Ricoeur As Another: Introduction
Ricoeur As Another: Introduction
Ricoeur As Another: Introduction
RICOEUR AS ANOTHER
Edited by
Richard A. Cohen
James L. Marsh
Contents
Published by
State University of New York Press} Albany
vii
Sigla
XV
Charles E. Reagan
Lenore Langsdorf
James L. Marsh.
p. em.- (SUNY series in the philosophy of the social sciences)
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-7914-51895 (alk. paper)-ISBN 0-79145190-9 (pbk. : alk. paper)
1. Ricoeur, Paul. 2. Ethics. 3. Subjectivity. I. Cohen, Richard A. II. Marsh,
james L. Ill. Series.
33
57
71
Don Ihde
93
2001031188
10 9 8 7 6
543 2 1
107
Patrick L. Bourgeois
109
Richard A. Cohen
127
v
vi
CONTENTS
Eric Crump
161
David PeUauer
187
Bernard P. Dauenhauer
Introduction
203
223
235
Index
237
After an initial reading nf Ricoeur's Oneself as Another, we have the impression of ave!}' sjgnificant work. One may or may not go all the way with
Charles Reagan, one of the contributors to this volume, when he says that
this is "Ricoeur's most elegantly written, clearly organized, and closely argued
work" (2), or, later in his essay, that the book is "the very model of his
philosophical style" (33). But we do have a sense nonetheless that the work
brings to a tentative conclusiont always open to further developmerit 1 a series
of different but related inquiries carried out over the course of a lifetime into
the self, freedom, interpretation, narrative, and critique.
One relatively new aspect of the work is that the last four chapters. represent Ricoeur's first fully systematic and sustained statement of his ethics
and its ontological implications. Ethics is not a fully new concern of Ricoeur's,
but his reflections in the .past have been mote momentary and episodic and
most often in the context of pursuing something else. This relatively new
ethical aspect of his work is related to other kinds of inquiry that have been
typical Ricoeurian themes, such as action theory, the semantics and pragmatics of language, and narrative theory. All of the themes in this new book,
however, are unified by the theme of the self as another and as related to the
other.
One of Ricoeur's early works, Freedom and Nature, was a sustained phenomenological inquiry into the nature and limits of freedom. We are lefr at
the end of that work, however, with a question about the ethical implications of his inquiry into freedom. Oneself as Another can be taken as his most
mature- answer to that question.
Much, of course, intervenes in the time between Freedom and Nature and
Oneself as Another. Soon after writing that first book,"Ricoe1lr in Symbolism
take his famous henneneutical rum, moving fro~ direct
'" phenomenological description of human experience to interpretation of that
olBVil begins to
vii
ix
INTRODUCTION
INTRODUCTION
linking of earlier themes and methodologies with the method and content
the rest of his career. Such a turn continues in subsequent works such as
viii
interplay between particular and universal, analytic and synthetic, experiential and interpretative, hermeneutical and explanatory, disparate and synthetic lines of inquiry. Freedom and Nature brings to synthetic completion
earlier universal, eidetic phenomenological inquiries into Husserl, Jaspers,
Marcel, and other related thinkers and themes in phenomenology and existentialism. At the same time, that work opens onto more concrete reflections
Oneself as Another.
Ricoeur's book, then, represents a tentative completion of earlier inquiries
into the free, embodied self going back to his very earliest work. What kind
of ethics is implied by his account of the free, embodied, social self, which
is in the world and mediated by structures of language and by a psychological
and social unconscious? The book at the same time represents a synthetic
and fiction, the right and the good, dury and happiness, justification and
application, the self and the other. The contemporary ethical Humpty Dumpry,
which has been split up and carved up hy Aristotelians and Kantians,
communitarians and Rawlsians or Habermasians, universalists and advocates
of application to the particular, Ricoeur attempts to put back together again.
In the opinion of at least some of the authors of this. volume, contested
somewhat by others, Ricoeur largely succeeds in that task But all agree about
the importance and philosophical provocativeness of what he has tried to do.
The editors have divided the volume into parts, the first dealing primarily
with Ricoeur's thought itself and the second dealing with his relations to
other thinkers. Charles Reagan's essay, which starts off the volume, reflects
on how Ricoeur's sense of personal identity is inextricably bound up with the
other; how Ricoeur's philosophical ethics is the first major statement of his
ethics,. a Ricoeurian groundwork fur the metaphysics of morals; and how
Ricoeur's style of philosophy, his dialogal and dialectical respect. for other
thinkers from whom he learns as well as criticizes, enacts and instantiates the
relationship between self and other articulated and defended in the book.
Lenore Langsdorf's essay, following hints given by Ricoeur himself, develops a mode of intentionality correlative to Husserlian intentionality. This
new mode of intentionality) generative intentionality~- is characterized by a
dependence on human others as helping to constitute the self, the anchoring
of the self in a lived body that is agent and patient in relation to the world,
and the ongoing composition of the lived body from physical constituents of
other bodies during and after the process of birth. Such a conception of
INTRODUCTION
ethical action, which cannot be encompassed within science. Van den Hengel's
answer to the question; "Can there be a SCience of action?'1 is~- therefore,
"
" anduno""
yes
: yes t' to the extent that expJanation is essential to under,
standing,- 'fno" to the extent that human action involves and implies attes~
tation, a committed trust, a "believing" in what the self says and what it
does.
Don lhde in his essay suggests that Oneself as Another may be the capstone
book of Ricoeur's career, because his dialectical and hermeneutical moves are
"more subtly made, less visible in the foreground, and placed in the most
complex and synthetic display of his philosophy to date" (97). In his essay
lhde interrogates Ricoeur~ linking of analytic philosophy and hermeneutics
from the perspective of his (Ihde's) own work in hermeneutics and philosophy of science. In his use of science fiction versus literary fiction to characterize the differences between analytic philosophy and hermeneutics, Ricoeur
correctly criticizes- science fiction>s attempt to render contingent the corpo..
INTRODUCTION
xi
But then Ricoeur surprisingly and mistakenly identifies the science fiction
version of science with technology as such. Ricoeur recognizes Parfit's
technomyth, but does not recognize his own. Deepest of all, however, is
count can be altered slightly but without substantially changing his overall
position. Thus~ Ricoeur's nuanced position can be seen-as an adequate link
self is not so separate as-to be inviolate, closed, out of relation) simply passive
as Ricoeur claims, but is more passive than any passivityt because it arises in
pure subjection to the other.
xii
INTRODUCTION
concerning the priority of the right over the good, and then assesses the
strength of that critique. Dauenhauer argues that Rawls argues illegitimately
for an obvious clarity to rights and duties as they are spelled out in consti
tutions. Because there is a necessary ambiguity and indeterminacy in consti~
tutional law, we are inevitably forced to reflect on a people's prior sense of
ethical life, in the light of which constitutions are interpreted and revised.
Ricoeur's theory does more justice to this concrete historical sense of a people's
ethical life, "the aiming for the good life, with and for others, in just institutions," than does Rawls. Ricoeur's understanding of ethical life better corresponds to a societis understanding that its citizens are pursuing some.
common good, in the light of which they become aware of complex distributional questions that call for universal norms~ and hence require a consti.rution that rules out scapegoating. The citizenry learns that this constitutional
imperative can never be definitively satisfied and hence that there is no
alternative. to an ongoing exercise of practical wisdom. Ricoeur thus provides
a preferable alternative to Rawls's insistence on the priority of the tight over
the good. There is a reciprocity between right and good that Rawls does not
see, as well as a rooting of abstract reflection on universal norms in a people~s
prior sense of the good life.
INTRODUCTION
xiii
Jim Marsh's essay, in that it synthetically takes on the whole book, but
especially the last four essays, touches on all or most of the themes rased in
Part Two. Marsh argues that ethical theory has recently been besieged by a
series of ethical antinomies between "is" and "ought," concrete individual
other and reflectively justified norm, justification and application, deontology and teleology, duty and happiness, self and other. Ricoeur has taken a
significant step toward putting this ethical Humpty Dumpty back together
again. At the same time, Marsh does raise a few questions concerning Ricoeur's
achievement. Is the ethical level prior to the moral level in the way Ricoeur
claims? Is there not in our everyday experience a lived sense of deontology
and tight that coexists with and relates to our striving for the good? Again,
does not Habermans, following Gunther, develop criteria for application of
norms that Ricoeur needs to take into account? Does he not make the move
too quickly to prudence and conviction?
What should be apparent in this brief. summary of the essays in this
volume is that Oneself as Another is a book rich in insights and potential
consequences. As is characteristic of all of Ricoeur's works, it opens up questions for further discussion. From Part One, for example, we may ask whether
Ricoeur's narrative account of the self does not give us a richer, deeper sense
of self than the relatively thin accounts of thinkers such as Habermas, Rawls,
or Ape!. In his critique of analytic notions of literature, does not Ricoeur
give in to his own technomyth, and thus inadvertently endorse an excessively negative sense of technology? Does Ricoeur's notion of the self move
between the Scylla. of foundationalism and the Charybdis of relativism in
such a way that he provides a genuine alternative and implicit critique to
postmodem claims concerning the death of the self? Is there an opening to
and use of intentionality analysis in Ricoeur's work that would imply and
require a more explicit thematizing of the relationship between phenomenology and hermeneutics in his work?
Part Two similarly opens up a rich vein of questioning. Three of the essays
deal in whole or in part with the issue of Levinas versus Ricoeur. Does
Ricoeues j_lldicious "yes't and ''no', to Levinasian otherness and mediation
with conscious, responsible selfhood work; or is such criticism and mediation
open to fundamental challenge? Does Ricoeur's mediation of otherness provide an alternative to and corrective to postmodemism,_ or does postmodernism
have resources for a reply? ls Ricoeur's rejection of the priority of the right
over the good and his privileging of ethical life in community over reflective
justification of ethical norms a convincing answer to thinkers such as
Habermas and Rawls? Is Ricoeur's insistence on ethical universalism in
form and content, at the same time recognizing the rights of particular
xiv
INTRODUCTION
Macintyre and Taylor? Finally, does Ricoeur put the ethical Humpty Dumpty
back together again or does he at least take significant steps toward doing so?
What would or could communitarians, Kantian, Rawlsian, or Habermasian
universalists, postmodemists, and Oadamerian prudentialists and traditionalists say in reply? Thus, Oneself as Another, the contributors to this volume
think and have tried to show, is a huge step forward, not only in the ques-
Sigla
James L. Marsh
NOTE
I. I wish to express my appreciation to Kirk Kanzelberger, my graduate
assistant, for his work in scanning, word processing and editing this work.
His care and competence have certainly contributed to whatever quality the
work may have.
Cc
Ci
CI
OF
Ora
EBI
FM
FN
FP
FS
HHS
Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences. Ed. and trans. John Thompson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980.
HT
IT
xvi
SIGLA
L1
L2
1.3
Lf
LJ
Lmv
LV
OA
PA
PART ONE
RICOEUR IN HIMSELF
1960.
RF
RM
Sa
sa
I
I
From Text to Action. Trans. Kathleen Blarney and John B. Thompson. Evanston, !11.: Northwestern University Press, 199!.
TN1
TN2
TN3
Tr
Temps et Recit. Tomes I, II, III. Paris: Le Seuil, 1983, 1984, 1985.
ONE
Personal Identity
Charles E. Reagan
Dring
CHARLES E. REAGAN
was actually read. Ricoeur then revised the first version by expanding several
chapters. The second edition follows closely the order and topics of the first
edition. This version was first given as lectures at the University of Munich
in the same year. Yet Ricoeur was not satisfied with his text and continued
for two more years to work and rework it. This was time well spent: Oneself
as Another is, in my opinion, Ricoeues most elegantly written, clearly orga.nized, and closely argued work. This is high praise for an author whose work
as a whole exemplifies these traits.
What I intend to do here is to give a synopsis of the book in order to show
what the question of personal identity is and how Ricoeur progressively
argues for a concept ofpersonalidentity that is i11extricably bound up with
a co11~ept ()f the other and the rel~tiol) between theselfaiid the. oth~l':ib~D.;
j wlll giv~ a more detailed acZ~~nt of the three chapters on ethics. These
chapters are interesting in their own right, and they come as close as anything Ricoeur has written to being a clear accountof his "philosophisal
ethics." He has written many articles on-individual moral or political c~n
cepts and concerns, but he has 11ever written a theoretical work on..e.rhics.
These chapters serve as his "groundwo;k. for a metaphysics of morals." ....
My second goal in this essay is to p~iiit out some of the things ;,;~~ his
students, learned about philosophy from Paul Ricoeur, as well as to comment
on some of the constant features in his philosophical style. Above all, Paul
Ricoeur is a teacher of philosophy. He taught us to do a .careful reading of
philosqphical texts, to always give the m()st generous inte,Pietation(oiiili='
big;;~us or obscure texts, and togi~e full credit to th()se. we havereada!;.d
f[(;'n:;;.;hom we have leamed. His fundamental thesis as a philosopher is that
vrtually everY ph.itosopher, ancient, modem, or contemporaryl has seen a
piece of the truth. Now our task is to adjudicate among competing interpretation.s, each of which daiinstobe ~bsolute.
. ...
The. tit!~ itself~ this book, Oneself as Another, indicates the three converging themes that make up this work: a reilexive Jn~.<litatiotl onthe self or
subject;. a QigJ.ectic_J)J:l, Jh~. rne_ar:t~ng. of the word mbne or"it~ln~;, fri ilie sense
of identical (idem) or in the sense ~f "one and the same" (ipse), or sellhoo<l;
a ciiai~tticJ?en~:en_ ~~-self_ and~-~- '~other.'; Ri~oeiii>S rrieditatio~- tak~s place
with-;;, the ~~l:lt.,">i of the history Of the philosophy of the subject and, in
particular, of the philosophy of Descartes and Nietzsche. For Descartes, the
cogito is both indubitable and the ultimate foundation of all that can be
known. For Nietzsche, on the contrary, the cogito is the name of an illusion.
Ricoeur, in his typically dialectic mode, says, "the her.meneutics of J;!le..s.!:lf
is placed at an equal distance from the apology of thecogiio and fromits
overthrow" f:'l-).
.
.
PERSONAL IDENTITY
as ..,.
a.;d
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
t~!iili:Loaf!iM?n'' (mimesiS!.
of the action recounted will begin t? correspond ro. the broaq~r con~ept of
the acting and suffering indivldi.ial,.whichour analytic-he~~eneutical prcice:
clt.lie is capable of eliCititlg"(i8).
The fourth group(chapters 7, 8, and 9) makes aJiJ)aldetoQf through the
ethical and moral determinations of action. "It is in the three ethical studies
that tneaiafectlc.ofthe~;;;n;,-;;;;J the.other will find its appropriate philosophical development" (18). Ricoeur admits that his studies appear to be
fragmentary and lack a unity,. He says, "The fragmentary character of these
studies results from the analytic-reflective structure that imposes arduous
detours on our hermeneutics, beginning as early as the first study" (19). The
thematic unity is found in human action. But human action does not serve as
,;i,-.Jti;;;;;~ f~~nd;ti~;} ofsomeset~f derived disciplines. Rather, there is an
aJ1alogi<;a(l1nity becalJ,S<' of the. polysemy of "action" and pecaus>()(':th.,
v;;l;ty an.tl <:~~;ing~ncy of the questions that activate the analyses l~adin.g
i;;:,azt;th~r~ft~ctlononth~ self' (19.:.20); .
. "fh~~tl\readihatooJ.tk;R;coel!r's analyses is descriptio!h!1!JITiltion,.pres.cxiptioncNa;ratbre.idet>tity serv~~ ,;; ;~~~~~;i:~gq ~~lation\l!ftJ'!~t!fl!lJ>e!VIIeen
the descrlmionthat_prevai!s)l!~.;:~alyt:icalph!lCl8o.Phies()f actipn and the
presc~lp~ion that desig,:;~~es.allthedetet'tninations ofaction by me:n:sof'!
generis t~rmon the basis of the predicate~ 'go~d' and '~bligato11'"' (20}.
The final study (chapter 10) explores the ciritologiCal consequences of the
hermeneutics of the self. Ricoeur claims that the dialectic between the "same"
and the "other" will prevent an ontology of act and power from bec<oming
encased in a tautology. "The polysemy of otherness, which 1 shall propose in
the tenth study, will imprifltupon the entire ontology of acting the seaLof
the diversity, qfsefl'e that foils the ambition of arriving at an ultimate foundation, characteristic
cogito phi!cisophies" (21).
A;;"~(h~;:a:;;;,:~~t~ri;~ic th~t clistir!g;;-i~hesRieaeur's hermeneutic of the self
from the philosophies of the cogito is the t)IP" of certainty appropriate to the
hermeneutics, in contradistinction to the claims of self-evidence ancl self-
{~;;..dation of the philosophies of the cogito. ~icoeur us.es the. word attestation
to describe the level of certitude appropriate to his herrnene.utics. With re~
spect to the "epistemological e~~ltation" ofTh!scartes's cogito and irs destruction by Nietzsche and his followers, Ricoeur claims, ''Attestation !lla~app~~
of the
it is alwaysvulrie"t'able:
"Th;;, ~.;l~e~abilltv~;;,iffbe~ex:
In juridical arguments, we recogoize levels of certainty appropriate to different situations, such as "probably cause," "preponderance of -the evidence,n
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
. Rl~~euto,;.ltted the lectures from his work for two reasons: (1) He wanted
this book to be an autonomous philosophical discourse by putting into parentheses the convictions that tied him to his biblical faith. This has been
a guiding principle in all of his philosophical work. (2} If Ricoeur has defended his work from becoming a "crypto-theology," he also defends biblical
faith from becoming a "crypto-philosophy." In particular, he does not want
biblical faith to replace the cogito as a form of foundation against which his
hermeneutics has fought continually.
PERSONAL IDENTITY
Ricoeur begins his studies of the self by looking at the linguistic means
at our .dispQ,f!lto.identifyanyrhi!lg, to refer to individual ~hit)gsaiiapl<Ok
them out of a group of similar things. He claims that aperso;.. is, at the
lowest level possible, "one of the things that we distinguish by means of
identifying reference" (27). He will begin with a linguistic study of the
qpera\i<?(!~ ?fJ!lcJividuali;:~tion found in natur.al languages. Definite descriptions create a class with single mem:ber {e:g.:;ihefirst man to walk
on the moon}, while proper names refer to a single individual without,
however, giving any information about the individual (e.g., Socrates).
The third category of individualizing operators is made up of pronouns
(e.g., you, he) and deictics such as demonstratives (e.g., this one, that
one), adverbs of time and place (e.g., now, then, here, there), and the
tenses of verbs. These operators individualize with reference to the speaker.
"Here" means in the proximity of the speakerl in relation to which {'there"
cution" (44).
10
11
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
The next two chapters link up the linguistic analysis of identifYing reference
and speech-acts with the philosophy of action. In chapter 3, Ricoeur deals
with the concepts in the philosophy of action, devoid of reference to a
particular agent. The following chapter introduces the imputation of agency.
"What does action, we shall ask, teach about its agent? And to what extent
can what is learned in this way contribute to clarifYing the difference between ipse and idem?" (56).
At the level of identifYing reference, the network of concepts with which
we describe action refers to an agent as being spoken about. But this is far
different from an explicit self-imputation of an action to an agent. Only at
the end of Ricoeur's next chapter will. we see the interrelationship between
identifYing reference and self-designation of an "acting subject.''
For the purposes of this study, Ricoeur puts "in parentheses" the unifYing
principle of chains of actions, that is, the "practical unities Of a higher order."
These include teclrniques, skilled crafts, arts, games, all of which order chains
of actions so that some actions ate understood as parts of higher-order actions. This means that at this point he willset aside ethical predicates that
evaluate actions, or chains of actions, as good, just, etc.
Action and agent belong to the same conceptual schema; this includes
concepts such as motive, circumstance, intention, deliberation, voluntary,
constraint, intended consequences, and so forth. The important thing is,
they form a coherent network such that one must understand how all of
them function and what they mean, in order to understand any one of them.
The network as a whole detetmines what will (1count as" an action. One way
of seeing this network is that it constitutes the list of questions that can be
asked of an agent about an action: when, under what circumstances, with
Ricoeur believes that analytic philosophy of action has created problems for
itself by focusing its discussion on the question of what will count as an
action among the events that lwppen in the world. This has led it to couple the
question "what?' with the question "why?" such that distinguishingbetween
an action and an event depends on the mode of explanation of the action
(the "why?"). "The use of 'why?' in the explanation of action thus becomes
the arbiter of the description of what counts as actions" (61).'
Ricoeur now looks at the analytic philosophy of action as it interprets the
meaning of "intention.'' The fundamental and guiding question of this view
ignorance or of constraint. Ricoeur claims that the main victim of this kind
of analysis is the dichotomy between reason for acting and cause. He says
that there is a whole spectrum of answers to "why?" and only at the far
extremes of the spectrUm do you find a pure opposition between reason and
cause. In the case of "backward-looking" motives such as vengeance, the line
between cause and reason is completely erased. He condudest ''But one can
see how fluid the border is between reason-for-acting, forward-looking motive, mental cause, and cause as such (a grimacing face made me jump). The
criterion of the question 'why?' is therefore firm; its application surprisingly
flexible" (69).
According to Ricoeur, the analytic philosophy of action has been preoccupied with the question "what-whyf' to the exclusion of the question "who?".
He says, "In my opinion, it is the exclusive concern with the tntth of the
description that tends to overshadow any interest in assigning the action to
its agent" (72). This is the same reason that analytic philosophy has neglected the sense of intention as '~intending~to''; the present intention to do
something in the futute. The dilemma is. that the rruth of such an intention
claim rests on the nonverifiable declaration of the agent, or leads to a theory
of internal mental events. For Ricoeur, only a pl~e."."_~'?l()~_()f".~t~~~~i~n
can account for "it>tenditlg-to.'' The criteriot> of I:!'IJ;b..)s not tbe verifiability
of a descriptio;;,-; but ilie~o~fiel.;nce in a testi!TI;;ny. Even a declared intention
belongs to the category ota-snare<Icontesslon-and not to the category of a
public description. In concll!sioli; meiniention-to,'' relegated to the third
rank by conceptual analysis of the type done by Anscombe, finds itself in the
first rank from the phenomenological perspective. This is because this seJ:lS.~
of itltenti<m is very close tothe .act of promisit)g.
In Ric~ur's first three chapters, the question "whor' was eclipsed by
semantic considerations of the pair "what/why?". In chapter 4, he returns to
the central focus of "who?", or the relation between the agent and the action. Earlier studies con~~nttated on distinguishing actions from events and
on the relationship between intentional explanations and causal explanations. In returning to the role of the agent, Ricoeur recalls the theses of
Srrawson discussed in his first chapter, and the linguistic act of as0Ptiotk
Strawson;s principal theses are that petS<)."'_.".re_':tJ;;g~c~p~-~;'c~fais''a.r'd.aL
12
n/
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
a~trib!.!ltoJ.l.9fPredi"~.te,~js_~>[persons or bodies; certain predicates are attributable l'r'rLt()!'~rs~s and tb.~y:-;;;.;-11:;;r reducihluo.51!l.Y. on~.arJID)'.set.o
predic:ate_s_attributablt; to bodies. Secondly, we attribute both body predicates
and person pt~il!~a_t_e_s_to_th~=;ame.Jhing,..thatis, .P~r~ 0ns. Finally, Il!~ntal
predicates-are-attributable to ourselves and others without haymg_a_Qiffi,rt;llt
()fl'.h~!~~.(>dies and to tha!_clf_f'".':S.()I!!, therefore lies at the point of articu.lation of the r;;wer to act which is ours and of the course of things which
belongs to the world order'' (111). So, the power of acting is rooted in a
ph~p.QmellOlogy-ofthe:'!.s_'!!}:' and the ontology of the "livec{~.J:<>ciy;;
__ mean.J_~g.
Tuffiing his attention to contemporary theory of action, Ricoeur wants to
show that ascription has a different meaning than attribution. Each term in
the network of action (what? why?), refers back to the who?. When we speak
of the action, we ask who did it. When ;;;.;~k for the motive, we refer
directly to the agent. Ricoeur notes that these inquiries are not symmetrical:
1
Ricoeur asks why contemporary philosophy of action has resisted any kind
of profound analysis of the relation between the action and the agent. He
gives two reasons: Much of th~ dlScu;sion is dominated by ,J'l ;;;.;;:~logy of
events {Davidson) and other analyses are dominated by an ontology of "things
in general" (Strawson).
Ricoeur rejects, however, the claim that moral or judicial imputation of
an action to an agent is merely a strong form of ascription. The first reason
by
NARRATIVE IDENTITY
Up to this point, Ricoeur limited his discussion to semantic and pragmatic
considerations of the theory of language and theory of action with respect to
the constitution of the self as self-desigoation and as agent of an action. At
the end of his analyses, he reintroduced the phenomenological concept of a
"lived body" as the intermediary between action and agent. All of this served
as a "propadeutic to the question of selfhood [ips&ti]" (113). In addition, the
whole problematic of personal identity has been omitted.
To tie these two themes together, considering the contemporary debates
in Anglo-American philosophy about personal identity, Ricoeur will introduce the dialectic between sameness (memeti) and seljhood (ipseiti) and the
central idea of narrative identity. Once he has been able to show the advantages of this narrative identity in resolving the paradoxes of the problem of
personal identity, he can finally tum to the thesis stated in his introduction,
"namely that narrative theory finds one of its major justifications in the role
it plays as a middle ground between the descriptive viewpoint on action, to
which we have confined ourselves until now, and the prescriptive viewpoint
which will prevail in the studies that follow. A triad has thus imposed itself
on my analysis: describe, narrate, prescribe--each moment of the triad im
plying a specific relation between the constitution of action and the constitution of the self' (114-115). Narrative already contains, even in its most
14
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
This leads to a third sense of identity, that of uninterrupted continuity between two stages of development of what we take to be the same individual.
This kind of identity overcomes the problem of a lack of sameness or similarity required in the qualitative sense of identity. Another sense is perma-
manence in time" (119). Ricoeur reminds us that he has dealt at length with
the concept of character in two of his previous works. In Freedom and Nature, character was seen as an absolutely permanent and involuntary aspect
of our experience (along with our birth and our unconscious) to which we
could, at most, consent. 10 It was the nonchosen perspective on our values
and our capabilities. In Fallible Man, character represented a finite restriction
on my openness to the world of things, ideas, values, and persons." In the
present work, Ricoeur wants to modify his view of character by situating it
within the dialectic of identity. What is at issue is the immutability of character, which he took as a given in his previous works. "Character, l would
say today, designates the set of lasting dispositions by which a person is
recognized" (121). Here, sameness is constitutive of selfhood.
But if identity in terms of sameness and identity in terms of selfhood find
convergence in the idea
will hold firm"' (124). So the dialectic of sameness and selfhood has two
poles~ character, where sameness and permanence of dispositions constitute
15
mediating concept.
His thesis is that the true nature of narrative identity is found only in the
dialectic of sameness and selfhood, and the dialectic itself is the main contribution of the narrative theoty to the constitution of the self. His arguments are in two steps: First, in an analysis of emplotment (mi!;e en intrigue/
along the same lines as we found in Time and Narrative, the construction of
a narrative plot integrates diversity, variability, and discontinuity into the
permanence in time. In short, it unifies elements that appear to be totally
disparate. Secondly, this same emplotment, transferred from action to. characters--characters in a narrative as distinct from "character" as a fundamen..-
16
CHARLES E. REAGAN
the term 'ethics' for the aim of an accomplished life and the term 'morality'
for the articulation of this aim in norms characterized at once by the claim
to universality and an effect of constraint {later I shall say what links these
two features together)" ( 170). From a historical point of view, we see the
ethical concern of Aristotle in the teleological interest in the "good life.'' The
moral point of view is found in Kant's deontology. In this chapter, Ricoeur
seeks to establish the primacy of ethics over morals, the necessity for the goal
of ethics to pass through the screen of norms (moral rules), and the recourse
of such norms to the ethical goal. "In other words, according to the working
hypothesis I am proposing, morality is held to constitute only a limited,
although .legitimate and even indispensable, actualization of the ethical aim,
and ethics in this sense would then encompass morality'' (I 70). But what is
the relation berween these tenns and selfhood? Ricoeur answers, "To the
PERSONAL IDENTITY
17
ethical aim will correspond what we shall henceforth call self-esteem, aod to
the deontological moment, self-respect" (171).
Ricoeur argues at length for the primacy of ethics over morals. But what
is the goal of ethics (visee ethiqw)? "Let us define 'ethical intention' ali aiming
at the 'good life' with and. for otlters,.mjust institutions" (172). The. "good life"
is the aim of ethics. If we distinguish between practices and a "life-plan," the
former are lower on the. scale than the latter and their integration is found
in. the nanative unity of a life. Jn this discussion, which is well centered on
Ari.srotle's Nicomachean Ethics,. there is a hierarchy in which practices, in
eluding professions, games, and art,. are subordinate to the idea of "the good
life."The linkage with self-esteem is the following: Our practices are defined
byconstrl.lctive rules aod standards of excellence.. In appreciating the excellence or success in our actions, we begin to appreciate ourselves as the author
of those actions. R.icoeur points out that "life" in the expression "good life"
does not have a biological .meaning .as much as. a social meaning that was
familiar t() the Gre.eks. They spoke of a "life of pleasure," a "political life,"
a "contemplative life," etc. For Ricoeur, "life" has this sense as well as the
notion of the rootedness of our lives in the biological sense of "to live."
Finally, it is in the narrative unity of a life that the estimations applied to
particular actions and the evaluation of pen;~ themselves are joined to
gether. In fact, Ricoeur claims that there is a sort of "hermeneutical circle"
between our Hves as a whole under the idea of the "good life," and our most
important particul~r choices; such as_ career1 spouse, leisure- pursuits, etc. But
this is not the 9nlY hermeneutical connection. "For the agent, Interpreting
the text of an action is interpreting himself or herself' (179). A bit further,
Ricoeur says, ''On the ethical plane, self-interpretation becomes self-esteem.
In return, self-esteem follows the fate of interpretation" ( 179 );
If the "good life" is the goalof erhiq, it. is lived with aod for others. This
becomes the b.asis for the second part of Ricoeut's reflection o.n ethics.. He
designates this concern for the other as solicittk. It is not something added
to self-esteem from the outside but is l!ll internal, dialogical dimension "such
that self-esteem and. solicitude cannot be eJ<perlenced or reflected upon one
without the other" (180). Self-esteem is not founded on accomplishment,
but on capacity; the ability to judge (to esteem) Is based on the ability to act
(le pouvoir-faire). "The question is then whether the mediation of the other
is not required along the route from capacity to realization'' (181). The
importance of this question is found in certain political theories in which
individuals have rights independently of any social connections and the role
of the state is relegated to protecting antecedently existing rights. According
to Ricoeur, this view rests on. a misunderstaoding of the role of the other as
19
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
structures that extend beyond simple interpersonal relations but are bound
up with the latter through their function of the distribution of roles, responsibilities, privileges, goods, and rewards. Ricoeur asks if justice is found on
the level of ethics and teleology or, as Rawls and Kant would have it, only
on the deontological level of morals. Ricoeur's own answer is that justice has
two sides: the side of the good which is an extension of interpersonal relations, and the legal side where it implies a judicial system of coherent laws.
He is concerned in this chapter with the first sense or aspect of justice.
But what is the relation between the institution, as an abstract organization of distribution of goods and burdens, and the individuals who make up
18
the latter governs institutions and the former interpersonal relations" ( 184).
Equality is presupposed in our relations of friendship, while it is a goal to be
achieved in our political institutions. Ricoeur thus takes from Aristotle "the
ethics of reciprocity, of sharing, of living together" (187). Self-esteem is the
reflexive moment of the goal of the good life, while the relation between the
self and the other is characterized by solicitude, which is based on the exchange of giving and receiving. For Ricoeur, this shows the primacy of the
ethical goal of the good life, including solicitude for the other, over the
moral claims of obligation. As he says, friendship involves reciprocity, while
the moral injunction is asymmetrical.
distribution transcends the terms of the opposition. The institution as regulation of the distribution of roles, hence as a system, is indeed something
more and scmething other than the individuals who play those roles.... An
institution considered as a rule of distribution exists only to the extent that
individuals take part in it" (200). Distributive justice is not a matter of mere
arithmetical equality among individuals but a propordona[ equality which
relates merit to each individual. In conclusion, Ricoeur says that justice adds
equality to solicitude and its range is all humanity rather than interperscnal
relations. This is why he adds 11 in just institutions" to our ethical pursuit of
the '(good lifen lived ''with and for others. 11
21
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
20
22
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
(1) We can see how the attempt to give a purely procedural foundation for
strict and easy: Only that which serves the city is good, that whic.h harl!l,S
it is evil. But Antigone is driven by the conviction that she is obliged, by
unwritten laws, to provide a decent burial for her brother. Ricoeur says; "But
in invoking them [the unwritten laws] to found her intimate conviction, she
posited the limit that points up to human, all too human, character of every
institution" (245). It is just such a limit thatleads to ethics being instrUcted
by tragedy. Once again, Ricoeur's thesis is that the dialectic of ethics. and
morality is played out in the moral judgment in particular situations.
Moral formalism, in Kant's sense, is forced .to rely. on the intuition of
ethics in three areas already discussed: the universal self, the plurality of
persons, and the institutional environment. Ricoeur now takes these three
areas up again in reverse order, beginning with institutions. In the preceding
chapter, he had already shown the possibility of conflict inherent in the idea
of justice as a "just distribution.'! In short, it_is the diversity o contributions,
whether individual or collective, that raises the problem of a just distribution
of rights, roles, responsibilities, and goods. This problem had led Aristotle to
his idea of "proportional justice." The importance of Institutions for this
solution is clear: Referring to his seventh study, Ricoeur says, "We then
admitted that it was only in a specific institutional milieu that the capacities
and predispositions that distinguish human action can blossom;. the individual, we said then, becomes human only under the condition of certain
institutions; and we added: if this is so, the obligation to serve these institutions is itself a condition for the human agent to continue to develop"
(254--255). Now, the political state is the set of practices organized around
the distribution of power and domination. "Democracy," says Ricoeur, (jis not
a political system without conllicts but a system in which conflicts are open
and negotiable in accordance with recognized rules of arbitration" (258}. In
response to the "crisis of legitimacy" of certain political institutions, he calls
for the public recognition of traditions that .make a place for tolerance and
pluralism, "not out of concessions to extern~l- pressures, but out of inner
conviction, even if this is late in coming'' (261).
Ricoeur next considers the possibility of conflicts imbedded in the very
nature of the second version of Kant's categorical imperative~ the universfd~
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAl IDENTITY
In order to argue for this thesis, Ricoeur says that we must first make an
extended revision to Kantian formalism that will clearly show the universalist claim and will shatpen as much as possible its conflict with contextualism.
He will make this revision in three steps: {l) Question the priority Kant
gives to the principle of autonomy with respect to the plurality of individuals
and the principle of justice as applied to institutions. Ricoeur thinks that the
principle of autonomy should be at the end of the series, not at the beginning. (2) Question the restrictive use Kant makes of the criterion of univer
salization. According to Ricoeur, this criterion is very impoverished since it
is limited to noncontradiction and ignores the idea of the coherence of a
moral system. Such a coherence shows that such a formalism is not vacuous,
in the sense that a. whole series of moral obligations or rules can be derived
from the single principle requiring respect for others; furthermore, these
moral obligations are mutually coherent and not conlltcrual among them
selves. Finally, these rules are such that inferior rules are coherent with
superior rules. (3) Finally, Kant's formalism lies on the retrospective path of
just(fication, while the real conflicts atise in the prospective direction of deriving
judgments from rules and rules from prirtciples, that is, in the application of
universal principles to concrete cases. In sum, Ricoeur's goal is to show both
the credibility of the demand fur universalization and the contextual chat
acter of the application of moral rules.
It is, he says, the job of political practice to deal with this conflict and
these perplexities. He seeks moreover to underline the importance of the
hisr:midty of these political choices.
Next, if we move from the political level t<l the level of interpersonal
relations, a new dichotomy or conflict arises: the otherness (altbiti) of individuals is opposed to the unitary aspect of the concept of humanity. There
is a schism, between respect for the law and respect for persons. In short,
there is again a conflict between urtiversalism and contexrualism.(if we have
a concept of justice that is purely procedural, an e_i.~Q[!!t~ can
resolve the conflicts:)ut is the situation the same with the ptinciple of
respect for persons? Is resorting to developmental biology to decide whether
the fetus is a person, a thing, or something intermediary not similar to
looking for the best arguments in a debate ovet the righrs of the fetus? Ricoeur
accepts this thesis, but only t<l a certain point. He is in favor of contextualist
explanatinns but objects strenuously to uan apology of difference for the sake
of difference which, finally,. makes all differences i11different,. to the extent
that lt makes all discussiort useless" (286). In other words, what Ricoeur
rejects in an ethic& of atgumentation {representing the demand for universalization) is not the taking into account of circumstances in consttttcting the
best argument, but its attempt at purificatiDn. Kant wanted to purify all moral
24
26
27
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
arguments from any kind of inclination, desire, pleasure, happiness, etc., and
tion of these rules to difficult particular cases calls for an appeal to the
ultimate telos of morality.
The dialectic between ethics as the teleological goal of "a good life lived
with others in just institutions" and a morality of universal rules finds its
mediation in "practical wisdom." This wisdom is precisely the application of
moral rules to particular cases where a "conflict of convictionsn is tempered
by an ethics of argumentation. In his moral theory, Ricoeur replaces the
"conflict of interpretations" of his hermeneutics with a conflict of convic. .
28
CHARLES E. REAGAN
PERSONAL IDENTITY
29
tenus ofa.dialectic of action .and affection. In the dialec.tic between the self
and the .ather, ;itis thefaee ofthe0thenthat.appears to me .and says, "Thou
shalt ,not kill." Jt js .the . ather wh<> ce<>nstitutes me as re~onsible, !hat !is,
[email protected] answei.ing. ''In :tliisway, the w<>td-.of :the other .comes to .be:p!aced
at .the "!gin .oLmy ,ac.ti" (336). :Sq, ~elf,de;sjgnadon :which imputes :moral
.respomibiliey ,fur mY :acts to ;me thas its oiigin :outside .of :the self.
The next;pl!)les are:a l:lebate:.hetw.een'Kant:anl:ll.evinas. ''Kant :pursre$p.ect
for -the :law .Rbove tegpectfor :otherpersons; ltevinassays ;that :the .face .<lf:the
other singlilarize :the .commandment. To .he ;effective, !however, &he veice.of
.the other:must'.become;nty\Vdice;fuis .oommandmUMibecomemy:c.mn~iction.
This l:lialeellic :between ;the ..elf ;and ,the :other :was :lllready anticipated -in
Ricoeur's ,discussion .of promising: "'!.If . another 'W.ete :not counmng .on me,
would I .be .capable '"fikeef)ing .my word, df :maintaining myself?" ;(34lj.
Ricoeur says that amongihe most suwect iiaeas are ihose ,_Of, the "!bad" :or
'rgood" :consCience. A -,discussion ,of :c0nsdie:nc~ -will ;giv 1'him, lhe ~-sa)% --a
perfect opportunity cto put :to :the ctest Jiis thesis :that ':attestation of S<!llhood
is inseparable ifrom.an .exercise ofsuspiciioti" .(341.').liv.en if .we .overcome :.the
distinction ;between "\good" .and '!bad" c<Jns.Cienae, .WI'! must still :ileal .with
phenomena Hf it)junaiion .1ll1il .debt . whiCh . are ingniined .in >.the .idea .of .conscience. There.are three . challenges .to .overcome in:order :to rescue ,the .concept .of consCience :from :NietzSri:he's :attaCk.
Hrst;cluillenge. 1'he i.conscienceiscfhe ,place where illusions ~boutoneselfare
mixed with the :ttuth,of attestation. Afrer.an.<>xtended :discussi<mofil\liet2S<Ohes
analyses . ofthe concept.ofcenscienc.e, Ricoeur '5ll)'S :that.the furce ofl\lierzsche's
method . of suspicion:is .that, all conscience is ':bad .conscience." The trap, says
Ricoeur, is.the.danger ofa;newdogmatism.Jn.order'to return to the id.ea of
conscience) we- musnibandan ,fue -.ideas Of'~-good" -and-'\bad" ._consCience and .go
back to a kind of nonmoral suspicion ,which .is the;or.h.edace oaf attestation.
Second challenge. "What 'happens .when We '~de-moralize" .tbe conscience?
How do we keep .from falling back into the ;trap of good" and "bad" consdence?Ricoeursays, "A,;emark.made.earlier.withrespect to.the.metaphor of
the court.puts US\On the rjght;path. :Is it.,not 'because the stage ofmorality has
been dissociated from the .tiiad .ethics-moralityconviction, .then hypostasized
because ,of this .dissociation, that ;the phenomenon of c<>nscience 'has been
correlativelyimpoverished and the revealing metaphor of.the voice has been
eclipsed by the stitling metaphor ofthe court:r' (351>). Ricoeur says that the
first injliD.ction is a call tolivewell with and for others in justinstitutions. It
is because violence can spoil all of our interpersonal relationships that we have
the law or interdiction "Thou shalt not kill." Violence causes a short circuit
and the voice of conscience becomes the verdict of a court. We need to take
the reverse path, from interdiction-verdict to the injunction to live well.
CHARLES E. REAGAN
TJ~ir;d chalierl!le The otherness of the conscience can be fout1d in the
NOTES
I.
2.
3.
page
PERSONAL IDENTITY
31