1) The author argues that critics of the European Union misunderstand its present reality. In reality, the EU is becoming more cosmopolitan and less defined by national identities.
2) The author asserts that the solution to the EU's problems is more European integration, not less. Nationalist thinking has created barriers, while a more cosmopolitan Europe without strict national categories would be better.
3) The EU's standards for membership should be based on how European it is, not on religious or ethnic definitions. A truly European identity is open and inclusive of many backgrounds.
1) The author argues that critics of the European Union misunderstand its present reality. In reality, the EU is becoming more cosmopolitan and less defined by national identities.
2) The author asserts that the solution to the EU's problems is more European integration, not less. Nationalist thinking has created barriers, while a more cosmopolitan Europe without strict national categories would be better.
3) The EU's standards for membership should be based on how European it is, not on religious or ethnic definitions. A truly European identity is open and inclusive of many backgrounds.
1) The author argues that critics of the European Union misunderstand its present reality. In reality, the EU is becoming more cosmopolitan and less defined by national identities.
2) The author asserts that the solution to the EU's problems is more European integration, not less. Nationalist thinking has created barriers, while a more cosmopolitan Europe without strict national categories would be better.
3) The EU's standards for membership should be based on how European it is, not on religious or ethnic definitions. A truly European identity is open and inclusive of many backgrounds.
1) The author argues that critics of the European Union misunderstand its present reality. In reality, the EU is becoming more cosmopolitan and less defined by national identities.
2) The author asserts that the solution to the EU's problems is more European integration, not less. Nationalist thinking has created barriers, while a more cosmopolitan Europe without strict national categories would be better.
3) The EU's standards for membership should be based on how European it is, not on religious or ethnic definitions. A truly European identity is open and inclusive of many backgrounds.
higher. The left in other countries of the world should be patient about passing judgment on the present policies of Lulas government. For the moment, we should assume that Lulas vi- sion of the future of Brazil is governed by the values of the left. Whether this vision will be- come reality is a different and currently unde- Ulrich Beck urope has a novel and empirical reality that all its critics fundamentally skip over. The reason anti-Europeans cant imagine a future for Europe is that they cant imagine its present. They are trapped in the contradictions of EU member nations misun- derstanding of themselves. And this false pic- ture of Europes present is blocking its future development. Imagine for a moment what would happen if the European Union applied for membership in the European Union. Its application would be flatly rejected. Why? Because the European Union doesnt live up to its own criteria of de- mocracy, of Europeanness. As I have argued in these pages (Democracy Beyond the Na- tion-State, Winter 1999) and elsewhere, this paradox goes right to the heart of whats wrong with the European Union. It isnt European enough. I think I can demonstrate that the eurosk- eptics have it exactly backward. The solution to the EUs problems is not more national re- alism. Rather, it is more Europe, more of the reality we are already experiencinga cosmo- politan Europe. National categories of thought have created this impasse. National irrealism is Europes problem. I make my case with three theses. 1. The European Union is not a Christian club. As an empirical assertion this is so obvious its a wonder how the debate got started. To call Europe a Christian club is to talk as if Londistan did not existthe capital city of Islam outside the Islamic world. To say the European Union is a Christian club is to el- evate unreality into a theory, the propositions of which are radically wrong. The easiest ex- ample is the now ubiquitous idea that Europe is a great community of common descent. Turkey is, of course, the looming question that has brought this long-buried discourse of origins out of hiding. People who want to keep the Turks out have suddenly discovered that the roots of Europe lie in its Christian heri- tage. Those who share our continent, but do not share this Christian heritage, are seen as Europes Other. But this is to take the idea of an ethnic na- tionthat you have an identity you get from your parents, which cant be learned or un- learnedand apply it at the level of Europe. It conceives national and cultural identities as so inherently and mutually exclusive that you cant have two of them in the same logical space. This is not only empirically wrong, it is to- tally at odds with the idea of Europe. If identi- ties are mutually exclusive, Europe is an im- possible project. The whole idea of the EU was based on the idea that one could be German and French or British and German at the same time. Dangerous traces of this exclusivist idea Understanding the Real Europe E POLITICS ABROAD
cidable question. It is the beginning of a four-
year, perhaps eight-year, journey in which many lessons will be learned before we can come to an evaluation of what Lula truly means. Jos Eisenberg is professor of political science at the Instituto Universitrio de Pesquisas do Rio de Janeiro (IUPERJ), in Brazil. DISSENT / Summer 2003 33 33 33 33 33 exist even in the seemingly benign idea of cul- tural dialogue. The picture normally evoked by dialogue is of two separate entities, Islam and the West, each occupying its own terri- tory, who then need to reach out to the other in order to have contact. But in fact, these en- tities already interpenetrate each other. And whats more, their internal differences are as large as any they have with each other. Where can you find room in Islam and the West for all the second- and third-generation Mus- lim immigrants who are now an integral part of every country in Europe? Or for that matter for Westernized Muslims? Or for the Arab bourgeoisie? The Oriental Christians? The Is- raeli Arabs? The list of exceptions goes on un- til it swamps the rule. The closer we look at empirical reality, the clearer it becomes that the presumption of cultural homogeneity is really a denial of reality. But it gets worse. Those who would re-in- vent the Christian West in order to build walls around Europe are turning the project of the European Enlightenment on its head. They are turning Europe back into a religion. Indeed, they are virtually turning it into a race. There could be nothing more anti-Western and anti- Enlightenment than that. The true standards for Europeanness lie in the answer to the question, What will make Europe more European? And the answer is a more cosmopolitan Europe, where national identities become less and less exclusive and more and more inclusive. Europeanness means being able to combine in one existence things that only appear to be mutually exclu- sive in the small-mindedness of ethnic think- ing. It is, of course, perfectly possible to be a Muslim and a democrat, just as one can be a socialist and a small businesspersonor, less pleasantly, a lover of the Bavarian landscape and the founder of an anti-foreigner organiza- tion. The European conception of humanity doesnt contain any concrete definition of what it means to be human. It cant. It is of its es- sence that it be anti-essentialist. Strictly speak- ing, it is a-human, in the sense that one can be a-religious. The European idea of man was formed precisely by casting off all the nave conceptions of what it meant to be human that had been imposed on it by religion and moral- izing metaphysics. It is no accident that Europeanness is mostly defined procedurally. Only a pragmatic- political definition can express this a-human essence. The flipside of this substantial emp- tiness is radical tolerance and radical openness. It is this that is the secret of Europes success. 2. Cosmopolitan Europe is in the process of bidding farewell to postmodernity. In sim- plified form, we might say that we are pass- ing from nationalistic Europe, through postmodern Europe, to cosmopolitan Eu- rope. Cosmopolitan Europe was consciously con- ceived and launched after the Second World War as the political antithesis to a nationalis- tic Europe and the physical and moral devas- tation that had emerged from it. It was in this spirit that Winston Churchill, standing amid the ruins of a destroyed continent in 1946, claimed, If Europe were once united, there would be no limit to the happiness, to the pros- perity and the glory which its four hundred million people would enjoy. It was the charis- matic statesmen of the Western democracies and specifically the individuals and groups most identified with resistance to the Nazis who reinvented Europe. And they consciously sought to reach past the mass graves and na- tional cemeteries back into the European his- tory of ideas. osmopolitan Europe is thus a project born of resistance. It is important to re- member what this means because two things come together in it. In the first place, resistance was not the automatic result of col- lapse. It was a reaction against the traumatic experience of European values being perverted. Cosmopolitan Europe was born in the bitter realization that the idea of what constitutes the truly human implies the subhuman. And that when truly human becomes the basis of a nation state, the result is a totalitarian regime that seeks to exclude, to separate out, to re- model, or to annihilate all people who cant or dont want to fit its ideal. This brings us to the second point: if we no longer base ourselves on some transcendent POLITICS ABROAD C 34 34 34 34 34 DISSENT / Summer 2003 human substance that needs to be saved, then what is it we are trying to nurture and preserve? If we are now dealing with de-centered quasi- subjects of which no one can definitively say what they are or what they ought to want to be, then what is the inviolate essence our in- stitutions should be set up to protect? On what grounds can we guarantee that it wont be hauled off, tortured, and killed? The resistance that built Europe was motivated by clear ideas of inviolable human dignity, and of the moral duty to relieve the suffering of others. The ba- sis of common humanity was the feeling of sympathya structurally empty feeling that draws its content from outside. These cosmo- politan ideals then became the foundations of the postwar European project. Cosmopolitan Europe was founded as something that struggles morally, politically, historically, and economically for reconcilia- tion. It was intended as a decisive break with all previous political history, and it accom- plished it. With it, 1,500 years of intra-Euro- pean warfare came definitively to a close. This ideal of reconciliation was not so much preached idealistically as practiced material- istically. The first step toward the limitless happiness that Churchill foresaw was a limit- less market. Reconciliation was accomplished by being encoded into institutions, through the creation of profane interdependence in the economy, in politics, in security matters, in sci- ence, and in culture. Cosmopolitanism was created consciously, but it was created first as a reality, not as a theory. f we want to excavate the original con- sciousness of cosmopolitanism that lies at the basis of the European project, it is the collective memory of the holocaust that pro- vides our clearest archiveas Daniel Levy and Natan Sznaider argue in Memory Unbound: The Holocaust and the Formation of Cosmopoli- tan Memory.* The founding set of documents of European cosmopolitanism, written when the war was still warm, as it were, were those of the Nuremberg Trials. Here we can see clearly how a cosmopolitan institutional logic was the first thing the builders of Europe reached for in trying to make a break with the past. The Nuremberg court created both legal categories and a trial procedure that went far beyond the sovereignty of the nation state. It did so for practical reasons. It was the only way to capture in legal concepts and court proce- dures the historical monstrosity that was the systematic and state-organized extermination of the Jews. Article 6 of the Charter of the International Military Tribunal delineates three categories of crime: crimes against peace, war crimes, and crimes against humanity. It was in terms of these new categories that Nazi crimes were judged and Nazi criminals tried and sentenced. Crimes against peace and war crimes both still presuppose the laws of a nation-state system of which they are violations. The concept of crimes against humanity, on the other hand, suspends the nation-state presumption. It is the embodiment of the cosmopolitan worldview in legal form. It was in many ways ahead of its time. The lawyers and judges who participated in the Nuremberg Tribunal were ultimately unable to come to grips with this new category. But of the three, it is this cat- egory that has endured in the European imagi- nation. Today, even when we speak of war criminals, what we really mean, as if it were now obvious, is people who have committed crimes against humanity. What was being introduced here was not a new law or a even a new legal principle but rather a new legal logic that broke with the pre- vious nation-state logic of international law. Here is the definition in Article 6c: Crimes against humanity: namely, murder, ex- termination, enslavement, deportation and other inhumane acts committed against any civilian population, before or during the war; or persecutions on political, racial or religious grounds in execution of or in connection with any crime within the jurisdiction of the Tribu- nal, whether or not in violation of domestic law of the country where perpetrated. The first key formulation is before and dur- ing the warThis is what distinguishes crimes against humanity from war crimes: there may be no war. And the second is that such crimes I *Published in Germany as Erinnerung im globalen Zeitalter: Der Holocaust (Suhrkamp Verlag, Frankfurt a.M.,2001). POLITICS ABROAD DISSENT / Summer 2003 35 35 35 35 35 exist whether or not in violation of domestic law of the country where perpetrated. These enormous breaks with nationally based legal concepts were necessary because the persecution of the Jews was legal accord- ing to the laws of Nazi Germany and happened before the war took place. But taken together they change everything. They posit an indi- vidual responsibility for all perpetrators that is based outside the national legal context, in the community of nations. What had been crimes against the state now became crimes against humanity. So if the state is a criminal one, the individual who serves it must still reckon with being charged and sentenced for his or her deeds before an international court of law. Finally, the phrase any civilian population suspends the principle of citizenship and re- places it with the principle of cosmopolitan responsibility. This cosmopolitan legal principle is designed to protect the civilian population not from the violence of other hostile states (which is the province of war crimes) but from violence committed by states against their own citizensor more important, against its noncitizens, against people deemed outside its legal boundaries while existing inside its bor- ders. This is not only far-reaching and provoca- tive. It is a complete reversal of legal principles. It negates what had previously been the ulti- mate legal legitimation, the national legal code. It suspends that code. Cosmopolitan law is forced to break national law in order to come into force. But now an interesting question arises that is much harder to answer than it seems at first sight. Who are crimes against humanity com- mitted against? Legally speaking, were these crimes against the Jews only? If they were com- mitted against humanity, as the name implies, does that mean everybody? Including the per- petrators? here were those who argued at the time of Nuremberg that the idea of crimes against humanity was a legal nul- lity because humanity is an empty concept. That objection should have more force today than it did at the time. If cosmopolitan Eu- rope is founded in opposition to all substan- tial ideas of what constitutes the truly human, then what are we defending under the banner of human rights? It is at this point that cosmopolitan Europe generates a genuinely European inner contra- diction, legally, morally, and politically. The tra- ditions from which colonial, nationalist, and genocidal horror originated were clearly Euro- pean. But so were the new legal standards against which these acts were condemned and tried in the spotlight of world publicity. At this formative moment in its history, Europe mobi- lized its traditions to produce something his- torically new. It took the idea of recognition of the humanity of the Other and made it the foundation of an historically new counter-logic. It specifically designed this logic to counter- act the ethnic perversion of the European tra- dition to which the nation-based form of Eu- ropean modernity had just shown itself so hor- ribly liable. It was an attempt to distill a Euro- pean antidote to Europe. Understood in this sense, the memory of the Holocaust is not just a monument to Europes sense of the tragic. It is a memorial specifically to the European barbarism that was made possible by the marriage of modernity and the nation-state. It is a mass grave upon which the new Europe made an oath and chose a different path. Europes collective memory of the Holocaust provides the basis of the EU. It is a warning sign that when modernity de- velops exclusively in the grooves of the nation- state, it builds the potential for a moral, politi- cal, economic, and technological catastrophe without limit, without mercy, and without even any consideration for its own survival. In its elevation of pessimism to permanent despair, postmodernity joins hands with nation- alistic Europe. Both deny the possibility of struggling against the horror of European his- tory by radicalizing the idea of Europe. And both ignore the attempt to make Europe more European by making it more cosmopolitan. In this sense, present-day European pessimism reverses the old rule: it remembers the past in order to forget the present. And I believe that Jrgen Habermas is completely correct in his argument that there is a deep continuity be- tween European pessimism and postmodernity. Both have in common a critique of modernity, POLITICS ABROAD T 36 36 36 36 36 DISSENT / Summer 2003 an antimodernity, that offers no alternative but the past. By contrast, cosmopolitan Europe is the European traditions institutionalized internal critique. This process is not complete; it can- not be completed. Indeed, the sequence of en- lightenment, postmodernity, and cosmopolitan modernity represents its beginning stages. 3. National categories of thought make the thought of Europe impossible. The national point of view sees two ways and two ways only of reading contemporary Eu- ropean politics and integration. It sees it ei- ther as federalism, leading to a federal super- state, or as inter-governmentalism, leading to a federation of states. Both models are empiri- cally inadequate. They fail to grasp essential things both about present-day Europe and about the nations that make it up. But they are also, in a deep-structural sense, anti-Euro- pean. They deny the goal most worth attain- ing: a Europe of diversity, a Europe that helps diversity to flourish. This is obvious when it comes to the idea of a federation of states that are seen as de- fending their sovereignty against the expansion of European power. From that perspective, Eu- ropean integration is a kind of European self- colonization. But its just as true in the con- ception of a federal super state. That is how Europe looks when it is filtered through the exclusive categories of national thought, which can only understand it in one way: as a huge ethnocultural nation-state. This makes no sense, as its opponents point out. Such a na- tion is improbable, unwanted and un-Euro- pean. But rather than faulting their concep- tion, they fault reality. It never occurs to them that perhaps Europe isnt properly conceived of as a nation-state. oth the federation of states and the fed- eral super-state describe the same zero- sum game from different angles. Either there is one single state of Europe (federalism), in which case there are no national member states; or else the national member states re- main Europes rulers, in which case there is no Europe (inter-governmentalism). Within this framework of thought, whatever Europe gains, the individual nations lose. And this is true whether one is for a given option or against it. This is what it means to say that national categories of thought make the thought of Eu- rope impossible. Caught up in the false alter- natives of the national viewpoint, we are given the choice between no Europeor no Europe! The same two sides of one dead-end are as prominent as theyve ever been in the current debate about the Constitution. Methodological nationalism denies the em- pirical reality of Europe, which is that it is al- ready a unity of diversity. And it misses that this is already also true of the nations that make it up. Europe is inconceivable on the basis of national homogeneity. But European nations themselves no longer have this homogeneity either. People who want to preserve the old nation-states have first to pretend that those old states still exist, that they are still national containers from which others are excluded. They pretend this kind of France still exists, and this kind of Germany, and this kind of Brit- ain. But they dont. All that now exists is the new France, the new Germany, and the new Britain: no longer nation-states but transnation- al states that have been cosmopolitanized from within. The same is true of a cosmopolitan Europe. It is not only practically but logically impos- sible for it to be the replacement of many small nations with one large nation. It can only be conceived of as a cosmopolitan unity. Other- wise it wouldnt be Europe. But it can become a transnational state, a more defined and com- plex variant of what its component nations are already becoming. Just as the Peace of Westphalia ended the religious wars by separating state from religion, we might consider it the ultimate goal of the European project to separate state and nation. Cosmopolitanism does not mean an abolition of nation, any more than Westphalia meant an abolition of religion. Rather, it means the con- stitutional enshrinement of the principle of national and cultural and ethnic and religious tolerance. Many people consider the Peace of Westphalia the foundation of the modern Eu- POLITICS ABROAD B DISSENT / Summer 2003 37 37 37 37 37 ropean state system. If that is true, then the principle of tolerance was Europes founding principle, the basis of its unwritten constitu- tion. And on this argument, the essence of the postwar European project has been to deepen this principle of tolerance and to extend it. The a-religious state did not abolish religion. Rather, it allowed it to flourish. It allowed there to be more than one; it allowed true religious diver- sity. And the same is true of the a-national state. The goal is not to abolish national iden- tities, but to save them from their own perver- sion, just as Westphalia saved religion from its perversion into religious war. The concept of a cosmopolitan Europe opens our eyes to what has already long been here, which now needs to be affirmed and radicalized against the narrow-minded tenden- cies of the national viewpoint. A logic of in- clusive oppositions is the only way to finally attain a Europe of national diversity. The con- cept of the a-national, cosmopolitan state both mirrors the reality of Europe and furthers the realization of its norms. The legal realities of the EU already express this new kind of both/and reality that is gradu- ally replacing the old either/or of national ho- mogeneity. National and European legal and political cultures have co-existed for decades and are continuing to evolve together. They have merged into a European legal culture without abolishing national political cultures. They present a domain of continuous overlap that expresses political and social reality. The problem is that our ideas of the nation-state have failed to keep up with this reality. The creation of interdependencies in ev- ery field of politicsthe politics of mutual im- brication that makes Europeanization such a ubiquitous feature of our livesis not a one- off form of cooperation that ultimately leaves the nation-states involved untouched. Rather, Europeanization seizes and transforms national sovereignty in the core of its being. This is where the intergovernmental perspective fails to grasp reality. Nation-states have already turned into transnational states, not only so- cially, but administratively, in the heart of their raison dtat. Europe has already changed from a nation-state system into a transnational state system. The point is to make it a better one, in pragmatic and practical terms. he question has often been asked, if the nations of Europe are so discontented, why is it that they so rarely say no to Eu- rope? And the answer is because they follow their own national interests. But without intend- ing it, each following its own interests pulls all of them further and further into the same co- operative system. Each nation limits its right to go off on its own because it expects the others to combine togetherand if they do not, it will be disadvantaged. When repeated over time, these expectations of each others expectations create in each country a new national core. Each nation now has the expectations of all the oth- ers encoded within it. This is how European interests emerge as a nations own interests. This is how the na- tional zero-sum game can be gradually replaced by a European plus-sum game. And this is how national interests become Europeanized. They become reflexive national interests by follow- ing repeated joint strategies of self-limitation. And they follow these strategies because they work. So it is not only the social fabric that has become thoroughly cosmopolitanized. It is even true of the pure national interests them- selves. Nations dont follow cosmopolitan re- alism out of altruism, but rather out of ego- ism, out of realism. The decline of the nation-state is really a decline of the national content of the state and an opportunity to create a cosmopolitan state system that is better able to deal with the prob- lems that all nations face in the world today. Economic globalization, transnational terror- ism, global warming: the litany is familiar and daunting. There is a host of problems that are clearly beyond the power of the old order of nation-states to cope. The answer to global problems that are gathering ominously all around and that refuse to yield to nation-state solutions is for politics to take a quantum leap from the nation-state system to the cosmopoli- tan state system. Politics needs to regain cred- ibility in order to craft real solutions. More than anywhere else in the world, Eu- rope shows that this step is possible. Europe teaches the modern world that the political evolution of states and state systems is by no POLITICS ABROAD T 38 38 38 38 38 DISSENT / Summer 2003 means at an end. National realpolitik is becom- ing unreal, not only in Europe, but throughout the world. It is turning into a lose-lose game. Europeanization means creating a new politics. It means entering as a player into the meta- power game, into the struggle to form the rules of a new global order. The catchphrase for the future might be, Move over AmericaEurope is back! Translated from the German by Michael Pollak Ulrich Beck is professor of sociology at the University of Munich and the London School of Economics and Political Science. His latest book is Conversation with Ulrich BeckAn Introduction to his Work (forthcoming, Polity Press, 2003). POLITICS ABROAD