Ernest Bloch Lectures - 1999: Lecture 3
Ernest Bloch Lectures - 1999: Lecture 3
Ernest Bloch Lectures - 1999: Lecture 3
25/04/15 18:51
Lecture 3. Methodology:
The New Empiricism: Systematic Musicology in a
Postmodern Age
David Huron
KEYWORDS: methodology, empiricism, postmodernism, musicology
ABSTRACT: A survey of intellectual currents in the philosophy of knowledge and research
methodology is given. This survey provides the backdrop for taking stock of the
methodological differences that have arisen between disciplines, such as the methods
commonly used in science, history or literary theory. Postmodernism and scientific
empiricism are described and portrayed as two sides of the same coin we call skepticism. It is
proposed that the choice of methodological approach for any given research program is
guided by moral and esthetic considerations. Careful assessment of these risks may suggest
choosing an unorthodox method, such as quantitative methods in history, or deconstruction in
science. It is argued that methodological tools (such as Ockham's razor) should not be
mistaken for philosophical world-views. The article advocates a broadening of
methodological education in both arts and sciences disciplines. In particular, it advocates and
defends the use of quantitative empirical methodology in various areas of music scholarship.
Introduction
[1] Scholarly disciplines distinguish themselves from one another, principally by their subject matter.
Musicology differs from chemistry, and chemistry differs from political science because each of these
disciplines investigates different phenomena. Apart from the subject of study, scholarly disciplines also
frequently differ in how they approach research. The methods of the historian, the scientist, and the
literary scholar often differ dramatically. Moreover, even within scholarly disciplines, significant
methodological differences are common.
[2] Over the past two decades, music scholarship has been influenced by at least two notable
methodological movements. One of these is the so-called "new musicology." The new musicology is
loosely guided by a recognition of the limits of human understanding, an awareness of the social milieu in
which scholarship is pursued, and a realization of the political arena in which the fruits of scholarship are
used and abused. The influence of the new musicology is evident primarily in recent historical musicology
and ethnomusicology, but it has proved broadly influential in all areas of music scholarship, including
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 1 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
music education.
[3] Simultaneously, the past two decades have witnessed a rise in scientifically inspired music research.
This increase in empirical scholarship is apparent in the founding of several journals, including
Psychomusicology (founded 1981), Empirical Studies in the Arts (1982), Music Perception (1983),
Musicae Scientiae (1997), and Systematic Musicology (1998). This new empirical enthusiasm is
especially evident in the psychology of music and in the resurrection of systematic musicology. But
empiricism is also influential in certain areas of music education and in performance research. Music
researchers engaged in empirical work appear to be motivated by an interest in certain forms of rigor, and
a belief in the possibility of establishing positive, useful musical knowledge.
[4] The contrast between the new musicology and the new empiricism could hardly be more stark. While
the new musicology is not merely a branch of Postmodernism, the influence of Postmodern thinking is
clearly evident. Similarly, while recent music empiricism is not merely the offspring of Positivism, the
family resemblance is unmistakable. Yet the preeminent intellectual quarrel of our time is precisely that
between Positivism and Postmodernism -- two scholarly approaches that are widely regarded as mortal
enemies. {1} How have these diametrically opposed methodologies arisen, and what is a thoughtful
scholar to learn from the contrast? How indeed, ought one to conduct music research?
[5] By methodology, I mean any formal or semi-formal approach to acquiring insight or knowledge. A
methodology may consist of a set of fixed rules or injunctions, or it may consist of casual guidelines,
suggestions or heuristics. From time to time, a particular methodology emerges that is shared in common
by several disciplines. One example is the so-called Neyman-Pearson paradigm for inductive empirical
research commonly used in the physical sciences (Neyman and Pearson, 1928, 1967). But not all
disciplines adopt the same methodologies, nor should they.
[6] Different research goals, different fears, different opportunities, and different dispositions can
influence the adoption and development of research methods. For any given scholarly pursuit, some
research methods will prove to be better suited than others. Part of the scholar's responsibility then, is to
identify and refine methods that are appropriate to her or his field of study. This responsibility includes
recognizing when a popular research method ceases to be appropriate, and adapting one's research to take
advantage of new insights concerning the conduct of research as these insights become known.
Two Cultures
[7] Historically, the most pronounced methodological differences can be observed in the broad contrast
between the sciences and the humanities. (For convenience, in this article I will use the term "humanities"
to refer to both the humanities and the arts.) In humanities scholarship, research methods include
historiographic, semiotic, deconstructive, feminist, hermeneutical, and many other methods. In the
sciences, the principal scholarly approaches include modeling and simulation, analysis-by-synthesis,
correlational and experimental approaches.
[8] Many scholars presume that methodological differences reflect basic philosophical disagreements
concerning the nature of scholarly research. I think this view masks the more fundamental causes of
methodological divergence. As I will argue in this article, in most cases, the main methodological
differences between disciplines can be traced to the materials and circumstances of the particular field of
study. That is, differences in research methods typically reflect concrete differences between fields (or
sub-fields) rather than reflecting some underlying difference in philosophical outlook. This is the reason, I
will contend, why Muslims and Christians, atheists and anarchists, liberals and libertarians, have little
difficulty working with each other in most disciplines. Although deep personal beliefs may motivate an
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 2 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
individual to work on particular problems, one's core philosophical beliefs often have little to do with
one's scholarly approach.
Overview
[12] My goal in this article is to take stock of the methodological differences that arise between
disciplines and to attempt to understand their origins and circumstantial merits. As I've already noted, I
think the concrete circumstances of research are especially formative. However, before I argue this case, it
behooves me to address the noisy (and certainly interesting) debates in the philosophy of knowledge. In
particular, it is appropriate to address the often acrimonious debate between empiricism and
postmodernism.
[13] Of course not all sciences are empirical and not all humanities scholarship is postmodern. The field
of mathematics (which is popularly often considered "scientific") relies almost exclusively on deductive
methods rather than empirical methods. Similarly, although postmodernism has been a dominant
paradigm in many humanities disciplines over the past two decades, there exist other methodological
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 3 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
traditions in humanities scholarship. The reason why I propose to focus on the empirical and
postmodernist traditions is that they are seemingly the most irreconcilable. I believe we have the most to
learn by examining this debate.
[14] This paper is divided into two parts. In Part I, I outline some of the intellectual history that forms the
background for contemporary empiricism and postmodernism. Part II focuses more specifically on
methodology. In particular, I identify what I think are the principal causes that lead to the adoption of
different methodologies in different fields and sub-fields. Part II also provides historical examples where
disciplines have dramatically changed their methodological preferences in response to new circumstances.
My claim is that the resources available for music scholarship are rapidly evolving, and that musicology
has much to gain by adapting empirical methods to many musical problems. I conclude by outlining some
of the basic ideas underlying what might be called the "new empiricism."
Pgina 4 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Theory originally published in 1905, but reprinted innumerable times throughout the past century. In his
book, Duhem notes that science never provides theories or explanations of some ultimate reality.
Theoretical entities and mathematical laws are merely conventions that summarize certain types of
relationships. It can never be determined whether scientific theories are "true" in the sense of explaining
or capturing some underlying reality. Scientific theories are merely conventions that help scientists
organize the observable patterns of the world.
[20] A variation of conventionalism, known as instrumentalism similarly posits that empiricism does not
provide ultimate explanations: the engineer has no deep understanding of why a bridge does not fall
down. Rather, the engineer relies on theories as tools that are reasonably predictive of practical outcomes.
For the instrumentalist, theories are judged, not by their "truthfulness," but by their predictive utility.
[21] The most well-known attempt to resolve the problem of induction was formulated by Karl Popper in
1934. Popper accepted that no amount of observation could ever verify that a particular proposition is
true. That is, an observer cannot prove that all swans are white. However, Popper argued that one could be
certain of falsity. For example, observing a single black swan would allow one to conclude that the claim - all swans are white -- is false. Accordingly, Popper endeavored to explain the growth of knowledge as
arising by trimming the tree of possible hypotheses using the pruning shears of falsification. Truth is what
remains after the falsehoods have been trimmed away.
[22] Popper's approach was criticized by van Quine, Lakatos, Agassi, Feyerabend and others. One
problem is that it is not exactly clear what is falsified by a falsifying observation. It may be that the
observation itself is incorrect, or the manner by which the phenomenon of interest is defined, or the
overall theoretical framework within which a specific hypothesis is posited. (For example, the observer of
a purported black swan might have been drunk, or the swan might have been painted, or the animal might
be claimed to be a different species.) A related problem is fairly technical, and so difficult to describe
succinctly. In order to avoid prematurely jettisoning a theory, Popper abandoned the notion of a falsifying
observation and replaced it with the concept of a falsifying phenomenon. Yet to establish a falsifying
phenomenon, researchers must engage in an activity of verification -- an activity which Popper himself
argued was impossible. In Popper's methodology, the nasty problem of inductive truth returns through the
rear door.
[23] Despite such difficulties, Popper's falsificationism has remained highly influential in the day-to-day
practice of empirical research. In the professional journals of science, editors regular remove claims that
such-and-such is true, or that such-and-such a theory is verified, or even that the data "support" such-andsuch a hypothesis. On the contrary, the boiler-plate language for scientific claims is: the null hypothesis
was rejected or the data are consistent with such-and-such a hypothesis. Of course this circumspect
language is abandoned in secondary and popular scientific writings, as well as in the informal
conversations of scientists. This gap between official skepticism and colloquial certainty is a proper
subject of study for sociologists of science.
[24] Another, less influential scientific epistemology in the twentieth century was positivism. Positivism
never provided a proposal for resolving the problem of induction. Nevertheless, it is worth brief mention
here for two reasons. First logical positivism drew attention to the issue of language and meaning in
scientific discourse, and secondly, "positivism" has been the preeminent target of postmodernist critiques.
[25] Positivism began as a social philosophy in France, initiated by Saint-Simon and Comte, and spread to
influence the sciences in the early twentieth century. The tenants of positivism were articulated by the socalled Vienna Circle (including Schlick and Carnap) and culminated in the classic statement of 1936 by
A.J. Ayer. In science, logical positivism held sway from roughly 1930 to 1965. However, this influence
was almost exclusively restricted to American psychology; only a small minority of empiricists ever
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 5 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Postmodernism
[28] Postmodernism is many things, and any attempt to summarize it is in danger of oversimplification.
(Indeed, one of the principal tenants of postmodernism is that one should not attempt to represent the
world-views of others.) In the same way that philosophers of science disagree with one another, those who
call themselves postmodernists also are not of one mind. Nevertheless, there are a number of common
themes that tend to recur in postmodernist writings. Postmodernism is a philosophical movement that
focuses on how meanings get constructed, and how power is commandeered and exercised through
language, representation and discourse. {3}
[29] Postmodernism is interested in scholarship, because scholarly endeavors are among the preeminent
meaning-conferring activities in our society. Postmodernism is especially interested in science, principally
because, at least in Western societies, science holds a power of persuasion second to no other institution.
It is a power, of which the most powerful politicians can only express envy.
[30] Postmodernism begins from a position surprisingly similar to Popper's anti-verification stance and
Duhem's conventionalism. Where Duhem and Popper thought that the truth is unknowable,
postmodernism assumes that there is no absolute truth to be known. More precisely, "truth" ought to be
understood as a social construction that relates to a local or partial perspective on the world. Our mistake
is to assume that as observers, we can climb out of the box which is our world. There is no such objective
perspective.
[31] There are, rather, a vast number of interpretations about the world. In this, the world is akin to a
series of texts. As illustrated in the writings of Jacques Derrida, any text can be deconstructed to reveal
multiple interpretations, no one of which can be construed as complete, definitive, or privileged. From
this, postmodernists conclude that there is no objective truth, and similarly that there is no rational basis
for moral, esthetic or epistemological judgment.
[32] If there is no absolute basis for these judgments, how do people in the world go about making the
decisions they do? The most successful achievements of postmodernism have been in drawing attention to
the power relations that exist in any situation where an individual makes some claim. As Nancy Hartsock
has suggested, "the will to power [is] inherent in the effort to create theory" (1990; p.164). Like the
politician or the business person, scholars are consciously or unconsciously motivated by the desire to
commandeer resources and establish influence. Unlike the politician or the business person, we scholars
purport to have no hidden agenda -- a self-deception that makes us the most dangerous of all story-tellers.
[33] It is the most powerful members of society who are able to establish and project their own stories as
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 6 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
so-called "master narratives." These narratives relate not only to claims of truth, but also to moral and
artistic claims. The "canons" of art and knowledge are those works exalted by, and serving, the social
elites. Insofar as works of art give legitimacy to those who produce them, "A work of art is an act of
power." (Rahn, 1993)
[34] This admittedly pessimistic view of the world could well lead one to despair. Since there is no
legitimate power, how does the conscientious person act so as to construct a better world? Postmodernism
offers various strategies that might be regarded as serving the goal of expos. That is, the postmodernist
helps the cause through a sort of investigative journalism that exposes how behaviors are self-serving. At
its best, postmodernism is a democratizing ladle that stirs up the political soup and resists the
entrenchment of a single power. By creating a sort of chaos of meaning, it calls existing canons into
question, subverts master narratives, and so gives flower to what has been called "the politics of
difference".
Pgina 7 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
the room will remain fixed. However, if you walk in a circle around the room, the visual angles between
various objects will change. As you approach two objects, the angle separating them will increase.
Conversely, as you move away from two objects, the angle separating them will decrease.
[41] According to this logic, if the earth is in motion, then one ought to be able to see slight angular shifts
between the stars over the course of the year. Using his new-fangled invention, the telescope, Galileo did
indeed make careful measurements of the angular relationships between the stars over the course of a
year. He found, however, that there was no change whatsoever. In effect, Galileo carried out a critical
experiment -- one whose results were not consistent with the idea that the earth is in motion. How did
Galileo respond to this result? Galileo suggested that the reason why no parallax shifts could be observed
was because the stars are extremely far away.
[42] Feyerabend pointed out that this is an ad hoc hypothesis. A critical experiment was carried out to
determine whether the earth or the sun was in motion, and Galileo's theory lost. Moreover, Galileo had the
audacity to defend his theory by offering an ad hoc hypothesis. By modern scientific standards, one would
have to conclude that the Scholastics' theory was superior, and that, as a scientist, Galileo himself should
have recognized that the evidence was more consistent with the earth-centered theory.
[43] Of course, from our modern perspective, Galileo was right to persevere with his sun-centered theory
of the solar system. As it turns out, his ad hoc hypothesis regarding the extreme distance to the stars is
considered by astronomers to be correct.
[44] From this history, Feyerabend draws the following conclusions. First, the progress of science may
depend on bad argument and ignoring data. Second, Galileo should be recognized, not as a great scientist,
but as a successful propagandist. Third, had Galileo followed modern standards of scientific method the
result would have been scientifically wrong. Fourth, the injunction against ad hoc hypotheses in science
can produce scientifically incorrect results. Fifth, the use of critical experiments in science can produce
scientifically incorrect results. Sixth, no methodological rule will ensure a correct result. Seventh, there is
no scientific method. And eighth, in matters of methodology, concludes Feyerabend, anything goes. Like
Popper and Lakatos, Feyerabend argued that there is no set of rules that guarantees the progress of
knowledge.
[45] In assessing Feyerabend's work, we need to look at both his successes and failures. Let's begin with
some problems. Recall that the problem of induction is the problem of how general conclusions can be
drawn from a finite set of observations. Consider, the fourth and fifth of Feyerabend's conclusions. He
notes that two rules in scientific methodology (namely, the rule forbidding ad hoc hypotheses, and the
instruction to devise critical experiments) failed to produce a valid result in Galileo's case. From these two
historical observations, Feyerabend formulates the general conclusion: no methodological rule will ensure
a correct result. By now you should recognize that this is an inductive argument, and as Hume pointed
out, we can't ever be sure that generalizing from specific observations produces a valid generalization.
[46] Showing that some methodological rules don't work in a single case, doesn't allow us to claim that all
methodological rules are wrong. Even if one were to show that all known methodological rules were
inadequate, one can't logically conclude than there are no true methodological rules.
[47] A further problem with Feyerabend's argument is that he exaggerates Galileo's importance in the
promotion of the sun-centered theory. The beliefs and arguments of a single person are typically limited.
Knowledge is socially distributed, and ideas catch on, only when the wider population is prepared to be
convinced. In fact, the heliocentric theory of the solar system was not immediately adopted by scientists
because of Galileo's arguments. The heliocentric theory didn't gain many converts until after Kepler
showed that the planets move in elliptical orbits. Kepler's laws made the sun-centered theory a much
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 8 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
simpler system for describing planetary motions. In short, Galileo's fame and importance as a scientific
champion is primarily retrospective and ahistorical.
[48] Feyerabend's historical and analytic work is insufficient to support his general conclusion: namely
that in methodology, the only correct rule is "anything goes." Moreover, Feyerabend's own dictum is not
born out by observation. Anyone observing any meeting of any academic group will understand that, in
their debates, it is not true that `anything goes.' All disciplines have more or less loose standards of
evidence, of sound argument, and so on. Although a handful of scholars might wish that debates could be
settled through physical combat, for the majority of scholars such "methods" are no longer admissible.
There may be no methodological recipe that guarantees the advance of knowledge, but similarly, it is not
the case that anything goes.
[49] On the positive side, Feyerabend has drawn attention to the social and political environment in which
science takes place. Feyerabend stated that his main reason for writing Against Method was
"humanitarian, not intellectual". Feyerabend wanted to provide rhetorical support for the marginalized and
dispossessed (p.4). In drawing attention to the sociology of science, Feyerabend and his followers have
met strong resistance from scientists themselves. Until recently, most scientists rejected the notion that
science is shaped by a socio-political context. The failings of science notwithstanding, this does not mean
that scholars working in the sociology of science have been doing a good job.
Pgina 9 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
incommensurable -- not measurable using a single yard-stick. Paradigm shifts occur, not because
supporters of the old paradigm become convinced by the new paradigm. Instead, argues Kuhn, new
paradigms replace old paradigms because old scientists die, and new paradigm supporters are able to
place their colleagues and students in important positions of power (professorships, journal editors,
granting agencies, etc.) Once advocates of the new paradigm have seized power, the textbooks in the
discipline are re-written so that the revolutionary change is re-cast as a natural and inevitable step in the
continuing smooth progress of the discipline.
[55] While Kuhn's work had an enormous impact in the social sciences, it had comparatively little impact
in the sciences themselves. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions portrayed science as akin to fashion:
changes do not arise from some sort of rational debate. Change is simply determined by who holds power.
Although Thomas Kuhn denied that he was arguing that science does not progress, his study of the history
of science strongly implies that "scientific progress" is an illusion perpetrated by scientists who reconstruct history to place themselves (and their paradigms) at the pinnacle of a long lineage of
achievement.
[56] Many social sciences and humanities scholars applauded Kuhn because his portrayal removed
science from the epistemological high ground. The presumed authority of science is unwarranted. Like
different cultures around the world, there is no valid yard-stick by which one can claim that one scientific
culture is better than another.
[57] Kuhn's writings also appealed to those scientists (and other scholars) whose views place them outside
the mainstream. For those scientists whose unorthodox views are routinely ignored by their colleagues,
Kuhn's message is highly reassuring. The reason why other people don't understand us and don't care
about what we say, is that they are enmeshed in the old paradigm: no amount of reasoned debate can be
expected to convince the existing powers. In short, Kuhn's characterization of science provides a measure
of comfort to the marginalized and dispossessed.
[58] Shortly after the publication of Kuhn's book, a young Bengali philosopher named Jagdish
Hattiangadi wrote a detailed critique of the work. Although Kuhn regarded himself as a historian of
science with great sympathies for science, Hattiangadi noted that Kuhn's work removed any possibility
that science could be viewed as a rational enterprise. Although Kuhn never said as much, his theory had
significant repercussions: for example, a chemist who believes that modern chemistry is better than
ancient chemistry must simply be deluded. Hattiangadi noted that, either there is no progress whatsoever
in science, or Kuhn's portrayal of science is wrong. Hattiangadi concluded that Kuhn's work failed to
account for the widespread belief that scientific progress is a fact. Moreover, as early as 1963, Hattiangadi
predicted that Kuhn's book would become wildly successful among social and humanities scholars -- a
prediction that proved correct.
Postmodernism: An Assessment
[59] With this background in place, let's return to our discussion of postmodernism. In general,
postmodernism takes issue with the Enlightenment project of deriving absolute or universal truths from
particular knowledge. That is, postmodernism posits a radical opposition to induction. We cannot
generalize from the particular; the global does not follow from the local.
[60] At first glance, it would appear that postmodernism would be as critical of Feyerabend and Kuhn as
of the positivists. For the arguments of Feyerabend and Kuhn also rest on the assumption that we can
learn general lessons from specific historical examples. However, postmodernism is less concerned with
such convoluted issues than it is with the general goal of causing intellectual havoc for those who want to
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 10 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
make strong knowledge claims. Accordingly, the works of Feyerabend and Kuhn are regarded as allies in
the task of unraveling science's presumed authority.
[61] Of course postmodernism also has its critics. Much of the recent unhappiness with postmodernism is
that it appears to deny the possibility for meaningful human change. For example, many feminist thinkers
have dismissed a postmodernist approach because it removes the high moral ground. In lobbying for
political change, most feminists have been motivated by a sense of injustice. However, if there are no
absolute precepts of justice, then the message postmodernism gives to feminists is that they are simply
engaged in Machiavellian maneuvers to wrest power. In the words of Joseph Natoli, "postmodernist
politics here has nothing to do with substance but only with the tactics." (1997, p. 101) On the one hand,
postmodernism encourages feminists to wrest power away from the male establishment; but at the same
time, postmodernism tells feminists not to believe that their actions are at all justified. Understandably,
many feminists are uncomfortable with this contradiction.
[62] The nub of the issue, I think, is evident in the following two propositions associated with
postmodernism:
(1) There is no privileged interpretation.
(2) All interpretations are equally valid.
As the postmodernist writer Catherine Belsey has noted, postmodernism has been badly received by the
public primarily because postmodernists have failed to distinguish between sense and nonsense. This is
the logical outcome for those who believe that (2) is simply a restatement of (1).
[63] If we accept the proposition that there is no privileged interpretation, it does not necessarily follow
that all interpretations are equally valid. For those who accept (1) but not (2), it follows that some
interpretations must be "better" than others -- hence raising the question of what is meant by "better."
[64] Postmodernism has served an important role by encouraging scholars to think carefully, laterally, and
self-reflectively. Unfortunately, postmodernism encourages slovenly research and a disinterest in pursuing
rigor. Postmodernism draws welcome attention to the social and political context of knowledge and
knowledge claims. But postmodernism goes too far when it concludes that reality is socially constructed
rather than socially mediated. Postmodernism serves an important role when it encourages us to think
about power relations, and in particular how certain groups are politically disenfranchised because they
have little control over how meanings get established. But at the same time, postmodernism subverts all
values, and transforms justice into mere tactical maneuvers to gain power. In reducing all relationships to
power, postmodernism leaves no room for other human motivations. Scholarship may have political
dimensions, but that doesn't mean that all scholars are plotting power-mongers. Postmodernism is
important insofar as it draws attention to the symbolic and cultural milieu of human existence. But, while
we should recognize that human beings are cultural entities, we must also recognize that humans are also
biological entities with a priori instinctive and dispositional knowledge about the world that originates in
an inductive process of evolutionary adaptation (Plotkin, 1994). Foucault regrettably denied any status for
humans as biological entities whose mental hardware exists for the very purpose of gaining knowledge
about the world.
[65] When pushed on the issue of relativism, postmodernists will temporarily disown their philosophy and
accept the need for some notion of logic and rigor. Belsey, for example, claims that as postmodernists,
"we should not abandon the notion of rigor; the project of substantiating our readings" (Belsey, 1993, p.
561) Similarly, Natoli recognizes that "logic" (1997, p.162) and "precision" (p.120) make for compelling
narratives. However, postmodernists are oddly uninterested in how these approaches gain their rhetorical
power. What is "logic"? What is "rigor"? What is it about rationality that makes some narratives so
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 11 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
mentally seductive or compelling? It is exactly this task that has preoccupied philosophers of knowledge
over the past 2,500 years and was the focus of Enlightenment efforts in epistemology. The Enlightenment
project of attempting to characterize the value of various knowledge claims is not subverted by
postmodernism. On the contrary, postmodernism simply raises anew the question of what it means to do
good scholarship.
Methodological Differences
[67] As noted in the introduction, one of the principal goals of this paper is to better account for why
methodologies differ for different disciplines. In pursuing this goal I will outline a taxonomy of research
methodologies based on four distinctions. In brief, these are:
False-positive skepticism versus false-negative skepticism. False-positive skepticism holds that
theories or hypotheses ought to be rejected given the slightest contradicting evidence. Falsenegative skepticism holds that theories or hypotheses ought to be conserved unless there is
overwhelming contradicting evidence.
High risk versus low risk theories. Theories, hypotheses, interpretations and intuitions carry moral
and esthetic repercussions. In testing some knowledge claim, the burden of evidence can shift
depending on the consequences of the theory. Many theories carry negligible risks, however.
Retrospective versus prospective data. Some areas of research (such as manuscript studies) have
only pre-existing evidence or data. Other areas of research (such as behavioral studies) have
opportunities to collect newly generated evidence. Prospective data allows researchers to more
rigorously test knowledge claims by attempting to forecast properties of yet-to-be-collected data.
Data-rich versus data-poor fields. Fields of study can also be characterized according to the volume
of pertinent evidence. When the evidence is minimal, researchers in data-rich fields have the luxury
of suspending judgment until more evidence is assembled. By contrast, researchers in data poor
fields often must interpret a set of data that is both very small and final -- with no hope of additional
forthcoming evidence.
[68] Below, I will describe more fully these four distinctions. My claim is that fields of study can be
usefully characterized by these taxonomic categories. Each of these four distinctions has repercussions for
formulating field-appropriate methodologies. I will suggest that these taxonomic distinctions not only help
us to better understand why methodologies diverge for various fields, but also help us to better recognize
when an existing methodology is inappropriate for some area of study.
[69] Additionally, I will note that fields of research sometimes experience major changes in their basic
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 12 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
working conditions -- changes that precipitate shifts in methodology. A formerly uncontentious field of
research (such as education) may abruptly find that its latest theories {4} carry high moral risk. A
previously data-poor field (such as theology) may become inundated by new sources of information. And
a formerly retrospective discipline (such as history) may unexpectedly find a class of events for which it
can offer testable predictions. Later in this article I will briefly discuss two case examples of such shifts in
resources and methods. My first example is the transformation of sub-atomic physics so that its methods
increasingly resemble those in philosophy and literary theory. My second example will be the increasing
influence of empirical methods in music scholarship.
Actually
True, Useful
or Knowable
Thought to be
True, Useful
or Knowable
Thought to be
False, Useless
or Unknowable
Correct
Inference
Actually
False Positive Error Correct
False, Useless (Type I Error)
Inference
or Unknowable
[73] The false-positive skeptic tends to make statements such as the following:
"You don't know that for sure."
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 13 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Pgina 14 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Pgina 15 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
commonly expressed by scientists. Objecting to scientific theories on this basis is clearly a fallacy, but it is
understandable why scholars from data-poor disciplines would tend to respond skeptically to the cocky
assurance of others. We will return to consider the issue of explanatory closure later, when we discuss
Ockham's razor and the issue of reductionism.
[86] Having proposed this association between theory-discarding skepticism and science (on the one
hand) and theory-conserving skepticism and the humanities (on the other hand), let me now retract and
refine it. I do not think that there is any necessary association. The origin of this tendency, I propose, has
nothing to do with the nature of scientific as opposed to humanities scholarship. I should also hasten to
add that I do not believe that individual scholars are solely theory-discarding or theory-conserving
skeptics. People have pretty good intuitions when to approach a phenomenon as a false-positive skeptic
and when to approach a phenomenon as a false-negative skeptic.
[87] If there is no necessary connection between theory-discarding skepticism and science, and theoryconserving skepticism and the humanities, where does this apparent association come from? I think there
are two factors that have contributed to these differing methodological dispositions. As already suggested,
one factor relates to the quantity of available evidence or data for investigating hypotheses or theories. A
second factor pertains to the moral and esthetic repercussions of the hypotheses. These two factors are
interrelated so it is difficult to discuss each factor in isolation. Nevertheless, in the ensuing discussion, I
will attempt to discuss each issue independently.
Pgina 16 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
sufficient volume of evident so the researcher can assemble a convincing case. If the field is data poor
(such as often happens in jurisprudence), then one must expect to make a lot of errors; the moral
repercussions of a false-positive versus a false-negative error will determine whether the researcher
should adopt a theory-conserving or theory-discarding skepticism. In criminal law, one can expect many
failures to convict guilty people in order to minimize the number of wrongful convictions.
[92] In contrast with legal proceedings, most scholarly hypotheses have marginal moral or esthetic risk.
For example, whether a theory of the origins of Romanesque architecture is true or false has little moral
impact. However, risk is never entirely absent. Suppose that a musicologist found evidence suggesting
that one composer had plagiarized a melody from another composer. If the claim of plagiarism was in fact
false, then the first composer's reputation would be unjustly tarnished. If that composer were still living,
then a false claim of plagiarism would be morally reprehensible.
[93] To the knowledgeable statistician there is nothing new in this discussion. Modern statisticians have
always understood the reciprocal relationship between false positive and false negative errors, and have
long recognized that whether a researcher endeavors to reduce one or the other depends entirely on the
attendant risks of making either error. In most traditional arts and humanities scholarship, making a false
positive claim rarely has onerous moral or esthetic repercussions. Conversely, false-negative claims have
often been seen as reckless.
[94] Perhaps the best known theory-conserving argument is Pascal's Wager. Unconvinced by the many
proofs offered for the existence of God, Pascal asked what would be lost if the proposition were true but
our evidence scant? Pascal argued that the repercussions of making a false-negative error were simply too
onerous. He chose to believe in God, not because the positive evidence was compelling, but because he
thought that the moral risk associated with wrongly dismissing the hypothesis would require an
extraordinary volume of contradicting evidence (Pascal, 1669).
[95] Historically, statistical tests have been used almost exclusively to minimize false-positive errors. It is
the community of theory-discarding skeptics who have made the greatest use of statistics. I suspect that
this historical association between the use of statistical inference and false-positive skepticism may
account for much of the widespread suspicion of statistical arguments among arts and humanities
scholars. Yet there is nothing in statistical inference per se that is contrary to the traditional
arts/humanities scholar's penchant for false negative skepticism. As statisticians well know, common
statistical procedures are equally adept at serving the theory-conserving skeptic.
[96] As noted earlier, the science/false-positive and humanities/false-negative association is changing.
Contemporary medicine has become more cognizant of the dangers of prematurely discarding theories.
Concurrently, many arts and humanities researchers are becoming more aware of the problems of theoryconserving skepticism. In the case of music, several hundred years of speculative theorizing has led to the
promulgation of innumerable ideas -- many of which surely lack substance {8}. Until recently, there was
little one could do about this. The scarcity of pertinent data in many humanities fields simply made it
impossible to satisfy statistical criteria for minimizing false positive errors. The opportunities to address
these problems have been immensely expanded due to the growing availability of computer databases,
comprehensive reference tools, and the growing use of experiment-based data collection. We will return
to these issues shortly.
Historical Fields
[97] Fields can be characterized according to whether the principal evidence or data arise from the past or
from the future. Historical fields are fields whose fundamental data already exist. Archeology,
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 17 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
paleontology and art history are examples of historical fields. In each of these fields, the principal
phenomena of study are ones that occurred in the past. These phenomena are accessible for study only
through the tenuous traces of currently existing data. Historical data might include paper documents,
physical objects, oral histories, or unspoken memories. Normally, the existing evidence constitutes a
proper subset of all of the pertinent evidence, most of which has been destroyed by the passage of time.
[98] It would be wrong to think of historical fields as principally belonging to the humanities. The
sciences of astronomy, geology, and paleoanthropology are predominantly historical fields. Each of these
sciences is concerned primarily with evidence of past events. Indeed, the preeminent historical discipline,
it might be argued, is astronomy: the light that reaches astronomers' telescopes is typically hundreds or
millions of years old. It is rare that astronomers get to study "current events."
Pgina 18 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
[104] The origin of the Theory of Continental Drift arose from observing the suspicious visual fit between
the east coasts of the American continents and the west coasts of Europe and Africa. The bulge of northwest Africa appears to fit like a piece of a jig-saw puzzle into the Caribbean gulf. This observation was
ridiculed as childish nonsense by geologists in the first part of the twentieth century. Geologists were right
to dismiss the similarity of the coast-lines as evidence in support of the theory of continental drift, since
this similarity was the origin of the theory in the first place. Plate tectonics gained credence only when
independent evidence was gathered consistent with the spreading of the Atlantic sea-bed.
[105] Such "post hoc theorizing has particularly plagued evolutionary theorizing (see Gould, 1978; Gould
& Lewontin, 1979; Lewontin, 1991; Rosen, 1982). Nevertheless, in some cases, evolutionary theories can
arise that make predictions about yet-to-be-gathered data (such as the Trivers-Willard hypothesis). Good
theories are a priori; that is, the theory suggests or predicts certain facts or phenomena before those facts
are ascertained or observed.
[106] Fields that rely exclusively on retrospective data are susceptible to post hoc theorizing where
hypotheses are easy to form and difficult to test. This is a problem that is endemic to many fields,
especially historical fields (including astronomy). Nevertheless, careful attention to the underlying logic
of a theory may permit testing of unexpected predictions of pre-existing prospective data. The fields of
astronomy and evolutionary biology have demonstrated that there are many more opportunities for testing
historical theories than is recognized by historians working in humanities disciplines.
Pgina 19 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
factor.
Positivist Fallacy
[116] Data poor fields raise some special methodological concerns. One of these is the problem known as
the positivist fallacy. If a phenomenon leaves no trail of evidence, then there is nothing to study. We may
even be tempted to conclude that nothing has happened. In other words, the positivist fallacy is the
misconception that absence of evidence may be interpreted as evidence of absence.
[117] Positivism had a marked impact on mid-twentieth century American psychology. In particular, the
influence of logical positivism was notable in the behaviorists such as J.B. Watson and B.F. Skinner. The
classic example of the positivist fallacy was the penchant of behaviorists to dismiss unobservable mental
states as non-existent. For example, because "consciousness" could not be observed, for the positivist it
must be regarded as an occult or fictional quality with no truth status (Ayer, 1936).
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 20 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
[118] If it is true that the positivist fallacy tends to arise from data-poor conditions, then it should be
possible to observe this same misconception in humanities scholarship -- whenever data is limited.
Consider, by way of example, the following argument from the distinguished historical musicologist,
Albert Seay. At the beginning of his otherwise fine book on medieval music, Seay provides the following
rationale for focusing predominantly on sacred music in preference to secular music:
"Although much music did exist for secular purposes and many musicians satisfied the needs
of secular audiences, the Church and its musical opportunities remained the central
preoccupation. No better evidence of this emphasis on the religious can be seen than in the
relative scarcity of both information and primary source materials for secular music as
compared to those for the sacred." (Seay, 1975, p.2)
In other words, Seay is arguing that, with regard to secular medieval music-making, absence of evidence
is evidence of absence. Since secular activities generated little documentation, we have almost no idea of
the extent and day-to-day pertinence of medieval secular music-making. For illiterate peasants, "do-ityourself" folk music may have shaped daily musical experience far more than has been supposed. Of
course Seay may be entirely right about the relative unimportance of secular music-making, but in basing
his argument on the absence of data, he is in the company of the most rabid logical positivist. The
positivist fallacy is commonly regarded as a symptom of scientific excess. However, it knows no
disciplinary boundaries; it tends to appear whenever pertinent data are scarce.
Pgina 21 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
model more realistic, regrettably, it also greatly increases the capacity for self-deception.
Pgina 22 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
reductionistic accounts "explain" only in the sense of making flat (ex planum). The world as an enchanting
place is transformed into a prosaic, colorless, and seemingly senseless enterprise. Among humanities
scholars, musicians and musicologists have been among the most vocal critics of `nothing but'
reductionism. Music theorists explicitly embrace complexity and scorn simplicity. {9}. John Cage
cautioned strongly against such "logical minimizations." Moreover, Cage was prescient in recognizing
that this reductive tendency is not limited to the sciences. It is surprising where one can find such "nothing
but" forms of reductionism.
[131] Consider, once again, postmodernism. The postmodernist/deconstructionist philosophy advocates
the unpacking of concepts and utterances in terms of socially constructed roles and power relations (e.g.
Hacking, 1995). Postmodernism has helped to expose innumerable subtle and not-so-subtle ways in which
ostensibly rational discourse manifests convoluted forms of dominance and control. But postmodernism
goes much further. The most abstract principles of law, philosophy, and even science are best understood
from the point-of-view of politics: everything reduces to politics. Notice that in this formulation,
postmodernism and deconstruction bear all the hallmarks of nothing-but reductionism. Any thought you
care to express can be reduced to a political motive. A sociobiologist may believe a social phenomenon to
be ultimately reducible to underlying chemical interactions. But the postmodernist trumps this
reductionism by viewing all scientific discourses as ultimately reducible to power ploys. As in the case of
the scientific reductive synthesis, one cannot help but be impressed by the breathless grandiosity of such
postmodernist patterns of explanations.
[132] There is, I would suggest a more helpful way of understanding the value of reductionism while
avoiding some of the more unsavory excesses (in both the sciences and the humanities). A helpful
distinction is to treat "reductionism" as a potentially useful strategy for discovery rather than a belief
about how the world is. Concretely, the postmodernist might use the assumption of hegemony as a
technique to help unravel a complex behavior. Similarly, the sociobiologist might use the assumption of a
recessive gene as a technique to help analyze a personality trait. In both cases, there are dangers in
assuming that the tool is the reality. But in both cases, there remains the possibility that the reductive
explanatory principle proves useful in understanding the phenomenon in question.
Pgina 23 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Anderson, 1972; Gell-Mann, 1994; Gleick, 1987; Pagels, 1988). In addition, a researcher can cogently
hold a humanistic view of the origins of human behavior, yet rely on reductionism as a useful method for
investigation. That is, one need not believe that human behavior is mechanistic in order to use
reductionism as a way of probing the complexities of the world. Using reductionism as a research strategy
does not commit a researcher to a mechanistic world-view. Similarly, analyzing a phenomenon as a
holistic emergent property does not thereby transform the researcher into a spiritualist.
A Quantitative Role
[135] Earlier we noted that "empiricism" simply means knowledge gained through observation. For many
critics of empiricism, it not the idea of observational knowledge per se that raises concerns, but
empiricism's widespread reliance on quantitative methods.
[136] Perhaps the preeminent concern is that quantitative methods force phenomena into numerical
categories that may or may not be appropriate. A researcher, for example, might ask listeners to rate
musical excerpts on a scale from 1 to 10, where 1 represents "maximum sadness" and 10 represents
"maximum happiness." This practice is open to innumerable objections: happiness and sadness may be
independent phenomena that do not exist on some unified continuum; the musical excerpt may not retain a
consistent character throughout the passage; a "poignant" passage might be both "happy" and "sad"
simultaneously; a passage might be recognizable as intending to portray happiness, but a listener may find
the portrayal unconvincing, and so "sadly" a failure; the numerical judgments may be uninterpretable (is
the value 2 intended to be half as sad as the value 1?), etc.
[137] Concerns such as these actually form much of the fundamental curriculum for training in
quantitative methodology. For example, empiricists are taught that any judgment scale should use a single
adjective (ranging from "least X" to "most X") rather than using mixed adjectives ("most X" to "most Y").
Similarly, empiricists learn that measurements are never to be construed as direct indices of actual
phenomena, and operational definitions should not be reified. Statisticians have devised completely
independent analytic procedures, depending on the properties of various measurement scales.
[138] For many humanistically-inclined scholars, however, there remains something inherently wrong
about quantifying human experiences -- especially those experiences related to human attachment,
esthetic experience, and spiritual life. Many scholars would agree with Renato Poggioli's view that the
technical and quantitative have their place, but not in the arts:
"Technicism" means that the technical genius invades spiritual realms where technique has no
raison d'tre. ... It is not against the technical or the machine that the spirit justly revolts; it is
against this reduction of nonmaterial values to the brute categories of the mechanical and
technical." [p.138]
Once again, let me respond to this view by distinguishing methodologies of scholarly inquiry from
philosophical beliefs about the nature of the world. Lest this distinction seem too abstract, consider the
following extended illustration, which draws a parallel to scholarly attitudes regarding the use of writing
and musical notation.
[139] Socrates famously criticized the new fangled invention of writing. He rightly pointed to a number of
predictable, yet questionable, consequences of relying on written texts. Specifically, Socrates predicted a
decline in the importance of rote memory, and the waning of oratory skills.
[140] Socrates' predictions have been amply proved correct. Few modern children can recite more than a
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 24 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
single poem, politicians rely on teleprompters, and humanities scholars make public presentations with
their heads buried in dense texts that leave listeners confused. Socrates' legitimate criticisms
notwithstanding, writing caught on. In fact, writing was soon recognized as providing an invaluable
window on previously unknown phenomena. With writing, for example, the Greeks discovered grammar.
By removing speech from the ephemeral moment, the ancients discovered "parts of speech" (nouns,
adjectives, particles, etc.) as well as tenses, conjugations, sentences, plots, and other structures. In short,
the invention of writing provided an unprecedented opportunity to better understand language, and
(paradoxically) speech.
[141] An almost identical history attended the advent of musical notation. Music theorizing was common
long before music was written down. But music notation unquestionably inspired and facilitated the
growth of music theory in the West. As in the case of written language, musical notation allowed those
who study music to identify patterns of organization that would otherwise be difficult or impossible to
discern.
[142] Of course, like Socrates, musical notation has drawn its critics. Jazz musicians are likely to resonate
with the observations of a nineteenth century Arab traveler to Europe, Faris al-Shidyaq:
"The Franks [Europeans] have no `free' music unbound by those graphic signs of theirs ... so
that if you suggest to one of them that he should sing a couple of lines extempore ... he cannot
do so. This is strange considering their excellence in this art, for singing in this fashion is
natural and was in use among them before these graphic signs and symbols came into being."
[As quoted in Nettl, 1985, p.123]
[143] A perhaps unfortunate repercussion of musical notation has been the reification of notation as
music. The very noun "music" has today acquired meanings that would have confounded ancient
musicians. In modern times it is possible for "music" to fall off a stand or to be eaten by one's dog.
Consider philosopher Nelson Goodman's well-known conception of the identity of the musical work:
"A score, whether or not ever used as a guide for a performance, has as a primary function the
authoritative identification of a work from performance to performance. Often scores and
notations -- and pseudo-scores and pseudo-notations -- have such other more exciting
functions as facilitating transposition, comprehension, or even composition; but every score,
as a score, has the logically prior office of identifying a work." (Goodman, 1976/1981;
p.128).
For Goodman, the notion of the existence of a musical work devoid of any score is a highly complex and
thorny philosophical issue. In Goodman's view, the very identity of "music" is intimately linked and
equated with material notational artifacts of a certain sort. This is what is meant by "reification."
[144] As in the case of written language and musical notation, quantitative methods provide (1) important
opportunities for glimpsing otherwise invisible patterns of organizations, and (2) similar opportunities for
reification and fetishism. Scholarly attitudes toward musical notation are rightly mixed: notation has
provided extraordinary opportunities for scholarly inquiry, but it has also spawned some moot and
questionable beliefs regarding the nature of the musical world.
[145] In the case of applying quantitative methods in music scholarship, we are a long way away from
such excesses. On the contrary, music scholarship has barely begun to take advantage of the genuine
opportunities provided for better understanding musical organization. Of the many examples that can be
used to illustrate the promise of quantitative empirical methods, two examples must suffice. My first
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 25 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
example relates to the concept of the "melodic arch" whereas the second example relates to the concept of
"gap fill".
[149] In Huron's study, each of the alternative notions of a "melodic arch" converged on the same answer.
Although there are many individual phrases that do not exhibit an arch-shape, the great majority of
phrases do indeed have a roughly ascending-descending contour. That is, the results are consistent with a
general theoretical notion of a melodic arch (at least in Western folksong melodies). One might suppose
that averaging together thousands of melodic phrases constitutes the epitome of quantitative lunacy. Yet,
such simple quantitative procedures can prove remarkably useful in addressing certain kinds of musical
questions.
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 26 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Gap Fill
[150] A common criticism of empirical studies in music is that they merely confirm our intuitions. A good
counter-example is provided by the phenomenon of "gap fill." For 500 years, music scholars have
observed that large melodic leaps tend to be followed by changes of melodic direction. This phenomena
goes under a number of names, but let us use Leonard Meyer's terminology: "gap fill."
[151] In a series of empirical studies, Paul von Hippel (2000a, 2000b, von Hippel & Huron, 2000) carried
out extensive empirical investigations of the gap fill concept. The results are not at all consistent with
music theorists' intuitions about gap fill. The story has two parts:
(1) It is indeed the case that the majority of large intervals tend to be followed by a change in
melodic direction. This pattern occurs in melodies from cultures spanning five continents and
500 years. This pattern is evident both for immediate pitch continuations, as well as delayed
pitch continuations.
However ...
(2) If you completely scramble the order of notes within a melody, you end up with "random"
melodies that tend to have exactly the same amount of gap fill as the original melodies
themselves. This pattern occurs in melodies from cultures spanning five continents and 500
years.
[152] The fact that scrambled (randomly reordered) versions of the same melodies produce the same gap
fill tendency suggests that gap fill is not a consequence of compositional intent.
[153] There is a straightforward explanation for why this happens -- a phenomenon that statisticians call
"regression toward the mean". A large leap will have a tendency to take the melody towards the upper or
lower extremes of a melody's range. Having landed (say) near the top of the range, the melody has little
choice but to continue with one of the lower notes. In real music, the closer the leap is to the extremes of
the range, the more likely the contour changes direction. When a leap lands in the middle of the tessitura,
reversing direction is no more common than continuing in the same direction.
[154] Quantitatively, this account is very strong. After accounting for regression-toward-the-mean, there
is no residual melodic behavior that can be attributed to a hypothetical principle of gap fill. While
research on peripheral aspects of this issue continues, at this point it appears that "gap fill" is a musical
concept without any reality in a large and diverse sample of actual notated music {10}.
Pgina 27 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Pgina 28 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
changes in a field that ought to cause us to revisit and revise our methodological strategies and
commitments. In the remaining sections, we consider some of the misconceptions and failures that attend
either (1) failing to recognize field-specific differences, or (2) failing to recognize changing conditions
within a field of research.
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 29 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
[169] Over the decades, a number of humanities scholars have criticized contemporary psychology and
sociology for adopting methods more commonly associated with the physical sciences. However, these
criticisms are based on the false assumption that disciplines are defined, not only by their subject matter,
but also by their methods. As we have seen, methods arise not from the subject of research, but by the
riskiness of the hypotheses, by the availability of pertinent data, by the ability of researchers to observe
the effects of a priori manipulations, and by the opportunity to collect evidence independent from the
original evidence used to formulate some theory or interpretation.
[170] It is wrong, I believe, to portray methodologies as competing philosophical allegiances. It is not a
question of whether "scientific" methods prevail over interpretive, hermeneutic, phenomenological, or
other traditional humanities methods, or vice versa. The question is whether researchers use the best
methodology (or `basket' of methods) for the task at hand.
[171] To many scholars, it appears that over the course of the twentieth century, the humanities "lost" a
number of disciplines -- including linguistics, archeology, psychology, and (to a lesser extent)
anthropology and sociology. I disagree. The subject matter of these disciplines has changed little over the
past century. Linguists are still interested in the origins, structures and acquisition of human languages.
Archaeologists are still interested in how artifacts inform us about past human civilizations. Psychologists
are still interested in human thoughts and motivations. Sociologists and anthropologists are still interested
in the nature of human interaction and the nature of culture. In each discipline, human beings and human
lives remain central. What has changed for these disciplines is primarily the volume of available evidence
-- and consequently the opportunities to address more refined questions using methods that better exploit
the expanded data resources.
[172] The prospect of gaining access to increased data is not merely an opportunity to be taken or ignored,
as one pleases. Where pertinent data is readily available, it is morally reprehensible not to use it since
failing to use the data increases the likelihood of making both false-positive and false-negative errors. In
short, empirical data deserves our attention for precisely the same reason that small amounts of historical
data warrant the historian's best interpretive efforts: failing to attempt to learn from the information at
hand is to encourage and condone ignorance {11}.
Pgina 30 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
divinity by future equivalents of medieval theologians." (Glashow & Ginsparg, 1986; p.7).
[175] Glashow's allusion to theology is derisive. But particle physicists may need to get used to the
apparently inevitable methodological transformation that awaits their discipline. Humanities scholars can
be forgiven for shedding crocodile tears: for centuries, historians have had to struggle to make sense of
manuscript fragments that they knew would never be made whole. When data is finite, interpretation is
the only scholarly activity that remains. Moreover, the interpretive, hermeneutic enterprise is an activity
that remains of value.
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 31 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Pgina 32 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
deprived of adequate practical education relating to methodology. To the postmodernist skeptic, one must
respond with the reverse skepticism: What if there are truths? What if some truths are knowable? What if
some interpretations are better than others? What if we fail to learn from the evidence that is available to
us?
Conclusion
[186] By way of review, the basic arguments I have presented can be reconstructed and summarized as
follows:
1. Postmodernists are right to note that knowledge claims do not take place in a moral vacuum.
Theories, hypotheses, interpretations and opinions carry moral (and esthetic) repercussions.
Moreover, choosing to avoid making knowledge claims is similarly an act with moral
consequences.
2. Anyone wishing to make any knowledge claim about the world, has no choice but to navigate the
treacherous path between false positive and false negative errors. This includes claims that say `I
don't know' and `We cannot know.' There is nothing epistemologically safer about these negative
claims compared with the corresponding positive claims `I know' or `In principal, we can know.'
3. The "Problem of Induction" is intractable and omnipresent: no amount of observation can establish
the truth of some proposition. This problem applies not only to empiricism, but also to the critiques
of empiricism offered by anti-foundationalist writers like Feyerabend. No amount of observation
about the history of science can establish the general claim that the enterprise of science is irrational
or arational.
4. Despite the problem of induction, observation remains indispensable to knowledge in ways we do
not understand. Our very biological machinery has evolved to facilitate acquiring knowledge about
the world. We can show that observations are consistent with some theories and not other theories -even though we cannot prove that one theory is better than another.
5. Fields of study differ according to the volume and quality of available evidence ("data") used to
support or assess different claims, views, interpretations, or theories.
6. When data are inaccessible or non-existent, the field is susceptible to the positivist fallacy -- that
absence of evidence can be interpreted as evidence of absence.
7. Data-poor fields are unable to support research whose goal is to minimize false-positive claims.
Theory-discarding skeptics therefore avoid pursuing research in data-poor fields; they conclude that
no conclusions can be drawn from the available data.
8. Other scholars will recognize the possibly onerous moral repercussions from failing to attempt to
learn from small amounts of data/evidence. Data-poor fields will attract only theory-conserving
skeptics, that is, scholars whose goal is to minimize false-negative claims.
9. When the volume of data is small, false-negative skeptics are logically consistent when they
support multiple alternative hypotheses or interpretations. Pluralism is therefore preferred over
parsimony. Conclusions are open rather than closed.
10. Unfortunately, scholars working in data-poor fields will typically make innumerable false-positive
errors. That is, many ideas will be promulgated that lack merit.
11. Data-rich fields provide greater power for hypothesis testing. More stringent criteria allow testing
that minimizes false-positive claims. As a result, competing hypotheses can be rejected with some
assurance. Parsimony is therefore preferred to pluralism. Researchers aim for closed explanations.
12. Data can also be characterized as retrospective or prospective. Retrospective data invites two
methodological problems. First, retrospective data is susceptible to unfettered "story-telling:"
scholars are adept at formulating theories that account for any existing set of data. That is, it is
tempting to use retrospective data both to formulate an explanatory theory and to provide evidence
in support of the theory. A second problem with retrospective data is that possible causal
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 33 de 40
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
25/04/15 18:51
[187] In this paper, I have endeavored to rekindle the view that the humanities are distinguished from the
sciences primarily by their subject matter, and secondarily by a philosophical tendency towards
humanistic rather than mechanistic conceptions of the world. More importantly, I have argued against the
idea that the sciences and humanities are necessarily distinguished by their methodological habits. It is
true that humanities disciplines currently tend to embrace false-negative skepticism, tend to be historical
in orientation, tend to prefer pluralism to parsimony, and tend to prefer open accounts rather than closed
explanations. However, I have noted that these methodological tendencies primarily arise from the
structures and material circumstances attending the particular fields of study involved. Specifically, many
humanities disciplines (though not all) are comparatively data-poor, deal with lower risk hypotheses, and
are unable to carry out formal experiments. Data-poor disciplines repel false-positive skeptics because
such disciplines provide an environment where false-positive skepticism is not productive.
[188] My claim that methodological differences arise primarily from the concrete research conditions of
individual disciplines should evoke no surprise. Philosophers of knowledge all presume that what might
loosely be called "rationality" is not discipline-specific. What is good for the epistemological goose ought
to be good for the epistemological gander as well.
[189] Fields of study do have discipline-specific methodological needs. For example, manuscript studies
have developed analytic methods based on water marks, chain lines, binding patterns, and so on. But there
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 34 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
are also underlying patterns to how different disciplines approach their goals, and there are some unifying
principles in research. In summary, while the humanities and sciences may rightly diverge in their
philosophical conceptions about the nature of the world, they nevertheless share deep methodological
commonalities. All fields of study can greatly benefit from an awareness of both the wide variety of
available research methods and the innumerable pointers to methodological potholes.
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 35 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
[197] In light of the above observations concerning methodology, it should be obvious that I think both
humanities scholars and scientists should be educated with an aim to providing a broader repertoire of
research methodologies. In particular, humanities scholars ought to learn the basics of statistical inference,
and scientists ought to be exposed to phenomenological and deconstructionist approaches.
[198] Finally, moral and ethical philosophers should take a greater interest in epistemological ethics.
Knowledge claims have consequences, and it is important for scholars to be cognizant of the moral and
esthetic repercussions of their views -- including the view that something is unknowable. Better research
on risk is needed in order to help researchers recognize when to adopt a theory-conserving or theorydiscarding stance.
Footnotes
{1} It should be noted that the term "Positivism" is rarely used by modern empiricists; however, it is a
designation commonly used in humanities scholarship, hence our use of it here. For a discussion of the socalled "culture wars" see: Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont, Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern
Intellectuals' Abuse of Science, New York: Picador, 1998; and Joseph Natoli's A Primer to Postmodernity,
Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1997 -- notably Chapter 8: Postmodernity's War with Science. Return.
{2} See Belsey (1993), Feyerabend (1975), Foucault (1970, 1977), Hartsock (1990), Kuhn (1962/1970),
Natoli (1997). Return.
{3} In the pithy words of Foucault, "There is no power relation without the correlative constitution of a
field of knowledge, nor any knowledge that does not presuppose and constitute at the same time power
relations." (p. 27). Return.
{4} Throughout this article, the word "theory" should be interpreted broadly to mean any claim,
hypothesis, theory, interpretation or view. Return.
{5} A standard textbook on scientific method notes the following: "In contrast to the consequences of
publishing false results, the consequences of a Type II error are not seen as being very serious." (Cozby,
1989; p. 147). Return.
{6} It is essential to recommend new rather than established quacks. Established quackery has usually
been the subject of research that has failed to establish its efficacy. Untested quackery has a better chance
of being helpful. Return.
{7} Once again, the reader is reminded that throughout this article, the word "data" should be interpreted
broadly to mean any information or evidence. Return.
{8} An example will be given later in this article. Return.
{9} "In musical interpretations, complexity is cherished ... In the social sciences, complexity seems to be
avoided: the details of phenomena are levelled so that the findings can be expressed in the simplest
possible way." (Rahn, 1983; p. 197).
{10} Statisticians have written extensively about the phenomenon of regression-toward-the-mean.
Unfortunately, it appears to be a concept that is difficult for humans to grasp. Even Nobel laureate, W.F.
Sharpe, incorrectly mistook regression-toward-the-mean for a new economic phenomenon (see, for
example, Gary Smith, "Do Statistics Test Scores Regress Toward the Mean?"). As often happens with
significant discoveries, a careful literature search sometimes finds that the same discovery was made
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 36 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
decades earlier by another scholar. In a 1924 study, Henry Watt suggested that gap-fill in music can be
attributed to regression toward the mean. Given the poor level of statistical numeracy among music
scholars, I predict that it will take another 70 years before the preponderance of music theorists
understand what has been demonstrated regarding gap fill. Return.
{11} There may be statistical reasons for excluding some data from an analysis. Return.
References
Agassi, Joseph. 1975.
Science in Flux. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Co.
Anderson, Philip. 1972.
More is different. Science, Aug. 4, 1972, pp.393Ayer, Alfred J. 1936
Language, Truth and Logic. London: Victor Gollantz.
Belsey, Catherine. 1993.
"Towards Cultural History," in: A Postmodern Reader, J. Natoli & L. Hutcheon (eds.) New York: SUNY
Press, pp. 561, 555-556 [sic]. Quote is from page 561.
Cozby, Paul C. 1989.
Method in Behavioral Research. Mountain View, CA: Mayfield Publishing Co., 4th edition.
Cook, Nicholas. 1990.
Music, Imagination, and Culture. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Duhem, Pierre. 1905.
La Thorie Physique: Son Objet, Sa Structure. Paris: Marcel Rivire; 2nd edition, 1914. Translated by P.P.
Wiener as: The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1954;
reprinted New York: Atheneum, 1962, 1977.
Elster, Jon. 1989.
Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Feyerabend, Paul. 1975.
Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge. London: Verso Editions 7.
Fischer, David H. 1970.
Historians' Fallacies: Towards a Logic of Historical Thought. New York: Harper Collins.
Fitt, Mary. 1959.
Diels' Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. Translated by Kathleen Freeman as Ancilla to The pre-Socratic
philosophers: A complete translation. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1983; 5th edition.
Foucault, Michel. 1970.
The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. New York: Pantheon, 1970.
Foucault, Michel. 1977.
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 37 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. New York: Vintage/Random House.
Gell-Mann, Murray. 1994.
The Quark and the Jaguar. New York: W.H. Freeman.
Gellner, Ernest. 1974.
Legitimation of Belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Glashow, Sheldon & Ginsparg, Paul. 1986.
Desperately seeking superstrings. Physics Today, May 1986, p.7.
Gleick, James. 1987.
Chaos: Making a New Science. New York: Penguin Books.
Goldin, Claudia & Rouse, Cecilia. 2000.
Orchestrating impartiality: The impact of `blind' auditions on female musicians. American Economic
Review, September 2000.
Goodman, Nelson. 1976/1981.
Languages of Art; An Approach to a Theory of Symbols, Brighton, Sussex: Harvester Press.
Gould, S.J. 1978.
Sociobiology: The art of storytelling. New Scientist, Vol. 80, pp. 530-533.
Gould, S.J., & Lewontin, R.C. 1979.
The spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian program: A critique of the adaptationist programme.
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Vol. 250, pp. 281-288.
Hacking, Ian. 1995.
Rewriting the Soul: Multiple Personality and the Sciences of Memory. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton
University Press.
Hartsock, Nancy. 1990.
"Foucault on power: A theory for women?" In: Linda Nicholson (ed.) Feminism/Postmodernism. New
York: Routledge.
Hattiangadi, Jagdish N. 1983.
A methodology without methodological rules. In: R. Cohen & M. Wartofsky (eds.), Language, Logic, and
Method. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Co., pp. 103-151.
von Hippel, Paul. 2000a.
Redefining pitch proximity: Tessitura and mobility as constraints on melodic intervals. Music Perception,
Vol. 17, No. 3, pp. 315-327.
von Hippel, Paul. 2000b.
Questioning a melodic archetype: Do listeners use gap-fill to classify melodies? Music Perception, Vol.
18, No. 2, pp. 139-153.
von Hippel, Paul, & Huron, David. 2000.
Why do skips precede reversals? The effect of tessitura on melodic structure. Music Perception, Vol 18,
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 38 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
Pgina 39 de 40
25/04/15 18:51
1959.
Rahn, John. 1983.
A Theory for All Music: Problems and solutions in the analysis of non-Western forms. Toronto: Toronto
University Press.
Rahn, John. 1993.
"Differences" Perspectives of New Music, Vol. 31, No. 2, pp. 58-71.
Quine, Willard Van. 1953.
From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Roberts, Clayton. 1996.
The Logic of Historical Explanation. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Rosen, D.E. 1982.
Telostean interrelationships, morphological function and evolutionary inference. American Zoologist, Vol.
22, pp. 261-273.
Seay, Albert. 1975.
Music in the Medieval World. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall Inc.
Watt, Henry J. 1924.
Functions of the size of interval in the songs of Schubert and of the Chippewa [i.e., Ojibway] and Teton
Sioux [i.e., Lakota] Indians. British Journal of Psychology, Vol. 14, No. 4, pp. 370-386.
Webb, E.J., Campbell, D.T., Schwartz, R.D., Sechrest, R., and Grove, J.B. 1981.
Nonreactive Measures in the Social Sciences. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 2nd edition.
This document is available at http://dactyl.som.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
http://musiccog.ohio-state.edu/Music220/Bloch.lectures/3.Methodology.html
Pgina 40 de 40