The Emergence of Eternal Life
The Emergence of Eternal Life
The Emergence of Eternal Life
The question of whether life exists beyond death remains one of the
most pertinent of our existence, and theologians continue to address
what relevance the answer has for our life in the present. In this
book, William J. Hoye employs the phenomenon of emergence
the way higher forms of existence arise from a collection of simpler
interactions as a framework for understanding and defending the
concept of Eternal Life, showing how it emerges from our present
life, our human longing for fulfillment and happiness, and our
striving for knowledge of reality. Hoye uses the work of Karl Rahner
and Thomas Aquinas to explore questions concerning suffering, the
ultimate relevance of morality, and how the fundamental idea of
responsibility changes when viewed eschatologically. Contemporary
reasons for denying an afterlife are examined critically and extensively.
This book will be of great interest to those studying systematic
theology, theological anthropology, and Catholic theology.
william j. hoye is Professor of Systematic Theology at the University of Munster. He is the author of many books, including most
recently Die Wirklichkeit der Wahrheit (2013); Tugenden. Was sie wert
sind, warum wir sie brauchen (2010); Liebgewordene theologische Denkfehler (2006); and Die mystische Theologie des Nicolaus Cusanus (2004).
THE EMERGENCE OF
ET ERNAL LIF E
WILLIAM J. HOYE
I. Title.
To
my friend Mitch,
Alden F. Mitchell
Contents
Difficulties
The Experience Prejudice
The Praxis Prejudice
Hedonism
The ambivalent teaching of Christian Faith
3.3
3.4
3.5
3.6
3.7
3.8
3.9
The question
Transcendental hope in ones own resurrection as the horizon for
experiencing the resurrection of Jesus
Reality as the liberating horizon
Wonder
By his very nature man strives for fulfillment
The rationality of reality
The final and comprehensive goal of human nature
The expectation of the fulfillment of human desire
The compatibility of the dogma on hell with the foregoing
argumentation
4.4
4.5
4.6
vii
page 1
5
10
13
13
20
42
58
64
77
77
80
84
85
86
92
97
99
104
111
112
119
120
122
129
135
viii
Contents
4.7
4.8
4.9
4.10
4.11
144
148
153
157
167
169
169
171
176
180
181
183
191
201
204
216
237
243
247
249
252
258
276
Bibliography
Index
278
290
chapter o ne
of what God is. It is typical for contemporary culture that serious people,
including scientists, believe that they know with clear certainty and without
further ado that there exists no life after death. They need not bother
studying theology; they know it quasi-intuitively. On the one hand, this
attitude has the positive aspect in that it shows that a theological position
is something that everyman has, but, on the other hand, it also reveals the
light-mindedness that prevails in theological matters.
Educated believers in Eternal Life are normally well acquainted with the
thesis that it is merely a wish projection or simply a pious imagination
for the purpose of distracting ones attention from the responsibilities or
joys of this world. Who today is not aware of the Marxist criticism of
religion? Rather, one is surprised that these critical objections continue to
be repeated.
A careful agnosticism is easier to respect. Applying the principle of
Occams Razor, the believer can take the burden of proof on himself. But
it is one thing to argue in favor of ones own belief and another to refute
negations. A negation should be falsifiable if it purports to make a truth
claim.
The skeptical argument that one cannot imagine a life after death or,
better, cannot understand it or cannot even think of it responsibly cannot
be answered with the remark, first of all, that the believer need not maintain
that our imagination can have any validity in this matter. It is no great feat
to realize that the afterlife transcends imagination.
Thinking about it is another matter. If the afterlife could not be an object
of thought in any way, then we would have to consider it to be nothing,
and then it would be impossible to believe in it. But it is possible to know
that something is not understandable, that it transcends understanding
and this can be thought and demonstrated.
A peculiarity of Eternal Life is that it challenges understanding. It attacks
the prevalent mindset. For us, it is especially difficult to conceive of because
it stands in contradiction to our contemporary understanding of reality. In
the long run, this is, in fact, even a plausible reason for positively believing
in Eternal Life not in the sense that I believe because it is absurd but
rather that I believe because it challenges my understanding.
In fact, the Christian idea of Eternal Life seems rather to be a provocation,
for it teaches that the purpose and result of all of our work consists finally in
knowledge of some kind. And Eternal Life is this: to know you, the only
true God, and Jesus Christ whom you have sent (Jn 17:3). Specifically,
it is knowledge of God, which is what we are ultimately striving for in
whatsoever we pursue. All human activity has intellectual speculation for
its end, as Thomas Aquinas dares to put it.1 This tells the man of praxis
that his happiness consists in theory. The knowledge of God therefore is
the final end of all human study and activity.2 Life has ultimate meaning
only at its end. The opium that Christianity has to offer is hardly what
the average person today would consider to be a desirable pleasure, not to
mention the fact that hell is also a component of Christian eschatology
and can hardly be called opium.
How is a teaching like this to be rendered comprehensible? If Eternal
Life is what human beings are really interested in, then the relevancy of an
intellectual pursuit of the question should be evident in any case.
It is possible that we have replaced our belief in the afterlife with a belief
in something in this world. The popular idea that ones immortality consists
in being remembered by others in the future might be an example of this
kind of secularization. A similar idea is that we can achieve perpetuity in
our works. Of course, this is not a real ersatz for eternity. Remembrance,
books, and art works may have a practically unlimited duration, but they
are obviously not eternal and offer no really adequate solution to the
problem of death. Death assumes the role of the Final Judgment and gives
rise to the problem of perpetuity.3 What in the Christian perspective had
been called acedia becomes depression in the secularized world.4
Max Horkheimer expressed the hypothesis that the idea of society may
also represent a secularized form of life after death. The individual lives his
own life to its natural end and has contributed in some way to the life of
society. Society itself takes on the aura of eternity. An indication of this can
be seen in the strength of protests against weapons that could annihilate all
mankind. The species seems to contain more reality and importance than
the sum of the individual members. Horkheimer states: The meaning that
every action in life won from the thought of eternity is replaced by the
absolutizing of the collective, in which the individuals feel integrated.5
1
3
2 Ibid.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 25.
Rosa, Beschleunigung, 288, suggests that the relinquishment of the idea of a life after death having
validity beyond question and supported as a binding cultural component, from which and with
respect to which life before death receives its meaning and direction, must unavoidably have to put
into question the basis of its subjective and cultural meaning . . . If previously the end of ones own
life was seen in a perspective with the expected end of the world, which, at the same time, signalized
the beginning of true time, both time horizons moved visibly apart owing to the fading of the
latter (emphasis in original).
It is a question of a psychic condition that is characterized by barrenness and emptiness (accompanied at the same time by an inner restlessness) and a paralysis of the soul as the result of the
souls inability to direct its energy toward a firm, definitive and convincingly worthwhile goal and
energetically develop it. Ibid., 388.
Horkheimer, Bedrohung, 21.
Under this presumption, the possibility that human society could some
day be extinguished appears unbearable.
The teleological structure of such ideas at least resembles and is presumably inherited from Christian belief. The final state gives meaning to
every action. The expected future classless society serves as the justification
for present activity. The whole relationship between the final state and the
meaning of life is characteristic. Marxism, for example, justifies present
activity on the basis of an expected future state. Daily life does not exhaust
its significance within the bounds of each day. Understanding life as a
network of final causes, culminating in an ultimate final cause, is possibly
a frame of thinking that is simply natural and unavoidable.
More essential than such comparisons is an analysis based on concrete
experience. What is the most important aspect of life as we know it?
Although this question is not so easily answered, I think that it would be
safe to say that reality, or the awareness of reality, is what is most important
to human beings. If you imagined a situation in which you could have
something desirable say, pleasure or a friend but without this being real
(in the sense of being more than merely my own subjectivity), what would
you prefer: reality with its normal pains and problems or pleasure as nothing
more than a feeling or your friend but only as an imagined thought? Are we
really happiest when we are day-dreaming? As Augustine remarked: And
how much human nature loves the knowledge of its existence, and how it
shrinks from being deceived, will be sufficiently understood from this fact
that every man prefers to grieve in a sane mind, rather than to be glad in
madness.6 Since the presence of reality is what I would call truth, the
question is whether one prefers living in truth or in falsehood regardless
of how delightful the falsehood may be. This makes it understandable
how Thomas Aquinas can claim that what gives us most delight is the
knowledge of divine things, regardless of how inadequate it may be:
Everything desires most of all its own last end. But the human mind is
moved to more desire and love and delight over the knowledge of divine
things, little as it can discern about them, than over the perfect knowledge
that it has of the lowest things.7
Otherwise, this assertion that knowledge of God is the goal of human life
would sound incredible.
Admittedly, the notion of emergence does not provide a concrete explanation of how something occurs, but it does, at least, convey the rudimentary
knowledge that what occurs is real, that is, a participation in reality.
Reality does not simply exist, it changes and develops. Reality happens.
Reality is not merely a collection of realities. It is more like an energy field.
It is dynamic; it is moving, evolving. Within it, new realities can emerge.
New wholes are more than the sum of the elements out of which they
have arisen. The analogy to light is helpful. Light is not just there, it is
happening, it is energy making, as it were, colors emerge in objects. If
the light desists, so do the colors immediately.
The idea of a whole is, of course, an analogous notion. There are wholes
that are nothing more than a collection of elements; however, it is important
to acknowledge that there exist many wholes that are more than their
elements. A melody is more than a collection of notes. A word is more
than a collection of letters. Dgo is not a word, dog is. And dog, again,
is more than a word; it is also a notion, possessing meaning, which is more
8
Ibid., c. 53.
than just the word. Furthermore, a sentence is more than the words of
which it is composed; in contrast to words, a sentence can have the quality
of being true or false. Out of letters, meaning emerges; out of words, truth.
Out of matter, life emerges, an animal being more than the chemicals of
which it is composed. Out of living beings, conscious life emerges; out of
human life, Eternal Life which is, so to speak, the meaning of human
life, like the notion connected with the word.
As the classical principle, found in Aristotle, asserts: in some cases, the
whole is greater than the sum of its parts, that is, more than just a heap.9 In
this case, Aristotle concludes that there must be a cause of the unification of
wholes that are more than aggregates. He calls the cause reality [;
actus], which is more than a reality. The cause of the whole that is a
human being is then the soul, the primordial act of reality [actus primus]
of a natural body having the potentiality to live. It is extremely difficult
to translate the Greek word energeia [] or the Latin word actus
into contemporary language. Should one say reality or actuality? Since
actuality is obviously the translation of actualitas, which was coined in
medieval theology during the lifetime of Thomas Aquinas and used by him
as distinct from actus the phrase actualitas omnium actuum (although it
occurs only once in Thomass work) is important I prefer using the
translation reality. One must remember, however, that reality is to be
thought of in the sense of an act, or actualization, or realization, that is,
not as a collection of elements. Reality is not simply a universal notion;
it is more like a light field, in which colors emerge.
A different approach to the phenomenon of the emergence of organic
species in time employs the idea of so-called seminal reasons [rationes
seminales]. With this notion, Augustine explained how there can be development within creation. Accordingly, when God originally created the
world, he instilled things with seminal reasons that is, virtual principles of things later to evolve. With time, they develop into actual being.
Evolution is, accordingly, the maturation of quasi-seeds, hidden in matter
from the beginning. Consequently, change is simply the realization of what
already exists virtually. The concept was possibly influenced by Platos theory of recollection, according to which knowledge involves remembering
what one already knew. Bonaventure is a later defender of this idea, arguing
that the forms that come into existence are all present in matter. The substance of matter, he writes, is pregnant with everything.10 This would
9
10
be like taking the immortality of the spiritual soul for the cause of Eternal
Life, implying that the cause lies within the nature of human beings.
It is more plausible to interpret Eternal Life as a case of what is called
emergence, provided that emergence be viewed ontologically that is,
as a development of being. The result is not already present from the start,
but a capacity for it is. Obviously, existing reality contains more realities
than have been thus far revealed. It evolves and grows. When an individual
grows, reality grows. Reality happens. Light reveals more about reality than,
say, a stone. As shown herein, new realities are not merely collections of their
parts. In this case, the whole is more than its parts. It may well be that new
realities are susceptible to a method of reduction, but evolution cannot be
adequately explained by the factors that can be found by reduction. What
develops is not predestined in the original elements from which it arises. In
view of evolutionary phenomena such as loss-of-function mutations, not
all evolution can be explained by reductionism.11
The physicist Philip W. Anderson (Princeton University) describes the
principle of emergence as a philosophical foundation for modern science.12
As he puts it: The watchword is not reductionism but emergence. Emergent complex phenomena are by no means a violation of the microscopic
laws, but they do not appear as logically consequent on these laws13 a
potentia obedientialis (see page 103), so to speak. The method of reduction
cannot be reversed, so that developments would be predestined. Anderson
notes:
The ability to reduce everything to simple fundamental laws does not imply
the ability to start from those laws and reconstruct the universe. The constructionist hypothesis breaks down when confronted with the twin difficulties of scale and complexity. At each level of complexity entirely new
properties appear. Psychology is not applied biology, nor is biology applied
chemistry. We can now see that the whole becomes not merely more, but
very different from the sum of its parts.14
11
12
13
Cf. Brandt, Konnen Tiere denken?, 1516: Materialistic reductionism has been overcome by the
new emergence research on biological systems. It has arrived at the acceptance of characteristics that
cannot be predicted by an individual examination of the physical components (physics, chemistry).
This principle of emergence is as pervasive a philosophical foundation of the viewpoint of modern
science as is reductionism. It underlies, for example, all of biology . . . and much of geology. It
represents an open frontier for the physicist, a frontier which has no practical barriers in terms of
expense or feasibility, merely intellectual ones. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA, 92 (July 1995), in an
introductory paper at a colloquium entitled Physics: The Opening to Complexity, held June 26
and 27, 1994, at the National Academy of Sciences, in Irvine, CA, 6653.
14 Anderson, More Is Different, 393396.
Ibid., 66536654.
10
22
11
Ibid.
24
Ibid.
25
Ibid., c. 18.
26
Ibid., c. 19.
12
Ibid.
28
Ibid.
chapter t wo
2.1 Difficulties
This book pursues two intentions: (1) the question of whether there really
exists life beyond death is to be examined as stringently as possible, and
(2) the relevance of such knowledge for our present life is to be studied.
With the ingenuousness appropriate to such questions, I intend to present
an affirmative answer to the first question and to show that life after death
reveals the ultimate meaning of the present life; however, a number of
obstacles stand in the way.
2.1.1 The inevitable naiveness of statements on Eternal Life
The expression life after death is, of course, deliberately naive. Speaking
of after in a context that has to do with eternity has to be either ambivalent
or meaningless. There can be nothing like a continuation in eternity, as
though one continued on to exist after death, although in a different
manner. Furthermore, the term life is not less naive. Nevertheless, this
use of language has advantages over a well-defined technical terminology,
which could convey the impression of precise univocity, whereas obviously
inadequate language serves as a reminder that our theological categories
are ineluctably ambivalent. This rudimentary fact is all the less likely to
escape notice if simple, everyday language is used. Life after death is, in
truth, a paradoxical expression and this is appropriate.
The teaching that no true sentence about God can ever be univocal
was taught not only in the Middle Ages by Thomas Aquinas with his
thesis that notions justly predicated of God are always analogous but
also by someone like the contemporary physicist and philosopher Carl
Friedrich von Weizsacker. He demands from theological statements that
they be both incomprehensible and, nonetheless, stimulating. Logical
univocity, he writes, is the manner in which humans speak of their
13
14
own, for them understandable matters.1 According to him, all talk about
divine things in the human language must have the form of stimulating
incomprehensibility.2
It is quite appropriate when Thomas Aquinas claims that pictures and
symbols of God that are more dissimilar to him are to be preferred to those
that possess more similarity. At the beginning of his Summa theologiae,
Thomas defends this principle. He refers to Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, who wrote: We cannot be enlightened by the divine rays except
they be hidden within the covering of many sacred veils.3 Accordingly,
it is advisable to predicate qualities of God that clearly cannot be taken
literally. It is more fitting to communicate divine things in the figures of
vile bodies than in those of noble bodies. Thomas explains that with this
method,
mens minds are the better preserved from error. For then it is clear that these
things are not literal descriptions of divine truths, which might have been
open to doubt had they been expressed under the figure of nobler bodies,
especially for those who could think of nothing nobler than bodies.4
2 Ibid.
Weizsacker, Wahrnehmung, 267.
Dionysius the Areopagite, De caelesti hierarchia, c. 1. Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 1,
a. 9c.
5 Ibid.
Ibid., ad 3.
2.1 Difficulties
15
16
after their death presents our dominantly secular way of thinking with
excessive demands.
2.1.3 A counterargument: Vain curiosity
Among the arguments that are brought up against the question of life
after death is the well-known criticism that it represents nothing but vain
curiosity. We will never be able to find out anything reliable about it. It
is a matter of believing: either you believe or you do not believe. This
kind of comment is part and parcel of our culture. It makes sense only
on the presumption that Eternal Life has no intrinsic relationship to the
present life. As a critical argument, it is as old as Christianity. Cicero, who
seems to be the originator of the word curiosity, criticized the intellectual
interest in crossing over the borders of knowledge that are defined by
religion. In an excellent historical study of the notion of curiosity, Gunther
Bos notes: At a time preceding Christian authors, Cicero was aware of
the limitation of the human striving for knowledge and a point of great
importance he speaks repeatedly of the curious crossing of the border that
religion set down.6 And, in the second century ad, Apuleius promulgated
in his Metamorphoses a negative view of curiosity that is still influential
today. In this story Lucius is turned into a donkey as a punishment for
his inopportune curiosity [inprospera curiositas]. For Apuleius the highest
degree of forbidden curiosity consists in breaking a divine prohibition.
He speaks of blasphemous curiosity [sacrilegia curiositas]. (The popular
claim that previous to Christianity curiosity had no negative connotation
is obviously untrue.)
Why should it be forbidden to be interested in the goal of life? Through
the objection that such interests are mere curiosity, the project of enquiring
into questions concerning the afterlife seems to lose at once all of its
legitimacy. When I tell someone that I am giving thought to eschatological
questions, I often get the impression that he or she is offended and then
makes comments to the effect that I ought not to continue. We are allowed
to think about all sorts of questions but not about the whole. If a natural
scientist makes negative claims about religious questions that supposedly
are soon to be solved by science or at least shown to be merely pseudoquestions, even some theologians not rarely accept this and retreat. But
why should it be a priori impossible to pose questions about the meaning
of life? Why should we have to go through life blindly, on our way to some
end but without any awareness of what this end might be? Why should
6
17
2.1 Difficulties
we be able to set our own goals to take our life, as it is said, in our own
hands but incapable of integrating these goals into an organic unity?
Why must the purposes that I envision in my life remain in a hopelessly
disintegrated state? Why can short-range goals be possible but a final goal
remains out of the question? Why does the question about the ultimate goal
of all my goals become mere curiosity? From this question, it is worthwhile
noting, Aristotle developed his entire ethics and political philosophy.
What am I to think when the statement is expressed without any
justification that we can know only that there exists an afterlife but that
we know nothing about what it is and yet, nonetheless, that this knowledge,
coming from divine Revelation, is supposed to serve as a guidepost? This
is at least how I understand the following teaching of Joseph Ratzingers:
We found that, at any rate to some extent, we could extrapolate from the
present life to the existence if not the character of the life to come. Yet the
content of eternal life, what it is [Was] as distinct from its existence [Dass],
lies completely outside the scope of our experience, being quite simply
unknowable from our perspective. And so, in the concluding chapter of this
book, as we reflect on the hints which divine revelation offers about this
what-it-is [Was], in its fundamental possibilities, we must be alert to the
limitations of what we can say. The tradition of faith is not given to us for
the satisfying of idle curiosity. Where it exceeds the proper limits of human
experience, its aim is to direct us, not to divert, that is, to entertain us. This
is why it opens up what lies beyond only to the extent that this will be a
helpful signpost for those in the here and now.7
This would seem to imply that disbelievers are quite abandoned. The
classical idea of the inborn desire of human nature [desiderium naturale] is
replaced by a supernaturalism. In truth, as we shall see, intellectual curiosity
is essential to our question. The unquenchable striving for knowledge of
reality will be shown to be fundamental.
The same view can be found in the standard work Mysterium Salutis:
Eschatology in the New Testament does not intend to be a teaching on
the far-off end of the ages but an illumination and proclamation of the
present.8
The principles that Ratzinger formulates sound unassuming, but one
can question whether they can be conceived meaningfully. If it were true
that that which lies completely beyond the sphere of our experience is
from our standpoint utterly unknowable, then it would not be plausible
to me how divine Revelation can convey such knowledge. No one less than
St. Thomas Aquinas discards this possibility a priori. For him, Revelation
7
18
does not alter Gods unknowableness.9 To the contrary, the insight into
Gods unknowableness encompasses any such Revelation. Revelation does
not transcend this insight but rather serves to intensify it. According to
Thomas, the truth of Faith gives support to the divine unknowableness.10
The reason for this lies not in the nature of Revelation but rather in human
nature. Because Revelation has to reach human beings, it presupposes a
listener, a hearer of the Word. Grace presupposes nature [gratia supponit
naturam], to quote a Scholastic axiom. Thus, human nature transcendentally lays down a condition for the possibility of divine Revelation. Even
divine Revelation is unable to reveal to a hearer what he or she is by nature
unable to understand.11 However, this does not apply to concrete aspects of
Revelation; it is the fundamental mode that is pre-determined. Although
we are elevated by Revelation to know something that would otherwise be
unknown to us, states Thomas, nevertheless, we would not know anything in any other manner than through sensibles.12 Corporality remains
for Aquinas an unconditional dimension.
This implies that theologians cannot avoid disputing with philosophers.
Theology should not, however, let itself be superseded by philosophy. In
Thomass mind, there is no doubt that Christian Revelation brings new
knowledge. What he denies is only that the question of Gods unknowableness is influenced by it:
Although concerning God we do not know through the Revelation of grace
in this life what God is and thus are united with him as with the unknown,
nevertheless we do know him more fully insofar as more and higher effects
of his are shown to us and insofar as we attribute to him some things out
of divine Revelation that cannot be reached by natural reason, for example,
that God is triune and one.13
2.1 Difficulties
19
17
20
21
with God, and this union is a conscious union. It is obvious, then, that
Christianity cannot do without a notion of experience in its worldview. It
is absolutely dependent on a notion of experience that extends far enough
and deep enough to embrace the eternal vision of God himself. It must
therefore be acknowledged that Eternal Life seems in some way to be an
experiential fact, albeit no one has been there and returned with a factual
report. Nevertheless, experience taken in the usual sense seems to speak
against a belief in the afterlife.
The purpose of the present subchapter is not only to criticize the usual
notion of experience but also, above all, to broaden and deepen the customary notion of experience so that it can be valid for eschatology. What
I refer to as the Experience Prejudice is the restriction of experience to
the empirical, the sensual. The crucial breakthrough here must be the
awareness that experience embraces more than facts that is, more than
the given (data) in experience. If the Christian worldview is true, then the
realm of conscious experience is more far-reaching than one would normally presume. The notion of Erlebnis (see pages 3941) bears witness to
this.
The Experience Prejudice is the conviction that only that is real which
in some way or another is an object of empirical experience or is somehow
related to empirical experience; in its simplest form: I will only believe
it if I see it. The point of view of this prejudice is a conviction that
is presupposed without further reasoning; conversely, its filter effect is
comprehensive. It requires a priori that anything like Eternal Life must
be judged to be superfluous since it lies by definition beyond time
experience, as we know it, being something temporal. Experience is empirical, it is the participation of consciousness in empirical reality. The Experience Prejudice, which is a typical fundamental presumption of our age,
presents a major hindrance to a belief in a life after death. Empiricism
is a teaching that defines reality itself as empirical. Reality being empirical, there is no place left for Eternal Life, which cannot be reduced to
a fact or, for that matter, even to something temporal. If it were real,
it is arguable, then one would expect something as presumably important as the afterlife to be in some way empirically noticeable or at least
significant.
Relevant for a theological treatment of Eternal Life are, in particular,
three forms of the Experience Prejudice: neopositivism; Jesus Christ as the
foundation of Christian theology; and the idea of an experience of God,
as frequently understood in theology in the past few decades.
22
Hardly anyone would claim that natural science is the only access we have to
reality the claim itself is self-refuting but the opinion is quite widespread
that it is our most mature and reliable access. Positivism and neopositivism
articulate this common conviction. Positivism is the philosophical belief
that the object of empirical science is reality and vice versa. Reality is
defined as that which can be in any way treated by empirical science.
Expressed negatively: whatever is inaccessible to scientific treatment is
regarded as nonexistent. This viewpoint can be called scientism; it is, of
course, a philosophical decision and is taught in no way by natural science
itself. It makes natural science into a metaphysics. For classical positivism,
religion ranks as a preliminary stage of knowledge that will be superseded
by science.
In his extraordinarily popular book Language, Truth and Logic, Alfred J.
Ayer expresses a straightforward application of the Experience Prejudice:
We conclude, therefore, that the argument from religious experience is altogether fallacious. The fact that people have religious experiences is interesting
from the psychological point of view, but it does not in any way imply that
there is such a thing as religious knowledge . . . The theist . . . may believe
that his experiences are cognitive experiences, but, unless he can formulate
his knowledge in propositions that are empirically verifiable, we may be
sure that he is deceiving himself. It follows that those philosophers who fill
their books with assertions that they intuitively know this or that moral
or religious truth are merely providing material for the psychoanalyst. For
no act of intuition can be said to reveal a truth about any matter of fact
unless it issues in verifiable propositions.18
Ayer states outright what many contemporaries implicitly think. Metaphysics and, consequently, theological statements referring to a transcendent God are not so much false as simply meaningless:
We shall maintain that no statement which refers to a reality transcending the limits of all possible sense-experience can possibly have any literal
significance; from which it must follow that the labors of those who have
striven to describe such a reality have all been devoted to the production of
nonsense.19
19
Ibid., 34.
23
24
the word has come to mean a very tiny quantity. In the expression to add
a pinch of salt, Germans can say Idee instead of pinch. Contemporary
culture has been carrying on a direct polemic against Platonism, retaining
the original Platonic terms and turning their meaning and importance
verily upside down.
The reduction of reality to the concrete reaches a high point in neopositivism. Neopositivism is not difficult to criticize. Because this axiom is itself
certainly not empirically verifiable, it proves itself to be inadequate through
the simple fact that it teaches that only empirically relevant knowledge is
permitted. The Verification Principle or that of Falsification has the
quality of a postulate. It is similar to a dogmatic truth. Because, however, it
is itself not susceptible to verification, a breakthrough is exposed. Through
their own explicit teaching, neopositivists demonstrate that there is truth
that cannot be verified in experience.
A particularly influential adaptation of the Experience Prejudice within
theology is exhibited in the overemphasis of the theological significance
of Jesus Christ. Time is accepted as the horizon of reality. In other words,
history becomes the all-encompassing dimension, and Jesus Christ is a definite historical figure. Treating him as the starting point and foundation of
Christian theology represents the most convincing form of the Experience
Prejudice within theology. The appeal to Christ in a theological argumentation often has the advantage of providing a relationship to experience.
Jesus belongs to the givens of history.
In theology, the Experience Prejudice finds further expression when a
separation is made between the historical Jesus and the Christ of Faith.
This is like someone claiming that the circle on the blackboard is not really
a circle but rather only little heaps of chalk and that the circle exists only
in our imagination. This leads some theologians to a denial of knowledge
about the afterlife with the argument that we have no pictures of it.
The German philosopher Richard Schaeffler pointed out that the
basic mistake of positivism is that experience is treated as self-evident.22
Schaeffler argues that experience has a dimension of transcendental
reflection and that God is the name that names the condition which
makes experience possible.23 God is the only possible explanation because
nothing that occurs within experience can ground experience. If human
transcendentality makes the relationship to objects of consciousness
possible, then an object that appears within the transcendental horizon
cannot be the condition for the opening of this horizon.24 Being not an
object of experience, God is thus the condition for the development of the
22
23
Ibid., 124.
24
Ibid., 119.
25
Rahner, Foundations, 13. (Throughout this volume and unless otherwise noted, Rahner refers to
Karl Rahner.)
26
29
27
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, I, c. 7; John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, n. 43.
32 Ibid., 11.
Cf. Rahner, Foundations, 36.
34 Rahner, Schriften, 5051.
Cf. John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, n. 48.
A letter of July 24, 1968; as quoted in Eicher, Anthropologische Wende, 79, n. 1.
Cf. Fischer, Mensch, 160, n. 109.
28
Both philosophy and theology have the final goal of human existence as
their object.43 Both should be seeking Truth, each with its own autonomy.
Rahner describes the relationship between believing and thinking as a
circular movement between the question and the answer. The question that
the human being himself is presents the condition of the possibility for
hearing the answer that Christian Revelation is. The question establishes
the condition for real hearing, he says, and the answer first brings the
question to its reflective self-givenness.44 The circle runs between the
horizons of understanding and what is said, heard, and understood.45 In
this way, the philosophical presuppositions become a part of the content of
Revelation theology, and philosophy is seen to be a factor within Christian
theology.46
Pope John Paul II expresses a warning about the attempt to separate
theology from philosophy. The result, he notes, would not be an independent theology but rather an impoverished and enfeebled theology.
37
40
44
38 Ibid., n. 5.
39 Cf. ibid., n. 56.
Cf. John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, n. 55.
41 Ibid.
42 Cf. ibid., n. 43.
43 Cf. ibid., n. 15.
Ibid.
45 Rahner, Foundations, 24.
46 Cf. ibid., 25.
Rahner, Schriften, 23.
29
Without philosophy, theology is reduced to particular feelings and experiences. Thus, it would become a study of myths instead of being:
Deprived of reason, Faith has stressed feeling and experience, and so run the
risk of no longer being a universal proposition. It is an illusion to think that
Faith, tied to weak reasoning, might be more penetrating; on the contrary,
Faith then runs the grave risk of withering into myth or superstition. By the
same token, reason which is unrelated to an adult Faith is not prompted to
turn its gaze to the newness and radicality of being.47
Not for pastoral or pedagogical reasons but instead by the very nature of the
revealed word do certain tasks that are the responsibility of theology itself
demand recourse to philosophical enquiry.48 Because of this, the believer
must do philosophy before doing Christology. Faith in Christ presupposes
reason.
2.2.3 The notion of the experience of God
The form of the Experience Prejudice that is most common and influential
within theology is the idea that it is possible to experience God in the
present life. To the best of my knowledge, the term experience of God is
never used in an eschatological context. In another book, I attempted to
come to terms with the idea extensively.49 It might seem at first sight that
the acknowledgment of an experience of God [cognitio Dei experimentalis50 ]
must be supportive of Christian Faith. However, in reality, this prejudgment
has a laming effect on eschatology for it leads to the consequence that it
is difficult to think of anything meaningful under the eschatological term
vision of God. If God could already be experienced in this life, then life
after death would seem to be in principle superfluous because it would
have nothing more to offer than an experience of God. Otherwise, one
would have to conceive of an experience of God in this life that would not
be fulfilling. Rahner finds no better solution than the metaphor of spatial
closeness. In the eschatological vision, God, he teaches, is closer than in
experiences of God in this world. It must be admitted, at least, that it is
difficult to distinguish the heavenly experience of God from the alleged
mystical experience of God before death.
Hans Urs von Balthasar, who during the course of his life dissociated
himself from the notion experience of God,51 confirmed the closeness of
Eternal Life and mysticism, which he described as a thin veil, a foretaste,
47
50
30
54
55
31
be fully happy in this life, then there would be no way of justifying Gods
failure to bring this about; God does not play hide-and-seek games with
us. Concrete suffering is neither absolutely unavoidable nor unnatural and
meaningless when it does occur.
I now attempt to get beyond the notion of an experience of God by
broadening the horizon.56 Not in all Rahner with his idea of a transcendental experience being the best-known example but in most cases,
the notion of an experience of God is closely associated with the idea of
concreteness. An experience is usually concrete and the idea of the concrete
is held in high estimation by our modern mindset. So, most authors using
the term experience of God emphasize its concreteness. The aspect of
concreteness presents a good starting point for an analysis of the idea of
the experience of God.
Facts are concrete. Etymologically, concrete means grown together.
If one wants to do theology that is, to reflect on God then one must first
get beyond facts. Of course, they ought not to be denied, but they must be
transcended. Facts are not simply statically there; as the etymology reveals,
in some way or another, they have been made (Latin factum, thing done,
neuter past participle of facere, to do, to make). Facts must be appreciated
for what they really are. A helpful as well as time-honored analogy can be
drawn to the appreciation of what colors are when one becomes aware that
they are light waves. Colors are, so to speak, the concretization of light, its
concrete forms. Furthermore, they are references to light. Without colors,
light is invisible; when colors are perceived, then one knows, without seeing
it, that light is present.
Although, admittedly, nothing conclusive can be proven from the fact,
it is revealing to note that the word concrete originated in Christian
theology. It reveals a point of view that the Christian idea of creation
has made thinkable. Today, the term which first occurred within highly
abstract theology is part of everyday language. It is conceivable that the
term still includes hidden elements of Christian thought but in a secularized
form. It is perhaps no accident that it has been employed for an antitheological purpose. In its original meaning, concrete signified precisely
that which is not God. God was unhesitatingly considered an abstract
being. A creature was understood as that which has grown together made
as a fact and which is consequently contingent. A creature is susceptible
to corruption. The concrete is thus, by definition, a participation in God
but itself anything but God.
56
For a lengthier treatment of my arguments, the reader may want to consult my book, Gotteserfahrung?
32
A further term belonging to everyday language and originally a theological concept is abstract. Both concrete and abstract taken in an
epistemological sense were coined by the Roman statesman, Christian
philosopher, and theologian Anicius Manlius Torquatus Severinus Boethius
(480524 ad). This occurred in an unmistakably theological work namely,
On the Trinity. There, the term abstract is used to define what theology
is. In contrast to physics and mathematics, theology studies the abstract,
the objects of physics and mathematics being restricted to the inabstract.
Taken in the original sense of the word abstract, one could say that without the abstract, there would be no theology. Today, the word abstract
has ironically taken on a pejorative connotation for theologians as well as
others. At the same time it is often used polemically. The values attached to
the terms abstract and concrete are in this case reversed in comparison
to the original usage. Understood in the contemporary sense, the concrete
possesses more reality than the abstract. The Oxford English Dictionary
gives as the first definition, naming a real thing. This is taken to be
the equivalent of belonging to immediate experience of actual things or
events. Abstract then has just the opposite meaning. It implies being
at a distance from reality; the more abstract something is, the weaker is its
reality. It also has the meaning of abstruse, or difficult to understand.
According to the leading German dictionary, abstract means that something occurs only in thought, being theoretical and without an immediate
relationship to reality.57 As could be expected, concrete then has the
meaning of something real, existing in the world beyond mere thought.
According to the scholarly Historical Dictionary of Philosophy [Historisches
Worterbuch der Philosophie], the presupposition that the concrete represents
the fullest reality was made popular through Marxism.58 It is ironic, then,
when theologians employ the two terms in the same sense; neither is it
surprising that the term experience of God became popular in the last
third of the twentieth century.
Marxism defines the concrete as a unity, or a totality, of various predicates: The concrete is concrete because it is the sum of many predicates,
that is, the unity of the manifold.59 The Philosophical Dictionary [Philosophisches Worterbuch], which was widespread in the German Democratic
Republic, describes concrete as a rich totality of many qualifications and
relationships.60 As in Leibniz, for a totality to be concrete, it must be such
57
58
60
33
that it embodies the possibility of being real. The elements, for example,
may not contradict one another.
For Thomas Aquinas, in contrast, the concrete is already something
real and not the totality of predicates that can become real. In his eyes,
what grows together are only two aspects: essence and being. Something
definable is given existence. An essence can be composed of a limitless
number of elements, whereas being presents only two possibilities. The
concrete is not only a set of compatible predicates; it is a unity of possibility
and actuality. The two questions that can be posed regarding the concrete
are what it is and whether it is. Every experience is qualified by this duality.
The concrete is per se the existent. Accordingly, an imagined object say,
a unicorn is not concrete. The act of existence is not included among
the predicates but is rather united to the predicates in its own right. It
is revealing that words like the existent and reality mean the concrete
whole and, nonetheless, are derived not from the predicates qualifying the
object but instead simply from its act of existence.
Even in mystical experiences this duality of the what something is and
the that it is remains valid. One of the best definitions of mysticism
Teresa of Avila,
Life, c. 10, 1.
64 McGinn, The Foundations, xvii.
65 McGinn, Flowering, xi.
Egan, Soundings, xviii.
34
Gods quid est is unknowable. In this life, we can only know his quia est.
We can, however, learn something about what God is not (i.e., about quid
non est) and substitute this knowledge for quid est knowledge. What we
can know about God himself is only that he exists. It is distinct of God
that he does not have existence there being no whatness in him that
could have it. Creatures, in contrast, have existence.66
The Oxford English Dictionary gives the following as the first definition
for reality: The quality of being real or having an actual existence.
Other than the fact that actual existence would seem to be redundant,
this definition is perfectly appropriate. Hence, we have an awareness of
existents and existence, which is had by existents and for which reason
they are so designated. Unicorns are not existents. Moreover, we are aware
in every experience of existence itself, which is identified with God. God
cannot be an existent, just as water cannot be made wet. To say that
God exists is, according to Thomas Aquinas, like saying that running
runs.67
Aquinas acknowledges two kinds of visions of God. The first is the
eschatological vision, the second the insight into Gods unknowableness:
The vision of God is twofold. One is perfect, whereby Gods Essence is seen:
the other is imperfect, whereby, though we see not what God is, yet we see
what he is not; and whereby, the more perfectly we know God in this life,
the more we understand that he surpasses all that the mind comprehends.68
The first takes place in heaven, whereas the second is its state of inchoation,
as possessed by wayfarers.69 For Thomas it is, therefore, not an experience
of God, to say nothing of a mystical experience, which represents in this
life the reference to the eschatological vision.
What, then, are the experiences of God that are recounted in the Bible?
Thomas responds to this question with unhesitant consistency:
But that some men are spoken of in Sacred Scripture as having seen God
must be understood either in reference to an imaginary vision, or even a
corporeal one: according as the presence of divine power was manifested
through some corporeal species, whether appearing externally, or formed
internally in the imagination; or even according as some men have perceived
some intelligible knowledge of God through his spiritual effects.70
66
67
68
70
35
Contrary to his contemporary St. Bonaventure, according to whom knowledge of Gods quid est can be attained by grace,74 Thomas allows for no
exception. An experience remains a unity of essence and existence no matter
where it originates. Thomas maintains that Revelation, in particular, does
not change Gods unknowableness, for he is not unknowable in himself
but only for us. If his Revelation is to be heard by us, then it must conform
to the human presuppositions [gratia supponit naturam]. The essence of
human beings sets down the structure transcendentally.75 Although we
are elevated by Revelation to know something that would otherwise be
unknown to us, nevertheless not with the effect that we would know in
any other way than through sensibles.76
71
72
73
74
75
76
36
Of course, Aquinas does not doubt that we gain new knowledge from
Revelation. His denial applies only to our knowledge of Gods quid est. Even
in the case of an interior inspiration, Thomas permits no exceptions.77
Thomass position is further clarified by his solution to objections with
which he confronts himself. Even when Scripture explicitly speaks of someone having seen God face to face, he maintains his position. In such
situations in which the wording of Holy Scripture stands in contradiction to his own position, Thomas uses the hermeneutical method of the
pious interpretation [pia interpretatio]. This hermeneutics, which was
common in the Middle Ages, presumes a sharp distinction between the
verbal statement of a Faith authority and the truth that the interpreter has
in mind.78
In Gen 32:31, for example, we read that Jacob remarks: I have seen God
face to face and have survived. This would seem, as Thomas objects, to
mean that Jacob saw God himself [per essentiam], although still alive in this
life.79 As in similar cases, however, Thomas answers this argument by asserting, first, that this Scriptural authority-text requires an interpretation. This
approach results in his stating that the text cannot really mean what it seems
to say. Thomas allows different interpretations, but he absolutely excludes
the interpretation that it really was God who was seen. He insists that seeing God from face to face cannot mean that the divine essence itself is seen
but only some figure representing God.80 In this context, he also allows
the interpretation of the expression seeing God face to face that understands it as an indication of the eminence of the experience.81 Appealing
to Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, Thomas consistently holds that what
we are dealing with is always a theophany, that is, a created appearance
of God [Dei apparitio].82 However, when the beatific vision is at question, Thomas is not willing in contrast to some of his contemporaries
to let Dionysius teaching apply.
77
79
80
81
37
83
84
85
38
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 173, a. 1c; q. 171, a. 2c.
88 Ibid.
89 Ibid., q. 173, a. 1c.
90 Ibid., q. 174, a. 5, ad 1.
Cf. ibid., q. 174, a. 5c.
92 Ibid., q. 173, a. 1c.
93 Cf. ibid., q. 175, a. 1c.
94 See page 34.
Cf. ibid.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 47.
39
40
41
So the question naturally arises of why there is a need for such a word,
which has acquired an overwhelming, inflationary popularity in innumerable areas of contemporary life. There seems to be almost nothing in
consumer advertisements to which it cannot be applied. Other European
languages have taken it over. Obviously, the problem is an acute need for
reality, real reality and not just virtual reality. Contemporary culture has
become deaf to reality, and the advertisers try to fill the need with the
promise of an Erlebnis:
Just as the remoteness from and hunger for experience, caused by distress
over the complicated working of civilization transformed by the Industrial
Revolution, brought the word Erlebnis into general usage, so also the new,
distanced attitude that historical consciousness takes to tradition gives the
concept of Erlebnis its epistemological function.106
110
42
43
remarked: One still hears that this kind of Faith implies a devaluation
of the present, as though just the opposite were not the case. To every
unprejudiced look it is evident: Only if there exists a life after death, does
true life before death exist.111
If one responded that Eternal Life has the meaning of being a reward for
a morally good life, then this would indeed be ultimate meaning. However,
this thought would undermine true morality because it would then be selfseeking, implying that one would be interested primarily in ones own
happiness. With a promise in the Beyond, morality in the present life
appears to lose its impetus. Belief in the opium of a life after death is seen
to be immoral because it distracts from responsibility. Morality requires the
improvement of this world and not an escape from it. Religion and God
are acceptable only insofar as they foster morality. The Church appears to
be a moral institution, to be judged on its influence on morality. For the
Praxis Prejudice, there is then a plausibility in the position that leading a
morally good life is enough even though one may not attend church. To
my mind, religion must be relevant for praxis.
This Marxist criticism is as strong in many minds today as it ever
has been. Aggressiveness remains one of its dominant notes. The highly
respected sociologist Ulrich Beck articulates this standpoint unequivocally.
For him, Christian eschatology is nothing but a deception, nothing but
shallow words. He claims that Christianity undermines the desire and right
for equality and interprets life in the world as unreal since real life begins
after death. Consequently, there is no real death. Death is just a change
of stage, a costume change.112
The special logic of religion lies in the comparison between the brief
afflictions of worldly existence and eternal heavenly happiness.113 Christianity requires that the believers declare their agreement with their earthly
afflictions during this life while the promised reward is not paid until one
has departed from this world. According to Beck, religion achieves peace
and solidarity by teaching that we should not look closely at our situation. It tells us not to compare our situation with the situation of others,
for your worldly suffering is fictitious; the supernatural harmony is real.
The unity of society is guaranteed through the derealization of social reality. The actual situation disappears in the fog of transitoriness. Instead
of calling for self-knowledge, Christianity says, Forget your situation!
What are hunger, sickness, hatred, longing, injustice, death, murder, war,
111
112
44
115 Ibid.
116 Ibid.
117 Ibid., 386.
Ibid., 344.
119 Weizs
Weizsacker, Ambivalence, 275.
acker, Seligpreisungen, 15.
45
Cf. Marx, Capital, Vol. I, Part III: The Production of Absolute Surplus-Value, Chapter 7: The
Labour-Process and the Process of Producing Surplus-Value, Section 1: The Labour-Process or
the Production of Use-Values, in Marx/Engels, Collected Works.
46
Work is a process between man and nature whereby man is the initiator.
The role of thought is not completely overlooked. It distinguishes human
work from the actions of animals:
We are not now dealing with those primitive instinctive forms of labor that
remind us of the mere animal . . . We pre-suppose labor in a form that stamps
it as exclusively human. A spider conducts operations that resemble those
of a weaver, and a bee puts to shame many an architect in the construction
of her cells. But what distinguishes the worst architect from the best of bees
is this, that the architect raises his structure in imagination before he erects
it in reality.
The will, obeying thought, becomes the source of the action: Besides the
exertion of the bodily organs, the process demands that, during the whole
operation, the workmans will be steadily in consonance with his purpose.
This means close attention, Marx continues. Technology represents the
instrument with which thought is conveyed into nature.
Nature can be turned into tools for achieving an aim: Nature becomes
one of the organs of mans activity, one that he annexes to his own bodily
organs. As the earth is his original larder, so too it is his original tool house.
The instruments of labor become increasingly complex and sophisticated,
but the basic structure remains. All machines and computers are, so to
speak, simply extensions of the hand, which is the original tool. The
product is the conclusion of the work process. As Marx expresses it:
The process disappears in the product, the latter is a use-value, Natures
material adapted by a change of form to the wants of man. Labor has
47
incorporated itself with its subject: the former is materialized, the latter
transformed. That which in the laborer appeared as movement, now appears
in the product as a fixed quality without motion.
48
49
technology ensconcing itself, and not vice versa.126 Because it lies so deeply
in us, Heidegger calls the essence of technology the supreme danger,127
the extreme danger,128 danger in the highest sense,129 or simply the
danger.130 The perspective derived from this extends so far that we even
overlook ourselves. To be sure, we reproduce ourselves in a certain sense
through our work; we make the world more humane. In truth, however,
precisely nowhere does man today any longer encounter himself, that is,
his essence.131 What we have lost is truth, a deeper truth than the truth of
science and technology. But if we succeed in posing the forgotten question
about ourselves and reality, we have already begun to free ourselves from
this prejudice and to see beyond it. This criticism does not merely entail
an opposition to technology but also a transcendence of it.
2.3.4 The technical form of morality and religion today
Morality has become a matter of what we ought to do. Christianity has
become a morality of love. Love, as understood through the filter of the
Praxis Prejudice, is helping. In contemporary language, this kind of love
is called Charity. But this is no longer the theological virtue of love,
which is bestowed on us in grace and grants us orientation in the whole.
We no longer receive Charity, we do it. Originally, Charity was another
word for agape, the specifically Christian kind of love. Today, Charity
is humiliating for many suffering people. Dependence of this kind is
considered debasing. Why do people in need feel that Charity is degrading?
Is it not the Christian love that is exemplified in the story of the Good
Samaritan? In fact, what our age reads in the story of the Good Samaritan is
love filtered through the essence of technology. This development involves
a major change in consciousness. It has been brought about through the
power of the primacy of praxis, which changes the world but fails to
appreciate the world or the needy person whom Charity wants to help.
The question of the parable of the Good Samaritan is what neighbor
means or, as the lawyer questioning Jesus conceives of it, Who is my
neighbor? (Lk 10:29). The Praxis Prejudice tends to see the man who fell
among the robbers as a neighbor even in the face of the fact that Jesus
explicitly turns the question around: He calls the Samaritan a neighbor.
This is a decisive difference. Love entails more than just helping. In my
126
129
128
Ibid., 333.
50
opinion, if this is not seen, then Eternal Life will have to be judged
superfluous.
Exegetes often understand the parable as simply broadening the term
neighbor, thus remaining within the horizon of the original question.
They say that everyone who needs help is my neighbor. Hans Kung interprets the parable as teaching that a neighbor is everyone who needs me.132
Need implies that the persons state can be changed; he embodies, so to
speak, a kind of receptiveness for my practice. In his commentary of Lukes
Gospel, Karl Heinrich Rengstorf expresses it crassly: To whom am I
neighbor?, that is, who is dependent upon me to accord him full selfless
love?133
As a matter of fact, Jesus does not give an answer to the question at all;
he changes the question. The parable recounts an occurrence that prepares
the listener for the new question. The emphasis is not on the suffering
man but rather on the manner in which the Samaritan experiences him.
The Samaritan becomes his neighbor. It is not, By helping I become his
neighbor.134
If one reads the original Greek text attentively and not some translations that turn it into a teaching on praxis it is clear that the verb that
Jesus uses is to become. He asks, Who has become neighbor to the man
who fell among the robbers? In other words, it is not doing that is primary
but rather becoming. Jesus does not simply repeat the question of who
is my neighbor? The act of becoming occurs before the Samaritan does
anything for the man. It happens when he sees him and is moved by compassion. The other two travelers also saw him but passed by on the other
side, whereas the Samaritan saw him and was moved by compassion.
What is translated as moved by compassion is an unusual and drastic
verb in the original Greek namely, [splagchnizomai]. The
verb comes from the Greek substantive [splagchna]. Splagchna
are the innards of an animal sacrifice the entrails, kidneys, liver, and
lungs which are the best parts. Literally, the verb would mean that one
lets his entrails be eaten. Later, it came to mean the total sacrifice of the
animal inside and outside. Today, we would use the metaphor heart
instead; we might say, He let his heart be touched by him or His
heart went out to him. Furthermore, the verb does not occur outside of
Judeo-Christian literature. In the New Testament, it is mostly used to
characterize the divineness of Jesus behavior.
132
133
Kung, On Being, 258: It is impossible to work out in advance who my neighbor will be. This is
the meaning of the story of the man fallen among thieves: my neighbor is anyone who needs me
here and now (emphasis in original).
134 Leitheiser/Pesch, Handbuch, 304.
Rengstorf, Das Neue Testament, 141.
51
What happens is, first of all, the change in the Samaritans heart. He then
helps because he has become the neighbor of the man and not vice versa,
as is sometimes asserted. The main motion does not go from the Samaritan
to the man but instead in the opposite direction. The Samaritan acts on the
man actively and externally but, passively and internally, he is acted upon;
that is, he lets himself be acted upon and this is just the opposite of the
direction in which technology works. He has the ability to perceive reality
affectively, which the other two travelers seem not to have. His perception
is not simply the factual registration that a neighbor lies next to the road
and that the duty of love of neighbor applies. It is a personal, existential
experience, which is not praxis at least not in the modern sense, albeit
the Greeks would have called this praxis. From the Christian viewpoint,
it is the kind of love that is life, as 1 Jn 3:1517 expresses it: If you refuse
to love, you must remain dead . . . If a man who was rich enough in this
worlds goods saw that one of his brothers was in need, but closed his
heart [ ; ta splagchna] to him, how could the love of God be
living in him? Love is a kind of becoming. Love means union, Thomas
Aquinas teaches, defining love more precisely as a union of the affect [unio
affectus or unio affectiva]; the effective aspect of love [effectus amoris] occurs
later.135
After the Samaritan has become one with the suffering man, he then
goes to him and does something to help him. As Aristotle said, the beloved
is like another self. There is simple love, with which one desires something
for oneself, and then there is the love of friendship, which desires something
good for the other. Aquinas expresses it as follows:
Love is twofold, that is, love of concupiscence and love of friendship, each
of these arises from a kind of apprehension of the oneness of the thing loved
with the lover. For when we love a thing, by desiring it, we apprehend it
as belonging to our well-being. In like manner when a man loves another
with the love of friendship, he wills good to him, just as he wills good to
himself: wherefore he apprehends him as his other self, insofar, that is, as he
wills good to him as to himself. Hence, a friend is called a mans other self
(Nicomachean Ethics, IX, 4), and Augustine says (Confessions, IV, 6), Well
did one say to his friend: Thou half of my soul.136
135
136
The union of lover and beloved is twofold. There is real union, consisting in the conjunction of
one with the other. This union belongs to joy or pleasure, which follows desire. There is also an
affective union, consisting in an aptitude or proportion, insofar as one thing, from the very fact
of its having an aptitude for and an inclination to another, partakes of it: and love betokens such
a union. This union precedes the movement of desire. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, III,
q. 25, a. 2, ad 2.
Ibid., q. 28, a. 1c.
52
Presumably, the two other travelers saw the man on the wayside as their
neighbor according to the law but are not criticized by Jesus. It would seem
to follow as a confirmation of my reading that this was not the point of
the parable. What distinguishes the Samaritan from them is the manner
in which he sees. Umberto Eco wisely wrote in The Name of the Rose:
The most that one can do is to look more closely. Aquinas described the
union of love as follows: The beloved is contained in the lover insofar
as he or she is impressed in his or her affect by a kind of accompanying
delight [complacentia].137 The sequence is Love precedes desire138 and
praxis follows desire.
The becoming of love in the affect is an ontological extension of selflove. Hence, real love of another being is grounded in self-love. We are to
love our neighbor like ourselves. The beloved is a second self. To speak
of selflessness is a misunderstanding, despite the fact that many Christians
consider selflessness as the specific characteristic of Christian love.
Neither is action Christian love itself. It is an effect, as well as a sign,
of love. Love of ones neighbor is more than morality, more than the
fulfillment of a moral law. Weizsacker appreciates this when he writes: In
the end the final basis of human social life is love and not morality. Morality
is the next-to-the-final basis.139 He explains:
In real human life equality can never be completely realized. The hierarchy that not even reason can abolish is the hierarchy of reason itself. The
relationship between parents and dependent children, between teachers and
students, between doctors and patients, even between those with knowledge
and those without, cannot be symmetric. The balance is what religion calls
love. Those with knowledge treat those without knowledge basically as
their equals. One loves even the partner who cannot or does not want to be
proven equal. One loves even ones enemy. In modern civilization, exactly
because of a belief in the autonomy of reason, there are few things more
difficult than love. But without love, humankind in its community cannot
survive.140
Suffering is one source of love, the love of compassion. However, there also
are positive sources of love above all, the beautiful. Weizsacker also saw
this:
For humans, erotic love has become, next to morality, a second and completely different kind of release from the ego, and in a different way moves
the ego toward maturity. Common to both, despite all the differences of
how they are experienced, is a quality of sensation that one could perhaps
137
139
53
call bliss, the overwhelming bliss of erotic ecstasy and the quiet bliss of the
good deed, more exactly, the good will. Perhaps what they have in common
is that both steps originate in the blindness of the ego and teach us to see
something entirely different. For the core of reality, as the Indians say, is the
trinity of being, consciousness and bliss.141
This is seconded by another commentator: Love is not just an attitude . . . Love is the actions of love.143
Immanuel Kant sees the essence of love in a feeling: Love is a matter of
feeling, not of willing . . . The joy over the physical or moral well-being of
another is human love.144
Paul Tillich, to the contrary, realizes that love is an ontological concept.
Its emotional element is a consequence of its ontological nature. It is false
to define love by its emotional side.145
Suffering and compassion represent one mode through which reality
changes us. Beauty is another. In the technical mindset, beauty is overlooked. It can be seen only in a contemplative perception.146
Also hidden to the technical mindset is the essence of man. In our
nature, there is something that does not submit to being manipulated by
praxis. It lies beyond our power. Traditionally, it has been religions that
have been cultivating this. Joseph Ratzinger pointed out that salvation is
not something that we can produce; it is a gift. Love in its purest form can
only be received as an unearned gift.
Be that as it may, it is in any case not difficult to understand how a
sensitive observer of the human condition in the nineteenth century
namely, Karl Marx could let himself be blinded by the importance of
work. When we are sick, health looms much more in the fore of our values
than when we are healthy. In his own experience of beauty, however, Marx
141
144
145
146
142 K
143 Wendland, Ethik, 15.
Ibid., 101.
ung, On Being, 256; 255.
Kant, Metaphysik der Sitten, VI, 401. Cf. ibid., XXIII, 407.
Tillich, Systematic Theology, Vol. I, 279.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 180, q. 2, ad 3.
54
One can hardly imagine a more telling refutation of the Praxis Prejudice.
The Praxis Prejudice is like a pair of blue eyeglasses. Once I have gotten
used to them, I forget that I am wearing them and that the visible world
does not consist in variations of blue. We have become so used to this
viewpoint that we see things in accordance with it that do not fit at all. For
example, when I say God created the world in a lecture at the university,
what I am doing is called theory, as a preparation, say, for teaching in
a secondary school. But when the same sentence is said in school, it is
now called praxis. College studies a term that originally meant a kind of
love for knowledge, for theory have become use-oriented. Many study
in order to have a good job afterwards and this can mean simply to
earn more money. University studies are then basically comparable to the
manual training of a craftsman. The notion of theory has itself become
praxis-oriented; it is understood as a preparation for praxis. Theory today
147
Cf. Marx, letter to his wife, Jenny Marx, of June 21, 1856 (Marx/Engels Correspondence 1856;
MECW Vol. XL, 54).
55
149
150
Ibid.
56
152
57
Thomas even claims that Holy Scripture agrees with Aristotle in understanding mans final happiness as speculation. Contemporary English does
not allow the following translation of the Latin, in which Thomas emphasizes his statement with the expression the speculation of what is most
speculative [speculationem optimi speculabilis].
Nicholas of Cusa, at the end of the Middle Ages, makes the same claim:
For speculatio, or contemplatio or visio, is the most perfect act, rendering
our highest nature, namely, the intellectual, happy, as Aristotle has also
shown.154
It is obvious that the term speculation has taken on quite a different
meaning since his time, for he can write: Speculation [speculatio] is living
in peace, for it is the resting of the rational spirit, or its final happiness.155
Cusanus also refers to the speculation of truth, writing: This speculation
is for those who see life and eternal happiness.156
With the word speculation, the problematic reveals its acute challenge for today. For us, speculation represents just the contrary to what
Cusanus, together with the entire Western tradition preceding him, understood by it. It is next to impossible for us to understand speculation as
fulfilling happiness. For us, it does not signify intensive reality but rather
a separation from reality, like the word abstract. Moreover, not only has
the word been given a meaning contrary to the original, it is also a term
with a strong negative connotation. It is used in a psychological combat against the traditional meaning. For this tradition, speculation is a
deep grasping of the essence of a reality, deeper in any case than concrete,
empirical perception in time and space. Man has no better way of reaching
reality.
For Cusanus, God is closely associated with theory. The word God
[theos], he asserts, comes from the word theory.157
The Greek word theoria is also translated into Latin as meditation or
contemplation. The contemplative life [vita contemplativa], as opposed
to the practical life, is the theoretical life [ ]. As with the
words theory and speculation, the meaning in popular language has
been reversed. Whereas meditation, or contemplation, originally meant an
apprehension of reality, today the tendency is to think of them as turning
inward, away from objective reality. The perceptive thinker Weizsacker is
one of the few who realized this. He observes:
154
156
157
58
Meditation, he maintains,
is not a flight into ones own inner world, but it is a shield against those
innermost inhibitions that prevent us from facing our neighbor and reality.
And there is something else: A large part of what is thought to be an active
facing of reality is actually nothing but a flight from the facing of oneself.159
2.4 Hedonism
The reduction of happiness to a feeling is perhaps the dominant philosophy
of the present day. Hedonism teaches practical methods for attaining the
feeling of happiness. With the appropriate discipline, a little can bring about
the same feeling as much can. The gourmet can enjoy more pleasure in his
tiny portions than the glutton in his immoderate portions. The hedonist
attempts to be content with what he has or what is presumably acquirable.
He substitutes contentedness for happiness. The ideal of contentedness
has become, in fact, the predominant enemy of happiness and religion.
We tell ourselves, for example, that we should be content with health or
with the little that we actually have instead of striving for greater joys and
then being disappointed. The striving for happiness is curtailed or, at least
as an ideal, moderated. Hedonism can be defined as the ideal of reducing
happiness to an affect.
One form of hedonism focuses on sensual pleasure, but a higher, more
serious form revolves around spiritual joy. While it is easy to see the error
in sensual hedonism, this is more difficult in higher hedonism. Greek
hedonists such as Epicurus (342/1270 bc), who put great value on the
joys of friendship, who derived more delight from doing a good deed than
from receiving one, who considered dying for a friend good, who lived
an ascetical life were responding philosophically to the question of what
mans highest good is. In other words, what is the meaning of life? What
are we striving for ultimately and universally? Hedonism of this kind is a
qualified answer to the question of ethics: What is the goal of life?
Epicurus taught that everyone should realize that the highest good lies
not in human beings or noble things but rather in the pleasure, or delight,
we derive from them. Accordingly, the ultimate is a subjective feeling.
158
159
2.4 Hedonism
59
Although he was well aware that most people are concerned explicitly with
other matters, Epicurus was convinced that this is the objective ideal of
human life. Whereas we today tend to think of morality as a matter of
duty, of norms, rules, commandments, prohibitions, compromises, and so
forth, the Greeks saw delight as a sign of the most mature virtue.
The purpose of morality was for them to become happy. However,
on the question of what happiness consists in, a hedonist differed from a
Platonist. For Plato, happiness is the attainment of the Good. The hedonist,
in contrast, contends that what we want ultimately and most of all is to
feel good. We have been taught to spurn Plato and, in fact, hedonism is
a popular approach in our time (filling, as it were, the place that religion
previously held). Enjoying life as much as is decently possible is for many
the highest goal. I dont feel like it today is accepted as an excuse. Carpe
diem! is the first self-evident principle of this convincing anti-eschatological
worldview. Whether it can be said that happiness is something that can
be acquired, or at least sought after, in this life is a question that will be
addressed in a subsequent chapter.
Hedonism is also concerned with pain. Avoiding pain is the negative
side of seeking pleasure. Accordingly, one must accept compromises that
arise from weighing the possible advantages and disadvantages. One may
try to either maximize pleasure or minimize pain. The former is typical
for the wealthy, who can afford the costs of pleasure. The latter, chosen
by Epicurus himself for whom the greatest pleasure lies in the avoidance
of pain in the body and in quietude in the soul involves asceticism; one
tries to reduce ones desires so that frustration is minimized. A little should
suffice. Choices become a calculation: to gain one pleasure, I may be willing
to forbear another. Health thus becomes crucial today, and the hedonist,
for example, may avoid certain tasty foods because they are detrimental to
his health. Expect as little as possible and we will be more easily content.
With the right discipline, more pleasure can be derived from what one
has. Freedom from inner turmoil called ataraxia becomes a key to
happiness ironically. That there is something wrong with this philosophy
is indicated in one of Epicurus teachings: Even on the rack the wise man
is happy . . . When on the rack, however, he will give vent to cries and
groans.160
Hedonism seeks to discover the original motivation for all decisions. It
sees that everything sought by us is accompanied by some kind of pleasure
or delight. From this, it concludes that what we always seek is delight. In
animals and babies, neither of whom have been unfittingly educated, this
160
60
Aristotle argues that we would still strive after certain activities like seeing,
knowing, remembering, and acquiring a good character, even if they did
not provide any pleasure. In his own words:
No one would choose to live with the intellect of a child throughout his
life, however much he were to be pleased with the things that children are
pleased with, nor to get enjoyment by doing some most disgraceful deed,
though he were never to feel any pain in consequence. And there are many
things we should be keen on even if they brought no pleasure, e.g., seeing,
remembering, knowing, possessing the virtues. If pleasures necessarily do
accompany these, that makes no odds; we should choose these even if no
pleasure resulted. It seems to be clear, then, that pleasure is neither the good
nor that all pleasure is desirable.163
161
163
162
2.4 Hedonism
61
166
167
62
In other words, we get pleasure from having something, but the having
is not what we seek; rather, it is the something.
Feelings are not simply subjective states that are brought about by external efficient causes. By nature, feelings have an intentional character. The
realities corresponding to the feelings determine what kind of delight one
experiences; the realities are formal causes, not efficient causes. Instances
of pleasure and joy are as different as the realities inducing them. We
enjoy different people differently. It is obviously possible for parents to
love each child unconditionally, without having to divide their love. One
loves an individual person and not the state of being in love at least, this
is what nature expects. Loving Woman, eternal,169 and not a particular
woman, is insulting to the latter. Loving the state of being in love and for
that reason seeking an apt person is an insult to this unfortunate person.
Everyone seems to know naturally that we ought not to regard people as
(efficient) causes of pleasure but as the content; that is, as the formal cause,
making love for this person be what it is. Whether delight is good or bad
is determined by the reality that gives rise to it. The feelings of a sadist are
not considered to be objectively good by others. It would be foolish to say
that if someone enjoys doing something, then he should do it. It depends
on what he is doing. As Thomas says:
If delight were the last end, it would be desirable in itself. But that is false:
for it makes a difference what delight is desired, considering the object
from which delight ensues: for the delight which follows upon good and
desirable activities is good and desirable; but that which follows upon evil
activities is evil and to be shunned. Delight therefore has its goodness and
desirability from something beyond itself. Therefore, it is not itself the final
end, happiness.170
Ironically, the concentration on delight corrupts the attention on happiness. Pleasure is not detrimental in itself but only in the sense that it involves
nearsightedness. The debauchee is insatiably restless and unsatisfied.
168
170
2.4 Hedonism
63
Thomas argues further that even love, which like delight also takes place
in the will, is not the final end. The definition of love as a feeling is
drastically misleading. Spinozas definition (Love is joy, accompanied by
the image of its external cause171 ) is a classical example of this misunderstanding. Aquinas extensively discusses this question in his Summa contra
gentiles, distinguishing two ways of being fulfilled. There is, first, a kind of
fulfillment added to something that is already complete with regard to its
species; and, second, there is a kind of fulfillment required for the species
to exist at all. A house, for example, would not be a house if the purpose
of being a place to live in were not actualized in it. A house not made for
living is not really a house in the full sense of the word because it lacks
something that belongs to its definition. An airplane not made for flying
is not an airplane in the full sense. Among those attributes that belong
to the definition of something, some are elements of the essence, some
are necessary for the continuing existence of the thing. Aspects like attractiveness and comfort also belong to the definition of a house. If, however,
something exists completely in its species, then its further activities are
its ends. The normal end of a house is to be lived in, once the house is
completed. Thomas explains: And in like manner the proper activity of
each thing, which is a sort of use of it, is the end of the thing. But the
perfections which go to make up the species are not the end of the thing:
rather the thing is their end.172
This structure applies to delight, or pleasure. Like health, delight is
necessary for a being to continue living well and is thus attributed to the
species. Such things serve the completeness of a being, but they are not its
end. The relationship is just the other way around. Hence, Thomas writes:
Now when we say that delight is the perfection of activity, we do not mean
that activity specifically considered is directed to the purpose of delight
the fact is that it is ordained to other ends, as eating is ordained to the
preservation of the individual we mean that delight ranks among the
perfections which go to make up the species of a thing: for through the
delight that we take in any action we apply ourselves to it more attentively
and fittingly.173
In brief, delight is similar to beauty and bodily strength. Both serve a being
and not vice versa. The body does not exist in order to be beautiful or in
order to be healthy.
171
172
Amor est laetitia concomitante idea causae externae. Spinoza, Ethica IV, propos. 44.
173 Ibid.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 26.
64
65
with arguments that the author himself holds to be invalid. Often enough,
such arguments were derived from Faith doctrine, especially from Scriptural
texts. However, Biblical texts were also used to establish a positive as well as
a negative answer. Peter Abelard initiated this conception shortly before the
first medieval universities arose. In his book Sic et non,174 he systematized
Faith authorities so that to every question posed, they responded both
affirmatively and negatively.
Whereas in the structure of a Quaestio, which arose out of Abelards
method, the author thereafter presented his own opinion, Abelard expressed
no opinion at all. The young students were simply left on their own. By
combining traditional doctrine with logic, Abelard forced the young students into a state of doubt. The more the teachings of the Scripture arouse
[excitant] the readers and attract them by these contradictions to search for
the truth, the more the authority of these Scriptures are commendable,175
he maintained. His purpose was to confuse his readers so that they would
be provoked [provocent] to become doubtful and then left to the use of their
own reason. From a state of doubt, provoked by an unthinkable logical
contradiction, the search for truth could commence.
With this method, the teaching of Faith undermines the idea that Faith
can simply be passed on from generation to generation. Faith itself forces
honest believers to do their own thinking. Faith without understanding
is, as Thomas Aquinas expressed it, naked. Theology professors who do
nothing more than hand down the teaching of Faith to their students
produce, according to him, empty heads. Speaking of students who learn
only the teaching of Faith without doing any of their own thinking, Thomas
remarks: If the teacher determines a question with naked authorities, then
the listeners will have the certitude that such is the case, but they will have
acquired neither knowledge nor insight and they will leave empty.176
In Christian doctrine we find, in fact, expressions that confirm a life
after death as well as some that deny it. Attempting to be orthodox does
not seem to be the solution. I find some remarks of Professor Wigand
Siebel with regard to a new catechism (Botschaft des Glaubens) published
by the Catholic bishops of Germany in 1979 informative and representative
of the situation today.177 He begins by criticizing Kungs criticism of the
catechism as being an innovation backwards. He then counters with the
remark that the German bishops are in truth not conservative, as Kung
maintains, but instead have proven to be so innovative that they have made
174
176
177
66
The author concludes by posing the question of what the bishops will
think if Christians who are true to the Bible do not accept the bishops
new teaching, according to which no one resurrects but only receives a lost
sociological contact.
In a few sentences, Siebel construed a complicated conflict among
Catholic believers. The theologian Kung is posed against the German
bishops, who in turn are seen in opposition to Scripture and tradition but
in conformity with scholarly exegesis. Finally, the people of the Church
are placed in opposition to the bishops. The Christian Siebel, who claims
to be orthodox and finds himself in a position to judge which teaching is
orthodox, stands above all of these different Revelation sources. How am
I to decide a dispute like this among Catholics and there is no reason
to doubt that they all look upon themselves as true Christians striving for
truth in this case by simply listening to Revelation? How am I to decide
which position is the true teaching of Revelation? In any case, I will not
succeed by simply appealing to Faith.
2.5.2 Some theologians as examples
Here again, one is confronted with dissidence. The former professor for
dogmatics, editor of the new edition of the Lexicon for Theology and the
Church [Lexikon fur Theologie und Kirche], and former President of the
Pontifical Council for Promoting Christian Unity, Walter Cardinal Kasper
defines eschatological statements as having the purpose of guiding us today
in view of the future. The crisis in view of the future, he writes, lies in
the question about the goals and criteria for this future. This is where theological talk about the future begins, if it is trying to present Jesus Christ as
the unique grounding and the permanent criterion for a new behavior that
67
opens up the future.178 Hope expressions are ultimately not of a theoretical but of a practical nature, he explains. They are marks of a path that
we must walk in order to experience their power in the doing of truth.179
What the eschatological symbols communicate to us is that nothing can
come between us and the love of Christ (Rom 8:35; cf. verse 39). In the
face of such a minimum, Kasper confesses explicitly: Nothing more can
really be said theologically, and theologically nothing more is needed to be
said, because this is enough to overcome the fear of the future and to pass
the test of the present out of the strength of hope.180 In his eyes, hope
itself, without a specific object, becomes the very essence of eschatology.
The reader wonders how Kasper can know this. He presents no reasons
for such a comprehensive and radical interpretation. It is obvious that he
argues against a counterposition, but he does not tell us explicitly what
it is. Presumably, he simply relies on the presupposed convictions of his
readers to find his position plausible.
Heinrich Ott has a similar viewpoint, hardly lacking in clarity: The
eschatological sentences on Eternal Life do not express knowledge about a
future state but rather a profession of Faith in God as the future God.181
In The Common Catechism: A Book of Christian Faith, a joint project of
Protestant and Catholic theologians, there is a supposedly orthodox and
ecumenical treatment of eschatology. With no pretense of being novel, this
catechism makes assertions such as the following:
The statements in the Bible about the end and goal of history, therefore,
do not constitute a preview of future events in the history of the world
and mankind. If this supposition is correct . . . then we must renounce the
idea that eschatological statements, statements about the last things, are
telling us something about what will take place in the future.182
The future aspect of Biblical eschatology does not have the intention of
telling us anything about the future beforehand but only wants to set
in motion human actions oriented toward the future.183 The catechism
excludes any possibility of finding out anything of the contents. We must
confess, therefore: we do not actually know anything about the last things,
it concludes. Then, after this drastic view, the trivial truth is added as a
justification: We cannot in any sense picture them to ourselves.184 We are
told: Statements about the future are a particular kind of statement about
the present.185 Their purpose is to remind us that we must carry out our
irreplaceable and creative role as free creatures in the here and now. The
178
182
179 Ibid.
180 Ibid.
Kasper, Gott und die Zukunft, 24.
183 Ibid., 533.
184 Ibid., 544.
Common Catechism, 532.
181
185
68
194
69
202
Ibid., 166.
70
is: Anyone who believes in the Son has Eternal Life. There is no future
tense in Jn 6:47: I tell you most solemnly, everybody who believes has
Eternal Life.
Accordingly, death is life before the conversion to Christian Faith: I
tell you most solemnly whoever listens to my words, and believes in the
one who sent me, has Eternal Life; without being brought to judgment
he has passed from death to life (Jn 5:24). Jesus paradoxical statement
emphasizes the present: Jesus said, I am the resurrection and I am life. If
a man has Faith in me, even though he dies, he shall come to life; and no
one who is alive and has Faith shall ever die (Jn 11:2526).
Paul similarly depicts heaven as a state that the believer has already
reached: And in union with Christ Jesus he raised us up and enthroned
us with him in the heavenly realms (Eph 2:6).
In Col 3:13, he asks, Were you not raised to life with Christ? Death
in this sense is behind us: I repeat, you died; and now your life lies hidden
with Christ in God. Death is identified with the state of sin.203
In Johns first letter, the afterlife seems to consist simply in love: We
have passed out of death and into life, and of this we can be sure because
we love our brothers. If you refuse to love, you must remain dead (1 Jn
3:1415).
Conversely, of course, texts asserting an existence after death are also
abundant. But the dissidence is the problem. How is the reader to decide
which version is Revelation truth? It is conceivable that the positive expressions are to be read metaphorically. Then, eschatology would be a set of
symbols accentuating the here and now. What is now important is that the
requisite hermeneutical tools are not provided by the Bible; they can come
only from a rational theology.
2.5.4 The resolution of the ambiguity within Faith
It cannot be the case that one simply has a free choice between options. In
his book Eternal Life [Ewiges Leben], Kung arrives at the conclusion that
neither the one view nor the other can be proven to be true and that we
therefore are, in fact, free to choose. Consequently, no one can forbid me
to believe, if I so decide.
This is a very popular point of view; however, in my opinion, the decision
is not completely left to our free will. If reason were really unable to decide,
then the principle of Occams Razor would apply. This principle, which
203
71
205 Ibid.
Ratzinger, Eschatology, 161.
Rahner, Foundations, 432 (emphasis in original).
207
Ibid.
72
This hermeneutical principle enables us to distinguish authentically eschatological from apocalyptic statements. Eschatological statements and
apocalyptic statements are not necessarily different in the means which
they employ to represent the future, Rahner writes. The same expressions
can have both a metaphorical and a literal meaning. Moreover,
apocalyptic can be understood as a mode of expression through which man
really takes the concreteness of his eschatological future seriously, and does
not forget the fact that his final and definitive future really arises out of his
present life, both individual and social, and that this future is the final and
definitive validity of his free actions.209
Ibid.
209
Ibid., 433.
210
Ibid.
211
Ibid.
73
74
75
Thus, Thomas lays down three rules of interpreting Scripture: first, one
may not presume that a Scriptural text has but one meaning; second, the
interpretation that is attributed to the text must be a truth in its own right;
and third, this meaning must conform to the wording of the text. What
the human author intended is not decisive.
It is important to note that the meaning involved here is not one of the
spiritual senses of Scripture but rather the literal, historical sense. Thomass
well-known teaching on the four senses of Scripture is not what is being
treated here; it is the literal, historical sense that itself has more than one
meaning. This is possible because it is not a human author who is being
considered but rather God, who is Truth itself. Since the literal sense is
that which the author intends, and since the author of Holy Scripture is
God, who by one act comprehends all things by his intellect, Thomas
argues, it is not unfitting, as Augustine says (Confessiones, XII), if, even
according to the literal sense, one word in Holy Scripture should have
several senses.223
Thomas concludes that every meaning that represents a truth in itself
and does not contradict the text is a literal meaning intended by God:
Every truth which, respecting the letter of the text [salva litterae circumstantia], can be adapted [aptari] to divine Scripture is its meaning.224
This implies an unexpected individualism. This pertains to the dignity of
divine Scripture that under one letter many meanings are contained. And
thus it harmonizes with the diverse thoughts of different individuals, so
that each one is amazed to find in divine Scripture the truth which he has
thought in his own mind.225
The notion of truth is the key to this position: No matter who says it,
every truth comes from the Holy Spirit.226
222
223
224
226
76
228
chapter t hree
78
you have. But this does not come down to a Cartesian method of doubt,
as if the believer were expected to prove his conviction before he believed
or to presume that his Faith played no role. Descartes wanted to doubt
everything possible and discovered even under this condition that he could
not get beyond his own thinking. Reason is not the first step. Rather, one
begins with an awareness, a self-reflection, a kind of connatural knowledge,
convincing by means of an affective concordance, a sympathy. It is a matter
of a kind of circular movement. To give my reason for believing in logic, I
do not have to, and I cannot, abstract from logic and prove its legitimacy
before doing it. Methodical doubt does not go that deep. If I find no
reason to deny logic, then I am adequately justified in believing in it. If,
to cite another analogy, I want to justify the fact that I am writing this
book in English, then I will hardly avoid using the English language to
defend myself. Many things in life are like this. To have a mother tongue,
one must start learning a language at an early age. One cannot wait until
one is old enough to make a rationally grounded decision on the question;
then it is too late. To be sure, one can later find good reasons to retain
ones mother tongue or to desist in using it and learn another language
although this new language will hardly ever become a mother tongue.
But how can I find plausible reasons for believing in an afterlife? The
question is instead how the misunderstandings that deny it can be cleared
up. This is down to earth; it is not dealing with reality beyond the empirical
world but rather with human thoughts occurring here and now. The
theological work in this case resembles that of a window cleaner, who
merely removes the obstructions to a clear view.
Various approaches to an answer are worth considering. In addition to
simply turning to the teaching of Faith (see page 64) say, in the Apostles
Creed one can argue from Christs Resurrection. The conviction can also
be approached as being something basically natural.
One of the obstructing misunderstandings that must be corrected is
the influential idea that belief in the immortality of the soul is something
medieval and has been overcome by the Enlightenment. The historical fact
is that precisely Enlightenment thinkers not only believed in but also put
great emphasis on the idea of the immortality of the soul. This conviction
could even be called a dogma of the Enlightenment. A few examples can
prove instructive.
In 1767, one of the most influential books of German Enlightenment
philosophy appeared: Moses Mendelssohns Phaedo, or on the Immortality
of the Soul, which became extremely widely read and discussed. Gotthold
Ephraim Lessings Education of the Human Race, published in 1780, shortly
79
before the end of his life, summed up the whole of Christian teaching in
a single sentence: And so Christ became the first reliable practical teacher
of the immortality of the soul.1 Both Rousseau and Robespierre believed
in a personal God and in divine providence, as well as in the immortality
of the soul. In 1794, Robespierre had the Convention promulgate the brief
decree stating that the French nation believed in the immortality of the
soul as well as in a Supreme Being. After declaring, To the tomb, and
to immortality! in his last speech to the National Convention before his
execution, Robespierre added, Death is the beginning of immortality.
Goethe claimed to have been caused a good deal of trouble by the poem
Urania, written by Christoph August Tiedge and ending with the stanza:
When my eyes their final tears have shed
You beckon, call me to divinity.
A man, a pilgrim, lays down his weary head,
A god begins his passage instantly.
Goethe was annoyed by the time when nothing was sung and nothing
declaimed except Urania. Wherever you went, you found the Urania on
all tables; Urania and immortality were the subject of every conversation.
He complained that stupid women who plumed themselves on believing
in immortality along with Tiedge had sometimes examined [him] on this
point in a very conceited way.2
It is not surprising that immortality has been called the real central
dogma of the Enlightenment.3 In his lectures on the destiny of the
scholar, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, the enlightened philosopher par excellence, emphatically sung the praises of immortality:
What is called death cannot interrupt my work . . . I have . . . seized hold of
eternity. I lift my head boldly to the threatening precipice, to the raging
cataract and to the rumbling clouds swimming in a sea of fire, and say: I
am eternal, and I defy your power. Rend apart the last mote of the body I
call mine: my will alone . . . will soar boldly and coldly above the ruins of
the universe.4
80
Kant, too, maintains that the theodicy problem can be solved only if the
soul is immortal.
Not only in the European Enlightenment does the belief in immortality
play an important role. The American statesman and political theorist
Thomas Jefferson also held it high. The second point in his three-point
creed is that there is a future state of rewards and punishments.6 The
elder statesman Benjamin Franklin, who represented the essentials of a
secularized Christianity, listed in his own credo that the soul of man is
immortal, and will be treated with justice in another life respecting its
conduct in this.7
Nonetheless, I hesitate to presume that the immortality of the soul can
justify the Christian belief in Eternal Life. Actually, in itself it could not even
be called life but simply bare existence. Not only is some kind of realization
of sensuality necessary but, above all, God is required. As Benedict XVI has
expressed it, Belief in Eternal Life is merely the application of belief in God
to our own existence.8 In a further sense, it can be seen in relationship to
the belief in Christs Resurrection, which ultimately represents an unfolding
of the belief in God. The human hope for fulfillment is a participation in
belief in God. This aspect was deeply reflected on by Rahner.
81
Therefore, the assertion of the abiding validity of ones existence, and not
the ontological immortality of the soul, is the essential point that grounds
ones belief in Eternal Life.
Of course, resurrection does not concern just the body. It encompasses
the whole of mans concrete existence. It promises the abiding validity
of his single and entire existence.14 This cannot mean that what human
longing desires is to continue to live on forever in time as we now know it.
Time becomes madness if it cannot reach fulfillment. To be able to go on
forever would be the hell of empty meaninglessness. No moment would
have any importance because one could postpone and put everything off
until an empty later which will always be there.15 The present would have
no special value since it would return incessantly.
Christs Resurrection is not the presuppositionless proof of my own
resurrection. Rather, it has for me the form of a confirmation of hope. We
are prejudiced by our instinctive longing. We have a certain expectation
10
13
11 Ibid., 208209.
Ibid., 208.
14 Ibid.
15 Ibid., 271.
Ibid.
12
Ibid., 268.
82
Ibid., 269.
Ibid., 271.
17
20
18
83
Hence, it is not the case that we have no contact at all with Christs
Resurrection and that we examine it without prejudice. The searching
awareness in our being comes together with the historical witness to his
Resurrection, which surprisingly is unique, for where else in our culture
does one find a similar claim? (Even mystics to whom Christ appears
do not claim to have an experience of the Resurrection.) The searching
presupposes a kind of knowledge that is sought. Rahner claims that only
he is able to believe in Christs Resurrection who has already had this kind
of experience himself.29 The influence is reciprocal.
24
26
28
25 Ibid., 272.
Ibid. (emphasis in original).
27 Nietzsche, Thus Spoke, The Drunken Song, c. 59.
Ibid.
29 Ibid., 274.
Rahner, Foundations, 273274.
84
31
Ibid.
3.4 Wonder
85
a being [ens] but rather being itself [esse ipsum], God remains unknowable
for us. As Thomas Aquinas argues:
In truth, the first cause lies above being [ens], insofar as it is infinite being
itself [ipsum esse]. Being [ens] is what finitely participates in being [esse] and
this is proportionate to our intellect . . . Only what has a quiddity participating in being can be grasped by our intellect. But Gods quiddity is being
itself [ipsum esse] and hence lies beyond our intellect.32
Being in the sense attributed to God is, of course, not human fulfillment
but rather the necessary precondition for it.
3.4 Wonder
Human beings are able to wonder about being. Wonder arises, as Thomas
Aquinas observes, in agreement with Aristotle, when an effect is manifest
and its cause hidden.33 When we see an effect as such, we naturally wonder
about the cause.34 In the present question, what we are concerned with
is reality; we wonder about the cause of reality namely, God, absolute
Being.35 Of course, all animals have contact with reality but only selfreflection is capable of knowing reality as reality. In this case, the cause is
not an efficient cause but is more like a formal cause, similar to light as the
cause of colors, or to meanings as the cause of sentences, or health as the
final cause of a surgical operation.
If we apprehend a reality precisely as a reality and wonder about it, then
our attention is factually directed toward God. As Thomas Aquinas wrote:
The rational nature, in as much as it apprehends the universal notion
of good and being [universalem boni et entis rationem], is immediately
related to the universal principle of being [essendi principium].36 Religion
begins not with an experience of God but with such existential wonder. It
awakens, moreover, a striving. Wonder about reality is an indication that
we are destined for the future, no matter what might come. Wonder is the
connector between reality and belief. Believing is trusting in the dynamics
of wonder about reality. God is not the content of religion, as Thomas
astutely asserts; he is its end.37
Hence, the fundamental relationship to God is not initiated by Faith.
Faith is not necessary to enter a relationship with God. Its necessity arises
32
33
34
36
86
when the eschatological dimension of the relationship is taken into consideration.38 In other words, to achieve salvation, Faith is necessary. The three
theological virtues articulate this. Faith presupposes wonder and means
trusting in the dynamics of wonder. Hope indicates the orientation to the
future, whereas love represents the aspect of desire (which in the future is
to emerge as delight).
(Presumably, Rahner says this because he knows that this is, in fact, the
position of Aquinas.) Be that as it may, this striving does not consist in a
direct striving for God. It is rather a striving for fulfilling happiness, which
in turn requires God for its realization.
By nature, human beings strive for joy and pleasure and shun suffering
and pain. Essentially, this striving cannot be totally fulfilled as long as we
exist in time. No joy lasts forever, death being in any case an absolute
barrier. Self-consciousness lies even deeper in human nature than time.
We live in countless ways, and we are often aware that we are living.
Reflection heightens life and, at the same time, undermines it, bringing
experience into the light, so to speak, but also putting us in a certain
sense above experience. We observe ourselves and realize our inadequacy.
38
39
87
This means that there is more in our consciousness than what we are
presently experiencing. Whatever activity has arisen into the light of selfconsciousness becomes relativized. All experiences become ambivalent.
Even when they appear fulfilling, they open a new perspective for still
greater fulfillment. Disappointment lies deeper in human life than either
joy or suffering. In its deepest essence, life is thirst and desire.
The feeling of joy should not, however, be identified with happiness. In
his autobiography, C. S. Lewis attributes his conversion to a unique experience of joy; he was surprised by joy, as he entitles the book. He describes
it as an unsatisfied desire which is itself more desirable than any other
satisfaction.40 He takes the term from Wordsworth: Surprised by joy
impatient as the wind.41 The experience has a positive and negative aspect.
It might almost equally well be called a particular kind of unhappiness or
grief.42 He then adds the important qualification: But then it is a kind we
want.43 It lasts only briefly and occurs quite unexpectedly, but it awakens
an insatiable longing that is enough for this life. And before I knew what I
desired, the desire itself was gone, the whole glimpse withdrawn, the world
turned commonplace again, or only stirred by a longing for the longing
that had just ceased.44 This intense desire appears as incalculably important, although unexpected. It opens consciousness to a new perspective.
The peculiar fact that desiring it is having it cannot be overestimated. In
other words, this particular desire is its own fulfillment. Lewis describes
the experience in the following words:
It had been a particular hill walk on a morning of white mist. The other
volumes of the Ring (The Rheingold and The Valkyrie) had just arrived as a
Christmas present from my father, and the thought of all the reading before
me, mixed with the coldness and loneliness of the hillside, the drops of
moisture on every branch, and the distant murmur of the concealed town,
had produced a longing (yet it was also fruition) which had flowed over
from the mind and seemed to involve the whole body. That walk I now
remembered. It seemed to me that I had tasted heaven then. If only such a
moment could return! But what I never realized was that it had returned
that the remembering of that walk was itself a new experience of just the
same kind. True, it was desire, not possession. But then what I had felt
on the walk had also been desire, and only possession insofar as that kind
of desire is itself desirable, is the fullest possession we can know on earth;
or rather, because the very nature of Joy makes nonsense of our common
distinction between having and wanting. There, to have is to want and to
40
41
42
88
Ibid., 166.
Thomas Aquinas, De veritate, q. 13, a. 3, ad 9. Cf. Augustine, De Genesi, XII, 26, 54.
Lewis, Surprised by Joy, 168.
89
A person is not simply what he or she is, a person is what he or she has
become. In an important sense, a person is more than what he or she is.
In other words, we are also determined by what we love and for which
we are striving. Actually, our longing to be more than we are comprises
the most relevant aspects of our life. Our will is more important than our
achievements. Moreover, our will is more important than our reason. A
person is defined by what he or she loves. Love is not the fulfillment of a
desire to be united with the beloved; it is the union of desire itself [unio
affectus] with the beloved.49 I am not simply what I am. What I want is
decisive. This is the primary criterion for the meaning of life.
It is important to acknowledge the object of willing, for willing itself is
not what I desire but rather its object. Desire is not empty; it is always the
desire of something, as Lewis said.
Desire is comprehensive, being both diverse and unified. The idea of
happiness is defined in such a way that it embraces all desires and defines
the meaning of life. Everything that we do and love is directed to an end.
Life is a history, defined ultimately by goals, and the human spirit embraces
the body. As Rahner expresses it:
For the spiritual soul, of course, as spirit, and as form of the body, does not
possess two completely different functions but in both its partial functions it
has only one, namely, to fulfill its unitary nature as spirit. Consequently, its
corporeality is necessarily an integrating factor of its constitution as spirit,
48
49
90
Human nature strives for definitive fulfillment. This is not a choice but
more like an instinct, being natural but not really free. Nonetheless, we
are in full agreement with it. This striving cannot find fulfillment in
temporal reality and it cannot be extinguished. We are unable not to desire
fulfillment. Life runs in the form of becoming conscious of realities, desiring
them and becoming disappointed by self-reflection, which transcends all
contents. What we strive for can be either goals that I conceive of and
project into the future or into consequent realization or goals that, so to
speak, pull on me. Love is a striving, but the striving itself is pulled. As
Weizsacker expressed it: It can be said that ascent is eros and descent
is agape, but one must add that ascent will be agape craving its own
possibility.51 That our desire for happiness does not consist in a projection
is clear from the fact that we are unable to define the content of happiness.
The word is the name for all that we desire but it does not indicate what
it is that we desire. We are being drawn by it without being able to say
what it is. (We can know that God is, but the unending openness is not an
experience not even a transcendental experience of God.) This striving
for absolute fulfillment cannot be satisfied under the present temporal
conditions. Human beings exist in an inner tension, a quasi-frustration.
There is a kind of reflection involved in this self-transcendent desire
that is not simply the apprehension of an apprehension but rather one
simultaneous act of consciousness. When I see a tree, I know simultaneously, in the same act, that I am seeing the tree. But, in itself, this does
not demand eternity. The apprehension of the apprehension can take place
at a later step, so that self-consciousness in this case would consist of two
conscious acts. For example, through memory, I can in the present recall
experiences of the past; however, that is not self-reflection in the full sense.
In one present act there can occur a two-fold apprehension. While I am
seeing something, I am aware of my seeing. This kind of self-reflection has
a peculiar structure. It is not as though I had two pictures simultaneously,
one of the tree and one of my seeing the tree. Instead, I have an awareness
of my seeing, concomitant with the act of seeing something. Looked at
more closely, what is happening is that I am experiencing something visual
and the fact of existence of this act. Self-reflection, in the full sense of the
term, is simultaneously seeing something and grasping the existence of this
seeing something. Moreover, by directing my attention to the object, it can
50
51
91
also be a grasping of the existence of the object. Then I see it not just as a
tree but instead as a mode of being.
Furthermore, I do not merely apprehend existence at the moment. I
have a notion of existence. My awareness of existence is not bound to
certain temporal moments. This implies an openness of a special kind
that is, an openness toward eternal infinity but not in the sense that we
have contact directly with eternal infinity. Rather, our striving is endless,
never being fulfilled, and in this sense it indirectly implies eternal infinity.
As Aquinas wrote:
Man naturally craves after permanent continuance: as is shown by this,
that while existence is desired by all, man by his understanding apprehends
existence, not in the present moment only, as dumb animals do, but existence
absolutely. Therefore, man attains to permanence on the part of his soul,
whereby he apprehends existence absolute and for all time.52
53
92
Not even atheism can oppose mans natural striving, for atheism does
not occur at the same level as Faith in the transcendent meaning of life.
Transcendence is a peculiarity of human life. Denying transcendence robs
it of an indispensable factor. The alternative to a truly human life is the
life of an unreflecting animal:
To give up on any form of transcending oneself means, de facto, to give up
on ones own human existence and to be contented with belonging to the
animal kingdom. The tragedy of modern man is not that he knows less and
less about the meaning of his own life, but that it bothers him less and less.56
55 Ibid., 236237.
Havel, Letters, 236.
Ibid., 237. Without the awareness of death, nothing like the meaning of life could exist, and
human life would therefore have nothing human in it: it would remain on the animal level. Ibid.,
240.
93
If the whole universe has no meaning, we should never have found out that
it has no meaning just as, if there were no light in the universe and therefore
no creatures with eyes, we should never know it was dark. Dark would be a
word without meaning.57
It is a source of wonder that natural laws exist and are valid and this
without a single exception. We assume, moreover, that they always have
been and always will be valid. The world can be studied; it can be read
like a book. Science is possible an astonishing fact, which should not
go unacknowledged. The rationality of nature is astounding. Even when
something goes wrong for instance, an airplane crashes we do not jump
to the conclusion that something has gone wrong in physics. We depend
imperturbably on the reliability of natural laws and the mathematics governing the world. In the physical world where one would least expect
it rationality prevails.
The rationality of nature becomes especially evident in irrational things.
Whatever happens, for example, is followed by something else, connected
by a continuity of time. The world not only is, it becomes. Evolution
characterizes nature. The physical world is governed by natural laws. Such
laws, as they are called, are temporal. They are not a description of the
present but rather a determination of the future or the past. Natural laws
testify to the innate teleology of nature; that is, the phenomenon that nature
is directed toward ends, that events seem to have a purpose. Nature is in
motion, the past determining the present and the future, and the future
being a result of the present. There is, in other words, an interconnection
within the temporal dimension.
There are countless mathematical values in nature that arouse wonder.
In John Updikes novel Rogers Version, a character is depicted who sees
a revelation of a divine creator in the improbability of the mathematical
precision in nature:
Nobody knows how much dark matter there is in the galaxies, or if the
neutrino has mass. The point is, its debatable, its that close. For it to be
that close now, it had to be terrifically close then, at the outset. Why? Why
so? These amounts are arbitrary, they could have been anything. And there
is dozens of amounts like them that have to be just what they are in order
to give life time to evolve. Take the strong force, which binds the atomic
nuclei together. Make it five percent weaker, and the deuteron couldnt form
and there would be no deuterium, which means the main nuclear reaction
chain used by the sun couldnt function; if it were two percent stronger, two
protons could stick together and the existence of the di-protons would make
hydrogen so explosive the present universe would consist entirely of helium.
57
94
The rationality of material nature is, moreover, reliable. Scientific knowledge knows no temporal boundary. There exists dependable order. The
world is capable of being studied and, by respecting and relying on its laws,
of being manipulated. Natural laws that never apply in reality are impossible, perhaps even unthinkable. Can a natural law be without effect?
We also trust the rules of logic. Unhesitatingly, we rely on the principle
of noncontradiction, which demands absolute recognition from us and
enjoys unlimited validity, often even being applicable to God. Even more
wondrous is the fact that inanimate nature also reveals teleological rationality, often even with mathematical stringency. Thus, a certain amount
of rational order in nature cannot be denied.
Natural laws, for example, exist even in the least rational matter; mathematics rules matter; spirit (i.e., rationality) somehow exists in matter and
determines it. What happens in the physical world is governed by these
laws and they are so dominant that they permit no real exceptions whatsoever. If nothing at all happened in the world, then the question could
be posed whether natural laws would really exist. If, for example, nothing
ever fell, would Galileis laws be real? We foster no doubt that the laws will
still hold the next day. In fact, we probably believe, without reflecting on
it, that they will hold forever. What will happen next year is thus often
necessarily determined by what is happening today. We trust natural laws
and mathematics unhesitatingly. They mark the inner content of reality.
The physical universe consists in a unity. Natural laws seem to apply
everywhere and at every time. Research can be done on everything. We rely
on the knowableness of reality. The world is a book that we can read with
the light of our reason.59 This trust extends even so far that many people
expect justice from history; we feel an impetus to rebel when injustice or
any other kind of meaninglessness prevails. It seems to be a common idea
that the physical world is not just physical or that the physical is not devoid
of the rational. The cosmos certainly appears to be rational.
58
59
95
Even when we do not see it, we are still convinced that what happens in
the world makes sense, or, at least, we tend to believe that it makes sense.
Often, when something tragic occurs, we try to make sense of it, presuming
that there must be some meaning in it. Although we do not see any sense,
we protest and demand meaningfulness. We even think that some kinds of
extreme suffering are unjust: Why should this innocent child be suffering?
This indicates that we strongly believe that existence ought to be just. It is
difficult to be fatalistic in the face of overt injustice. There seems to be a
conviction that particular events in the world ought to make sense. When
we say that a particular death is senseless, we are uttering a complaint, not
an expression of regretful resignation. When a disaster occurs, one often
hears complaints about the meaninglessness of the tragic occurrence. The
point is that the strength of our protest depends on the strength of our
belief in ultimate meaning. Our complaints presuppose the belief that the
world ought to be rational and just. We try to fit apparently senseless events
into a general picture of sensibleness, such as the conviction that when an
airplane crashes, natural laws cannot have failed.
Another dimension in which the world is considered meaningful by us
is revealed in the idea of responsibility. We even find the idea of being
responsible for the entire world sensible. We speak of responsibility sometimes despite the fact that there is no one to whom responsibility should
be directed.
Our natural desire for fulfillment is a further case of immanent rationality. The future-oriented tendency in human nature that is most important
to us is the desire for happiness. It lies in human nature itself and not in
conscious decisions or desires. By nature one could say instinctively
human beings strive for fulfillment. However, such fulfillment cannot be
reached in this life. These two facts justify the belief in Eternal Life after
death. Thomas Aquinas argues as follows:
The natural desire of man must be fulfilled by his arrival at his final end.
But that is impossible in this life: therefore it must be attained after this life.
It is impossible for a natural desire to be empty and vain: for nature does
nothing in vain. But the desire of nature (for happiness) would be empty
and vain, if it could never possibly be fulfilled. Therefore this natural desire
of man is fulfillable. But not in this life. Therefore it must be fulfilled after
this life.60
Since the human soul is incorruptible, there exists a supporting basis for
this.
60
96
61
62
Cf. ibid., II, c. 55: Impossibile est naturale desiderium esse inane: natura enim nihil facit frustra.
Ibid., III, c. 2.
97
Every agent strives for something good and, since nothing is good and
desirable except insofar as it participates in the likeness of God goodness
itself all agents strive ineluctably for God, regardless of whether the agent
is aware of this.
Hence, we ought to avoid speaking of the intelligent designer, although
from our own point of view, we may discern intelligent design in nature.
God does not have plans or intentions. He does not strive for goodness but
rather simply communicates his goodness. As Augustine explains, using the
argument of the unity of time in God, the divine consciousness embraces
all three modes of time but in a more perfect way than we do. He knows the
past but not by looking back and the future but not by looking forward.
For he does not pass from this to that by transition of thought, but beholds
all things with absolute unchangeableness.65
64
Ibid.
98
If our goals simply went on endlessly, never tending toward a final goal,
then there would be no motivation for striving for anything at all. Nothing
would be urgent since opportunities would be eternally repeated. A major
opponent to life after death is the ideal of contentment, which implies a
reneging of striving. But human nature refuses to be content in this life. A
consciousness of the future is essential to human life.
In the notion of happiness, the diversity of life is gathered together
in a collective term, although the naming of it is not a real definition.
It can be said that happiness is, at the least, the realization of the sum
of all conscious strivings. Nevertheless, it is my diversity, my happiness.
Happiness is individual. My life forms an individual unity in the mode of
a striving.
To be precise, not all of human life is included in the orientation toward
a final end. The unconscious biological activities in my body are not
integrated into these dynamics. As a rule of thumb, one could say that
whatever can be predicated of the I is united. Because it is I who
am walking, am thinking, am enjoying myself, we have an indication of the fact that all of these actions belong to one and the same
life. But the self (i.e., the I) is not a central point or a core of it
all. Instead, it embraces everything, like a network. It is not the conductor but rather the orchestra. I and my actions are not separate entities.
The I comes to exist because of reflection that is, not through a direct
apprehension. My actions are incidents of self-awareness. My self is the
self-consciousness of concrete actions but not an entity of its own. Thus,
my self embraces all of my conscious acts but is not independent of them.
(There is no verb that is attributable solely to the I.) It would make no
sense to say that the self, or the soul, alone is fulfilled. The soul is not
a being separate from the rest of the person and capable of Eternal Life.
It is a persons act of being, animating the content but in itself without
content.
Without my deciding it, my life is not just a doing or an experiencing.
I act on reality and I receive reality in my consciousness. However, at the
same time, consciousness is permeated with desire. I am a willing being.
I seek being and self-actualization. The will is directed to goals, including
my own existing. Goals are the content of willing. I do not simply will; I
always will something (although the object must not be separate from the
willing). Mental life is directed to the other. Life is obedience to reality.
Furthermore, I can relate different goals to one another, so that some goals
become means to other goals. In my desire for fulfilling reality, all of my
goals and means become means to this one goal. It is like the vanishing
99
67
68
Cf. Aristotle, On the Heavens, I, 4; 271 a 33; On the Soul, III, 9; 432 b 21sq.; 12; 434 a 3132. Cf. Huby,
What Did Aristotle Mean, 158166; Aristotles De Partibus Animalium, 9398; Johnson, Aristotle
on Teleology, 8082; Lennox, Aristotles Philosophy, 205224; Kullmann, Die Teleologie, 2425.
Cf. Albertus Magnus, Super Dion. Epist. V, p. 494, 5765, who draws a comparison to the way light
is seen in everything visible.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 75, a. 6c: Therefore, it is impossible for the intellectual
soul to be corruptible. Moreover, we may take a sign of this from the fact that everything naturally
aspires to existence after its own manner. Now, in things that have knowledge, desire ensues upon
knowledge. The senses indeed do not know existence, except under the conditions of here and
100
God and nature and allows for exceptions, claiming that God upholds the
rule more than nature.69
Against this it could be objected that animals have a natural desire to
exist and nonetheless they die. The difference is that as far as we know,
animals, in fact, do not crave after permanent existence. Only a being that
can reflect on its temporal existence is capable of this. So the question is
an exclusively personal one.
On the basis that it is impossible that a natural desire be in vain, for
nature does nothing in vain,70 Aquinas expands the principle to include
the human striving for fulfilling happiness. Commenting on Aristotle,
Thomas sees God as the reason for natures doing nothing in vain. God
causes with intelligence, he argues, implying that God has an end for his
actions viewed in human categories. God does nothing in vain because,
being an agent by way of intellect, his action has an end.71 Since God
is like the primary cause and nature is like a secondary cause, the divine
intelligence is concretized in nature. The famous analogy of Thomass is
that of the arrow shot off by the archer, who has a certain target in view.
He is the primary cause. The arrow is a merely secondary cause when it
moves to the target. The secondary cause does not have to have its final
cause explicitly in view in order to strive for it objectively.
Thomas also argues that the reason for natures doing nothing in vain
lies in the fact that everything in nature exists for a reason other than
itself.72 That is, nature itself is in a state of becoming. There exists an
interconnectedness among events in the world. Actions entail reactions. If
something is moving, in an instant later it will be in a different place than
it is now; it is impossible that it is moving and getting literally nowhere.
Movement is by nature teleological. It is impossible that something is
changing now but has no future. It is impossible that the longing for
happiness is a longing for nothing. In other words, emergence is an essential
characteristic of nature. Hence, as we have seen, the desire for happiness,
69
70
71
72
now, whereas the intellect apprehends existence absolutely, and for all time; so that everything that
has an intellect naturally desires always to exist. But a natural desire cannot be in vain. Therefore,
every intellectual substance is incorruptible. Cf. also Summa contra gentiles, II, c. 79: A natural
craving cannot be in vain. But man naturally craves after permanent continuance: as is shown by
this, that while existence is desired by all, man by his understanding apprehends existence, not in
the present moment only, as dumb animals do, but existence absolutely. Therefore, man attains to
permanence on the part of his soul, whereby he apprehends existence absolutely and for all time.
Cf. Henry of Ghent, In De caelo, I, c. 4; 271 a 33; In De anima, III, c. 9; 432 b 21sq.; Summa,
a. XXXVXL, a. XXXV, q. 6; p. 43; a. XLVIILII, a. XLVII, p. 4.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, II, c. 55.
Thomas Aquinas, In De caelo, I, lect. 8, n. 14.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, In De anima, III, lect. 17, n. 5.
101
and not the immortality of the soul, is, according to Thomas Aquinas, the
basis for asserting a life after death.73 Here, the Christian Thomas differs
explicitly from Aristotle:
By the name of beatitude the ultimate perfection of rational or of intellectual
nature is understood; and hence it is that it is naturally desired, since
everything naturally desires its ultimate perfection. Now there is a twofold
ultimate perfection of rational or of intellectual nature. The first is one
which it can procure of its own natural power; and this is in a measure
called beatitude or happiness. Hence, Aristotle says that mans ultimate
happiness consists in his most perfect contemplation, whereby in this life he
can behold the best intelligible object; and that is God. Above this happiness
there is still another, which we look forward to in the future, whereby we
shall see God as he is. This is beyond the nature of every created intellect.74
It would seem that the reason for the difference results from the Thomistic
notion of being. Whereas in the eyes of Aristotle, being [ousia] is an abstract
notion for beings, which for Aquinas is entitas, Thomass own conception
of being is the act of being [esse, or actus essendi]. He therefore has an
awareness of human striving that transcends beings. This aspect makes
it understandable why Aristotle never extended his principle to apply to
an afterlife. Having no notion of Being itself [esse] but only of beingness
[entitas], his perspective is limited to concrete being. Thus, he is unable to
see spirit and body as a unity.
Nicholas of Cusa offers an argument based on the presumption that God
is not a sadist. According to Cusanus, God cannot contradict himself. Being
directed by his intellect, he would be contradicting himself if he caused
man to live in frustration never to be fulfilled since he would be directing
human beings to an end that could never be reached. But this is impossible,
Nicholas reasons, because God only bestows good things, in accord with
reason.75 This is something quite different from Gods permitting suffering.
In itself, suffering does not imply an unavoidable contradiction to the
divine goodness, but the frustration of the desire for happiness would
involve a contradiction and is for this reason impossible.
This principle is, of course, not valid for all kinds of desires. It is limited
to desires that are embedded in the very nature of things. Animals, for
73
74
75
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 48 (quoted on page 95).
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 62, a. 1c.
Cf. Nicholas of Cusa, Sermo CCXI, n. 10, 122: Deus enim nihil frustra agit, et dare torturam,
quod optimo Deo non est ascribendum, qui solum novit dare bona. Cf. also De docta ignorantia,
III, c. 4; De visione Dei, c. 19; Sermo CXXXV, n. 14, 916; Sermo XLI, n. 8, 3236; Cribratio Alkorani,
Prol. 1; De docta ignorantia, I, c. 1.
102
example, have a natural desire for food, but it cannot be concluded on the
basis of this principle that they are going to find food. Among those desires
that human beings imagine but that do not fall under the principle are
those arising from free choice. Free choices are not natural in the sense
meant here. It would seem that the end comes first and then the desire for
it. If Paris did not exist, I could not plan a trip to Paris. If I take a normal
French flag into the sunshine, red, white, and blue are going to be visible.
Why is this necessary?
We have no reason to think that reality does not include the kind of
existence called Eternal Life. However, we know of no alternative that
would explain our longing. Human nature is not like the speed of light,
which presents an absolute limitation. There is no reason why emergence
should stop with the human species. Are we like Fourth of July rockets
that shoot up and, when extinguished, drop as ashes? Or does evolution
continue?
The specifically human act of reflection is the key. Aristotles thought
remains within the world of realities [entitates] but does not reach as far as
reality in the sense of the act of being [esse] although, of course, despite his
philosophy, he himself exists in being. Through reflection, we apprehend
the act of existence, of which Aristotles philosophy does not take account.
We apprehend it in a reality that has existence. We wonder about the
ground of existence. Why is there something and not rather nothing? Why
do I exist? From where does my existence come? Not just What is that?
That it is at all is the point. This opens us to universality as well as to the
idea of happiness. But as long as our reflection is limited to realities, the
longing cannot be fulfilled.
The end of our striving is not something existing absolutely in the
future. We strive for being at every moment. We do not have our eyes set
on the beyond, and in and through this striving we seek God, the ground
of being. All things, by desiring their own perfection, asserts Aquinas,
desire God himself, inasmuch as the perfections of all things are so many
similitudes of the divine being.76 All of the therapeutic activities of a
physician, for example, converge in the striving for health. When he treats
me in a certain way no matter what he is trying to bring about my
health. Every striving for reality, whether as something (e.g., chocolate)
or someone or as some actuality (e.g., eating or writing), converges in
the fundamental, all-encompassing striving for being. The end does not
have to be temporally separated from the means. Reality here is not too
76
103
abstract; it is, indeed, the only notion that adequately fits the situation.
Nothing less can articulate the specific horizon of human life.
Owing to our ability to reflect on our whole life, we have the capacity to
be happy. But we are not and can never be completely happy in temporal
reality. These paradoxical characteristics can be brought together by calling
us a potentia obedientialis for Eternal Life. This constitutes the deepest
definition of man. The term obediential potency indicates that Eternal
Life arises out of both natural and supernatural factors. On the one hand,
we are unable to achieve Eternal Life on our own but, on the other hand, we
have the capability to receive it as a gift. So it is not purely supernatural.77
According to Rahner, the obediential potency represents the consummation of philosophical anthropology, which grasps man as the obediential potency for supernatural Eternal Life. It entails the entire human
person, not just some particular sphere of his being. The potentia obedientialis, he states, must be identical with the spiritual-personal essence
of man.78 The obediential potency is our conscious-life history. It is not
simply something we have but it is we ourselves, with all that belongs to
our conscious-life history.
Aquinas, in contrast, argues negatively. He does not establish the existence of Eternal Life by claiming that man is striving for God and the
vision of God. Rather, he argues from the fact that our striving for happiness can never find fulfillment in the present life. To show this, he goes to
surprisingly great lengths to establish that we cannot be fully happy in this
life. He eliminates a series of possible answers, such as finding happiness in
virtue (as Aristotle did) or in Faith (as Christians might imagine) or even in
other kinds of knowledge of God (e.g., metaphysics).79 Neither morality
nor religion nor any philosophical knowledge of God can, in fact, fulfill
human nature. Of course, Thomas does not deny that such things are necessary prerequisites for happiness, without which we cannot be completely
happy. But he makes a surprisingly extensive effort to show that happiness
entails more.
Thomas then arrives indirectly at the conclusion that the fulfillment
must take place after death, there being no further alternative to consider.80
77
78
79
The beatific vision and knowledge are to some extent above the nature of the rational soul,
inasmuch as it cannot reach it on its own strength; but in another way it is in accordance with its
nature, inasmuch as it is capable of it by nature, having been made to the likeness of God. Ibid.,
III, q. 9, a. 2, ad 3.
Rahner, Potentia oboedientialis, 62.
80 Cf. ibid.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 48 (quoted herein on page 133).
104
When nature does anything at all, then it has already reached an end
in the very doing itself. Although the nature of talking is to communicate
thoughts, when I talk, no matter what I say, I am already actualizing at
least one end namely, the act of talking. Here, obviously nature cannot be
frustrated no matter what I say. This must hold, analogically, for Eternal
Life.
The desire for Eternal Life exists now and is actualized in the general
ontological form of desire. At death, the desire does not change and God
does not initiate a new activity a second creation, so to speak. God
does not change, neither when he creates nor when he re-creates. The only
possibility is that the quasi-light of being continues to shine and now, at the
death of the body, Eternal Life is caused by it. The emergence into Eternal
Life does not mean that one is transported somewhere else, any more than
being conscious of an object means departing from it to another sphere.
Consciousness is a different mode of being but not a total separation from
its object. In the same way, Eternal Life is not a totally new way of living
but simply a higher level. But why does this freedom from empirical reality
result in a higher level of life?
Death means that we are no longer bound down to time and the concrete.
More of what is contained in reality can reveal itself. Man always bears the
openness to more reality in himself, but he is unable to leave the temporal
ground until the physical collapses. If an experience of God were to occur
before biological death, then the person would already be, in an essential
sense, dead. There exist only two possibilities for us. Either we exist in time
or we exist in times eternal fulfillment that comes with death.
105
It is safe to presume that Faith teaching does not provide a great deal of
information about hell. Not much more can be asserted than the existence
and the eternity of hell. The idea that hell can be abbreviated if this
makes any sense in the realm of eternity does not alter the dilemma.
A further aspect is the teaching that hell begins immediately upon death.
The teaching magisterium leaves open the question about the nature of the
punishment. In the article on hell in the German Lexicon for Theology and
the Church, Ratzinger writes: There exist no dogmatic determinations on
the nature of the punishments of hell.86
There is general agreement that the essential punishment is to be
viewed as a distance from God. The authoritative Historical Dictionary of
81
83
86
106
90
Ibid., corpus.
107
There is no distinction between what flows from free will and what is
of predestination; as there is no distinction between what flows from a
secondary cause and from a first cause. For the providence of God produces
effects through the operation of secondary causes. Wherefore, that which
flows from free-will is also of predestination.91
96
98
108
Ibid., I, q. 63, a. 1, ad 4.
Ibid., a. 6, ad 8.
100
109
Rahner sees this state as a loss of humanity. It would be the life of a zombie:
Man would forget all about himself in his preoccupation with all the individual details of his world and his existence . . . He would remain mired in
the world and in himself, and no longer go through that mysterious process
which he is . . . Man would have forgotten the totality and its ground, and,
at the same time, if we can put it this way, would have forgotten that he had
forgotten . . . He would have ceased being a man. He would have regressed
to the level of a clever animal.103
102
104
106
107
110
who say to God, Thy will be done, and those to whom God says, in the
end, Thy will be done. All that are in Hell chose it.108
God is not totally absent; that would mean annihilation, which would
be a punishment literally for nobody.
The differentiation of hell is based on the same principle as the differentiation of heaven: Different degrees and kinds of love are determinative.
The natural desire for happiness is, in any case, the basis. Both heaven
and hell depend on it. In the case of hell, it can be said that hell is the
fulfillment of an underdeveloped desiderium naturale.109 It is justifiable to
conclude: Theologically interesting about this teaching is that it seems to
resolve the tension between divine mercy and justice.110 Thus, there is no
need to balance mercy and justice; they do not stand in conflict with one
another. Strictly speaking, therefore, hell must not be a contradiction to
heaven.
108
109
Lewis, Great Divorce, 72 (emphasis in original). The passage continues: Without that self-choice
there could be no Hell. No soul that seriously and constantly desires joy will ever miss it. Those
who seek find.
110 Ibid., 147.
Bender, Weggehen, 145.
chapter four
Eternal Life, in its essence, is the union of human consciousness with God.
By calling it a vision, emphasis is put on the immediateness of the union
with the known in its own reality that is, with existential objectivity.
A vision in this sense is different from an inner picture, enclosed in
consciousness; it is intentional; that is, it implies a relationship to the
known in its own being. But a vision of the Truth is not an understanding
of the Truth and neither is vision the same as insight.
To start treating Eternal Life in a way that distinguishes it from temporal
life, the common distinction between abstract and concrete can be
helpful. Since we are able to abstract from concrete matter, we have an
ability to conceive of abstractions; that is, we can apprehend realities in such
a way that we transcend their individuality in an immaterial mode. Owing
to the act of abstraction, we are able to open ourselves in a rudimentary way
to higher reality but without necessarily sacrificing the experienced reality.
Taken in this sense, the act of abstraction is not a cutting off of an aspect
of the object, separated from the object, but rather what Thomas Aquinas
calls an abstraction of the whole1 from a part. For example, the abstraction
white prescinds from the whole of the concrete object, whereas tree
includes leaves, roots, branches, and so on. This kind of access to abstract
forms presents a basic capacity for Eternal Life.2 Nonetheless, this capabilty
1
2
111
112
4
5
6
Non oportet quod per quemlibet actum intellectus fiat abstractio a sensibus. Oportet tamen quod
fiat per actum vehementissimum, qui est visio Dei per essentiam. Thomas Aquinas, De veritate,
q. 13, a. 3, ad 5.
According to Rahner, Geheimnis, 595, it is the divine incomprehensibility itself that is the object
of the beatific vision.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 53.
Cf. ibid.: That disposition therefore whereby a created intelligence is raised to the intellectual vision
of the divine substance is called the light of glory.
113
The first mode of light is physical light, which enables the eyes to see
things. The second mode is the light of the agent intellect, which enables
the person to know conscious objects. The light of glory is a third kind,
but it does not replace the light of the agent intellect. What it does is to
enable consciousness to actually know its objects. This is in my opinion
the same as the act of creation, the light of Being.
Being identical with absolute Being, the light of glory is analogous to the
emergence of the human soul. More precisely, it is absolute Being insofar
as it enlightens or, better, is united to a human consciousness. The
vision of God is a union with God in consciousness, actualized by absolute
Being.
Every experience has two aspects namely, what is experienced and that
it is experienced. In the beatific vision, there can be no other alternative
but that God be both, seeing that God is an autonomous reality being his
own being and not just having it. This implies that God has no distinct
forma (whatness) but rather is pure being. Expressed differently, the
divine forma is identical with his Being. Consequently, it is impossible to
distinguish in him between his knowableness and his Being. If God unites
himself to a consciousness, it must therefore be his Being itself that touches
consciousness.
Thus, the vision of God is essentially different from normal experiences.
It would be as if a stone that is being seen were in all its concrete materiality
within consciousness itself. Conversely, when we know immaterial things
like numbers or justice, for example, then it is in fact the whole thing that is
within consciousness since these are forms that are abstracted from matter
in which they otherwise exist. The problem of experiencing God could
be expressed by saying that God cannot be grasped predicatively. In other
words, our consciousness of him and he himself are not separate. To be
experienced predicatively, the object must be a creature. Rather, God can
be discovered through predication our normal way of reaching reality
but not experienced, for he is not concrete; that is, he is not a composition
of forma and existence.
One way of looking at it would be to apply the idea of light. We can then
see Gods union with the consciousness of the human being as analogous
to the way light makes the seeing of something possible. In thy light
they see the light (Ps 36:10) thus can be taken quite precisely, albeit not
literally. Studying the idea of the light of glory more closely can be helpful
in understanding the structure of Eternal Life.
The notion light of glory arose during the thirteenth century and has
since remained a basic element of Christian eschatology. It was, however,
114
not until 1241 that it became a sanctioned Faith teaching.7 Even today, the
interpretation of this doctrine, which undoubtedly calls for an interpretation, is still open.
The fact that it took more than a millennium for Christianity to commit itself to the idea that God himself is, strictly speaking, the object of
the vision in the afterlife is worth reflecting on. Until the thirteenth century, the question was open to dispute. Those theologians who were of
the opinion that God himself will be experienced in heaven based their
position especially on the authority of Augustine, who taught that the
divine substance itself will be seen.8 Augustine interpreted the invisibility
of God as applying to the incarnated corporeality.9 The opposite opinion appealed especially to the authority of Dionysius the Areopagite, John
Chrysostom, and John Damascene, as well as John Scotus Eriugena.10
Their interpretation maintained that not God himself but rather merely
intermediaries, called theophanies (i.e., appearances), will be seen. After
1241, this alternative interpretation was no longer acceptable. Now the
question in theology was no longer whether but how God will be seen.
Thus, today, Carl Friedrich von Weizsacker can wisely state without more
ado that seeing God is the highest promise that can be granted to a human
being (see page 69).
For Albert the Great, the eschatological vision takes place without a
medium that is, without any theophany.11 The substantial presence of
God in Eternal Life makes a theophany superfluous. Rather than rejecting the idea of theophanies, however, Albert reinterprets it by regarding a
theophany not as a medium quo but as a medium sub quo, thus opening the
possibility of interpreting theophanies as the light of glory.12 Regardless of
its subtlety, this development can be considered one of the most important
steps in the history of Christian eschatology (an ingenious reinterpretation13 ). A medium quo is the presence of an object in thought through
which the object itself is known. A medium sub quo is a condition that
enables objective knowledge to take place. It is not a content of knowledge.
To see something visible, three things are required: an object, a subject,
and light enveloping both. In some way, the object enters the subjects
consciousness so that it is seen; not, however, as it exists in itself. If this
7
9
10
11
12
115
process takes place correctly, then we have truth that is, the (albeit deficient) presence of a reality in consciousness.
Thomas Aquinas follows Albert in defining the lumen gloriae as a medium
sub quo. Furthermore, he interprets the light of glory as a disposition,
analogous to a habitus.14 This teaching might seem to present a rather
unexpected turn since it means that man has a natural capacity for the
vision of God but that this capacity has to be enhanced, and this must
be done in the manner of a habit. Thomas is clearly stretching the light
metaphor. Certainly, it would be impossible to imagine a light in which
God and man were united; God cannot be enveloped by some light. By
comparison, my eye, for example, is capable by nature of seeing colored
things and colored things are capable of being seen, but actual seeing will
take place only if there is light present, shining on the object and my eye.
When Thomas calls the light of glory a habit, it is important to realize that
a habit is neither an act nor a potency, but it is the ultimate perfection of
a capability, rendering the actualization easier and stable. The professional
athlete, the soprano at the opera, the scientist, the prize-winning author
all do things that most of us can do in a very basic manner, but they have
brought this ability to maturity. In other words, with them, it has become a
habit. In them, natural capabilities have been developed but not replaced.
Thomas interprets the light of glory as such a habit namely, as the full
development of a capability, but not as a new capability. In other words, the
eschatological development fits to the principle of emergence. A human
being cannot immediately emerge out of a plant. An animal having no
wings is not going to fly suddenly. An animal without a highly developed
brain is not going to start thinking one day.
A further aspect is that the realization of the eschatological vision is
supernatural. It must be caused by God,15 although God does nothing
new:
The property of a higher nature cannot be attained by a lower nature except
by the action of that higher nature to which it properly belongs. But to
see God by the divine essence is the property of the divine nature: for it is
proper to every agent to act by its own proper form. Therefore no subsistent
intelligence can see God by the divine essence except through the action of
God bringing it about . . . To see the substance of God transcends the limits
of every created nature.16
14
15
16
116
Hence, there must be some divine action.17 Nevertheless, this cannot mean
that a new action occurs on the part of God, who is, after all, unchangeable.
This is similar to his direct creation of human souls. Only from the point
of view of the human does it appear that something new has happened.
But the occurrence of colors previously not seen in a room does not mean
that the light in the room has changed; the explanation lies, of course, in
the introduction of new objects.
For knowledge to take place, the object must in some way or another be
present in consciousness. This ontological truth, which is the real presence
of an object in consciousness in contrast to cognitional truth, is the presupposition for knowledge, as Thomas Aquinas expresses it.18 In the case
of God, this presence requires a special disposition in man beyond what
is natural. If something is a content of knowledge, then its presence in
consciousness is called a forma intelligibilis. Hence, God must be united
to consciousness like a forma intelligibilis.19 In other words, there must be
some kind of divine similitude present.20 God himself is then both the
possibility to see himself and what is seen.21 The light of glory is God
himself.
God can be united to a human consciousness because he is absolute
Being [esse ipsum], whereas everything else is a being. When related to
consciousness, absolute Being has the form of absolute Truth itself [veritas
ipsa]. As absolute Truth, God can be united with human consciousness but
not in the form of a truth.22 Whatever else is united with our consciousness
is a being [ens] or a truth [verum] but not Being itself nor Truth itself.
Moreover, the same light of glory makes it possible to experience everything
else in addition to God. As Thomas says: When then an understanding
is raised by divine light to see the substance of God, it is much more
perfected by the same light to understand all other objects in nature.23
This demands that only God can be united to our consciousness in his
entirety. Everything else can be known but retains its own being. The tree
that I look at does not enter my consciousness in its own being; I truly know
17
18
19
20
22
23
117
24
25
26
27
28
29
118
However, the light of glory does not function the way the light of the
intellect, the agent intellect, does. It does not make anything knowable, as
the agent intellect does. What it does precisely is to make it possible for
the intellect to actually know.33
Every other object of knowledge needs light in order to be known, but
God is himself light and therefore is knowable without a further medium.
In this case, the light that makes knowledge possible is itself the content of
the knowledge. As Thomas writes:
Visible things are not light alone and therefore not only a light is required
in order for them to determine vision but also a species of the thing seen.
30
31
33
119
But the divine essence is itself pure light and therefore it does not require
any other species than the light itself in order to be seen.34
Therefore, it can be said that the light of glory is the medium sub quo, the
medium quo, and the quod. If the divine essence is to be seen, then it can
only be seen in and through itself. It can be said that it is the content of
the vision that is, that which is seen, as well as that by which it is seen. In
other words, the divine essence must be the quod and the quo of the vision.35
Since God is seen as the light of glory, he remains incomprehensible in
Eternal Life, even more so than in this life. Sunlight can be blinding, but
that is little in comparison to looking directly into the sun itself.
120
not existing totally in consciousness. An act of attention is just the opposite of a withdrawal from reality, implying, on the one hand, a heightened
mental activity but, on the other hand, making its object more present.
Doing something attentively intensifies the act without distracting from
it. Attention not only enhances what one is doing, it also embraces the act
in the horizon of its light. Attention is heightened subjective activity that
means heightened awareness of the object, not forgetfulness. It illuminates
the object, thus making it real. To state it more exactly: Attention is a
concomitant apprehension of the existence of the object.
A botanist sees the same flower as I do. The conductor of a symphony
hears the same concert as I do. But, in both cases, the degrees of appreciation
are quite different; they see the respective object better than I do. When
you ask a small child how many pieces of fruit you have all together if you
have three apples and two pears, he or she may simply count them all one
by one. That presupposes a certain degree of abstraction, for apples are not
pears and vice versa. To see them as mathematical units is an achievement
of abstraction. But it represents a considerably higher degree of abstraction
to know quite generally and without counting that three and two make
five, no matter what you are dealing with, without nevertheless forgetting
the pieces of fruit. The mathematician sees the fruits but he sees them, so
to speak, in a deeper manner. The relationship between God and creatures
is analogous to this, as is the relationship of activities and desires in us.
It is quite possible for us to desire simultaneously one thing and another
by seeing the one and the many. We can desire, for example, to eat one
of the apples because we desire to retain our strength and health in order
to help the needy so that we can glorify God. A series of motivations like
this intensifies the elements. One desire in this case does not detract from
the others. Love of neighbor and love of God are not separate from one
another. In fact, if you separate them, they both suffer. In any case, God
cannot be loved without loving humans (Anyone who says I love God
and hates his brother is a liar 1 Jn 4:20). Attention is an act that includes
another act and never occurs alone.
121
38
122
eschatology, which comprises about 330 long pages and devotes no less
than 50 pages to New Testament eschatology 3 pages to Johns Gospel
ignores the texts. Furthermore, the texts are missing in Dieter Hattrup,
Eschatologie, and Johanna Rahner, Einfuhrung in die christliche Eschatologie
(more than 300 pages); even in Ratzingers Eschatology, Death and Eternal
Life they are not taken into account. I can think of no other explanation for
this disconcerting fact than the influence of the contemporary prejudice
of the primacy of praxis as opposed to theory and of the preference for the
concrete as opposed to the abstract. They seem to make no sense in the
Scriptural teaching and are consequently ignored.
The well-known objection to Christianity that it is an opium owing to
its preaching of the afterlife collapses in view of this. Paradoxes like these
are hardly the result of wishful thinking. Instead, they stand in distinct
contradiction to what most people today wish.
Plato, Laws, V.
123
a politician. A competent politician for him is one who prefers, above all,
the life of pure theory:
And if they [the cave dwellers] were in the habit of conferring honors among
themselves on those who were quickest to observe the passing shadows and
to remark which of them went before, and which followed after, and which
were together; and who were therefore best able to draw conclusions as to
the future, do you think that he would care for such honors and glories,
or envy the possessors of them? Would he not say with Homer, Better to
be the poor servant of a poor master, and to endure anything, rather than
think as they do and live after their manner?40
One should not forget that in the cave allegory, the levels of abstraction
seem to imply an increased distance from the realities as abstraction is
often understood but, in fact, they mean a deeper penetration of them.
He who has realized that the horses, turtles, and so forth on the wall,
which represents the concrete reality of the prisoners, are in truth shadows
of horses, turtles, and so forth knows the shadow-realities better. He who
realizes that the things projecting shadows are only horses, turtles, and so
forth made, let us say, of clay in any case, products of human work
understands better what these horses, turtles, and so forth really are. At
the final level of ascent that is, in the heaven of ideas the philosopher
continues to see the same horses, turtles, and so forth but now finally in
their most real reality.
Aristotle expressed the same view unequivocally: The activity of God,
which surpasses all others in blessedness, must be contemplative; and of
human activities, therefore, that which is most akin to this must be most
of the nature of happiness . . . Happiness, therefore, must be some form of
contemplation [; theoria].41
Taking this into account, it is not surprising that Thomas Aquinas
claims that Aristotle and the Bible share the same teaching with respect to
contemplation as being mans happiness.42
In the third century ad, the Neoplatonist Plotinus (205269/70 ad)
movingly described the apex of mans ascent to the Good, where the
contemplator marvels at Beauty itself:
One that shall know this vision with what passion of love shall he not
be seized, with what pang of desire, what longing to be molten into one
with This, what wondering delight! If he that has never seen this Being must
hunger for It as for all his welfare, he that has known must love and reverence.
40
42
124
The transcendent desire for beauty that, in turn, makes those loving it
themselves beautiful, as Plotinus teaches, represents an idea that has been
neglected in Christian theology.
Nicholas Cusanus is an unequivocal witness at the end of the Middle
Ages. He identifies speculation, a Latin translation of theoria, with God
himself.44 God, who is called theos ([a word] which comes from theoro,
i.e., video), is . . . the vision of visions.45 Here, one is in the true, where it
is the Truthfulness of the true truth.46 At this point, the contemplator has
reached happiness: By means of the foregoing speculation a contemplator
arrives most delightfully at the Cause, the Beginning, and the End of both
himself and all other things, so that he reaches a happy conclusion.47
I know of no theologian who has formulated this aspect of eschatology
more emphatically than Nicholas of Cusa. As foreign as it may appear to
us today, it is a fact that five hundred years ago, Cusanus taught that the
most extreme happiness of a human being consists in an apprehension of
the intellect. To appreciate this position, a strenuous effort of intellectual
concentration may be required.
When Cusanus says that happiness consists in an apprehension, he means
a particular kind of apprehension; he refers to it as the apprehension of
truth, by which he means something quite specific. He expressed this
frequently, including in sermons for laymen, so that it cannot be claimed
that the idea is esoteric. The highest happiness, he stated in a sermon in
1445, is the apprehension of truth [in apprehensione veritatis].48 This is not
philosophy. For we believe from Christs teaching that happiness consists
in the contemplation [contemplatio], or in the vision of wisdom, which is
God.49 In another sermon, using several terms, he claims that Aristotle
taught the same thing: For speculatio, or contemplatio, or visio, is the most
perfect act, rendering our most high nature, namely, the intellectual, happy,
as Aristotle has also shown.50
At the end of his life, following a highly active participation in Church
and world politics, Nicholas of Cusa wrote a book with the novel title On
the Apex of Theory [De apice theoriae]. This expression is used by him here,
four months before his death, for the first time; apparently, it is his own
creation.
43
45
47
49
125
126
59
127
Nicholas of Cusa, De dato patris luminum, II, n. 100. Cf. De quaerendo deum, II, n. 34; Compendium,
I, c. 1, n. 2.
62 Nicholas of Cusa, Sermo LIV, n. 23.
Ibid., c. 10, n. 34.
64 Ibid., n. 89.
Cf. Nicholas of Cusa, De apice theoriae, n. 8.
66 Weizs
Wittgenstein, Notebooks, 81.
acker, Der Garten, 500. See pages 69 and 114.
128
68
129
Eternal Life is life in the Truth, without the distance normally separating
subject and object. We will know our loved ones in their concrete reality
and not with the distance that now always separates and frustrates us. As
Aristotle has taught, theoria is the highest form of living; it is the life of the
gods. It is a form, the deepest form, of grasping reality.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 46. Cf. In III. Sententiarum, dist. 23, q. 1, a. 2, ad 3;
De veritate, q. 10, a. 8; Summa theologiae, I, q. 87, a. 1; a. 3.
Cf. Hoye, Gotteserkenntnis, 270; Trottmann, La vision, in particular 115208.
130
75
76
77
131
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 46. With this teaching, Thomas stands in
contradiction to Augustine, who speaks of seipsam per seipsam novit (quoted ibid.).
Cf. Hoye, Gotteserkenntnis, 269284; Die Unerkennbarkeit, 117139.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, In IV. Sententiarum, dist. 49, q. 2, a. 1c.
82 Cf. ibid., c. 51.
83 Cf. ibid.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 37.
One can know God in many ways: through his essence, through sensible things, or through
intelligible effects. We have to make a similar distinction about that which is natural to man. For
something is contrary to nature and according to nature for one and the same thing according to its
different states, because the nature of the thing is not the same when it is in the state of becoming
and when it has complete existence, as Rabbi Moses says. Thus, full stature and other things of the
kind are natural to man when he has reached maturity, but it would be contrary to nature for a boy
to have full stature at birth.
Thus, it must be said that to know God in some fashion is natural for the human intelligence
according to any state. But in the beginning, that is, in this life, it is natural for it to know God
through sensible creatures. It is also natural for it to reach the knowledge of God through himself
when it reaches its full perfection, that is, in heaven. Thus, if in this life it is raised to the knowledge
of God which it will have in heaven, this will be contrary to nature, just as it would be contrary to
nature for a baby boy to have a beard. Thomas Aquinas, De veritate, q. 13, a. 1, ad 1. Nevertheless,
132
After having gotten this far, Thomas continues on with a deeper analysis.
At the end of twelve chapters, in which he treats various aspects, he comes
to the following recapitulation:
If then the final happiness of man does not consist in those exterior advantages which are called goods of fortune, nor in goods of the body, nor in
goods of the soul in its sentient part, nor in the intellectual part in respect of
the moral virtues, nor in the virtues of the practical intellect, called art and
prudence, it remains that mans final happiness consists in the contemplation
of truth.85
The idea of a vision of Truth itself The final end is the manifest vision
of the first Truth in itself 86 and not of a truth or truths is extremely
abstract. The fundamental situation is that we see a reality and the seeing
of the reality is a truth. But Thomas is not content with this, for the notion
of a vision of Truth is not unequivocal. What does it mean to see Truth
itself? When we say that God is Truth itself, clearly we do not mean that
he is an abstract notion, no less than calling God absolute Being means
that he is the abstract notion of beingness. That would certainly not be the
source of fulfilled happiness. Now I must imagine what it would mean not
only to see a tree but also to see the truth of the seeing. Then this must
be universalized and made transcendent, and then we have the vision of
Truth itself. What is the content of such a vision?
After excluding other kinds of knowledge, including metaphysical contemplation and the knowledge attained through Faith, Thomas summarizes
his examination:
Now it is impossible for human happiness to consist in that contemplation
which is by intuition of first principles a very imperfect study of things,
as being the most general, and not amounting to more than a potential
knowledge: it is in fact not the end but the beginning of human study: it is
supplied to us by nature, and not by any close investigation of truth. Nor can
happiness consist in the sciences, the object-matter of which is the meanest
things, whereas happiness should be an activity of the intellect dealing
with the noblest objects of intelligence. Therefore, the conclusion remains
that the final happiness of man consists in contemplation guided by wisdom
to the study of the things of God.87
85
86
it is supernatural in the sense that its realization goes beyond the capabilities of a human being. Cf.
ibid., q. 14, a. 2c.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 37.
87 Ibid., c. 37.
Ibid., c. 152: Ultimus autem finis est manifesta visio primae veritatis in seipsa.
133
If then human happiness does not consist in the knowledge of God whereby
he is commonly known by all or most men according to some vague estimate,
nor again in the knowledge of God whereby he is known demonstratively in
speculative science, nor in the knowledge of God whereby he is known by
Faith . . . ; if again it is impossible in this life to arrive at a higher knowledge
of God so as to know him in his essence, or to understand other pure spirits,
and thereby attain to a nearer knowledge of God; and still final happiness
must be placed in some knowledge of God; it follows that it is impossible
for the final happiness of man to be in this life.88
The divine being is the pivotal point: As God is his being, so too is he his
truth [veritas], which is the forma of the intellect.91 Hence, we have the
divine essence as both that which [quod ] is seen and that whereby [quo] it
is seen.92
However, it cannot be that God is subsumed into human consciousness,
with the consequence that man becomes more than God:
It is manifest that the divine essence may be related to the created intellect
as an intelligible species by which it understands . . . Yet, it cannot be the
form of another thing in its natural being, for the result of this would be
that, once joined to another thing, it would make up one nature. This could
not be, since the divine essence is in itself perfect in its own nature. But
an intelligible species, united with an intellect, does not make up a nature;
rather, it perfects the intellect for the act of understanding, and this is not
incompatible with the perfection of the divine essence.93
88
90
91
92
134
To say that God is Truth is paradoxical, for the presuppositions for the
definition of knowledge as the correspondence between thought and its
object seem to be lacking. To repeat, This is the uniqueness of the divine
essence that an intellect can be united to it without any similitude, because
the divine essence itself is its own being and this never occurs with any
other forms.96 As pure act, God can be united to a consciousness in such
a way that he determines consciousness in its contents.97
More precisely, the divine being is able to determine consciousness
insofar as he is the cause of all beings. In a text that has drawn little
attention, Thomas states:
The divine essence is not something universal in being [in essendo], since it is
distinct from all other things, but only in causing, since that which is through
itself [per se] is the cause of all that is not through itself. Consequently, being
subsisting through itself is the cause of all being received in another. And
in this way [!] the divine essence is a knowable that can determine the
intellect.98
In other words, the condition for the possibility of the vision of God lies
not in the divine truth but rather in the divine being. Expressed in another
way: God in himself, distinct from other realities, is not a content of the
visio.
In this sense, Gods infinite transcendence is not impinged on by this
idea. His being united with human consciousness in this way does not
94
95
96
97
98
135
imply that man has reached divine infinity and brought it down to his own
finite level.
The subject represents the possibility and the predicate the actualization
of a possibility.101 Sentences are like tools with which we both fasten and
form the reality around us. The mental process of abstracting is actually an
activity on reality.
Weizsacker attributes this potentiality to our ability to reflect. Although
I disagree with his explanation, it will help us to advance in understanding how predication works by taking a closer look at it. The cardinal
99
100
Ibid., 468.
101
136
103
137
If the verb being has a meaning in a sentence that goes beyond the
simple copula, then is or are signifies in any case more than being now,
as Weizsacker believes; they signify being now.
For Weizsackers theology, it is necessary to interpret being temporally. To substantiate his own position, he quotes on several occasions an
enigmatic sentence of Georg Pichts: Time itself is being.104 This is to be
understood in the sense that being means being in time. The verb is in
the sentence is to be taken as a transitive verb. Time is being in the sense
that it produces being.105
Having a more natural viewpoint, Thomas Aquinas teaches that truth
is based on reality instead of being the appearance of the unity of time, as
Weizsacker asserts. Thomas maintains that it is even impossible to think
the notion of truth without referring to the notion of reality, just as son
cannot be thought without reference to father. Truth presupposes reality
and is a function of reality. Truth occurs at different levels. On the surface,
we have the truth of indicative sentences; beneath it is the truth of thought;
and beneath this level is ontological truth, with consciousness becoming
the object before emerging in the form of a thought.
Truth and truth-asserting sentences come about because we reflect on
our knowledge. In this rudimentary case, reflection is not simply the apprehension of an apprehension.106 It is not one conscious act having another
one as its object; it is rather one act being aware of itself simultaneously.
Weizsacker analyzes reflection as consisting of two acts, one occurring after
the other, making it a temporal phenomenon. Consequently, time would
be the dimension encompassing both. Weizsacker approaches reality in a
Platonic way; that is, he sees a pyramid of levels of abstraction, such that
the subject of a sentence is the universal and the predicate is a particular
case included in the universal.
But, for Aquinas, reflection is not a higher level of abstraction. Neither
is it something like a subsequent thematization, as Rahner interprets him.
For Thomas, it is the apprehension of an act of existence that is, of
the actualization of a possibility. At the same time, therefore, it is also the
apprehension of that which has the act of existence. The relation between
a possibility and its actualization is quite different from the relation of a
particular case and the universal.
The twofold structure of the sentence corresponds to this double structure of reflective consciousness: consciousness and self-consciousness.
104
106
138
Ibid., 610.
108
139
hold of the reality around us. Weizsacker describes the process of forming
a sentence as a kind of grasping of reality [Zugreifen auf die Wirklichkeit]:
The bivalence, the division of reality into alternatives, is not a property the
world shows us without our assistance; it is the way we successfully grasp
reality. Intellect is power-forming. But the bivalence of logic is valid only
for reflective statements. Through the grasp of doubt the isolated simple
statement becomes a reflective statement.109
110
140
141
142
143
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, I, c. 12. Cf. Summa theologiae, I, q. 3, a. 4, ad 2 (quoted
on page 35).
144
128
Ibid., ad 3.
145
have two different directions, so to speak, from above and from below,
although they can arrive at the same knowledge. The sum of the angles of
a triangle can be found out by measuring each one and adding them or by
mathematically analyzing triangles of any and all sorts. The mathematician
in this case will arrive at a more exact result. He would never say, more or
less 180 degrees, and his knowledge applies to all triangles whatsoever, even
when no concrete triangle at all is present. Actually, the empirical presence
is more of a hindrance than a help. Conversely, concrete knowledge of the
singular has advantages. I know my dog, in a certain sense, better than the
biologist.
These analogies can be applied to God and reality. After having presented
an argument from Faith teaching for a life after death, Aquinas argues from
reason:
For the ultimate fulfillment of the rational creature is to be found in that
which is the principle of its being . . . There resides in every man a natural
desire to know the cause of any effect which he sees; and thence arises
wonder in men. But if the intellect of the rational creature could not reach
so far as to the first cause of things, the natural desire [desiderium naturae]
would remain void. Hence, it must be absolutely granted that the blessed
see the essence of God.129
146
In this way, the principle is brought to bear that Thomas sets down as
the very first sentence of his treatment of our knowledge of God in the
Summa theologiae: Since anything whatsoever is knowable according as
132
133
act of understanding is the proper operation of an intellectual substance. Therefore, this act is its
end. And that which is most perfect in this operation is the ultimate end, particularly in the case
of operations that are not ordered to any products, such as the acts of understanding and sensing.
Now, since operations of this type are specified by their objects, through which they are known
also, any one of these operations must be more perfect when its object is more perfect. And so,
to understand the most perfect intelligible object, which is God, is the most perfect thing in the
genus of this operation of understanding. Therefore, to know God by an act of understanding is
the ultimate end of every intellectual substance. Ibid., c. 25. Cf. De veritate, q. 8, a. 1c.
Thomas Aquinas, De potentia, q. 3, a. 5, ad 1.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 25.
147
it is actual [in actu], God, who is pure act without any admixture of
potentiality, is in himself supremely knowable.134 Once the goal has been
reached, the genetical structure of knowledge, of consciousness, is turned
around: No longer is reality experienced in the mode of particular realities;
instead, reality itself is immediately encountered. This is the only way
in which Eternal Life is conceivable. For the present, we encounter only
realities immediately; then we shall encounter reality itself immediately
and, through its mediation, everything else. As Aquinas expressed it:
Those who see the divine essence see what they see in God not by any
likeness, but by the divine essence itself united to their intellect . . . According
to the knowledge whereby things are known by those who see the essence
of God, they are seen in God himself not by any other similitudes but by
the divine essence alone present to the intellect; by which also God himself
is seen.135
This means that the attention directed to God does not in any way distract
from the attention paid to creatures.136 To the contrary, it intensifies the
consciousness of creatures, makes them, literally speaking, more real. As
Cusanus expresses it, they will be seen in their truth. The experience
implied here is given expression in his enigmatic phrase, the apprehension
of truth.
That psychosomatic influences work in both directions is well known.
True as it may be that all knowledge begins with the senses, still we are
acquainted with enough phenomena in which the process starts with the
mind. As Einstein wisely noted: The theory determines beforehand what
can be observed.137 Normal physical actions can begin with a conscious
decision. A powerful delight can bring tears to ones eyes. Out of fear,
bodily organs can react by quivering. Guilt can make a face turn red. Being
in love can cause laughter, and so on.
This attempt to come to terms with the inner structure of Eternal Life
may not be extremely informative, but it at least gives us a standpoint
to believe in it responsibly. Furthermore, it does provide us with enough
knowledge to orient our present life, at least showing that the decisive
factor in life is desire.
134
136
137
148
149
150
145
151
Rahner, Concept, 66. Without Revelation this formal causality would be unknown to us; cf.
Theological Investigations, 330.
Cf. Rahner, Der dreifaltige Gott, 336337, n. 31; 338, n. 34; Der Begriff des Geheimnisses,
9497.
149 Rahner, Spirit, 87.
Rahner, Theological Investigations, 327.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, In IV. Sententiarum, dist. 49, q. 2, a. 1, ad 8.
152
The similarity with God, which is the goal of every creature, does not derive
from the content but rather from the mode of knowing. Understood in
this way, the divine essence is at once the object of the vision and that
whereby it is seen.155
God nevertheless unites himself immediately with human consciousness.
It is not a matter of some representation of God, a theophany. The forma
by which the mind of the individual seeing God through his own essence
sees God is the divine essence itself, Thomas emphasizes. He then goes
on to explain, Nevertheless it does not follow that it be that forma that
is part of a thing in being, but that it function in the act of knowing like
151
152
153
155
Quod quidem non debet intelligi quasi divina essentia sit vera forma intellectus nostri; vel quia
ex ea et intellectu nostro efficiatur unum simpliciter, sicut in naturalibus ex forma et materia
naturali: sed quia proportio essentiae divinae ad intellectum nostrum est sicut proportio formae
ad materiam. Ibid., sol.
Ibid. Cf. Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 51; De veritate, q. 8, a. 1, ad 6.
154 Ibid., ad 5.
Ibid., a. 1c (emphasis added).
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 51; In IV. Sententiarum, dist. 49, q. 2, a. 1c.
153
the forma that is a part of the existing thing.156 This means that God
is not a species (i.e., a content) of consciousness taken in a strict sense.
Consciousness is rather being compared to matter, which is rendered a
reality by the ontological form. But, again, God is also not literally an
ontological form; his causality is only analogous to one.
Aquinas explanation of this unique situation is undoubtedly somewhat
complicated. He admits that the infinite and the finite cannot be related to
one another. But he does not admit that this implies that we can have no
knowledge of God. It is enough to assert, as he says, a relationship similar
to a relationship [proportionalitas quae est similitudo proportionum].157 In
this sense, he claims that there is not a relation but rather a relationship
[proportionalitatem tantum] between God and man in consciousness.158
Thomas justifies his calling God a forma of the vision in the following
manner:
Whenever in a receiver two things are received of which one is more perfect
than the other, the relationship of the more perfect to the less perfect is like
the relationship of the form to that which can be perfected by it . . . And,
therefore, since the created intellect, which exists in a created substance, is
more imperfect than the divine essence existing in it, the divine essence is
compared to that intellect in a certain way as a form.159
Texts like these, it must be said, have been overlooked in studies of Thomas.
Thomas argues that consciousness, the visio, is the act by which man
most resembles God, and resembling God is the goal of every being.
Furthermore, the ultimate goal of consciousness is seeing God, this being
also the way God knows everything.160 The resemblance to God consists
in the mode of existence (i.e., consciousness) and the object [quod videtur]
of this mode as well as the causality [quo videtur] of it.161
154
If this is understood as just one element among others, then the entire
eschatology disintegrates. If it is legitimate to speak of an experience of
God at all, then it would certainly hold true for the beatific vision. But
then one must be aware of the fact that the notion is analogous and
estranged. Experience takes on a meaning that is related to what we
know so well and call experience and yet is fundamentally different. To
use the term experience in a way that is relevant for eschatology, one
must free oneself, in any case, from the idea of experience being necessarily
concrete.
The traditional teaching of Christian Faith has always defined salvation
as an unmediated vision of the divine essence. As the Catechism of the
Catholic Church, n. 1023, teaches: Those who die in Gods grace and
friendship and are perfectly purified live for ever with Christ. They are
like God for ever, for they see him as he is, face to face (1 Jn 3:2; cf. 1
Cor 13:12; Rev 22:4). The Catechism then quotes the authoritative dogma
that goes back to the fourteenth century, declaring that the blessed see the
divine essence with an intuitive vision, and even face to face, without the
mediation of any creature.163
The beatific vision not only comprises the whole, it is also the essence of
Eternal Life. Rahner confirms this traditional teaching: What is normally
meant by the vision of God in the usage of theological language is the
whole of fulfilled salvation.164 There can be nothing in addition to this
vision because there can be no further actualization of the human being.
The same position can be found in Thomas Aquinas: The vision of the
divinity is the whole reality of our happiness.165 Expressed in other words
and accentuating the uniqueness, it can be said that Eternal Life, and thus
ultimate and fulfilled happiness, is in its entirety contemplation.166 In this
contemplation, the whole person is turned toward God: the love of God
is complete and perfect, he is loved with the whole heart, and soul, and
162
164
165
166
155
169
156
This helps to understand Thomas Aquinas claim that the end of consciousness is the end of all human actions and desires and that this end
consists in knowing the First Truth.172 End has here the meaning of a
final cause, as maturity is the end of childhood. Consequently, Aquinas can
assert that whatever is desirable in whatsoever kind of happiness is included
in a higher degree in the divine beatitude.173 Love that says You shall not
die! reaches not just the inner self of the beloved but also his createdness.
Thomas expands on this principle: The entire capability of the creature
will be applied to seeing and loving God. Love generates from seeing
God. Seeing is the foundation, for you cannot love what you do not know.
God is the whole, but he is not seen and loved totally by man. Thomas
distinguishes between the whole [totum] and wholly [totaliter]. Our mind
can know the whole God but not wholly, he states.174 If our mind could
not know the whole of God, it would know nothing, seeing that God has
no parts. Hence, nothing of him is left out. Yet, although all of him is
known, it is nevertheless not totally known that is, not in such a way that
we would see relationships to all of his effects.175 From this, it follows that
170
172
173
174
175
157
it is one and the same to love God and to love any good thing whatsoever,
since all good things [omnia bona] are in God.176 This means that the
more a mind knows different things in God, the more perfectly it sees
God.177
It is often presumed that religion begins with Faith (or even that religion
is Faith). For Thomas Aquinas, Faith is not the first step, for Faith is
preceded by wonder. It is not insignificant that only after treating more
than 1,200 other questions in his Summa theologiae does Thomas take up
the question of the necessity of Faith.179 The section on Faith occurs at
the beginning of the Second Part of the Second Part that is, within the
special moral theology, which deals with individual virtues and follows the
extensive exposition of the First Part of the Second Part on the fundamentals
of general moral theology. Compared with modern theology, this is in
itself extraordinary. It is surprising, first of all, that among the thirty-eight
questions posed in the section on Faith, there is no question to be found
on the necessity of Faith itself [fides] that is, Faith taken as a virtue.
What one does find in its stead is a question on the necessity of believing
[credere]; in other words, whether acts of Faith are necessary. This is a novel
turn in Thomass thought, for in his other treatments of Faith in previous
176
177
178
179
158
works,180 there does occur a question on the necessity of the virtue of Faith.
Whereas in these earlier works Thomas argues that Faith defined as the
commencement of eternal beatitude is required because one cannot strive
toward a goal that is unknown,181 this argument, as well as the point of view,
is conspicuously dropped in the presentation in the Summa theologiae.
Here, digressing from his procedure in the other studies, Thomas sets
out by drawing a clear distinction between Faith taken as a habit [fides]
and Faith taken as an act [credere]; separate questiones are devoted to them.
This separation is conducive to diverting the focus of the question regarding the necessity of Faith away from the virtue so that attention can be
concentrated instead on the acts of believing. This provides Thomas with a
suitable framework for introducing a new approach to the necessity question. The key factor in this approach for theologians today, presumably
unexpected is the notion of being [ratio entis]. Expressed briefly, he
argues: Believing is necessary because we think being.
This necessity, of course, is not absolute; the context in which the answer
is relevant is a practical one namely, salvation.182 Salvation serves as the
condition for the necessity of believing. Because we think being, we require
Faith in order to attain our salvation; without salvation, there would be
no need for Faith. In other words looked at negatively Faith is not
regarded by Thomas as a prerequisite for doing theology. The necessity
that Thomas affirms is not located in the realm of scientific theory. In fact,
he deliberately refrains from defining Christian theology as the study of
Faith its object is not what has been revealed that is, the revelata
but rather revelabilia, what can be revealed.183 Interestingly, Aquinas never
once uses the Anselmian expression Faith seeking understanding [fides
quaerens intellectum]; neither does stating that the context is practical mean
that believing is a requirement for Christian morality. The treatment of
Faith in the Summa does not begin until after morality has been thoroughly
grounded. The context in which he does, in fact, locate the necessity of
Faith is eschatological that is, future-oriented;184 for ultimate happiness
exists only in the afterlife.
180
181
182
183
184
In particular, in the Commentary on the Sentences, the De veritate, the In De trinitate, and the
Summa contra gentiles.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, In III. Sententiarum, dist. 23, q. 1, a. 5; dist. 24, q. 1, a. 3; De veritate, q. 14,
a. 10; In De trinitate, q. 3, a. 1; Summa contra gentiles, I, c. 5; III, c. 152.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 1, a. 5c; IIII, q. 2, a. 5.
Cf. ibid., a. 2; a. 7, where the subject of theology is declared to be God, not Faith.
It is the future-orientedness and not, for example, God, or Christ, or the Church that distinguishes
the supernatural virtue of Faith from faith in general. Cf. ibid., IIII, q. 4, a. 1c; a. 7c.
159
But how does it come about that the abstract notion of being makes
Faith necessary for the attainment of salvation? This is the problem with
which I would now like to try to cope.
Let me begin by recounting the steps of the succinct argumentation
in the Summa article. Thomas commences by establishing in general that
there does not have to be an incompatibility implied between simultaneous
natural and supernatural causality. As an example, he cites the fact that
water naturally tends to move downward, but it is nonetheless susceptible
to being moved sideways by the gravity of the moon, causing the ocean
tides a phenomenon of which Galileo Galilei seems to have been unaware.
With this as the general background, he then moves on to the particular
case of Gods supernatural causality and argues that only human beings are
susceptible to the immediate influence of God himself because only they
enjoy a direct relationship to him. This relationship, far from being a threat
to human self-determination, is grounded in our natural ability to think
universals.185 This capability should not be interpreted as separate from
concrete life; it consists in a manner of apprehending concrete particulars
as universals that is, in a manner not restricted to the concrete particular:
Our intellect is able to consider in an abstraction what it knows in the
concrete.186 The relationship to God, who is the universal principle of
being, is especially established by the ultimate, universal abstraction of
being and the good. The rational nature has an immediate relationship to
the universal principle of being, Thomas argues, insofar as it apprehends
the notion of the good and being [boni et entis rationem]187 (see page 85).
A nature of this kind, as he continues to reason, cannot possibly achieve
full happiness on its own;188 by its very nature, it requires supernatural
knowledge namely, the vision of God himself. Mans ultimate happiness
consists in a supernatural vision of God.189 Yet, the question remains:
What role does believing play in this context?
At this point in the argumentation, Thomass thought assumes an interesting development. After asserting that the necessary reason for believing
depends on the fact that we affirmatively know being, he explains that the
beatific vision can only be reached in the manner of a learning process; in
this metaphor, God is (surprisingly) put in the role of a teacher: in the
185
186
188
Now the created rational nature alone is immediately subordinate to God, since other creatures
do not attain to the universal, but only to something particular, while they partake of the divine
goodness either in being only, as inanimate things, or also in living, and in knowing singulars,
as plants and animals. Ibid., q. 2, a. 3c.
187 Ibid., IIII, q. 2, a. 3c.
Ibid., I, q. 12, a. 4, ad 3.
189 Ibid., IIII, q. 2, a. 3c.
Cf. ibid., III, q. 5, a. 5, ad 1.
160
193
194
195
161
199
200
201
202
203
In the Summa contra gentiles, I, c. 5, n. 1, the text concentrates on God and not on the reality of the
world. Emphasis is put on the aspect of desiring. But what one should learn here is desire, desire
for God himself. The argumentation presupposes the principle that one cannot strive after the
unknown: Nullus enim desiderio et studio in aliquid tendit nisi sit ei praecognitum. Ibid., n. 2.
For this reason, it is necessary that desire for God be learned. Cf. ibid. This explicit application of
the learning analogy to desire paves the way to the approach in the Summa theologiae.
On the temporariness of Faith, cf. ibid., IIII, q. 9, a. 2, ad 1.
Thomas Aquinas, In De trinitate, q. 6, a. 1c (22).
Precisely speaking, it is a medium propter quod. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 2,
a. 2c; cf. ibid., q. 5, a. 3, ad 2.
Ibid., q. 1, a. 4, ad 3.
Cum enim fides non assentiat alicui, nisi propter veritatem primam credibilem, non habet quod
sit actu credibile nisi ex veritate prima, sicut color est visibilis ex luce; et ideo veritas prima est
162
Truth itself [veritas prima] is like a formal object and all of the other
objects (except for God) are like material objects.204 However, the light
analogy can be deceptive for, strictly speaking, the light of Faith . . . does
not move by way of the intellect, but rather by way of the will. Hence, it
does not make one see what one believes . . . , it makes one freely assent.205
Not knowledge but rather the voluntary assent is the essence.206 Indeed,
Thomas goes so far as to maintain that what is externally proposed [i.e.,
the truths of Faith], derived initially from divine Revelation, functions
like the empirical helps that present the occasion for insight into the first
principles of thought.207
The influence of Faith on what is believed is also comparable to the
kind of medium that consists in the demonstrative force of a proof in
geometry. The conclusions are like material objects; the proof is like the
formal object.208 The principles presumed by the proof virtually contain
the whole science.209
These metaphors clarify the significance of the universal notion of being.
It represents the cardinal point of our relationship to both God and the
world, in which we live out our life history. By choosing it as the key factor
for his argumentation, Thomas succeeds in uniting the fundamental components of life: God, the world, and human beings. By explicitly adjoining
to it the notion of the good, he underscores the duality characteristic of acts
of Faith, which involve both the intellect and the will simultaneously.210
The believing will causes the firm adhesion of the intellect.211 Beings are
grasped as good, and this is truth; Faith adds the supporting affirmation.212
Experienced realities spontaneously give rise to desire. The convertibility
of being, truth, and the good is brought to life.
What still must be explained now is how this structure works out in
the succession of history. Knowing any reality, as Thomas asserts, gives rise
204
205
206
207
208
209
211
formale in objecto fidei, et a qua est tota ratio objecti. Quidquid autem est illud quod de Deo
creditur . . . , hoc est materiale in objecto fidei; ea autem quae ex istis credibilibus consequuntur,
sunt quasi accidentaliter. Thomas Aquinas, In III. Sententiarum, dist. 24, q. 1, a. 1, sol. 1. Passio,
et alia hujusmodi quae continentur in symbolo, se habent materialiter ad objectum fidei. Ibid.,
ad 1.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 1, a. 1c; ibid., q. 5, a. 1c; ibid., q. 7, a. 1, ad 3; In
III. Sententiarum, dist. 24, q. 1, a. 1, sol. 1, ad 1.
Thomas Aquinas, In De trinitate, q. 3, a. 1, ad 4.
Assensum, qui est principalis actus fidei. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 6, a. 1c.
Cf. ibid., q. 4, a. 1c; q. 8, a. 5, ad 3; q. 4, a. 1c; q. 14, a. 1; a. 12; I, q. 16, a. 2; In III. Sententiarum,
dist. 24, q. 1, a. 1, sol. 2; dist. 23, q. 2, a. 2, sol. 1.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, In De trinitate, q. 3, a. 1, ad 4.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 1, a. 1c.
210 Cf. ibid., q. 4, a. 2c.
Cf. ibid., I, q. 1, a. 7c.
212 Cf. ibid., q. 2, a. 1, ad 3; q. 4, a. 1c.
Ibid., a. 1c.
163
to the desire to know its cause.213 This is experienced as wonder [admiratio].214 But every object of knowledge is a being. Being [ens], as the
ultimate resolution possible to human thought, encompasses abstractly
everything in the world. Hence, the desire to know the cause of beings as
such transcends the causality within the world. In this way, being discloses
the divine transcendent causality.215 Since ens is for us the culmination
of knowledge in the world, Faith is eschatological. It is the affirmation
of the real possibility of the desired knowledge, revealed through each
and every being. It follows, then, that supernatural Revelation, in comparison to Faith, can only claim a secondary role. Everything contained
in Scripture divinely handed-down is related to the object of Faith, as
Thomas puts it, accidentally or secondarily.216 Revelation contributes
support to the natural situation in which human beings find themselves; and this, as Thomas describes it, is a gradual ascent [gradatim
ascendens] toward God. Creatures are paths [viae].217 The paths leading to
God are as diverse as the world itself.218 With regard to our practical decisions, the cardinal virtue of prudence is necessary. Revelation is required
because these paths are so difficult to climb on our own.219 Faith, although
coming from above, conforms to the same paths.220 Above all, supernatural
Revelation for example, the teaching that God is one and three supports
the experience of wonder, and this it does by reaffirming the unknowability
of the transcendent cause of being. Therein lies the relevance of the fact that
Revelation proposes things to human thought that lie beyond the reach
of reason.221 Faith does not reveal to us what God is, what truth is, but
only that God is, that truth is but that suffices to ignite desire.222 More
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
222
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 25; De malo, q. 9, a. 1c.
Inest enim homini naturale desiderium cognoscendi causam, cum intuetur effectum; et ex hoc
admiratio in hominibus consurgit. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 12, a. 1c. Cf. ibid.,
q. 105, a. 7c; IIII, q. 180, a. 3, ad 3.
Intellectus autem humanus cognoscit ens universale. Desiderat igitur naturaliter cognoscere
causam eius, quae solum Deus est. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 25.
Per accidens autem vel secundario se habent ad obiectum fidei omnia quae in Scriptura divinitus
tradita continentur. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 2, a. 5c.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, IV, c. 1. Cf. the beginning of Thomas Aquinas, In De
trinitate.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, IV, c. 1.
Cf. ibid. Revelation does not alter the manner of knowing; cf. Thomas Aquinas, In De trinitate,
q. 6, a. 3c.
221 Cf. ibid., c. 7.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, IV, c. 1.
It is also necessary that such truth be proposed to men for belief so that they may have a truer
knowledge of God. For then only do we know God truly when we believe him to be above
everything that it is possible for man to think about him; for, as we have shown, the divine
substance surpasses the natural knowledge of which man is capable. Hence, by the fact that some
things about God are proposed to man that surpass his reason, there is strengthened in man the
164
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
233
view that God is something above what he can think. Ibid., I, c. 5. Summa theologiae, I, q. 1, a. 1
argues in the same way. With regard to truth, cf. In III. Sententiarum, dist. 24, q. 1, a. 1, sol. 2.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 16, a. 1c.
The act of faith is the first motion of the mind toward God. Thomas Aquinas, In De trinitate,
q. 3, a. 2c (5). Fides est necessaria tanquam principium spiritualis vitae. Summa theologiae, IIII,
q. 16, a. 1, ad 1; cf. ibid., q. 3, a. 1, ad 3; q. 4, a. 7; q. 7, a. 2c.
Ibid., q. 1, a. 9, ad 2; a. 10, arg. 1; q. 5, a. 4c; q. 6, a. 1. He also makes a distinction between primary
and secondary Faith: creatures and human actions belong to Faith in a secondary sense. Faith,
first and principally, is about the first truth, secondarily, about certain considerations concerning
creatures, and furthermore extends to the direction of human actions. Ibid., q. 8, a. 6c. Cf. ibid.,
I, q. 1, a. 7c; In De trinitate, q. 5, a. 4, ad 8.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 12, a. 6c (quoted on page 169).
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, In De trinitate, q. 3, a. 3c; ad 1.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, I, c. 1.
According to Dionysius, between man and angel there is this difference that an angel perceives the
truth by simple apprehension, whereas man arrives at the perception of a simple truth by a process
from several premises. Accordingly, then, the contemplative life has one act wherein it is finally
completed, namely, the contemplation of truth, and from this act it derives its unity. Yet it has
many acts whereby it arrives at this final act. Some of these pertain to the reception of principles
from which it proceeds to the contemplation of truth; others are concerned with deducing from
the principles, the truth, the knowledge of which is sought; and the last and crowning act is the
contemplation itself of the truth. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 180, a. 3c.
The first truth, which is the object of Faith, is the end of all our desires and actions. Ibid., q. 4,
a. 2, ad 3; cf. Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 25; In De trinitate, q. 3, a. 2c (3 and 4).
232 Cf. ibid., q. 2, a. 5c.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 1, a. 2, ad 3.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, I, c. 1, n. 5.
165
235
236
237
Each thing intends, as its ultimate end, to be united with God as closely as is possible for
it . . . An intellectual substance tends to divine knowledge as an ultimate end. Ibid., III, c. 25.
That operation of man is substantially his happiness, or his felicity, whereby he primarily attains
to God. This is the act of understanding, for we cannot will what we do not understand. Therefore,
the ultimate felicity of man lies substantially in knowing God through his intellect. Ibid., c. 26.
Its felicity will consist in understanding God. Ibid., c. 25.
Faith consists primarily and principally in speculation, in as much as it is founded on the first
truth. But since the first truth is also the last end for the sake of which our works are done,
hence it is that faith extends to works. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 9, a. 3c.
The practical arts are ordered to the speculative ones, and likewise every human operation to
intellectual speculation, as an end. Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 25. The end of the intellect is
the end of all human actions . . . Consequently, the first truth is the ultimate end. So, the ultimate
end of the whole man, and of all his operations and desires, is to know the first truth, which is
God. Ibid.
Via fidei. Thomas Aquinas, In De trinitate, q. 3, a. 1c (3).
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, III, q. 1, a. 7c.
166
its proponents today. The question is posed: Since heaven consists in seeing
God face to face for eternity, must this not become boring? Furthermore,
if the vision of God is the fulfillment of our natural desire for happiness,
how can there be any wonder? For wonder is a kind of expectation of a
cause but, in Eternal Life, the universal and first cause itself will be known.
The causality that grounds wonder about beings is not efficient causality.
In this connection, the idea of an efficient cause is not relevant since an
efficient cause is a being and not universal being itself. Wonder will not
cease although it will forever be the same face that is viewed. Seeing God
himself is not the same as comprehending him. He will be seen in his totality
but not totally [totus, non totaliter]. Since he cannot be comprehended by
us, there will be even more intensive wonder. It is not the wonder arising
from an effect and directed to the cause. The cause itself arouses wonder
because of its incomprehensibility. Consequently, boredom is unthinkable
in Eternal Life.
According to Rahner, the very essence of human existence lies in its orientation to the divine incomprehensibility. He describes man as the being
who is oriented to the mystery as such, this orientation being a constitutive element of his being both in his natural state and in his supernatural
elevation.238 Human nature remains unchanged in the afterlife; otherwise, it would not be the respective person itself. Neither grace nor glory
impairs human nature. From the principle, Glory fulfills nature; it does
not destroy it, Thomas concludes, Therefore, even the imperfection that
belongs to nature is not removed by the light of glory, like, for example,
that it exists out of nothing. For this reason the created intellect falls short
of the possibility of comprehension, and cannot be brought to comprehension by the light of glory.239 Hence, not even the eschatological fulfillment
of the beatific vision effects the rescindment of the incomprehensibility of
God. He remains essentially and perpetually the holy mystery.240
In other words, the vision of God can never become boring because wonder cannot cease. Nothing that is looked upon with wonder can become
tiresome, since as long as there is wonder desire is moved, as Aquinas
states. The divine substance is ceaselessly seen with wonder by whatsoever
created intellect, for no created intellect comprehends it. Consequently, it
is impossible that an intellectual substance become weary of that vision.241
238
240
241
167
Wonder in the face of reality as well as the desire to grasp reality cannot
come to a standstill in the vision of God, regardless of the fact that the
very ground of reality is seen. The inadequacy testified to in wonder, being
thoroughly human, cannot be removed without removing human nature
itself.
168
with the eye. The singularity of the vision can be treated by comparing it
to normal experience on the basis of the fact that experience in our present
state occurs, so to speak, predicatively; that is, it has the structure of a
sentence, consisting of a subject and a predicate. This is the manner in
which human beings attain truth.
To avoid certain misunderstandings, recourse has been taken to distinctions that commence with familiar aspects of temporal life and then
in a certain sense transcend them: from the concrete, we advance to the
abstract; from beings, we gain an awareness of Being itself; from truths, we
acquire the idea of Truth itself.
My presumption is that everyone is actually, almost intuitively, already
aware of the fact that this conception of life is accurate, provided that we let
our experience speak without prejudice. The ultimate state of fulfillment
for us is the (conscious) apprehension of Truth but not taken in the sense
of a kind of pure reflection. A pure apprehension is impossible for us.
The vision of God must necessarily have a certain structure, which cannot be attained within time. The only way in which Eternal Life is rationally
conceivable for us is as an inversion of the structure of consciousness. In
the present, we encounter only realities directly and, through their mediation, we gain knowledge of reality itself; in Eternal Life, we will encounter
reality itself directly and, through its mediation, everything else. No longer
is reality experienced in the mode of particular realities; instead, reality
itself is directly encountered.
Gustav Mahlers Resurrection Symphony contains a compelling summary of this eschatology:
Primal Light
O little red rose!
Humankind lies in greatest need!
Humankind lies in greatest pain!
Much rather would I be in Heaven!
Then I came into a broad path;
And an angel came and wanted to turn me away.
But no, I would not be turned away!
I am from God and would return to God!
The dear God will give me a little light,
Will light me to eternal, blissful life.242
242
c h a p t e r fi v e
But then the question arises of whether there remains a place for others,
especially for loved ones. Is God enough? The answer requires a fine
distinction. On the one hand, God is all of Eternal Life and fulfills all
desires: If God alone were seen, who is the fount and principle of all
being and of all truth, he would so fill the natural desire of knowledge
that nothing else would be desired, and the seer would be completely
1
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 12, a. 6c. Cf. In IV. Sententiarum, dist. 49, q. 2, a. 1, ad 2.
169
170
beatified.2 In this sense, God alone, in fact, suffices but, on the other
hand, as Thomas further clarifies the matter, it is still better to see both
God and, in God, creatures:
Although it is more to see God than to see all things else, still it is a greater
thing to see him, so that all things are known in him, than to see him in
such a way that not all things, but the fewer or the more, are known in him.
For it has been shown in this article that the more things are known in God
according as he is seen more or less perfectly.3
Ibid., ad 3.
171
Ibid., a. 7c.
172
What is foreign to human nature cannot, as Gradl, Deus beatitudo, 209, writes, participate in human
happiness, but it is wrong to assert that nothing that is accidental can belong to it. Accidental aspects
are not absolutely necessary and cannot be a ground for expecting Eternal Life since they do not
comprise the desire of nature, but they nonetheless can belong to complete happiness. See pages
252258.
Laporta, La destinee, 100.
173
11
13
15
174
17 Ibid., 24.
18 Ibid., n. 10.
Nicholas of Cusa, Sermo XLI, n. 7, 513.
20 Thomas Aquinas, De malo, q. 16, a. 3c.
Nicholas of Cusa, Sermo XXVIII, n. 3, 68.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 63, a. 3c.
175
Herein the imagination plays us false; for one is liable to think that, because
a man seeks to occupy a higher grade as to accidentals, which can increase
without the destruction of the subject, he can also seek a higher grade of
nature, to which he could not attain without ceasing to exist. Now it is quite
evident that God surpasses the angels, not merely in accidentals, but also in
degree of nature; and one angel, another. Consequently, it is impossible for
one angel of lower degree to desire equality with a higher; and still more to
covet equality with God.22
Another misunderstanding would be the ideal of total autonomy. But complete self-determination comes down to desiring ones own nonexistence:
Not that he [the devil] desired to resemble God by being subject to no
one else absolutely; for so he would be desiring his own non-being; since
no creature can exist except by holding its existence under God.23
If it were at all possible for man to exist as though there were no God,
then in fact God would be superfluous for him. If God were not in some
sense a good for man, Thomas asserts that there would be no reason to
love him.24 This implies that it is good for man to love himself for from
self-love, love for God arises.
No one is helped by being made into someone or something else.25
That cannot be the meaning of a new creation. Aristotle puts it briefly:
A true friend, who desires the good of his friend, cannot wish that his
friend become a god. In Eternal Life, we must retain our humanity and
our individuality. Gods almightiness cannot go so far as to annihilate what
he has already created.
It is obvious that God has not created simply the best possible creature
and left it at that. He has preferred to create a plethora of different beings.
There can be no melody with just one note; there can be no symphony
with just one instrument; there can be no harmony without variety.
We could ask whether this is not unjust to us lesser beings. My individual
fulfillment may be inferior to that of others, but it is what my individual
happiness consists in. I might envy some aspects of the happiness of a
superior or inferior being and want them for myself. I might, for example,
envy the total identity of a dog with what he is doing at the moment for
instance, being one with his eating. Yet, I do not really want to be a dog in
this state myself.
Ones individual life history defines what a human being is. What is
relevant in this history are the desires that have developed. In them lies
a supernatural thrust. Since happiness is by definition the attainment of
what one loves and desires, there can be no happiness without love. Out
22
25
23 Ibid.
24 Cf. ibid., IIII, q. 26, a. 13, ad 3.
Ibid.
Cf. Spaemann, Happiness, 171172.
176
of this love, there emerges the eternal union of a human being with divine
being, and this is happiness.
27
29
31
177
Teach me, O Lord, how it is that by a single viewing you discern all things
individually and at once. When I open a book, for reading, I see the whole
page confusedly. And if I want to discern the individual letters, syllables,
and words, I have to turn to each individually and successively. And only
successively can I read one letter after another, one word after another, [one]
passage after another. But you, O Lord, behold at once the entire page, and
you read it without taking any time.32
However, God, being one as well as all, also adapts to each individual,
so that he embraces individual histories as eternity, in which, as Cusanus
often emphasizes, motion is rest. By this, he embraces time:
Now, if two of us men read the same thing, one more quickly and the other
more slowly, you read with both of us; and you seem to read in time, because
you read with us who are reading. But above time you see and read all things
at once; for your seeing is your reading. Simultaneously from eternity
and beyond all passing of time you have viewed all books that have been
written and that can be written, and you have read them at once; but you
also now read them successively, in accompaniment of all who are reading
them. You do not read one thing in eternity and another thing in time, in
accompaniment of those who are reading. Rather, you read [one and] the
same thing doing so in [one and] the same manner, because you are not
mutable, since you are fixed eternity. But since eternity does not desert time,
it seems to be moved with time, even though in eternity motion is rest.33
33
Ibid.
34
178
is the mind of God. And so, that which is made will be an image of the
exemplar-form.35 Accordingly, the truth of something is the thing itself
in its more real reality. It is like the levels in the Platonic cave allegory.
Truth exists in analogous stages. At each level, one is dealing with the same
thing but in its truer reality. First it has the reality of a shadow, then of a
wooden figure, then of physical beings, and so on. The Platonic question
is repeatedly, What is that really? Each time, the answer is an image
of something more real. Truth itself, God, is the exemplar of everything
that exists or can exist.36 Only in appearance does the passage of truth
depart from the world; rather, the ascension is an entering into it more
deeply. Cusanus calls temporal truths conjectures or surmises. They are
always only partial truths, but they draw us toward themselves. Truth is
an emergent phenomenon. The ambivalence of our truths represents a
reference to Eternal Life.
Truth occurs in levels. The realization that what has thus far appeared to
be reality is actually only an image. It is in itself the next step in the ascent
or, if one wills, descent, in which the exemplar is seen. Realities become
simpler. But there is an end, a summit, and this is known in and through
the most simple oneness-of-truth.37 In other words, in God, in the purity
of Truth,38 everything coincides in multiplicity and simplicity.
Living in Truth takes place in the manner of levels of attention. Nicholas
speaks of a path to the apprehension of Truth.39 It is not a question of
apprehending spiritual things but rather of apprehending one and the
same thing in increasing degrees of truth. The ascent out of the cave of the
temporal world has the appearance of being a departure from the original
realities but, in fact, it is a deeper mode of seeing them, in comparison
to which the previous apprehension saw mere shadows. In this state, the
intellect perceives all things intellectually and beyond every sensible, distracting, and obscuring mode. Indeed, it beholds the entire sensible world
not in a sensory manner but in a truer, namely, intellectual, manner.40
That there exist levels of apprehension is familiar to us. When we hear
someone talking, different people hear differently. Someone who does
not know the language hears only sounds, one following the next. A more
capable hearer might hear words but not understand the sentences. Another
35
36
37
38
39
40
179
42
chapter s ix
181
2 Ibid., a. 1c.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 10, a. 6c.
4 Ibid., 435.
5 Ibid., 437.
Rahner, Foundations, 441.
182
To overcome the natural tendency to think of eternity as endlessly ongoing time, Rahner suggests that instead of speaking of life after death,
we demythologize this expression and speak rather of life through death.
At death, temporal life becomes Eternal Life. Strictly speaking, eternity
does not occur after death anyway, after being itself a temporal term. As
Rahner phrased it: The achieved final validity of human existence which
has grown to maturity in freedom comes to be through death, not after
it.6 If there were ongoing time after death, then life would be ultimately
meaningless. Instead, time must be subsumed into eternity:
If we simply have time continue beyond a persons death, and have the soul
survive in this time, so that new time comes to be instead of time being
subsumed into its final and definitive validity, then we get into insuperable
difficulties today both in understanding what the Christian doctrine really
means and also in living it existentially.7
Understood in this way, the danger of thinking in categories of a spiritualism that flees from the world and asserts a salvation void of history is
averted.8
Moreover, the relevance of time implies the relevance of individuality.
Analogous to the question of why time is necessary is the question of why
individuals are necessary. C. S. Lewis offers an answer to the question of
why God creates more than one human. Why does he make each soul
unique?
If he had no use for all these differences, I do not see why he should
have created more souls than one. Be sure that the ins and outs of your
individuality are no mystery to him; and one day they will no longer be a
mystery to you. The mould in which a key is made would be a strange thing,
if you had never seen a key: and the key itself a strange thing if you had never
seen a lock. Your soul has a curious shape because it is a hollow made to fit a
particular swelling in the infinite contours of the divine substance, or a key
to unlock one of the doors in the house with many mansions. For it is not
humanity in the abstract that is to be saved, but you you, the individual
reader, John Stubbs or Janet Smith. Blessed and fortunate creature, your eyes
shall behold him and not anothers. All that you are, sins apart, is destined,
if you will let God have his good way, to utter satisfaction. The Brocken
spectre looked to every man like his first love, because she was a cheat.
But God will look to every soul like its first love because he is its first love.
Your place in heaven will seem to be made for you and you alone, because
you were made for it made for it stitch by stitch as a glove is made for a
hand.9
6
Ibid.
Ibid.
183
184
one must apprehend at one and the same time that is, in a unity the
future as future, that is, as a possibility, and the present as present, that is,
as reality, and the past as past. As we experience it, time has a rich structure;
it is not like a line, having only one dimension. We can in a way even free
ourselves from it (e.g., we can think of the notion of time). In the future
perfect (e.g., someday I shall have completed this book), we look back on
future time as though it were past. Basically, however, all of the modes of
time that we know can be reduced to possibility and actuality. For human
beings, only the present is actual, whereas the past and the future remain
possible realities. Hence, it can be said that nature knows no change since
consciousness of time is a prerequisite.
Augustines reflections on the relationship between change and consciousness of change are fundamental. We know three fundamental modes
of time: the past, the present, and the future. Thanks to our ability to reflect,
they can become further differentiated and complex. With the future perfect, we think of the future as past. It is ironical that only the present, which
is a quasi-point in time, lacking duration, is in the primary sense of the
term real. Although both the past and the future extend for longer or
shorter intervals of time, they have no reality. Whereas they are composed
of an innumerable number of parts last year consisted of 365 days, each
day of 24 hours, and so on the present has no parts. Only the present can
be an object of experience. The present experience of the past is memory
and the present experience of the future is expectation. My thoughts, even
the inmost and deepest places of my soul, writes Augustine, are mangled
by various commotions until I shall flow together into thee, purged and
molten in the fire of thy love.13
That we experience change is an important aspect of the extension of
consciousness. Neither the past nor the future is real, but change, which
takes place in the flow of time, is real. Time is a presupposition for change.
To experience change, it is necessary that at least two points of time be seen
simultaneously. For humans, this can be done only by seeing at least one
temporal point as possible reality. Aristotle analyzes change as the reality of a
being that is simultaneously seen as possible. This double perception cannot
occur in nature, where change takes place, but rather only in consciousness,
perceiving nature. The temporal transition is intrinsic to our awareness of
time:
But, then, how is it that there are the two times, past and future, when even
the past is now no longer and the future is now not yet? But if the present
were always present, and did not pass into past time, it obviously would
13
185
not be time but eternity. If, then, time present if it be time comes into
existence only because it passes into time past, how can we say that even this
is, since the cause of its being is that it will cease to be? Thus, can we not
truly say that time is only as it tends toward non-being?14
186
Distended over points of time, man is, so to speak, broken up by the points
of time. He can extend his attention to the past and to the future; he can
even think of the future as past (i.e., the future-perfect tense). But he is
unable to repose in any particular moment. His existential infirmity is that
he sometimes wants time to stand still. But the bliss of a perfect moment
inevitably becomes past. Mans earthly destiny is to know what he wants
but nonetheless be unable to reach it. He stretches out over points of time
but only in his consciousness. He is made to strive for Eternal Life, in which
all of these points of time have simultaneous existence. This would be the
fulfilling consummation that the distentio animi, torn between times, is
longing for:
My life is but a stretching out . . . Thy right hand has upheld me in my Lord,
the Son of Man, the Mediator between thee, the One, and us, the many
in so many ways and by so many means. Thus through him I may lay hold
upon him in whom I am also laid hold upon; and I may be gathered up from
my old way of life to follow that One and to forget that which is behind, no
longer stretched out but now pulled together again stretching forth not
to what shall be and shall pass away but to those things that are before me.
Not distractedly now, but intently, I follow on for the prize of my heavenly
calling . . . But now my years are spent in mourning. And thou, O Lord, art
my comfort, my eternal Father. But I have been torn between the times,
the order of which I do not know, and my thoughts, even the inmost and
deepest places of my soul, are mangled by various commotions until I shall
flow together into thee, purged and molten in the fire of thy love.19
This ineluctable predicament, which Augustine brings to poignant expression for all time, is the essential state of human existence. We long for the
present and are unable to take hold of it. Without the phenomenon of
transition from one point of time to the next, there would be no present
and no past for us. It is the price we pay. It is unnecessary that the present
have any kind of extension. Transition can take place with mere points of
time. Actually, we do not really experience the present since it has no duration. It would seem that we abstract the present out of the transition. Time
is present only when it passes into the past. In other words, the present
moment is a passage into nothingness. Ironically, the present becomes real
by ceasing to exist. If present time did not pass over into the past, it would
not be time at all but rather eternity. It is no wonder that elusive time is
difficult to define:
If times should abide, they would not be times . . . What, then, is time? If
no one asks me, I know what it is. If I wish to explain it to him who asks
19
187
me, I do not know. Yet I say with confidence that I know that if nothing
passed away, there would be no past time; and if nothing were still coming,
there would be no future time; and if there were nothing at all, there would
be no present time.20
The three temporal modes of past, present, and future are associated with
three different acts of consciousness namely, remembering, actual attending, and expecting. The transition from one to the other exists only in
consciousness:
Our attention has a continuity and it is through this that what is present may
proceed to become absent. Therefore, future time, which is nonexistent, is
not long; but a long future is a long expectation of the future. Nor is
time past, which is now no longer, long; a long past is a long memory of
the past.21
21 Ibid., c. 28.
Ibid., c. 14.
Quoted from Weizsacker, Zeit und Wissen, 26. Cf. Aufbau, 556.
23
Ibid., 594.
188
25 Weizs
Weizsacker, Zeit und Wissen, 26.
acker, Aufbau, 615.
Augustine, Confessions, XI, c. 20. But Augustine allows for a less strict way of speaking: Let it still
be said, then, as our misapplied custom has it: There are three times, past, present, and future. I
shall not be troubled by it, nor argue, nor object always provided that what is said is understood,
so that neither the future nor the past is said to exist now. There are but few things about which we
speak properly and many more about which we speak improperly though we understand one
anothers meaning. Ibid.
189
190
that we are unable to experience time in this way does not mean that it is
unthinkable. Reflection can transcend experienced time to a certain extent.
Hence, we are able to predicate eternity of God, although our experience
only provides us with a point of departure for this idea.
When God embraces all nows in his eternity, then he sees past and
future points of time as occurring realities that is, as nows. The classical
problem about how there can be free choice if God already knows the
future is consequently not a real problem at all, for knowledge occurring
simultaneously with free choice does not impinge on its freedom. If I know
what you are going to do in an hour, then you will not be free in an hour to
do it, but if I see you actually doing it, that is, in the present, your freedom
is not impinged upon. When human beings know the future, they know it
beforehand and it is this disjunction that undermines freedom. However,
divine providence does not imply predetermination; or, a better expression
would be that divine predetermination must be conceived as an aspect of
divine providence, as Aquinas teaches.34 Knowing the future determines it
only in a certain manner of speaking. God is unchangeable, both in his
being and in his actions.35 Creation, as Aquinas discerningly emphasizes,
occurs without change.36 Unchangeableness, as predicated of God, does
not represent a deficiency, as it would in our own life. Whereas change
involves the realization of a possibility, God is already the actualization of
all realities.
A common misunderstanding of the difference between time and eternity consists in thinking that the essential difference lies in the fact that
eternity has no beginning and no end; in other words, that it endures endlessly. In fact, this characteristic, called sempiternitas, is a note of eternity,
but it is only secondary.37 Even if time were infinite, there would still be
beginnings and ends in it for example, the beginning and the end of a
day.38 A final characteristic of eternity worth mentioning is that God is not,
strictly speaking, eternal, he is eternity itself since he is his own being39
in contrast to human beings, who are not their being.
An appropriate way of articulating eternity is to say that it is at once
both motion and rest. For of God it is most true to say that he is motion
at rest and rest in motion, as Hans Urs von Balthasar explains with regard
to the eschatological vision.40
34
36
37
40
191
An explanation of the same insight namely, that what one loves determines
ones eternal treasure can be found in Thomas Aquinas.43
Thomas speaks in this context of Charity, which is that form of love that
is directed to the vision of God in Eternal Life; Charity is characterized,
so to speak, by the transcendent dimension of love. As opposed to the
other theological virtues of Faith and Hope, Charity lasts for eternity and
embraces all forms of love, directing them to their final end. Since all
human good is directed toward eternal happiness as its final end, the love
of Charity includes in itself all human kinds of love.44 Thus, creatures
become paths to happiness.45
As the universal good, God is within all love as the quasi-essence and
goal. This does not apply only to other human beings but also to anything
at all in creation. In the love to any good whatsoever the highest goodness
is loved,46 Thomas remarks. If we love anything at all, then we are loving
God. But love of God is not just an effect of worldly love; it precedes it
and is its source. We must assert that love which is an act of the appetitive
power, even in this state of life, tends to God first, and flows on from him
41
42
43
44
192
to other things, and in this sense Charity loves God immediately, and other
things through God.47 The ultimate meaning of the active life of praxis
is love of God.48 God is the goal that is, the final cause of worldly love:
The end of all human actions and affections is the love of God, whereby
principally we attain to our last end.49 In every end that we explicitly
desire, we implicitly strive for God. Because he is the final end, God is
desired in every desire, Thomas maintains. But this is to desire God
himself implicitly.50 In other words, the movement toward any particular
good is the same movement as that toward God.51
This means, for example, that the love for a human is also, at the same
time, love for God.52 In his well-known essay on the unity of love of God
and love of neighbor, Rahner accentuates this relationship:
The categorized explicit love of neighbor is the primary act of the love of
God. The love of God unreflectedly but really and always intends God in
supernatural transcendentality in the love of neighbor as such, and even the
explicit love of God is still borne by that opening in trusting love to the
whole of reality which takes place in the love of neighbor. It is radically true,
that is, by an ontological and not merely moral or psychological necessity,
that whoever does not love the brother whom he sees, also cannot love
God whom he does not see, and that one can love God whom one does not
see only by loving ones visible brother lovingly.53
For Thomas, the union with love of God holds true even for self-love.54
Self-realization is love for God, for every striving after being is a striving
for God, Being Itself. Everything in creation has being and, consequently,
points to God. A friend being another self, the love of a friend is also
derived from self-love.55
One of the rare theologians who defended self-love was the Puritan
Jonathan Edwards (17031758). He argued as follows:
A Christian spirit is not contrary to all self-love. It is not a thing contrary to
Christianity that a man should love himself; or what is the same thing that
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
193
he should love his own happiness. Christianity does not tend to destroy
a mans love to his own happiness; it would therein tend to destroy the
humanity. Christianity is not destructive of humanity. That a man should
love his own happiness is necessary to his nature, as a faculty of will is; and it
is impossible that it should be destroyed in any other way than by destroying
his being. The saints love their own happiness; yea, those that are perfect in
holiness. The saints and angels in heaven love their own happiness. Otherwise their happiness, which God has given them, would be no happiness to
them; for that which anyone does not love he can enjoy no happiness in.56
Self-love is not the opposite of love for others but rather is enhanced by
love for others: A mans self is as it were extended and enlarged by love.
Others so far as beloved do, as it were, become parts of himself; so that
wherein their interest is promoted he looks on his own as promoted, and
wherein their interest is touched his is touched.57
Edwards further explained:
In some sense, the most benevolent generous person in the world seeks his
own happiness in doing good to others, because he places his happiness in
their good. His mind is so enlarged as to take them, as it were, into himself.
Thus when they are happy he feels it, he partakes with them, and is happy
in their happiness.58
Similarly, Thomas Aquinas argues that self-love is the basis for the love of
others. He even teaches that the love that is directed to others arises in
man out of his love for himself, insofar as someone relates to the other as
to himself.59 Thomas adds that man is necessarily led to desiring the good
of the other by his desire for his own good.60
C. S. Lewis was also convinced that the desire for happiness is by nature
not egoistical:
We are afraid that heaven is a bribe, and that if we make it our goal we
shall no longer be disinterested. It is not so. Heaven offers nothing that a
mercenary soul can desire. It is safe to tell the pure in heart that they shall
see God, for only the pure in heart want to. There are rewards that do not
sully motives. A mans love for a woman is not mercenary because he wants
to marry her, nor is his love for poetry mercenary because he wants to read
it, nor his love of exercise less disinterested because he wants to run and leap
and walk. Love, by definition, seeks to enjoy its object.61
56
57
58
60
194
By the end of temporal life, we have become who we are, our individuality has been created. But the end itself is only the completion of the
self-definition and not, as some theologians maintain, the comprehensive
decision, determining the eternal fate. This position, which is referred to
as the final-decision hypothesis,62 sees life history as a preparation for a
conclusive decision immediately preceding death. It reflects on ones life
history, but the decision that is directly relevant for Eternal Life occurs
in the final moments. A variation of this hypothesis views the phase of
maturity as relevant. Similar to this is the thesis that high points in life
are determinative. In this case, it would be key moral decisions that are
determinative.
All of these hypotheses reduce the rest of life, normal life, to irrelevancy
or to practice for the decisive decisions. Instead, all of life history is a kind
of death. Each moment dies away into the past but nonetheless retains
eternal relevance. Final death is, so to speak, the completion of dying.
It is not really an event in its own right. It reveals the temporariness
of life history. Life must come to an end in order to become eternally
meaningful.
It is one thing to say that love of a human being is love for God but
another to assert that love of a human being emerges into Eternal Life.
The question arises about how love of another human involves not only
God but also Eternal Life, if it is true that love means a fulfilling union
with the beloved. It is common experience as well as a long-standing
truism that friends desire to keep company with one another. Thomas
Aquinas even claims that this appears to be the most characteristic mark
of friendship.63 He accentuates this, interestingly, by remarking that we
even take more delight in the company of a friend than in the company of
ourselves.64 He explains this by the fact that we are able to know others
better than ourselves. But keeping company is, of course, only one kind
of union. A closer analysis of love reveals that it consists in a reciprocal
encounter revolving around different kinds of union. The thesis that I wish
to support maintains that the union of love that is the essence of love is not
the fulfillment of the longing for union with the beloved but rather the
union of longing itself with the beloved. This affective union is a form of
becoming, prior to the desire for physical union.
62
63
64
195
66
Ibid., 27.
67
Ibid., 26.
68
196
For example, it can arise from opportunism or ambition or from the desire
of a reward or remuneration. Aquinas offers a fitting analysis:
Since pity is grief for anothers distress, . . . from the very fact that a person
takes pity on anyone, it follows that anothers distress grieves him. And since
sorrow or grief is about ones own ills, one grieves or sorrows for anothers
distress, insofar as one looks upon anothers distress as ones own.69
Neither is benevolence that is, the willing of good the essence of love.
Thomas criticizes Aristotle for not going deeply enough when he defines
love as benevolence. According to Aquinas, benevolence follows upon love.
Like helping, benevolence is a manifestation of love. The Philosopher, by
thus defining to love, Thomas explains, does not describe it fully, but
mentions only that part of its definition in which the act of love is chiefly
manifested.71 The essential union is not the union with the desired good,
or with the friend for whom it is desired, but rather, as Aquinas perceptively
puts it: Love precedes desire.72 In other words, there is a union preceding
desire and a union following desire. The affective union precedes the movement of desire.73 Thus, love is a kind of becoming, taking place in the affect:
69
71
72
73
70 Ibid.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 30, a. 2c.
Ibid., q. 27, a. 2, ad 1. To love is indeed an act of the will tending to the good, but it adds a certain
union with the beloved, which union is not denoted by goodwill. Ibid., ad 2.
Amor praecedit desiderium. Ibid., III, q. 25, a. 2c.
The union of lover and beloved is twofold. There is real union, consisting in the conjunction of
one with the other. This union belongs to joy or pleasure, which follows desire. There is also an
affective union, consisting in an aptitude or proportion, insofar as one thing, from the very fact of
its having an aptitude for and an inclination to another, partakes of it: and love betokens such a
197
Goodwill properly speaking is that act of the will whereby we wish well to
another. Now this act of the will differs from actual love, considered not
only as being in the sensitive appetite but also as being in the intellective
appetite or will. For the love which is in the sensitive appetite is a passion.
Now every passion seeks its object with a certain eagerness. And the passion
of love is not aroused suddenly, but is born of an earnest consideration of the
beloved object; wherefore the Philosopher, showing the difference between
goodwill and the love which is a passion, says that goodwill does not imply
impetuosity or desire, that is to say, has not an eager inclination, because
it is by the sole judgment of his reason that one man wishes another well.
Again love of this kind arises from previous acquaintance, whereas goodwill
sometimes arises suddenly, as happens to us if we look on at a boxing-match,
and we wish one of the boxers to win. But that kind of love which is in the
intellective appetite also differs from goodwill, because it denotes a certain
union of the lovers heart with the beloved, in as much as the lover deems
the beloved as somehow one with him, or belonging to him, and so tends
toward him [movetur in ipsum]. On the other hand, goodwill is a simple act
of the will, whereby we wish a person well, even without presupposing the
aforesaid union of the heart with him.74
74
77
union. This union precedes the movement of desire [Unio affectiva . . . praecedit motum desiderii].
Ibid., ad 2.
75 Cf. ibid., III, q. 28, a. 1, ad 2.
76 Augustine, De trinitate, VIII.
Ibid., IIII, q. 27, a. 2c.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, III, q. 25, a. 1c. The union of lover and beloved is twofold.
The first is real union; for instance, when the beloved is present with the lover. The second is union
of affection: and this union must be considered in relation to the preceding apprehension; since
movement of the appetite follows apprehension. Now love being twofold, viz. love of concupiscence
and love of friendship, each of these arises from a kind of apprehension of the oneness of the thing
loved with the lover. For when we love a thing, by desiring it, we apprehend it as belonging to our
well-being. In like manner when a man loves another with the love of friendship, he wills good
198
The union, therefore, that love is in its essence takes place in the affect.
There occurs a mutual presence: The beloved is contained in the lover
insofar as he or she is impressed on the lovers heart [impressum in affectu] by
a kind of accompanying delight [per quandam complacentiam].78 (And,
conversely, the lover is also truly contained in the beloved insofar as the
lover pursues in a certain manner what is intimate in the beloved.79 )
Now, a further characteristic of the essence of love between friends,
desiring the company of one another, is that this desire remains essentially unfulfilled. This is primarily owing to reflective consciousness. It is
reflection that renders love unavoidably unfulfillable in the present human
condition. Since reflection differentiates between the being and the forma
of the object, the more self-conscious love becomes, the greater the cleft
between desire and its fulfillment. Observing oneself, even when it means
observing oneself being happy, implies a detachment: I as both the observer
and the observed.
Self-reflection lies at the core of the problem of human love for it is, on
the one hand, an indispensable prerequisite for fulfilling happiness and,
on the other hand, an ineluctable deterrent. It is fundamental that for
human beings happiness must be conscious, if it is to be happiness at all.
There is nothing, it may be presumed, which we value more highly than
consciousness. Human love is specifically conscious love. It is precisely I,
or we, who love. Through self-reflection, we are able to view whatever is
good qua good.80
Aquinas teaches, furthermore, that, as opposed to animals, we are able
to view sensual beauty as beautiful.81 Whereas, according to Aristotle and
Thomas, animals do experience pleasure, humans additionally take pleasure
in the beauty of sensible things.82 As a rule, the spirit enhances the sensual.
This can be explained by the fact that self-reflection always has some reality
as its content and it apprehends this content both as real and as possible,
thus enhancing its presence and rendering it, so to speak, more real. It
sees the contingency of reality. In fact, this is precisely the mode in which
human reflection grasps reality.
78
81
82
to him, just as he wills good to himself: wherefore he apprehends him as his other self, insofar,
to wit, as he wills good to him as to himself. Hence, a friend is called a mans other self (Ethic.,
IX, 4), and Augustine says (Confess., IV, 6), Well did one say to his friend: Thou half of my soul.
The first of these unions is caused effectively by love; because love moves man to desire and seek
the presence of the beloved, as of something suitable and belonging to him. The second union is
caused formally by love; because love itself is this union or bond. Ibid., q. 28, a. 1c.
79 Ibid.
80 Cf. ibid., I, q. 59, a. 1c. Cf. De veritate, q. 23, a. 1c.
Ibid., a. 2, ad 1.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 91, a. 3, ad 3.
Cf. ibid., IIII, q. 141, a. 4, ad 3.
199
The first thing to which the desire for good arising from love is directed
is the existence of the beloved. (Actually, self-reflection is nothing else but
the apprehension of the act of existence.) As Aristotle expressed it: what we
desire most with regard to ourselves is the apprehension of our existence.
Hence, the friend being a second self, what we desire most of him is
his existence.83 Here, the typical irony of the basic human situation comes
into play: self-reflection means both self-possession and self-alienation. For
conscious living, being present implies observing oneself, which in turn
involves a gap between oneself as subject and as object. Even in the word
I, which has the appearance of being able to attain complete identity, there
still lies a dualism of the observer and the observed. As subject, I see myself
as object. I thus involves a certain self-alienation, an inner cleft. Living in
reality implies an asymptotic hiatus. (This ontological suffering, moreover,
cannot be assuaged by justice.) Human experience remains per se conscious
experience. With its three distinct words, a statement like I love you is
disappointingly complex in comparison to the union it is trying to express.
The complete union with the other can be achieved only in a situation in which no cleft exists between what exists and its act of existence.
We conceive complete happiness as comprising the perfect identity of the
apprehension of the presence of the beloved together with ones consciousness of this. Ecstasy is therefore imagined to imply the extinguishment
of self-consciousness, self-forgetfulness, and conversely the total and
immediate presence in the other. But the realization of this vision shatters the vision, splits it in two. Complete union with the other with full
awareness would indeed overcome the dualism of the experience and the
experienced, eliminating the gap between being both one with oneself and
one with the other. Truth is nothing else but the conscious presence of an
object accompanied by the active awareness of this presence. If a knowing
subject were to obtain complete objectivity that is, a thoroughgoing identity of thought and object then, according to the standpoint of Thomas
Aquinas, there would be no truth at all. Truth always involves two factors namely, the object and the subject and, for there to be truth, the
subject must contribute something of its own [aliquid proprium].84 Without this duality, there could not be the phenomenon that we call truth
a name for the specific human way of being in reality. Not having the
problem of intentionality, an animal can be subsumed into its object uninhibitedly. A dog while eating is, enviably, one with its eating. Not having
83
84
Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, IX, 12; 1171 b 291172 a 3; 9; 1170 b 1019.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, De veritate, q. 1, a. 3c. Otherwise, Aquinas explains, one could not speak of
an adaequatio, as in the traditional definition of truth.
200
85
86
87
88
201
He concludes: To love God . . . would mean, then, to long for the attainment of the full capacity to love, for the realization of that which God
stands for in oneself.90 Thomas Aquinas, to the contrary, needs to make
no excessive demands on human nature since he does not hold God to be
merely a word that stands for a projected ideal, having no reality beyond
ourselves.
In sum, the union sought by love ultimately requires divine being, which
alone has the necessary ontological structure to bring about a union in
which union and its reflection attain the longed-for fulfillment. Therefore,
in the present human condition, love is opened to a kind of union that
can be attained only in the mode of eschatological hope. Love awakens
a vision that animates hope. This dimension is necessarily eschatological.
Nonetheless, the fact that the experience of love awakens a vision in us
that can find no satisfying fulfillment in this life is purposeful. We dream
of finding someone who is completely one with us. The dream is neither
fulfilled in time nor is it in vain.
Ibid., 60.
Cf. De dignitate conditionis humanae. Possibly written by Alcuin (d. 804), also ascribed to Athanasius.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, II, c. 80.
202
would call pain. The brain does not suffer pain. The two phases can be distinguished by the terms phantasm and species. The phantasm includes
the content of a sensible apprehension. Out of the phantasm, the light of
consciousness produces a species, which Rahner understands as a creation
of the spontaneous activity of the spirit which is of such a nature that as
such it can manifest the external object as passively received.93 The initial,
passive reception of an apprehension is also an act of the spirit because the
spirit is the soul of the body. Hence, the conclusion can be drawn:
When it [the free spirit] produces the phantasm, it determines itself not
merely insofar as, as the act of matter, it receives this determination as its
matter into itself, but as free it has already actively determined itself, and so
as separated soul it can retain in itself this determination which we called
earlier the intelligible species in the narrower sense.94
Thus, it is evident also that in the free spirit as such an intelligible species is
given which goes beyond the light of the intellect, beyond the a priori structure of the spirit, without the agent intellect as such becoming a patient.96
The phantasm that is, the empirical presence of the object in the
knower is subsumed into the reality of the intelligible species, which
means that it remains in the spirit possessing a kind of timelessness. In other
words, the individual person is indelibly and permanently determined by
his experiences during life. Life history is retained in memory, even after
bodily death. Rahner arrives at the following conclusion:
Thus, according to Thomas, the separated souls still have a relation to the
singular objects known earlier through a determination (determinantur) or
93
94
Ibid., 381.
95
Ibid.
96
Ibid.
203
In his novel Joseph and His Brothers, Thomas Mann depicts what he calls
The Sunken Treasure, lying more deeply in memory than the concomitant suffering:
She did not curse the man she loved because of the suffering he had caused
her, or that she had caused herself on his account, for the pains of love are
special pains that no one has ever repented having endured. You have made
my life rich it blossoms! Those were the words of Enis prayer in the
midst of her anguish, and one can see in them the special nature of loves
torments, which can even emerge as a prayer of thanksgiving. In any case,
she had lived and loved loved unhappily, to be sure, but is there really
such a thing and should not every sense of pity here be dismissed as silly and
officious? . . . And yet at the bottom of her soul lay a treasure in which she
secretly took greater pride than in all her spiritual and worldly honors, and
which, whether she admitted it or not, she would not have surrendered for
anything in the world. A sunken treasure in the depths but it still silently
sent its light up into the murky days of her renunciation. And however
much it represented her defeat it also lent to her spiritual and worldly pride
an indispensable element of essential humanity a pride in life. It was a
memory not so much of him, whom she heard had now become lord over
Egypt; he was merely an instrument, just as she, Mut-em-enet, had been an
instrument. But rather almost independently of him it was a recognition
97
Ibid., 381382.
98
204
205
206
The positive side of the ambivalent state in which we find ourselves lies,
for Weizsacker, in the resulting suffering that arouses insight. Its danger
lies in the incorrigible acceptance of partial happiness.110 Of course, this
does not imply the passive acceptance of concrete suffering; resistance is
the essential component. Suffering has this advantage over pleasure and joy
that it does not tempt us to stand still. For this reason, John of the Cross
could make the claim that the road of suffering is more secure and even
more profitable than that of fruition and action.111
This insight is old; many centuries earlier Boethius had written:
Strange is the thing I am trying to express. And for this cause I can scarce
find words to make clear my thought. For truly I believe that Ill Fortune
is of more use to men than Good Fortune. For Good Fortune, when she
wears the guise of happiness, and most seems to caress, is always lying; Ill
Fortune is always truthful, since, in changing, she shows her inconstancy.
The one deceives, the other teaches; the one enchains the minds of those
who enjoy her favor by the semblance of delusive good, the other delivers
them by the knowledge of the frail nature of happiness. Accordingly, thou
mayst see the one fickle, shifting as the breeze, and ever self-deceived; the
107
108
110
111
207
Do we then have to agree with Leibniz that this is the best possible world,
that is, that no better world say, in particular a world devoid of unjust
suffering is really possible? I would prefer to pose the question in the
following way: Is it good to create beings like us in a situation like ours?
Then the question can be posed whether God could create a better world
than ours. Stated in this way, we are dealing with a comparative instead of
a superlative.
Thomas Aquinas argues in favor of the thesis that the universe cannot
be better than it is. He compares it to a zither, saying that the melody of a
zither would be spoiled if an additional string were added to it. In his own
words: God cannot make something better than it is. Just as he cannot
make the number four larger, for, if it were, then it would no longer be the
number four. But he can make something better than it.113 A world totally
without suffering would not be this world of human beings. However, this
does not exclude the possibility that creatures could be improved in their
manner of existing or that a certain amount of suffering could be alleviated.
Humans can certainly become better humans for example, with regard
to their morality but they remain human. Nevertheless, a world without
suffering would no longer be human.
This approach can lead to the insight that suffering may possibly be more
advantageous for a successful life than pleasure or joy. It goes without saying
that we can mature personally through pleasure and joy, but suffering is
more advantageous for leading us to maturity, although it does involve
an acute risk of discouragement and despair. No normal person desires to
repose in pain. Pain makes us want to move away from it. Suffering is,
therefore, a more reliable incentive to keep on moving than pleasure and
joy. The meaning of life lies in the development of longing, and suffering
naturally arouses longing, whereas pleasure and joy are more characterized
by fulfillment.
Joy and suffering have in common that both give rise to longing, one in
a positive way, the other in a negative way. So it can even be maintained
that ultimately both serve the same purpose. In the case of joy, it is not so
112
113
208
easy to ascertain this significance since it seems to have its own meaning
in itself. It does not seem to be sensible to ask why we find joy good and
worth striving for. In any case, both open us to reality, albeit in opposite
ways. Reality itself teaches us, as it were, to open ourselves to it. We could
speak of a divine pedagogy of life. It cannot fully fail.
This has been incomparably expressed by Rainer Maria Rilke in his
poem Motto114 :
That is longing: living in turmoil
and having no home in time
and those are wishes: gentle dialogs
of days hours with eternity
And that is life. Until out of a yesterday
the most lonely hour rises
which, smiling differently than the other sisters (hours)
silently encounters eternity
Religion explicates the fundamental relativization of the self. The self can
become aware of the fact that it is not the hub of the universe surrounding
it. There exist other selves who see me as an object, integrating me in their
own worlds. I can objectivize myself and regard myself as one factor in a
comparison, so that I can conclude that another person has more right in a
given situation than I do. I can be humble without disparaging my talents
and achievements.
Wildes profound claim that Nothing in the whole world is meaningless,
suffering least of all holds true not only for prison but also for the depths of
a Nazi concentration camp during World War II. Even in a concentration
camp, the will to live can be established only by making larger sense out of
ones seemingly senseless suffering. Suffering is a contradiction to happiness
but not to living. To live is to suffer; surviving depends on finding meaning
in suffering. If life has any purpose at all, then there must be a purpose in
suffering and in dying.
Writing from his own experience in a concentration camp during World
War II, Viktor E. Frankl confirms this point of view:
The experience of camp life shows that man does have a choice of action.
There were enough examples, often of a heroic nature, which proved that
apathy could be overcome, irritability suppressed. Man can preserve a vestige of spiritual freedom, of independence of mind, even in such terrible
conditions of psychic and physical stress.115
114
115
209
The fact that a few prisoners were able to make sacrifices is for Frankl a
proof that a fundamental freedom of choice still exists:
We who lived in concentration camps can remember the men who walked
through the huts comforting others, giving away their last piece of bread.
They may have been few in number, but they offer sufficient proof that
everything can be taken from a man but one thing: the last of the human
freedoms to choose ones attitude in any given set of circumstances, to
choose ones own way. And there were always choices to make. Every day,
every hour, offered the opportunity to make a decision, a decision which
determined whether you would or would not submit to those powers which
threatened to rob you of your very self, your inner freedom; which determined whether or not you would become the plaything of circumstance,
renouncing freedom and dignity to become molded into the form of the
typical inmate.116
Frankl refers to Dostoyevsky, who asserts that one can become worthy of
ones suffering, if the inner freedom is upheld:
Dostoyevsky said once, There is only one thing that I dread: not to be
worthy of my sufferings. These words frequently came to my mind after
I became acquainted with those martyrs whose behavior in camp, whose
suffering and death, bore witness to the fact that the last inner freedom
cannot be lost. It can be said that they were worthy of their sufferings;
the way they bore their suffering was a genuine inner achievement. It is this
spiritual freedom which cannot be taken away that makes life meaningful
and purposeful.118
116
Ibid., 6566.
117
Ibid., 66.
118
Ibid.
210
Frankl concludes:
Whenever one is confronted with an inescapable, unavoidable situation
whenever one has to face a fate which cannot be changed, e.g., an incurable
disease, such as an inoperable cancer; just then one is given a last chance to
actualize the highest value, to fulfill the deepest meaning, the meaning of
suffering. For what matters above all is the attitude we take toward suffering,
the attitude in which we take our suffering upon ourselves . . . A bit later,
I remember, it seemed to me that I would die in the near future. In this
critical situation, however, my concern was different from that of most of
my comrades. Their question was, Will we survive the camp? For, if not, all
this suffering has no meaning. The question which beset me was, Has all
this suffering, this dying around us, a meaning? For, if not, then ultimately
there is no meaning to survival; for a life whose meaning depends upon such
a happenstance as whether one escapes or not would ultimately not be
worth living at all.121
Survival, then, cannot be the ultimate purpose of living. In this sense, even
the ideal of political peace is criticized by Vaclav Havel. In the context of
the peace movement, he maintains that the absence of heroes who know
for what they are dying is the first step to the piles of corpses of those who
are slaughtered like cattle. He calls the peace ideal a bait and argues that a
life that is not willing to sacrifice itself for its own meaning is not worth
119
Ibid., 67.
120
Ibid.
121
Ibid.
211
123
126
212
To the fetus, birth appears to be death. What the caterpillar calls the end
of the world, to quote Laotse, the rest of the world calls a butterfly.
It certainly goes without saying that this does not mean that suffering
is eliminated or alleviated in itself. But it does reveal a dimension that
is meaningful and hence a way to legitimatize suffering. If absolutely no
meaning could be found in connection with suffering, then the logically
compulsory conclusion would be a rejection of God, at least, as he is understood in the Christian tradition. A believer cannot simply be consternated
and then go on living as before.
127
Ibid.
128
213
214
of Thomass text, which states that God permits evil in order to produce
good; even for God, the end does not justify the means. In other words,
there is no contradiction, for infinite goodness even encompasses suffering
as well as other forms of evil. Thomas does not attempt to relativize divine
goodness, as though evil somehow were to lie beyond God.
Hence, it is not as though suffering and joy were being compared on the
same scale. If there were no intrinsic meaning involved with suffering, then
it would be impossible to justify a single tear of a weeping child. In Gods
eyes, not even the slightest suffering lies beyond his attention. Instead,
salvation must be a development of suffering and not just a compensation
for it. Grace perfects nature. Swimming well may result in winning a
trophy, but it also results in healthier muscles. Without suffering, there
would be no potentiality for the fulfillment of the longing that suffering
has produced. Only he who has once suffered from a toothache knows the
pleasure of being freed from the pain. As expressed by Thomas: Good is
better known in contrast with evil, and while evil results come about, we
more ardently desire good results: as sick men best know what a blessing
health is.134 Can a man know the joy that a new mother experiences after
a successful childbirth without ceasing to be a man? The joy of arrival
cannot be without the journey. Can the delight of seeing a lost friend again
be had in any other way? There can be no fulfillment of longing without
the longing, and Eternal Life could not attain more.
The significance of suffering is, in short, paradoxical. It is neither good
nor meaningful in itself; to the contrary, it is naturally and rightly rejected.
The rejection of suffering or, for that matter, the experience of any other
kind of evil is the result of a belief in the fundamental goodness of
reality. However, a protest against religion on the grounds of suffering is a
misunderstanding of ones own nature, which owing to reflection reveals
negative aspects even of positive experiences (e.g., their temporariness). But
precisely therein lies its specific function in the attainment of meaning.
Feeling need is necessary for life. A person who never knows hunger is
sick, for we need food. Who would want an infected appendix not to be
painful? Like some other forms of pain, it is a meaningful signal. One
could go so far as to say that if we could not attain fulfillment without
134
enhances our admiration of the good; for we enjoy and value the good more when we compare it
with the evil. For the Almighty God, who, as even the heathen acknowledges, has supreme power
over all things, being himself supremely good, would never permit the existence of anything evil
among his works, if he were not so omnipotent and good that he could bring good even out of
evil. For what is that which we call evil but the absence of good?
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 71.
215
God, then it would be a sign of sickness not to strive for absolute meaning
(i.e., God). It would be a subjective defect not to need God. Whatever
arouses a subjective awareness of a need for God would be a means of
becoming healthy. Then, the definitive completion of life can take place;
otherwise, there would be nothing that could come to completion. In the
inner response to failure, the true attitude toward life is revealed.
Regardless of whatever else can be said about suffering, at least viewed
eschatologically, it possesses a positive aspect, which depends on the natural
resistance to it that suffering ignites. This in no way implies a weakening
of the fight against suffering. To the contrary, the attitude of fighting
suffering can quite readily distract from a genuine appreciation of it; often,
compassion is a more appropriate reaction. Granting forgiveness for a
suffered injustice also represents a highly noble response impossible
without the existence of guilt, which is a deep form of suffering. Easily
convinced that suffering should not really exist, we tend to overlook its
essence. But we overlook the essence of life itself if we believe that suffering
does not belong to it but that it is rather the result of external conditions
that can be eliminated. Weizsacker argues:
The idea that suffering is simply a result of reproachable social developments
is naive (or a projection); why do we have the ability to feel physical and
psychological pain if we did not have need of these indicators?135
216
The deepest cause of suffering, finally, is self-consciousness. Self-consciousness turns everything, whether in itself positive or negative, into a
kind of suffering because of the observers separation from his or her own
consciousness. Furthermore, the conscious awareness of suffering opens
the door to its deeper positive meaning. The suffering caused by selfconsciousness cannot be assuaged, for it belongs to the very essence of
human life.
Within modern Christianity, Weil notes that the only means to avoid
suffering is not to think. The awakening of thought, she writes, is
painful.139 As Kafka expressed it: The bone of his own forehead obstructs
his way; he knocks himself bloody against his own forehead.140
217
Morality puts us instead on the right path toward the end. All of morality
can be summarized in love. Every virtue is a form of love, every moral action
an expression of love. It is, precisely speaking, love that will be brought to
ultimate validity in Eternal Life. As Aquinas argues:
The final end of something is that to which it strives to attain by its own
operations. But by all its own ordered and right operations man strives to
attain to the contemplation of truth, for the operations of the active virtues
are a kind of preparation and disposition for the contemplative virtues.
Mans end therefore is to attain to the contemplation of truth. For this
reason the soul is united to the body, which is mans being. Hence, being
united to a body does not mean that the knowledge one had is lost, but
rather the soul is united to the body so that it may acquire knowledge.143
The essence of morality lies in the cardinal virtue of prudence. The morally
good human is the prudent human. According to the Catechism of the
Catholic Church (n. 1806), prudence is called auriga virtutum (the charioteer of the virtues); it guides the other virtues by setting rule and measure.
It is prudence that immediately guides the judgment of conscience. Prudence is the virtue that makes the other virtues be virtues.144 It is the orientation of human life in accordance with reason, which, in turn, receives
its orientation from reality. Every moral virtue, as Thomas also expresses
it, is necessarily prudent,145 and No moral virtue is possible without
prudence.146 Temperance is not per se a virtue. If temperance be in the
concupiscible, without prudence being in the rational part, temperance is
not a virtue,147 Thomas emphasizes.
What prudence accomplishes is to put the concrete act into the perspective of the final end, thus uniting the universal and the particular. It
concretizes the general goal of life in individual decisions.
Because it views the concrete in a universal perspective, it is called the
wisdom that is accessible to humans.148 The specific human form of the
contemplative life, which actually transcends the human [superhumana], is
the moral life that is, the living out of the moral virtues.149 As Thomas
explains:
143
144
146
147
148
149
merely negative (relief from preceding anxiety); and this alone is what can be ascribed to virtue, as
a struggle against the influence of the evil principle in a human being (emphasis in original).
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, II, c. 83.
145 Thomas Aquinas, De virtutibus, q. 1, a. 12, ad 23.
Cf. Pieper, Werke, Vol. IV, 5.
Thomas Aquinas, De veritate, q. 14, a. 6.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 4, a. 5c.
Cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, VI, 8; Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 47, a. 1, ad 2.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, De virtutibus, q. 5, a. 1c.
218
150
151
Ibid., a. 9, ad 2.
219
Unity with the will of God is the Christian formula for morality, being one
with God is the Christian formula for eudaimonia. That which motivates
moral action namely, love is, at the same time, that of which fulfillment
is thought of as blessedness. Morality is not disinterested any more than
blessedness is egoistical. The Christian thinking in terms of reward, which is
so massively present in the New Testament, can be understood only in terms
of God himself saying: I myself will be your reward (Gn 15:1). Concerning
the love which inspires all moral action, Paul said, it does not end, which
means that it outlasts the stage of morality, which is only one of its forms of
appearance.152
220
What is most important in the idea of responsibility is the ultimate dependence of human existence. Our decisions always have the form of responses.
It is difficult to appreciate this from an atheistic point of view. If God
does not exist, then, as Dostoyevsky says, everything is permitted. But
the response extends further than Hans Jonass reduction of responsibility
to a relationship between humans: Responsibility is primarily between
human beings . . . The archetype of all responsibility is that of a human for
a human.158
In our notion of responsibility, there is additionally an aspect of transcendence implied. The constitution of Germany begins with the expression,
Conscious of their responsibility before God and men. The constitution
even maintains that we have responsibility for future generations, to whom
we will hardly be known. In the constitution of Japan (1946), in which
the word occurs for the first time in a constitution, there is obviously a
transcendent dimension reaching beyond the sovereignty of the people:
We believe that no nation is responsible to itself alone, but that laws of
political morality are universal; and that obedience to such laws is incumbent
upon all nations who would sustain their own sovereignty and justify their
sovereign relationship with other nations.
Since this time, the term has become commonplace. Indicative of the
inflationary development is the constitution of South Africa (1997), in
which the word responsibility occurs more than fifty times.
A different kind of exaggeration of the importance of responsibility
is the idea that individuals can be responsible for the world. This idea
is understandable if one presumes that there is no creator. Probably the
idea is a form of secularization: Gods responsibility is turned into human
responsibility. But, of course, no human being has an overview of the
157
Ibid., 77.
158
221
world and of the coming history and thus cannot carry responsibility for
it all. To argue from the point of view of a responsibility for the world and
history is a deception, which often serves as a subterfuge to avoid the real
responsibility that one has.
Responsibility is by essence always limited. Havel criticized the peace
movement for absolutizing responsibility. The claim to possess a viewpoint
from which an entire situation can be evaluated is a misunderstanding. The
conclusion that peace, for example, is an absolute, to which everything else
must be subordinated, does have the appearance of being moral, but it is
not so in reality. Survival cannot be the highest value for a human.
The nature of responsibility is such that it can be meaningfully realized
even in the case of a failure to achieve for what one was striving. In failure,
success can occur. Frankl articulates this in a uniquely moving way:
An active life serves the purpose of giving man the opportunity to realize
values in creative work, while a passive life of enjoyment affords him the
opportunity to obtain fulfillment in experiencing beauty, art, or nature. But
there is also purpose in that life which is almost barren of both creation and
enjoyment and which admits of but one possibility of high moral behavior:
namely, in mans attitude to his existence, an existence restricted by external
forces. A creative life and a life of enjoyment are banned to him. But not
only creativeness and enjoyment are meaningful.159
Meaning exists in the world before I become active. Martin Luther made
the observation: It is the surest sign of a bad will, namely, that it cannot
accept being hindered.160 How I react to success and failure should not
differ essentially. Resignation because of failure is a bad sign. Spaemann
approaches this from the presumption that two individuals stand in conflict
with one another, both with a good conscience:
Then the conflict of Kreon and Antigone would not take place. Still, the
ultimate purity of motivation will show itself primarily in the fact that each
of the two is prepared to calmly accept the outcome, even when it thwarts
his or her own plans because what mattered to them was the beauty of the
action which is pleasing to God and not the forcing of a certain outcome.
Tranquility is the criterium of love of God.161
160
222
223
The omnipresence of Gods omniscient eye is reduced to conscience. Conscience is experienced as the court before which the individual is at one
and the same time the accused, the accuser, and the judge. To avoid a
contradiction, Kant claims that we imagine our judge as being a person
who differs from ourselves, existing at the end of history:
Now, this original intellectual and (since it is the thought of duty) moral
predisposition called conscience is peculiar in that, although its business is
a business of a human being with himself, one constrained by his reason
sees himself constrained to carry it on as at the bidding of another person.
For the affair here is that of trying a case (causa) before a court. But to
think of a human being who is accused by his conscience as one and the same
person as the judge is an absurd way of representing a court, since then the
prosecutor would always lose. For all duties a human beings conscience
will, accordingly, have to think of someone other than himself (i.e., other
than the human being as such) as the judge of his actions, if conscience is
not to be in contradiction with itself. This other may be an actual person or
a merely ideal person that reason creates for itself.166
224
It is obvious that conscience as judge possesses, according to Kant, characteristics that belong to the God of the Final Judgment:
Such an ideal person (the authorized judge of conscience) must be a scrutinizer of hearts, since the court is set up within the human being. But
he must also impose all obligation, that is, he must be, or be thought as, a
person in relation to whom all duties whatsoever are to be regarded as also
his commands; for conscience is the inner judge of all free actions.170
167
169
225
Be that as it may, for Kant it remains impossible to view the judge as a really
existent person, seeing that the whole question revolves around practical
reason:
This is not to say that a human being is entitled, through the idea to which
his conscience unavoidably guides him, to assume that such a supreme being
actually exists outside himself still less that he is bound by his conscience
to do so. For the idea is not given to him objectively, by theoretical reason,
but only subjectively, by practical reason, putting itself under obligation
to act in keeping with this idea; and through using practical reason, but
only in following out the analogy with a lawgiver for all rational beings in
the world, human beings are merely pointed in the direction of thinking
of conscientiousness [Verantwortlichkeit] (which is also called religio) as
accountability to a holy being (morally lawgiving reason) distinct from us
yet present in our inmost being, and of submitting to the will of this being,
as the rule of justice. The concept of religion is here for us only a principle
of estimating all our duties as divine commands.172
The Last Judgment thus becomes a symbol, and its reality, in various
aspects, is now to be found in individual conscience.
Against this background, we can better understand why defining an
extremely important notion in our understanding of life is a cause for
embarrassment. The idea of responsibility proves to be not merely an
object, or product, of pure rationality.
Furthermore, it becomes understandable why no equivalent of responsibility existed in ancient Greek. Greek morality is essentially different
from a morality of responsibility. It is not surprising, then, that an extensive study of the idea of responsibility among the ancient Greeks comes to
the conclusion that there not only was no such idea but that the idea was
even unthinkable.173
With the Last Judgment scene, Christianity puts morality into a new
and completely different context from the conception of Greek thought.
171
173
226
Eschatology becomes mythology, and its place is taken over by an abstraction; this abstraction combines in one notion both God and man. It is no
wonder that the notion is at once potent and quite diffuse.
The interpretation of the Last Judgment as being responsibility that is,
as a matter of conscience is not new. In the ninth century, John Scotus Eriugena taught that the Last Judgment actually takes place in conscience.175
For traditional theology, it has been clear that conscience plays a decisive
role in eschatology. In other words, Kants teaching is not an accentuation
of conscience; rather, it is an elimination of eschatology. Ethics has always
been a part of Christian thought. This presents a wonderful example of
the attempt of an autonomous morality to establish its independence from
Christianity.
If the Christian world has become a world of symbols, then the notion
of responsibility acquires a new importance. In it, the weight is instilled
that was previously predicated of God. The highest respect is due to it.
Responsibility is all-knowing and all-just. Its relevance is stronger than
the Biblical scene of the Last Judgment, which is an obvious metaphor,
whereas responsibility is certainly not regarded as one. The divine reality
is contained in the idea of responsibility. But is it possible to reduce the
Christian idea to mere responsibility and still retain its extraordinary
force and qualities?
174
175
227
Havel feels that conscience implies more than just an autonomous oughtness and that responsibility involves the idea that someone is watching
us:
It seems to me that even when no one is watching, and even when he is
certain no one will ever find out about his behavior, there is something in
man that compels him to behave (to a degree, at least) as though someone
were constantly observing him. And if he does something he shouldnt in
such a situation, he may even engage in a kind of dialogue with this
observer, pleading his own case and attempting, in all manner of ways, to
explain and apologize for his own behavior.
Havel believes that the ground of Being is somehow present. In opposition to Kants analysis, he calls it a meta-experience:
Kant talks about the moral law within me and the categorical imperative,
but he understands it, I think, too exclusively as an a priori and not enough
as a concrete experience of existence, or rather as a meta-experience.
228
This is, of course, not explicitly Christian language, but associating God
with Being, or the total integrity of Being is common enough in Christian
theology. In any case, in responsibility, there exists a transcendence beyond
the concrete world and in this transcendence human identity has its essence.
Responsibility is always responsibility to someone:
But to whom are we responsible? I dont know to whom, but it is certainly
not, in the final instance, to any of the transitory things of this world. It
follows that I am convinced that the primary source of all responsibility,
or better still, the final reason for it, is the assumption of an absolute
horizon. It is precisely responsibility as the bearer of continuity and thus
of identity, that is the clearest existential reflection or pledge in man of
the permanence and absoluteness of the absolute horizon of Being. It might
be said, therefore, that this absolute horizon is present in us not only as an
assumption, but also as a source of humanity and as a challenge.
Aware that God is often anthropomorphically understood, Havel hesitates to speak explicitly of God, but one can imagine no other possible
explanation:
Clearly this is a supremely spiritual experience, or rather an experience of
something supremely spiritual. Nevertheless, I confess I still cant talk of God
in this connection . . . If God does not occupy the place I am trying to define
here, it will all appear to be no more than some abstract shilly-shallying. But
what am I to do?
229
230
for having a bad character without its resulting in actions. Havel describes
a feeling that we are being observed by a transcendent judge, a supernatural
conscience, so to speak. Responsibility is not limited to taking on responsibility for something; we can also be held responsible for something.
Responsibility implies a personal relationship to a higher being. As Picht in
his important essay on responsibility writes, when we call the accountability of a subordinate to his superior responsibility, an ethical dimension
in the relationship is revealed. The superior appears as the representative
of a higher order that possesses an unbounded absoluteness.177 For Havel,
our personal identity arises out of this relationship.178
At the beginning of the history of modern democracy, the essential Christian elements of our notion of responsibility were articulated in the American Declaration of Independence, albeit in a deistic form. In the final
paragraph, two phrases were inserted into Jeffersons original version.
One is an explicit appeal to the judge of the world (appealing to the
Supreme Judge of the world for the rectitude of our intentions) and
the other states: with a firm reliance on the protection of divine Providence. In this context, the notion of responsibility would be superfluous. In fact, the word did not exist in English at this time. The concept
of divine predestination, however, was common. The idea of democracy
originally included a historic consciousness. History was believed to be
moving toward a goal. Even if the goal remained unknown to us concretely, the belief in it was supported by the belief in the divine will.179 In
the United States of America, there prevailed a sense of mission for the
world.
It can be observed that the idea of responsibility to is gradually disappearing. In the Constitution of South Africa, in which the notion of
responsibility occurs, as mentioned previously, in an inflationary manner,
the expression responsibility to is completely missing. Responsibility is
being secularized. The element of transcendence is being eclipsed.
6.6.3 The individuality of responsibility
Responsibility involves individuality. There is not a general responsibility
that is valid for everyone. The responsibility of parents for their children
177
178
179
231
They can find different answers although both are seeking the true good.
For a similar reason, no human carries responsibility for the world.
This is a common misconception. Responsibility implies that there is an
ultimate judge to whom one must answer. Only God could have such a
responsibility, but responsibility does not apply to him at all. Aquinas poses
the surprising question of whether it is necessary for the human will, in
order to be good, to be conformed to the divine will, as regards the thing
willed.182
Although this sounds like the very essence of Christian morality, Thomas
responds negatively. According to him, first of all, we actually cannot know
180
181
Ibid.
182
Ibid.
232
what God wills concretely. But this is not what is required of us. In a
general sense, our intention can always conform to the divine will but not
necessarily in respect to the concrete particular question. We can know
in a general way what God wills, Thomas admits. For we know that
whatever God wills, he wills it under the aspect of good. Consequently,
whoever wills a thing under any aspect of good, has a will conformed to
the divine will, as to the reason of the thing willed. But we know not what
God wills in particular: and in this respect we are not bound to conform
our will to the divine will.183
Thomas differentiates in the following manner: What human beings
should will is not necessarily that which God wills that it occurs but rather
that which God wants them to will184 in other words, what their
conscience dictates. This can be quite different for different people, not to
mention the fact that conscience can err.
The relationship to God lies in the intentional perspective. In the ideal
case, one chooses a concrete good because of the fact that it is good; that is,
it represents goodness. In the words of Aquinas: A mans will is not right
in willing a particular good, unless he refers it to the common good as an
end: since even the natural appetite of each part is ordained to the common
good of the whole. We naturally raise our arm to protect our head from
a blow. The intention defines the quality of the action: Now it is the end
that supplies the formal reason, as it were, of willing whatever is directed to
the end. Consequently, in order that a man wills some particular good with
a right will, he must will that particular good materially, and the divine
and universal good formally. For this reason, it is possible to contradict
the divine will and, at the same time, conform to it: Therefore the human
will is bound to be conformed to the divine will, as to that which is willed
formally, for it is bound to will the divine and universal good; but not as
to that which is willed materially.185
Doing the right thing is not yet morality. In other words, the virtue of
prudence is indispensable. Because humans exist in a tension between the
concrete and the abstract, moral choices are a matter of comparatives. The
superlative pertains to the horizon or final end, whereas choices always
take place in the concrete. An ethics respecting the individual conscience
excludes, therefore, responsibility for the world, taken as a whole. Humans
never know what the best in a given situation really is.
183
Ibid., ad 1.
184
Ibid., a. 10c.
185
Ibid.
233
For this reason, pure idealism is in itself immoral. Rather than coming
to moral decisions by comparing alternatives, the idealist proceeds by way
of a deduction from what he considers to be the highest good. Since he
avoids the complications of the concrete, which always exhibits different
aspects, he tends to become self-righteous. He readily imagines that he has
a clean conscience.
6.6.4 The subordination of civil law to moral law
The subjective individuality of morality is the basis for the human right
of freedom of conscience that is, the acknowledged right to do what is,
presumably, objectively wrong. The relevance of this insight can be further
seen in the idea that the state cannot forbid by law everything that is
immoral. The individuality of the citizens can take preference over general
moral values and rules, with eschatology providing an ultimate goal that
transcends all worldly matters. Morality is not something absolute in this
life. Hence, the state does not have to forbid whatever is immoral. For a
well-functioning society, enjoying peace and justice is not the ultimate goal
of human life.
This unusual position of Thomas Aquinas is certainly relevant. According to him, there can be good reasons for civil law to diverge from moral
law. Something may not be forbidden by civil law simply because it is
immoral; other factors must be given consideration. Thomass position is
based on more than the pluralistic state of society. It is valid in a society
that is dominated by the Christian Church, as in the Middle Ages, during
which Thomas is writing. The principle is also valid in a theocratic society
that sees civil law as a direct transposition of divine law. The individually
limited sphere of responsibility perhaps ironically transcends civil law.
Admittedly, Thomas is easy to misunderstand. As an example, Martin
Luther King, Jr., who attributed precisely the contrary position to him,
can be cited:
Just law is a man-made code that squares with the moral law or the law of
God. An unjust law is a code that is out of harmony with the moral law. To
put it in the terms of Saint Thomas Aquinas, an unjust law is a human law
that is not rooted in eternal and natural law. Any law that uplifts human
personality is just. Any law that degrades human personality is unjust. All
segregation statutes are unjust because segregation distorts the soul and
damages the personality.186
186
234
Thomas himself was not unaware of an argument like this but against it, he
appeals to a subjective aspect. The pivotal point is based on the difference
between an action and a habit. Whereas actions occur in objective reality,
habits exist in the inner personal character of individuals. I divide Thomass
argument into the following steps:
(1) Law is framed as a rule or measure of human acts. Now a measure
should be homogeneous with that which it measures. Wherefore laws
imposed on men should also be in keeping with their condition.
(2) Now possibility or faculty of action is due to an interior habit or
disposition: since the same thing is not possible to one who has not
a virtuous habit, as is possible to one who has.
(3) Thus the same is not possible to a child as to a full-grown man:
for which reason the law for children is not the same as for adults,
since many things are permitted to children, which in an adult are
punished by law or at any rate are open to blame.
(4) In like manner many things which are permissible to men not
perfect in virtue should not be tolerable [tolleranda] in a virtuous
man.
(5) Now human law is framed for a number of human beings, the
majority of whom are not perfect in virtue. Wherefore human laws
do not forbid all vices, from which the virtuous abstain, but only
the more grievous vices, from which it is possible for the majority to
abstain; and chiefly those that are to the hurt of others, without the
prohibition of which human society could not be maintained: thus
human law prohibits murder, theft, and such like.187
Then, Thomas adds a further explanation. By overtaxing people, their
behavior can become worse:
The purpose of human law is to lead men to virtue, not suddenly, but
gradually. Wherefore it does not lay upon the multitude of imperfect men
the burdens of those who are already virtuous, that is, that they should
abstain from all evil. Otherwise these imperfect ones, being unable to bear
such precepts, would break out into yet greater evils. Thus, it is written
(Ps 30:33): He that violently bloweth his nose, bringeth out blood; and
(Mt 9:17) that if new wine, that is, precepts of a perfect life, is put
into old bottles, that is, into imperfect men, the bottles break, and the
wine runneth out, that is, the precepts are despised, and those men, from
contempt, break into evils worse still.188
187
188
Ibid., ad 2.
235
In this way, Thomas arrives at the conclusion that civil law must not always
be in conformity with the divine eternal law:
The natural law is a participation in us of the eternal law: while human law
falls short of the eternal law. Now Augustine says: The law which is framed
for the government of states, allows and leaves unpunished many things
that are punished by divine providence. Nor, if this law does not attempt to
do everything, is this a reason why it should be blamed for what it does.
Wherefore, too, human law does not prohibit everything that is forbidden
by the natural law.189
236
chapter s ev en
Sensuality
The resurrection of the body
In this chapter, the heuristic principle that I have called the anthropological
factor is applied explicitly to the resurrected body. When it has become
conscious, human sensuality is not a purely biological phenomenon; added
to it is a participation in spirit. There is an essential difference between the
ordinary processes of gathering information through stimuli and reacting
to it in my stomach while it is digesting and the discomfort or pain that
might arise from it and enter into my consciousness. Conscious sensuality
represents a heightening of preconscious sense activities. If life has a meaning, then we must let our thinking and willing be shaped by the structure
of means and ends that is given by reality. Living like this in the truth does
not impinge on human dignity; it is a conformation to it. Conformity of
this nature is not self-alienation but rather leads to an inner harmony, to a
kind of friendship with ones self. As a result of the peculiar intentionality of
human nature, friendship with reality brings about friendship with oneself.
Human existence is per se existence in the world. Similarly, sensuality must
be viewed and affirmed in its true role in reality, thus becoming specifically
human. Then its relevancy for the perfection of human nature will become
visible. If we understand body or flesh as signifying sensuality, then the
question arises in what way the resurrection of the body is a participation
in Eternal Life. What does a body, or bodiliness, have to do with the vision
of God? In what does the relationship of sensuality to God consist?
The Christian teaching speaks paradoxically but happily of a spiritual body (Sown as an animal body, it is raised as a spiritual body. 1
Cor 15:44). In other words, a non-bodily body a real body and yet not a
body. Although it is not an oxymoron, the term spiritual body is admittedly misleading. The Greek word provides some help. Greek adjectives
ending in -ikos describe not the material out of which things are made but
the power or energy that animates them,1 notes Wright with regard to
1
237
238
Sensuality
spiritual, which in Greek is pneumatikon. Tradition also calls it a resurrected body, a transfigured, glorified body, illuminated as it were by the
Light of Glory. Glorification is an appropriate term. We cannot know
now what such a body will be like, but we can presume that it will not
be less real than our present body. Strictly speaking, it can be said that
whatever can be experienced as good in our present body will have to be
included in the resurrection.
Conversely, to see God, there must be an abstraction from the bodily
senses. It is a matter of attention, and attention is a kind of abstraction. The
mind must be fully concentrated on God and not diverted by attention to
the senses. It is typical for human beings that they cannot pay attention
to all of the cognitive powers simultaneously. If I am listening attentively
to someone, I may be neglecting my seeing and smelling. Hence, Thomas
states:
But for the understanding to be raised up to the vision of the divine essence,
the whole attention must be concentrated on this vision since this is the
most intensely intelligible object, and the understanding can reach it only by
striving for it with a total effort. Therefore, it is necessary to have complete
abstraction from the bodily senses when the mind is raised to the vision of
God.2
Furthermore, the importance of attention is even accentuated for spiritual consciousness since the mind operates in an immaterial sphere, either
by knowing abstract things or by abstracting from material things. Thus,
knowledge is more or less freed from materiality as such. The more immaterial its object, the higher the intellects knowledge. Thomas notes:
Therefore, if it is ever raised beyond its ordinary level to see the highest
of immaterial things, namely, the divine essence, it must be wholly cut off
from the sight of material things, at least, during that act. Hence, since the
sensitive powers can deal only with material things, one cannot be raised to
a vision of the divine essence unless one is wholly deprived of the use of the
bodily senses.3
Ibid.
239
Sensuality
other hand, that the senses partake in Eternal Life. Put in another way:
death is a prerequisite and the resurrection is a necessity. In other words,
if physical existence ceases, it can in a certain sense be resurrected in the
vision of God. The difference lies in the structure of the relationship. If
a multitude can be seen in a unified whole, then this is possible. If many
things can be viewed under one aspect, as is, for example, the case with
universal notions, then it is possible to grasp many things simultaneously
with one simple act. This is a general rule:
In this way our intellect understands together both the subject and the
predicate as forming parts of one proposition; and also two things compared
together, according as they agree in one point of comparison. From this it is
evident that many things, insofar as they are distinct, cannot be understood
at once; but insofar as they are comprised under one intelligible concept,
they can be understood together.5
Seen in this way, the vision of God can include a multitude of everything
that one has loved in this life but included in this one, single, eternal vision
of God.
The resurrection of the body is also described as an overflowing [redundantia]. As Aquinas expresses it:
After the resurrection, the beatified soul will be joined to the body in
a different way from that in which it is now united to it. For, in the
resurrection, the body will be entirely subject to the spirit to such an extent
that the properties of glory will overflow from the spirit into the body.
Hence, they will be called spiritual bodies . . . Therefore, in the resurrection
there will be no defilement of the understanding and its power will not be
weakened in any way by any union whatsoever with the body. Hence, even
without transport out of the bodily senses, it will contemplate the divine
essence. However, the body is not now subject to the spirit in this way.6
Because we are a unity, the senses can distract from the intellect in the
present life and in Eternal Life, the intellect can overflow to the senses.7 It
belongs to the essence of the human soul that it needs the senses: Since
the soul is united to the body as its natural form, it belongs to the soul to
have a natural disposition to understand by turning to phantasms.8
Sensuality must be distinguished from the senses. The senses are physical,
whereas sensuality occurs within consciousness. C. S. Lewis articulates it
well:
5
6
7
Ibid., a. 5c.
240
Sensuality
About the resurrection of the body. I agree with you that the old picture
of the soul re-assuming the corpse perhaps blown to bits or long since
usefully dissipated through nature is absurd. Nor is it what St. Pauls words
imply. And I admit that if you ask me what I substitute for this, I have only
speculations to offer. The principle behind these speculations is this. We
are not, in this doctrine, concerned with matter as such at all; with waves
and atoms and all that. What the soul cries out for is the resurrection of
the senses. Even in this life matter would be nothing to us if it were not the
source of sensations.9
10
Ibid., 121.
11
Sensuality
241
only matter we know and would miss. Neuroscience speaks of the qualia
of consciousness. Our experience is not as concrete as we might tend to
think. That is, I know matter but my knowing is not material. I know that
my body is composed of chemicals, but I am usually not really interested
in them. The neuronal processes in my brain are not as interesting to me
as the qualia they make possible.
We are standing in a fascinating countryside, seeing the hills and trees,
smelling the vegetation, feeling the warm air on our skin, hearing the birds
and insects. All of this exists in our consciousness as a unity and in a higher
form than in the world or in the senses (the brain knows no such feelings).
The resurrection of the body must be analogous to this.
We are familiar with an emergence from the physical to the spiritual.
When I see a rose, for example, activities take place in my nerves. The form,
the smell, the color of the rose have arisen in my nerves. But I do not yet
experience them. Then it can happen that they emerge into consciousness.
I am aware of seeing and smelling the rose. By reflecting on my experience, I
can realize that the rose is red. At this point, I have a predicative perception
of the rose; I can form sentences about it, which may be true or false. This
is knowledge that arises through the senses, but it is of a higher nature. It
implies that I do not just see the rose; I also am aware of seeing it. I see
it, in other words, as a reality. This is a perception of which the senses are
incapable. Out of materiality, something immaterial has emerged.
The emergence of the original perception can continue further. I can see
the rose as beautiful and good. I take pleasure in it; or, even further: I may
experience joy or delight. Joy is more spiritual than pleasure. Moreover,
out of pleasure, joy can arise and out of joy, the happiness of Eternal Life
can arise.
There can be no doubt that for the Christianity of the Modern Age,
the whole dimension of sensual pleasure has been quite foreign. However,
the theology of the Middle Ages commonly had a rather open attitude
toward eros. This is exemplified by the many commentaries of the Canticle
of Canticles and also in the Scholastic Dotes-teaching that is, the depiction
of essential aspects of the heavenly happiness in the metaphorical imagery
of bridal gifts [dotes].12 The erotic garden inspired not only Bernard of
Clairvaux and Mechthild of Magdeburg but even the schoolmaster and
stone-collector Albert the Great, who uses the physical touches of love
[tactus amoris] to depict the highest form of contemplative union with
God. He refers, for example, to inherence [inhaerentiam]; that is, when
12
Cf. Wicki, Lehre, 202237. Particularly interesting is the fact that the brides role in the Christian
nuptial metaphor belongs to the human being, who receives illogically the bridal gifts.
242
Sensuality
one enters as it were into the other.13 The rich and multifaceted frieze of
Christian nuptial mysticism reaching as far as phenomena like Teresa of
Avilas
experience of mystical transverberation bears witness to a positive
relationship to erotic sensuality. Berninis statue of St. Teresa in ecstasy
renders eros and mysticism indistinguishable.
Finally, the fact that the belief in a resurrection of the body is a central
dogma makes it hardly possible for Christianity to maintain a thoroughgoing rejection of the body. For dogmatics, there can be no doubt that
corporeality belongs to Eternal Life. The whole person is to be fulfilled.
The body represents the concretion of spirit, the expression and embodiment of the soul. How then, the question arises, is an orthodox Christian
to conceive sensual pleasures in the afterlife?
Thomas formulates the question in more precise and differentiated ways.
One form is: Are such carnal pleasures necessary for fulfilling happiness?
Applied to Christ, he asks whether it was necessary for him to eat after his
Resurrection; to this form of the question, Thomas answers negatively.14
Thomas criticizes the interpretation of the pleasures of Eternal Life as being
identical to the carnal pleasure in the present life [sicut et nunc]. This is
underlined by a comparison to the Christian heresy of chiliasm, or millennianism, which also taught that during the thousand-year reign of Christ in
the future of this world, the resurrected would enjoy such carnal pleasures.15
In these teachings, there is notably no reference to a spiritual body.
Having rejected the idea that there is a necessity involved, Aquinas goes
on to express an affirmative position on sensuality in the afterlife: Then
happiness will not only be in the soul, but also in the body, and even the
happiness of the soul will be increased extensively insofar as the soul will
enjoy not only its own good but also the good of the body.16
In his response, Thomas draws a comparison to the beauty of the human
body, which need not be beautiful by necessity but is surely improved by
beauty: sensuality is related to the spirit, he says, like beauty to the body.
In the case of the glorified body, there must be an increase in happiness.
Thomas emphasizes this by expressly teaching that the senses of smell and
sight will enjoy an unsurpassable perfection in the afterlife.17
13
14
15
16
17
Tertia (conjunctio) est per inhaerentiam, quando unum quasi ingreditur alterum, et contrahit
impressiones et affectiones a natura ejus: et hic est tactus amoris, et assimilatur tactui naturali, in
quo tangentia agunt et patiuntur ad invicem, et imprimunt sibi mutuo suas proprietates. Albertus
Magnus, In I. Sententiarum, dist. 1, a. 12 (Ed. Par. XXV, 25, 2930).
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, IV, c. 83; In IV. Sententiarum, dist. 44, q. 1, a. 3d, ad 1
and ad 4.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, IV, c. 83.
Thomas Aquinas, In IV. Sententiarum, dist. 49, q. 1, a. 4, qc. 1c.
Sed in corporibus gloriosis erit odor in ultima sua perfectione . . . Et sensus odoratus in sanctis . . . cognoscet non solum excellentias odorum . . . sed etiam minimas odorum differentias. Ibid.,
243
18
19
21
22
dist. 44, q. 2, a. 1d, ad 3. Visus corporis gloriosi erit perfectissimus. Ibid., ad 6. Aquinas holds
sexual pleasure to be the greatest among the sensual pleasures. Cf. De malo, q. 15, a. 4c; Quaestiones
quodlibetales, XII, q. 14, a. 1c.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, De potentia, q. 9, a. 2, ad 14. Cf. also Summa contra gentiles, IV, c. 26: The
minds act of understanding is not its being; and its will act is neither its being, nor its act of
understanding. For this reason, also, the mind understood and the mind beloved are not persons,
since they are not subsisting. Even the mind itself existing in its nature is not a person, for it is not
the whole which subsists, but a part of the subsistent; namely, of the man.
20 Cf. ibid., q. 15, a. 2, ad 18.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, De virtutibus, q. 1, a. 4, ad 8.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, IV, c. 83.
Thomas Aquinas, In III. Metaphysicorum, lect. 11, n. 470.
244
Sensuality
normal to feel misused if one is merely the means for another persons
pleasure. No one wants to be perceived as nothing but a means to an end.
Decisive is what is enjoyed. The feeling depends on the content or, more
precisely, on what one thinks the content is. It is possible to enjoy the taste
of some foreign dish and then, on learning what it was that one had eaten,
be overcome by nausea. The feelings of pleasure and joy presuppose the
existence of a corresponding reality or, at least, an awareness of it. They
require an object.
The basic principle of Platos teaching on pleasure and joy can be summarized in the phrase Without desire, no joy.23 In normal life, it is difficult
to avoid a mixture. But even when sensual pleasure is only partially a
final end, there is something wrong. The inversion of the natural interrelation can be subtle and occurs sometimes without us being fully aware of
what is happening. Lewis gives a good analysis of an all-too-well-known
experience:
A lover, in obedience to a quite uncalculating impulse, which may be full of
good will as well as of desire and need not be forgetful of God, embraces his
beloved, and then, quite innocently, experiences a thrill of sexual pleasure;
but the second embrace may have that pleasure in view, may be a means
to an end, may be the first downward step toward the state of regarding a
fellow creature as a thing, as a machine to be used for his pleasure. Thus
the bloom of innocence, the element of obedience and the readiness to take
what comes is rubbed off every activity. Thoughts undertaken for Gods
sake like that on which we are engaged at the moment are continued as
if they were an end in themselves, and then as if our pleasure in thinking
were the end, and finally as if our pride or celebrity were the end. Thus all
day long, and all the days of our life, we are sliding, slipping, falling away
as if God were, to our present consciousness, a smooth inclined plane on
which there is no resting.24
24
245
as the life of Adam and Eve in paradise is aptly called. Confronted with
the argument that since sexual intercourse between human beings is
what makes them most similar to animals owing to the vehemence of
the pleasure [in coniunctione carnali maxime efficitur homo similis bestiis,
propter vehementiam delectationis], Adam and Eve could not have had any
sexual intercourse, Thomas answers that their
sensual delight would be the greater in proportion to the greater purity
of nature owing to the dominance of reason and the greater sensibility of
the body, as a sober person does not take less pleasure in food taken in
moderation than the glutton.25
The ironic truth that the controlling influence of reason, seeking objective
truth, can cause an increase in carnal pleasure is worth thinking about to
understand the glorified body better. We are all familiar with an analogy
in which sensual reality becomes heightened through its becoming more
spiritual. Memory has this ability. It can bring back physical experiences,
including carnal pleasure, and render them even more real than they actually were when they took place in the past. In his unsurpassable fashion,
Lewis compares the glorification to the power of memory:
25
26
27
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 98, a. 2, obj. 3 and ad 3. Cf. Gilson, Le thomisme, 346,
n. 29.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 141, a. 2, ad 3.
28 Ibid., a. 8, ad 1.
Cf. ibid.
246
Sensuality
It need no longer be intermittent. Above all, it need no longer be private
to the soul in which it occurs. I can now communicate to you the fields
of my boyhood they are building-estates today only imperfectly, by
words. Perhaps the day is coming when I can take you for a walk through
them . . . Thus in the sense-bodies of the redeemed the whole New Earth
will arise. The same, yet not the same, as this. It was sown in corruption, it
is raised in incorruption . . . What was sown in momentariness is raised in
still permanence.29
247
33
35
36
37
34 Cf. ibid.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Compendium theologiae, c. 156.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, III, q. 4, a. 5c.
Everything gives pleasure according as it is loved. Ibid., q. 31, a. 6c.
The senses are loved for two reasons: for the purpose of knowledge and on account of their
usefulness. Wherefore the senses afford pleasure in both these ways. Ibid.
248
Sensuality
7.2.1 The knowledge of sensual pleasure as something good
249
Seen in this way, physical pleasure becomes spiritual joy,48 and in this sense,
pleasure is a required part of Eternal Life. The English language seems to
know the same distinction, so that we could say: insofar as it has become
joy, sensual pleasure is a component of human beatitude.
47
48
49
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, III, q. 31, a. 3c. Il ny a pas une seule des choses que nous
desirons dont le desir, interprete et regle par la raison, ne puisse recevoir une signification legitime.
Gilson, Le Thomisme, 435.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, III, q. 31, a. 3c.
Cf. Gradl, Deus beatitudo hominis, 212.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 26.
250
Sensuality
Ibid.
51
Ibid.
251
of causality, lying deeper than efficient causality. When the will moves
the understanding, moreover, this happens thanks to the apprehension
of the act of understanding as being a good itself. In other words, the
will starts moving on the actual apprehension of an object, for the will
would never desire to understand if the act of understanding were not first
apprehended as something good. Understanding moves the will as its final
cause, and final causality is more fundamental than efficient causality and
occurs before it. Nothing moves without a final cause.
If we hold delight for the goal, then we turn the situation upside down.
What we want, first of all, is reality, not an illusion. If an illusion is realized
to be an illusion, it loses its influence. A placebo stops working when the
deception is unmasked. What we want is truth and not a feeling devoid of
truth. Hence, it is the intellect that makes the difference, for it is responsible
for distinguishing the true from the false. The delight is in itself the same,
regardless of whether it is enjoying true reality or a counterfeit.
To the question of why there is such a thing as delight in life, the
following answer can now be given: There is pleasure and delight in life so
that we might become happy. Delight is a help on our pilgrimage. Dante
described this well:
And just as the pilgrim who walks along a road on which he has never
travelled before believes that every house which he sees from afar is an inn,
and finding it not so, fixes his expectations on the next one, and so moves
from house to house until he comes to the inn, so our soul, as soon as it
enters upon this new and never travelled road of life, fixes its eyes on the
goal of its supreme good, and therefore believes that everything it sees which
seems to possess some good in it is that supreme good. Because its knowledge
is at first imperfect through lack of experience and instruction, small goods
appear great, and so from these it conceives its first desires. Thus, we see
little children setting their desire first of all on an apple, and then growing
older desiring to possess a little bird, and then still later desiring to possess
fine clothes, then a horse, and then a woman, and then modest wealth, then
greater riches, and then still more. This comes about because in none of
these things does one find what one is searching after, but hopes to find it
further on. Consequently, it may be seen that one object of desire stands
in front of another before the eyes of our soul very much in the manner
of a pyramid, where the smallest object at first covers them all and is, as it
were, the apex of the ultimate object of desire, namely, God, who is, as it
were, the base of all the rest. And so the further we move from the apex
toward the base, the greater the objects of desire appear; this is the reason
why acquisition causes human desires to become progressively inflated.52
52
252
Sensuality
The fundamental principle of Eternal Life is that the vision of God makes
up not just the essence but the whole of Eternal Life. Thomas Aquinas
reiterates this clearly: The vision itself of the divinity is the entire substance
of our beatitude.57 In other words, attentive contemplation is everything:
Final and consummate beatitude, which is expected in the future life,
53
55
56
253
This structure is just the opposite of normal life at the present time. Now,
we experience the world and in and through the world God, whereas in
heaven, the world is experienced in God. What is more, contemplative
life, as Thomas puts it, is loving God and our neighbor.62 Concentration
on God generally means a heightened, deeper realization of our engagement
with beloved creatures. Turning to Gods face does not imply turning away
from what we value in the world. To the contrary, it intensifies its reality.
Lewis grasped the paradox well:
In Heaven there will be no anguish and no duty of turning away from
our earthly Beloveds. First, because we shall have turned already; from
the portraits to the Original, from the rivulets to the Fountain, from the
creatures he made lovable to Love himself. But secondly, because we shall
find them all in him. By loving him more than them we shall love them
more than we now do.63
The unity of the love for God and for neighbor is essential. As Thomas
puts it: Everything good exists in God . . . and therefore it is one to love
58
59
60
62
63
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, III, q. 3, a. 5c. Cf. Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 37; In III.
Sententiarum, dist. 35, q. 1, a. 2, quaestiuncula 3, corpus.
Cf. Albertus Magnus, Summa, I, tr. 2, a. 7, c. 2.
61 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 175, a. 4, ad 1.
Platon, Philebos, 15 b.
Thomas Aquinas, De veritate, q. 22, a. 11, ad 11. Cf. Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 180, a. 7, ad 1: Et
haec est ultima perfectio contemplativae vitae, ut scilicet non solum divina veritas videatur, sed
etiam ut ametur.
Lewis, Four Loves, 191.
254
Sensuality
God and any good thing whatsoever.64 The connection becomes clearer
when one says that individual realities were already in God beforehand. As
Thomas categorically states: Whatever is desirable in whatsoever beatitude, whether true or false, pre-exists wholly and in a more eminent degree
in the divine beatitude.65 In this respect, God and neighbor are not two
separate beings; rather, they comprise a unity, God being the final cause.
In love to neighbor, love to God is included, as the end is included in
what leads to the end, and vice versa.66 The principle is universal: In the
love to whatsoever good, the highest goodness is loved.67 There is a direct
proportion between seeing God and seeing creatures in him.68 The more
creatures are seen, the more intensely God is seen.
This relationship can be expressed in different ways. Classical theology
teaches not only that God is immanent in the world but also that the
world is immanent in God.69 It can even be said that creatures in God
are identical with Gods essence. In God the creature is the divine essence
itself,70 Thomas emphasizes. Hence, God has the whole of being in
himself.71
The eschatological knowledge of human beings takes part in the divine
knowledge. God knows creatures by knowing himself and in this way
knows them better than we can know them. We know things by grasping
their whatness, whereas God grasps both the whatness and the concrete act
of existence. Thomas Aquinas developed the unusual idea that God knows
both the form and the matter of things, whereas we cannot really know
matter:
God knows all singulars, not only in their universal causes, but also each
in its proper and singular nature . . . Since divine art produces not only the
form but also the matter, it contains not only the likeness of form but also
that of matter . . . Whether a thing has a vigorous or a feeble share in the act
of being, it has this from God alone; and because each thing participates in
an act of existence given by God, the likeness of each is found in him.72
64
65
67
68
69
70
71
72
255
For this reason, Eternal Life includes individual people and things in a
more real way than in the present life:
There comes forth from God not only whatever belongs to their universal
nature, but likewise all that goes to make up their principles of individuation;
since he is the cause of the entire substance of the thing, as to both its matter
and its form. And for as much as he causes, he does know; for his knowledge
is the cause of a thing. . . Therefore as by his essence, by which he causes all
things, God is the likeness of all things, and knows all things, not only as to
their universal natures, but also as to their singularity.73
Now, it is often presumed that by saying that the vision of God is the
whole of Eternal Life, an unacceptable individualism is implied, but this
is a misunderstanding. A human individual is by nature a social being.
Friends are necessarily included. Thomas explains that happiness is socially
constituted, writes Gradl. Heavenly happiness is no purely individual
matter but a union with God and other happy humans.74
Taken in this sense, God is a medium. The seeing of him encompasses
all knowledge and even every activity:
The Blessed are united to God in such a way that he is the rationale [ratio]
of all knowledge and activity, for otherwise the act of happiness would be
impeded by the other instances of knowledge and activity. Therefore, the
attention of the Blessed is directed first to God himself and they have him
as the medium of every other instance of knowledge and as the rule of every
operation [regulam cuiuslibet operationis].75
256
Sensuality
can also be a preparation for praxis even for those who are more inclined
to the active life. Those who are more adapted to the active life can
prepare themselves for the contemplative by the practice of the active
life, Thomas asserts.77 Conversely: Those who are more adapted to the
contemplative life can take upon themselves the works of the active life, so
as to become yet more apt for contemplation.78 In other words, theory
encompasses praxis, as light encompasses colored things; it makes praxis
conscious, thus rendering it human. Moreover, theory makes praxis more
real; praxis makes theory richer and more comprehensive.
Consequently, Thomas can conclude that the end of the intellect, which
is truth, is the end of all human actions, and the ultimate end of the
whole person is, therefore, to know God, who is Truth itself.79 It is crucial
to understand this. In other words, truth means the presence of reality
in consciousness. The entire capability of the creature will be applied to
seeing and loving God.80 The striving of the will includes in itself all
human strivings:
For it is not only things pertaining to the will that the will desires, but also
that which pertains to each power, and to the entire man. Wherefore man
wills naturally not only the object of the will, but also other things that
are appropriate to the other powers; such as the knowledge of truth, which
befits the intellect; and to be and to live and other like things which regard
the natural well-being; all of which are included in the object of the will, as
so many particular goods.81
Consciousness includes not only knowledge but also embraces love and
joy as well as every practical activity. At a next lower level, sensuality is a
participation in consciousness.
One might think that a spirit without a body would be more godlike since God is pure spirit. But Thomas argues in favor of the opposite
position: The soul united to the body is more like God than separated
from the body because it then has its own nature more perfectly.82 Hence,
77
79
80
81
82
78 Ibid.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IIII, q. 182, a. 4, ad 3.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 25 (quoted on page 146).
Thomas Aquinas, De caritate, a. 10, ad 5 (emphasis added).
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, III, q. 10, a. 1c. Cf. also De veritate, q. 14, a. 2, ad 6; a. 3, ad 3;
a. 5, ad 5.
Thomas Aquinas, De potentia, q. 5, a. 10, ad 5. A soul which is united to its glorified body has more
resemblance to God than when it is separated from it, insofar as it has more perfect being when it is
joined to it. And the more perfect something is, the closer it resembles God. Thomas Aquinas, In
IV. Sententiarum, dist. 49, q. 1, a. 4, qc. 1, ad 1. Thomas argues further that a heart is more similar
to God when it is moving than when it is at rest, even though God never moves.
257
the teaching on the resurrected body confirms that a human being would
not be better if it became a pure spirit.83
To conclude, the glorified spirit envelops the body and renders it spiritual. Sensations arise out of nerves. The redeemed have, so to speak,
sense-bodies, rising from their graves. Thus, not just the spirit is fulfilled
in the afterlife but also the whole person. One could say: Everything that
falls under the light of the spirit will participate in salvation; everything
that falls within the radius of the spirit insofar as it expresses itself as I
will be saved. Thomas emphasizes the corporeal aspect in his commentary
on the passage in Job (19:2627), where it is said, After my awaking, he
will set me close to him, and from my flesh I shall look on God. He whom
I shall see will take my part: these eyes will gaze on him and find him not
aloof. Thomas then adds:
To exclude this, Job places, whom I myself will see, as though he should
say: Not only will my soul see God but I myself who subsist from body
and soul. To indicate that the body will be a participant in that vision in its
own proper way he adds, and my eyes will behold him, not because the
eyes of the body would see the divine essence, but because the eyes of the
body will see God made man. They will also see the glory of God shining
in created things.84
Aquinas rejects two misinterpretations, the first being that the body does
not participate in Eternal Life. He argues from the standpoint that I
shall see God and that I consists in soul and body. The bodies of the
resurrected, moreover, are not just heavenly bodies; in a certain manner,
they possess flesh. Without its body, the soul is not a person. The other
misinterpretation understands the body as having the same mode of existence as it does on Earth. Thomas underlines that the resurrected body
exists as a participation in the vision. Finally, he sees in the text (my eyes
will gaze on him) a rejection of the idea that it is not the individual but
merely the human species that is saved. This would be a kind of everlasting
life of the species but one lacking self-identity [identitas eiusdem]. Thomas
insists that the text teaches a resurrection of the individual in the afterlife.85
As a further clarification, Thomas draws a comparison to the cause of
a work of art. Yet, in this case, the cause in question is not the artist
but rather art itself. Everything that is expressly revealed in the work
of art is completely included implicitly and originally in art itself, he
explains. And in a similar way, whatever appears in the parts of the body
83
84
85
Cf. ibid.
258
Sensuality
259
The term first distinguishes the soul from all other forms of living,
which are all called second actualities. If I walk, talk, think, feel, and so
on, I am realizing second actualities. Even if there is a chain of connected
acts I want something to eat, stand up, walk to the kitchen, pick up an
apple, and peel it we do not then have third or fourth acts, but only a
chain of secondary acts. The first act, furthermore, does not exist next
to second acts and certainly not as the first in a series; rather, it is, so to
speak, the actness [actualitas or actus omnium actuum] of the second
acts. However, using an abstract notion here like actness is deceptive,
for the soul, of course, is in reality not an abstract notion, but at least,
this manipulation of everyday language makes it clear that there are only
two kinds of acts (i.e., first and second). If I meet a small animal lying on
my path and want to know whether it is dead or alive, I might push it
with my foot. If it then moves, I can conclude from this second act
that it is alive; in other words, that it has a soul. To be precise, this is
not a conclusion, for I see the soul, if not distinctly, immediately in the
movement, this being nothing other than the concretization of life. The
soul is the actuality itself, it does not add any qualities to the living being. It
refers to a kind of happening namely, to living. The soul is not an answer
to questions regarding what something alive is but merely to the question of
whether something is living that is, whether it has life, whether it is living
actuality (in Latin: actus, not ens or res; in Greek: or ,
which has the connotation of fulfillment). The soul is a principle of life,
the act of living in all activities of a living organism. To say that something
has life is equivalent to saying that it has a soul. In Aristotles eyes, it is
manifest that the soul is also the final cause of its body.88 It is not like an
inner spring, or a heart, out of which life flows and is dispersed; neither is
it an efficient cause. But what for classical thought was manifest is today
rather difficult. It would be extremely interesting if neuroscientists showed
some appreciation of this concept instead of simply presuming, as is often
the case, that the soul is supposed to be some kind of entity somewhere
within the living being.
Everything that I do or experience is a second act. To capture the first
act linguistically, we would need a global verb that would say all without
adding a further quality. It would have to be a verb denoting existing but
without the connotation that existing just means the bare fact of existence.
It would have to include every activity as modes of existing. We have, in
fact, no verb that expresses what I do insofar as I exist. Thomas teaches
88
260
Sensuality
that our own essence is unknown to us since we only experience our second
acts directly. Actually, self-consciousness comes down to nothing else but
the awareness of our existing concomitant to second acts of life. Thomas
reasons as follows:
It cannot be said that the soul of itself knows concerning itself what it
essentially is. For a cognitive faculty comes to be actually cognisant by there
being in it the object which is known. If the object is in it potentially, it
knows potentially: if the object is in it actually, it is actually cognisant: if in
an intermediate way, it is habitually cognisant. But the soul is always present
to itself actually, and never merely potentially or habitually. If then the soul
of itself knows itself by its essence, it must have an intellectual perception
of itself, of what it essentially is, which clearly is not the case.89
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 46. Cf. In III. Sententiarum, dist. 23, q. 1, a. 2, ad 3;
De veritate, q. 10, a. 8; Summa theologiae, I, q. 87, a. 1; a. 3.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, II, c. 69.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 76, a. 8c.
261
scandalous because it meant that the dead Christ lying in the tomb was
not Christ in a univocal sense, as Thomas explicitly concluded.92
Neuroscientists who reject the notion of the soul as nonsense invariably
understand it as a reality, like a tiny homunculus, similar to medieval
depictions of the soul leaving the body at death, ascending toward heaven
sometimes being carried by angels since, according to traditional theology,
the soul is unable to move without its body. A prominent scientist like
the Nobel laureate winner Francis Crick, who ranks among the most
significant pioneers in gene technology, is a consummate example. He
claims that modern neurobiology has no need for the religious idea of a
soul.93 Crick considers it to be the Astonishing Hypothesis that all of our
behavior is nothing other than the interaction of an incredible number of
neurons. He asserts ironically that scientific certitude alone can free
us from the superstitious conceptions of our forefathers.94 The record of
religious beliefs in explaining scientific phenomena has been so poor in the
past that there is little reason to believe that the conventional religions will
do much better in the future.95 Speaking with an astonishing degree of
ignorance of our real history, he argues:
Not only do the beliefs of most popular religions contradict each other
but, by scientific standards, they are based on evidence so flimsy that only
an act of blind Faith can make them acceptable. If the members of a
church really believe in a life after death, why do they not conduct sound
experiments to establish it? They may not succeed but at least they could
try. History has shown that mysteries which the churches thought only
they could explain (e.g., the age of the earth) have yielded to a concerted
scientific attack. Moreover, the true answers are usually far from those of
conventional religions. If revealed religions have revealed anything it is that
they are usually wrong.96
93
94
95
97
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Quaestiones quodlibetales, III, q. 2, a. 2c: Separata anima a corpore, sicut non
dicitur homo nisi aequivoce, ita nec dicitur oculus nisi aequivoce . . . Sicut ergo Christus in triduo
mortis propter separationem animae a corpore, quae est vera corruptio, non dicitur fuisse homo
univoce, sed homo mortuus, ita nec oculus eius in triduo mortis fuit univoce oculus, sed aequivoce,
sicut oculus mortuus; et eadem ratio est de aliis partibus corporis Christi.
Cf. Crick, The Astonishing Hypothesis, 7.
Other hypotheses about mans nature, especially those based on religious beliefs, are based on
evidence that is even more flimsy but this is not in itself a decisive argument against them. Only
scientific certainty (with all its limitations) can in the long run rid us of the superstitions of our
ancestors. Ibid., 257.
96 Ibid.
Ibid., 258.
As his source, he cites only The Catholic Catechism by John A. Hardon, 1975, without a page
reference. As was to be expected, I have been unable to find a source for such a nonsensical
definition.
262
Sensuality
This is in head-on contradiction to the religious beliefs of billions of human beings alive today.
Crick, The Astonishing Hypothesis, 261.
100 Singer, Der Beobachter, 39.
101 Ibid.
Singer, Ein neues Menschenbild?, 10.
103 Singer, Ein neues Menschenbild?, 88.
Singer, Gehirn&Geist, 32.
105 Cf. ibid.
106 Ibid.
Singer, Uber
Bewutsein.
263
108
264
Sensuality
111
112
113
114
115
Ibid., n. 365. Reference is made to the Council of Vienne (1312) (DS 902).
Man naturally desires his own salvation; but the soul, since it is part of mans body, is not an entire
man, and my soul is not I; hence, although the soul obtains salvation in another life, nevertheless,
not I or any man. Thomas Aquinas, In I Ad Corinthios, XV, lect. 2.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, De potentia, q. 9, a. 2, ad 14.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, IV, c. 26: The mind itself existing in its nature is not
a person, for it is not the whole which subsists, but a part of the subsistent, namely, of the man.
Thomas Aquinas, De spiritualibus creaturis, a. 9, ad 4. Cf. In De anima, II, lect. 1, n. 3.
Thomas Aquinas, De anima, q. unica, a. 8, ad 15. It is united to it so that it might acquire
knowledge. Summa contra gentiles, II, c. 83; cf. Summa theologiae, I, q. 76, a. 5.
116 Ibid., III, c. 144.
Cf. Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, II, c. 68.
265
we do not reflect on it, we may live without seeing the problem. But once
we begin to think about it philosophically, the task ahead is strenuous.
7.5.2 The whole soul in each part of the body
Different aspects have been taken into view to express the relationship
between the soul and the body. One of these is the presence of the whole
soul in each part of the body. If the soul were united to the body merely as
its motor, we might say that it is not in each part of the body but instead
only in the one part through which it would move the others. But since
the soul is united to the body as its actuality, it must necessarily be present
in the whole body, as well as in each of its parts. For it is not an accidental
form but rather the substantial form of the body being, so to speak,
living bodiness itself. The actuality is what grounds individuality. Having
certain qualities, or being characterized by different genomes or individual
histories, does not bring about individuality; it comes from the ontological
actuality.117
7.5.3 The body in the soul
It helps to realize that although it is not false to speak of the soul being
in the body, it is more appropriate to say that the body is in the soul.
The soul is not like a core or the motor of the living thing. Rather, it
envelops the entire being. Meister Eckhart, to quote just one witness out of
the tradition, writes: Usually we say that the soul is in the body, while
in truth the body is rather in the soul.118 But this does not exclude the
possibility that the classical teaching sometimes also speaks of the entire soul
being in each part of the body completely. As Thomas Aquinas expresses
it, The soul is in the body as containing it, not as contained by it.119 He
concludes further: The intellective soul contains the sensitive.120
7.5.4 Thomas Aquinas thesis: The human soul
as the form of the body
Both pre-philosophic thinking and the teaching of Christian Faith presume
that a human being is one reality. It is always the same I that does quite
117
118
119
120
266
Sensuality
different things, that writes, eats, sees, tastes, thinks, reflects, loves, and so
on. However, the unity of the person becomes extremely difficult when
one begins to reflect and philosophize on it. How are two forms of being
namely, material and immaterial to be thought of as a unity, seeing that
they are incompatible with one another? The acts of seeing something and
of becoming explicitly aware of the fact that one is seeing something are
essentially different. In thought, we can know not only concrete singulars
but also universals and other immaterial things, like truth and beauty.
Furthermore, thought is reflexive. As Thomas argues: No sense has reflex
knowledge of itself and its own activity: the sight does not see itself,
nor see that it sees. But intellect is cognisant of itself, and knows that it
understands.121
To put it pointedly: Spirit is a part of the soul, and the soul is a part of
the human person.122 The body is also a part of the person but not a part
of the soul. To the contrary, the soul is rather a part of the body.
In the traditional Aristotelian categories, the claim that man is a unity
involves being able to think of man as having just one substantial form
or, in other words, only one soul, including in itself vegetable, animal,
and spiritual life. Thomas Aquinas was the first thinker to fulfill this
requirement.123 His original approach is based on his new understanding of
being. Soul is defined, in accordance with Aristotle, as an act [actus primus]
and being is understood by Thomas as the act of all acts that is, as it were,
the actness or actuality of all acts [actualitas omnium actuum]. The word
actualitas, which was unknown to previous generations of thinkers and
introduced no sooner than in the thirteenth century, raises the observer
to a higher level of apprehension. Animal life and the life of reflecting
consciousness may be quite different from one another, but both are forms
of being, analogous, for example, to left and right being contradictories
and yet both being kinds of directions.
The thesis of how to unite body and soul, materiality and immateriality,
is succinctly stated by Aquinas: Now it is clear that the intellectual soul,
by virtue of its very being, is united to the body as its form; yet, after the
dissolution of the body, the intellectual soul retains its own being.124
In sum, the thesis on the unity of man implies that one and the same
essential form makes man an actual being [ens actu], a body, a living being,
an animal, and a man.125 Body and soul are so closely united that they
can be characterized with the terms implicit and explicit. Accordingly,
what is implicitly present in the soul appears explicitly in the parts of the
121
123
124
267
126
127
128
129
131
132
133
268
Sensuality
The soul communicates that existence in which it subsists to the corporeal
matter, out of which together with the intellectual soul there results unity
of existence, so that the existence of the whole composite is also the souls
existence. This is not the case with other non-subsistent forms. For this
reason the human soul retains its own existence after the dissolution of the
body, whereas this is not the case with other forms.134
Consequently, it is clear that matter and form share one and the same
act of being [unum esse].135 A thought and the sentence expressing the
thought cannot share the same being, but the meaning in both cases can.
The meaning that I thought in my head and wrote down is, under normal
conditions, the meaning of the sentence. If I am misunderstood, then I
naturally feel that something has gone wrong.
The immaterial soul shares its being with the bodys being by way of
the form.136 The act of being is the key: The spiritual soul is united to
the body as its form through its being.137 Although spirit and matter are
contraries, both are modes of being. To combine contraries in a unity, a
higher level of abstraction must be attained. Thomas accomplishes this
through his understanding of being. The body is thus more than just the
symbol of the spirit. Its very being is the same as the being of the spirit.
The spirit is not just the first actuality of the body; the first actuality of
spirit and body is one and the same.
What does form [forma; Greek: , ] mean? One way to
explain it is to say that everything that we experience or know except for
the act of existence is a form. What a dictionary contains are forms. But
how then can the soul be a form since it is the act of living existence? In
fact, form itself does not exist, but it is determinative of existence. For
example, the term dog in the dictionary does not exist as a real dog. But
what makes a really existing dog a dog is the form defined in the dictionary.
The meaning of abstract notions (i.e., a universal) does not itself exist in
some nominalistic way. Running per se does not run, but a running dog is
running thanks to the form of running. Running is not the efficient cause,
the dog is; running is the formal cause. Seeing is the form of a living eye.
Living is the form of a living being.
134
135
137
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, I, q. 76, a. 1, ad 5. The same act of being that belongs to the
soul is communicated to the body, Thomas emphasizes, so that there is one act of being of the
whole composite. De anima, a. 1, ad 1.
136 Cf. ibid., II, c. 68.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, IV, c. 81.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, q. 76, a. 6, ad 3.
269
139
Ibid.
140
Ibid., 95.
270
Sensuality
143
Ibid., 65.
Cf. ibid., 76: For an agent to be able to do what it cannot do of itself must involve its having
infinite being as its transcendent ground in such a way that, while this ground is not a factor in the
agent itself ; it nevertheless belongs to it. Cf. also ibid., 64, where it is said that we can see God as
the transcendent ground of all reality, of its existence and of its becoming, as the primordial reality
comprising everything, supporting everything, but precisely for that reason cannot regard him as
a partial factor and component in the reality with which we are confronted, nor as a member of
its causal series.
Thomas Aquinas, Summa contra gentiles, III, c. 70.
271
We might
quite well think of God as the transcendent ground of all reality, of its existence and of its becoming, as the primordial reality comprising everything,
supporting everything, but precisely for that reason we cannot regard him as
a partial factor and component in the reality with which we are confronted,
nor as a member of its causal series.146
Ibid., c. 72.
145
146
Ibid., 64.
147
Ibid., 65.
272
Sensuality
and increasing reality is inserted side by side with the causal efficacy of the
finite cause as though fundamentally it were itself a partial cause. When we
are dealing with a form of becoming which is truly an increase and not just
a variation, the relation of the absolute ground of being to the finite agent
must rather be envisaged in such a way that the absolute ground of being
and becoming is always regarded as a factor linked to the finite agent and
belonging to it, though transcending it.148
He even goes so far as to claim that the perfected material reality must be
a factor related to the perfection of spirit itself, not something that there is
as well, in addition to spiritual perfection . . . Spirit must be thought of as
seeking and finding itself through the perfection of what is material.151
The union arising from the emerging of spirit out of matter is only
possible because of the presence of Being since spirit represents a real
increase in being and not just a form of matter. Matter and spirit become
real through the effect of Being. Rahner explains the divine causing of
mans self-movement as follows:
The agents rising beyond and above itself in action and becoming takes place
because the absolute Being is the cause and ground of this self-movement,
in such a way that the latter has this fundamental ground immanent within
it as a factor intrinsically related to the movement.152
Ibid., 75.
Ibid., 59.
149
152
Ibid., 76.
Ibid., 88.
150
153
Ibid., 56.
Cf. ibid., 8387.
273
the originating cause, the fundamental ground and reason of the minds
transcendental dynamism.154 The orienting term of transcendence does
not move in the manner of an efficient but rather in that of a final cause.
This dynamism only exists and can exist because it tends precisely toward
that term and so is sustained by it.155 The self-motion represents a mode
of the attracting causality. It is not as though man existed in himself and
then established a relationship to his final goal. Instead, in the dynamic of
his living, the final goal is already present and effective.156 This immanence
of the term of transcendence is possible only because it is not an object but
rather the horizon of consciousness: The orienting term as a constitutive
factor of the dynamic tendency is immanent in it.157
The self-transcendence then explains how parents can be the total cause
of a child, body and spirit, while God can nonetheless be a concomitant
cause:
If the operation of a creature is on principle to be regarded as a selftranscendence in such a way that the effect is not derivable from the essence
of the creature acting and yet must be considered as effected by this agent,
it is possible to say, without anxiety, if such a general concept of becoming
and operation is presupposed, that the parents are the cause of the one
entire human being and so also of its soul, because . . . that not only does
not exclude, but positively includes, the fact that the parents can only be
the cause of the human being in virtue of the power of God which renders
possible their self-transcendence, and which is immanent in their causality
without belonging to the constitutive factors of their essence. And then the
statement that God directly creates the soul of a human being does not
imply any denial of the statement that the parents procreate the human
being in his unity. It makes the statement more precise by indicating that
this procreation belongs to that kind of created efficient causality in which
the agent by virtue of divine causality essentially exceeds the limits set by
his own essence.158
157
158
274
Sensuality
161
275
Hence, reality includes more than material reality and more than what
exists in the present, just as light includes more than the colors visible at a
given time. This is not to say that immaterial reality is included in material
reality but, in a real sense, it can emerge out of it without being simply
added or grafted to it. Nonetheless, materiality itself on its own strength
cannot cause immateriality. Divine causality, to repeat, is analogous to the
way light causes colors. In a dark room or in empty space, no colors exist. If
light is shining, then colors can exist provided that the appropriate matter
be present. If, for example, a sunflower is present, then yellow will be
visible.
Rahner comes to the conclusion that human parents are the cause of a
child, although a child is not, so to speak, deducible from its parents; it is
not an extension of them but instead represents an independent entity. The
child is truly the parents child and nevertheless an autonomous being
without involving a contradiction.
In striving for more being, a creature strives for similitude with God,
returning, as it were, to God.162 There exists a striving like this in all of
reality. According to Thomas Aquinas, even matter has such a striving
[appetitus materiae]; ultimately, the physical world strives, as it appears,
toward human existence. In the process of generation [processus generationis], inorganic matter tends toward vegetable life, and this in turn strives
for animal life; animal life tends in turn toward intellectual life.163
162
163
Cf. ibid.
chapter eight
I see no reason for not applying the insight explicated in the previous
section to the question of Eternal Life and viewing Eternal Life as a further
case of emergence. This implies that Eternal Life emerges out of temporal
life. It is the fulfilling actualization of human potentiality. By the name
of beatitude the ultimate perfection of rational or of intellectual nature is
understood, Thomas argues, and hence it is that it is naturally desired,
since everything desires by nature its ultimate perfection.1 It is more than
temporal life but it is not simply an effect having its cause completely
within temporal existence. For example, it is not simply an extension of
temporal life. Actually, the difference between matter and spirit is greater
than the difference between spirit and fulfilled spirit.
For new reality to emerge, a potency for it must exist. An animal lacking
wings is not likely to fly. An animal without a highly developed brain will
not think self-consciously. The actualized thinking of human beings is a
potency for Eternal Life. The technical term for this is potentia obedientialis;
that is, a capacity that can be actualized but only by another agent. Rahner
understands human life in the whole of its essence as a potentia obedientialis
for Revelation and Eternal Life. Eternal Life is not a miracle; moreover, it
is just the opposite of the abrogation of a natural law. Being the fulfillment
of a natural desire, the heavenly vision is not to be considered a miracle.
Etienne
Gilson even goes so far as to assert that the Christian has a right to
happiness insofar as he is a human being.2 Accordingly, the beatific vision
is in one sense natural and in another supernatural. With respect to what it
consists in, it is natural; the cause of its taking place is supernatural. What
takes place is codetermined by human nature, while the fact that it takes
place presupposes a causality lying beyond the reach of human powers.
Depending on when it occurs, the same activity can be both in conformity
with ones nature and contrary to it. As Thomas Aquinas argues, it would
1
276
277
Ibid., a. 3, ad 6.
Bibliography
Abelard, Peter. Sic et non. A Critical Edition. Ed. Blanche B. Boyer and Richard
McKeon. The University of Chicago Press, 1976.
Adkins, Arthur W. H. Merit and Responsibility: A Study in Greek Values. Oxford:
Clarendon, 1960.
Aeschylus. Agamemnon. Ten Greek Plays. Transl. Gilbert Murray et al. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1929.
Albertus Magnus. Commentarii in I Sententiarum. Opera omnia. Vols. XXVXXVI.
Paris: Viv`es, 1893.
Liber II Physicorum. Opera Omnia. Vol. IV, 1. Munster: Aschendorff, 1987.
Summa theologiae sive De mirabili scientia Dei libri. Opera Omnia. Vol. XXXIV.
Munster: Aschendorff, 1978.
Super Dionysii mysticam theologiam et epistulas. Opera Omnia. Vol.
XXXVII, 2. Munster: Aschendorff, 1978.
Alighieri, Dante. The Convivio. Transl. Richard Lansing. New York: Garland,
1990.
Anderson, Philip W. More Is Different: Broken Symmetry and the Nature
of the Hierarchical Structure of Science. Science 177, No. 4047 (1972):
393396.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA. Vol. XCII. July 1995, in
an introductory paper at a colloquium entitled Physics: The Opening
to Complexity, held June 26 and 27, 1994, at the National Academy of
Sciences, Irvine, CA.
Anselm of Canterbury. Monologium. Basic Writings: Proslogium; Monologium; Gaunilons on Behalf of the Fool; Cur deus homo. Transl. Sidney Norton Deane.
La Salle, IL: Open Court, second edition, 1962.
Aristotle. De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I (with passages
from II.13). Transl. with notes David M. Balme. Oxford: Clarendon, 1972,
9398.
Metaphysics. Aristotle in 23 Volumes. Vols. XVII and XVIII. Transl. Hugh Tredennick. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 19891990.
Nicomachean Ethics. Transl. William D. Ross. Oxford University Press, 1980.
On the Heavens. Transl. W. K. C. Guthrie. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1970.
278
Bibliography
279
280
Bibliography
Bibliography
281
282
Bibliography
Galilei, Galileo. Opere. Ed. Nazionale cura et labore Antonio Favaro. Florence:
Tip. di G. Barb`era, 19291939.
Gilson, Etienne.
Le thomisme. Paris: Vrin, sixth edition, 1965.
Sur la problematique thomiste de la vision beatifique. Archives dhistoire doctrinale et litteraire du moyen a ge 31 (1964): 6788.
Glorieux, Palemon. Endurcissement final et grace derni`eres. Nouvelle Revue
Theologique 59 (1932): 865892.
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von. Faust: A Tragedy. Second Part. Transl. Anna Swanwick. New York: J. D. Williams, 1882.
Goriceva, Tatjana. Die Kraft der Ohnmachtigen. Weisheit aus dem Leiden. Wuppertal: Brockhaus, second edition, 1987.
Gradl, Stefan. Deus beatitudo hominis Eine evangelische Annaherung an die
Gluckslehre des Thomas von Aquin. Louvain: Peeters, 2004.
Gregory of Nyssa, The Life of Moses. Transl. Abraham J. Malherbe and Everett
Ferguson. New York: Paulist Press, 1978.
Habermas, Jurgen. Das Entzucken u ber den Schock der Deflationierung: Ein
Bibliography
283
Hofstadter, Richard. Academic Freedom in the Age of the College. New Brunswick,
NJ: Transaction Publishers, 1996.
Hopkins, Jasper. A Miscellany on Nicholas of Cusa. Minneapolis, MN: A. J. Banning, 1994.
Hoye, William J. Demokratie und Christentum. Die christliche Verantwortung fur
demokratische Prinzipien. Munster: Aschendorff, 1999.
Gotteserfahrung? Klarung eines Grundbegriffs der gegenwartigen Theologie. Zurich:
Benziger, 1993.
Gotteserkenntnis per essentiam im 13. Jahrhundert. Die Auseinandersetzungen
an der Pariser Universitat im XIII. Jahrhundert. Miscellanea Mediaevalia.
Vol. X. Ed. Albert Zimmermann. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1976, 269284.
Hermeneutische Uberlegungen
u ber die zwei von Gott verfaten Bucher.
Religiose Erfahrung. Richard Schaefflers Beitrag zu Religionsphilosophie und
Theologie. Ed. Thomas M. Schmidt and Siegfried Wiedenhofer. Freiburg:
Karl Alber, 2010, 5684.
Human Love as Unfulfilling Union According to St. Thomas Aquinas. Proceedings of the International Congress on Christian Humanism in the Third
Millennium: The Perspective of Saint Thomas Aquinas. Vol. I. Vatican City:
Accademia Romana di San Tommaso dAquino e di Religione Cattolica,
2003, 516524.
Lehramtliche Aussagen und wissenschaftliche Wahrheit in der katholischen
Theologie. Zeitschrift fur katholische Theologie 105 (1983): 159166.
Sunde, Damonen und Gottesliebe nach Thomas von Aquin. Die Machte des
Guten und Bosen. Vorstellungen im XII. und XIII. Jahrhundert. Miscellanea
Mediaevalia. Vol. XI. Ed. Albert Zimmermann. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1977,
206234.
Die Unerkennbarkeit Gottes als die letzte Erkenntnis nach Thomas von
Aquin. Thomas von Aquin. Miscellanea Mediaevalia. Vol. XIX. Ed. Albert
Zimmermann. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1988, 117139.
Die Verfinsterung des absoluten Geheimnisses. Eine Kritik der Gotteslehre Karl
Rahners. Dusseldorf: Patmos, 1979.
284
Bibliography
Uber
den Zustand der Seele nach dem Tode. Metaphysik. Ed. Karl
Heinrich Ludwig Politz. Preuische Akademie der Wissenschaften. Vol.
XXVIII, 1. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1968, 233261.
Kasper, Walter. Gott und die Zukunft. Heute von Gott reden. Ed. Martin Hengel
and Rudolf Reinhardt. Munich: Kaiser, 1977, 724.
Kehl, Medard. Holle. Lexikon fur Theologie und Kirche. Vol. V. Freiburg: Herder,
third edition, 1996, 230238.
King, Martin Luther, Jr. Letter from Birmingham City Jail (April 1963). A Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings of Martin Luther King. Ed. James M.
Washington. San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1986.
Kremer, Klaus. Gott und Welt in der klassischen Metaphysik. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer,
1969.
Kullmann, Wolfgang. Die Teleologie in der aristotelischen Biologie. Aristoteles als
Zoologe, Embryologe und Genetiker. Heidelberg: Carl Winter, 1978.
Kung, Hans. On Being a Christian. Transl. Edward Quinn. Garden City, NY:
Image Books, 1984.
Laporta, Jorge. La destinee de la nature humaine. Paris: Vrin, 1965.
Leitheiser, Ludwig, and Christian Pesch. Handbuch zur katholischen Schulbibel.
Vol. II. Dusseldorf: Patmos, third edition, 1963.
Lennox, James G. Aristotles Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life
Science. Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim. Education of the Human Race (1780). Transl. Fred W.
Robertson. London: C. K. Paul, third edition, 1881.
Lewis, Clive S. The Four Loves. New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1960.
The Great Divorce. HarperSanFrancisco, 2001.
Bibliography
285
286
Bibliography
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Transl. Walter Kaufmann. New York:
Modern Library, 1995.
Ott, Heinrich. Eschatologie. Versuch eines dogmatischen Grundrisses. Zollikon:
Evangelischer Verlag, 1958.
Pegis, Anton C. At the Origins of the Thomistic Notion of Man. New York:
Macmillan, 1963.
St. Thomas and the Problem of the Soul in the Thirteenth Century. Toronto:
Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1976.
Philosophisches Worterbuch. Ed. Georg Klaus and Manfred Buhr. Leipzig: VEB
Bibliographisches Institut, tenth edition, 1974.
Picht, Georg. Wahrheit, Vernunft, Verantwortung. Stuttgart: Klett, 1969.
Pieper, Josef. Werke in acht Banden. Ed. Berthold Wald. Vol. V: Schriften zur Philosophischen Anthropologie und Ethik: Grundstrukturen menschlicher Existenz.
Hamburg: Meiner, 2007.
Plato. Opera. Ed. John Burnet. Oxford University Press, 1903.
Philebos. Transl. Dorothea Frede. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1997.
Plotinus. Enneads. Ed. Arthur H. Armstrong, Paul Henry, and Hans-Rudolf
Schwyzer. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989 et seq.
Pound, Ezra. The Pisan Cantos. Ed. Richard Sieburth. New York: New Directions
Books, 2003.
Rahner, Johanna. Einfuhrung in die christliche Eschatologie. Freiburg: Herder, 2010.
Rahner, Karl. Anschauung Gottes. Herders theologisches Taschenlexikon. Vol. I.
Freiburg: Herder, 1972, 116119.
The Concept of Mystery in Catholic Theology, Theological Investigations.
Vol. IV: More Recent Writings. Transl. Kevin Smith: Baltimore, MD:
Helicon, 1966, 3673.
Der dreifaltige Gott als transzendenter Urgrund der Heilsgeschichte. Mysterium Salutis. Grundri Heilsgeschichtlicher Dogmatik. Ed. Johannes Feiner
and Magnus Lohrer. Vol. II: Die Heilsgeschichte vor Christus. Zurich:
Benzinger, 1967.
Foundations of Christian Faith. An Introduction to the Idea of Christianity. Transl.
William V. Dych. New York: Crossroad, 1978.
Geheimnis. II. In der systematischen Theologie. Lexikon fur Theologie und
Kirche. Vol. IV. Freiburg: Herder, second edition, 1960, 595.
Geheimnis. II. Theologisch. Handbuch theologischer Grundbegriffe. Ed. Heinrich Fries. Vol. I. Munchen: Kosel, 1962, 449.
Hearer of the Word. Laying the Foundation for a Philosophy of Religion, Transl.
Joseph Donceel. Intr. and ed. Andrew Tallon. New York: Continuum, 1994.
Hominisation. The Evolutionary Origin of Man as a Theological Problem. Transl.
William T. OHara. Freiburg: Herder, 1965.
Potentia oboedientialis. Herders Theologisches Taschenlexikon. Ed. Karl Rahner. Vol. VI. Freiburg: Herder, 1973.
Reflections on the Unity of the Love of God and the Love of Neighbor.
Theological Investigations. Vol. VI. Transl. Karl H. and Boniface Kruger.
New York: Crossroad, 1982, 231249.
Bibliography
287
Uber
Bewutsein und unsere Grenzen. http://file1.npage.de/002835/55/download//bewusstsein und unsere grenzen.pdf.
288
Bibliography
Solle, Dorothee. Die Hinreise. Zur religiosen Erfahrung. Texte und Uberlegungen.
Stuttgart: Kreuz, 1975.
Spaemann, Robert. Happiness and Benevolence. Transl. Jeremiah Alberg. Edinburgh: Clark, 2000.
Moralische Grundbegriffe. Munchen: Beck, 1982.
Spinoza, Benedictus de. Ethics. Ed. Thomas Deegan. Salzburg: Institut fur Anglistik und Amerikanistik, 1981.
Splett, Jorg. Freiheits-Erfahrung: Vergegenwartigungen christlicher Anthropo-theologie. Frankfurt on the Main: Knecht, 1986.
Stange, Carl. Die Unsterblichkeit der Seele. Gutersloh: Bertelsmann, 1925.
Tennyson, Alfred. In Memoriam A. H. H. (1850).
Teresa of Avila.
The Life of St. Teresa of Jesus, of the Order of Our Lady of Carmel.
Transl. David Lewis. London: Thomas Baker, third edition, 1997.
Thomas Aquinas. Opera omnia. Ed. Roberto Busa. Stuttgart: FrommannHolzboog, 1980.
Summa theologiae. Transl. Fathers of the English Dominican Province. London,
second edition, 1920.
Tillich, Paul. Systematic Theology. Vol. I. University of Chicago Press, second edition, 1971.
Troisfontaines, Roger. I Do Not Die. New York: Desclee, 1963.
Trottmann, Christian. La vision beatifique des disputes scolastiques a` sa definition
Bibliography
289
Zeit und Wissen. Offene Systeme II Logik und Zeit. Ed. Krzysztof Maurin.
Stuttgart: Klett, 1981, 1738.
Wendland, Heinz-Dietrich. Ethik des Neuen Testaments. Gottingen: Vandenhoeck
& Ruprecht, 1970.
Wicki, Nikolaus. Die Lehre von der himmlischen Seligkeit in der mittelalterlichen
Scholastik von Petrus Lombardus bis Thomas von Aquin. Fribourg, CH:
Universitats-Verlag, 1954.
Wilde, Oscar. De profundis. London: Methuen, 1913; second edition, 1950; quoted
according to www.gutenberg.org/files/921/921-h/921-h.htm.
William of St. Thierry. The Nature and Dignity of Love. Transl. Thomas X. Davis.
Kalamazoo, MI: Cistercian Publications, 1981.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Notebooks. Oxford: Blackwell, 1961.
Wordsworth, William. The Poetical Works of Wordsworth. Ed. Thomas Hutchinson
and Ernest de Selincourt. London: Oxford University Press, 1965.
Wright, Nicholas Thomas. Surprised by Hope: Rethinking Heaven, the Resurrection,
and the Mission of the Church. New York: HarperOne, 2008.
Index
causality, 270
entitas, 101
esse, 101
God, 162
ousia, 101
Bender, Melanie, 105, 110
Benedict XII, 154
Benedict XVI/Joseph Ratzinger, 17, 53, 71, 80,
105, 109, 122, 153, 154
Berger, David, 149
Bernard of Clairvaux, 241
Bernini, Giovanni Lorenzo, 242
Biblicism, 27
bodysoul problem, 262
Boethius, Anicius Manlius Torquatus Severinus,
32, 183, 189, 206, 207, 213
Bonaventure, 6, 29, 35
boredom, 166
Borges, Jorge Luis, 185
Boros, Ladislaus, 194
Bos, Gunther, 16
Brandt, Reinhard, 7
Brunner, Emil, 68
Bultmann, Rudolf, 68
Cano, Melchor, 74
causality
out of nothing, 10
secondary, 271
cave allegory, 122, 178
celebration, 56
change, 10, 143
charity, 191
Chenu, Marie-Dominique, 74
Christology, 2529
and conscience, 26
and truth, 26
Christological bottleneck, 25
transcendental, 80
Chrysostom, John, 114
Cicero, Marcus Tullius, 16
290
Index
Claudel, Paul, 195
concrete, 3133
double structure, 146
conformity, 140
conscience, 223, 224
Last Judgment, 226
consciousness, 191, 202
contemplation, 155, 253
of the beloved, 156
contemplative knowledge, 122129
Biblical teaching, 120122
contemplative life, 57, 217, 253, 255, 256
co-perception, 135
copula, 136
creation, 1012
and succession, 11
evolution, 269, 274
out of nothing, 8
Crick, Francis, 261263
curiosity, 1619
Damascene, John, 114
Dante, Aligieri, 251, 253
delight, see joy
Descartes, Rene, 78, 141, 262
desiderium naturale, 17, 8692, 96, 101, 131, 145,
276
boundaries, 172176
desire, 191201
and joy, 88
Dickens, Charles, 108
Dilthey, Wilhelm, 39
Dionysius the Areopagite, 14, 36, 37, 106, 114,
164
disbelief in a life after death, 1376
experience prejudice, 2041
natural aversion, 1416
philosophical prejudices, 1963
vain curiosity, 1619
Dondaine, Hyacinthe F., 114
Dostoyevsky, Fyodor, 26, 74, 204, 209, 220
doubt, 65
Eckhart, Meister, 76, 119, 265
Eco, Umberto, 52
ecstasy, 199
Edwards, Jonathan, 192, 193
Egan, Harvey D., 33
Eicher, Peter, 27
Einstein, Albert, 188
emergence, 59, 112119
Aristotle, 6, 9
from physical to spiritual, 241
in consciousness, 9
seminal reasons, 6
end
of all human actions, 146
of the mind, 146
Engelhard, Markus, 29
Eni, 203
Epicurus, 58, 59
epikeia, 235
Erlebnis, 3941
eros, 90
Eternal Life
boredom, 166
life history, 180236
eternity, 180
definition, 183
fullness of time, 181
motion and rest, 190
time, 181190
experience, 2041
concrete, 241
Erlebnis, 3941
of God, 2939
predicative structure, 135143
experience of God
Bonaventure, 29
Catechism of the Catholic Church, 30
concrete, 3133
Hans Urs von Balthasar, 29
in the Bible, 3439
mysticism, 33
rapture, 3839
theodicy, 3031
faith, 91
act, 158
and Eternal Life, 6476
and philosophy, 131
and reason, 28, 130
as light, 161
faith authorities, 65
habit, 158
implicit, 164
wonder, 157
Feinendegen, Norbert, 87
Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 79
fideism, 27
final-decision hypothesis, 194
final end, 98
Fischer, Klaus, 27
Fonvizin, Natalja D., 26
form, 268
two kinds, 148
forma intelligibilis, 116, 148153
Frankl, Viktor, 155, 156, 208210, 219, 221
Franklin, Benjamin, 80
Freud, Sigmund, 61
291
292
friend
second self, 199
friendship
with oneself, 237
Fromm, Erich, 37, 195, 200
fulguration, 8
future perfect tense, 82
Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 40, 41
Galilei, Galileo, 76, 94, 159
Gilson, Etienne,
118, 245, 249, 276
Glorieux, Palemon, 194
goal of human nature, 9799
God
being, 229, 270
efficient cause, 270
essence and existence, 200
experience, 2939
final cause, 272
holy mystery, 166
immanence of God in world, 254
immanence of world in God, 254
knowledge of God through his essence, 133
light, 148
Truth, 133, 134
unchangeableness, 112
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von, 40, 62, 79,
109
Good Samaritan, 4952
Goriceva, Tatjana, 204
grace and nature, 26
grace presupposes and fulfills nature, 171, 181
Gradl, Stefan, 172, 248, 249, 255
Gregory of Nyssa, 73, 190
Habermas, Jurgen, 119
Hamilton, Alexander, 222
happiness, 132133
and human nature, 169171
divine, 145
joy, 249252
right, 276
Hardon, John A., 261
Hattrup, Dieter, 122, 173, 182
Havel, Vaclav, 92, 210, 211, 221, 227230
hedonism, 5863, 243
Heidegger, Martin, 4749
hell, 104110
deficient love, 109
free will, 106
objective loneliness, 108
Henry of Ghent, 100
hermeneutics, 7176
historical reading, 73
theoretical reading, 73
Index
heuristic principles, 171
history, 230
Hodges, Herbert Arthur, 39
Hoffmann, Georg, 68
Hofstadter, Richard, 74
Homer, 123
hominisation, 269275
hope
in ones own resurrection, 8084
transcendental, 80
Hopkins, Jasper, 173
Horkheimer, Max, 3
Hoye, William J., 18, 29, 31, 3436, 89, 94, 107,
114, 129, 131, 134, 149, 230
Huby, Pamela M., 99
Hugh of St. Victor, 73
hylomorphism, 262
idea, 2324
immortality of the soul, 7880, 181
in the Enlightenment, 7880
theodicy, 7980
implicit Faith, 164
individuality, 169, 172, 175
intelligent designer, 97
interpretation of eschatological teachings,
7176
Jacob, 121
Jefferson, Thomas, 80, 230
Job, 257
John of the Cross, 30, 206
John Paul II, 2729
John Scotus Eriugena, 74, 114, 226
Johnson, Monte Ransome, 99
Jonas, Hans, 220
Jonsen, Albert R., 219
joy, 8889
and desire, 88
and eternity, 83
happiness, 249252
pleasure, 248, 249
Kafka, Franz, 213, 216
Kant, Immanuel, 9, 53, 80, 141, 216, 222227
the other world, 9
Kasper, Walter, 66, 67
Kehl, Medard, 109
Kierkegaard, Sren, 201
King, Martin Luther, Jr., 233
knowledge
effect of truth, 142
Kremer, Klaus, 265
Kullmann, Wolfgang, 99
Kung, Hans, 50, 53, 65, 66
Index
Laertius, Diogenes, 59
Laporta, Jorge, 172
Last Judgment, 222, 224226
conscience, 226
leisure, 4748
Leitheiser, Ludwig, 50
Lennox, James G., 99
Lessing, Gotthold Ephraim, 78
lethargy, 92
Lewis, Clive S., 8789, 92, 93, 109, 110, 182, 193,
203, 206, 239, 240, 244246, 252, 253
life before death, 180
life history, 170, 175, 180236
Eternal Life, 180236
life through death, 182
light, 170
God, 148
of Being, 118
of Faith, 161
of glory, 112119, 144, 183, 203
Lorenz, Konrad, 8
love, 82, 89, 191193
a feeling, 53, 63
agape, 90
as union, 52, 195198
atheism, 200
eros, 90
essence, 196
existence of beloved, 199
goodwill, 197
not helping, 195
of God, 191192
of neighbor, 192
the beautiful, 52
unfulfilled, 198
union of the affect, 195, 196, 198
unity of love of God and love of neighbor,
253
vision, 201
Lubac, Henri de, 37
Lucretius, 88, 89
Luther, Martin, 221
MacDonald, George, 206
Madison, James, 222
Mahler, Gustav, 168
Mann, Thomas, 203, 204
Marcel, Gabriel, 82
Marx, Jenny, 54
Marx, Karl, 45, 46, 53, 54
Marxism
self-criticism, 5354
matter, 240, 272
divine knowledge, 254
frozen spirit, 274
293
McGinn, Bernard, 33
meaning of life, 180
Mechthild of Magdeburg, 241
medium quo, 114, 119
medium quod, 148
medium sub quo, 115, 119, 148
memory, 201204
human dignity, 201
Mendelssohn, Moses, 78
morality, 216236
civil law, 233235
divine will, 231232
epikeia, 235
failure, 221
God, 235
love, 217, 218
prudence, 217218
responsibility, 219233
solicitude, 218
wisdom, 217218
motion, 143
mysticism, 33
naiveness of statements on Eternal Life, 1314
nature does nothing in vain, 95, 96, 99100, 104,
131, 145, 173, 201
Nicholas of Cusa, 57, 76, 101, 124128, 147,
172174, 176179, 253
Nicolas, Jean Herve, 19
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 83
obediential potency, 103, 276
Ott, Heinrich, 67, 68
Paul, 212, 219, 240
peace, 221
Pegis, Anton Charles, 266
Pesch, Christian, 50
phantasm, 202, 239
Picht, Georg, 222, 230
Pieper, Josef, 47, 48, 79, 217
pious interpretation, 73
Planck, Max, 262
Plato, 23, 24, 59, 122, 123, 126, 135, 137, 139, 140,
142, 173, 178, 195, 244, 252, 253
pleasure
good, 248
joy, 248249
love, 247
reason, 244
Plotinus, 123, 124, 148
poiesis, 122
positivism and neopositivism, 2225
possibility, 135
and reality, 136, 143
294
Index
295
Index
Splett, Jorg, 42, 43
Stange, Carl, 79
subject-predicate dualism, 135136
suffering, 95, 101, 204216
self-consciousness, 216
theodicy, 204205, 213
technical mindset, 4547
essence of technology, 4849
Marxism, 4547
morality, 4955
teleology, 96
temporality, 180
Tennyson, Alfred, 61
Teresa of Avila,
242
theodicy, 79, 80, 204205, 213
theology and philosophy, 2729, 131
theophanies, 129
theoretical life, 57
theoria, 122, 124
theory, 5458
and praxis, 256
celebration, 56
happiness, 55
Thomas Aquinas, 3, 811, 13, 14, 1719, 2528,
30, 3340, 51, 53, 56, 57, 6063, 65, 7375,
85, 88, 91, 9597, 99103, 105108, 111, 112,
115119, 123, 129149, 151166, 169171, 174,
175, 181, 183, 185, 189202, 207, 213218,
231235, 238, 239, 242250, 252268, 270,
274277
Tillich, Paul, 53
time, 97
and being, 137
and eternity, 8283
definition, 183184
desire, 191201
distentio animi, 186
modes, 187, 188
unity, 97, 137
transcendence, 229
Troisfontaines, Roger, 194
truth, 139142
and knowledge, 134, 142
and Truth itself, 76
and truths, 132, 133, 177
becoming, 139, 141
before knowledge, 141
conformity, 140
desire for, 176179