Guz Zetti
Guz Zetti
Guz Zetti
The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
New Literary History.
http://www.jstor.org
(I) the verisimilitude of the space, within which the position of the character is always determined, even when a close-up eliminates the decor;
(2) [the fact that] the intention and effects of the decoupage are exclusively
dramatic or psychological.
In other words, played in a theater and seen from a seat in the orchestra,
the scene would have exactly the same meaning, the event would continue
to exist objectively. The changes in the camera's point of view add
nothing. They only present reality in a more effective manner. First by
permitting a better view, then by putting the accent where it belongs.1
Like most theorists and critics, Bazin shows no inclination to challenge
the idea that narrative, with its "dramatic or psychological" requirements, is the controlling factor in shooting and cutting and that the
image has only the very subordinate role of supplying "accent." In
fact, except in the limited class of instances where "the verisimilitude
of the space" is at stake, he proposes no terms at all with which to
explain the form of the image. Elsewhere, he makes this silence a
critical principle, siding with directors "who believe in reality" as opposed to those "who believe in the image."2 When he discusses a
specific shot, he does so only to the extent that the narrative informs
I Qu'est-ce que le Cinema? (Paris, 1958), I, I40. The translation is mine and
corresponds to that in What is Cinema? tr. Hugh Gray (Berkeley and Los Angeles,
I969), pp. 31-32. The term decoupage, which has no English equivalent, designates
the division of the action into shots; it is to be distiguished from montage, which
means editing.
2 Qu'est-ce que le Cinema? I, 132.
38o
it, never as it reflects the whole array of decisions made by the cinematographer, editor, and director. The requirements of spatial verisimilitude and narrative are, in his view, independent of these decisions to
such an extent that he willingly associates different sets of decisions
with "exactly the same meaning."
This conception of image and narrative, paradoxical and deficient
as it seems, merely reflects that implied in the style of classical sound
films.3 To understand the source and consequence of these deficiencies,
one must examine the conventions of that style in some detail, specifically those that link the "dramatic or psychological" to the spatial.
For this purpose, it is useful to refer to the practical manuals of cinematography and editing where these conventions are formulated as rules.
The fact that they appear in this guise rather than as theoretical or
critical propositions is significant in itself, since it reflects the consensus
of critics and viewers that "film" is so completely identified with
classical narrative that the workings of this style are not convention,
but "technique." Yet inasmuch as these rules are compatible only
with certain views of image and narrative, they undeniably constitute
a critical and theoretical position.
Two sets of rules, those governing continuity and screen direction,
are of particular relevance to the relation of narrative to image.4 The
first concerns the problem of showing an ongoing action in successive
shots. The basic rule of this set requires the editor to join the shots
so that the action is picked up at the beginning of the second at the
precise point it reaches by the end of the first. In shots that show
human beings, as in many that do not, the action normally includes
segments of continuous movement as well as resting points, called
"nodes." A second, and much looser, rule favors placing the cut on
the node. The consequence of both rules is to permit the logic of the
action to dominate that of the cutting. Cuts so made tend to be
"invisible": that is, they do not signify that two pieces of film have
been joined together, as they would if a segment of the action were
repeated or omitted or if the cut interrupted movement or stasis.
The continuity rules specify further that at the point of the cut
there must be a substantial change of scale or angle or both. Thus, if
3 I use the term classical more broadly than Bazin, who restricts it to the common
practices of decoupage among films of the 19305.
4 My account of these rules follows that in Karel Reisz and Gavin Millar, The
Technique of Film Editing, 2nd ed. (New York, i969), pp. 213-26, cited hereafter as "Reisz." The same rules may be found in Terrence St. John Marner,
Directing Motion Pictures (London and New York, I972), Arthur L. Gaskill and
David A. Englander, How to Shoot a Movie Story (New York, I967), and Kenneth
H. Roberts and Win Sharples, Jr., A Primer of Film-making (New York, I971).
38I
the editor begins with a medium shot showing the actor from head to
mid-thigh, the rule allows a cut to a close-up of the face of the same
person seen from the same angle, but not, say, to a shot that shows
him, again from the same angle, from head to waist. The rationale
given is that the prohibited cut produces a change of scale slight enough
to seem jumpy and awkward.
But a more consequential explanation is possible. In the essay
"Dickens, Griffith, and Us," Eisenstein observes that the difference
in the American and Russian conceptions of the close-up is reflected
in the two respective languages.5 The Russian term literally means
a "large shot," as does the French "gros plan." Thus in Russian and
French, the shot is defined by its graphic aspect, the scale of the image
on the surface of the screen, whereas in English, it is defined by the
proximity of the camera to the subject. This observation suggests a
potential ambiguity in the instance I have given of the rule of scalechange: for any cut that takes the camera closer to the subject is
capable of signifying both "enlargement" and "approach." The small
change of scale prohibited by the rule would link two shots whose
overall graphic patterns within the rectangle are inevitably very similar,
thus calling attention to the surface of the screen and to the associated
signification "enlargement." By contrast, the close-up permitted by
the rule changes the graphic pattern sufficiently that attention to the
screen surface goes unrewarded, allowing the cut to be understood
unambiguously as a movement of viewpoint situated within the space
in which the action is played. Small changes of angle are excluded
on the same principle.
In addition, angle changes are subject to the rules governing screen
direction. A shot in which Actor A is shown screen-left and Actor B
screen-right must not be immediately followed by a shot in which their
screen positions are reversed. This condition will be met if both shots
are taken from the same side of an imaginary line, sometimes called
the director's line or center line, established between the two actors
on the floor of the shooting location. The simplest instance is a dialogue
scene in which A and B sit at opposite ends of a table: shots taken
from any angle within the I8o0 in front of the table may be cut
together; shots taken from behind the table can be cut in continuity
with these only if the camera or actors move, thus establishing a new
center line, or if a spatially "neutral" shot such as a close-up, insert,
or high-angle, is intercut. Similarly, a shot of an actor walking screen5 Sergei M. Eisenstein, Film Form, ed. and tr. Jay Leyda (London, 1963), pp.
237-38. The essay in question is included under the title "Dickens, Griffith, and
the Film Today."
382
383
384
385
?~,~1i
i~~
i :::
::
f:
::
''?e
'-~:'::'
....
,,
0-=...
O
t.
. A
387
388
narratives often in some way concern the act of making images: Blowup, 8 2, Muriel, The Decameron, and Le Petit Soldat are obvious
examples.
The shot I have been discussing begins with some action not evident
in the illustration. An attendant opens and closes the car door on
Juliette's side, apparently to ask her what she wants, then crosses
behind the vehicle to fill the tank; Juliette's husband enters and squats
in the position shown. The chosen framing is thus in part justified by
the action, since it allows us to see that the transaction between
Juliette and the attendant continues while she speaks with her husband. However, this logic serves only to raise a further question, since
the attendant is an anonymous figure in the drama, an extra, and this
piece of action has no narrative consequences.
This issue, unresolved here, is taken up four shots later by means of
the nearly static image (shown in Illustration 2) in combination with
the following text: "There is also another young woman, of whom
we know nothing. We wouldn't even know how to say that honestly"
(Deux ou Trois Choses, p. 65). Though the young woman is placed
in the frame in a way ordinarily reserved for the main characters of
the drama, she indeed does not appear elsewhere in the film. The text
stresses that it is not the director, the first person singular, who knows
nothing about her, but "we," the spectators. His pretended inability
to say this "honestly" jokes about the fact, unreported in the film, that
the young woman is the second assistant director, Isabel Pons. But the
text is more than just a joke. We do indeed know the sort of thing
about her that Godard in the opening sequence tells us about Juliette:
namely, the color of her hair and sweater, the expression on her face,
the movements of her head. The sort of thing we do not know is what
the narrative might tell us. If we were in a position to get Godard's
joke, we would understand that he knows something about her that he
can easily express neither in the image nor in the narrative. His text
and image stress instead that we are not in this position. Not only are
we ignorant of the specifics narrative might report, but narrative does
not even give us terms for stating this ignorance "honestly": that is,
for recognizing the sort of "knowledge" it promotes and suppresses.
Including himself among the spectators, the "we" of the text, Godard
in this rather opaque fashion suggests that narrative itself, quite apart
from the particularities of its execution, has a "problematic," a structure which encourages us to think only of certain things as in need, or
capable, of explanation.
The following shot (Illustration 3) and its commentary make a
parallel argument about the image: "There is also a cloudy sky, on the
389
390
shot shown in Illustration 2 can, and must, be taken to mean that the
young woman is to be understood in relation to the objects-in particular, the advertisements-grouped around her in the frame. Since
we have no means of knowing exactly the size of the signs on the wall,
and since we do not see the plane of the ground linking figure and
wall, we have no certain sense of the space between them. Godard
thus strengthens the flattening tendency of the image by composing
the elements chiefly in reference to a single plane, an effect that is
even more striking in the color original, where the yellow and blue
signs are set against a white wall.
It is clear even without taking the analysis further that in this style
the classical chain of logic linking image to narrative is at its every point
opposed and questioned. If the dichotomy "classicism versus modernism" is understood (to use the language of structuralism) "diachronically," then it is sufficient merely to record these oppositions as differences. Some distinguished recent theorists, despite the synchronic
nature of their method, take this view. The philosopher F. E. Sparshott argues that critical differences about film cannot be resolved
by discussion of the properties of the image, which is sufficiently complex to support differing, even opposing, views. Christian Metz portrays film language as a heterogenous ensemble of elements, none of
which occupies a controlling place or authorizes a critical principle.11
In reply, I should point out that since modernist styles take account
of more aspects of the image, they are in a position to relate it to narrative in a more complex and more complete way. This is true not only
in cases like that of Deux ou Trois Choses, where the interrogation of
classical conventions is carried to exhaustion, but even of such films
as The Gospel According to Matthew, whose modernism consists
chiefly in certain discordantly documentary habits of cinematography,
which function, as their author observes, only "to make the presence
of the camera felt." 12
Completeness of this sort is not, however, a criterion that may be
simply applied in the judgment of films. It does not, for example, imply
that because Pasolini's style habitually calls attention to the presence
of the camera, his films are to be preferred to those that do not. Rather,
Metz develops this view most fully in Language et Cinema (Paris, 197 ).
I
Sparshott's essay, "Basic Film Aesthetics," is reprinted in Film Theory and
Criticism, ed. Gerald Mast and Marshall Cohen (New York, London, Toronto,
1974), pp. 209-32.
Pier Paolo Pasolini, "Le cinema de poksie," Cahiers du Cinema, No. 171
I2
(Oct. 1965), p. 64. Pasolini uses the phrase in a general discussion without
specific reference to The Gospel According to Matthew, though this film clearly
belongs to "the cinema of poetry."
39I
it suggests that the modernist model of image and narrative has a more
valid claim to set the terms for interpretation and criticism. This means,
at a minimum, accepting the premise that narrative and image in
film, like text and music in opera, are distinct strands, one of which is
not fully reducible to the other, and that critical positions, which, like
Bazin's, reject this premise are compromised at the root.
To apply this principle in the interpretation and criticism of classical
films is, obviously, to resist not only the manifest intentions of their authors but the assent given those intentions by spectators. The very
intelligibility of classical styles demonstrates that these intentions are
viable, that one may "succeed" in using narrative to suppress certain
attributes of the image. What, then, justifies this resistance? As the
sequence from Deux ou Trois Choses demonstrates, a given characterization of the image, two or three dimensional, bounded or "analogous,"
is neither a question of personal predilection, as Sparshott supposes,
nor an isolated choice, but rather entails a whole ensemble of propositions, not the least of which involve the relation of the spectator to the
image. Thus one cannot argue that the image can be determined
exclusively by style, if style is defined in isolation from the conditions
that circumscribe the relation of spectator to screen. Modernist styles
show that what is truly at issue in style extends beyond such exclusively
formal questions as whether the image is taken to be surface or spatial
reference to whether it is characterized as a material component in the
work of author and spectator. The rules of continuity and directionality suggest the extent to which classical styles are predicated on
denying this. The critic who acquiesces in this denial foregoes the
recognition not only that we, spectators and directors alike, live in a
material world, to which the cinema belongs, but that the conditions
of that world-in particular, the physical situation of the spectator
and the material attributes of the image as they originate in optical
and chemical processes and in human choice and labor-are pertinent
to viewing or making films.
Such a recognition requires neither hostility to the classical film
nor prejudice to critical questions that might be asked of it. Rather, it
simply proposes that as a first principle criticism treat the organization
of the image plane as significant, even when the style insists that it is
not, and understand that such significance originates not in style alone
but in the relation of the film image both to the space to which it
refers and to the conditions that bound its presentation to the spectator.
In taking account of these relations, interpretation, along with the
criticism based on it, necessarily outruns the terms of narrative. Even
when such criticism is in accord with the intentions of the director as
392
they are recorded in the style, it is justified not by them but by the
aspiration to understand and respond to narrative film in its complete
manifestation as a significant object.
HARVARDUNIVERSITY