchronic
totality. Its position in relation to history is therefore the same as that
of primitives to the eternal past : in Sartre's system, history plays
exactly the part of a myth.
Indeed, the problem raised by the Critique de la raison dialectique
is reducible to the question : under what conditions is the myth of
the French Revolution possible? And I am prepared to grant that
the contemporary Frenchman must believe in this myth in order
fully to play the part of an historical agent and also that Sartre's
analysis admirably extracts the set of formal conditions necessary
if this result is to be secured. But it does not follow that his meaning,
just because it is the richest (and so most suited to inspire practical
action), should be the truest. Here the dialectic turns against itself.
This truth is a matter of context, and if we place ourselves outside
it - as the man of science is bound to do -what appeared as an experi
enced truth first becomes confused and finally disappears altogether.
The so-called men of the Left still cling to a period of contemporary
history which bestowed the blessing of a congruence between prac
tical imperatives and schemes of interpretation. Perhaps this golden
age of historical consciousness has already passed ; and that this
eventuality can at any rate be envisaged proves that what we have
here is only a contingent context like the fortuitous 'focusing' of an
optical instrument when its object-glass and eye-piece move in
relation to each other. We are still 'in focus' so far as the French
Revolution is concerned, but so we should have been in relation to
the Fronde had we lived earlier. The former will rapidly cease to
afford a coherent image on which our action can be modelled, just
as the latter has already done. What we learn from reading Retz is
2 54
257
biased even when it claims not to be, for it inevitably remains partial
- that is, incomplete - and this is itself a form of partiality. When one
proposes to write a history of the French Revolution one knows (or
ought to know) that it cannot, simultaneously and under the same
heading, be that of the Jacobin and that of the aristocrat. Ex hypo
thesi, their respective totalizations (each of which is anti-symmetric
to the other) are equally true. One must therefore choose between
two alternatives. One must select as the principal either one or a
third (for there are an infinite number of them) and give up the
attempt to find in history a totalization of the set of partial totaliza
tions ; or alternatively one must recognize them all as equally real :
but only to discover that the French Revolution as commonly con
ceived never took place.
History does not therefore escape the common obligation of all
knowledge, to employ a code to analyse its object, even (and especi
ally) if a continuous reality is attributed to that object.* The distinc
tive features of historical knowledge are due not to the absence of a
code, which is illusory, but to its particular nature : the code consists
in a chronology. There is no history without dates. To be convinced
of this it is sufficient to consider how a pupil succeeds in learning
history : he reduces it to an emaciated body, the skeleton of which is
formed by dates. Not without reason, there has been a reaction
against this dry method, but one which often runs to the opposite
extreme. Dates may not be the whole of history, nor what is most
interesting about it, but they are its sine qua non, for history's entire
originality and distinctive nature lie in apprehending the relation
between before and after, which would perforce dissolve if its terms
could not, at least in principle, be dated.
Now, this chronological coding conceals a very much more com
plex nature than one supposes when one thinks of historical dates
illusion of having overcome the insoluble antinomy (in such a system) between
my self and others, consists of the assignation, by historical consciousness, of
the metaphysical function of Other to the Papuans. By reducing the latter to the
state of means, barely sufficient for its philosophical appetite, historical reason
abandons itself to a sort of intellectual cannibalism much more revolting to the
anthropologist than real cannibalism.
* In this sense too, one can speak of an antinomy of historical knowledge : if it
claims to reach the continuous it is impossible, being condemned to an infinite
regress ; but to render it possible, events must be quantified and thereafter
temporality ceases to be the privileged dimension of historical knowledge because
as soon as it is quantified each event can, for all useful purposes, be treated as
if it were the result of a choice between possible pre-existents.
Pp. 242-3.
' i
' !
266
THE SAVAGE M I N D
I I I STOHY A N D D I ALECTI C
world is not merely coherent but the very one demanded in the
case of an object whose elementary structure presents the picture of
a discontinuous complexity.
The false antinomy between logical and prelogical mentality was
surmounted at the same time. The savage mind is logical in the
same sense and the same fashion as ours, though as our own is only
when it is applied to knowledge of a universe in which it recognizes
physical and semantic properties simultaneously. This misunder
standing once dispelled, it remains no less true that, contrary to
Levy-Bruhl's opinion, its thought proceeds through understanding,
not affectivity, with the aid of distinctions and oppositions, not by
confusion and participation. Although the term had not yet come
into use, numerous texts of Durkheim and Mauss show that they
understood that so-called primitive thought is a quantified form of
thought.
It will be objected that there remains a major difference between
the thought of primitives and our own : Information Theory is con
cerned with genuine messages whereas primitives mistake mere
manifestations of physical determinism for messages. Two con
siderations, however, deprive this argument of any weight. In the
first place, Information Theory has been generalized, and it extends
to phenomena not intrinsically possessing the character of messages,
notably to those of biology ; the illusions of totemism have had at
least the merit of illuminating the fundamental place belonging to
phenomena of this order, in the internal economy of systems of
classification. In treating the sensible properties of the animal and
plant kingdoms as if they were the elements of a message, and in
discovering 'signatures' - and so signs - in them, men have made
mistakes of identification : the meaningful element was not always
the one they supposed. But, without perfected instruments which
would have permitted them to place it where it most often is namely, at the microscopic level - they already discerned ' as through
a glass darkly' principles of interpretation whose heuristic value and
accordance with reality have been revealed to us only through very
recent inventions : telecommunications, computers and electron
microscopes.
Above all, during the period of their transmission, when they
have an objective existence outside the consciousness of transmitters
and receivers, messages display properties which they have in
common with the physical world. Hence, despite their mistakes
z68
B IB L I O G RAPHY
271
THE SAVAGE M I N D
B IB L I O GRAPHY
272
273
B I B L I O GRAPHY
B I B L I O GRAPHY
278
279
I N D EX
46-8
Ashanti, 133 n.
Asmat, 6o
Astrology, 42
Athapaskan, so
AUGER, P., 263
Aurora, 76-So
Aymara, 43
Azande, I I
BACH, J. S., 242
Baganda, I I2-3, I78
Bahima, ISO
BALANDIER, G., 234-5 n.
Balovale, 6
BALZAC, H. DE, I30
Bambara, I63
Banyoro, ISO, I79-8o
Bard, 6s, I84
BARROWS, D.P., s
Bateso, ISI
BATESON, G . , 174. I77
BEATTIE, J.H. M., 179-80
BECKWITH, M. w., so
BEIDELMAN, T. 0., I44
Bemba, 62
BENEDICT, P. K., I89
BERGSON, H., 137
BETH, E.W., 248 n.
Bhil, I20-I
Birds, S4-6I, 96, I47, I49, 1 89
Birds, names given to, 2031 ::u 3
Birth,
1 37,
1 53,
173,
CALAME-GRIAULE, G., I 6 3
Canela, 4 0 n.
Cannibalism, 78, r os, 257-8 n.
CAPELL, A., 57
Carcajou (Gulo luscus), so-3
CARPENTER, E., 64
Caste, I I 3-33, r 62
Chance, 14, r 84-5, r 87, 220
CHARBONNIER, G., 234
Cherburg, r 8o-r n.
CHEVAL (the postman), 17
Chickasaw, I I7, I I g, 1 26, r 64, 204
Chinese, 65 n., ro6, r 65 n.
Chinook, r
Chippewa, 1 02, I I 6, r 67
Churinga, 87-8, 237-44
Classification, 3g-74, 1 35-22 1 ,
22g-44, 2Sg-62, 267-8
22, 24, 26-7
ro6, I I I , I I g, 1 37-40,
COGHLAN,
230
r 8-2 r ,
6 2 , ! 3 8-g, 1 4 1 , 1 53
DORSEY, G.A., 1 28
DoRSEY, J. O., 69, I48-g
Drysdale river, r 68, I74,
DUPIRE, M., 145
1 3 7-9,
go,
BouLAINVILLIERS (Boulainviller),
Comte H. DE, 261-2 n.
Bouriate, 8-g
BOWERS, A. w., so
Brassica rapa, 201-3, 2 1 1-2
Bricolage, r 6-36, r s o n.
BRi:iNDAL, V., r 8s n., 201 n.
BROUILLETTE, B., 50
CLOUET, F.,
Coahuila, 5
Code, go-8,
20,
Computer, 8g, 1 5 1
CoMTE, A., 1 63-4, 2 1 8-20
Concept, conceptual, 1-5,
178, 230
Bushmen,
Comprehension,
264-5
Blackfoot, r o
BoAs, F . , r , 2 1 , 1 3 5-6, r 8g
BocHET, G., 1 54
Bororo (Africa), 145
Bororo (Brazil), 3g n., gg, I I4,
INDEX
107,
r r7,
r r g,
CoNKLIN H. C.,
Continuous
and passim
n., 5 5 ,
3 , 7-8, 3g
and
172,
1 29-3 1 ,
discontinuous,
r g5-200,
2 15-6,
224-8, 232-4, 25 6-64, 268
84, I44,
r s s,
DENNETT, R. E., I 3 3
DENNLER, J. G., 44 n.
DENSMORE, F., 50, r 65 n.
DESCARTES, R., 24g
DETAILLE, E., 28
Determinism, geographical, 94-6
Devanga, 120
Diachrony, 52-3, 63, 66-74, 87-8,
I48-g, I S S , r 66, r g7, 227 n.,
2 3 I -44, 256, 263
Dialectical reason, 245-6g
Dinka,
I 2 I , 1 28-9
n.
I I,
s6,
I I-2,
r g6-7 n.
so, 64
EvANs-PRITCHARD, E. E.,
2 I O, 23 6-44, 264
I66, I 8g
Gi:iDEL,
84, r oo, I02,
Endogamy, I I I-33
FREEMAN, J. D.,
1 04, I 63,
Gahuku-Gama, 30
GALEN, 42
Games, 3o-2, I 26
GARDINER, A.H., I72, r 8 s , 201-3,
2 I I , 2I5 n.
GEDDES, W. R. , 205
GILGES, W., 6
GILLEN, F. J,, 8 I-2, 84, 86, 88, r r 4,
GOBINEAu, Comte J,A. DE, 26r-2 n.
I 8S , 2 I 8, 242, 265
Eskimo, 40,
I45
238, 240-1
225
Dakota, r 8g
Dates, 25 8-62
Dayak, 54, 56, 205 n.
DEACON, B., 2 5 !
Death, 3 1-2, 6 5 , 76-8 r ,
DELATTE, A., 42
Delaware, 142
Demography, 66-74,
176
55
B., 6
French Revolution, 254-5,
26I-2 n.
FREIRE-MARRECO,
258,
K.,
262
1 96
3 , 37,
g6, 144
HEDIGER, H., 38
HEIM, R., r 86
Helmene, 8
HENDERSON, J., 7
HENRY, J., r os n.
HERMES TRISMEGISTUS,
42
153
I95,
KRIGE, J . D . , I59 n.
KROEBER, A. L. , 7I, I28, 175-7,
196-7 n.
Kuruba, I2I
Kwakiutl, I 89
LA BARRE, w., 44
Lacandon, I 87 n.
LA FLEscHE, F., s6,
Iakoute, 8, 9
latmul, I74
lban, s4, s6
Information theory, I S4, 268-g
Infrastructures, 90-6, I3o-1, 2 I3-4
lntichiuma, 226-8
Ioway, I67
Iroquois, 57,
Mabuiag, I I S
McCLELLAN, C., 99
McCoNNEL, U., I74
McLENNAN, J. F., I I 8, 231
Magic and religion, 220-8
MAHONY, F. See FrscHER
Maithakudi, IOO-I
Maize, 6I, 73, I I2
Malaita, 78-8o
286
INDEX
Malecite,
8
MALINOWSKI, B., 3, 74, 9 1 , 250
Mandan, 52
MANNHARDT, W., 95
MANU, Laws of, ro6, 126
Manufactured
articles,
121-9,
143-4, 1 5 1 , 174-5
Marriage rules, 8I-4, 88, 103-6,
I09-33, I SS, 243, 264-6
MARSH, G.H., 153
MARX, K . , 130, 246, 253
Mashona, ros
Matabele, 105
Mathematics, 248 n.
MAuss, M., I I , r8 n., 39, 40, 57,
223, 268
Maya, 1 87 n., 1 89
MEGGITT, M. J., 222
MELIES, G., I 7
Menomini, 57, I r6, 1 67, r 88, 229
Menstruation, 46-8, 5 1-2, 9 1 , 144,
225
Mentality, primitive, 37-8, 25 1 ,
267-8
Metaphor, SI-2, ros-6, ISO n.,
204-8, 212-3, 224-8, 239
Meteorology, 9I-7
Metonymy, 52, ro6, 150 n., 204-8,
212-3, 224-8
MrcHELSON, T., 3 1-2, 65, roo,
199 n.
Micmac, 8
MIDDLETON, J., 179-80
MILL, J. S., 172
Mind, savage, 219-20, 222-3, 245,
249 n., 263, 267-g
Miwok, 175, 178, 181
Mixe, 189
Mocassin, 143
Models, small-scale, 23-5, r so n.
Mohawk, 178
Mohican, 142
Montagnais, 8
MoRGAN, L., u 8
Morphology, 7-9
Mota, 76, 79-80, I77
Motivation, 1 54-60
Motlav, 78-8o
120
Murngin, 9 1-3, 96, 174
Muskogi, I I7
Munda,
1 6-22,
2S-6, 3o-3, S I-2, 68-']o, 9o-3,
127-8, 13 1-6, I48-so, r 6s-6,
I68-9, 2I8, 223, 228-44, 254-5
and passim
Naga, 73
Nandi, I I4
Names,
Numerology,
170-1,
178, 216
Omens, 54-6, 13 1-3
Oraon, 1 20
Ordinal names, 1 82, 187, 1 89-97
Organicism, 169
Organism, 103-4, 1 36, I48, 1 5 1-4,
169-'73, 175-6
Osage, s6, 59, 6r, 69-70, 140,
142-3, 145, 147, 149, 170-1, 173,
I78
Ossete, 8
Painting, 22-30
Papago, 165 n.
Papuans, 257-8 n.
INDEX
iI,
RADCLIFFE-BROWN, A. R.,
I ,
SMITH.
A. H., 5
E., 6
Solomon Islands, I40
Species, notions of, I 36-72, I75,
I77, I 85-7, zoo-I6, 224-8
SPECK, F. G., 8, I66
SPENCER, B., 8 1-2, 84, 86, 88, I I4,
238, 240-I
SPENGLER, 0., 244
STANNER, w. E. H., 94, 228
Statistics (distribution), 72, 8 I-2,
85-6, uz, I59-6o, I 86-7, 232
STEPHEN, A. M., 6o
STREHLOW, C., I 67-8, 239
STREHLOW, T. G . H., 89, 229, 235,
239, 24I , 243
STURTEVANT, W. C., 5, I 83
Subanum, 5, IJ9
Superstructures, I I7, I JO, 2 I J-4,
254
Surrealists, 2 I
SwANTON, J. R., 6o, I I 9, I 65
Synchrony, s2-3, 63, 66-74, I48-9,
I55, I 66, I 97, 2"27 n., 23 I-44,
254, 256, 263
Syntagmatic, paradigmatic, ISO n.,
203, 206-8, 2 I I , 2 I 5-6
SMITH BowEN,
Sacrifice, 223-8
Saibai, I I S
St John Chrysostom, I05
Samoa, I 05
SARTRE, J. - P., I Jo, 245-6, 248-56,
257-8 n., 264
Sauk, I70, I73, I88
SAUSSURE, F. DE, I 8, I49, I 56,
I 58-<)
SCHOOLCRAFT, R. H. See WILLIAMS,
M. L. W.
204 n.
SEDEIS (Societe d'etudes et de
documentation economiques, indus
trielles et sociales), 70
Seminole, 5, I 82
Sense, I72, 2 IO, 249, 253-4, 255
Senufo, I 54
SHARP, R. LAURISTON, 88, IOO--I,
I 5 I n., I 67, 236
Sherente, 53
SIEGFRIED, A., 70
Sign, Signification, I 8-zo, 36,
IJ0-3, I40, I 56-6o, I72-3,
I 8I-3, r8s-6, 2o3-I5, 2 I 9-23,
239, 250, 257, 259, z66-9
Silence, 65
SJLLANS, R., 5
SIMPSON, G. G., I 2, I J , 63, I 56
Sioux, 57 n., 59, I40, I 67, I 73, I76,
I 89
SKINNER, A., I 67, I73, i 88, 229
Smells, I 2-3
SEBILLOT, P.,
Tanoan, 7 I
Tastes, I 2-3
Taxonomy, 9-I 3, I S-6, 38-45,
IJ7-9, I 53-4, I 56, I 86-9, 203,
23I
Teleology, 252
TERTULLIAN, I05
TESSMANN, G.; 3, 6I n., 98-9, I04
Tewa, 5-'7
THOMAS, N. w., l l 3
THOMSON D . F., 45, I 67, I 83-4,
I88
Thunder Birds, 96, 229
THURNWALD, R., 200
THURSTON, E., 63 n., I 2 I
Tikopia, I 39, 228 n.
Tikuna, Io6-7
Tiwi, I77, I 9o, I95, I 99-2oo, 206,
209, 2 I I , 2I2-3 n.
Tjongandji, IOO-I
z88
,
Wakelbura, I 02
A. RAPONDA, 5
WALLIS, W. D., I 90
Walpari, I I4
WARNER, W. LLOYD, 9I-3, 96, I 74
Warramunga, 8 I , 85-7, I I4, I 84,
238
Water-colours (Aranda), 89, 244
WATERMAN, T. T., I 68, I96-7 n.
Wawilak sisters, 9I-3
WEYDEN, R. VAN DER, 28
WHEELWRIGHT, M. C., I 28, 203
WHrTE, c. M. N., 6s, 98
WHITE, L . A., 227 n.
WALKER,
174, 183,
1 86-8, Z I Z
WILLIAMS, M. L W., 56
WILSON, G. L., 48, so
Winnebago, 57, 140, 14Z, 167, 170
Wmz, P., 63 n.
WITKOWSKI, G. J., ZOI
WOENSDREGT, J., 169
Wolverine, so-3
Wormwood. See Artemisia
WoRSLEY, P., 1 5 6
Wotjobaluk, 5 7 , 105
WYMAN,
L . C . , 40, Z04
Yathaikeno, xoo-1
Yoruba, 105, 1 3 1-3
Yuma, 180
Yurlunggur (snake), 91-3
Yurok, 168, 177, 189, 196-7