Two Concepts of Social Capital: Bourdieu vs. Putnam

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 26

Two Concepts of Social Capital: Bourdieu vs.

Putnam
Martti Siisiäinen
Department of Social Sciences and
Philosophy
University of Jyväskylä
e-mail: [email protected]

Paper presented at ISTR Fourth International Conference


"The Third Sector: For What and for Whom?"
Trinity College, Dublin, Ireland
July 5-8, 2000
The paper sets out to compare Robert D. Putnam's concept of social capital with that
of Pierre Bourdieu's. Putnam's concept of social capital has three components:
moral obligations and norms, social values (especially trust) and social networks
(especially voluntary associations). Putnam's central thesis is that if a region has a
well-functioning economic system and a high level of political integration, these are
the result of the region’s successful accumulation of social capital (see 1993). In the
United States many social problems are caused by the decline of social capital; a
tendency that has been going on for the last three decades (Putnam 1993). Adam
Seligman also writes in the same spirit: "The emphasis in modern societies on
consensus (is) based on interconnected networks of trust - among citizens, families,
voluntary organizations, religious denominations, civic associations, and the like.
Similarly the very "legitimation" of modern societies is founded on the "trust" of
authority and governments as generalisations" (1997, 14). The same kinds of voices
are heard among proponents of American communitarianism. Putnam’s ideas are -
to a large extent – a continuation of a current within the American theory of
pluralism. They are also reminiscent of functionalist conceptions of social
integration from the 1950s and early 1960s. The theoretical contributions of the
Putnamian concept and the problems that arise in connection with it are discussed
in the paper.
But there is also an older concept of social capital, developed by Pierre
Bourdieu in the 1970s and early 1980s. Bourdieu’s concept is connected with his
theoretical ideas on class. He identifies three dimensions of capital each with its own
relationship to class: economic, cultural and social capital. These three resources
become socially effective, and their ownership is legitimized through the mediation
of symbolic capital (see p. 13). Bourdieu’s concept of social capital puts the emphasis
on conflicts and the power function (social relations that increase the ability of an
actor to advance her/his interests). Social positions and the division of economic,
cultural and social resources in general are legitimized with the help of symbolic
capital. From the Bourdieuan perspective, social capital becomes a resource in the
social struggles that are carried out in different social arenas or fields. For example,
the problem of trust (which Bourdieu does not discuss much explicitly) can now be
dealt with as a part of the symbolic struggle (or the absence of struggles) in society.
Trust as a potential component of symbolic capital can be exploited in the practice of
symbolic power and symbolic exchange.
The paper starts with an examination of the three components of Putnam's
concept of social capital (norms and obligations, trust and social, networks,
especially voluntary associations) followed by a discussion of their inherent
theoretical problems. In the second part of the paper the three components of
Putnam's social capital are looked at from a Bourdieuan perspective. The structure
of the paper is based on Putnam's concept, and its critical tone on Bourdieu's
sociology of struggle.

Putnam's concept of social capital

At the beginning of his "Making Democracy work" Putnam says that in drawing his
conclusions about Italy's governmental reforms during the last few decades, his
purposes are theoretical and his method empirical (1993, 3). In this paper I will
concentrate on his theoretical conclusions, especially about civil society. The main
question of Putnam's Italian study is: what are the preconditions for the
development of strong, responsive representative institutions and a prosperous
economy? The governmental reform of 1976-77 in Italy, responsible for establishing
new bodies of local government, offers a good opportunity to provide an answer to
this question. The main result of Putnam's study is that governmental reform
succeeded well in Northern Italy because it was supported by a florescence of "civic
community". This was also the main reason for the economic prosperity of Northern
Italy in comparison with the Southern part of the country. In areas with a well-
functioning local government and a prosperous economy, the public activity of
citizens has created an atmosphere of mutual co-operation, vital social networks,
equal political relations and the tradition of citizen participation. Behind all of these
phenomena radiates the ethos of mutual trust between citizens (Putnam 1993, 6-7).
The activity of a civic community, a major factor behind economic and go-
vernmental effectiveness, is measured in Putnam's study in terms of voting activity,
the reading of newspapers, and participation in sports clubs and voluntary cultural
associations. The result of regional comparison is as follows:

"In the North the crucial social, political, and even religious allegiances and alignments were ho-
rizontal, while those in the South were vertical. Collaboration, mutual assistance, civic obligation, and
even trust - not universal, or course, but extending further beyond the limits of kinship than
anywhere else in Europe in this era - were the distinguishing features in the North. The chief virtue in
the South, by contrast, was the imposition of hierarchy and order on latent anarchy" (op.cit. 130).

These differences between horizontal and vertical patterns of organizing


social allegiances and alignments had fatal consequences for the development of
political actors. "In the North people were citizens, in the South they were subjects"
(op.cit. 121). The quality of the civil society "predestined" to a large extent the future
economic and political development of the region. Putnam calls this historical
ballast (or treasure) "path dependence": "where you can get to depends on where
you are coming from, and some destinations you simply cannot get to from here"
(op. cit. 179). The concept of social capital expresses the sociological essence of
communal vitality. A solution to the problem of common action and opportunism
presupposes the development of voluntary collective action, and it is connected to
the inherited social capital in the community. Forms of social capital are general
moral resources of the community, and they can be divided into three main
components: first, trust (and more generally 'positive' values with respect to
development); second, social norms and obligations; and third, social networks of
citizens' activity, especially voluntary associations. Here I am mainly going to deal
with the problems of trust and voluntary associations. I will discuss moral
obligations only these are related to trust and associations.

Trust

When we speak about trust in modern societies we speak about "generalized trust".
Individual actors do something for the general good not because they know other
interactors but because they trust that their own action will be "rewarded" via the
positive development of communal relations (see Newton 1999, 8-). In the modern
world we will need trust when we leave the sphere based on familiarity and enter a
world dominated by contingency, complexity and risk (see Luhmann 1988; 1991).
Trust is needed when role expectations and familiar relationships no longer help us
to anticipate the reactions of our individual or collective interaction partners. In
situations of this kind, people gather the harvest whose seeds have been sown in the
micro interactions of the past (see Seligman 1997). Choices in micro-level
interactions produce, first, mutual reciprocity and trust; and second, as a non-
intended consequence of these choices, trust on a higher (macro) level, and thereby
integrative values (or their absence) (cf. Coleman 1988). This is the basis of social
consensus. As Seligman puts it:

"The emphasis in modern societies on consensus (italics/MS).... (is) based on interconnected networks
of trust - among citizens, families, voluntary organizations, religious denominations, civic
associations, and the like. Similarly the very "legitimation" of modern societies is founded on the
"trust" of authority and governments as generalizations“ (1997, 14)

Well-functioning modern societies have to have a value basis that is based


on the voluntary regulation of social relations between persons who are foreigners
to each other. Generalized trust creates the basis for "brave reciprocity", and social
networks and associations that are not means for realizing the short-term interests
of any specific groups. These two factors in turn create trust. The circle is ready:
trust creates reciprocity and voluntary associations, reciprocity and associations
strengthen and produce trust (see Putnam 1993, 163-185). The more social capital is
used, the more it grows (Coleman 1988). The forms of social capital are self-
reinforcing and cumulative by nature. Vicious circles are expressed in society as
distrust, breaking of the norms of reciprocity, avoiding one's duties, isolation,
disorder and stagnation. The result is the development of a 'non-civic community'.
Virtuous (or rosy, see Govier 1997) circles, on the other hand, result in social
equilibrium manifesting itself in a high level of co-operation, expanding trust,
strong reciprocity, civic activity and collective well-being (Putnam 1993. 177).
One of Putnam's problems is the explanation of the origin of social trust.
Modern (or premodern) “thick trust“ develops in personal relations (see Newton
1999, 18-20). Social trust in complex, postindustrial (or postmodern) societies comes
from two related sources: norms of reciprocity and networks of civic engagement
(Putnam 1993, 171). However, in practice norms of reciprocity are functions of
networks of reciprocity. Among these networks voluntary associations are superior
in importance. In practice Putnam's civil society is reduced to the examination of the
functions of voluntary associations. In this way voluntary associations are dealt with
as the sole source of trust (see Cohen 1999, 217). In Jean Cohen's words:

"Once the state is defined and dismissed as a third-party enforcer, once law is turned into sanctions
that provide for a certain level of social order but no more, once institutions are dismissed as irrele-
vant to social trust, and once a vital civil society is reduced to the presence or absence of intermediate
voluntary associations, no other source is conceivable" (Cohen 1999, 219).

It has to be remembered too that Putnam's voluntary associations in


"Making Democracy Work" consist mainly of sports clubs and cultural associations,
which have positive functions concerning the development of social integration and
consensus. Putnam is not able to deal with distrust, and those social movements and
voluntary associations that present challenges to the prevailing consensus or to
integrative institutions. In Putnam's theoretical framework, distrust is mostly
connected to "pathological" forms of collective action, like the new social
movements or organizations that are seen to advance narrow group interests (see
Putnam 1993; Mouritsen 1997, 36).

Voluntary associations as sources of trust

Putnam's concept of voluntary association connects his ideas to one of the currents
within the American theory of pluralism. Voluntary association is the most
important form of horizontal interaction and reciprocity. Voluntary associations
influence social interaction and co-operation between actors in several ways (see
Putnam 1993, 173-174). Associations first "increase the potential costs to a defector in
any individual transaction“; second, "foster robust norms of reciprocity"; and third,
“facilitate communication and improve the flow of information about the
trustworthiness of individuals". They "allow reputations to be transmitted and
refined"; and, finally, they "embody past success at collaboration, which can serve as
a culturally-defined template for future collaboration".
Putnam is not alone in stressing the importance of voluntary associations in
the formation and development of modern society. On the contrary, one can make
the generalization that voluntary associations and modern democratic nations were
born as dialectical twins in such a way that "you can't find one without the other"
(e.g. Tenbruch & Ruoff 1983; Richter 1985; Siisiäinen 1986). Following in Luhmann's
footsteps, voluntary associations can be regarded as socially organized groups
based on mutual trust between the members. It is trust that helps to build and holds
together the relations between the members. As a rational form of solving
administrative problems and reducing the complexity of the environment (Umwelt)
voluntary association is also a central embodiment of confidence (see Richter 1985;
Siisiäinen 1998). Putnam's central problem, however, is that in practice he reduces
the concept of civil society to voluntary associations of a specific type (sports clubs,
cultural associations).
Putnam's ideas about the relationship between voluntary associations
continue the long line of studies from de Tocqueville's "Democracy in America" to
Bentley (1908) and Truman (1951). In this tradition social interests were identified
with organized interests in the form of voluntary associations (visible interests).
These were taken as the base for examining the relationship between civil society
and the state. A plurality of crosscutting voluntary associations was understood as
the main precondition for a stable democracy. Conflicting interests and the problem
of non-organized interests were not included in the approach. However, in this
tradition (with some exceptions) voluntary associations were tied by definition to
the interests of association members (e.g. Bentley 1908; c.f. Weber 1911).
It is typical of Putnam that he does not discuss conflicts between interests
(new social movements, parties). This holds true for three kinds of conflicts. First,
there are conflicts between those associations that are functional in creating and
supporting social consensus, and those associations and movements that are critical
of the dominant political values (and of the values represented by the sports clubs
and cultural associations studied by Putnam) (conflicts between different parts of
civil society). A theory about conflicting interests presupposes different types of
trust (and distrust) and different types of association. Some of these associations
create trust only among their own members, and distrust of other (hegemonic)
organizations. A large part of the groups and informal associations of civil society
cannot be discerned by the Putnamian vision. His vision - following in the footsteps
of de Tocqueville - is too Euro-American centered to be able to see youth
subcultures or subcultural public spheres. A vision - or theoretical “glasses“ -
inherited from the 19th century perceives only homological organizational forms
inherited from the same century, no more. This limited vision also prevents Putnam
from seeing the role of the mass media and of alternative forms of communication
(see Shapiro 1997).
Second, Putnam is nothing to say about conflicts between civil society and
the political society (and the state). Or, to put it in another way, Putnam does not
deal with politics. Because he is not dealing with conflicts or new challenges
presented to the political system, his theory can be seen as a kind of wish to escape
politics in the de Tocquevillean tradition (see Shapiro 1997; Mouritsen 1997; Cohen
1999; Warren 1999). This means that the Putnamian “theory“ can be characterized
as continuing the tradition of American "pacific functionalism" of the 1960s; focusing
on the integrative functions of voluntary associations (see Mouritsen op. cit.).
However, as Putnam only mentions in passing, civil society is (also) the seedbed of
social conflicts and conflicting individual and collective actors.
Third, Putnam neglects the vertical dimension of voluntary associations and
the power relations that are inherent in all modern associations (at least as a po-
tential tendency). As Max Weber has remarked, voluntary associations are relations
of domination (Herrschaftsverhälnisse) in two respects: first, within the association
(domination exercised by the leadership upon rank-and-file members), and second,
in relation to the outside world (by the organization towards the outsiders) (Weber
1911).
Putnam has little to say about the problems of internal democracy in
existing voluntary associations, and their internal power structures. As we know,
from Rousseau to present-day discussions of (and in) new social movements,
problems of oligarchy (Michels) and bureaucratization (Weber) are still among the
most serious obstacles to the development of democratic voluntary organizations
and civil society.
Voluntary associations also play a central role in the selection of those issues
and interests that are allowed to enter the political arena. This problem was also
studied by another, critical current within the American pluralist "school":

"The democratic society is able to survive because it manages conflict by establishing priorities
among a multitude of potential conflicts ... He who determines what politics is about runs the
country, because the definition of the alternatives is the choice of conflicts and the choice of conflicts
allocates power... All forms of political organization have a bias in favor of the exploitation of some
kinds of conflicts and the depression of others, because organization is the mobilization of bias. Some
conflicts are organized into politics while others are organized out" (Schattschneider 1960, 66, 68, 71).

This selectivity of the political system tends to increase the supremacy of


upper strata in the system of voluntary associations and their over-representation in
the leadership of associations. Therefore the picture that the prevailing totality of
voluntary associations gives of the variety of existing interests in society is biased. In
Shattschneider's words: "the flaw in the pluralist heaven is that the heavenly chorus
sings with a strong upper class accent" (Schattschneider 1960, 35).

Voluntary associations and social integration

The US-centredness of Putnam's analysis accentuates the narrowness of his


approach in understanding the production of "consensus" on the level of society.
This can be concretized by discussing the development of the Nordic welfare state(s)
as a compromise between different and conflicting interests (or as a hegemonic
project). Comparative studies on trust show that the citizens of the Nordic countries
belong to the most "trusting" in the world in the Putnamian sense of the word (see
Inglehart 1997; 1999). My argument is that this is connected to the development of
the Nordic welfare state’s function in guaranteeing (in principle at least, and even
though imperfectly) a minimum level of living. This means that political and social
welfare institutions increase the capacity of citizens to anticipate the future (and
thus, most probably, the level of their confidence). Citizens of the Nordic countries
also occupy top positions in international comparison of the number of the
memberships in voluntary associations and the number of acting voluntary
associations (see Siisiäinen 1999). The Nordic countries are also among those
countries in which no general decline of social capital has taken place (as, according
to Putnam (and many others) is the case in the USA (Putnam 1995; Siisiäinen 1995;
1999). Besides the Nordic countries, volunteerism and voluntary associations are
doing well in many other European countries as well (for example in Holland) (see
Van Dept et. al. 1999).
The development of the Nordic welfare state can be understood as a kind of
hegemonic project, or a neo-corporatist compromise between different interest
organizations, social movements and institutions of the state (for a discussion of
these concepts, see Jessop 1983; Siisiäinen 1987). The neo-corporatist practices that
led to the Nordic welfare state are no doubt far from the 'ideal speech situation'
(Habermas) or deliberative democracy. However, it can be said that it is one of the
most successful moves in that direction in societies based on social inequalities.
Most probably the Nordic countries also get the highest points in a Putnamian scale
measuring the amount of positive social capital (cf. Inglehart 1999)1.

1 There are, of course, differences between the Nordic countries, which, however, are not dealt with in this paper.
So far this information about the Nordic countries could be interpreted as
supporting Putnam’s ideas of the relationship between the activity of voluntary
associations, and societal consensus based on value compromises. But the problem
with respect to Putnam is that these Nordic structures of consensus and "trust" are
very often the results of "struggles" between conflicting interests. In Putnam's
analysis only those associations are examined which are able to rise above social
conflicts. The example of the Nordic countries points to the conclusion that
particularly those associations that are critical and in opposition to the prevailing
value consensus are the most important in the creation of trust on the societal level
and developing a hegemonic system based on leadership in the civil society (see
Siisiäinen 1986).
For example, in Finland institutions of the welfare state have sometimes
originated as critical social movements, which presented the political system with
demands. They were often objected - at least in the beginning - by the economic and
political elites. Many of these movements were critical not only of details but also of
the whole political system. In the course of time these protest movements have
resulted in the establishment of registered associations that were able to take part in
the (neo-corporatist) negotiations between the various parties to the conflict and the
state. All major movements have become integrated into the political system in this
way (see Siisiäinen 1994). A severe problem with Putnam's theory is that it excludes
conflicts and conflicting associations from its conceptual apparatus and from the list
of preconditions of consensus (c.f. Warren 1999); and thus ignores a central element
that has to be dealt with if we want to understand the birth of a trusting society
based on compromises of interest.
All this said, it is now time to turn to the conflict and power side of social ca-
pital as represented by Bourdieu. To some extent Bourdieu's theorization tries to
answer those questions that Putnam leaves untouched (although Bourdieu – as far
as I know – has never entered into a debate with the Putnamians at all): the
relationship between social capital and power, symbolic power and universal values
(trust?), and the preconditions for social consensus.

Bourdieu's social and symbolic capital

Jeffrey Alexander has drawn attention to the affinities between the modernization
theories of the 1950s and 1990s theories of the neo-modern. Many of de
Tocqueville's themes that were revitalized in the pluralist theorization of the 1950s
have reappeared in American sociological and politological discourses (see
Alexander 1994; 1995). In a way certain of Putnam's ideas similarly reproduce ideas
of the functionalist and pluralist theorizations of the 1950s. One example of these
similarities is the differentiation between the modern, rational form of voluntary
associations and the premodern form of familiar groups (voluntary associations ba-
sed on trust vs. amoral familism based on blood-ties and serving the interests of
specific groups). For example, Seligman identifies different forms of
fundamentalism as "binary opposites" to associations based on trust (Seligman 1997;
1999).
If Putnam can be seen as carrying on theories of pluralism and func-
tionalism, it is more difficult to characterize Bourdieu in the same terms since he
consistently opposes the use of labels of this kind (see e.g. Bourdieu 1991; Bourdieu
& Wacquant 1995). However, if we accept Loïc Wacquant's characterization of
Bourdieu's whole production "as a materialist anthropology of the specific contribu-
tion that various forms of symbolic violence make to the reproduction of structures
of domination", we can at least say that the theoretical roots of Bourdieu's con-
ception should be searched rather in the sociology of conflict and structuralist
tradition than in the sociology of integration and functionalism. Putnam's idea of
social capital deals with collective values and societal integration, whereas
Bourdieu's approach is made from the point of view of actors engaged in struggle in
pursuit of their interests.
This is how Bourdieu ties together - even though not without problems - the
most central of his concepts, habitus and conflict:

"I developed the concept of 'habitus' to incorporate the objective structures of society and the sub-
jective role of agents within it. The habitus is a set of dispositions, reflexes and forms of behavior
people acquire through acting in society. It reflects the different positions people have in society, for
example, whether they are brought up in a middle-class environment or in a working-class suburb. It
is part of how society produces itself. But there is also change. Conflict is built into society. People can
find that their expectations and ways of living are suddenly out of step with the new social position
they find themselves in... Then the question of social agency and political intervention becomes very
important" (Bourdieu 2000, 19).

Bourdieu's formulations leave plenty of room for different interpretations: at


one extreme he has been presented as representing a reductionist idea of the actor.
On the other hand, he has been seen as a proponent of a constructivist idea of actors
making their own choices and their own history, even though they are not totally
free and do not employ the categories of thought of their own choice.
In the following pages I will try to show how the points of departure
expressed in the citation manifest themselves in Bourdieu's concept of social and
symbolic capital, and in the way he deals with the problem of symbolic power and
universal (or general) values; and especially with the problem of disinterested
action.
Fields and forms of capital

One of the theoretical cornerstones of Bourdieu's sociology is the idea of society as a


plurality of social fields. Forms of capital (economic, cultural and social) are the core
factors defining positions and possibilities of the various actors in any field. Each
social field has a profile of its own, depending on the proportionate importance
within it of each of the forms of capital. The forms of capital controlled by the
various agents are trumps that define the chances of winning the stakes in the game.

"The field of power is a field of forces defined by the structure of the existing balance of forces between
forms of power, or between different species of capital. It is also simultaneously a field of struggles for
power among the holders of different forms of power. It is a space of play and competition in which social
agents and institutions which all posses the determinate quantity of specific capital (economic and
cultural capital in particular) sufficient to occupy the dominant positions within their respective fields
[the economic field, the field of higher civil service or the state, the university field, and the
intellectual field] confront one another in strategies aimed at preserving or transforming this balance
of forces... This struggle for the imposition of the dominant principle leads, at every moment, to a
balance in the sharing of power, that is, to what I call a division of the work of domination. It is also a
struggle over the legitimate principle of legitimation and the legitimate mode of reproduction"
(Bourdieu & Wacquant 1996, 76)

The main components of social resources whose control defines the social
position of actors are economic, cultural and social capital (see Bourdieu 1986).
Economic capital consists of capital in Marx's sense of the word, but also of other
economic possessions that increase an actor's capacities in society. Cultural capital
has three forms of existence. It exists, first, as incorporated in the habitus; and is to a
large extent created through primary pedagogy, that is, in (early) childhood.
Second, cultural capital is objectivized in cultural articles. Third, it also exists
institutionalized in cultural institutions and is expressed in terms of certificates,
diplomas and examinations (see Bourdieu 1977; 1979; Bourdieu & Passeron 1977).

Finally social capital is

"l'ensemble des ressources actuelles ou potentielles qui sont liées à la possession d'un réseau durable
de relations plus ou moins institutionnalisées d'interconnaissance et d'interreconnaissance; ou, en
d'autres termes, à l'appartenance à un groupe, comme ensemble d'agents qui ne sont pas seulement
dotés de propriétés communes ... mais sont aussi unis par des liaisons permanentes et utiles (Bourdieu
1980, 2).

Social capital thus has two components: it is, first, a resource that is con-
nected with group membership and social networks. "The volume of social capital
possessed by a given agent ... depends on the size of the network of connections that
he can effectively mobilize" (Bourdieu 1986, 249). It is a quality produced by the
totality of the relationships between actors, rather than merely a common "quality"
of the group (Bourdieu 1980, 2). Membership in groups, and involvement in the
social networks developing within these and in the social relations arising from the
membership can be utilized in efforts to improve the social position of the actors in a
variety of different fields. Voluntary associations, trade unions, political parties,
secret societies (cf. the freemasons) are modern examples of embodiments of social
capital. Differences in the control of social capital may explain why the same
amount of economic and cultural capital can yield different degrees of profit, and
different powers of influence to different actors. Group memberships creating social
capital have a "multiplication effect" on the influence of other forms of capital (see
Bourdieu 1986; Joppke 1987; cf. Coleman 1988).
Voluntary associations as social capital can be understood as resources
produced by the association as a collective and shared by its members. In this way,
social capital for Bourdieu is a collective phenomenon, even though it is viewed
from the perspective of actors who are exploiting its potentialities. Bureaucratic
organization is an effective administrative tool in concentrating social capital and
transforming quantity (number of members) to quality (organizational
effectiveness). The formation of an association can create a sense of solidarity among
a mass of persons, it gives a "name", institutionalizes the capital that is being
accumulated. The economic, social and symbolic "profit" that follows from
belonging to the association establishes a concrete base for the growth of solidarity.
From this perspective, the formation of a voluntary association can (also) be seen as
collective and individual strategies of investment aimed at the creation of
permanent networks of relations that will make possible the accumulation of social
capital (Bourdieu 1986). This social capital accumulated in voluntary associations
can be delegated, and thus represented by the leadership of the association; and
some part of it even spreads out to rank-and-file members (see Bourdieu 1980, 3;
1986, 251). The development of social networks is dependent both on individual
subjective feeling (recognition, respect, and communality) and on the institutional
guarantees afforded by the organization.
The second characteristic of social capital is that it is based on mutual
cognition and recognition (see Bourdieu (1980; 1986; 1998a). This is how it acquires a
symbolic character, and is transformed into symbolic capital (1986). In order to
become effective, social capital, "objective" differences between groups or classes
have to be transformed into symbolic differences and classifications that make
possible symbolic recognition and distinction. Social classes implicated by the
distribution of economic, cultural and social capital are only "classes on paper", that
is, only potentialities, unless they are transformed into meaningful differences,
mediated by symbolic capital (see Bourdieu 1985). "Symbolic capital ... is nothing
other than capital, in whatever form, when perceived by an agent endowed with
categories of perception arising from the internalization (embodiment) of the
structure of its distribution, i.e. when it is known and recognized as self-evident"
(Bourdieu 1985, 204). As symbolic capital, distinctions are "the product of the
internalization of the structures to which they are applied" (op.cit. 204).
Bourdieu draws a parallel between the concept of symbolic capital and legitimate
capital; because it is symbolic capital that defines what forms and uses of capital are
recognized as legitimate bases of social positions in a given society. The effec-
tiveness of symbolic capital depends on real practices of communication. In that
respect symbolic capital cannot be institutionalized, objectified or incorporated into
the habitus. It exists and grows only in intersubjective reflection and can be
recognized only there. Economic and cultural capital have their own modes of
existence (money, shares; examinations and diplomas); whereas symbolic capital
exist only in the "eyes of the others". It inevitably assumes an ideological function: it
gives the legitimized forms of distinction and classification a taken-for-granted
character, and thus conceals the arbitrary way in which the forms of capital are
distributed among individuals in society (see Bourdieu 1986; 1987; 1998a; Joppke
1987, 60).

Symbolic power and "trust" or "capital of recognition"

Trust is not a concept in Bourdieu's sociological vocabulary. Therefore I do not claim


that the following represents Bourdieu's authentic views on trust. I am instead
trying to locate Putnam's concept of trust within Bourdieu's theoretical co-ordinates,
in order to see what it might look like from his point of view. Bourdieu comes clo-
sest to the Putnamian concept of trust when he speaks of the "capital of recognition";
the "universal" as the "object of universal recognition"; the "sacrifice of selfish
(especially economic) interests that is recognized as legitimate and of "universal
values" (virtue); and of all of these as potential euphemisms in the symbolic uses of
power (see Bourdieu 1998a; 1998b; Bourdieu & Wacquant 1996). Ideas about "brave
reciprocity" and "generalized reciprocity" can be contrasted with Bourdieu's ideas
about the (im)possibility of disinterested action, participation in games (the concept
of interest and illusion) and the exchange of gifts.
With a slight exaggeration of the differences between Putnam's and
Bourdieu's ideas we can formulate a Bourdieuan concept of trust: trust can be
understood as a universalized value (virtue) posited as the basis of voluntary, di-
sinterested action and exchange (or interaction). However, in the last analysis, the
universal character of trust can be questioned and - as a rule - revealed as a
euphemism concealing the hidden, but underlying specific interests of the powerful.
As stated above, Bourdieu's idea is that economic, cultural, and social capital
becomes meaningful and socially effective only through the process of symbolic
translation. That is why symbolic power, the power to make different entities exist
by symbolic categorizing becomes decisively important within the total system of
power. Knowledge of the social world becomes the object of political and ideo-
logical struggles. Influencing the categories and distinctions through which the
world is perceived becomes a major way in changing (or conserving) the social
world. It is by seeing things in the legitimate way that the implicit can be made
explicit, and potential groups transformed into actual groups (Bourdieu 1985, 202-
203).
The use of symbolic power is successful when prevailing "objective"
structures are perceived by actors with the help of categories that are the products
the same objective structures. This would result in the most absolute recognition of
legitimacy; because everyday life is apprehended as self-evident (the quasi-perfect
coincidence of objective and embodied structures) (1985, 204). "Symbolic violence...
is the violence which is exercised upon a social agent with his or her complicity... I call
misrecognition the fact of recognizing a violence which is wielded precisely inasmuch
as one does not perceive it as such" (Bourdieu & Wacquant 1996, 167-168).
The roots or sources of symbolic capital can be almost anywhere, its central
criterion is that actors perceive and recognize its existence. In Bourdieu's conception
of symbolic power it is important to pay attention to those authorities in whose
hands the symbolic capital is concentrated. In modern western democracies the state
is the field in which struggles for the monopoly of legitimate symbolic power are (or
were?) fought. The modern state has been a kind of super-agent that combines the
struggles over legitimate power taking place in different fields. The modern state
holds not only the monopoly of physical violence but also, above all, the "monopoly
of legitimate symbolic violence, i.e., the power to constitute and to impose as universally
applicable within a given "nation".... a common set of coercive norms" (Bourdieu &
Wacquant 1996, 112). This stresses the importance of school and other institutions of
socialization in the system of symbolic power.
Symbolic power or violence is also involved in the politics of universal
values.

"Illusio is in the fact of being interested in the game, of taking the game seriously. Illusio is the fact of
being caught up in and by the game, of believing the game is "worth the candle," or, more simply,
that playing is worth the effort. In fact, the word interest initially meant very precisely what I include
under the notion of illusio, that is, the fact of attributing importance to a social game, the fact that
what happens matters to those who are engaged in it, who are in the game. Interest is to "be there", to
participate, to admit that the game is worth playing and that the stakes created in and through the
fact of playing are worth pursuing; it is to recognize the game and to recognize its stakes... (I)llusio is
the enchanted relation to a game that is the product of a relation of ontological complicity between
mental structures and the objective structures of social space. That is what I meant in speaking about
interests: games which matter to you are important and interesting because they have been imposed
and introduced in your mind, in your body, in a form called the feel for the game (Bourdieu 1998a,
76-77).
The notion of interest is opposed to that of disinterestedness, but also to that of indifference.
One can be interested in a game (in the sense of not indifferent), while at the same time being
disinterested. The disinterested person "does not see why they are playing," it's all the same to
them.." (1998a, 76-77).

In discussing the problem of whether interests and universal values/trust


are compatible in society, Bourdieu and Putnam share some formal and seemingly
similar ideas. One of them - Putnam - seems to think that trust and interest conflict;
the other - Bourdieu - that interest and universal values (virtue, capital of
recognition) exclude each other. Putnam refuses to deal with interests or interest
organizations (as representatives of amoral familism), Bourdieu doubts the
possibility of disinterestedness and thus of generalized trust as a general value. In
Putnam's approach interest organizations are left out of the study, but neither does
he discuss the problems of those groups who do not have any associations of their
own (for example, groups with too weak resources to found an association).
Bourdieu's theoretical concepts make it possible to discuss the problem of how
actors who do not have any interest at all in taking part in the games of modern
democracy as expressed, for example, in people’s decreasing participation in
elections in many democracies (e.g. political apathy or conscious renunciation).
Bourdieu stresses the importance of historical and empirical examination of
the problem of universal values and universal truth. All too often, he argues, it
appears up that "in a certain field at a certain moment, the logic of the game is such
that certain agents have an interest in the universal" (1991, 33). So, even behind uni-
versal values lurk the specific interests of certain groups. It is also quite often the
case that different groups and classes take part in the game (or actually in several
games played at the same time in the same field) but are actually playing (or
imagine themselves to be playing) different games. Weber notices this when he
speaks of the differences between upper-class and folk religions (see Weber 1976).
Same kinds of difference can be discerned in the voluntary sector, or in the struggles
over the future content of the so-called third sector. In these struggles, members of
social movements and voluntary associations may have moral 'interests' in the
game, whereas economic elites may be guided by 'rational' economic interests,
counting the costs and benefits; and may appeal to universal values and use
euphemisms to veil their basic interests.
Great moments for the system of symbolic power come as the lower classes
accept euphemistic value banners suggested by social elites. This is what happens
all the time in the name of globalization, if we are to believe Bourdieu (Bourdieu
1998b).
What about the great ideas of American pluralism and of the American
political system, namely those of volunteering and voluntary action? How do they
relate to Bourdieu's conception of universal values and the (im)possibility of
disinterested action? What could Bourdieu's position be like on the problem of
"brave reciprocity" rising from social interaction or exchange?
Bourdieu tries to overcome the juxtaposition of 'structuralism' and
'phenomenologism' (see Bourdieu & Wacquant 1996) or "economism" and
“semiologism" (see Bourdieu 1980b) and solve dialectically the problem of the
relationship between structural conditioning and actors' freedom of choice.
Bourdieu's own solution is embodied in the concept of habitus. Bourdieu
characterizes his own approach as genetic structuralism (Bourdieu 1991, 14).
According to Bourdieu, the habitus develops through the internalization of the
objective structures of the environment in the form of practices. Habitus forms a
durable generative principle that guides the actor in his/her new choices between
alternatives that are present in a certain conjuncture. Thus the habitus

"produces practices that tend to reproduce the regularities immanent in the objective conditions of
the production of their generative principle, while adjusting to the demands inscribed as objective
potentialities in the situation, as defined by the cognitive and motivating structures making up the
habitus" (1977, 78).

Practices are the result of the co-influence of "objective structures" as ma-


nifested in the forms of prevailing alternatives at a certain moment in history, and
the "subjective structures" inside the habitus, manifested as dispositions directing
the choices of the actor toward alternatives that are homological with the structures
that have produced the habitus (causalité du probable) (Bourdieu 1977; 1974).
Bourdieu stresses that the habitus cannot be reduced to structures because it is born
as practices. It is creative and thus the reproduction of social structures is never one-
to-one reproduction but extended and creative reproduction directed by the habitus
(Bourdieu 1977). Bourdieu does not deny the existence of "objective" structures and
their influence on the formation of habitus;, which, for its part, becomes the
structuring structure leading via practices to the development of new structures. It
is easy to see the influence of Bourdieu's concept of habitus on Giddens' concept of
the duality of structure (see Giddens 1985).
It is possible to accept Bourdieu's repeated protestations that he is not a
structuralist. But it is also possible to make the opposite interpretation - with a little
help from some bad will - and define Bourdieu as the prototype of a structuralist or
reductionist (e.g., Alexander 1995, 128-202). It is easy to find citations from Bourdieu
that echo structuralist tones. The strong emphasis placed by Bourdieu on the im-
portance of symbolic power and the difficulties of autonomous, genuine voluntary
action make it easy to accuse Bourdieu of reductionism:

"Symbolic power relations tend to reproduce and to reinforce the power relations which constitute
the structure of the social space. More concretely, the legitimation of the social order ... results from
the fact that agents apply to the objective structures of the social world structures of perception and
appreciation that have emerged from these objective structures and tend therefore to see the world as
self-evident" (Bourdieu 1991, sit. Alexander 1995, 141).

If we take this citation in isolation from the context of Bourdieu's total


production, we can accede to Alexander's accusation of reductionism. But it is also
possible to take Bourdieu's claims seriously: to accept that he is only defining the
conditions under which symbolic power is effective and successful in influencing
actors' practices. And it is also possible to take to heart Bourdieu's brief remarks on
the resistance of the dominated (e.g. Bourdieu & Passeron 1998, viii) and share
Bourdieu's optimism - that has been growing, especially in the 1990s - concerning
the possibility that actors, and actors' social movements will through knowledge
and subsequent action, change the world (see Bourdieu & Wacquant 1996; Bourdieu
2000). It is also easy - with the help of a certain amount of goodwill - to find
numerous of Bourdieu’s formulations specifying the preconditions for the success of
symbolic power in reproducing the dominant structures. Another thing is that
Bourdieu's theoretical conception does not give much help if we want to analyze the
processes of change caused by conflicting agents and movements. This is one of the
limits of his approach. However, it seems that Bourdieu is more and more interested
in the forces of change in his latest writings (cf. Bourdieu 1998b; 2000).
According to Bourdieu, habitus is not the fate of certain people, but "an open
system of dispositions that is constantly subjected to experiences, and therefore
constantly affected by them in a way that either reinforces or modifies its structures.
It is durable but not eternal!" (Bourdieu & Wacquant 1996, 133). But in any case, it is
something that preconditions the freedom - and voluntary character - of the actor’s
choices. And it is also something that we must take into account when we discuss
the relation of Bourdieu's theorizations to the problem of generalized trust and
altruism.
Further, Bourdieu's idea of society composed of different fields emphasizes
the non-reductionist character of his sociology. As fields, all spaces within society
are contested; and actors' positions within them have to be fought for continually.
This is why Bourdieu does not accept either Althusser's concept of ideological state
apparatuses or Luhmann's systems theory. Organizations (e.g.. voluntary
associations) must also be understood as fields with their own stakes to be struggled
for not as systemic structures (see Bourdieu & Wacquant 1996, 102-104).
We can at least say that Bourdieu is very skeptical with respect to altruistic
action that is (at the same time) free of any specific interest of the actor. This gives
his position a coloring that is almost dramatically opposed to Putnam's romantic
idea of generalized trust. Bourdieu tries to define the situation that makes
disinterestedness possible: "If the disinterestedness is sociologically possible, it can
be so only through the encounter between habitus predisposed to disinterestedness
and universes in which disinterestedness in rewarded" (Bourdieu 1998a, 88).
Volunteering is one of the fields dominated by the universal values of altruism and
disinterestedness. In a skeptical (or to some extent even cynical) spirit we can say
that private interests can be concealed as universal at least in two ways in the "non-
profit" or "voluntary sector". First, those who volunteer or are said to behave
altruistically can simply try to present the necessary as universal. Second, the
interests and calculations of the powerful (for example efforts to cut public spending
by demolishing welfare state services) can be presented under positive banners such
as flexibility, subsidiary principle, or communality. When individuals can rise above
their narrow interests and show that they have adopted the position of the
community, the community interprets this as a recognition of collective values. The
community will reward this kind of action by affording profit of universalization to
the actors in question (Bourdieu 1991, 88).
Bourdieu speaks about the triumph of the universal when such worlds are
favored which recognize - at least in words - universal values as virtue. Then why
not also trust? This is how Bourdieu sees the impact of universal values on
development (cf. Putnam's conception of trust): "The profit of universalization is
undoubtedly one of the historical engines of the progress of the universal. This is
because it favors the creation of universes where universal values (reason, virtue,
etc.) are at least verbally recognized and wherein operates a circular process of
mutual reinforcement of the strategies of universalization seeking to obtain the
profits (if only negative) associated with conformity to universal rules and to the
structures of those universes officially devoted to the universal" (Bourdieu 1998a,
60). The triumph of virtue carries forward the progress of the universal. It
presupposes the recognition of the universal, i.e. the primacy of the group and
general interests with respect to the individual actor. Putnam seems to believe that
the development of generalized trust means that actors really can rise above their
specific interests; whereas Bourdieu thinks that "universal values are particular,
universalized values, which are thus subject to suspicion (universal culture is the
culture of the dominants...)" (Bourdieu op.cit, 90). What values will become
universal values will decided in the struggles taking place in different fields of
society, that is, through social conflicts.
If we want to follow the lines that are implicit in Bourdieu's ideas about the
(im)possibility of disinterested action, we can, for example, have a look at the deve-
lopment of the third sector as a field of symbolic struggle (see Siisiäinen 2000). The
disinterested sacrifice of - mostly female - volunteers could serve as an example of
following the logic of universal values. This would accord with the notion of the
dominant structure of symbolic capital if the increase in volunteering in the third
sector were to prove to correlate with the reduction of the welfare services provided
by the state and - for example - with the lowering of the taxation of capital incomes.
This kind of system would also hide all traces of the pattern of gift exchange that
can be a component in many forms of volunteering. In a system of symbolic power,
gift exchange is covered by universalizing strategies denying the interestedness of
the parties to the exchange. The total structure of exchange gains autonomy from
conscious individual choices. Gift givers and receivers "collaborate, without
knowing it, in a work of dissimulation tending to deny the truth of exchange, the
exchange of exact equivalent, which represents the destruction of the exchange of
gifts" (1998a, 94). The task of sociology is to reveal this double sidedness of exchange
as a combination of objective and subjective truth. This is where sociology enters the
field of struggles - for example - over the third sector, and becomes a part of the
struggle over the principles of its construction (see Siisiäinen 2000).

Social problems as sociological problems in Putnam and Bourdieu

The differences between Putnam's and Bourdieu's theoretical approaches are clearly
revealed when they are adopted in dealing with concrete problems of society. I have
selected Putnam's widely-known article "Bowling alone: American Declining Social
Capital" (1995) and the collection of Bourdieu's writings "Acts of Resistance. Against
the New Myths of Our Time" (1998b) as my data to show the differences.
In both publications, current social problems are examined in a critical way
(e.g. family violence, alienation caused by unemployment and the breaking down of
communities, drugs). Putnam is worried - most of all - about the decline of the heart
of American civil society, the social capital. Voting activity is going down, distrust
of the government has risen in 20 years from 30 to 75% (in 1992). With minor
exceptions, membership figures in traditional American voluntary associations (the
Red Cross, PTAs, the Lions etc.), in trade unions and religious associations have
fallen steadily. And that is not all. The bastions of social capital, the family and the
neighborhood, have been through hard times: neither the nuclear nor the extended
family is any longer a stronghold of mutual togetherness, and social intercourse
between neighbors (e.g. visits) has declined. Therefore it is no wonder that the
proportion of Americans trusting their fellow-citizens decreased from 58 % in 1960
to 37 % in 1993. As civic activity and trust go hand in hand, Putnam concludes that
American social capital has been declining for the last 30 years on a wide front.
Putnam identifies four factors behind the decline of social capital in the
USA. First, the increasing presence of women in the labor force has lessened the
time that is available for building social capital in families, and the resources that
this needs. The second factor destroying social capital is social mobility and the
rootlessness that follows it (cf. Coleman 1988). The third factor is caused by
demographic changes (increase in divorces, decrease in the average number of
children per family, decline of real incomes). Especially fatal for the maintenance of
social capital is the worsening of the preconditions of middle- class parenthood;
because the middle class has traditionally been responsible for the accumulation of
social capital in America. Finally, Putnam blames the technological changes that are
responsible for the privatization or individualization of leisure. The main obstacle
for the construction of social capital during free time is, however, television and its
supremacy in the competition over the uses of leisure (Putnam 1995, 74-75).
Putnam also lists measures for improving the preconditions for the deve-
lopment of social capital. These include research, the examination of co-effects of
macro structures, and putting an end to developments, that were discussed above.
As to the development of the third, or voluntary sector, it is interesting to see how
Putnam understands the (real or possible) impact of the welfare state – or, in his
terms, of public policy - on the formation of social capital. According to Putnam, it is
well known that in some instances "public policy has destroyed highly effective
social networks and norms. American slum-clearance policy of the 1950s and 1960s,
for example, renovated physical capital, but at a very high cost to existing social
capital" (1995, 76-77)2. On the other hand improving the conditions of schools and
charity associations has had a positive effect on social-capital accumulation (op.cit
77).
This discussion, unfortunately, is left on a tentative level compared to the
theorizations in "Making Democracy Work". There are some ideas in "Bowling
alone" that are inconsistent with the ideas to be found in "Making Democracy work"
about the direction of causal relations between the economy, government and social
capital. Because the ideas in the book are more profoundly developed, they are the
basis for regarding Putnam as a romantic functionalist and pluralist.
Bourdieu's ideas as to the sources and causes of current social problems can
be reconstructed by reading his book "Acts of Resistance. Against the New Myths of

2 It is very easy to see the kinship between these ideas and those of many American communitarianists (see e.g.
Cohen 1999; Siisiäinen 2000).
Our Time" (1998b). In it Bourdieu wages his war against the negative consequences
of globalization - as he understands them - and its main ideology or grand narrative,
neo-liberalism. His goal is to analyze and dismantle the myth of neo-liberalism and
the euphemisms employed in its construction. Globalization means the birth of a
global economy proper, and this system manifests itself in the form of the alleged
necessities that different national economies and states are facing at present. Neo-
liberalism is the grand narrative of globalization. In public discourses globalization
is presented as a mythic inevitability forcing national economies and states to take
certain actions. The dominant discourse claims that there are no alternatives to the
prevailing development, which is why people take many presuppositions for
granted (maximum growth; rising productivity and competitiveness as the ultimate
goals of human actions; and the idea that economic forces cannot be resisted) (1998b,
30-31). This doxa appears in disguise of euphemisms such as flexibility (“souplesse“);
deregulation, corporate trust etc.
Bourdieu's position to the modern state is twofold: first, in his published
works throughout the period of 1970s, 1980s and 1990s he speaks of the state as a
fountain or super-agent of the symbolic violence that guarantees the system of
dominant symbolic power with the help of the monopoly of symbolic classification
and categorization; especially in the educational system (e.g. 1996; 1998a). On the
other hand, in "Acts of Resistance" he speaks of the ambiguous character of the state:
the European welfare state is also a guarantor of social the functions of welfare and
human rights such as education, health and social security (1998b, 33-34). The
European welfare state can thus also be understood as a kind of compromise, which
includes the historical achievements of social movements (e.g. welfare rights).
The myth of globalization is "the main weapon in the battles against the
gains of the welfare state.... And it is in the name of this model (pitting European
workers against the workers in the rest of the world/MS) that flexible working,
another magic word of neo-liberalism, is imposed, meaning night work, weekend
work, irregular working hours, things which have always been part of employers'
dreams" (1998b, 34). "Conservative revolutions" are dressed up in all the signs of
modernity, and present themselves as progressive developments in the name of
liberalism. Their consequences can be felt in different spheres of society (such as
increasing insecurity, a feeling of distress, lost jobs, suffering, sickness, suicide,
alcoholism, drug addiction, domestic violence etc.) (1998b, 36-39). These are all
problems that capture the attention of American communitarians and Putnamians
as well.
Bourdieu asks for a sociology that would be prepared to take part in a
critical venture to develop "economics of happiness" which - in contrast to narrow,
short-term economics, "would take note of all the profits, individual and collective,
material and symbolic, associated with activity (such as security), and also all the
material and symbolic costs associated with inactivity or precarious employment"
(op. cit. 40). After discussing the ambiguous character of the welfare state, Bourdieu
draws the following conclusion: "I think that the dominated groups in society have
an interest in defending the state, particularly its social aspect" (1998b, 41).
One of the euphemisms developed by social forces that would like to
demolish the welfare state is the concept of competence (and the ideology of
competence that has been constructed around the concept) which extends the ideas
of social neo-Darwinism. In Bourdieu's words, the "ideology of competence serves
very well to justify an opposition which is rather like that between masters and
slaves. On the one hand there are full citizens who have very rare and overpaid
capacities and activities ..... , and then, on the other side, there is a great mass of
people condemned to borderline jobs or unemployment" (1998b, 42-43).
Competence is in Bourdieu's view the heart of a "sociodicy" that provides justifica-
tion for the dominant groups' privileges, and which is accepted by the dominated.
The structure of inequality is given ethical and intellectual justification at the same
time with the help of the ideology of competence: "The poor are not just immoral,
alcoholic and degenerate, they are stupid, they lack intelligence" (1998b, 43). The
existence of an excluded and under-privileged group, with all the problems
consequent upon this, is thus indirectly legitimized.

Conclusion: Putnam or/and Bourdieu

Thus Bourdieu and Putnam van be seen to carry on, and develop further, the ideas
of two opposing sociological traditions and apply these ideas to current problems of
civil society. Putnam's work preserves many of the ideas of the sociology of integra-
tion. His concepts of social capital and trust are directed to questions about
mechanisms that strengthen the integration of the values of society, and solidarity
and togetherness; and that create consensus and sustain the stable development of
society (moving equilibrium). As already noted, it is difficult to deal with conflicts
or opposing interests using Putnam's approach.
Bourdieu's main theoretical interests are in the examination of social
conflicts or struggles about the stakes in different fields; forms of power/violence;
and forms of domination (Herrschaft) and deprivation. Trust - in the Putnamian
sense of the word - has no place in Bourdieu's theorization. In those areas where the
two approaches overlap (e.g.. social exchange, recognition/trust), the visual angles
adopted are almost oppositional.
These different points of departure create a kind of theoretical "path de-
pendence": "where you can get to depends on where you are coming from, and
some destinations you simply cannot get to from here" (Putnam 1993, 179). From the
Putnamian theoretical perspective, conflicts fall outside the process of consensus
and integration; social struggles are interpreted as expressions of amoral familism,
or of differences connected with the uneven exchange between regions (e.g.
Northern and Southern Italy) or between social groups. Many developers of the
American theory of pluralism also took into account specific interests, discussed the
problem of non-organized or "potential" interests, and saw "the flaw of the pluralist
heaven" (Schattschneider); whereas Putnam operates theoretically on the level of
societal consensus, deals mainly with organized interests (voluntary associations),
and selects his concepts from the corresponding points of view.
Bourdieu for his part excludes from his theory even the idea of 'genuine'
consensus and universal values whose central function is to maintain it in everyday
practices. Thus it is easy - in fact too easy - to say that because Bourdieu is not
talking about trust leading to consensus on the societal level, it is justified to ignore
his ideas in any theoretical discussion in which social capital is assumed to be based
on trust. This is exactly what many students of trust/social capital do. It happens all
too often that his ideas are rejected after receiving only a brief mention (cf. Newton
1999; Misztal 1996) or to ignore them totally (e.g. Seligman 1997; Govier 1997;
Putnam 1993). This underlines the narrow perspective of Putnam’s theories.
In the last analysis, the choice between Putnam and Bourdieu depends; first,
on what problems we are interested in and, second, on our position concerning the
dispute between the sociology of integration and the sociology of conflict. Trust and
voluntary associations create consensus and economic welfare in Putnam's approach
on the condition that the specific interests of certain groups and conflicts between
them are cancelled out. Bourdieu's sociological focus is on the conflictual fields,
including the inside working of voluntary associations, and on the structures of
power and violence that are produced and reproduced/destroyed by agents who
have an interest in the game that is played in the field in question.
However, it can be argued that it is possible to see Bourdieu's ideas about
the centrality of conflicts as part and parcel of creating a theory of the preconditions
(or impossibility) of social consensus or hegemony. But in this case, we need critical
theoretical tools to be able to analyze both the opportunity structures improving the
creation of consensus and the obstacles to the development of the "ideal speech
situation". The stability of a system which includes conflicts needs trust, because
"the best point to manage conflict is before it starts" (Schattschneider 1960, 15).
Universal values such as trust can only be understood as ideal types without real
equivalents. Bourdieu's concepts of the forms of capital and symbolic violence, on
the other hand, are needed for an analysis of the obstacles preventing the realization
of the ideal type of "ideal speech situation".

References

Alexander, Jeffrey: Fin de Siécle Social Theory. London: Verso 1995.


Alexander, Jeffrey: Modern, Anti, Post, and Neo: How Social theories Have Tried to
Understand the "New World" of "Our Time". Zeitschrift für Soziologie Jg. 23
(1994) 3, p. 165-197.
Bentley, A.F.: The Process of Government. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press
1908.
Bourdieu, Pierre: Acts of Resistance. Against the New Myths of Our Time. (Transl.
by Richard Nice). Cambridge: Polity 1998b.
Bourdieu, Pierre: Avenir de classe et causalité du probable. Revue Française de
Sociologie 15 (1974) 3, 3-42.
Bourdieu, Pierre: Choses Dites. Paris: Minuit 1987).
Bourdieu, Pierre: In Other Words: Essays Toward a Reflexive Sociology.
Cambridge: Polity 1991.
Bourdieu, Pierre: La distinction - critique sociale du jugement. Paris: Minuit 1979.
Bourdieu, Pierre: Le capital social. Actes de la Recherche en Sciences Sociales 31
(1980), 2-3
Bourdieu, Pierre: Le sens pratique. Paris: Minuit 1980b.
Bourdieu, Pierre: Outline of a Theory of Practice. New York: Cambridge University
Press 1977.
Bourdieu, Pierre: Practical Reason. On the Theory of Action. Cambridge: Polity
1998a.
Bourdieu, Pierre: The forms of capital. In: John G. Richardson (ed.): Handbook of
Theory and Research for the Sociology of Education. New York: Greenwood
Press 1986, s. 241-258.
Bourdieu, Pierre: The politics of protest. An interview by Kevin Ovenden. Socialist
Review Nr. 242 (2000), p.18-20.
Bourdieu, Pierre: The social space and the genesis of groups. Social Science
Information 24 (1985b) 2, 195-220.
Bourdieu, Pierre & Passeron, Jean-Claude: Academic order and social order. Preface
to the 1990 Edition. In: Bourdieu, Pierre & Passeron, Jean-Claude:
Reproduction in Education, Society and Culture. London: SAGE 1998, vii-xi.
Bourdieu, Pierre & Passeron, Jean-Claude: Reproduction in Education, Society and
Culture. London: SAGE 1977.
Bourdieu Pierre & Wacquant Loïc: An Invitation to reflexive sociology. Cambridge:
Polity 1996.
Cohen, Jean: Trust, voluntary associations and workable democracy: the
Coleman, James S.: Social capital in the creation of human capital. American Journal
of Sociology, vol. 94 (1988) Supplement, 95-120. contemporary American
discourse of civil society. In: Mark E. Warren (ed.): Democracy and Trust.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1999, 208-248.
Giddens, A.: Yhteiskuntateorian keskeisiä ongelmia. Helsinki: Otava 1985.
Govier, Trudy: Social trust and Human Communities. Montreal & Kingston:
McGill-Gueen's University Press 1997.
Inglehart, Ronald: Modernization and Postmodernization: Cultural, Economic, and
Political Change in 43 Societies. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
1997.
Inglehart, Ronald: Trust, well-being and democracy. In: Mark E. Warren (ed.):
Democracy and Trust. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1999, 88-120.
Jessop, Bob: Accumulation, state forms, and hegemonic project. Kapitalistate 10/11
(1983), 89-112.
Joppke, C.: The cultural dimensions of class formation and class struggle: on the
social theory of Pierre Bourdieu. Berkeley Journal of Sociology 21 (1987), p.
53-78.
Luhmann, Niklas: Familiarity, confidence, Trust: Problems and Alternatives. In:
Diego Gambetta (ed.): Trust: Making and Breaking Cooperative relations.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell 1988, 94-107.
Luhmann, Niklas: Soziologie des Risikos. Berlin: de Gruyter 1991.
Misztal, Barbara A.: Trust in Modern Societies. The Search for the Bases of Social
Order. Cambridge: Polity 1997.
Mouritsen, Per: What's the Civil in Civil Society? Robert Putnam's Republicanism
and Italy. Aarhus: Department of Political Science, Aarhus University 1999.
Newton, Kenneth: Social capital and democracy in modern Europe. In: Jan Van
Dept & Marco Maraffi & Kenneth Newton & Paul Whiteley (eds.): Social
Capital and European Democracy. London and New York: Routledge 1999
(p. 3-24)
Putnam, Robert D.: Bowling alone: America's declining social capital. Journal of
Democracy Vol. 6 (1995) 1, 64-78.
Putnam, Robert D.: Making democracy work. Civic traditions in modern Italy.
Princeton: Princeton University Press 1993
Richter, Rudolf: Soziokulturelle Dimensionen freiwilliger Vereinigungen. München:
Beiträge zur Kommunalwissenchaft 1985.
Schattschneider, E.E.: The Semi-sovereign People. New York: Holt, Rinehart &
Winston 1960.
Seligman, Adam: The problem of trust. Princeton: Princeton University Press 1997.
Seligman, Adam: Trust and Generalized Exchange. Paper presented at the Summer
School, University of Jyväskylä, 1999.
Shapiro, Michael J.: Bowling Blind: Post Liberal Civil Society and the Worlds of
Neo-Tocquevillean Social Theory. http//www.press.jhu.edu. jour-
nals/theory _&_ event/v0011/1shapiro.html
Siisiäinen. Martti: Gamla sociala kitt i upplösning - föreningverksamhetens up-
pgång och fall. Teoksessa Kurt Klaudi Klausen & Per Selle (Red.): Frivillig
organisering i Norden. Oslo: Tano og Jurist- & Økonomieforbundets Forlag
1995, p. 96-114.
Siisiäinen, Martti: Intressit, yhdistyslaitos ja poliittisen järjestelmän vakaisuus.
Jyväskylä Studies in Education, Psychology and Social Research 57.
Jyväskylä, Jyväskylän yliopisto 1986.
Siisiäinen, Martti: Organizations and the struggle about classes. Jyväskylä:
Publications of the Department of Sociology 38, University of Jyväskylä 1987.
Siisiäinen, Martti: Social capital, power and the third sector. In: Martti Siisiäinen &
Petri Kinnunen & Elina Hietanen (eds.): The Third Sector in Finland. Helsinki:
STKL 2000, p. 3-25.
Siisiäinen, Martti: Social movements, voluntary associations and the development of
the welfare state in Finland. International Review of Administrative Sciences
Vol. 60 (1994) 2, 249-269.
Siisiäinen, Martti: Voluntary Associations and Social Capital in Finland. In: Jan Van
Dept & Marco Maraffi & Ken Newton & Paul Whiteley (eds.): Social Capital
and European Democracy. London and New York: Routledge 1999 , p. 120-
143.
Siisiäinen, Martti: Voluntary Associations and the Theory of Autopoietic Systems.
Paper presented at the 14th World Congress of Sociology, WG01, Session
Dealing with Complexity, Montreal 28.7.1998.
Tenbruch, F. & Ruoff, W.: Modernisierung - Vergesellschaftung - Gruppenbildung -
Vereinswesen. Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie,
Sonderheft 25 (19869, 263-285.
Tocqueville, Alexis de: Democracy in America I-II. New York Alfred A. Knopf 1951.
Truman, D.B.: The Governmental Process. New York: Alfred A. Knopf 1951.
Van Dept, Jan & Maraffi, Marco & Newton, Kenneth & Whiteley, Paul (eds.): Social
Capital and European Democracy. London and New York: Routledge 1999
Warren, Mark E.: Democratic theory and trust. Mark E. Warren (ed.): Democracy
and Trust. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1999, 346-260.
Weber, Max: Geschäftsbericht. In: Verhandlungen des ersten deutschen
Soziologentages vom 19.-22. Oktober. Tübingen 1911, 39-61.
Weber, Max: Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Tübingen: J.B.C. Mohr (Paul Siebeck)
1976.

You might also like