Yve-Alain Bois and John Shepley. Painting As Model.
Yve-Alain Bois and John Shepley. Painting As Model.
Yve-Alain Bois and John Shepley. Painting As Model.
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to October.
http://www.jstor.org
Painting as Model
Fene^trejaune cadmium, ou, Les dessous de la peinture by HubertDamisch,
Paris, Editionsdu Seuil, 1984.
YVE-ALAIN
BOIS
126
OCTOBER
Paintingas Model
127
128
OCTOBER
nonsense with which the artist'smind was momentarilyencumbered. It is because the line has the functionof destroyingthe plane as such that it will have
to be straight:
The interdictionof any other line but the straightcorresponded to
the experientialfactthat a line curvinginward on a canvas or piece
of paper defines "full"or "empty"spaces, which the imaging consciousness is irresistiblyled to consider for themselvesto the detriment of the line that serves as their pretext. Mondrian's paintings
are made to counter such impulses and to hinder the movement
whereby an unreal object is constitutedfromthe tangible realityof
the painting,the eye being ceaselessly led back to the painting'sconstituentelements, line, color, design (p. 69).
Damisch's thesisis rigorouslyanti-Sartrean:in opposition to the "imaging
consciousness,"whichnecessarilyhas as itspurpose the constitutionofan image,
he sees in Mondrian's canvases, in Pollock's, in Picasso's Portrait
of Vollard,each
with its own modality, "an ever-reversedkaleidoscope that offersto aesthetic
a task both novel and withoutassignable end.., the 'meaning' of the
perception
work consistingpreciselyin this swarmingand ambiguous appeal" (p. 78). Or
again: "If the painter has chosen to prohibitthe imaging consciousness from
giving itselffreerein . . . it is forthe purpose of awakening in the spectatorthe
uneasiness with which the perception of a painting should be accompanied"
(p. 71). Now, this task of the painter is the stake ofhis art; it is what makes his
canvas a specifictheoreticalmodel, thedevelopmentofa thoughtwhose properly
pictorial aspect cannot be circumvented:
One cannot give way to reveriein frontof a Mondrian painting,nor
even to pure contemplation.But it is here thattherecomes intoplay,
beyond the sensorial pleasure granted us by Sartre, some more
secret activityof consciousness, an activityby definitionwithoutassignable end, contraryto the imaging activitywhich exhausts itself
in the constitutionof its object. Each time perceptionthinksit can go
beyond what is given it to see toward what it would constituteas
meaning, it is immediatelyled back to the firstexperience, which
wants it to falterin constitutingthat white as background and this
black as a form(ibid.).
I would call this theoreticalmodel introducedby Damisch perceptive,
but
by antiphrasis,because forthe painters studied it is a question in each case of
"disturbingthe permanent structuresof perception, and firstof all the figure/
ground relationship,beyond which one would be unable to speak of a perceptive field"(p. 110, in connectionwith Dubuffet). With the exception of one or
two texts,especially the one of 1974 on Valerio Adami, all the articlesin Fenitre
jaune cadmiuminsiston this point: "Painting, forthe one who produces it as for
Paintingas Model
129
the one who consumes it, is always a matterof perception"(p. 148). And all the
examples chosen (except forAdami and Saul Steinberg) assign to modernity
the preliminarytask of confusing the figure/groundopposition, without the
assurance of which no perceptioncould establish itselfin imaging synthesis.It
is this "perceptive model" that allows Damisch not only to compare Pollock
and Mondrian but also to establishthe ambiguityof the figure/ground
relationas
the
theme
of
the
American
and
to
ship
very
painter's interlacings
reject as
the
some
divide
that
have
tried
to
enforce
between
particularlyunproductive
Pollock's great abstract period, that of the all-over works of 1947-50, and his
so-called figurativecanvases of 1951 and the years that followed. Likewise,
Dubuffet'sgreat period (the 1950s) is deciphered, by directappeal to MerleauPonty, as an essential moment in this historyof perceptiveambiguity:
By treatingthe figuresas so many vaguely silhouettedbackgrounds
whose texturehe strivesto decipher and - conversely- by carrying
his gaze toward the less differentiatedbackgrounds to catch their
secretfiguresand mechanics, this painter has restoredto the idea of
formits original meaning, ifit is true that formcannot be reduced to
the geometricoutline of objects, that it is bound up with the texture
of things,and thatit draws simultaneouslyon all our senses (p. 117).
The phenomenologicalthemeof the originalunityof the senses oftenreturnsin
Damisch's writing,but it would be vain to see in these studies an application of
Merleau-Ponty's theory.And this is not only because this recurrenttheme is
seriouslyquestioned withregard to Fautrier(p. 134) or because the criticismof
"pure visibility"is reorientedthroughpsychoanalysis(pp. 262-263), but also
because phenomenologicalapprehensionin Damisch opens onto a second model,
copresentwith the first.
The TechnicalModel
In opposition to the "optical" interpretationthat has been given to
Pollock's all-over paintings by leading American formalistcritics(Greenberg,
Fried), an interpretationthatpartakes in a certainway, but much more subtly,
of Sartrean unreality,3Damisch proposes fromthe starta reading that I would
call technical.
It begins (but this also applies to the textson Klee, Dubuffet,or
Mondrian) with an insistenceon the realspace set in play by these canvases (of
course, it is always a question of counteringthe Sartrean imaginaryor unreal-
On the notion of opticsand the "relative indifferenceto the material process of elaboration"
3. the
of
work, typical of Clement Greenberg and Michael Fried, see Jean Clay, "La peinture en
charpie," dossier Ryman, Macula, nos. 3-4 (1978), pp. 171-172.
130
OCTOBER
4.
See especially Jean Clay, "Pollock, Mondrian, Seurat: la profoundeur plate," in Hans
Namuth, L'atelierdeJacksonPollock,Paris, Macula, 1982.
Paintingas Model
131
in the order of perception. From then on it becomes one of the essential question marks of Damisch's inquiry, functioningalmost as an epistemologicaltest
in his discourse. The reemergence of the hidden undersides in Dubuffet
(p. 114), the exchanges ofpositionbetween outer surfaceand underside in Klee
(p. 213), the interweavingsof Mondrian and later of Rouan- all of these become theoreticalmodels that demonstratethe painting of this centuryjust as
no accidentthat
perspectivedemonstratedthatof theRenaissance. It is therefore
the
the book appears under the sign of Le chef-d'oeuvre
inconnu; essay devoted to
the novel provides the subtitleto the collection: "The Undersides of Painting."
If one is to believe Frenhofer,it looks as thoughpaintingshould produce its fulleffectonly insofaras it proceeds, in its most intimatetexture, froma predeterminedexchange of positions that would be the
equivalent of a kind of weaving in which the threads would go up
and down alternatively,the same strandpassing now above and now
below, without the possibility of being assigned a univocal sign
(p. 16).
Frenhofer'sname is invoked in no less than fivetextsin thiscollectionin addition to the one devoted to the "philosophical study"of Balzac ("whoever writes
proceeds in a way not dissimilar to one who paints, using a quotation that he
had firstsingled out for completelydifferentpurposes, to start out on a new
in every sense of the word" [p. 258]). Far removed from recent
development,
the Frenhoferof Damisch has been, fromhis first
romanticistinterpretations,5
a
emblem
of
the
texts,
conversion, the signal of invention- with Cezanne
c'est
moi") and, one should add, Seurat - of a new thicknessthat
("Frenhofer,
would no longer borrow fromthe old academic recipes:
And if one wants modernityin painting to be signaled by the replacement of the superimpositionof preparations,of underpainting,
glazing, transparencies, and varnish, by another craft based on
flatness, the juxtaposition of touches, and simultaneous contrast,
how can we not see that the problem of the "undersides"will only
have been displaced or transformed,painting having necessarily
kept somethingof its thickness,even ifit were aiming only at surface
effects?(p. 37).
Here, fromthe beginning, a metaphor intervenesto help us see that this
model is irreducibleto the perceptive
technical
model as it was earlier described,
it
is
its
that
of
the
inscribed
on the chessboard, "in its
corollary:
although
figure
132
OCTOBER
Paintingas Model
133
6.
134
OCTOBER
by a fewyears
Already in the essay devoted to Dubuffetin
1962--anticipating
flatbedpictureplane in connecLeo Steinberg'sinventionof the concept of the
tion withRauschenberg- then in more recentstudies, the confusionofthe vertical and horizontalproposed by one side of modern paintingwas taken foran
essential mutation,participating,ifyou like, in a critique of optics, whose importance is yetto be measured.7 This model includes Dubuffet'stwindesires"to
forcethe gaze to consider the painted surfaceas a ground viewed fromabove,
and at the same time to erect the ground into a wall calling forman's interven"an area, a space of play, attion by line or imprint"(p. 112); Pollock's grounds,
tacked by the artistfromall sides at once, which he did not hesitateto penetrate
in person and which . . . put up a physical resistance to him" (p. 149); Saul
Steinberg's Tables(p. 231), but I would be temptedto say of these, contraryto
Damisch, that they do not come "directlyinto the inquiry," and are among
"those that proliferatein its wake" (p. 130). Even Mondrian's work, as I have
tried to show elsewhere,8touches on this symbolicmodel, this taxonomic collapse, this overturningof oppositions- especially between representationand
action- on which our whole Western aesthetic is founded. Damisch probably
had an intuitionof this, since forhim the studyof Mondrian's work is "an invitation to createunder its most concrete aspects" (p. 72). The revelation of this
model is one of the mostfruitful
pointsofDamisch's book. From cubism to miniof
from
the
abstraction
the 1920s to that of the '50s and '60s, I would
malism,
almost go as far as to point to all the high points of modern art as verifications
of this discovery,as demonstrationsof its validity.
The Strategic
Model
Shortlybefore his death, "and as though in passing," Barnett Newman
confidedto Damisch "thateverythinghe had been able to do had meaning only
in relationto Pollock's work and againstit"(p. 154). I like to thinkthatDamisch
recalled thisremarkwhen he read Levi-Strauss's Voiedesmasques,and thatfrom
long knowledge of this kind of secret, then fromits sudden emergence as evimodel.9 Like
dence, a fourthmodel emerged in Damisch's text, a strategic
7.
Leo Steinberg,
"Other
Criteria"
inthecollection
ofthesamename,New
(1972),reprinted
"surrealist"
York,OxfordUniversity
Press,1972,pp. 55-91. For a readingof Giacometti's
Paintingas Model
135
chess pieces, like phonemes in language, a work has significance,as LeviStrauss shows, firstby what it is not and what it opposes, that is, in each case
according to its position, its value, withina field- itselfliving and stratified
which has above all to be circumscribedby definingits rules. Livi-Strauss's
condescending remarksabout art historians,unable, in his opinion, to understand the structuralor rather the strategic nature of signification,are not
strictlydeserved, at least if one considers art historyin its earlier phases and
conceived the
not forwhat it has largelybecome today. As we know, Wb1fflin
baroque paradigm as incomprehensibleunless measured against the classical;
of sixteenth-and
and Riegl demonstratedin a thickvolume how the Kunstwollen
Dutch art was at firstnegativelydefinedin relationto that
seventeenth-century
of Italian art of the same period. Such readings are, in any case, commonplace
in Fenitrejaune
cadmium(see, forexample, the comparisons between Pollock and
and
have the merit of no longer taking seriouslythe autonomy of
Mondrian)
what is called style. Likewise, since strategymeans power stakes, there are
many observationsin thisbook on the historyof the artisticinstitutionin its relation to production, whetherit has to do with the role of criticism,the museum, the market,the public, or even the relationship(fundamentallychanged
since C6zanne, p. 123) that the painter maintains with his or her canvas.
But the interestof the strategicmodel does not reside so much thereas in
what it allows us to think historicallyof the concepts revealed by the other
models as well as the ties that they maintain among themselves. One will
notice, by the way, that this fourthmodel was not born directlyfroma confrontationwith the works themselves: it does not immediatelytake account of
pictorial inventionitself,of the status of the theoreticalin painting, but of the
conditions of its appearance, of what establishes itselfbetween works; it finds
itselfwith respect to the other models in a second, metacriticalposition, and
thisis whyit allows us to ask again the question ofthe pictorialspecificity(of invention) and survivalofpainting,withoutgettingstuckonce more in the essentialism to which American formalistcriticismhad accustomed us. "It is not
enough, in order forthere to be painting, that the painter take up his brushes
"it is still
again," Damisch tellsus: it is stillnecessarythat it be worththe effort,
that
in
succeed
to
us
that
necessary
[thepainter]
demonstrating
paintingis somewe
cannot
do
that
it
is
without,
thing
positively
indispensable to us, and that it
would be madness - worse still, a historical error- to let it lie fallow today"
(p. 293).
potential masks always by its side, masks that mighthave been chosen in its stead and substituted
forit. In discussing a particular problem, I hope to have shown that a mask is not primarilywhat
it representsbut what it transforms,that is to say, what it chooses notto represent.Like a myth,a
mask denies as much as it affirms.It is not made solely of what it says or thinksit is saying, but
what it excludes" (Claude Levi-Strauss, The WayofMasks, trans. Sylvia Modelski, Seattle, Universityof Washington Press, 1982, p. 144).
136
OCTOBER
Paintingas Model
137
ironic attitudetoward the apocalyptic tone adopted today concerningthe impasse in which art findsitself,an impasse to be taken simplyas one ofthe many
interruptedmatches to which historyholds the secret.10