African Ubuntu Philosophy David Lutz
African Ubuntu Philosophy David Lutz
African Ubuntu Philosophy David Lutz
1. Introduction
Our globalising world needs a theory of ethical global management that is consistent with our
common human nature. All management theories that maintain that the purpose of business
management is maximisation of owner wealth must be rejected, because some owner-wealthmaximising actions are unethical. Furthermore, we should reject all theories of business ethics
and corporate governance that are rooted in individualistic philosophical systems, including
social-contract and stakeholder theories, because they attempt to correct the errors of ownerwealth-maximisation theories without addressing the philosophical root of the problem: individualism. Since we human persons are naturally communal, not individualistic, and since all
traditional cultures are communal cultures, the place to begin developing the needed theory of
ethical global management is the philosophy of traditional cultures in all regions of the world.
The ubuntu philosophy of Africa can make a significant contribution to the requisite theory
of ethical global management, because it correctly understands that we are truly human only in
community with other persons. Moreover, since all human persons share the same human nature, we find substantial agreement between traditional African and traditional non-African
philosophy. Within the limitations of this paper, two other philosophical traditions will be
considered briefly, the Confucian tradition of Asia and the Platonic-Aristotelian tradition of
Europe.
2. Ubuntu Philosophy
One of the most striking features of the cultures of sub-Saharan Africa is their nonindividualistic character: Although African cultures display awesome diversity, they also show
remarkable similarities. Community is the cornerstone in African thought and life.1 An African
is not a rugged individual, but a person within a community. In the words of John Mbiti, I am,
because we are; and since we are, therefore I am.2 Or, as Yusufu Turaki puts it: People are not
individuals, living in a state of independence, but part of a community, living in relationships
and interdependence.3
The communal character of African culture does not mean, however, that the good of the individual person is subordinated to that of the group, as is the case with Marxist collectivism. In
a true community, the individual does not pursue the common good instead of his or her own
good, but rather pursues his or her own good by pursuing the common good. The ethics of a true
community does not ask persons to sacrifice their own good in order to promote the good of
others, but instead to recognise that they can attain their own true good only by promoting the
good of others. Obiora Ike and Ndidi Nnoli Edozien explain this by describing the structure of
Igbo society:
The Igbo social structure consists of many small local communities. Within the village itself,
power is held by various groups, and social balance is maintained by a system of checks and
balances. Igbo society was such that even though there existed a strong community consciousness, the individuals rights and existence as an entity were not neglected. Free speech,
free movement and free action in Igbo society were guaranteed.4
And Kwame Gyekye makes the same point in interpreting an Akan proverb:
The clan is like a cluster of trees which, when seen from afar, appear huddled together, but
which would be seen to stand individually when closely approached. ... The proverb stresses
the social reality of the individual; it expresses the idea that the individual has a separate iden-
tity and that, like the tree, some of whose branches may touch other trees, the individual is
separately rooted and is not completely absorbed by the cluster. That is, communality does
not obliterate or squeeze out individuality.5
In southern Africa, the traditional understanding that one is truly human only as a member of a
community is expressed in terms of ubuntu. In the words of Mogobe Ramose, Ubuntu is
simultaneously the foundation and the edifice of African philosophy.6 According to Richard
Tambulasi and Happy Kayuni, Ubuntu is the basis of African communal cultural life.7 And
Jabulani Sithole writes, Ubuntu functions as a unifying factor, bringing people together regardless of their background or access to wealth.8
The word ubuntu belongs to the Nguni group of languages, and has cognates in other Bantu
languages. It can best be translated into English as humanness, or being human.9 As Desmond
Tutu explains:
Ubuntu is very difficult to render into a Western language. It speaks of the very essence of being human. When we want to give high praise to someone we say, Yu, u nobuntu; Hey, he
or she has ubuntu. This means they are generous, hospitable, friendly, caring and compassionate. They share what they have. It also means my humanity is caught up, is inextricably
bound up, in theirs. We belong in a bundle of life.10
As is the case with traditional ethics elsewhere, traditional African ethics is virtue ethics. In the
words of Joseph Nyasani: Virtues like patience, optimism, mutual sympathy and empathy are
eminently characteristic of the African way of life and certainly point to a peculiar mode of
existence that extends the realm of the individual potentialities to embrace the life of others and
their concerns.11 And Wendy Luhabe writes:
Our own African culture taught us concepts such as respect, trust, compassion and, above all,
that we are a collective with the success of one person depending very much on the success of
all. This is a concept widely refereed to as ubuntu or umntu ngumntu ngabanye (what
makes us human is our recognition of the humanity in others).12
Metz rejects U4, probably the dominant interpretation of African ethics in the literature, and
accepts U6 as the most promising theoretical formulation of an African ethic to be found in the
literature.15 U6 is better, he argues, because U4 roots ethics in the good of the agent, while U6
roots it in the good of other persons:
If I ask why I should help others, for example, [U4] says that the basic justificatory reason to
do so (though not my proper motive for doing so) is that it will help me by making me more
of a mensch or a better person. However, a better fundamental explanation of why I ought to
help others appeals not to the fact that it would be good for me, or at least not merely to this
fact, but to the fact that it would (likely) be good for them, an explanation that a selfrealization ethic by definition cannot invoke.16
Metz comments further, The idea that interpersonal relationships of some kinds have basic
moral status is not often found in Anglo-American or Continental normative theory.17 That is
certainly correct. If we consider traditional European normative theory, however, the case is
different. Aristotles ethics is both a theory of self-realisation and a theory of interpersonal
2
relationships, without contradiction. The Aristotelian virtues are perfections of the self that
involve relating with others.
Modern European moral philosophy assumes what Henry Sidgwick calls the dualism of
practical reason18 and C. S. Lewis calls the philosophy of hell19: the idea that one persons
good is separate from anothers. For the leading ancient and mediaeval moral philosophers, in
contrast, the common good is my good. An analogy may be helpful: In a true football team, as
distinguished from a collection of athletes wearing the same uniform, a player does not have to
choose between doing what is best for himself and doing is best for his team. Contributing to
the success of the team is simultaneously good for himself.
Aristotle is making the same point, I believe, when he says, The excellent person is related
to his friend in the same way as he is related to himself, since a friend is another himself.20
Moreover, explanations of ubuntu agree that we attain self-realisation through interpersonal
relationships. Lovemore Mbigi tells us, I cannot separate my humanity from the humanity of
those around me.21 In the words of Fred Luthans, et al., Under Ubuntu there is an individual
existence of the self and the simultaneous existence for others.22 And Augustine Shutte writes,
I only become fully human to the extent that I am included in relationships with others.23
Significantly, Aristotles argument that self-sacrifice is an act of self-love depends, not upon
reward after death, but upon a distinction between lower-order and higher-order goods: The
excellent person labours for his friends and for his native country, and will die for them if he
must; he will sacrifice money, honours and contested goods in general, in achieving what is fine
for himself.24 Aristotles ethics is not supernatural, but it is super-material. If material goods
were the only goods, then one persons good would continually conflict with the good of others.
If, however, non-material goods exist, then it is possible to reconcile the ethics of selfrealisation and the ethics of interpersonal relationships.
Scholars of ubuntu are in agreement that it recognises non-material goods. Shutte tells us that
the idea of ubuntu differs from the materialist view of the world and persons that is the dominant one in our scientific culture.25 According to Shepherd Shonhiwa, African life emphasises
humanity and relationships over material wealth.26 And Mbigi writes: The hallmark of Afrocentric philosophy is about being a good community member. It is also about living and enjoying life rather than the acquisition of the material creature comforts of life.27
Consequently, it is possible to interpret umuntu ngumuntu ngabantu, a person is a person
through other persons, in such a way that both U4 and U6 are true. The actions that produce
harmony, reduce discord and develop community are simultaneously the actions that perfect
ones valuable nature as a social being.
Reconciling self-realisation and communalism is important, because it solves the problem of
moral motivation. Modern Western ethical theories are confronted with, but have difficulty
answering, the question: Why should I be ethical (if doing so is not good for me)? If, however, I
understand that benefiting other persons is also good for me (even when, in the extreme, it leads
to my death), then I automatically have a motive to act ethically.
4. Ubuntu Management
The authors experience of teaching in several African universities, noting the textbooks used in
other African universities, participating in conferences, seminars and workshops in various
African countries, and communicating with and reading the publications of business scholars
from additional African countries suggests that there is a discrepancy between traditional African cultures and African business education, most of which is indistinguishable in theoretical
content from Anglo-American business education. Theories that were created within and for
individualistic cultures are not at home within communal cultures. African managers need a
management theory that is consistent with their communal cultures.
The first step in developing the requisite theory of African business management, based
upon the philosophy of ubuntu, is to recognise the firm as a community, not a collection of
individuals. As Luchien Karsten and Honorine Illa point out, Ubuntu provides a strong philosophical base for the community concept of management.28 And Dean McFarlin, et al. write
that African management philosophy views the corporation as a community and can be
summed up in one word ubuntu.29
When the firm is understood as a community, the purpose of management is neither to benefit one collection of individuals, as shareholder-value-maximisation theories claim, nor to benefit several collections of individuals, as stakeholder theories tell us, but to benefit the community, as well as the larger communities of which it is a part. In most African business schools,
the doctrine that shareholder-value-maximisation is the goal of management is assumed as
axiomatic. In addition to being unethical, this doctrine contradicts African cultures: A new
culture for enterprises is needed. This culture is about striving for decent survival and working
towards profit-making, but not striving for the greatest profit at all costs, especially not at the
exploitation of human beings, in order to attain goals characterised by greed and selfishness.30
To promote the good of a community is to promote the good of all its members: The underlying tenet of Afrocentric leadership is collectivism. This notion refers to communalism, or
living collectively, with the objective to ensure that no one falls too far behind anyone else.31
Shareholder-value theories, social-contract theories and stakeholder theories agree with one
another that the objective of business is to promote the good of individuals; they disagree only
concerning which individuals should be benefited. All three sets of theories are fundamentally at
odds with theories that understand the purpose of management to be promoting the good of the
community: Collectivism associated with harmony and cooperation means working for the
benefit of the whole, based on a long-term vision, rather than the benefit of constantly changing
individuals.32
African management theory can, of course, borrow from the West. Anglo-American management theories contain some truths that are universal. There is, however, need to discriminate
between theoretical elements that can enrich a management theory based on ubuntu philosophy
and elements that cannot:
The concept of Ubuntu emphasises the need to harness the solidarity tendency of the African
people in developing management practices and approaches. It is important for us to adopt
some Western and Eastern management techniques, but these will only enable African organisations to attain competitive parity.33
Although any management theory based on ubuntu philosophy must include the role of the
ubuntu virtues, there is no canonical listing of these virtues. Johann Broodryk identifies five
virtues or core values humanness, caring, sharing, respect and compassion each of which
has several associated values.34 Other authors identify other virtues. There is work to be done
in identifying the virtues of ubuntu management and determining how they relate to the real
world of African business.
Peter Drucker wrote in 1982 that the only philosophical traditions capable of serving as philosophies of management are the Confucian ethics of interdependence and the Aristotelian ethics
of prudence and self-development.38 Perhaps he can be excused for not including the African
ethics of ubuntu, on the grounds that no one had introduced him to it. In any event, a brief look
at the traditional philosophies of China and Greece reveals that they have much in common with
traditional African philosophy that is relevant to the philosophy of business management.
5.1. Confucian Management
Confucianism, which is not a religion but a humanistic philosophy, 39 influences Chinese
business today:
Although the Confucian system is not now in official vogue in China, the influence is still felt
in many facets of Chinese life. For the business person expecting to trade with China, an understanding of this system is essential. Confucianism is so ingrained after 2,000 years that it
cannot be ignored. It still forms the basis of most business practices in China.40
This passage may exaggerate somewhat the influence of Confucianism in contemporary Chinese business. Buddhism and Western capitalism are also significant influences. Nevertheless,
Confucianism has had a strong influence on Chinese culture in the past, is growing in popularity
in China today, and has the potential to make the practice of Chinese business more humane.
In traditional Chinese ethics, as in traditional African ethics, the institution of the family is
central: For Confucius, the family, hierarchically ordered, was the unit of society.41 Confucian
ethics is also virtue ethics. One translator of Confuciuss Analects renders the Confucian virtues
as humaneness (ren) an over-arching, all-encompassing virtue virtue (de), loyalty (zhong),
filial piety (xiao), good faith (xin), rightness (yi), reciprocity (shu), deference (rang), courage
(yong) and goodness (shan).42
According to Kam-hon Lee, Confucian ethics applied to business manifests itself in:
being sincere towards others (i.e. no deception and always seeking for mutual benefits);
being trustworthy in handling transactions (i.e. treasuring ones credibility);
taking righteousness as profits (i.e. treasuring righteousness more than profitability); and
being grounded on kindness (i.e. being kind to others and not taking advantages when
others are having crises).43
Confucianism forms the philosophical foundation of not only Chinese culture, but also the
cultures of Japan, Korea, Vietnam, Singapore and other East Asian nations: The virtues
stressed [by Confucianism] are fundamental for China and the Far East generally.44 The case of
Japan, the worlds second-largest national economy, is significant. The Japanese adopted technology from the West, formed business corporations consistent with their own traditional culture, and soon produced industrial goods of higher quality and at lower cost than Western companies: Japans example should be important for Africa, because it shows that modernization
need not mean Westernization. Developing countries need to learn from developed ones, but
they do not have to abandon their culture and traditions in the process.45
It should be noted that the economic empire that China is now building in Africa has more to
do with Adam Smith than with Confucius: The reasoning behind Chinas new focus on Africa
is simple. If its economic boom is to be sustained, Beijing must find more raw materials and
new markets for manufactured goods.46 The primary purpose of an empire is to enrich the
mother country at the expense of the colonies. In the past, most empires were built by first
conquering and then governing foreign lands. Since the middle of the twentieth century, following the collapse of the European empires and widespread condemnation of colonialism, imperial
strategy has shifted towards neo-colonialist domination of the economy of a foreign land, without political governance: With every day that passes, Chinas economic tentacles extend
deeper into Africa. While Europe sought direct political control, China is acquiring a vast and
informal economic empire.47
Confucian business management is partly a present reality and partly a legacy to be
claimed. Within China, Confucianism was suppressed during the Cultural Revolution, but is
regaining popularity today. It is also influential in other Asian nations. Insofar as it is a tradition
of communities and virtues, it is similar to traditional African and European traditions.
5.2. Platonic-Aristotelian Management
Much has been written about the differences between African and European philosophy. If one
compares traditional African philosophy with modern European philosophy, the contrast is,
indeed, striking. If one compares traditional African philosophy with traditional European
philosophy, however, the differences diminish.
In what is sometimes called the perennial philosophy, the mainstream of Western philosophy from the ancient Greek and Roman philosophers, through the mediaeval philosophers, and
continuing until it was rejected by the leading European philosophers during the Enlightenment,
it was understood that the city belongs among the things that exist by nature, and that man is
by nature a political [communal] animal.48 In other words, it is natural for human persons to
live in community with other human persons. Furthermore, traditional Western ethics is about
acquiring certain excellent habits and character traits. According to Plato, the chief of these
virtues are justice, moderation, courage and wisdom.49 Aristotle distinguished theoretical and
practical wisdom, and the latter came to be known as prudence, from the Latin prudentia. The
Western tradition also gained the concept of natural law from the Roman stoic Cicero, and was
simultaneously teleological and deontological, without inconsistency.
Among the early-modern European philosophers who rejected the perennial philosophy was
Thomas Hobbes. And, in order to understand the change that took place, one must understand
that the fundamental error of Hobbesian ethics is not egoism, as is commonly alleged, but
individualism. Within the tradition that Hobbes rejected, to pursue ones own true good is
ethical. When Socrates and Thrasymachus argue in Platos Republic about the advantageousness
of justice, it is Thrasymachus who asserts that the just is really anothers good and Socrates
(speaking for Plato) who maintains that it is better in every way [for the agent] to be just than
unjust.50 Hobbes innovation is not egoism, but the belief that the natural condition of mankind is solitary.51
As long as it is understood that ones own good is inseparable from the good of the community, egoism, or the pursuit of ones own true good, is altruistic. When persons are understood
as having interests independently of any community, however, we have conflict between my
interest and yours. After listing nineteen non-egoistic laws of nature, Hobbes tells us that a man
has no more to do in learning the laws of nature, but, when weighing the actions of other men
with his own, they seem too heavy, to put them into the other part of the balance, and his own
into their place, that his own passions, and self-love, may add nothing to the weight.52 Self-love
is now in conflict with natural law. If we understand egoism as the claim that acting ethically
is good for the agent, then Hobbesian ethics, like most of modern moral philosophy, is nonegoistic.
Ethical theories that tell us we must choose between egoism and altruism, between self-love
and love of others, between prudence and morality, or between ones own good and the common good are individualistic ethical theories. Not only theories of shareholder-valuemaximisation in business management, but also social-contract theories and stakeholder theories
in business ethics, are rooted in the individualistic philosophy of Hobbes. And, while many
writers have argued that the economics of Adam Smith must not be unethical, because he also
wrote a book on moral philosophy, one should note that his ethical theory is Hobbesian insofar
as it includes a separation of private and public interest: The wise and virtuous man is at all
times willing that his own private interest should be sacrificed to the public interest of his own
particular order or society.53 Smiths analysis of self-sacrifice could not be more different from
Aristotles.
Relatively little has been accomplished thus far in applying traditional Western philosophy
to business. Nevertheless, one can readily see the relevance of the four cardinal virtues to the
practice of management. The distinctive characteristic of the management profession is decision-making, and prudence is the virtue of the decision-maker. Aristotles sub-virtues of distributive, commutative and legal justice are required by any manager seeking to promote the
common good. Fortitude is required by managers who must make correct decisions in situations
where the consequences of doing so could be unpleasant. And temperance, especially its subordinate virtue humility, is required by the manager who is tempted to place too much confidence
in his or her own judgment, rather than seeking the counsel of subordinates.
Mbigi identifies ubuntu with the Western philosophical concept of solidarity: The concept
of Ubuntu ... is the collective solidarity of the poor on survival issues.54 Karol Wojtyla defines
solidarity as a firm and persevering determination to commit oneself to the common good; that
is to say, to the good of all and of each individual, because we are all really responsible for
all.55 The application of the solidarity to business involves understanding business firms, not as
legal fictions that serve as a nexus for a set of contracting relationships among individuals56
but as communities: A good business is a community with a purpose.57 And, when the firm is
understood as a community, the purpose of management is to promote the good of the community, the common good.
It is true, of course, that Plato and Aristotle did not write about communities the size of
ExxonMobil or Wal-Mart. In order to understand the large, multinational corporation as a
community, we need solidaritys twin subsidiarity, the principle that each social and political
group should help smaller or more local ones accomplish their respective ends without, however, arrogating those tasks to itself.58 According to subsidiarity, management should be decentralised. We should attempt to promote the common good at higher levels only when it is impossible to do so at lower levels in the organisation.
When Aristotle writes that in the case of the depraved, or those in a depraved condition, the
body is often held to rule the soul on account of their being in a condition that is bad and unnatural, he means neither that this condition is miraculous, nor that it is rare and unusual, nor
that it is artificial. He means that it is defective and, therefore, not conducive to human fulfilment. Hume failed to demonstrate that understanding virtue as natural and vice as unnatural is
erroneous. His Treatise on Human Nature was in fact one step towards the belief, popular today,
that there is no such thing as human nature.
To criticise Hume is not to demonstrate that ethics can be derived from our common human
nature. To the objection that doing so is problematic, the appropriate response is to acknowledge
that it is, but then to point out that deriving ethics from any other source is also problematic. Let
us consider briefly the two favorite philosophers of business ethics64: Immanuel Kant and
John Stuart Mill.
Kant rejected human nature as the starting point for moral philosophy and attempted to derive from pure practical reason an ethical theory that would be valid not merely for men but for
all rational beings generally.65 He criticises his predecessors for failing to ask whether the
principles of morality are to be sought at all in the knowledge of human nature.66 The metaphysics of morals must be completely isolated . . . not mixed with any anthropology.67 Nevertheless, in his resulting ethical theory, a central role is played by the concept of the will, which
belongs to some but not other theories of human nature. Furthermore, Kants ethical theory is
notoriously incapable of distinguishing ethical from unethical actions: It is very easy to see that
many immoral and trivial non-moral maxims are vindicated by Kants test quite as convincingly
in some cases more convincingly than the moral maxims which Kant aspires to uphold.68
Mills attempt to derive ethics from human experience contains a classic example of fallacious reasoning: If an object is seen, then it is visible; if a sound is heard, then it is audible;
therefore, if anything is desired, then it is desirable.69 His principle of utility is no more capable
of distinguishing ethical from unethical actions than is Kants categorical imperative. According
to utilitarianism, as John Rawls makes the point, there is no reason in principle why the greater
gains of some should not compensate for the lesser losses of others; or more importantly, why
the violation of the liberty of a few might not be made right by the greater good shared by
many.70
To paraphrase Winston Churchills assessment of democracy, deriving ethics from a common human nature is the worst approach, except for all those other approaches that have been
tried from time to time.71 All attempts to derive an ethical theory are encounter enormous problems. The most significant difference between the tradition of natural law and human virtues
and the ethical theories that are popular today is that the former, together with its accompanying
anthropology, were rejected by the mainstream of Western philosophy during the Enlightenment
though not on the basis of sound arguments.
Placing the perceived interests of relatives and members of ones ethnic group before that of the
community is, though common, a corruption of ubuntu. Tribalism is ethically equivalent to
racism; both involve denying others their due because they differ from us in some morally
irrelevant respect. It is in the true interest of each of the members of a true community to recruit
and promote on the basis of merit. Furthermore, this is a necessary condition for African business to become competitive with the rest of the world.
Another problem with defective communalism is groupthink73:
The disadvantage of collectivism is that it prevents individuals from acting without group
consensus. One observes that in organizations, alliances (sub-groups) are formed within the
larger group. Members of the alliances find themselves compelled to adopt the position taken
by the sub-group. In this situation, it is difficult for individuals to act independently regardless
of what their personal positions may be. Obviously, this practice can lead to frustration in the
process of negotiation, initiating change, or expansion. It may also be time-consuming and
inefficient.74
The antidote is leadership that creates an environment in which community members are permitted to disagree with other group members. Communalism is about commonality of interests,
not commonality of opinions. Deciding how best to promote the common good requires listening to differing ideas about how best to promote it.
A third, closely-related vice is the discouragement of individual initiative:
In Malawi, as in other East and Central African communities, tradition places social achievement above personal achievement. ... One often hears, Akhufuna akhale ndani! (What does
he/she want to be?) and Akudziyesa kuti ndi ndani (Who does he/she think he/she is?).
These commonly heard phrases signal social disapproval of the individual who places himself/herself above his or her fellow human beings, for example, through self-promotion in
business or at work.75
A distinction must be made here between unethical self-promotion, which benefits no one, and
ethical self-promotion, which promotes both the individual and the community. Seeking a
promotion through sycophancy, for example, benefits no one. But every society benefits from
people who excel in order to promote the common good. Aristotles analysis of the difference
between vicious and virtuous self-love76 is helpful here.
Notes
1
Lovemore Mbigi, The Spirit of African Leadership (Randburg: Knowres, 2005), p. 75.
John S. Mbiti, African Religions and Philosophy (Nairobi: East African Educational Publishers, 1969),
pp. 108-109.
3
Yusufu Turaki, Foundations of African Traditional Religion and Worldview (Nairobi: WordAlive
Publishers, 2006), p. 36.
4
Obiora F. Ike & Ndidi Nnoli Edozien, Understanding Africa: Traditional Legal Reasoning, Jurisprudence and Justice in Igboland (Enugu: CIDJAP Publications, 2001), p. 155.
5
Kwame Gyekye, The Unexamined Life: Philosophy and the African Experience (Accra: Sankofa, 1996),
p. 32.
6
Mogobe B. Ramose, African Philosophy through Ubuntu (Harare: Mond Books, 1999), p. 49.
7
Richard Tambulasi & Happy Kayuni, Can African Feet Divorce Western Shoes? The Case of Ubuntu
and Democratic Good Governance in Malawi, Nordic Journal of African Studies, Vol. 14, No. 2 (2005),
p. 147.
8
Jabulani Sithole, Africa Can Only Use Own Culture to Influence Globalization, afrol News, 15 May
2001, http://www.afrol.com/html/News2001/afr020_culture_econ.htm.
9
Reuel J. Khoza, Let Africa Lead: African Transformational Leadership for 21st Century Business
(Johannesburg: Vezubuntu, 2006), p. 6.
10
Desmond Mpilo Tutu, No Future without Forgiveness (London: Rider, 1999), pp. 34-35.
11
Joseph M. Nyasani, The Ontological Significance of I and We in African Philosophy, in I, We and
Body: First Joint Symposium of Philosophers from Africa and from the Netherlands, ed. Heinz Kimmerle
(Amsterdam: B. R. Grner, 1989), p. 9.
12
Wendy Luhabe, Defining Moments: Experiences of Black Executives in South Africas Workplace
(Pietermaritzburg: University of Natal Press, 2002), p. 103.
13
Ubuntu, and Other Management Tips, The Economist, Vol. 334, No. 7906 (18 March 1995), p. 68.
14
Thaddeus Metz, Toward an African Moral Theory, The Journal of Political Philosophy, Vol. 15, No.
3 (2007), pp. 331, 334.
15
Ibid.
16
Ibid., p. 332.
17
Ibid., p. 333.
18
Henry Sidgwick, The Methods of Ethics, 7th Ed. (London: Macmillan, 1907), p. 404, note 1.
19
C. S. Lewis, The Screwtape Letters, Rev. Ed. (New York: Macmillan, 1982), p. 81.
20
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. Terence Irwin (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1985), 1170b6-7.
21
Mbigi, The Spirit of African Leadership, p. 69.
22
Fred Luthans, Ren Van Wyk & Fred O. Walumbwa, Recognition and Development of Hope for
South African Organizational Leaders, The Leadership & Organization Development Journal, Vol. 25,
No. 6 (2004), p. 515.
23
Augustine Shutte, Ubuntu: An Ethic for the New South Africa (Cape Town: Cluster Publications, 2001),
p. 24.
24
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1169a18-35.
25
Shutte, Ubuntu, p. 21.
26
Shepherd Shonhiwa, The Effective Cross-Cultural Manager: A Guide for Business Leaders in Africa
(Cape Town: Zebra Press, 2006), p. 6.
27
Lovemore Mbigi, with Jenny Maree, Ubuntu: The Spirit of African Transformation Management
(Randburg: Knowres, 2005), p. 93.
28
Luchien Karsten & Honorine Illa, Ubuntu as a Key African Management Concept, Journal of Managerial Psychology, Vol. 20, No. 7 (2005), p. 612.
29
Dean B. McFarlin, Edward A. Coster & Connie Mogale-Pretorius, South African Management Development in the Twenty-First Century, Journal of Management Development, Vol. 18, No. 1 (1999), p. 71.
30
Johann Broodryk, Ubuntu Management Philosophy (Randburg: Knowres, 2005), p. 168.
31
Shepherd Shonhiwa, The Effective Cross-Cultural Manager, p. 41.
32
Emmanuel Arthur Nnadozie, African Culture and American Business in Africa (Kirksville, Missouri:
Afrimax, 1998), p. 44.
33
Mbigi, Ubuntu, pp. vii-viii.
34
Broodryk, Ubuntu Management Philosophy, p. 174.
35
Linda van der Colff, Leadership Lessons from the African Tree, Management Decision, Vol. 41, No.
3 (2003), p. 257.
36
Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism and Human Emotions, trans. Bernard Frechtman (New York: Philosophical Library, 1957), p. 15.
37
Nelson Mandela, Foreword to Let Africa Lead: African Transformational Leadership for 21st Century
Business, by Reuel J. Khoza (Johannesburg: Vezubuntu, 2006), p. xxv.
10
38
Peter F. Drucker, The Changing World of the Executive (London: Heinemann, 1982), pp. 245-54.
Shuji Hayashi, Culture and Management in Japan, trans. Frank Baldwin (Tokyo: University of Tokyo
Press, 1988), p. 13.
40
Laurence Jacobs, Gao Guopei and Paul Herbig, Confucian Roots in China: A Force for Todays
Business, Management Decision, Vol. 33, No. 10 (1995), p. 29.
41
Chee Keen Pang, Diane Roberts & John Sutton, Doing Business in China: The Art of War? International Journal of Contemporary Hospitality Management, Vol. 10, No. 7 (1998), p. 273.
42
Raymond Dawson, Note on the Translation of Key Terms, in Confucius, The Analects (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1993), pp. xxi-xxiv.
43
Kam-hon Lee, Moral Consideration and Strategic Management Moves: The Chinese Case, Management Decision, Vol. 34, No. 9 (1996), p. 67.
44
James R. Ware, Introduction to The Sayings of Confucius: The Teachings of Chinas Greatest Sage
(New York: Mentor Books, 1955), p. 18.
45
Robert Guest, The Shackled Continent: Africas Past, Present and Future (London: Macmillan, 2004),
p. 23.
46
David Blair, Why China is Trying to Colonise Africa, The Telegraph (London), 31 August 2007.
47
Ibid.
48
Aristotle, The Politics, trans. Carnes Lord (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1253a2-3.
49
Plato, The Republic, trans. G. M. A. Grube (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1974), 504a.
50
Ibid., 343c, 357b.
51
Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, or the Matter, Forme, & Power of a Common-wealth, Ecclesiasticall and
Civill (London: Andrew Crooke, 1651), Chap. 13.
52
Hobbes, Leviathan, Chap. 15.
53
Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (London: A. Millar and Edinburgh: A. Kincaid &
J. Bell, 1769), Part VI, Sect. II, Chap. 3.
54
Mbigi, Ubuntu, p. vii.
55
John Paul II, Encyclical Letter Sollicitudo Rei Socialis (30 December 1987), no. 38.
56
Michael C. Jensen & William H. Meckling, Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs,
and Ownership Structure, in Economics and Social Institutions, ed. Karl Brunner (Boston: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1979), p. 170.
57
Charles Handy, Whats a Business For? Harvard Business Review, December 2002, p. 5.
58
Paolo G. Carozza, Subsidiarity as a Structural Principle of International Human Rights Law, The
American Journal of International Law, Vol. 97:38 (2003), p. 38, n. 1.
59
Alasdair MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics (New York, Macmillan, 1966), p. 139.
60
David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature: Being an Attempt to Introduce the Experimental Method of
Reasoning into Moral Subjects (London: John Noon, 1739-40), Book III, Part I, Section II.
61
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1103a24-25.
62
John Wild, Platos Modern Enemies and the Theory of Natural Law (Chicago and London: University
of Chicago Press, 1953), p. 108.
63
Ibid., p. 167.
64
Joseph L. Badaracco & Allen P. Webb, Business Ethics: A View from the Trenches, California
Management Review, Vol. 37, No. 2 (Winter 1995), p. 25.
65
Immanuel Kant, Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), trans. James W. Ellington, (Indianapolis & Cambridge: Hackett, 1981), p. 20.
66
Ibid., p. 22
67
Ibid.
68
Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, 3rd Ed. (Notre Dame, Indiana: University
of Notre Dame Press, 2007), pp. 45-46.
69
John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism (London, 1863), Chapter IV.
70
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 26.
71
Winston Churchill, Speech in the House of Commons, 11 November 1947: Many forms of Government have been tried, and will be tried in this world of sin and woe. No one pretends that democracy is
perfect or all-wise. Indeed, it has been said that democracy is the worst form of government except all
those other forms that have been tried from time to time.
72
Peter John Opio, Towards an Ethics of Business in Africa: Integrity and Competitiveness, in Business
Ethics in the African Context Today, ed. Michel Lejeune & Philipp W. Rosemann (Nkozi: Uganda Martyrs University Press, 1996), pp. 99-100.
73
Irving L. Janis, Groupthink: Psychological Studies of Policy Decisions and Fiascoes, 2nd Ed. (Boston:
Houghton Mifflin, 1982).
39
11
74
12