History of Greek PH 010534 MBP
History of Greek PH 010534 MBP
History of Greek PH 010534 MBP
T, IV1U
I*
U B LI L.
LI
B MAH
DOD1 DOb3SEM S
A HISTORY OF
GREEK PHILOSOPHY
VOLUME
I
MAI MAR
6 1989
1990
MM
FEB 26
1
MAI MAR
7 1991
DEC
06
1992
MAI FEB i*
*M
OCT
.1
1992
FEB 2 2
UN
JAN 07
1996
A HISTORY OF
GREEK PHILOSOPHY
BY
W.
K.
C GUTHRIE,
VOLUME
I
KB.A.
The
right
of the
University
Henry VIII m 1534 The University has printed and published continuously
since 1584
Published
by
The
Trumpington, Street, Cambridge CB2 IRP East 32 57th Street, New York, NY 10022, USA 10 Stamford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia
Pitt Building,
<g)
CONTENTS
Preface
page
the Sources
ix
Note on
xiii
List of Abbreviations
I
xv
i
II
III
IN
GREECE
26
39
39
45
Introduction
Thales
(1)
(2)
46
50
50
52
Family
Water
of all things
54
58
61
hylozoism (9) The unity of being: science and myth Additional note: water and 'life'
(8) Self-change
and
life:
62
67
71
C.
Anaximander
(1) Date, writings, interests (2)
72 72
as arche
76
78
83
(3)
(4)
87
89
life
101
105
innumerable worlds*
106
Contents
D.
Anaximenes
(1) (2)
(3) (4)
page 115
115
1 1
116
119
(5) Air,
127
132
Meteorology Conclusion
Milesians : conclusion
139 139
E*
The
140
IV
146
148
Methods of approach
(1) Sources of the sixth and
fifth centuries
157
157
(2) Fourth-century
sources
excluding Aristotle
161
and
his pupils
169
171
C.
Life
173
181
D.
Man and
182
Numbers and
the
cosmos
the
212
musical
intervals.
(a) Introductory:
212
226
Aristotle's evi-
Numbers and
things from
numbers
(</)
Cosmology
Abstractions as numbers
239 282
301
(e)
(3)
The
306
Contents
E.
Individual Pythagoreans
(1)
page 319 3 20
3 22
Ecphantus
3 23 3 27
3 29
(4) Hicetas
Archytas
333
33 6
V ALCMAEON
VI
34*
3 60
3<*
XENOPHANES
(1)
Date and
life
(2) Social
and
political
outlook
3 64
36 5 I 66
(3) Writings (4) Tradition (5) Destructive criticism (6) Constructive theology (7)
37
373
3 Sl 3 83
God
identified
3 87
(10)
39
395
VII
HERACLITUS
(1) Difficulties (2) Sources (3) Writings (4)
(5)
and policy
43 45
4 6
4o8 4 IQ 41 3
vii
Date and
life
(6) Prophetic
Contents
(7) Relation to earlier thinkers
page 415
416 419
(8) Philosophical
(9)
methods: self-search
The Logos
of opposites
Harmony
is
435
() Everything is in continuous motion and change (c) The world an ever-living fire
(u)
Final explanation of the theory of change:
fire
449
454
459
and soul
464
469
473
(13)
The complete
world-picture: theology
fate
of the soul
482
(16) Conclusion
486 488
493
to
505
II.
514
Vlll
PREFACE
initiative
This volume marks the beginning of an enterprise undertaken on the of the Syndics of the Cambridge University Press. They
decided, first, that there was room for a comprehensive history of ancient Greek philosophy in English, on a considerable scale. The only such history available is the four-volume translation of Theodor
Gomperz's Greek Thinkers, the last volume of which was finished by Gomperz in 1909. This was a valuable work for its time, though somewhat discursive, but a vast amount of detailed research has been carried
out during the last half-century which has left no corner of the field untouched, and in some places has radically altered its contours. Secondly, the Syndics took the view that the plan of a composite
the Press has produced such notable and that in this subject examples it would be for the be whole to the preferable product of a single mind. Their third wish was that the work should not demand from its
history
had
certain drawbacks,
readers a knowledge of Greek. I am well aware of the magnitude of the task, and of my temerity in accepting the proposal of the Syndics that I should undertake it.
The
difficulties are
the reverse of those which beset a pioneer. Far this history deals with a subject of which
almost every detail has been minutely worked over many times. What is needed (and few would dispute the need) is a comprehensive and
systematic account which will so far as possible do justice to the
opposing views of reputable scholars, mediate between them, and give the most reasonable conclusions in a clear and readable form. The
qualities called for are
much
as clear-
headedness, sober sense, good judgment and perseverance. Yet to throw light on the Greek mind calls in addition for gifts of imagination, sympathy and insight. It means entering into the thoughts
men moulded by a civilization distant in time and place from our own who wrote and spoke in a different language. For some of them, though we may call them philosophers, not only reason but also
of
IX
Preface
myth and divine revelation were paths to truth. Their intermust be a scholar with an ear for the subtleties and overtones preter the of Greek language, capable of comparing a philosopher's use of it
poetry,
with that of the writers of non-philosophical poetry and prose. Where modern techniques of philosophical criticism will aid elucidation, he
should ideally be equipped to invoke them immune from any tendency to anachronism.
I
also,
while remaining
Such a paragon does not exist. By setting forth his qualifications have no intention of making any claims for myself: I hope only that
may
induce a proper
humility and help one to fall less woefully short of it. One thing that no one can do is to master the whole flood of writing on the subject
can only hope that my own selection of authorities has not been too arbitrary or inadequate^
I
and associate myself with one of the most sensitive of modern critics, who wrote: 'Although a conscientious working over of the whole enormous specialist literature would have been highly desirable in
itself, it
1 during my lifetime/ reader new to the subject should perhaps be warned that at the early period covered by the present volume, from the beginning of
finish
fifth
century
B.C.,
no
line is yet
drawn
between philosophy, theology, cosmogony and cosmology, astronomy, mathematics, biology and natural science in general. The word philo-
sophy must therefore be interpreted in a very wide sense, though possibly not much wider than that which it bore in Europe down to
the seventeenth century A.D. By the fifth century B.C. history, geography, and to a large extent medicine did receive separate treatment by certain writers. These will only enter incidentally, and our main
who
took
all
and present constitution and (whether or nor from religious motives) the origin and destiny of human life and its place in the whole. The medical writers, it is true, had to come
tried to determine its origin
to terms with these broad theories, which they criticized as relying too on instead of on confidently general principles empirical investigation. There was action and reaction here, and an acquaintance with the
1
Hermann
und Philosophic
(translated).
Preface
medical literature
is
essential for
Hesiod, 'Orpheus', Pherecydes and others as precursors of the philosophers, and the existence within them of a development away from mythopoeic towards rational thought, has become more and
gonies
that has been
more clearly recognized in recent times. Readers aware of the new light thrown on the ideas of the early philosophers by the
study of these mythographers
be surprised and disappointed that no preliminary chapters appear to be devoted to them and to their influence exclusively. I hope however that a reading of the chapters
may
on the philosophers themselves will show that this aspect has not been neglected. It was a difficult choice, but I decided that this was the best
course, namely that the question of how far the thought of, for example, Thales or Anaximenes was moulded by the myths of their own people, as well as those of Egypt and the Orient, should be discussed in direct
below.) continue this my history to include the Hellenistic period, stopping short of the Neoplatonists and those of their predecessors who are best understood in conjunction with them.
It is
Deo
volente, to
(Cf. p. 24 below. I understand that the Press has plans for a continuation by other hands.) I had thought to confine the Presocratics
to one volume, but as it has turned out, the period down to Heraclitus, with a comprehensive account of Pythagoreanism, has proved sufficient for this if the volumes are not to become uncomfortably large. Although
it
means
that there
is
scale
of the work.
a large task ahead, I make no apology for the Excellent short outlines exist already, and there
could be no justification for adding to their number. Students of a I hope find sufficient in particular philosopher, school or period will
the separate sections to orientate
their
starting-point for
own
researches.
For the
translated.
Greek has not been excluded, has been confined to footnotes unless
As
to these,
Preface
'indispensable as foundations for 1 the argument, but superfluous for understanding it Books have usually been referred to in the notes by short titles, and
5 .
articles
by
periodical, date
articles, will
and
titles
of
and page only. Full particulars of books, be found in the bibliography. The standard
philosophy
is
collection of
Greek
that of
Diels, re-edited
by Kranz (abbreviated
is
DK:
to
constantly made in the following pages. Under each philosopher the texts are divided into two sections. The first (A) contains testimonia^ that is, accounts in later Greek authorities of the
which reference
philosopher's life and doctrines, or paraphrases of his writings; in the second (B) are collected what in the opinion of the editors are
genuine quotations from the philosopher himself. In this book the number of a *B' passage is normally preceded by *fr.' (fragment), is retained. while for the others the letter
Mr F. H. Sandbach, Professor H. C. Baldry and Mr G. S. Kirk, who between them have read the volume in typescript. I owe much to their friendly and pertinent comments. I should also like to thank Mr J. D. Bowman for help in the preparation
My
of the index.
conclude with a request? To continue this work necessitates keeping up with the flow of periodical literature, and it is all too easy to overlook important articles or monographs. If scholars who see
May
volume think the enterprise worth while, perhaps they will be kind enough to send me offprints of their articles or particulars of newly published works. I cannot promise any adequate quid pro quo: I can only say that I shall be sincerely grateful.
this
W.K.C.G.
XII
made by
The problems to which this gives rise have been always recognized, and adequate accounts of the nature of the sources are available in several works, of which the best and most accessible is that of G. S. Kirk in KR, 1-7. (Others will be found in
later writers.
Ueberweg-Praechter, 10-26,
In view of this
I
EGP^
31-8.)
attempt beginning, but shall rather deal with particular source-problems as they arise over individual thinkers. (For the all-important Aristotle
am making no
see especially pp. 41-3.) But a certain amount must be briefly repeated here in order to make intelligible such references as will be necessary
EcV
Theophrastus the pupil of Aristotle wrote a general history of earlier philosophy and special works on some individual Presocratics. Only
extracts survive,
though they include the greater part of the book On Sensation. These works of Theophrastus formed the main foundation for what is known as the doxographical tradition, which took different
forms: 'opinions' arranged according to subjects, biographies, or somewhat artificial 'successions' (5ia8oxoci) of philosophers regarded
as master
and
pupil.
of the doxographical material was undertaken in the monumental work of Hermann Diels, Doxographi Graeci (Berlin,
The
classification
879)3 to
which
all
owe an
incalculable debt.
subsequent researchers into Presocratic philosophy The collections of the works of the early
as 86cci ('opinions',
hence 'doxography') or TOC ccpsaKovrcc (Latinized as Placita). There are two such collections or summaries extant, the Epitome falsely claimed as Plutarch's, and the
thinkers were
known
Physical Extracts (9uaiKa! eKAoyai) appearing in the Anthology or fifth century A.D.). Florilegium of 'Stobaeus' (John of Stobi, probably From a reference in the Christian bishop Theodoret (first half of fifth
xni
Note on
the Sources
century) it is known that both of these go back to a certain Aetius, and the two are printed by Diels in parallel columns as the Placita of
Aetius.
Aetius himself,
who
is
Between Theophrastus and Aetius was a Stoic summary, of the first century B.C. at the latest, which can be detected behind doxographical accounts in Varro and Cicero, and was named by Diels the Vetusta Placita. The doxographies in Hippolytus's Refutation ofall Heresies, and the
pseudo-Plutarchean Stromateis ('Miscellanies') preserved in Eusebius, appear to be independent of Aetius.
The Lives of the Philosophers by Diogenes Laertius (probably third century A.D.) exists entire, and contains matter from various Hellenistic sources of uneven value.
To sum
depends
first
up, our information about the Presocratic philosophers of all on extracts or quotations from their works which
range from one brief sentence in the case of Anaximander (and of Anaximenes perhaps not even that) to practically the whole of the
of Parmenides. Secondly we have occasional mention and discussion of Presocratic thought in Plato, and a more systematic
True
Way
exposition and criticism in Aristotle. Finally there is the postAristotelian information which (with a few exceptions which will be mentioned in discussing the sources for particular philosophers) depends on brief, and sometimes garbled, epitomes of the work of
Theophrastus, the distortions frequently taking the form of adaptation to Stoic thought. To see through this veil to the mind of archaic
the primary task of Presocratic scholarship. Whether worth while no one had a better right to say than Hermann Diels,
Greece
is
it is
who
to
posthumously count myself fortunate in that it has been vouchsafed to 1 dedicate the best part of my powers to the Presocratics/
'I
at the
end of
published lecture:
me
For further
account of Kirk
mentioned above. In addition, an appraisal of the historical work of Theophrastus, which does him more justice than earlier accounts, is to be found in C. H. Kahn, Anaximander^ 17-24.
1
Teh
schatze
mich
Vorsokratikern
LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS
In general, the titles of works cited in the text have not been so abbreviated as to be difficult of elucidation. Some periodicals, however, and
PERIODICALS
AJA AJP CP CQ CR
OTHER WORKS
ACP CAH
H. Cherniss,
Aristotle s Criticism
of Presocratic Philosophy.
DK EGP HCF KR
LSJ
G. G.
S. S.
Kirk and
J.
Liddell-Scott-Jones,
OCD
RE
ZN
Wissowa,
TEGP W.
Philosophers.
W.
Nestle.
xv
To
ported
it until at least the latter part of the nineteenth century. The discoveries about the nature of matter (if that term may still be used), the size and character of the Universe, and the human psyche which
hundred years are indeed so revolutionary that they may result in a radical reshaping of our fundamental outlook. Apart, however, from the fact that they are still in such a state of rapid transition that it is difficult to see what this new framework of thought will be, the conservatism of ordinary human minds ensures that much in the older outlook will continue to colour our general presuppositions for a long time to come. Even the modern
scientists
last
natural philosopher who studies the records of the earliest European thinkers may find that he has more in common with them than he
It is this fundamental and dateless character of much Greek makes it worth while to attempt a fresh presentation of which thought it for a contemporary reader. There is another side to the coin. With the Greeks we stand at the
expected.
beginning of rational thought in Europe. It follows that we shall not only be concerned with reasoned explanation or scientific observation, but shall be watching the emergence of these activities from the mists
sudden, emergence pre-scientific age. claim of Thales to traditional to the indeed shall I try justify gradual. I shall not intend but as the first be philosopher;
of a
This
is
not
regarded
by
rational,
rational
and
exists today.
thought, we it continued to shelter within what appear to be a roof and walls of solid
outlook. No such clearly-marked line existed, or Besides appreciating what is of permanent value in Greek may also learn from observing how much latent mythology
scientific
Introduction
reason. This
Aristotle, to
is
and Summary
in the earliest period, but even so much of
naturally
more obvious
the indispensable
is
groundwork of abstract concepts on which our some fixed ideas which we encounter with a sense has based, thinking of shock; for example, a conviction that the heavenly bodies are living creatures, a belief in the special perfection of circularity or sphericity,
and some curious notions about the primacy of the number three which
clearly antedate the beginnings of philosophical thought. This is not a condemnation of myth as false in itself. Its stories
and images may be, at an early stage of civilization, the only available means (and an effective one) of expressing profound and universal
truths.
may
choose
it
municate experiences and beliefs, the reality and cogency of which is a matter of conviction outrunning logical proof. This is genuine myth,
and
its
validity
when men
scientific
and importance are undoubted. The danger begins all that behind and are relying on a
logical
method based solely on a combination of observation and inference. The unconscious retention of inherited and irrational
in the vocabulary
obstacle, rather than an aid, to the pursuit of truth. The reason for making this point at the outset is that the implicit acceptance of mythical concepts is a habit that never completely
relaxes
even more heavily overlaid than in ancient Greece with the terminology of rational disciplines. This makes it more
its
hold.
Today
it is
difficult to detect
Without belittling the magnificent achievements of the Greeks in natural philosophy, metaphysics, psychology, epistemology, ethics and politics, we shall find that because they were pioneers, and therefore
much
nearer than ourselves to the mythical, magical or proverbial origins of some of the principles which they accepted without question,
we
can see these origins clearly; and this in turn throws light on the dubious credentials of some of the principles which gain a similarly
unquestioned acceptance among many today. Examples of these axioms in Greek thought are the assumption of
the earliest school in Miletus that reality
is
drawn to, or acts upon, like (in support of which Democritus the atomist was not above quoting the proverb 'Birds of a feather' and a line of Homer), and the aforementioned conviction of the primacy and
perfection of circular shape and motion which affected astronomy until the time of Kepler. It is not hard to detect the popular, unscientific origin of these general principles, but what of some to which our own
scientists subscribe, or subscribed until recently?
1 quotes the following:
*
Professor Dingle Nature abhors a vacuum', 'The Universe is homogeneous' (compare the Milesian premiss), 'Nature always works in the simplest way'. It is not only in the ancient world that, as he says,
Universe, instead of being a touchstone, becomes a mould, fashioned first of all to the investigator's liking and then used to give a false form to the things of experience*.
'the
history of Greek philosophy can be conveniently divided iato periods which show a real difference of outlook and interest, cor-
The
responding in part to changes of outward circumstances and habits of life. They also differ in the locality of the centres from which the main
intellectual influences
time, if this
were exerted upon the Greek world. At the same division is adopted, it is important not to lose sight of the
equally real continuity that runs through the whole development of thought from the Milesians to the Neoplatonists. To bring out this continuity, it will be worth while attempting a brief sketch of the
development of Greek philosophy before we proceed to consider it in detail. The next few pages may be regarded as a map of the country
which we have
the
to traverse,
and
it is
on the journey
Greek
settle-
ment.
Ionia,
Lydian and Persian rule, something happened in the sixth century before Christ which we call the beginning of European philosophy. Here with the Milesian opened the first, or Presocratic period of our subject,
and most prosof her own and wideperous of Greek cities, with numerous colonies an with endowed were indefatigable curiosity spread foreign contacts,
school. These men, inhabitants of one of the largest
1
The
Scientific
Introduction
and Summary
about the nature of the external world, the process by which it reached its present state, and its physical composition. In their attempts to
knowledge, they by no means excluded the possibility of divine agency, but they reached a conception
satisfy this intellectual craving for
of
very different from the polytheism current in contemporary Greek society. They believed that the world arose out of a primal
it
unity,
and that
this
still
being,
though now
possible by an everlasting motion of the primary stuff due, not to any external agent, but to its own essential animation. The distinction between a material and an efficient principle
had not yet been felt, and the primary entity, since it lived for ever and was the author of its own movement and change, and of all the ordered world of earth, sky and sea, was naturally thought to merit the epithet
'divine'.
Before the end of the century, the philosophical impulse was carried from the eastern to the western borders of the Greek world by the
migration of Pythagoras of Samos to the cities of Greek settlement in South Italy. Together with physical translation, it underwent a change
of spirit.
From now
develop in different ways, though the division is not so clearly marked as some later Greek scholars and classifiers supposed, and there was
some cross-fertilization,
Graecia.
as for example when Xenophanes from Asiatic in followed the track of Pythagoras and settled in Magna Colophon
So
far as
change in
spirit
Pythagoras and his followers were concerned, the affected both the motive and the content of philosophy.
understand, its purpose became the provision of intellectual foundations for a religious way of life; and in itself it acquired a less physical, more abstract and
From
satisfaction
know and
mathematical character. Study of matter gave way to study of form. The logical trend was followed up in the West by Parmenides of Elea and
and reached its climax in his teaching that true being was not be found in the physical world because, from the propositions 'It is' and 'It is one' (on which Milesian cosmology might be said to have been based; in any case Parmenides argued that the second followed from the first), the only valid conclusion was an unqualified denial of
his school,
to
Early Presocratics
physical
movement and change. Reason and the senses gave contraanswers to the question: 'What is reality?', and the answer of
little earlier,
Heraclitus of Ephesus was also advancing towards lie fateful division between reason and the senses. He preached the folly of relying on
sense-perception unchecked
rightful interpreter,
reason, though without going so far as to reject its witness absolutely as did Pannenides. In contrast to the Eleatic, who denied the very
possibility of
continuous cycle of flux and change* Rest, not movement, was the impossibility. Any apparent stability was only the result of a temporary
deadlock between the opposite tensions which were ceaselessly at work. only the logos^ which in its spiritual aspect is the rational principle governing the movements of the universe, including the law of cyclic change. The qualification ('in its spiritual aspect') is necessary
Everlasting
is
is
intimately con-
nected with that substance which had a kind of primacy in the world of Heraclitus, namely fire, or 'the hot and dry'.
The
The
rest
original
change from monism to pluralism. If the monistic hypothesis led to denying the reality of the apparent multiplicity of the world around us,
then in the interests of the phenomena that hypothesis must be and the rejected. This was the reasoning of Empedocles, Anaxagoras
Empedocles was a Sicilian, and like other philosophers of combined his search for the ultimate nature of things Graecia Magna with the demands of a deeply religious outlook, to which the nature
atomists.
and destiny of the human soul was of fundamental interest. He saw the answer to Parmenides in the substitution of four ultimate rootsubstances or elements (earth, water, air and fire) for the single principle
of the Milesians. Anaxagoras brought the spirit of Ionian physics from Asia Minor to Athens, where he lived in the time of Socrates and
Introduction
and Summary
Euripides, and enjoyed the friendship of Pericles and his circle. His doctrine of matter as consisting of an infinite number of qualitatively
'
different
pluralistic
seeds'
was a kind of half-way house to the culmination of this physics in the atomism of Leucippus and Democritus.
uncompromising
logic of Parmenides
An
was
all
to face philosophers with the problem of a moving cause. At its of start, rational thought had inherited from mythology the conception
separation of matter and spirit was as yet undreamed-of, and to the Milesian monists that the single primary substance of it was therefore natural to
physical entities as in
the world
its
it
might be
own
transformations.
thing that needed explaining, or that anyone might demand a separate cause of motion. The intellectual drawbacks of this naive combination
one corporeal entity are already becoming obvious in Heraclitus. By bringing the world to a full stop, as it were, Parmenides drove home the lesson that motion
of matter and
spirit,
in
was a phenomenon
explanation, and in the later Presocratics we see not only the change from a unity to a plurality of physical elements, but also the emergence of a moving cause beside
in
need of
its
own
and apart from the moving elements themselves. Empedocles, impelled by the needs of his moral and
as of his physical system, posited
religious, as well
and
Strife. In the physical world, these are used in a mechanical way to bring about respectively the combination with, and separation from each other of the four elements, whereby the cosmos is brought into
being. In the religious sphere they allow for a moral dualism, being the causes of good and evil respectively. Anaxagoras was hailed by Plato
and Aristotle
man to assert that Nous, Intelligence, was the of the motions originator leading to the formation of a cosmos from the tiny spermata of matter which, in his view, were its material conas the first
stituents.
Moreover he
explicitly insisted
on the transcendent
character
of this Nous, which 'existed alone and by itself and 'was mixed with
no
thing'.
their cause
of motion
any
of Empedocles or
themselves.
is,
emptiness could only be the place where Being was not. But nothing exists besides Being, and to say of Being 'it is not' is a logical
is
impossibility. Emptiness
*
own ground,
the
was
still
not-Being exists as much as Being'; that is, conceived as tied up with corporeal existence, they
must be place which was not occupied by body. They supposed the sum of reality to be made up of tiny solid atoms floating in infinite space. Once this picture is made conscious and
explicit, as it
now was
let
for the
first
time, matter
it
and, of atoms
able to ask
'Why
gives
still?'
were, set free, might perhaps seem as reasonas 'Why should they move?'
is,
as
it
comes near to the heart of their achievement when he says that the atomists 'made void 1 the cause of motion'. To appreciate this at its true worth, one must understand what a bold step it was to assert the existence of empty
Though he
them no
credit for
it,
Aristotle
logic of Parmenides. gradual emergence into consciousness of the problem of the first cause of motion, bound up as it is with that of the relation between
new
The
matter and
life, is
of Presocratic thought. In the time of Anaxagoras and Democritus, there occurred at Athens the change which the ancients universally associated with the name of
the end of the fourth, we are in our second main period, which most people would agree to call the zenith of Greek philosophy. Athens is its centre, and the outSocrates.
The
shift
may be described
265 b 24.
Introduction
and Summary
life
of cosmology and ontology to the more pressing business of human and conduct. Nor was the physical side of the microcosm excluded.
Contemporary with Socrates were Hippocrates and the earliest of those anonymous followers of his who with him produced the impressive body of medical and physiological writings known as the Hippocratic Corpus. At this time, says Aristotle roundly, 'the investigation of
nature came to a stop, and philosophers turned their attention to
practical morality
and
political thought'.
Some
philosophy from
the same thing. Socrates called down the skies and implanted it in the cities and homes of
much
men
'brought it into communal life, compelling it to attend to questions of virtue and vice, good and evil'. As for what went on in the heavens, that was far removed from our grasp, and even had it not
.
He
been,
It
it
had no relevance
to the
good
life.
new
spirit
found
its
first genuine philosopher. To say that he was actually responsible for the change of outlook goes much too far. The teaching of the con-
temporary Sophists was very largely ethical and political, and in this they needed no prompting from Socrates. These were the days of
Athens's growth to political maturity, to the leadership of Greece through her conduct in the Persian Wars and the subsequent founda-
tion of the Delian League, and to the democratic form of government free citizen the right not only to elect his rulers but
his turn in
exercising high and responsible office. To fit himself for success in the busy life of the city-state became a necessity for everyone. As the
contemporary eyes an inevitable retribution for hylris\ and the downfall of Athens at the hands of her rival Sparta. The years of war were marked internally by the increasing
Sicilian expedition (in
of the
revolution,
corruption of Periclean democracy, a murderously cruel oligarchic and the return of a democracy from which the spirit of
vengeance was by no means absent. All these events took place in Socrates's own lifetime, and created an atmosphere inimical to the
1
I,
4, 15.
Reaction towards
Humanism
prosecution of disinterested scientific research. To Aristophanes, a faithful enough mirror of the better opinion of his time, natural philoa were useless sort of sophers people and a suitable butt for not always
seem
it
precise
scientific
make
it
possible, the natural philosophers appeared to be not so much explaining the world as explaining it away. Faced with the choice of
believing either, with Parmenides, that motion and change were unatoms which real, or else that reality consisted of atoms and void
were not only invisible but lacking also the other sensible qualities of taste, smell and sound which mean everything to the human being it is not surprising if most men decided that the world of the philosophers had
little
to say to them.
the same time, the contrast between certain things which were ' c only conventional* and others which existed in nature' (whether it was borrowed from the physicists or merely shared with them as part
At
of the general spirit of the age) was eagerly seized on by some as the basis for an attack on absolute values or divine sanctions in the ethical
sphere. Virtue, like colour, was in the eye of the beholder, it did not 'by nature'. In the ensuing controversy, Socrates employed all
cations of his paradoxes: 'Virtue
exist
his
powers in the defence of absolute standards, through the impliis knowledge' and 'No man does
willingly'.
wrong
anyone understood the true nature of goodness its appeal would be irresistible, and failure to comply with its standards could only be due to a lack of full understanding. This full understanding he did not claim to have reached himself, but
if
unlike others he was aware of his ignorance. Since this at least was a in ethical matters in his starting-point, and an unjustified confidence
it
his mission to
of their ignorance of the nature of goodness and so to seek, with him, to remedy it. In carrying out this them persuade task, he developed the dialectical and elenctic methods of argument to
men
which
To
philosophers owed so much. account for the extraordinary influence of Socrates over sublater
Introduction
and Summary
sequent philosophy is something that must be left until later. Here it may be said that almost all later schools, whether originating with his
own
founded long
whether
dogmatic or
in character, acclaimed sceptical, hedonistic or ascetic all wisdom including their own. This
(<5)
that the
human mind
is
can grasp
it,
of it will be an
in practice.
of ontology, epistemology, ethics and psychology. To contemthe question involved in the poraries it would seem like begging
*
nature- versus-convention' controversy rather than settling it. Determined to defend and expand his master's teaching, Plato with
his
more universal genius, though he had no names for the branches of more recent philosophy just mentioned, wove something of all of them
had a
real nature
into the superb tapestry of his dialogues. Goodness because it stood at the head of the world of 'forms'.
entities
These were
ideal
having a substantial existence beyond space and time, and constituting the perfect patterns after which were modelled the fleeting
and imperfect representations of truth in ethical, mathematical and other spheres which are all that we encounter in this world. Knowledge
possible because, as Pythagorean and other religious teachers claimed, the human soul (of which for Plato the intellect was the highest and best part) is immortal and enters again and again into mortal bodies.
is
Between
its
incarnations
it is
Contamination with the corporeal dulls the memory of these, which may be reawakened by experience of their imperfect and mutable
representations
on
on
its
10
Socrates
soul may, even in this
life,
and Plato
much of the
truth
rigorous intellectual
a process of self-discipline. Philosophy is a canalization of the will and emotions as well as of the intellect. The soul has
recapture
by
and moral
three parts, a concupiscent, a spirited or impulsive, and a rational. The eras, or lilido, of each is directed towards a different class of object
(physical pleasure, honourable ambition, wisdom). In the soul of the true philosopher the lower two are not allowed to exceed the bounds
of their proper functions; the amount of eras directed towards their objects is diminished, and it flows with a corresponding increase in
strength towards the objectives of reason, which are knowledge and goodness. In this way the Socratic paradoxes receive a broader
psychological base.
Plato's
was not a
static
mind.
What
have said so
far
probably
represents not unfairly his convictions in middle life, as expressed in the great dialogues of that period, especially the Meno, Phaedo, Republic and Symposium. From this root sprang his political theory, aristocratic and authoritarian. Later it became apparent to him that
the doctrine of eternal, transcendent forms, which he had accepted with a partly religious enthusiasm, entailed serious intellectual difficulties.
As
a theory of
knowledge
it
demanded
the relations between forms and particulars, or between one form and another, lend themselves easily to rational explanation. Plato did not
hesitate to tackle these problems,
the critical writings which in the view of some twentieth-century philosophers constitute his most important philosophical achievement,
notably the Parmenides, Theaetetus and Sophist. The Parmenides raises, without solving, a number of difficulties involved in the theory of
forms, the Theaetetus is an inquiry into the nature of knowledge, and the Sophist, in a discussion of methods of classification, of the relations
different senses
of
'not-being', lays the foundations for much future work in logic. Plato retained to the end a teleological and theistic view of nature.
The Timaeus contains a cosmogony which sets out to show the primacy of a personal mind in the creation of the world: it was designed by God's intelligence to be the best of all possible worlds. Yet God is not
omnipotent.
ever
fall
model
since
its
ii
Introduction
and Summary
5
raw material is not made by God but given, and contains an irreducible minimum of stubbornly irrational 'necessity That the world is the
.
work, the Laws, product of intelligent design is as the climax of a detailed legislative scheme. His aim is to undermine
argued again in his last
the sophistic antithesis of nature and law: law is natural, and if the 'life according to nature' is the ideal, then it should be a law-abiding life.
left
was for twenty years the friend and pupil of Plato, and this an indelible impression on his thought. Since his own philosophical temperament was very different from his master's, it was inevitable that
Aristotle
a note of conflict should be discernible at the heart of his philosophy. His more down-to-earth mentality had no use for a world of transcen-
it
saw
as a
real
world of experience. He had a great admiration for his fellowNortherner Democritus, and it is conceivable that, had it not been for Plato, the atomic view of the world as an undesigned accretion of
particles
might have undergone remarkable developments in his keen and scientific brain. As it was, he retained throughout life from his Academic inheritance both a teleological outlook and a sense of the
supreme importance of form which sometimes led to working out of his own interpretation of nature.
difficulties in
the
compound of matter and form, 'matter' in its absolute sense meaning not physical body (all of which possesses some degree of form), but a wholly unqualified substratum with no
Every natural object
is
independent existence but logically demanded as that in which the forms inhere. Immanent form takes the place of the transcendent forms
of Plato. Everything has an indwelling impulse towards the development of its own specific form, as is seen most clearly in the organic
progress of seed to plant or embryo to adult. The process may also be described as that from potentiality to actuality. This dichotomy of existence into potential and actual was Aristotle's reply to Parmenides's
denial of change
on the ground
is
come
to be either out
of what
is
or what
not.
At the apex of the scala naturae exists purely actual form, which as perfect Being has no part in matter or potentiality; that is, God. His existence is necessary on the principle that no potentiality is called into
actuality save
by
12
Aristotle
generation, a seed is first produced by a mature plant, a child must have a father. (It is fundamental to Aristotle's teleology that the hen came before the egg.) On this plane, actual and potential are only
relative terms,
Universe
calls for
but to sustain the teleological order of the whole a perfect and absolute Being. To Aristotle as to
and
and
Plato, teleology implies the actual existence of a telos^ an ultimate final efficient cause for the sum-total of things as well as the individual
relative causes
which are
at
work within
In his
own nature God is pure mind or intellect, for that is the highest
type of being and the only one that can be conceived as existing apart from matter. He is not a deliberate creator, since any concern for the world of forms-in-matter could only detract from his perfection and
involve him in one
existence
is
enough to keep in motion (not 'set in motion , for to Aristotle the world is eternal) the whole world-order by activating the universal and
natural impulse towards form. In other words, everything is striving to imitate within its own limitations the perfection of God. Physically, his
existence leads directly to the circular motions instigated by the intelligences that move the heavenly bodies, which in turn render possible
life.
but his possession of reason gives him a line of communication. Thus the way kind of direct a unique position, of intellectual contemplation, of philosophy, is for man the way to
fulfil
his
it is
natural
to develop the activity of his highest part, to strive to realize his proper form. For him, unlike the rest of terrestrial nature, this is (as Aristotle
book of the
is
within him.
The abandonment of the transcendent forms of Plato had momentous consequences for ethics. The existence of justice, courage, temperance,
etc.,
among
meant
that the
knowledge. A man might act rightly by doing what he was told, no relying on an 'opinion' implanted by another; but he would have
'knowledge' of why he was behaving thus. Morals must be securely founded on fixed principles, and for this we need the philosopher who
13
Introduction
and Summary
knowledge of
reality,
of the absolute forms of the virtues which are but palely reflected in any virtuous acts on earth. For Aristotle all this is changed. Moral
virtue and rules of conduct
lie
gent. In the first two books of the Ethics he reminds us no less than six times of the principle that precision is not to be sought indiscriminately in all subjects and is out of place in the study of morality, the goal of
which
not knowledge but practice. The sentence We are not trying to find out what virtue is, but to become good men' seems aimed
'
is
deliberately at Plato and Socrates. In psychology, Aristotle defined the soul as, in his technical sense of
the word, the 'form' of the body; that is, the highest manifestation of the particular compound of form and matter which is a living creature.
This does not of course imply an epiphenomenalist view. That would be to turn his philosophy upside down. Form is the prior cause and is
however, exclude the doctrine of transmigration which Plato shared with the Pythagoreans. Aristotle is shy of the subject of immortality, but seems to have believed in the
in
It does,
survival,
is
though not necessarily the individual survival, of nous, which our link with the divine, and, as he once puts it, the only part of us
outside'.
the extent
of his knowledge and the soundness of his method still excite the admiration of workers in the same field. The identification and description of species was of course a task particularly suited to the genius of the philosopher who, like his master, saw reality in form, yet discovered this form in the natural world instead of banishing it beyond
the founder of the natural sciences as separate the doubtful disciplines, though advantage of an admitted cleavage * between science' and philosophy still lay in the future. In logic, which
He was
he regarded not
as a part of philosophy but as its organon or tool, he stood on Plato's shoulders to a greater extent than is sometimes realized. as elsewhere, his genius for
system and order takes him far mere of other men's ideas, and entitles him beyond rearrangement to his place as the true founder of formal logic and scientific method.
the
Yet here
Hellenistic
Aristotle
Thought
was the tutor of Alexander the Great, remained his friend throughout the period of his conquests, and died within a year of Alexander's death in 323. He stood therefore on the threshold of the new historical order which begins the third main period of Greek philosophy. Whether or not Alexander aimed at establishing a worldwide community (and this is a much-disputed question), he at least
succeeded in bringing
it about that after his time the small, independent and self-contained city-states, which had formed the essential framework
life and thought, lost much of their reality as fully communities. independent Dying early with his work unfinished, he left a vast Asiatic and African dominion to his successors, European,
of
classical
Greek
who
carved
it
up
events were manifold, though doubtless gradual Certainly the Greek did not easily or quickly give up his belief in the city as the natural
community to which he belonged and owed his loyalty. These were fostered by the successor-kings themselves, who respected the power of the city-states and also saw in their preservation the best hope for the survival of Hellenic civilization among the exotic influences of the Eastern lands to which it was now transplanted. The
unit, the
local loyalties
power over local affairs citizens, though supervised by the central government, and the old political spirit of the Greeks was kept alive, though inevitably, as time went on, it became (as Rostovtzeff has said) rather
cities therefore still
and the
lives
of their
municipal than political in the true sense. On the mainland, especially, the combination of the cities into leagues went with a growing consciousness of Hellenic unity. In the early part of the new age, signs were not lacking of a spirit of optimism and confidence, of faith in human capacities and the triumph
of reason. The enormous expansion of the Hellenic horizon, the facilities for travel to, and commerce with, what had been little-known and
barbarian parts of the world, and the opportunities for a fresh start in new lands, increased the sense of activity and hopefulness. As time
and wars between political struggles the dynasties, and the disconcerting effect of the sudden new contacts between Greek and Oriental modes of life, as well as the effective
15
Introduction
and Summary
absorption of the cities in the new kingdoms, began to create a feeling of uncertainty and depression, which, together with the other general
features of the age,
was
The growing
sense
of the unimportance and helplessness of the individual, and even of the long-familiar social and political units, in the face of great and intractable
powers which seemed to mould events with the impersonal of men not unlike that inevitability of fate, had an effect on the minds
of our
own
age.
On the one hand, those of studious bent were set free for the pursuit
of knowledge for
its
own
sake, in
which
This did not manifest itself from the uncertainties of the present in bold and original flights of speculation like those of the dawn of philosophy. Scholarship and the special sciences, which had been given such a remarkable start by Aristotle and his collaborators, were inlife.
dustriously pursued first in the Lyceum itself by men like Theophrastus (Aristotle's friend and successor) and Strato, and then at Alexandria,
whither Strato himself migrated to become tutor to the son of the reigning monarch of Egypt. Here at the beginning of the third century B,C. the Museum, with its great library and research centre,
by Demetrius
of Phaleron. Exiled from Athens, this scholar-statesman, who was a friend of Theophrastus and had almost certainly attended the lectures
of Aristotle himself, carried the
spirit
novel and characteristic feature of the court of Ptolemy I about 295. age was a serious, well-documented study of the past, and in this the
lives
their share
of attention.
application of science to technology, especially in the military sphere, also made notable advances in the Hellenistic age.
The
community, the decreasing opportunity to play a decisive part in public life, meant more freedom for the intellectual to indulge in the secluded pursuits of study and research, it
also induced a widespread feeling
of uneasiness,
loss
of direction,
homelessness. In
earlier,
more compact
was
first
and foremost a
niche of his
citizen,
Hellenistic
Thought
were foreign, to be encountered only in the course of diplomacy or war. His world, like Aristotle's universe, was organically disposed. It had a centre and a circumference. As the Hellenistic age advanced, he became more like a Democritean atom, aimlessly adrift in an infinite
void.
of strangeness, the common accidents of poverty, exile, slavery, loneliness and death took on more frightening shapes and were brooded over more anxiously. One result of this,
Under
this sense
was an increase in the popularity of mystery-religions, both Greek and foreign, which in one form or another promised 'salvation'. Cults of this sort, from Egypt and
especially in the later Hellenistic period,
the Asiatic countries, not unknown to Greeks before, gained adherents from all ranks of society. Philosophy also was naturally not unaffected. New systems arose to meet the new needs, systems whose declared goal
philosophies which dominated the scene from the end of the fourth century onwards were Epicureanism and Stoicism. The latter in
particular attained such widespread influence that it might almost be called the representative philosophy of the Hellenistic and GraecoRoman ages. Both harked back for their inspiration to the thinkers of
The
the great creative period which ended with Aristotle. They were not on this account lacking in originality, to which Stoicism in particular
and becomes an
creation
is
by no means
easy.
reflection
yet his philosophy could be plausibly represented as arising simply from on the utterances of Socrates, the Pythagoreans, Heraclitus
and Parmenides. What distinguishes the Hellenistic systems is rather, as I have indicated, a difference of motive. Philosophy no longer springs, as Plato and Aristotle rightly said that it did in the first place, from a sense of wonder. Its function is to bring an assurance of peace, security and
self-sufficiency to the individual soul in
an apparently hostile or
indifferent world. It
was
should choose as the physical setting for their moral teaching an of the adaptation of some existing scheme. In this way the speculations
Introduction
earlier physical schools,
and Summary
some
extent transmuted, live
though
to
on
in
Epicurus,
who was
when
Aristotle
and Alexander
The
greatest
and of what might single cause of mental distress lay in fear of the gods happen after death. It was an outrage that men should be tormented
by
die notion that our race was at the mercy of a set of capricious and
man-like deities such as Greece had inherited from Homer, gods whose malice could continue to pursue its victims even beyond the grave. The
atomic theory of Democritus, which accounted for the origin of the Universe and for all that happens therein without the postulate of divine agency, seemed to him at the same time to express the truth and
mind of man from its most haunting fears. Undoubtedly the gods exist, but if, as true piety demands, we believe them to lead a life of calm and untroubled bliss, we cannot suppose them to concern themselves with human or mundane affairs. At death the soul (a
to liberate the
combination of especially
fine atoms) is dispersed. To fear death is therefore foolish, since so long as we live it is not present, and when it comes we no longer exist and are therefore unconscious that it has come.
Unlike Democritus,
who
initial
random
directions, Epicurus supposed the unimpeded motion of the atoms to be uniform in direction and speed, caused by their weight. Since he had the remarkable perspicacity to
all
anticipate the finding of modern science that in a vacuum all bodies will fall at an equal speed, irrespective of their relative weights, he had
to account for their collision and entanglement. This he did by assuming a power in the atoms to make a tiny swerve from their course
still
time and place undetermined, and this apparently unexplained hypothesis became a key-point of his system. In conjunction with his theory of the material, atomic composition of the mind, he used it to
at a
account for
resolved at
free-will, for,
all
costs to avoid the determinism of his predecessor. To suppose oneself a slave to destiny, he said, was worse than believing
the old
The
pleasure', but
it
would be more
The
line
of conduct which he
18
recommended was
the mind' in
'it is
which alone
lies
Moreover
not possible to
live pleasantly
honourably and
justly'.
without living prudently and said with some reason that Epicurus (Cicero
only succeeded in maintaining that pleasure was the summum bonum by giving the word a meaning which no one else would recognize.) Though blameless, the Epicurean ethic was somewhat negative, not to
say egoistic, since the attainment of the quiet mind, which was
called for abstention
ideal
its
aim,
from
all
public duties
and
responsibilities.
The
was
to the level of Horace's pig, yet as taught and lived by Epicurus himself his philosophy was not lacking in intellectual courage or moral nobility.
Nevertheless, in spite of his arguments to the contrary, a message of hope and comfort which relies for its effect chiefly on the >surance that
to carry the
death means complete extinction does not seem to the rr, jority of men word of salvation. As a counter-lure to the mystery-
religions it had no great force. At the same time its explicit hedonism, and relegation of virtue to the second rank in the hierarchy of goods,
the disapproval of other philosophical schools. Stoicism in its pure form was an even more austere creed, yet it proved capable of existing at different levels and making a wider appeal. Stoicism became
earned
it
when
adapted
is
by
the
Romans
to their
own
of conduct.
struck at the outset
by
the nation-
of this philosophy, Zeno of Citium, not a Greek at ality of the founder all but a Phoenician Semite, as was almost certainly the great systemof Stoic doctrine Chrysippus of Soli near Tarsus. Zeno reacted of chance. strongly against the idea that the Universe was the product He found the germ of truth rather in the mind-matter complex of
atizer
and put at the centre of his system the logos which has its material embodiment in fire. This union of mind and matter, for Heraclitus a naive assumption, was for Zeno a conscious achievement, following on study and explicit rejection of the Platonic and
Heraclitus,
Introduction
and Summary
Aristotelian forms of dualism. Nothing can exist without material embodiment. The cosmos is the work of a providence which orders all things
for the best, a product of conscious art, yet its designer is not transcendent. The divine essence impregnates everything, though not every-
where in the same purity. Only in man among sublunary creatures does it take the form of logos, materially represented by warm breath (pneuma)* In the outer heavens it is even purer, sheer fiery mind free from
the lower elements which contaminate it in and around the earth.
By the
his body possession of logos, which the lower animals lack, man, though is animal, shares the highest part of his nature with divinity; and since
everything strives to live in accordance with its best nature, this that is the is, a life in conformity with the logos proper goal for man. Hence
the Stoic ideal of the Sage, who has learned that nothing matters but the inner self. Externals (health, possessions, reputation), though the animal side of man may justify him in putting some before others, are
be right within is all that matters. This knowledge of the indifference of outward circumstances makes the Sage unshakably autarkes, and that is the sole requisite for a happy life.
intrinsically indifferent.
To
Not pleasure, but virtue (equated with wisdom) is the highest good. Unity was restored to the soul by Chrysippus, who reduced impulse and desire to judgments ('This is good for me', etc.), thus building a
new
is
knowledge.
Virtue
an absolute,
like straightness
paradox that there are goodness or wisdom and absolute folly or vice. The perfect Sage is extremely rare, yet all others are fools, and 'all sins are equal*. This was
criticized Stoic
illustrated
various analogies, for instance that a man is drowned just the same whether his head is one foot or several fathoms below the surface. Yet as with externals, the Stoics generally conceded that there
by
must be an intermediate class of actions, some though none properly good or bad.
preferable to others,
The
human
possession of logos,
momentous
corollary that
wisdom was
all
as
women
men
were by nature
the
free
conception of
a natural
human community. To
communally
20
as
much
Stoicism
human
for
all
instinct as self-preservation,
and the
ideal
community
is
one
men
race, the Cosmopolis or world-city, are kinsmen, sons of the one God. The whole idea of the
whole human
if it originated (as some would claim) in the mind of Alexander himself, owes much of its development and diffusion
should be
said,
however, that
this
conception
probably did not mature until some time later than Zeno and his followers, and reached its climax with Epictetus in the late first
century A.D. Meanwhile a
he
natural
though existing law may differ widely from the law of the Cosmopolis. Unlike Epicureanism, Stoicism recommends active participation in the life around one, and tries to
finds himself,
restore to the
gone with membership of the independent city-state. Zeno and Chrysippus made notable contributions
disciplines of epistemology, logic and philology. For the first time, theories of the nature and use of language were being discussed by men
who
used the Greek language and were steeped in the tradition of Greek thought, but who were yet bilingual, with not Greek but
another as their mother-tongue. They adopted the contemporary division of philosophy into logic, ethic and physic, but these elements
were united, and the system integrated, by the universality of the logos. This vital cosmic force, or deity, has a twofold function as the
principle both of knowledge times of Plato's Idea of the
that
is
reminded some-
Good, which he compared to the sun as on which depend not only the existence and life of the natural
also
affinities
world but
obvious
our perception of it through sight. The logos has also with the hylozoistic principle of several of the Pre-
things' and steered all of of as Plato, that however much he Zeno, things'. Yet we may say owed to his predecessors, his synthesis is infused with that new spirit
which
entitles it to
be
called in its
own
right
is
21
Introduction
and Summary
preliminary survey. It received fresh impetus and a new direction in the second century B.C. at the hands of Panaetius of Rhodes, who was
largely responsible for its introduction at Rome and its adaptation to Roman ideals and habits of thought. Regarding Socrates as the founder
recent philosophy, he looked to Plato and Aristotle no less than to Zeno. Fitted by nature to be a man of the world, the friend of
of
all
historian Polybius, he emphasized the necessity of affairs. His aristocratic Stoic bringing principles to bear on practical leanings led him to abandon the earlier theory of the natural equality
Scipio
and of the
of all men for one of natural differences between them, and his relations
with
Roman society were in fact bound up with his conviction that the
which he saw
as a
ideal state,
duties but giving to each section of the population its due rights and Roman conno more, came nearest to practical realization in the
stitution.
Sceptic,
Peripatetic,
Academic
con-
may fairly be said to have been overshadowed by the Stoa, Under Carneades in the second century, a notable opponent of Stoicism,
Academy took a
turn towards scepticism and disbelief in the possithe bility of certain knowledge. This was reversed under Antiochus, teacher and friend of Cicero, who said of him that he was, 'si perpauca
the
mutavisset, germanissimus Stoicus '.
between Academic, Peripatetic and Stoic teaching lay in words rather than substance. In general one may say that in spite of sharp mutual
criticisms, there
was always
felt
to
be much
Epicureanism
all.
a world-power, and the Roman ethos making its impact everywhere. The Roman genius did not lend itself to originality in philosophy, yet the mere act of interpreting the Greek philosophical
achievement in the Latin language, which was so successfully carried out by Cicero, was bound to bring its own modifications. Cicero's
'Duties*, the Stoic Ko6f|Kovra, though largely dependent on became a treatise 'De Officiis\ and officium was a conception Panaetius, which already had a purely Roman history and associations. Again, the Stoic ideal of the human community was not quite the same when
treatise
on
22
The
lifetime of Cicero
saw
also a revival
sophy by
certain spirits
who were
by
god and man, but wished to give this a more philosophical basis than was offered by the emotional cults of Isis or Cybele. It is, however, by no means free from the superstitious credulity of its time. It is the
existence of this
Graeco-Roman school
much of
the difficulty of reconstructing the Pythagoreanism of the time of Plato and earlier. Most of our information about Pythagoreanism comes from writers of the later period, and what they say about the earlier
contaminated with post-Aristotelian ideas. Whole books were freely written and promulgated in the name of well-known early
phase
is
Pythagorean thinkers.
Perhaps the chief importance of the Neopythagoreans
is
that they
helped to pave the way for Plotinus in the third century A.D. and the whole of the great and influential movement of Neoplatonism. The
Neoplatonists Porphyry and lamblichus both wrote lives of Pythagoras, and there was a close affinity between the two schools, as was only
natural and inevitable, considering how deeply the successors of Pythagoras affected the mind of Plato himself.
We
have
now
Christian eras.
In
crossed the line between the pre-Christian and the its primitive form, the teaching of Jesus and his
may seem to have had little to do with the and continuous unfolding of Greek philosophy. But after impressive the conquests of Alexander, this continuing development was accompanied
by ever widening opportunities for impact on other peoples. Greek and Semite had already met in Zeno and later Stoic philosophers. The first men to set down the new Gospel in writing did so not in their
function as the lingua franca of the greatly enlarged Hellenic world. The task of converting the Gentiles brought the need
itself to its
own vernacular but in the language of Plato and Aristotle as it had now
adapted
to
meet them on
their
own ground,
as
we
in his famous
Introduction
Christian belief that
all
and Summary
men
are sons of
God by
Stoic poet Aratus. Later on, there is a continuous interaction between Christian and pagan thought. The Christian attitude varies in individual
writers
between extreme hostility and considerable sympathy, from the to do with Athens?' of Tertullian to the idea of Greek philosophy as a praeparatio evangelica, the idea that, as Clement
philosophy had prepared the Greeks for Christ, prepared the Jews. With the birth of the highly spiritual religious philosophy of Neoplatonism, the interaction became even more marked. Whether for hostile and apologetic purposes or not,
Law
understanding and some degree of assimilation of the views of the opposite camp became indispensable. Thus even with the growth of
Christianity to be the recognized religion of the civilized world, the continuity is not broken nor the influence of the Greek tradition at an
end. Plato, Aristotle and the Stoics continue to exert their power over have our Cambridge Platonists the scholastics of the Middle Ages. in the seventeenth century, our Catholic Thomists and our Protestant
We
Platonists today. To trace this whole story is not the work of one book, nor probably of one man. I mention the continuance of the Greek tradition in
Christian philosophy because it is something that must not be forgotten, and constitutes one of the reasons for continuing to study ancient Greek
thought today. But the present work will be confined to the nonChristian world, and that being so, I think it is best to make the break before the Neoplatonists rather than attempt to include them. With
Plotinus and his followers, as well as with their Christian contemporaries, there does seem to enter a new religious spirit which is not fundamentally
Greek (Plotinus himself was an Egyptian and his pupil Porphyry a Syrian
who originally bore the name of Malchus), and points rather forward
as
In the course of
mention the names of a large number of philosophers and attempt to assess their achievement. Yet only of three or four of these do we possess any whole or connected writings. Plato's dialogues
to us entire.
Of Aristotle we have
24
a large
amount of
on the
been reworked and enlarged by pupils or editors. In addition to these manuscripts, which were intended for use within the
Aristotle's has
pretension to literary merit, Aristotle left a number of published dialogues which were greatly admired in antiquity for their style as well as their content. These, however, are lost.
little
We
have some complete treatises of his successor Theophrastus. Of Epicurus, who was one of the most prolific writers of antiquity, we now
possess only three philosophical letters to friends (of which one, though containing genuine sentiments of Epicurus, is probably not
from his hand), a collection of forty 'Principal Doctrines* mere sentence or brief paragraph and some aphorisms.
For
all
all
each a
example Stoics not excepting Zeno himself, we are dependent on quotations and
the other major figures in Greek philosophy, including for the Presocratics, Socrates (who wrote nothing), and the
excerpts of varying lengths occurring in other authors, or paraphrases and accounts of their thought which often display a more or less
obvious
outstanding difficulty for a historian of Greek at the outset. Except for Plato and
II
Purely practical considerations ordain that we should not pursue our subject too far into its embryonic stage, or at least not to a time before
its
It
conception. What may we call the conception of Greek philosophy? occurred when the conviction began to take shape in men's minds that the apparent chaos of events must conceal an underlying order,
this
the product of impersonal forces. To the mind of a pre-philosophical man, there is no special difficulty in accounting for the apparently haphazard nature of much that goes on in the world.
and that
order
is
high
spirits, jealousy,
What more
ways of
the world
similar explanation?
He
sees himself to
be
mercy of superior and incomprehensible forces, which sometimes seem to act with little regard for consistency or justice. Doubtless they
are the expression of beings like-minded with himself, only longerlived and more powerful. Our present purpose does not require us to enter the troubled regions of anthropological controversy by suggesting
that these remarks have
origin,
or origins, of religious
belief.
assumptions of that type of polytheism or polydaemonism which dominated the early mind of Greece and can be studied in all its
picturesque detail in the Homeric poems.
rain
phenomena
like
and death, but also those overmastering psychological impulses through which a man feels no less that he is in the power of something beyond his own control.
illness
26
Greek Polytheism
an act of
folly
means
that
'Zeus took away his wits', outstanding prowess on the field of battle * is owed to the god who breathed might into' the hero. In this way
for one of its most constant needs, the need for an excuse. Responsibility for impulsive action which is bound to be regretted when (in our significant expression) the doer 'comes to
himself can be transferred from the agent to an external compulsion. In our own age the impersonal factors (repression, complex, trauma and
the like), which have replaced Aphrodite or Dionysus, are sometimes put to the same use.
The
belief that
men
perfect deities
may
are the playthings of powerful but morally imseem to put them in a very humble and pitiable
position, and expressions of pessimism about the human lot are frequent in Homer. At the same time it contains an assumption almost of arrogance, which the advent of a more philosophical outlook must
assumes that the ruling powers of the universe concern themselves intimately with human affairs. The gods take
dispel; for at least
it
thought not only for the fate of humanity as a whole or of cities, but even for the fortunes of individuals (to whom, if the men are chieftains,
they may even be related by blood). If A prospers, while his neighbour B is ruined, this will be because the one has earned the favour, the other
the enmity, of a god. Gods quarrel over whether Greeks or Trojans shall win the war; Zeus pities Hector, but Athena insists on the glorifiexpress their feelings to Achilles them. When Apollo, after deceiving by taking the human form of Agenor, finally reveals himself, the infuriated hero bursts out in his
cation of Achilles.
presence:
I
'You have wronged me, Apollo, and if I had the power, should requite you for it* In spite of the ultimate invincibility of the
its
had gods, this familiar intercourse between earth and heaven must have of the earliest influence the Under side. and stimulating satisfying
of gods and men* and his divine philosophical thinking, the 'Father an affair of family were dissolved into an impersonal 'necessity',
natural laws and the interaction of 'airs, ethers, waters
and other
in the Phaedo. To many this strange things', as Socrates calls them must have brought a feeling of loneliness and desertion, and it is no wonder that the old and colourful polytheism retained its hold to a
in Greece
of more rise, in the sixth century B.C., views. cosmological Moreover, to appreciate the extraordinary achievement of the early state of philosophical thinkers, we must recognize that in the prevailing
knowledge the religious explanation would seem by far the most natural and probable. The world as our perceptions show it to us is
The freedom and irresponsibility of personal of a clash of conflicting the will, unpredictable consequences wills, account for its vagaries, on a superficial view, far better than the of a single underlying order. Indeed in attempting to
chaotic and inconsistent.
still
more
hypothesis
on such
a hypothesis, the
first
philosophers, as Henri
unproved assumption'. Religious explanations had sufficed to account not only for the dayto-day events of the contemporary world, but also for its far-off even origins. In this respect we can see a considerable development,
before the days of philosophy, in the direction of an orderly process. The tendency towards systematization reaches perhaps its highest point in Hesiod's Theogony, yet in that poem the origins of sky, earth
all that they contain are still represented as the outcome of marriages and begettings on the part of personal beings.
beings
may seem
disguise for physical phenomena; yet was a genuine goddess who had been
must be remembered
that Gaia
of popular belief and widespread cult. In the cosmogony of Hesiod the all-powerful cosmic force is still Eros, 'fairest among the immortal
gods'. He is Love, the power of sexual generation, and his presence from the beginning is necessary to set on foot the matings and births which are thought of as the sole means of generation for all parts of
the universe as well as for the creatures
earlier
who
inhabit
it.
How far
this
first sought a more natural and impersonal explanation is which we must try to determine when we come to consider something their work in detail For the present we may say that in their attempt to conceive of the world as an ordered whole, and their search for its
those
who
28
Abandonment of Mythology
arche or beginning, they had predecessors in the genealogies of the and his idea of the of provinces and or distribution theologian dasmos^
away of
anthropomorphic imagery, with all its momentous consequences for the free development of speculation, was theirs alone. 1
birth of philosophy in Europe, then, consisted in the abandonment, at the level of conscious thought, of mythological solutions to
The
problems concerning the origin and nature of the universe and the processes that go on within it. For religious faith there is substituted
the faith that
basis of scientific
is,
thought with
all its
triumphs and
limitations: that
conceals a rational and intelligible order, that the causes of the natural world are to be sought within its boundaries, and that autonomous
human
reason
is
sufficient
The
next question to be considered is who were the authors of this intellectual revolution, in what conditions they were living, and to what
influences they
Its first
were open.
citizens
exponents, Thales, Anaximander and Anaximenes, were of Miletus, an Ionian Greek city on the west coast of Asia Minor, from the beginning of the sixth century B.C. onwards. In their time Miletus, which had already existed for some five hundred years,
was a centre radiating a tremendous energy. Ancient tradition hailed it as the mother of no less than ninety colonies, and modern research
confirms the reality of about forty-five of them in itself an astonishing number. 2 One of the oldest of these was the commercial settlement of
Naucratis in Egypt, founded in the middle of the seventh century. Miletus possessed great wealth, which it had obtained both by acting as a trading-centre for materials and manufactured goods brought to the
coast
factures of
from inner Anatolia and by the export of a variety of manuits own. Milesian woollen goods were famous throughout Greek lands. Thus shipping, trade and industry combined to give this
1
Hesiod as a predecessor of philosophical cosmogonists see O. Gtgon, Der Ui-sprung, and F. M. Cornford, Princ. Sap. ch. n. One of the most interesting of these figures on the borderline between myth and philosophy is Pherecydes of Syros in the sixth century, for whom see the excellent account of Kirk in KR, 48-72. 2 Pliny, N.H. v, 112: Miletus loniae caput. . .super XC urlium per cuncta maria genetrix.
On
ch.
i,
RE,
xv, 1590.
29
in Greece
busy harbour-city a leading position and wide connexions, extending to the Black Sea in the north, Mesopotamia in the east, Egypt in the south and the Greek cities of South Italy in the west. Its government was aristocratic, and its leading citizens lived in an atmosphere of luxury and of a culture which may be broadly described as humanistic and materialistic
in tendency.
product of human any great debt to the gods. The poetry of the Ionian Mimnermus was an appropriate expression of its spirit in the late seventh century. To
high standard of living was too obviously the energy, resource and initiative for it to acknowledge
Its
him
it
seemed
that, if there
were gods, they must have more sense than human affairs. From the gods we know
'
at
extolled the enjoyment of momentary pleasures and the gathering of roses while they lasted, mourned the swift passing of youth and the
misery and feebleness of old age. The philosopher of the same period and society looked outward to the world of nature, and matched his
human
wits against its secrets. Both are intelligible products of the same material culture, the same secular spirit. Both in their own way
relegate the gods to the background, and explanations of the origin and nature of the world as the handiwork of anthropomorphic deities seem
mythological and theological modes of thought seemed to have come, its development was facilitated by the fact that neither here nor in
any other Greek state w4s freedom of thought inhibited by the demands of a theocratic form of society such as existed in the neighbouring
Oriental countries.
Milesian philosophers, then, provided both the leisure and the stimulus for disinterested intellectual inquiry, and
the dictum of Aristotle and Plato, that the source and spring of philo1 sophy is wonder or curiosity, finds its justification. Tradition describes
these
men
as practical,
both active in
political life
and interested in
technical progress; but it was curiosity, and no thought of mastering the forces of nature in the interests of human welfare or destruction, which
led
them to those
1
first
30
phenomena which
constitute their chief title to fame. In the application of various techniques to the amelioration of human life the Egyptians of a thousand years before could probably have taught these
lessons.
lit
in
Egypt, for they lacked the necessary spark, that love of truth and knowledge for their own sakes which the Greeks possessed so strongly and
embodied
in their own word philosophiaJ- Philosophy (including pure can science) only be hampered by utilitarian motives, since it demands a greater degree of abstraction from the world of immediate experience,
wider generalization and a freer movement of the reason in the sphere of pure concepts than submission to practical ends will allow. That
practical purposes
may
also
if free rein is
given to die flights of pure scientific speculation, is true but irrelevant. Philosophy did not arise from a demand for the necessities or amenities
of
human
life.
satisfaction
condition of
*
agree with Aristotle, who, after making his point that philosophy has its origin in wonder, adds: History supports this conclusion, for it was after the provision of the
its
We may
life
life
who
the same thing: 'Leisure is the mother of Philosophy; and Common- wealth, the mother of Peace and Leisure: Where first
said
Cities, there
much
was
first
its
relations
with neighbouring powers, will also be relevant to our subject. Situated on the eastern fringe of the Greek-speaking peoples, it had at its back
different
fact, as a
recent historian
of ancient Persia has emphasized, its situation and activities placed it 'in the full current of Oriental thought'? This is something which has
long been generally recognized, but the conclusions which have been drawn concerning the actual extent of Oriental influence on the earliest
1
It is true,
and
word
ercxpfoc
developed
this
meaning of philo-
original connotation of skill in a particular craft or art carpenter, surgeon, driver, poet or musician had his particular oxxpioc. Yet this was
sophical
wisdom out of an
A good
not the
meaning in the minds of those who used the word 9iAocro<p{cx. 3 A. T. Olmstead, History of the Persian Empire^ 208.
31
in Greece
Greek philosophers show wide discrepancies, and have sometimes tended to be mere guesses based on prejudice rather than knowledge. It was difficult for some philhellenes of the nineteenth century to admit
any detraction from the pure originality of Greek thought. When the inevitable reaction set in, it became equally difficult for some, who felt that the adulation of everything Greek had gone to extreme lengths, to grant them any originality at all. In any case, it is no long time since
the decipherment of
thousands of clay tablets (even now far from complete) provided material for an appreciation of the science and philosophy of the ancient Near East and hence for a balanced estimate
many
could have taught the Greeks. To take first of all the question of contacts and opportunity for the interchange of ideas, we must remember that most of Ionia was under
it
of what
the rule of Lydia in the time of its king Alyattes, Smyrna but met his match in the Milesians and
them. 1 Alyattes ruled from about 610 to 560, a period which covers much of the lifetime of Thales. His son Croesus completed the conquest of the Ionian coastal strip, and after his defeat by Cyrus in 546 it became a part of the Persian Empire. Both these monarchs, however, seem to have felt bound to respect the power and reputation of
Miletus,
their
and independence and continued to live its own interference. Clearly from this, which might be
aspect, Milesians like all lonians must have had plenty of opportunity of getting to know the Oriental mind. the active side, these enter-
On
prising Greeks made journeys by land to Mesopotamia and by sea to Egypt; and the evidence all suggests that the first philosophers were
no
recluses,
who
shut themselves off from this ferment of their times, whom Thales at least made the
voyage to Egypt.
We are inclined to
having been, for
all
the high level of their civilizations, places where freedom of thought was inhibited by the demands of a religion which weighed heavily on every branch of life and was used in the interests of
a despotic central government; where the King was the embodiment 1 HdL I, I 7 ff.
of the Greeks
To deny
the
title
of
men of science
who
created
the technique of multiplication and division; who made an error of only one feet base lines of the Great Pyramid; who discovered how inch in the 75 to mark out the passing of the seasons by taking as a unit the lapse of time
between two heliacal risings of the star Sirius would be to narrow down the meaning of the term beyond what in this industrial age we should be willing
to do. 1
To
predict an eclipse, as he
is
must have
the earliest
fundamental techniques
of the domestication of animals, agriculture, pottery, brick-making, spinning, weaving and metallurgy. The Egyptians and Sumerians
alloyed copper with tin to
make
the
more
Ionian
useful bronze,
cities like
and in the
Miletus copied the Asiatic technique, which was superior to the Greek. The debt of Greek mathematics to Egypt and Babylon was one
textiles
which the Greeks themselves acknowledged. Herodotus writes that in his opinion geometry was invented in Egypt and brought from there
into Greece,
division of the day into twelve parts and the use of the polos and gnomon, which were instruments (or possibly the same instrument
under
names) for marking the time of day and the chief of the year such as solstice and equinox. Aristotle turning-points makes the general statement that the mathematical arts were founded
different
in Egypt. 3
further ahead in Egyptians led in geometry, the Babylonians were even arithmetic. In astronomy, arithmetical techniques were used by the
1
W.
P.
Ideas, p. 4.
a
3
98^23. For
a comparison of these
p. 35.
33
in Greece
Babylonians to bring the prediction of celestial phenomena to a remarkable degree of accuracy, and these techniques were developed by
I500B.C,
belief,
that,
Babylonian astronomy was based on which brings it even closer to the mind of
of
knowledge, papyrus documents from Egypt as far back as 2000 B.C. show that considerable progress had already been made there in the
arts
of medicine and surgery. All this store of knowledge and skill was waiting, as it were, on the doorstep of the Greeks, so that to call them the first scientists would, we
may
Yet
if
agree, be to impose an impossibly narrow meaning on the term. they did not create science, it is generally and on good grounds
lifted it
them would simply have stagnated at a certain elementary level underwent at their hands sudden and spectacular developments. These
developments were not in the direction of the better fulfilment of further the Baconian practical ends. They did not, unless accidentally,
ideal 'to
endow
the
life
of man with
infinite
commodities'.
It is
indeed
probable, and has been too casually denied in the past, that the Ionian philosophers were keenly interested in technical problems; but it is in
sphere that they were most inclined to be the eager pupils of neighbouring peoples. The uniqueness of their own achievement lies
this
elsewhere.
We
get a glimpse of
it
if
we
sophy and science are as yet inseparable, yet whereas we speak of Egyptian and Babylonian science, it is more natural to refer to the
philosophy of the Greeks. Why is this? The Egyptian and Mesopotamian peoples, so
felt
far as
we can
discover,
it
no
interest in
knowledge
for its
own
served a practical purpose. According to Herodotus, taxation in Egypt was based on the size of the rectangular plots of land into which the
its
country was divided under a system of private ownership. If a plot had area reduced by the encroachment of the river Nile, the owner could
put in a claim and royal surveyors were sent to measure the reduction, in order that the tax might be suitably adjusted. In giving the
credit for being the first geometers,
Egyptians
Herodotus
states
it
as his opinion
34
Aristotle,
to the fact that the priests enjoyed leisure for intellectual pursuits. He is c arguing that theoretical knowledge ( sciences that are directed neither
of
life
were
satisfied.
Thus
this
is
knowledge
first
arose
in those regions
arts first
leisure.
That
why
the mathematical
took their
enjoy leisure/
Egypt, for there the priestly caste was free to Herodotus too writes elsewhere of the perquisites and
privileges attached to the priestly life, which arose from the possession of land by the temples. If a priest was a scribe, he was immune from
any other kind of labour. Nevertheless Aristotle is too obviously advancing a favourite theory of his own, which he presses on many other occasions, and Herodotus's account of the practical limitations
of Egyptian geometry remains the more probable. 1 In holding that disinterested intellectual activity is a product of leisure, Aristotle
is
clearly right.
His mistake
lies
in
Egypt the character and purpose Athens, where it was part of a liberal education and also a subject of pure research. In Egypt it was the handmaid of land-measurement or
pyramid-building.* In Babylonia the conduct of practical life was governed to a large extent by religious considerations, and the religion was a stellar one.
In this
explanation which
stellar
gods.
The
a practical study, its virtue lying in the to educated men of the behaviour of the gave observations and calculations which it called forth
were extensive and accurate, but were tied to the service of established hand was in its beginnings, so religion. Greek philosophy on the other
far as the traditional
gods were concerned, agnostic or positively hostile. These peoples, then, the neighbours and in some things the teachers of the Greeks, were content when by trial and error they had evolved
1
Macdonald and
it
Cf. the interesting discussion of Hdt. n, 109 and Ar. Metaph. 981 buff, between C. 12 and 1952, 10. J. Gwyn Griffiths in CR 9 1950,
2 The practical bent of Egyptian mathematics emerges also from the interesting assessment of in Plato's Laws (819), which is the more impressive because Plato is expressing great admiration
and urging the Greeks to follow Egypt's example. Much Egyptian arithmetic was the equivalent of the Greek logistic. (See Karpinski's essay 'The Sources of Greek Mathematics* in d'Ooge's translation of Nicomachus's Introducdo Arithmeticae.)
35
in Greece
worked. They proceeded to make use of it, and felt no in the further question why it worked, no doubt because the
still
of being governed by religious dogma instead difference open to the free debate of reason. Here lies the fundamental between them and the Greeks. The Greek asked 'Why?', and this
interest in causes leads immediately to a further
that fire is a useful tool It will generalization. The Egyptian knows make his bricks hard and durable, will warm his house, turn sand into
glass,
their ore. He does these temper steel and extract metals from result in each case. But if, like the things and is content to enjoy the
different things, Greeks, you ask why the same thing, fire, does all these that is lit in the fire then you are no longer thinking separately of the blacksmith's workbrick-kiln, the fire in the hearth and the fire in the
of fire in general: begin to ask yourself what is the nature what are its properties as fire? This advance to higher generalizations constitutes the essence of the new step taken by the Greeks. The methods of the Babylonians have an algebraic character and show them to have been aware of certain general algebraic rules, but 'they formulated
shop.
You
mathematical problems only with specific numeral values for the coefficients of the equations'. 'No attempt was made to generalise the
results.'
vidual
The Egyptians had thought of geometry as a matter of indiit from the plane rectangular or triangular fields. The Greek lifts
1
of the concrete and material and begins to think about rectangles and whether they are triangles themselves, which have the same properties
embodied in
fields
inches long, or simply represented by lines drawn in the sand. In fact their material embodiment ceases to be of any importance, and we have
made
the discovery which above all others stands to the especial credit of the Greeks: the discovery of form. The Greek sense of form im-
presses itself on every manifestation of their activity, on literature and the graphic and plastic arts as much as on their philosophy. It marks the
advance from percepts to concepts, from the individual examples perceived by sight or touch to the universal notion which we conceive in
our minds
1
in sculpture
ideal
of
op.
S. F.
Mason,
by Wightman,
cit. 4.
from being
a triangle. 1
Elementary generalizations were of course necessary even for practical and empirical science and mathematics like those of the
Egyptians. But they did not reflect on them as single concepts, analyse and define those concepts and so make them usable as the material for,
or the constituent units of, yet higher generalizations. To do this one must be capable of dealing with the concept in abstraction, as a unity with a nature of its own. Then further consequences will be seen to flow from its nature as now defined, and a whole scientific or philosophical system can be built up which was unattainable so long as thought remained at the utilitarian level. In astronomy the Babylonians might amass data extending over centuries, based on careful observation
and involving considerable ingenuity of calculation. But it did not occur to them to use this mass of data as the basis for constructing a
rational
cosmology
like that
gift for
and (we must add) its inherent of the Greeks. The danger lies, of peculiar property course, in the temptation to run before one can walk. For the human reason to discover for the first time the extent of its powers is an
abstraction, with
its limitless
possibilities
intoxicating experience.
It
tends to look
accumulation of
available evidence
and in trying its a grand synthesis that is very largely its own to up not occur to the earliest natural philosophers to spend It did creation.
facts,
down on
species of animals and plants; or in developing experimental techniques whereby they might analyse the composition of various forms of
matter. That
1
is
not
Mr
(1948),
*Form can
be arrived at by empirical methods, as a happy accident supervening on die experimental manipulation of a material; or it may be a concept in the mind, that struggles into tangible shape through whatever channels it can. Their literature, philosophy and art show that the conceptual attitude to form was more deeply ingrained in the Greeks than in any other people of whom we know. To judge from the "geometrical" decoration of their early pottery, they might at that time have been totally blind to the surrounding world of natural phenomena. It was impossible for them to
of art. perceive an object, and then fluently translate this percept into a representational work After perception came the agonizing mental process of creating the concept; what die early concept of "man" looked like we can see on a "geometric" vase/
37
'What is the genesis of existing things? , that is, out of what did they come in the first place and what are they made of now? Is the whole
world ultimately of one substance or more? I have spoken of the danger of this mode of procedure, which no doubt strikes a modern scientist as in the literal sense preposterous. Yet if no one had begun
in the
science
first
place
by asking
as
and philosophy
The human mind being what it is, they could not have arisen in any other way. Even today, every scientist would admit that his experiments would be
idea, that
is,
out in the light of a guiding on the basis of a hypothesis formed in the mind but as
fruitless unless carried
yet unproved, the establishment or refutation of which gives direction to the factual inquiry. Too close an attachment to phenomena,
never lead to
such as was dictated by the practical nature of Oriental science, will scientific understanding. Scientific inquiry, as a French
scholar has put it, presupposes 'not only the love of truth for its own sake, but also a certain aptitude for abstraction, for reasoning on the
in other words, a certain philosophic spirit, for basis of pure concepts science in the strict sense is born of the bold speculation of the earliest
1
philosophers'.
The Greeks
way in
which they went beyond their predecessors and contemporaries. It is 9 the phrase Aoyov Si86vcu. The impulse 'to give a logos was the typically Greek one. Logos cannot be satisfactorily rendered by any single
English word. Faced with a set of phenomena, they felt that they must go behind them and account for their existence in the particular form
and manner in which they did exist. A complete logos is a description which at the same time explains. Besides form or structure, and ratio
or proportion, logos
definition
may mean,
all
according to
its
context, account,
and explanation
typically
Greek mind so closely connected that them by the same word? As Aristotle said, the only complete definition is one which includes a statement of the cause.
*
A fuller account of the uses of A6yos is given later in connexion with Heraclitus (pp. 420
38
R. Baccou,
ff.).
Ill
THE MILESIANS
A.
INTRODUCTION
We
have outgrown the tendency of which Cornford complained in 1907, to write the history of Greek philosophy 'as if Thales had
suddenly dropped from the sky, and as he bumped the earth ejaculated: "Everything must be made of water!"' It was a sign of the changed
outlook
that, in
preparing the
fifth
of the
Presocratic Philosophers in 1934, Walther Kranz put into effect a suggestion made by Diels himself in his preface to the fourth edition, namely to place at the beginning a chapter of extracts from early
cosmological, astronomical and gnomic writings, which in the previous editions had been relegated to an appendix. This raises the difficult
question whether the present work should follow the same plan. strong reason against doing so is the endlessly disputed authenticity
and date of the records of this 'pre-philosophical' tradition, which are for the most part preserved only as quotations in writers of a much later period. We may be sure that Hesiod's Theogony (the only extant work of its type) preceded the Milesian philosophers, but when
we come
to the fragments of Orphic cosmogony, or of the Theogony of Epimenides, it is difficult to be sure whether they may be reckoned as an influence on the Milesians or, on the contrary, as owing something to the Milesians themselves. Thus Kern saw in the fragments of
Epimenides the impact of Anaximenes, and Rohde maintained of the 'Rhapsodic Theogony' attributed to Orpheus that 'in the very few the Rhapsodies and passages in which a real coincidence exists between or Parmenides Empedokles, the poet of the Pherekydes, Herakleitos,
Rhapsodies
is
Recent opinion
is
on
Kern,
De
theogoniis-,
of
39
The Milesians
expressed in Orphic theogonical and cosmogonical fragments to the sixth century B.C., but doubts remain. All things considered, it seems
best to proceed at once to an examination of the remains of those who are usually, and not without reason, called the first of the philosophers.
The necessary reference to their actual or possible made where this examination demands it.
It is to Aristotle in the first place that
predecessors can be
those
who
and those
former he
who
first
the beginning of the new, 'physical' outlook to Thales and his successors at Miletus, hailing Thales himself as 'first founder of this kind of
1
philosophy'.
as
we have
was
justified,
that the
man whose
scientific
oudook
led
him
what he
religion to have
interests
suspected anthropobeen invented 'for the persuasion of the mob of law and utility',2 would have welcomed these
and
who
men
as his
own
something
mythical modes of
he does indeed reach out a hand, in a sudden flash of understanding, to those on the other side of the gulf, saying in a brief parenthesis that
there
is
is
also a lover
of wisdom, or
philosopher, since the material of myth also is that which has occasioned wonder in men's minds; but he makes it quite clear that the resemblance extends no further. The philosopher, he says in the same context, aims
knowledge which shall be both accurate and all-embracing, and above all shall be knowledge of causes. Only universals are true objects of knowledge: only generalization can lead to the discovery of
at a
by which Aristotle already, like a modern scientist, means general laws. Myth on the other hand, thinking in personal terms, demands rather particular causes for particular events. As Frankfort wrote: We understand phenomena, not by what makes them peculiar,
causes,
' 1
Metaph. A,
^bao.
Metaph.
B,
xoooaiS; A, 107^3.
40
Aristotle as Historian
of Philosophy
but by what makes them manifestations of general laws. But a general law cannot do justice to the individual character of each event. And
the individual character of the event
is
precisely
what
early
man
experiences most
strongly.'
understand the mentality of Aristotle is of primary importance for us as students of the Presocratics, owing to the peculiar nature of the
sources of our information about them.*
earliest authority for
To
Not only
is
he himself our
historical
work of
his
pupil
stamped with the impress of his school, and to a considerable extent of his own masterful personality.3 Here at the outset
is
Theophrastus and
note that, in the sense in which Frankfort uses the word we , he is already one of us, though separated from us by some 2300 years and from the beginnings of natural philosophy by only 250. This,
we may
incidentally,
is
some
and
his
own achievement. Some of his results, for example the structure which he attributed to the Universe, may seem absurd today; but in the method of his thought he moves easily among abstract concepts, and
his
whole
so
much
effort is directed to explanation by reference to general laws, so that he founded formal logic and was already faced with
the perennial problem of scientific inquiry: how is scientific knowledge of the individual possible at all, since science only explains by sub-
obviously
that operate universally? He has travelled far from fumbling attempts to cast off mythological explanation, and introduces the danger of distortion in his account of
early doctrines.
He was
a systematic philosopher first and a historian second, and his examination of his predecessors was explicitly directed towards eliciting how far they had travelled along the path that led to his own conception of
reality.
1
That
this
their aim,
* 3
Metaph. A, 98*bi8 and ch. 2 in general; Frankfort, Before Philosophy, 24. See the note on the sources, pp. xiii ff. That the OuaiKoSv A6^ai of Theophrastus was largely influenced by Aristotle's accounts of
Arist.
shown by J. McDiarmid (Harv. Stud, in Class. Philol. 1953). This work, however, must be used with caution. It is over-bold to make statements like that * on p. in There is nothing in Parmenides' poem to justify this interpretation* of the Way of of Opinion itself. Opinion, when we possess only a few brief quotations from the Way in Kahn, Anaximander^ 17-24. juster verdict on Theophrastus is to be found
the Presocratics has been
:
41
The Milesians
have taken tentative steps in other, and possibly even more promising directions, does not (naturally enough) occur to him.
Nevertheless the probable effect of this on the trustworthiness of what he says about them has sometimes been immensely exaggerated. sufficient to allow of a possess a large corpus of his works, quite and powers of judgment. Any just estimate of his mental quality
We
first
rank, brilliant
To speak in all time of sounds these terms of one of the leading philosophers ridiculous. Yet it is not superfluous, for it is apparently possible
and methodical, sane and cautious.
to suppose that whereas in logic, ontology, ethical and political thought, biology and zoology he generally displays these qualities in the
to assess his predecessors highest degree, yet as soon as he comes he blinded is so tradition in the philosophical by the problems and pre-
suppositions of his own thought that even any idea of the proper way to handle evidence. This
entirely at
variance with the knowledge of his mind which we gain from other portions of his work. We may add, also, first that he has a certain
he was an Ionian Greek, writing and speaking the same language as his fellow-Ionians of two or three centuries before and sharing far more of their outlook than we
advantage over us in the simple
fact that
can ever hope to do; secondly that he enjoyed a far more extensive first-hand acquaintance with the writings of some of them; and thirdly
that the
itself
amount of attention which he bestows on his predecessors is in some evidence of a genuine historical approach to his subject
which, followed out with the powers of an Aristotle, could hardly have such totally misleading results as are sometimes attributed to it. Not only did he think it proper to begin his investigation of a new topic
with a full review of previous opinions; he also wrote separate works on earlier schools of thought. His lost book on the Pythagoreans is one
which we might give a good deal to possess. To sum up, the amount of extant writing either from Aristotle's own pen or taken down by pupils from his teaching is sufficient not only to
where
guarantee the soundness of his judgment in general, but also to warn us it is most likely to fail him and to give us the material wherewith
4*
Aristotle as Historian
look, to
of Philosophy
show us where distortion is likely to arise, and of what kind. Of course when he describes the Milesians as having discovered only
the material cause of things to the neglect of the efficient, formal and * final, or castigates the atomists for lazily shelving* the problem of the motive cause, we understand that whereas his power of analysis has
raced far ahead of theirs, his historical sense has not kept pace with it sufficiently to enable him to see them in a proper perspective. The
systems of the earlier/Ajysza were not unsuccessful or partially successful attempts to fit reality into his fourfold scheme of causation, although in
the
first
they were.
we
are well acquainted with his philosophy in should not be too difficult to make the necesis
likely to be,
understanding, but a distortion of the balance of their interests by rigorous selection. He was only concerned with one facet of Milesian
thought, the 'philosophical , that is primarily the cosmogonical. Such meagre information as we have from non-Peripatetic sources about Anaximander, for instance, suggests that he had the true Ionian spirit
of universal
historic,
and that
of the
universe and of life were only introductory to a descriptive account of the earth and its inhabitants as they at present exist, containing elements
a 'mythical* or 'theological* to a 'physical* or 'natural* view of the universe came, Aristotle tells us, with Thales of
Miletus,
who
is
form what
the expression 'school* we can say with confidence that all were citizens of the same city, their lifetimes overlapped, later tradition described
their relations as those
one another, and a thread of continuity is discernible in what we know of their doctrines. To go further is to make inferences or conjectures,
2 though these are indeed probable enough.
See below, p. 75. These remarks about Aristotle's merits as a historian are expanded in Guthrie,/ffS, 1957 (0, 35-4I* a In the doxographical tradition Anaximander is StdSoxos xocl uafriTifc of Thales (Theophr. ap. Cic. Ac. Pr. n, 118 popularis et sodalis, Simpl., DK, 12x9; TroAi-nisKcd h-alpo$ (zV., DK, AI7; cf.
43
The Milesians
An
come
will best appraisal of the Milesian philosophical achievement at the end (pp. 140 ff, below). The questions which excited them
this
apparently confused and disordered world be reduced to simpler principles so that our reason can grasp what it is and how it works? What is it made of? How does change take place?
do things spring up and grow, then decline and die? How can one explain the alternation of day and night, summer and winter? They
Why
these
taking thought. They abandoned intellectual solutions. There might or substituted and mythological might not be a divine mind at the back of, or permeating, the works of nature (that was a question to which some of them sought an answer),
the
first
but
it
was no longer
wrath of Poseidon, or death caused by the arrows of Apollo or Artemis. A world ruled by anthropomorphic gods of the kind in which their gods human in their passions as well as in their outward form was a world ruled by caprice. Philosophy and science start with the bold confession of faith that not caprice but an
contemporaries believed
inherent orderliness underlies the phenomena, and the explanation of nature is to be sought within nature itself. They did not discard in a
generation all preconceptions arising from a mythical or anthropomorphic outlook. Mankind has not done that yet. But so far as we can
see,
first
to
make
xocl
on which
all
Burnet,
his
TToAhris (Strabo,
(Hippol.,
DK, AH).
Pliny in
DK,
Anaximenes ^KOUOEV 'AvoctndvSpou (Diog. Laert., DK, 13 A i); is Simpl, DK, A 5); auditory discipulus et successor (Cicero, Augustine,
For modern inferences as to the existence of a regular school cf. L. Robin, Greek Thought, 33 ,, Burnet, EGP, introd. 14, S. OsViecimski, in Charisteria T, Sinko, p. 233: *I call attention to the fact that the expression "school" is to be taken literally, in suitable proportion, of course, to the modern meaning of the term. I do not think it necessary to prove this statement here, as
suppose L. Robin and A. Rey (La Science Jans VAntlqulte II, 32) did it convincingly enough. Considering the evident continuity and consonance in principal questions of ideas, methods, and the general direction of researches of the three Milesians whom tradition always joins by such expressions as [those cited above], it would be very strange if in such an active and rich town
I
which besides the inherited old Minoan culture absorbed, too, the Egyptian and Babylonian civilisation, there were not something like either a school or brotherhood or as A. Rey (op. cit. 56) calls it "la corporation philosophico-scientifique". It could be the more so in that antiquity, above all the East, already knew different kinds of colleges, of priests, magi, astrologers, not to mention the exclusively Greek creation, Pythagoras's monastically scientific school/
as Miletus
44
Tholes
scientific
thought
is
mena conceals a framework which is radically simpler and more orderly, and so capable of being grasped by the human mind.
B.
THALES
Diogenes Laertius (i, 13) says that the Ionian philosophy started with Anaximander, but that Thales, 'a Milesian and therefore an Ionian,
instructed Anaximander'. There
late
is
much
view of this
compiler
that, so far as
regarded as a forerunner,
our knowledge goes, Thales ought to be and that the first philosophical system of
which we can say anything is that of Anaximander. The name of Thales was always held in high honour among the Greeks as that of an ideal
sage and scientist, and from the time of Herodotus onwards a considerable amount is narrated about him; but all that we have to suggest that
he founded the Ionian school of philosophy is the simple affirmation of Aristotle, who couples it with the bald statement that he regarded
water as the underlying substance out of which all things are made. This 'material principle' is described in the terms of Aristotle's own
thought, which are far from any that Thales could have used. How far the thought itself was different is a question for consideration. In any
case, Aristotle
makes
it
clear that
he
reasoning on which the statement was based, nor any details about his cosmological notions save that he believed the earth to rest on water.
felt justified in calling
In view, however, of the authority of Aristotle, and the fact that he Thales 'the founder of this type of philosophy' of those who according to Aristotle's ideas acknow(i.e. the philosophy
ledged only the 'material cause' and who were in his view the first to deserve the name of philosophers), it will be worth while examining the ancient evidence to discover, not necessarily what sort of man he
was
he was obviously a shadowy figure even to some of those who was current in the speak of him), but at least what picture of him ancient world, and what kind of achievements stood to his credit. We
(for
then go on to consider the probable implications of the statement about water which, from Aristotle to the present day, has been uni-
may
first
philosopher.
The Milesians
(i)
Date:
the eclipse
The
earliest extant
roughly 150 of his date in the following passage (i, 74, DK, A 5), which refers to the war between Lydia under Alyattes and Media under Cyaxares:
years after
author to speak of Thales is Herodotus, who lived him and gives us the most important indication
on
indecisively into
that the
its
sixth year,
an encounter took place at which happened day suddenly became of Miletus Thales predicted to the night. This is the loss of daylight which took it which place. actually lonians, fixing as its term the year in
Various dates have in the past been assigned to this eclipse, which must from Herodotus's description have approached totality, but astronomical opinion seems now agreed that it is one which took place on 28 May (22 Gregorian) 585 B.C. 1 Pliny (N.H. n, 12, 53), whose
ultimate source was the second century B.C. chronologist Apollodorus, OL 48 4 = 585/4). gives the date, if not exactly, yet to within one year (
.
This forecast of Thales, which according to Diogenes (i, 23) aroused the admiration not only of Herodotus but also of Xenophanes who was
practically his contemporary,
is
as well attested as
most
facts
of anti-
quity.
treatment of another story about Thales, that he assisted the passage of the Lydian king Croesus across the Halys by diverting the course of * the river. This ', says Herodotus, is the favourite version of the Greeks,
'
but
(i,
75). It should
be added that the date 585 for the battle between Cyaxares and Alyattes suits the historical circumstances well, now that it has been established
that the chronology of Herodotus, i, 130, which implies that Astyages son of Cyaxares succeeded his father in 594, is slightly erroneous. It
on the assumption that the fall of Astyages at the hands of Cyrus took place in the first year of the latter's reign (558), but comparison with the extant records of the Babylonian king Nabonidus shows this
rests
584 by astronomical reckoning, in which the number of the year is one less than that used by chronologists. Tannery (Pour I'hist. de la science hell^ne^ 57) still accepted the year 610, but is practically alone. There have been many discussions of this question, of which the following
1
may be
ZN,
Ency.
cited
ll
and
-
254, n. i; Boll,
rit.
9
will provide the references to others: T. L. Heath, Aristarchus, 13-18; * art. Tinsternisse* in art. Thales' in t vi, 2341 and 2353; G. J. Allman,
RE
Burnet,
EGP,
in the archonship of
Thales certainly had not the astronomical knowledge necessary to predict solar eclipses accurately for a particular region, nor to foresee
Now
whether partial or total. In particular he was ignorant of the sphericity of the earth and of the allowance to be made for parallax. Had it been otherwise, his prediction would not have been
their character,
it appears to have been, merely approximate. Herodotus the gives impression of choosing his words carefully to indicate that Thales did no more than indicate the year of the eclipse. 2 Until recently it was believed that he could have done this with a fair chance of success
isolated, nor, as
by means of
from
a period of calculation commonly known as the Saros, the Sumerian character sdr. This is a cycle of 223 lunar months
(18 years 10 days 8 hours) after which eclipses both of the sun and moon do in fact repeat themselves with very little change, and its
probable use
Boll and Sir
by Thales was accepted by authorities of the calibre of Thomas Heath. The character itself, as Heath knew, in
addition to even less relevant meanings, had only a numerical value (3600). Its first association with an astronomical meaning is in the
Suda,3 a passage which was only brought into connexion with the cycle of 223 lunations by an erroneous conjecture of Halley's in 1691,
whence
1
it
its
way
into
all
the textbooks. 4
Neugebauer
So already Ed. Meyer in RE, n, 1865, who gives Astyages's reign as 584-550. Cf. How and Wells, Commentary on Herodotus (1911, repr. 1949), I, 94, 383; Heath, op. cit. 15, n. 3. a C. Brugmann (Idg. Forsch. xv, 87-93) argued that the original etymological meaning of iviourds was not 'year* but resting-place* of the sun (from Sviofoo; cf. e.g. Od. x, 469), i.e. solstice. Fired by this interpretation, Diels suggested (Newjahrlb. 1914, 2) that Herodotus was
*
using it in this original sense. If so, Thales's prediction was that the eclipse would take place before the summer solstice, i.e. before the end of June 585. This would tally with the conjecture that it was based on the Egyptian eclipse of 603 as being one cycle earlier (see below), for that took
place
it is
on
18
ed. of Diels's
May (Gregorian). But the suggestion has received little notice Kranz in own Vorsokratiker writes *Da Herod, ein ganzes Jahr Spielraum lasst.
his fifth
.'
and
no doubt more probable that Herodotus would use the word in its by then far commoner sense of 'year*. Neugebauer (/be. cz*.) seems to be ignorant of Diels's suggestion. 3 Byzantine lexicon of c. A.D. 1000, commonly known until recently as *Suidas*. 4 This has been demonstrated by O. Neugebauer, The Exact Sciences in Antiquity^ 136; cf. 114. In interpreting Babylonian material Neugebauer is on his own ground, but some misconclusion of giving about his handling of authorities is aroused when he relates to Thales the not JR.. M. Cook's article on the lonians mJHS, 1946, 98 (*My tentative conclusion is that we do
47
The Milesians
calls
is
it
that
even
a beautiful example of a historical myth. His conclusion after 300 B.C. the Babylonian texts only suffice to say
that a solar eclipse is excluded or is possible. Before 300 the chances of successful prediction were still smaller, though there are indications
that an eighteen-year cycle
was used
the
moon. The conclusions of Schiaparelli are similar. 1 We see, however, from an early Assyrian text, that to say that a solar eclipse is excluded or is possible' was precisely what they did, and that it sufficed
for the astrological and religious purposes in which alone they were interested. The tablet in question contains the words :
Concerning the eclipse of the moon. .the observation was made and the .And when for an eclipse of the sun we made obsereclipse took place. was made and it did not take place. That which the observation vation, * I saw with my eyes to the King rny Lord I send.
.
Drastic political consequences are inferred from the eclipse of the moon, and, as Tannery remarks, the important thing for these people was not so much to make exact predictions as simply to see to it that
no
eclipse occurred unannounced. Considering his ample opportunities for contact with Orientals,
it is
very likely that Thales was acquainted with the limited means of prediction at their disposal, and he could very well have said that an in the year which ended during eclipse was possible somewhere
585 B.C.
He may,
as has
eighteen years earlier. That the eclipse of 585 occurred at the time and place of a battle, was nearly total, and had the dramatic consequence of causing the combatants to
visible in
which was
Egypt in 603,
cease fighting and negotiate a truce, was a happy chance by which his statement, in retrospect, acquired very naturally an air of precision that
to say definitely whether in the eighth and seventh centuries the lonians were generally the pioneers of Greek progress, but that on the present evidence it is at least as probable that they were not'), without mentioning that earlier, on p. 92, Mr Cook has expressly excluded the sixth-century philosophers from this judgment.
1
know enough
G.
non potevano
avevano
*
Schiaparelli, Scr. sidla storia delta astron. antica, I, 74: 'Quanto alle ecclisse di sole, essi riuscire, data la loro ignoranza della sfericit della terra, e la nessuna idea che
dell'efTetto della parallasse.'
From
first
published
coveries, 409. Cf. Schiaparelli, loc.cit., Tannery, Pour I* hist, de la science hell.
3
Heath,
op. cit.
i6
DieJs, Neuejahrll,
xxxm,
2, n. i, Boll in
i.
Thales as Astronomer
its
notoriety
among
his country-
important for two reasons: it fixes a date for what may be called the beginning of Greek philosophy, or at least for the
eclipse
is
The
activity
man whom the Greeks themselves called the first of it accounts for the and philosophers, exaggerated reputation as an astronomer which he enjoyed among his countrymen of later centuries.
of the
To take the latter point first, Eudemus, the pupil of Aristotle, in his lost
work on astronomy, made
(a) Thales
[sic].
a statement which
is
(D.L.
i,
KOCTCC TIVOCS as
was the first astronomer: he foretold eclipses and solstices 23. T. H. Martin may have been right in regarding the words part of the quotation, in which case Eudemus would not even
be taking responsibility for the statement himself. See Heath, op. cit. 14. More probably, however, they are due to Diogenes.) (i) Thales was the first to discover the eclipse of the sun (e$pe TrpcoTO$ qAtou exAetyiv) and that its period with respect to the solstices is not
.
(Dercyllides ap.
Theon of Smyrna,
battle
He foretold the eclipse of the sun which took place at the time of the between the Medes and the Lydians. .. (Clem. Alex. Strom, n, 41
.
St.,DK,A 5 .)
In
all
what
probability the last of these statements represents most closely Eudemus actually said. Even if he did attribute to Thales suffi-
cient astronomical
knowledge to discover the cause of eclipses and them accurately, he did so no doubt by an unjustified inference predict from the impressive incident of 585. Later writers expressly credit Thales with the discovery that solar eclipses were due to the intervention of the
moon
(Aet. n, 24,
owes its light to the sun (Aet. n, ments were quite impossible for Thales, and
DK, A 17 a), and that the moon 28, 5, DK, A 17^). These achievei,
his ignorance
becomes
even clearer when we see the fantastic explanation of eclipses given by his associate Anaximander.
To
by
return to the question of date, the surest indication is provided the eclipse, which agrees well with the statement in Diogenes
title
by Apollodorus
49
will
The Milesians
chronologist's usual method of fixing the floruit by some outstanding event in a man's life (for Thales doubtless the eclipse), and accounting him forty years old at that date. In that case he dated Thales's birth
in 01.39.1 (624)
not 35.1 as our text of Diogenes says which with agrees Diogenes's other statement that he died in Ol. 58 (548-5) aged seventy-eight. There were other late reports that he lived to
may be content to know that he lived at ninety or a hundred. Miletus in the time of Alyattes and Croesus kings of Lydia, Cyaxares and Astyages of Media, and Cyrus the Persian, and was an almost
exact contemporary of Solon of Athens.
We
(2)
Family
Herodotus
it
(i,
would be
170) says that his earliest forbears were Phoenician, and blood at the very interesting to find a trace of Semitic
beginning of Greek philosophy; but Diogenes in quoting this rightly adds that most writers represent him as a genuine Milesian of distinHis father's name, Examyes, is native Carian no and his mother bore the unlikely ancestry for a citizen of Miletus Greek name of Cleobulina. Diogenes explains the Phoenician element
guished family.
by
the phrase 'descendants of Cadmus and Agenor , and Zeller suggested that the confusion arose through Thales's ancestors being
Cadmeians of Boeotia who, as Herodotus elsewhere says, came over with the Ionian colonists (ZN, I, 255, n. i; cf. Hdt. i, 146). Cadmus
was, of course, in Greek mythology son of Agenor, King of Tyre, whence he had come to Boeotia to found the city of Thebes. 1
(3)
Traditional character
list
of the Seven Sages, which in our extant authorities goes back to Plato (Prot. 343 A), the name of Thales was constant, and he was often regarded as the foremost. This
In the fluctuations of the traditional
gave him a kind of ideal character, and many of the acts and sayings associated in the popular mind with sophia were attributed to him as
1
Interesting,
even
if
not
many
(" redskins*),
suggestion that the story of Cadmus, and may really belong to Minoans. (T. J.
35.)
Character of Thales
a matter of course. Everything of this kind that we are told about him must be classed as anecdote, but is of interest as showing at least the
kind of character that he had in the eyes of the Greeks themselves. He had a reputation for practical statesmanship. Herodotus (i, 170)
praises
him
cities
for his wise advice that in face of the Persian threat the
Ionian
ment
common centre of governand Diogenes (i, 25) relates a story that he dissuaded Miletus from making an alliance with Croesus. Plutarch (Solon, 2,
should federate, setting up a
1
in Teos,
DK, AII)
mentions the tradition that he engaged in trade, and the by Herodotus (i, 75), that he diverted
the course of the Halys for Croesus and his army, shows a reputation for skill in engineering. His observation of the Little Bear as a better
standard than the Great Bear for finding the Pole, mentioned by Callimachus (Pfeiffer, 1923, pp. 43 ff.), indicates a practical interest
in navigation.
Little Bear,
The
by
the
whereas the Greeks, according to Aratus (Phaen. 37-9) and Ovid (Trist. iv, 3, 1-2), used the Great Bear. Similarly he is said to
have put his geometrical knowledge to practical use in measuring the pyramids (Hieronymus of Rhodes, third century B.C., ap. D.L. I, 27)
at sea
(Eudemus
ap. Procl.
EucL
DK, A
20).
All this builds up an impressive picture of a practical genius and man of affairs in which there is no doubt some truth. The title of SopTios was
granted in his day, as for example to Solon, on grounds of practical wisdom, and a similar picture is given of Thales's follower Anaxi-
mander. Nevertheless, once he had achieved in the popular mind the status of the ideal man of science, there is no doubt that the stories
about him were invented or selected according to the picture of the philosophic temperament which a particular writer wished to convey.
Immediately
after telling
how
alliance
with
Croesus, Diogenes says that Heraclides Ponticus, the pupil of Plato, in a dialogue) as saying that he had lived in solitude represented him (i.e.
and kept apart from public affairs. The most amusing example of mutually cancelling propaganda is provided by the stories of the olive1 Though in G. Thomson's opinion die suggestion would have had no value from a military Sardis (The First Philosophers, 253). point of view in the contemporary situation after the fall of
51
The Milesians
presses
and of the
fall
into a well.
is
The former
is
told
by
Aristotle
by means of his skill in it was still winter that while Thales was able to meteorology predict the coming season would be a bumper one for olives. He accordingly
(PoL A, 1259 a 6), an^
to the effect that
all
was able
wanted them
own once. He
price
thus
demonstrated that
it is
easy for philosophers to make money if they not their aim, and the story was told, says Aris-
who
The
it
tale is
is
to prove that philosophy is of no practical use. too much for Aristotle's critical mind, and he comments
that this
men
fastened
on account of his wisdom. 1 Plato, on the other hand, in the Theaetetus (174 A), wants to show that philosophy is above mere its lack of any utilitarian taint is its practical considerations and that on
to Thales
He how
therefore says nothing about the olive-presses, but Thales, when engaged in star-gazing, fell into a well,
and was laughed at by a pert servant-girl for trying to find out what was going on in the heavens when he could not even see what was at his own feet. The process of selection persists, and a modern scholar,
who
wishes to
show
were 'not
recluses
engaged in
which he
pondering upon abstract questions. .but active practical men' (in is probably right), mentions the story of the olive-presses as
typical of Thales's reputation without a
word about
the well. 2
(4)
Mathematics
In mathematics, Thales was universally believed to have introduced geometry into Greece, having become acquainted with the study during
his travels in
1
it
EucL
Yet
this is the
Professor Cherniss
when he
reports that Thales was said to have regarded water as the beginning of all things, all he had really found was the statement that the earth floats on water, from which he made up the rest.
(/. Hist. Ideas, 1951, 321.)
*
i,
31.
The star-gazing
story
fathered
on Thales
in Aristoph. Clouds,
1713.
Thales as Mathematician
65. 3$, Fried!., DK, AII). following theorems:
(1) (2)
He was
specifically credited
with the
(3) If
(4)
(5)
The
is
are given.
comes from Proclus (DK, AII and 20), whose authority was Eudemus. Theorem (4) (actually in the form He was the first to inscribe a right-angled triangle in a circle') is quoted by Diogenes (i, 24) from Pamphila, a
ascription to Thales of theorems (i)-(3)
*
The
and
(5)
compiler of the first century A.D. It is impossible to estimate the actual extent of Thales' s achievement. The temptation to fasten particular discoveries on to individuals with a general reputation for wisdom was
strong in antiquity. The story goes that when he had succeeded with no. 4 he sacrificed an ox, exactly as Pythagoras is said to have done on
proving the theorem which commonly bears his name. Theorem (5) associated with the practical feat of measuring the distance of ships
sea. This,
is
at
of the height of the pyramids by measuring their shadows with which he was also credited (Hiero5 nymus ap. D.L. I, 27, Pliny, N.H. xxxvx, 82, Plut. Conv. 147 A,
however,
DK
A 21), could have been accomplished by an empirical rule without any understanding of the geometrical propositions involved, as Burnet
1 pointed out.
It
that,
even
if
we had
unimpeachable statements in ancient authorities that Thales 'proved' this or that theorem, the word 'proof has a meaning only in relation
to
its historical
context.*
Since
no
EGP,
Cf.
mathematical construction or proof may vary from age to age, and indeed in early Greek mathematics probably varied from generation to generation/ Of Thales's theorem (3) above, Eudemus actually says that it was discovered by Thales, but that the scientific proof (ImoTnuoviidi <5ar68eif is)
ap. Procl.
EucL
p.
299 Friedl.).
53
The Milesians
they would easily attribute to them the content which the word implied own day. Nevertheless, without claiming certainty in details,
reasonably say that there was some truth in the tradition
in their
we may
followed
by
Proclus, that Thales, besides the knowledge that he we know to have been limited to the solution
*
of practical problems, as in land-measurement), made many discoveries for himself, and in many laid the foundations for those who followed
him, employing an approach that inclined
(KocdoAiKcbTspov),
now
to the theoretical
now
The
Greek
from the
(5)
Water as
*arche
the unity
of all
things
This impulse to generalize, to discard the individual and accidental and bring out the universal and permanent, appears in a more extreme form
in the statement
which
is
generally agreed to constitute his claim to is, the statement that the first
first
doubtful whether any later occurrence of it is must therefore consider it carefully independent of his authority. in the context in which he it. First of all, he tells us that this places
is
from
is
of
all
We
is
what
'is
said'
of Thales.
the question whether Thales left any have only the statements of later writers than
It
On
down
meaning
course the word 'publish' had little nothing, in his day; but at least the confusion of later writers and the
it
and of
plain that
no writings of
his
were available in
1
Aristotle's time
He wrote nothing but a Nautical Astronomy (Simpl)j set forth his views in verse (Plut.); wrote a work On First Principles in at least two books (Galen, who quotes a passage containing obvious anachronisms as being from the second he wrote the Nautical book) some
;
say
nothing,
Astronomy being by Phocus of Samos, others that he wrote only two treatises, on the solstice and the equinox respectively (D.L.; all the passages in DK AI, B i and 2). Proclus (A*Q) says curiously that in his statement of die proposition that the angles at the base of an isosceles are
triangle
Thales followed the archaic fashion by using the word 'similar* (6po(as) instead of 'equal' (foots); but, in view of the obvious ignorance and confusion of other writers, little significance can be
attached to
this.
equal,
54
Water as 'Arche*
had no means of knowing the reasons which led Thales to make his statement, and when he ascribes a possible line of thought to him makes
no
guessing. The frankness and caution with which Aristotle introduces any statement about Thales are highly
is
reassuring, and we may feel confident of the distinction between what he has found on record and what is his own inference. Referring to what he has read or heard he says: Thales is said to have declared', 'they say he said', 'from what is recorded he seems to have thought';
*
to his
own
so
With
much of
'first
which he
introduces the
principle' of Thales.
principles which were in the nature of matter were the only principles of all things: that of which all things that are consist, and from which they first come to be and into which they are resolved as a final state (the substance
its
is
the element
and principle of
and therefore they think that nothing is either generated or destroyed, since this sort of entity is always preserved, as we say that Socrates neither comes to be absolutely when he comes to be beautiful or musical, nor ceases to be when he loses these characteristics, because the substratum, Socrates himself, remains. So it is, they say, with everything
all
things,
else: there is
always some permanent substance, or nature (9uai$), either is conserved in the generation of the rest from it.
principles they do not all agree, of philosophy, says that the principle is reason declared that the earth rests on water. His suppo-
On
the
Thales,
sition
may have
all
creatures is moist, and that warmth generated from moisture and all which lives by it; and that from things come to be is their first principle. for his Besides this, another reason supposition would be that the semina of and water is for moist things die origin of all things have a moist nature,
their nature.
think that the very early writers, who first, long before the present generation, wrote about the gods, also had this view of nature; for they named Oceanus and Tethys as the parents of generation, and made the gods
Some
swear by water in the oath by the river which they called Styx: what is oldest is most revered, and one swears by what one most reveres. Whether this view of nature is in fact ancient and primitive must perhaps remain in
55
The Milesians
cause in this way. doubt, but Thales at least is said to have described the first same the in No one would think Hippo worthy of inclusion class, owing to
the triviality of his thought.
In
account of Thales's cosmological views, they are of a later age. already set forth in the abundant philosophical terminology Ionian could have expressed his ideas in terms of substance No
this,
our
earliest
early
and
attribute (ovoioc
and
Trcc0o$),
or opposed to relatively, or of a substratum (yrroKgiuevov) of a now These element (oroixelov). ordinary speech, distinctions, part were only achieved after much strenuous logical analysis on the part of Plato and its elaboration into a technical vocabulary by Aristotle him(drrXcos) as
needed here, but in spite of the close interrelation between language and thought, it does not necessarily follow that what
self.
Great caution
is
Aristotle
is
giving
is
we
all
we may
safely call
them
the first natural philosophers, meaning by they were the first to attempt on a rational basis that simplification of reality which has been the quest of the human mind in all ages. As a modern writer on
this that
scientific
it,
Greeks:
There seems to be a deep-rooted tendency in the human mind to seek. something that persists through change. Consequently the desire for that what appears to explanation seems to be satisfied only by the discovery be new and different was there all the time. Hence the search for an under.
.
conserved in spite of lying identity, a persistent stuff, a substance that is 2 of which these changes can be explained. qualitative changes and in terms
1 Not only Aristotle, but a historian of philosophy in any age, is compelled to interpret earlier views in the language of his own day. Even the arrogance of Aristotle's assumption that he knew what his predecessors wanted to say better than they did themselves is an arrogance of which none of us is wholly innocent. It was Whitehead who wrote: 'Everything of importance has been said before by someone who did not discover it.' The ideas here attributed to Thales and his successors by no means involve *tlie definition of identity and difference as formulated in con-
sequence of Eleatic logic, and the distinction between subject and by Socrates and Plato' (McDiarmid, Theoph. on the Presoc. Causes, Aristotle *can seriously comment on die material theory of Homer in of the physicists* is quite unfair. Thales is for him the apx^iyos Tfjs
3
attribute as
92),
the
ToiaCnr^s 9iAoaro9ia$.
L. S, Stebbing,
404.
Simplification
ofReality
is
Aristotle. It
as evident in religious
as in philosophical accounts of the world. As Professor remarked, to introduce unity and tidiness into the world is
Broad has
something
which appeals
and,
to man's aesthetic
when pushed to its one and only one kind of material. 1 It was natural that the first philosophical simplification should also be the most extreme. The impulse to simplification was there, and thought had not yet advanced sufficiently for a consideration of the
difficulties it
than to his rational interests, extreme limits, leads to the view that there is
less
no
efforts
of the
earliest philosophers.
Although the terms 'substratum' and 'element were beyond the reach of the Milesians, Aristotle uses another word, arche, to describe their primary substance, which, whether they employed it in this way themselves or not, was in common use in their time and well within
their
($)
comprehension in the senses of (a) starting-point or beginning, originating cause. So used it is common in Homer, and the
far
usual translation of
is
not
from
it
in the Aristotelian passages as '(fim) principle the mark. In all probability (though the point has been
it
was already used of the primary substance by Thales's younger contemporary Anaximander (see below, p. 77), and it is a convenient term which we may regard as standing for a twofold condisputed)
ception in the thought of the Milesians. It means, first, the original state out of which the manifold world has developed and, secondly, the permanent ground of its being, or, as Aristotle would call it, the subAll things were once water (if that is the arche\ and to the philosopher all things are still water, since in spite of the changes which
stratum.
it
has undergone it remains the same substance (arche or physis, them all, for there is principle or permanent constitution) throughout
in fact
no
other.
Since
it is
Aristotle in particular
who
insists
on
the
distinction
between the
first
arche of
1
all
who
who
believed in a single
more than
one,
The Mind and its Place in Nature, 76. 2 For a fuller discussion of the meaning of dpxi !, see W. A. Heidel in CP, 1912, 2I5& Kirk (KR, 89) conjectures that only the first sense may have been in Thales's mind. See also his
cautious remarks
on pp.
9 if.
57
The Milesians
it is
worth noting
that
it
is
therefore not simply the outcome of an arbitrary classification of his own. The author of the Hippocratic treatise on the Nature of Man^ which was probably written about 400 B.C., 1 pours scorn on the unverifiable theories of
non-medical philosophers
who
think that
man
is
composed of
air, fire,
which cannot be
'that whatever clearly discerned in him'. 'They say', he continues, exists is one, being at the same time one and all, but they do not agree on its name. One of them says that this universal unity is air, another
fire,
own view by
(6)
Mythical precursors
For Thales's choice of water as the arche various reasons have been suggested, from Aristotle down to modern times. They may be divided into the mythical and the rational. Those who think that Thales was,
perhaps subconsciously, influenced by the mythical presuppositions of the society in which he was born and bred have again a choice, between
Eastern and Greek mythology. Some point to the undoubted fact that he lived in a country familiar with both Babylonian and Egyptian ideas, and, according to an unchallenged tradition, had himself visited
Egypt.
which was
mythology. Both were river-cultures, the one based on the two rivers of Mesopotamia and the other entirely
It
dependent for its life on the annual flooding of the Nile. boast of the Egyptian priests that not only Thales but also
learned from Egypt to
1
was the
Homer had
call
all
things (Plut.
F. Heinimann, Nomos und Pkysis, 158 with n. i. Cf. W. A. Heidel on Arist. Metaph. 1069325, 988 b 22 and other passages (Proc. Am. Acad. 45, 191011, 122, n. 166): *It is evident that Aristotle is here enlarging upon the criticism of the monists contained in Hippocrates,
IT. <pOcr,
dvOp.
i.'
De
Nat. Horn,
&v
TIS.
.
i (vi,
32
Littre").
The
is
speaking of
Some
have persisted until the end of the fourth century, but if any known thinker called earth the sole Apx^ it can only have been Xenophanes (pp. 383 f., below), nor is it easy to identify the contemporary champion of fire. 3 A Babylonian origin for Thales's theory was suggested as long ago as 1885 by Berthelot
(Les Qrigines de Valchimu^ 25 1).
58
Os. 34,
year the Nile submerged the narrow banks, and receded leaving it covered with
in
mud
of an incredible
fertility,
extraordinarily rapid. their livelihood it was easy to believe that all life arose in the first place from water. The earth itself had arisen out of Nun, the primordial
which the growth of new life was For those who crowded along this strip to get
still
surrounding
it
like the
everywhere beneath it as Thales said and also Homeric Oceanus. At first the waters covered
everything, but gradually sank until a small hillock appeared, to become the seat of primeval life. On this hillock the creator-god made his first appearance. Among Egyptian peasants the belief still persists
that the fertile slime left behind
by
the Nile in
its
the
power of actually originating life, and this belief in the spontaneous origin of life out of mud or slime will shortly meet us in Anaximander.
mentioned by Aristotle
The attribution to Thales of the notion that the earth floats on water, in the passage already quoted, is put by him rather more fully in the De Caelo (294 a 28)
:
rests
to us, and
attributed to Thales
of Miletus, namely
whose nature
or similar substances, to rest upon water, though none of them could rest on air.
because
it
wood
The Babylonian cosmology of the Enuma Elish, dating from perhaps the middle of the second millennium B.C., gives a similar picture of the primacy of water. I quote from the description by T. Jacobsen in
the
book
Before Philosophy, which contains excellent accounts for the and Mesopotamian ideas. After quoting of
This description presents the earliest stage of the universe as one of watery chaos. The chaos consisted of three intermingled elements: Apsu, who represents the sweet waters; Ti'amat,
identified
who
and
Mummu, who
with certainty but may represent cloud-banks and cannot as yet be mist. These three types of water were mingled in a large undefined mass. There was not yet even the idea of a sky above or firm ground beneath; all was water; not even a swampy bog had been formed, still less an island; and
there were yet
no gods.
59
The Milesians
From
cosmogony proceeds,
as in
Hesiod,
by
a series of genealogies.
turn out to be
male and female principles who can unite, beget and give birth. Such stories are common in Near Eastern lands, together with those
of great floods (a frequent fact of actual experience in Mesopotamia, as the inhabitants of Iraq learned to their cost in 1954) whereby the all-
pervading water sought to reclaim what was once its own. We need only remind ourselves of the Hebrew cosmogony, with its description
of die
spirit
of
talk
of
Olm-
water of
Thales
is
Garden of Eden story'. 1 Parallels from Greek mythology suggested themselves, as we have seen, to Aristotle himself. When he mentions Oceanus and Tethys
(Metaph. 983 b 30, above, xiv. Line 201 runs:
p. 55),
he
is
KCCI larjTipcc
TrjOOv
And
and
line
Oceanus,
first
246:
'(OKSOCVOU 6$ Trep yeveais TrAvreacri
Thwrca
all.
Oceanus,
who
is first
parent to them
Oceanus dwelt
of the earth
(//.
was
and
the great stream which flowing back upon itself (//. circled the whole earth; he was the source of all rivers,
wells
(//. xxi, 196). the origin of all things
xvm,
399) en-
sea, springs
interested in
cosmogony, and would take from earlier myths such portions as he wished. In Oceanus and Tethys we at least have male and female
principles of water
who
and the
parallel
with Apsu and Ti'amat is striking enough. The Greek myth itself may reflect the Oriental 2 Those Greek mythographers who were interested
1
This was suggested long ago by E. H. Meyer. See the critical remarks of F. Lukas, gonien y 154, n., and now U. Holscher, Hermes, 1953, 385, n. 3, 387.
Kosmo-
60
in Thales
cosmogony, however, though keeping Oceanus in a high position do not seem to have placed him at die very For Hesiod he is, like Pontus the sea, son of Earth and beginning.
Heaven, nor
first
is
came
in the earliest
Orphic theogonies.
Consideration of these suggestions of a possible origin for Thales's idea is justified by the interest of the subject, but it must be
that they are all conjectural This applies also to the rational explanations which follow.
(7) Rational explanations
emphasized
reason likely to occur to a modern mind is that water is the substance which can actually be observed, without only any apparatus of experiment such as was not available to to Thales, change, according
first
The
to its temperature, into solid, liquid and gaseous form. That therefore is the reason given for Thales's choice by some modern scholars, for example Burnet. But it was not the reason that occurred to
Aristotle,
and though he, like ourselves, was making a conjecture, it is possible that he came nearer to the mind of his Ionian predecessor. For him, the most likely thoughts to have been in Thales's mind are those which
Hence he observes that food and semen always contain moisture, and that the very warmth of life is a damp warmth. The connexion between heat and animal life, obvious to
experience,
*
was
1
insisted
it is it is
on
as essential
and
today. Aristotle himself speaks elsewhere of obvious that this is also a wet, or damp, heat,
provided by the blood. At death two things happen at once. The body goes cold, and it dries up. uyp6$, indeed, owing to these associations in the Greek mind, is a word rich in meaning which cannot be imparted
by any single English equivalent. Moist*, yes, but that will hardly do when Theocritus applies it to a bow as being flexible, when Plato
describes Eros,
applies
it
also
De
in the
12,
quoted
61
The Milesians
of dancers,
Xenophon of
.
Liddell-Scott-Jones)
Burnet (followed by Ross) calls the reasoning which Aristotle here attributes to Thales physiological , and suggests that Aristotle may
*
5
earlier thinker
to
be true of
Hippon, the man whom he dismisses in this same passage as too trivial 1 a thinker to be worth consideration. To introduce modem departmental distinctions
physiology and meteorology in speaking of 2 this early period is a serious anachronism* The thought here attributed to Thales does not link him with a later age when physiology is
like
beginning to show itself as a special interest among others; rather it shows him to be still under the influence of the more primitive stage
when
all
life.
We
saw
how, in the mythical cosmogonies of the Near East, the belief that everything was water was closely and directly connected with the
observation of its properties as the giver of
life.
acquainted with Egyptian ideas, and nothing is more likely than that these ancient notions were still at the back of his mind and directing his
thought along certain lines, even though, at the conscious level, he had made a deliberate break with mythology and was seeking a rational
account.
Moreover, the
line
consorts well with the only other remarks about the general nature of things which tradition ascribed to him.
(8) Self-change
Before turning to these, we may consider a little further the general reasons which are likely to have impelled him to choose water as the
arche primarily on the grounds that, as Aristotle says, it seemed to to be the stuff of life. These reasons are not far to seek.
1
him
Hippon was a figure of the mid-fifth century, mentioned again by Aristotle in D* Anima (405 b 2) as teaching that the soul is water. * Moreover, as Professor Baldry has pointed out (CQ, 1932, 28), an interest in birth and other phenomena connected with sex is a regular feature of primitive societies long before other
notice Aristotle's reference to the wetness of semen as a aspects of biology are thought of. possible reason for Thales's choice (cf. Baldry, p. 33). McDiarmid (Theophr. on the Presoc. Causes) unfortunately repeats the statement that 'at the time of Thales the prevailing interest
We
EGP,
48-9.
62
Hylo^oism
We
alike.
come
here to
something characteristic of
all
three Milesians
totle (as it
more advanced, and highly analytical, mind of an Aristhe notion of or principle cause, dpxn or amov, appeared to be
the
To
full
understanding of
phenomenon it was necessary to analyse it into its various components. It was not the stuff from which the enough to name the material
arche,
world is made.
it is
one only) appear in so many different forms? What is the cause into the change multiplicity of phenomena? Why not a dead, static world? Besides the one material substance, one must also discover the force which is at work producing movement and change within it. 'Presumably*, he writes, in explicit criticism of these same Milesians,
of
its
it is
itself that causes itself to change, just as neither wood the cause of the of either of change them, nor does the wood manufacture a bed nor the bronze a statue. There is else which is
nor bronze
something
the cause of the change. And to seek this should call it: the cause whence comes the
is
we
984321).
it,
then
itself.
indeed one
may
is
little
reflexion
on the pioneer
and the
undeveloped
clusion.
state
What he dismisses as absurd, that 'the substratum itself causes itself to change', does in fact more or less represent their view. In this introductory book of the he notes that none of the Metaphysics, monist philosophers made earth the each of primary substance,
though
turn (989aj). This meant little to him, but is perhaps significant nevertheless. In his more advanced view, what he called the four corporeal elements, or simple bodies, were all alike mere matter. All would remain inert were there not some motive
its
cause at
'if we would understand the sixth-century we must disabuse our minds of the atomistic conception
To them
1
there
as dead, inert
F.
M. Cornford,
The Milesians
matter,
and
it
for
them
to see
any
logical
necessity to divide their first principle into a material and a motive element. In water or air or fire as the sole fount of being,
its
inherent mobility.
Water
is
shows an apparently causeless restlessness, air life-giving, rushes hither and thither in the form of wind, fire leaps and flickers and feeds on other substances, and became later to Heraclitus literally the
sea
like this as quaint to speak of those who thought as themselves interested in physiology. Rather they reveal being still on
life
and the
of the world.
It is
the threshold of rational thought, nearer than we or Aristotle to the animism of the pre-scientific and the childish mind. Earth would not
serve their purpose as the arche, for they needed something which should be not only the material of change, but also its potential author. 1 This the other elements could be because to these early
thinkers they were alive. Aristotle had reached a stage of thought when to call water or air a living, divine power was no longer possible, but
enough to see his predecessors in a proper historical perspective and so do justice to their state of mind, the state of mind of an age before any distinction had been thought of between
far
spirit (or life)
reason the term hylozoists, commonly applied to the has been criticized as misleading, on the ground that it Milesians, suggests theories which explicitly deny the separate reality of matter
this
For
and
spirit?
We
this
itself,
which seems rather to suggest the truth, namely the state of mind of men who still had no clear conception of a distinction between the two.
it
is
above
all
to the spiritual
among
first
principles.
It
denotes
all
ment
1
between material and non-material, are prepared to maintain in arguthat nothing in fact exists which has not its origin in material
phenomena.
To
Cf. Simpl. Phys* 25 . 5i6 -rfiv yfiv SvoKlvrrrov Kl Suoyer&pATiTov oftaov oO -rrdvu TI fi{crocv dpXf)v OTro0a6act, For a similar animism in the thought of children see the work of Jean Piaget, as illustrated in The Child's Conception of the World^ The Child's Conception of Causality and later
books.
Burnet,
GP
>
12, n. 3,
Ueberweg-Praechter,
i,
p. 42.
To
return to Thales,
we have
considerations
making
it
water as arche
The
him.
by
Aristotle.
De
to have regarded the soul as a motive force, since he said that the lodestone has a soul because it makes the iron move. 3 are the more inclined to believe him because it was in fact a universal
We
and essential character of psyche motive being power. Secondly, Aristotle also said that Thales considered all things to be full of gods, and connected this on
as
its
Greek idea
own account (adding the characteristic 'perhaps') with the belief of other thinkers that 'soul is mingled in the whole* (De An. i,
his
Laws (8996)
things are full of gods', without ascribing name, and the late compilation of
Heraclitus the statement that
'all
all
by
Hence some have thought it to be one of those floating apophthegms which tended to become attached to anyone famous for his wisdom.*
We may say, first, that Plato at any rate does not attribute it to anyone
else,
and
that Aristotle
is
statement
related
a better authority than Diogenes, whose doubtless based on the well-known story about Heraclitus,
is
by
some
callers,
seeing
him warming
himself at the kitchen stove, hesitated to enter his house, but he told
1
1 66,
n. 12.
Burners reference to Arist Part. Anim. 645 a 17 in this I, 44. connexion (EGP, 50, n. 3; not 64537) seems irrelevant, and his statement that 'Here too there * are gods' means only that nothing is more divine than anything else* is surely extraordinary.
So Ueberweg-Praechter,
65
The Milesians
them not
to be afraid, 'for there were gods there too'. Even if this it would be difficult to know what philosophical
it.
significance to attach to
Secondly, there
It
is
all
able animism, or animatism, of the Greeks, which makes it all the more shared the belief himself. Study of the likely that he should have
Milesian thinkers reveals a close affinity between some of their beliefs and the general contemporary climate of thought. The difference
a crucial one
lies in their
fit
approach to these
into a rational
and determination to
them
the meagre tradition about Thales gives us a glimpse of this. That he saw no distinction between animate and inanimate
is
emphasized by Diogenes (i, 24) on the authority of Aristotle and he attributed even to the Hippias: 'Aristotle and Hippias say that
basing his conviction on the behaviour of the magnet and of amber.' If this and the other passages imply, as suggested above, an unconscious relic of mythological thinking, they
inanimate a share in
life,
show how completely the conscious mind of Thales has left such a stage behind. His argument has a scientific quality, and he attempted to base it on observation of the striking and unexplained phenomenon
also
An interesting point arises here, though as it is even more speculative than most of the things
be said about Thales, it is perhaps best confined to a footnote. Burnet (EGP, 50) agrees he probably did say there was soul in the magnet and amber (this statement not having the character of a floating apophthegm), but argues that we should not suppose him to have generalized from this; for *to say the magnet and amber are alive is to imply, if anything, that other things are not*. (So also Ueberweg-Praechter, i, 45, and Oswiecimski, Thales, 249.) Prima facie this is plausible: the noticeable thing about the behaviour of magnetic substances is its difference from that of other bodies. But the observation of it in something which was neither animal nor vegetable may well have had the opposite effect on the earliest scientific mind. Moreover, amber only exhibits its peculiar property when heated, whether by friction or otherwise, and this might naturally suggest to Thales that other kinds of matter would equally betray their psychic character if we could discover the right way to make them reveal it. If so, this is the earliest Greek instance of an appreciation of the value of experiment. The argument of Burnet would apply equally well to the statement that all things are water. On the surface it is the contrast between the wetness of water, shared by other moist substances, and the nature of, say, iron, that naturally strikes a beholder. It is only under heat that the metal
that can
that
reveals
its
property of liquefying.
66
i,
3, i
(Dox. 276),
after
arguments by Aristotle that the sperm of animals is moist and that plants are nourished by moisture added a third: that the fire of the sun and stars and the whole
itself,
cosmos, are nourished by exhalations from water'. Heidel notes, 1 was to the Greeks the nutritive element
fire is
Moisture, as
excellence, as
par
the motive element, and fire is 'fed 5 by it, in the form of vapour; and so Theophrastus refers Aristotle's words 'warmth itself is
generated
by moisture and
lives
by
it'
to the
the sun 'drawing water to itself (Hdt n, 25) made a deep impression on Greek thinkers from an early date, and on this analogy (which to
them was more than an analogy) they explained the fundamental processes of both microcosm and macrocosm, as we shall
increasingly
discover.
The juxtaposition of these three reasons in the doxography, and the natural use of the same word 'nourished' (Tpfepsrcci) for living and the celestial show once organisms fires, again the error of trying to separate 'physiological' and 'meteorological' considerations in this context. They are united (or rather, they have as yet no meaning) in the thought of those to whom the whole universe is a living organism.
(9)
science
and myth
can recover the mind of Thales from our meagre authorities, he asserted in the first place that the world was of one substance. To be the arche of the world, this substance must contain
far, then, as
So
we
within
the cause of motion and change (this, admittedly, would not be argued; it would be an assumption), and to a Greek this meant
itself
that
it
life-
he thought best
satisfied by water, or more generally the element of moisture (TO uypov, including of course such substances as blood and the sap of plants). This then was the arche, and as such was both alive
and everlasting.
At
1
this
1906, 340.
Sfc
Cf. Hipp.
uScop
Littr) TO
ydp m/p
-nxScvrcc
67
The Milesians
what,
if
is
own word
athanaton), and he would have only one answer: theos, or to thewn. Everlasting life is the mark of the divine, and of nothing else. Hence
Thales, though rejecting the anthropomorphic deities of popular of saying that, in a religion, could retain its language to the extent filled with gods. One may compare special sense, the whole world was
the use of 'the divine' attributed to Anaximander (pp. 87 f., below). It is not the choice of water as the arche that gives Thales his main
As
it:
If he
still
had championed the cause of treacle as the sole element, he would 1 have been rightly honoured as the father of speculative science.'
that, if there is
It is
Thales decided
it
at the basis
of all nature,
must be water.
scientist's
view he admits, had adumbrated the same idea, but by having Hesiod, to recourse gods and spirits endowed with special powers they begged the question, because the existence of such beings can neither be proved
nor disproved by the means wherewith we know the natural world. 'In a word, it was Thales who first attempted to explain the variety of nature as the modifications of something in nature/
precursors of Thales are worth a little more attention, in view of the importance of understanding something of the climate of thought into which Ionian philosophy was born. It would be
the hypothesis, the question he asked, that in the Others like constitutes his claim to immortality.
The mythological
say that they anticipated his idea, but they had familiarized a conception of cosmogony which must have smoothed the path for it. too
much to
was a common feature of early Greek cosmogonical beliefs, which they shared with those of the Near East and elsewhere, that in the be2 ginning all was fused together in an undifferentiated mass. The initial
It
making of the world, whether accomplished by the fiat of a creator or by other means, was a separation or division. As the Hebrew myth has it, God divided the light from the darkness and divided the waters which were under the firmament from the waters which were above the firmament', and so on. Diodorus at the beact in the
* .
W.
Cf.
10.
68
go back
physical speculation notion, however, Euripides sets in the legendary past, and there are other indications also that it antedated the beginnings of philosophical inquiry. In his play Melanippe the Wise, Euripides makes Melanippe
say:*
form because their nature was mingled. Later these bodies separated, and the world assumed the whole arrangement which it now displays. He supports this with a quotation from Euripides, who as he notes was deeply interested in the of his own time. This
The tale is not mine, I had it from my mother, how heaven and earth were one form; and when they were parted from one another, they gave birth to all things, and gave forth to the light trees, flying things, beasts, the nurslings of the salt sea, and the race of mortals.
For an example" of the mythology behind this we need look no In the Theogony he tells the primitive story of how Ouranos and Gaia, conceived as anthropomorphic figures, lay locked in an embrace until Kronos forced them apart. Again, the
further than Hesiod.
that is, attributed by the Greeks spoke of the world as having started in the form of an egg. When it broke, Eros, the spirit of generation, emerged, and, of the two halves of the egg, the upper now formed the sky and the lower the earth. There are several versions in this tradition,3 but they all seem to teach, of course in the central doctrine which is mythical form,
Orpheus
attributed
all
things
by Diogenes Laertius to Musaeus the pupil of Orpheus 'that come to be from one and are resolved again into the same*. 4
The
1
may
well have
p. 135),
*
Diod. r, 7. Diels-Kranz print this among the fragments of Democritus (6835, vol. n, but it more probably antedates the atomists. For its date and sources see the reff. in Guthrie, In the Beginning, 122, n. 10, and add Pfligersdorffer, Stud. iu Poseidonios, 100-46.
Fr. 484
Nauck:
oOK u6s 6 u00os dXA*
ob$ oOpctv6s TE
feuifr
HTjTpfcs
trdpa,
yald
T" fjv
nop^
liter
Thcrouai Trdvra
For
see Guthrie, Greek Religion, ch. iv. Orpheusjfand v6s Td ir^fa ylyveaOai KOC\ els T<xCrr6v ndXiv I, 3
<5cvoc\OEo6ai.
The Milesians
influenced Thales and his successors in the direction of
monism
it is
almost impossible to believe that it did not but does not detract of their achievement. The evolution of the greatly from the extent
in these mythical accounts proceeds in sexual terms. It is the mating and begetting of a series of pairs of powers achieved
cosmos
by
imagined in
form, and how near these stories are to the primitive is easily seen in Hesiod's description of the mutilation of Ouranos by his son Kronos and of the birth of Aphrodite. Granted that the
human
Milesians had the ground prepared for them by these myths, it is more important to reflect that they abandoned the whole mythical apparatus of personal agents, and, as Wightman says, tried to explain the variety of nature only in terms of something in nature itself, a natural
substance.
on
the one
hand
as a marvellous anticipation
as
of modem
cised
scientific thinking,
by
the Milesians
lies
form a bridge
between the two worlds of myth and reason. The search for a unity in the universe behind the multiplicity of phenomena is perennial and
universal. It is a religious
and
aesthetic, a philosophic
and a
scientific
of history. We have seen it in the and shall encounter it in religious poetry of a pre-philosophical age, its most extreme form a hundred years or so after Thales in Parmenides.
need; and
it
In modern times
seen a philosopher remark on the aesthetic appeal of unity and a logician describe it as the only thing which will to the physical scientists, we satisfy the desire for explanation. Turning
we have
one of them writing of 'the endeavour of physics to achieve a unified world-view. We do not accept appearances in their manycoloured fullness, but we want to explain them, that is, we want to
find
we
entered
its scientific
phase,
it is
any time and place at which unity emerged from the mythical and here in sixth-century Miletus. There is
is
a long way to go. Philosophy is so recently born that it can scarcely stand on its own legs, and only with many a backward glance at its
1
70
Science
and Monism
parent and even a grip on her hand; but it is borfi, because someone has sought the desired unity in a natural substande and removed the gods from the cosmogonical scene. Von Weizsacker continues his
this process
it
what is perceptible what is not and whether or not can credit this further we by perceptible,
necessary to explain
Anaximander.
draw attention to parallels between the views of these early thinkers and those of more recent science, since it is so easy to exaggerate resemblances and invite misleading conclusions. It may well be that the Milesians, as one would expect from their methods and
hesitates to
results in other fields offiistorie, were keen observers and may even have had an embryonic awareness of the uses of experiment; but when it comes to the constitution of the universe, there is almost an absurdity
One
in putting their inspired guesses beside the conclusions of modern experimental science. (Another obvious field for pitfalls is the com-
modern atomic
feel at
very distantly related phases of human history is natural and justified if the human mind is a subject of interest at all; and, in due segregation from the main argument, one may perhaps allow it a little indulgence.
In choosing water as the one basic substance, Thales was followed by van Helmont, who at the turn of the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries exemplified a similarly transitional phase between superstition and rationalism, with on the one hand his faith in alchemy and
devotion to Paracelsus, and on the other his solid scientific achievethe title of the father of modern chemistry.
In the present century, the following passage from the late Sir Charles Sherrington is of especial interest in view of the likelihood that Thales's
choice was determined
by
life:
menstruum of 'life*. It makes life possible. It was part of the plot by which our planet engendered life. Every egg-cell is mostly water, and water is its first habitat. Water it turns to endless purposes; mechanical support and bed for its membranous sheets as they form and
Water
is
the great
71
The Milesians
The early embryo is largely membranes. Here a particular piece grows fast because its cells do so. There it bulges or dips, to do this or that or simply to find room for itself. At some other centre of special
shape and fold.
activity
the sheet will thicken. Again at some other place it will thin and form a hole. This is how the mouth, which at first leads nowhere, presently opens into 1 the stomach. In the doing of all this, water is a main means.
Wightman sums up
Thales was dealing with things as they are, and not with things neatly sorted and cleaned up by chemists. His dictum, then, though certainly not wholly true, was, at its face value, very far from being nonsense. The greater part of the earth's surface is water; water pervades every region of our atmosphere;
life as
water
is
dream of a universal solvent; water disappears when fanned by the wind, and falls again from the clouds as rain; ice turns into water as does the snow that falls from the sides; and a whole country surrounded by a barren desert is fertile, rich, and populous because a huge mass of water
to the alchemist's
sweeps through
it
annually.
C.
ANAXIMANDER
and fellow-citizen of Thales
friend
was sixty-four in the year 547/6 (D.L. n, 2)! Following the tradition that Thales wrote nothing, Themistius described him as 'the first of
the Greeks, to our knowledge, who was bold enough to publish a treatise on nature'. Certain it is that he wrote a book, which seems to
have come into the hands of Apollodorus the chronologist, and we may feel some confidence that it was in the library of the Lyceum under
and Theophrastus. Yet it is perhaps worth remarking that Anaximander nor Anaximenes is mentioned by any writer before Aristotle. Plato, though he tells a story about Thales, and
Aristotle
neither
quotes the dictum elsewhere attributed to him that all things are full of gods, nowhere mentions the other two Milesians, nor makes any certain
reference to their doctrines. This remarkable fact has led the Swiss
Man
3 3
Am.
72
Anaximander: Writings
to suppose that Aristotle, with his deep interest in the historical aspect of his subject, must have out the works of these
scholar
Gigon
sought
two and discovered copies which up to his time had been lost. The Suda 1 lists as titles of works by Anaximander: On Nature,
Description of the Earth, The Fixed Stars, Sphere, 'and a few more'. These probably come from the catalogue of the Alexandrian library and
unnamed, and, on
the
lists
may
the assumption that the titles are in fact sub-titles, well have varied. Throughout antiquity the title 'On
Nature'
the
(irspi 9uaeco$)
to the writings of
Presocratics, who from the main bent of their interests were known
as 'the natural philosophers' or 'physiologers* (9uaiKoi, 9\JcnoA6yoi: so in Aristotle), The phrase was already in use as a title in the fifth and
fourth centuries
not indeed proved by the which a Hippocratic writer it, passages commonly or Plato refers to 'those who write on nature': this and similar phrases mark them off as a recognized group, but cannot be said to indicate 2 anything so definite as a title. More certain proof comes from someB.C.,
though
this fact is
cited to support
in
thing which does not seem to have impressed scholars in this connexion, namely the statement that Gorgias the fifth-century Sophist
called
'On
the Non-existent or
title
On
Nature'. 3
was chosen by
Gorgias himself, nor that it was intended as a parody of titles already extant. He may have had particularly in mind his contemporary
Melissus,
557. 10;
whose book according to Simplicius (Phys. 70. 1 6, De DK, 30 A4) was called 'On Nature or the Existent'.
Caelo,
of his writings in the Suda may be fairly taken to with the represent the scope of Anaximander's interests. Coupled
classification
1
The
See p. 47, n.
3,
above.
Hippocr.
De
i,
Pet.
Xen. Mem.
below).
I,
n,
Med. 20 (1,620 Littre"), Plato, Lys. 2i4B,PAa<&,96A,Eur. fr. 910 Nauck, AT. Gen. et Corr. 333 bi 8, Phys. 185 a 18 (quoted by Verdenius, loc. cit.
On the strength of some of these, Heidel (Proc. Am. Acad. XLV (1910), 81) said: 'It is IT. (pteecos reasonably certain that philosophical works were familiarly quoted as bearing the title some time before the close of the fifth century*, and Verdenius (Mnemos. 1947, 2723): *In the
fifth
sophical
3
and fourth centuries TT. 9^oecos was obviously regarded as the authentic works/ Sext. Adv. Math, vn, 65 (DK, 8283) & TCO rnypa90puh>cp
title
of early philo-
73
The Milesians
well-authenticated fact that he
drew a map of
the
known
world,
it
than a philosopher suggested to Heidel that he was more of a geographer were responsible who and that the limited interest of the Peripatetics
for the doxographic tradition has therefore given a somewhat distorted as a whole. The reports of his map go back picture of his achievements to the great Alexandrian geographer and librarian Eratosthenes, e.g.
that of Strabo
who
in claiming that
DK,
12
A 6):
clearly notable
men and
whom
first after
Anaximander the acquaintance and fellow-citizen of Thales, and Hecataeus of Miletus. The one was the first to publish a geographical tablet [map of the Hecataeus left a treatise which is authenticated as his from earth], whereas
the rest of his writings.
1
Anaximander was
natural
said (D.L. n, 2) to
also
accompaniment have constructed a sphere, that is, some sort of model of the heavens, but unfortunately we have no details of this, and we are still at the cloudy stage of history when the attribution of
particular
noted for his astronomical achievements, a to his interest in the cosmos as a whole. He is
is
almost impossible
sphere was
of
verification.
We
first celestial
fashioned
by Thales
De
to Pliny (n, 31, DK, Rep. i, 14, 22). Heidel mentions that according 12 A 5) Anaximander discovered the obliquity of the zodiac, but does
not here note that Eudemus in his Astronomical History credited this to Oenopides in the fifth century (DK, 41 .7). Like Thales, Anaximander
was
said to
dial
(gnomon), and to have shown by its aid the solstices, times, seasons, and equinoxes* (Eusebius, DK, A 4, cf. D.L. n, i). Herodotus, as we have seen (p. 33, above), regarded this as an importation from Babylonia,
1
and the
different
in the
tradition (D.L.
details
ir,
2,
Agathemerus in
I2A6, etc.) see Heidel, op. cit. 247; and for conjectural mander's map, Kahn, Anaximander, 82-4.
DK,
74
Scope of Anaximander s
Work
This
some doubt
dial,
according to Favorinus (op. D.L. n, i), he set up at Sparta, a city with which he is further connected by a story in Cicero (De Div. I,
he was responsible for a considerable saving of life by the warning Spartans of an impending earthquake and persuading them to spend the night in the open. 2 Thus, as one would expect from his
50, 112) that
geographical interests, he evidently had the Ionian taste for travel, and Aelian (c. A.D. 200) says that he led the expedition to found one of the numerous colonies of Miletus, that at Apollonia on the Black Sea coast
(F.H. in, 7, DK, A 3). No doubt like Thales he took a full part in the public life of his city, even if we may no longer accept the sixthcentury statue bearing the name of Anaximander, the lower part of
which has been discovered in the louleuterion of Miletus, been erected in honour of the philosopher.3
Heidel's minute examination of the evidence
as having
from non-Peripatetic
sources led
him
book was,
in
short and summary form/ a universal history and geography, 'purporting to sketch the life-history of the cosmos from the moment of its
emergence from infinitude to the author's own time'. Carrying this tendency even further, Cherniss says: 'Anaximander's purpose was to
give a description of the inhabited earth, geographical, ethnological and cultural, and the way in which it had come to be what it was. This
'
would mean
that the only part of Anaximander's doctrine on which we have anything but the smallest and most doubtful bits of information,
namely his cosmogony, was to him only incidental or preparatory to the main purpose of his work. We may admit the likelihood that
Aristotle
and
his followers
were
silent
far
about parts of the book that did in the opposite direction is to outrun
and compares it to the forecasts made by and experience, calling Anaximander *physicus'. It would be interesting to know how Anaximander did it: perhaps by observing the behaviour of the storks, like the inhabitants of the Larissa neighbourhood in the earthquakes of to know 1954. (The Times, 3 May 1954: 'We have watched the storks all day; it is the best way
doctors, seamen and farmers
e$pe D.L., KocreoKeOaoE Euseb., riafiyaye Suda. Cicero denies that this was an act of divination,
by reason of their
special skill
when
3
it is
coming.')
52),
but see
statue,
4
name must be
donor or dedicator.
75
The Milesians
Here our main purpose must be to attempt a reconstruction of Anaximander's cosmogonical views, and in this, as we have seen, we are better situated than we were with Thales. None of our informants,
or their sources, had knowledge of a book by Thales. They were dependent on anecdotes or a few apophthegms, the authenticity of
which was doubtful or worse. The treatise of Anaximander could be and we are told that quoted, and its style criticized, by Theophrastus, B.C. Whatever we may second in the a saw century copy Apollodorus
think of their interpretations,
in criticizing what they say
it is
safest to
Theophrastus both had the work, and to be correspondingly cautious from the standpoint of our own comparative
ignorance.
(2)
The Unlimited as
'arche
The
large part
57,
name for the arche. things 'the boundless', being the the of so-called nor other He says that it is neither water elements, but any a different substance which is boundless, from which there come into being
to introduce this
all
the heavens and the worlds within them. Things perish into those things out of which they have their being, as is due; for they make just recompense
to
one another for their injustice according to the ordinance [or perhaps so he puts it in somewhat poetical terms. 'assessment'] of rime
Having thus paraphrased and in part quoted Anaximander' s words, before him, proceeds to Simplicius, with Aristotle and Theophrastus interpret them:
It is clear that
other, he did not think it reasonable to conceive of one of these as underlying the rest, but posited something else. Moreover he does not account for genesis by a qualitative alteration of the element, but by a separation of the
opposites caused
by
Few
thorough mauling from many modern commentators. The above is no exception, and many difficulties have been discovered, if not created,
in
casual aside, that Anaximander's language here is rather poetical, gives us the valuable information that the previous sentence,
it.
The
The 'Arche
though
words.
in
Anaodmander
ment
they recompense to one another for their injustice according to the ordinance of time', and this is sufficient guarantee that the preceding clause is a true 2 representation of Anaximander's thought. The state-
cast in indirect speech in the Greek, preserves some of his actual At a minimum, 1 the criticism must refer to the clause: 'for
make
just
origin of things
on
Aristotle,
who
4,
are separated out, as Anaximander says.'B It is clear a different view has been taken) that the first (though sentence in the from means that
and
passage
Simplicius
Anaximander was
the
first
to give the
name
That he was
totle
apeiron (boundless, unlimited) to the arche. to use arche for that which writers from Arisc
onwards, with rather different ideas in their heads, called the substratum' appears not from this but from another passage of 'Anaximander Simplicius (Phys. 150.22); says that the opposites were in the substratum, which was a boundless body, and were separated out: he was the first to name the substratum arche.' notice also that
We
Theophrastus deemed
it
word by
Some
DK;
^{peaSca.
thinksthat KcrrdTfivroO xp6vouT&;iv is also not certain. Heidel is 1912, 233. Cf. also U. Holscher in Hermes, 1953, 2581". (who,
separating Theophrastus from Simplicius), McDiarmid, Theophr. on Presoc. Causes, 141 f. See also now the sensible remarks of Kahn, Anaximander, i6<5, and his review of earlier interpre-
1936. In spite of McDiarmid, Theophr. on Presoc. Causes, 968. McDiarmid is of course right in saying that 'recompense to one another for injustice* can have nothing to do with the relation of generated things to the apeiron. 3 dbcmrep 'Avcc{uav6p6s 91101. Aristode here groups Anaximander's 'boundless* with the 'mixture* of Empedocles and Anaxagoras, whose conceptions were in fact different, since they represented conscious attempts to escape the dilemma posed by Parmenides. After him, philosophers were conscious of distinctions and difficulties of which Anaximander had no inkling. This does not, however, invalidate the testimony, and it is probable if not, as Heidel said, 'proved beyond a doubt* (CP, 1912, 231) by this passage that Anaximander himself used the word kKptvecr0ai, or perhaps AiroKpivajeai (Kahn, Anaximander, 19 f.).
tations,
*
Cf. Heidel, CP, 1912, 215-16. McDiarmid (Theophr. on the Presoc. Causes, 138 ff.) has cast legitimate doubt on this final point, but his contention that Simpl. Phys. 150 is no evidence that Anaximander used the word bpxfi is only maintained by an alteration of the received text. See also
on
this
point Jaeger,
TEGP, 26,
77
The Milesians
With Anaximander
notion from which
in very different
perceptible.
it
physical theory takes a momentous step, to a has retreated many times before its reappearance
in the
form
modern world:
'The physical view of the world', writes the physicist von Weizsacker, 'has always had a tendency towards the non-perceptible. This stems immediately from the endeavour of physics to achieve a
unified world-view.
We do not accept appearances in their manycoloured fulness, but we want to explain them, that is, we want to reduce one fact to another. In this process what is perceptible is often
explained
by what
is
not perceptible.'
Anaximander then
larly
(and later philosophically) recognized elemental masses visible in the world of today, could have served as a basis for all the rest. Instead he posited an unnamed substance behind them all, less definite in
character,
which he described
as apeiron
limit or
fire
phenomenon
or any such familiar, sensibly manifest The original matrix of the universe
must be something more primitive and ultimate than any of them, of which they are all alike secondary manifestations or modifications,
obtained
by a process of 'separating
out*.
did he The following questions therefore suggest themselves: thus go behind the phenomena? What did he mean by apeiron} What were the 'opposites', and in what sense 'in the one and separated out'?
Why
(3)
The opposite*
reality
one seeking a unity behind the multiplicity of phenomena, on general grounds a reasonable one, as von Weizsacker has confirmed
from the
scientist's standpoint.
Anaximander had
also a
more
specific
reason for adopting it, and this introduces a fundamental feature of Greek thought with a long and influential history, namely the notion of the primary opposites. Later, when substance and attribute had
Aristotle,
p. 70.
it
was
78
The Opposites
elements
more of a
of their
were characterized by one or qualities, hot, cold, wet and dry, and because attributes were always in a state of conflict. European contrary
earth, water, air
and
fire
set
of contrary
From
Ovid
Frigida pugnabant calidis, umentia siccis
we
pass to Spenser
The earth the air the water and the fire Then gan to range themselves in huge array,
And with
and Milton
fierce
When
idea,
Anaximander
*
first tried
no
clear distinction
was
he spoke of the boundless', so also he designated the opposites 1 by article and adjective as the hot, the cold, the wet and the dry. These, as Cornford has said, are for Anaximander not qualities but
Just as
'"The hot" was not warmth, considered as an adjectival property of some substance which is warm. It is a substantive thing, and "the cold", its contrary, is another thing. Hence it was possible to think of the hot and the cold as two opposed things which might be
things.
fused together in an indistinct condition, like a mixture of wine and water' (Princ. Sap. 162).
The
conflict
of the opposites
is
an undeniable
fact
of nature. Water
whose nature it is to quench fire whenever it meets it, can the be original substance out of which fire, along with all the hardly
for instance,
1
Simpl. 150.24,
DK, A 9.
We
may
'heat* or 'dryness* are currently distinguished from 'hot* and 'dry*, he still has to apologize for the general term 'quality* (iroidrns) as an uncouth neologism (Theaet. i8iA).
I cannot agree with the reasoning of Holscher (following Reinhardt; see Hermes, 1953, 266) that the opposites enumerated as Anaximander's by Simplicius are not 'anaximandrisch*, nor see why *T& fiiretpov is in a different class*. 'Because*, says Holscher, 'it stands not for a quality (like
phenomenon
like
fire.'
also for
menon.
79
The Milesians
other forms of material existence, had
its
being.
Some
thinkers
make
mutual opposition e.g. air is them were unlimited, the others would have perished. As it is, they say, it is something else, out of which the known elements come (Phys. in, 204 b 24).
unlimited; for they are marked by so that if one of cold, water wet, fire hot
The
conflict is referred to
attested fragment of his another for their injustice according to the ordinance of time.'
by Anaximander himself in the only wellwritings: 'They make just recompense to one
To
which may
seem rather
subtle.
There
is
a sense in which
water (the cold and wet) can and does give birth to its opposite, fire (the hot and dry). No other meaning can be attached to Anaximander' s
sentence than that the 'injustice' which they commit consists in an encroachment, say, of fire by swallowing up some of its rival water, and
vice
verm.
It
was
in fact a
common Greek
belief,
which emerges
still
more
clearly in
of
the universe (that is, in the present world-order the sun) not only vaporized the moisture of earth and sea, thus turning it into mist or it and transformed it into fire. The process was air, but finally ignited
or moisture, actually spoken of as the 'nourishment' of the sun by water as we saw in connexion with Thales (p. 67 above).
can be created out of water, but only because of the simultaneous existence of both, and, as Anaximander says, their balance
In this sense
fire
is
is
followed
by a retribution in which the other regains the lost ground. Fire becomes cooled into cloud, cloud into rain which once more replenishes
the moisture
on earth. This
alternate
the dry, the cold and the wet, is an obvious expression of the annual variation of the seasons. 1 It in no way contradicts the observation which
abandonment of one of the opposites as primal arche, for it remains as true as ever that in a universe which was all water, like that
led to the
1
CP
So Heidel, *On Anaximander*, CP, 1912, 233-4, and Proc. Am. Acad. 1913, 684-5 ; 1947, 172; Comford, Prtnc. Sap. 168.
Vlastos,
80
Conflict
of the Opposites
rationalized a
of the Mesopotamian and Egyptian myths which Thales perhaps into little too precipitately, no fire could ever have come
being.
existing.
Thus whether the sentence 'things perish into those things out of which they have their being, according to necessity' is also Anaximander' s or is a paraphrase by Theophrastus or Simplicius, it cannot
refer (as
has frequently been thought to do) to the primal generation of the opposites out of, and final reabsorption into, the ultimate apeirony
it
but only to their mutual transformations in the present order. Otherwise its connexion with the quotation which follows would make no
sense.
1
To sum up, Anaximander had noticed that it is the natural tendency of each of the elements to swallow up its opposite. Fire and water must inevitably be in conflict. When they meet they struggle until one
or the other prevails, and either the fire is put out and nothing but the water remains, or else the water is dried up and fire remains in sole possession of the field. Conversely this may be described, in Simplicius's
3 words, as the conversion of water into fire and vice versa.' There is of course an intermediate stage, clearly visible to observation, of the con'
version of water into steam or vapour, which for the Greeks are included in the term aer. In the world as a whole, complete and final victory is never granted to one or the other of the opposing forces (or
litigants, as
is
Anaximander imagined them) the balance between them always being restored or maintained. If one gains a local advantage,
:
the other
encroaching elsewhere. evolved from a single substance, there must be enough of this substance to make the whole world, and probis
ably a good deal more besides. But if fire existed in that quantity, it would inevitably enjoy a permanent victory over its potential
1 Vlastos (CP, 1947, 170) thinks the plural 6 &v *is strange, for the reference is obviously to the Boundless*; but concludes that 'the Boundless is explicitly thought of as a plurality % This is much less probable than that the reference is not to the Boundless at all. The view of H. Frankel
it
u. Philos. 345-7) is subtle and interesting, but as Woodbury says (CP, 1955, I54f.) Anaximander with a more developed sense of the distinction between possible and actual than he is likely to have possessed. The view here taken is now supported by Kahn, Anaximander^
(Dichtung
credits
1676, 195 f.
a
tfjv els
81
The Milesians
rivals,
to
come
into existence; or if
the arche zndpkysis of the world were water, there could never be fire. This remains true whether we take Anaximander's word apeiron,
which he applied
mean
strictly infinite
in extent, as Aristotle did, or simply of an indefinite quantity large 1 enough to serve as source or reservoir from which all that exists has
been drawn. What exactly he did mean by the word has been matter of considerable controversy, and is now due for consideration.
It
the question What is of one material substance, and asked only whether that substance was
to regard the Milesians as interested only in ' the world made of? They assumed it to be made
else.
approached them from the standpoint of his own fourfold scheme, of the material, efficient, seeking only, as he tells us, for anticipations
formal and
he conceived them, they appeared to be concerned only with 'principles of a material kind' (ra$ ev OAr|$ i5ei novas, MetapL 983^7). But by thus limiting the scope and purpose
final causes as
of his review, he has undoubtedly misled those who, ignoring his own of intentions, supposed him to be writing a history explicit declaration
of philosophy. Not 'matter (for which they had no word, since they knew of no other form of existence) but rather 'nature' (physis) is the
correct keyword. It may be that no certain instance of this word occurs in the scanty fragments of the philosophers before Heraclitus, but we
9
have
it
2 Homer, and
this
enough
which they
new understanding of the world '.3 Most commonly it meant the real constitution or character of things, including the way it could also mean 'birth' or they behave, though 'growth' (e.g. in fr. 8). The two are not unconnected, since, as Aristotle Empedocles,
their
summed up
said (Pkys.
193^2), 'Physis
is
the
a
3
Another meaning of arche, as Heidel has illustrated in CPy 1912, 219 ff. Qd. x, 303, the 'bodily form* of a plant. See Kahn, Anaximander, 4, n. i and 201, n. 2. 'Nomos und Physis*, Hermes , 1953, 426. For a good discussion of the meaning of die word
see Kirk,
HCF,
42-3, 228-3 r
82
Anaximander
s 'Apeiron*
Physis could be both process and constitution or developed form, and the Milesians were interested in both aspects, though the evidence, such
suggests that the latter sense (which it has in the Odyssey) is likely to have predominated in the sixth century. The 'new understanding of the world' consisted in the substitution
as
it is,
of natural for mythological causes, that is, of internal development for external compulsion. This, as Pohlenz says, is well expressed by the
1 generalized use ofpfiysis, which is something essentially internal and intrinsic to the world, the principle of its growth and present organiza-
with
its
material constituent.
The
not simply that it consists of a single material primary assumption substance, but that the diversity of its present order is not from
eternity,
at a parti-
To
simple state or arche Anaximander gave the name of the and the process by which a world-order emerged from it he Boundless,
this initial
first
itself,
call it
DK, A 1 5),
for
Aristotle
mentions
apeiron.
some-
thing
is
We may
take
of these aspects of the word up to and including his time. In the first deserves to aspects, the temporal, the apeiron of Anaximander certainly to the familiar was be called infinite. The notion of infinity
temporal
Greek mind from remote antiquity in the religious conception of imto mortality, and Anaximander's description was in terms appropriate
this conception, for like
many of his
203 b 13;
DK,
According
63), he called his arche 'deathless and imperishable'. it the words 'eternal and
6, i;
ageless' (Ref.
different order
from
B2). This marks it off as something of a anything recognizable in the present world, and
DK,
for
1
it
meaning of arche as both the original state of things has existed from all time and the permanent ground of their
123
Very possibly
(fr.
Heraclitus
DK)
at this stage with a limiting genitive like TOU 5Xou or already uses it absolutely.
TWV
Svrcov,
though
83
The Milesians
being.
a arche of all things cannot itself have an arche beginning because then not it but that further arche would be the ultimate one.
The
And what
is
apeiron, for
an arche
would be a limit. So, in effect, says Aristotle (Phys. 203 by), using an 1 argument which seemed to Cornford to have 'an archaic ring'. Apart from the temporal sense of everlasting', apeiron has two main
'
meanings, according as the 'boundaries' (perata) which it lacks are thought of as external or internal. If a body is limited externally, this
comes up against something else, or so at least 2 it seemed to Aristotle and later writers. Beyond its limit there must be something other than itself. Conversely, then, a body which is uncan only be because
it
must continue
infinitely,
or at
least indefinitely, in
we
mander regarded the apeiron as infinite in this quantitative sense 'in order that becoming might not fail'. The extant 'opposites', as we have seen, and more complex bodies composed of them, are continually if the supply of them perishing. Consequently, it seems to be argued, is to be kept up as it is and has been for time out of mind the that is, the apeiron reservoir out of which new supplies come must
be inexhaustible and therefore
It
infinite.
seems doubtful, however, whether Anaximander used this argument himself.3 It looks rather as if the author had drawn that inference
is
supposing the existence of an infinite body, but without suggesting * Nor is it necessary', writes Aristotle (Phys. that Anaximander did so.
208 a 8;
DK, A 14),
'for
an
infinite sensible
body
to exist in actuality in
order that becoming may not fail; for the destruction of one thing may be the genesis of another, while the whole sum remains finite/ What
Aristotle says
is circular.
is
clearly right.
The
Perishing does not mean vanishing into nothingness, but changing into a different form of matter. This circularity, symbolized by Anaximander as the alternation of 'injustice' and 'reparation',
1
For reasons
himself see C. H.
2
in favour of supposing that the whole Kahn in Festsckr. Kappy 1958, 19-29.
Phys. 203!) 20 r6 Trerrepacru^vov dcel irp6s TI Trepocivciv. follows goes against the opinion of But-net (EGP, Cherniss (ACP, 379) and others.
3
What
57),
84
of
unlikely that Anaximander was capable of grasping the notion strict which came with further spatial or quantitative
infinity,
It is
indeed purely conceptual, and has no in the world of immediate sensible meaning experience. As one of the five reasons for in an Aristotle that believing infinite,
says
advances in mathematics.
number,
mathematical magnitude and the space beyond the sky are thought to 1 be infinite 'because they never give out in our thought'. It is hardly credible that Anaximander reasoned like this. He certainly regarded
the apeiron as an enormous mass surrounding (Trspigxsiv, Ar. Phys. 203 b 1 1) the whole of our world, but it may even have presented itself to his mind, as Cornford suggested, as a vast sphere. The word was in use in Greek to describe both spherical and circular shape, and, in an age without any sciences of grammar, semantics or logic, men were at
the
mercy of words
to
an extent which
it is
A word was more like a single whole entity, and its various meanings,
and separate, could only appear as of a single meaning. It is right therefore to take into account the fact that apeiron was used of spheres and rings, to indicate no doubt that one can go on and on around them without ever coming to a bounding line. This comes out
difficulty analyse
realize.
which we without
they gem-socket. Empedocles (fr. 28) speaks of an unlimited sphere, and the word is also applied to a seamless robe and a circular band of worshippers round an altar.2
particularly clearly when Aristotle says (Phys. 207 a 2) that finger-rings are called unlimited if have no
Secondly apeiron was used with internal perata chiefly in mind, to indicate that no line could be drawn between part and part within the
whole. In
A
1
body
*
this way it approximates to the notion of indeterminacy. unlimited in this sense may be made up of different sorts of
Phys. 203 b 23 8ia T6 Iv "ri3 vofjasi Eur. Or, 25 (cf. Aesch. Ag* 1382), Aesch.
fr.
cited
by Cornford,
85
The Milesians
matter, but they are fused into an indistinguishable mass. Standing on the shore, we can see clearly where sea and earth and air begin and end.
The world is not apeiron in the sense we are considering. But we can imagine some cataclysm occurring which would destroy those boundaries, just as
we
can imagine an
initial state
divisions of the
If earth,
world were so cleanly distinguished as they are now. sea and sky were fused in one heaving, molten mass, the world
might be described as a boundless, or unlimited, mixture (in Greek orreipov iJuyuoc), meaning that the boundaries between its various components were non-existent and they were inextricably confused.
The
own boundaries
are not at
Let
me
repeat that
we
distinctions
between
different uses
Some inheritance of the magical idea that a word or name has an independent existence and essence of its own, and can only therefore
be one thing, persisted until later times than this, and influenced even the thought of the most enlightened, however far it may have receded
into the subconscious.
Of that the
There is mander intended us to take his word, but only which sense was uppermost in his mind. This is likely to have been the notion of internal
indeterminacy rather than of spatial
solution to the problem that he
as
infinity, since the
former offered a
was trying
to solve.
He was impressed,
seen (pp. 79 ff., above), with the difficulty of supposing the single primary element to be water, or 'the wet', as Thales had done, or any of the actual opposites with their determined characteristics. Owing
to his belief in the inherent hostility
we have
and
'injustice'
one of them,
it
far
from serving
as source
of being to the
would
of its own.
It
must hold,
and suspended
as
it
were in
solution, the characteristics of all the future opposites which in due course were to be, in the significant word which was probably his
off' (or 'out')
own, 'separated
apeiron
'.
from
it.
Here we may
find, in all
why
it
86
so that their subsequent emergence into actual and active being always a possibility.
was
The difficulties of this conception, at least as it was expressed in the crude language of his time, were not immediately apparent. To bring them out fully required the uncompromising clarity of a Parmenides.
If the opposites could be separated out from the arcke, we may say, it must have contained them all the time and therefore could not be
described as a unity.
everything
came
But to make
one thing', Anaximander virtually cheated. 1 criticism belonged to a more advanced stage of
thought, a necessary stage between the naive monism of the Milesians and the Aristotelian distinction between various modes of being. 2
(5)
The
'apeiron
divine
There
the
is
little
more
on
words of Aristotle
in Phys. 203 b 6
(DK, A 15):
Everything either is an origin or has an origin: the unlimited has no origin, for that would be a limit of it. Moreover, being an origin [or source or .Therefore, as I say, principle: arche], it is ungenerated and imperishable.
. .
no origin for it, but it appears to be the origin of other things and to encompass all things and direct all things, as those philosophers say who do
there
is
1 The fact that this is an ancient formula, going back beyond the beginning of philosophy, is our best guarantee that in calling the earliest philosophers monistic in intention we are not (as some modern interpreters have argued) foisting on them the misconceptions that we have
f.,
above.
both ancient and modern, have been puzzled to know whether Anaximander's apeiron is a single substance or a mixture. (Cf. Cherniss, ACP, 375 ff., McDiarmid, Theophr. on Presoc. Causes, 100.) Probably the explanation given above comes closer to the mind of Anaximander than an outright denial of Aristotle's supposition that the opposites were in the apeiron, which was therefore a mixture. He had not faced the question. The distinction which some have emphasized between separating out and separating off (^KKpivgoOai and <5nroKp{vEcr6aci) seems to me of little significance in this connexion. (For Holscher's contrary view
It is
no wonder
see
KR,
130.)
Perhaps the explanation which shows most insight is that of Kahn (Anaximander, 23(5). In the light of Anaximander's conception of the universe as a living organism (cf. pp. 90 f., * below) he writes : For a Milesian they [sc. the opposites] were no more pre-existent in the &rmpov
than children pre-exist in the body of their parents before conception.'
87
The Milesians
not posit besides the unlimited other causes such as Mind or Love; and this they say is the divine, for it is immortal and imperishable, as Anaximander and most of the writers on nature call it.
Aristotle
is
whom
the belief in
an animate self-moving stuff was beginning to seem unsatisfactory so that like Empedocles and Anaxagoras they moved towards the notion of a separate moving force, from those who like the Milesians were still
at the hylozoist stage.
included or surrounded
all
For these a single arche filled the dual role; it things, and was also the directive force. This
steer',
5) to air,
from Anaximander's successor Anaximenes. Elsewhere among the Presocratics we find it in Heraclitus (whatever the correct reading and of fr. for which see and Parmenides 41, interpretation below, p. 429)
the rest of the language here quoted from 'philosophers of the unlimited' go back to Anaximander as well as the two epithets explicitly vouched for by Aristotle
(fr.
12, v. 3).
In
all
probability this
word and
as his. 1
as Aristotle says a little later (loya 18), impart acertain of tone to the pronouncements of early philosophers on the apeiron. Indeed the attribution to the arche not only of life but of
loftiness
These words,
directive
no surprise when Aristotle goes on to to the arche of Anaximander and those who explicitly
It is
therefore
For a Greek indeed, as he indicates in the next follows directly from the fact of immortality. If it includes directive or governing it also power implies at least some form of consciousness. For Anaximander we have no further evidence on this
thought
like
him.
clause,
it
point, but later monist philosophers ascribe consciousness and intelligence explicitly to their single material arche. This is the of
beginning
the road which will lead ultimately to the separation of matter and
1
.0% Ku^epvwpai 9pv(, says Odysseus to Athena in Soph. Aj. 35, and the doctor Eryximachus in Plato's Symposium says that his own art of medicine iraaa Cnr6 TOV) 0soO TOUTOU
.
TJSGP, 29
Kv/pepvarai
(i.e.
by Eros:
i8<$E).
88
Anaximander
moving
cause, that
identification
Cosmogony
is of matter and spirit, as the difficulty of their becomes more apparent; but that is still in the future. At 1 present the very word 'matter' is an anachronism.
(6)
the primal state, or original source of all things, we turn to the which a comes into world-order process by being. This is described as
From
being, in general terms, one of *separating-out', caused by an 'eternal motion' in the apeiron. In Aristotle's words (Phys. 187 a 20), 'the opposites are in the one and are separated out'. This statement of
the process follows well on our description of the primary nature of the 2 as an of all initial fusion the indeterminate But we apeiron opposites.
are not confined to the general term ekkrisis (or apokrisu] for our knowledge of how Anaximander supposed a world to be formed from
1 It must be stated in fairness that Prof. G. Vlastos has written (PQ, 1952, good conclusive evidence that either Anaximander or Anaxagoras called
113):
their
There
is
no
principle
(i) r6 Oelov does not * occur as a substantive for divinity* in any of the Presocratics or any other text prior to Aeschylus and Herodotus, while it is one of Aristotle's favourite terms; (ii) the ancients did not understand this particular text or any other text at their disposal to say that Anaximander himself taught that the apeiron was T6 0eTov; even the chapter in Aetius (i, 7) which generously supplies even Democritus with a god ( fire !) does not say that Anaximander's apeiron was god, but
"god" or even "divine".' I can only say that for me much more probable than not. Vlastos produces two arguments ex silenuo:
(i) is by no means conclusive when we consider the general frequency of article and neuter adj. at an early stage (cf. T6 <5crreipov itself). The expression T6 OEIOV is frequent in Aristotle not because it is a 'favourite* but because
only that Anaximander declared that the infinite ouranoi were gods*,
divinity is so frequently his subject. If Herodotus, who uses it several times, had written treatises * on natural theology it would no doubt have been a favourite* expression of his also. As for (ii),
the denial goes beyond the evidence, as arguments ex silentio, based on fragmentary sources, are almost bound to do. * But whether or not Anaximander called his principle divine*, it is of course true and important (and this is Vlastos's main point) that it had nothing whatever to do with the gods or cults of
popular religion.
Aristotle is in the context drawing a distinction, from his own point of view, between two kinds of early physical theory, those involving an alteration in the nature of the primitive of which Anaximander's was the first which speak only of a stuff (dAAolcocns), and those separating-out of what was there all the time. Thales he leaves out of the account, probably on the
2
grounds that too little was known about him. Following him Simplicius says (Phys. 150.20): 'Another way is not to adduce a change of matter as the cause, nor to account for the generation of things by the alteration of the substratum, but by separation (&<Kptai$). Thus Anaximander says that the opposites were in the substratum, which was an indeterminate (finreipov) body, and are separated out.* This dXXotcoais is a notion that belongs properly to Aristotelian physical not theory, and its introduction here throws little light on his early forerunners; but that does concern us now.
The Milesians
from the compilation called Stromateis and
reads thus
originating in Theophrastus,
(DK, AIO):
He says that at the birth of this cosmos a 1 germ of hot and cold was separated
off
from the eternal substance, and out of this a sphere of flame grew about the vapour surrounding the earth like the bark round a tree. When this was torn away and shut off in certain rings, the sun, moon and stars came into
existence.
The
last
by comparison with
the
13, 7,
shaped concentrations
'feltings')
of mist
with
fire,
breathing out
() (Hippolytus, Ref. i, 6, 4, DK, AII) The stars come into being as a circle of fire, separated off from the fire that pervades the cosmos and
surrounded by mist. There are breathing-places, certain pipe-like pas2 sages, through which the stars appear. When these are blocked, eclipses
occur.
The word
is
an adjective meaning
generative, fertile, able to bring to birth, and is used of eggs and seed.3 It is used again by Theophrastus in De Igne, 44 in relation to the life
of animals and plants only. 4 We can never know whether it is the actual word used by Anaximander, but it is in keeping with the language of
organic generation which seems to pervade the passage and, as we saw in discussing Aristotle's conjecture about Thales, is a likely colour for
the thought of these early speculators to have taken (pp. 61 f., above). The whole sentence strongly suggests, as Professor Baldry has well brought out,5 that Anaximander conceived his cosmogony on the
analogy of early views concerning the seed of animals and the develop1
Or
Dox.
Perhaps the simile is intended to compare the breathing-holes to the holes in a (musical) pipe. This would be appropriate, but cannot be said to be a certain translation of the Greek. 3 Examples: crnipiKx y6vipov (as opposed to Syovov), Ar. H.A. 523325; of eggs, Ar. G.A.
(as opposed to Oirnvuiov or dcveiiicttov, a wind-egg'). y6vipos xod 34>cov xcd <J>UTCOV (of the sun). 5 CQ> ^l 2 * 2 9 f There is admittedly an element of speculation in this, and for a more cautious view the reader is referred to Kirk in KR, i32f., but I should certainly not go further in that
4
579, crit n.
the phrasing
may be more
9o
cosmogonies shows
how
'separation' (ooroKpicns) of the seed in the womb, the part played by hot and cold, the word 9X016$, and the 'detachment' (cnroppayfjvai) of
the
all
familiar
from Greek
note with
As
word
one
may
round a growing organism, whether plant or animal'. Aristotle (H.A. v, 558328) uses it of the membrane round an egg, and Anaximander himself is said to have
Baldry that
applied
to the prickly skin which on his theory surrounded the earliest forms of animal life. It looks as if Anaximander saw the outer
it
embryo world, separating it from the womb of the which it was formed, 1 as a parallel phenomenon to this membrane which developed round eggs, animal embryos and trees
'skin' of the
'Boundless' in
2
alike.
is
Theophrastus or even
appropriate to the mentality of these intellectual pioneers. The arcke of Anaximander, the doxographers tell us,4 was in eternal
by Aristotle
is
nowhere explained, an omission but no doubt due to persistence of the belief that
this
is
Greek the very notion of life no cause was conceivable, let external involves self-caused motion, alone demanded. Anaximander has rejected the anthropomorphic imagery of sexual mating which formed the basis of mythical cosmogonies, but for him it is still natural and rational to regard the matrix of the world as animate and its origin as taking place from a kind of seed
eternally alive. Since for the
or egg.
1
K TOU
<5ci8f
orreipov,
as dddvorrov
*
and
Cf. e.g. De Nat. Pueri, 1 2 (vii, 488 Lime") : f| yovfi tiyevourai <pvcrcopiivT] (quoted by Baldry, 27). Leucippus actually spoke of a Oiifjv forming about the nascent cosmos (D.L. ix, 32). 3 The word meant sometimes the soft inner rind rather than the outer bark. Herodotus (vm, 115) speaks of people eating 9Xoi6v and leaves when no other food was available. In Hellenistic times Nicander uses it for the skin of Marsyas (AL 302) and of serpents (TA, 3 5 5, 392).
4
9*
The Milesians
This
from
nucleus, pregnant with the opposites, becomes detached the Boundless and develops into a sphere of fire enclosing a cold,
fertile
is
dark mist (cop). At this stage only two primary opposites can be said to be separated, hot including dry and cold including wet. The mist arises from the action of the hot peri-
phery on the cold-wet centre, and, under the same action of heat, wet and dry become in the end more completely separated, producing land
and
sea.
Anaximander says that the sea is a relic of the primal moisture, the greater part of which has been dried up by the fire.
Anaximander was among those whose accounts of the origin of the are mentioned by Aristotle in the Meteorologica (3 5 3 b 5 trans. Lee)
,
:
sea
Those who were more versed in secular philosophy [as opposed to the ancient theological poets] suppose it to have had a beginning. They say that at first the whole region about the earth was wet, and that as it dried up the water that evaporated became the cause of winds and the turnings of the sun and moon, while what was left is the sea: consequently they believe that the sea is still drying up and becoming less, and that in the end a time will come when
it is all
dried up.
He
is
disias
on the passage
(DK
A2y):
is
Some of them
The region
of the earth was moist, and subsequently part of the moisture was vaporized by the sun. . .but part of it left behind in the hollows of the earth forms the
sea.
Hence
it is
continually
becoming
less as
ally it will
be dry.
Of
this opinion,
cosmogony
is
continued by the natural exercise of their respective powers: heat dries up moisture and so on. Interesting also, after Aristotle's and our own
conjectures about Thales, is the immediate prominence of moisture and heat as soon as fertilization and generation are to take Heat
place.
especially has an important part to play as a first agent of genesis, and at a later stage it is the action of heat on moisture which produces animal
92
conjecture arising progress of physiological and medical knowledge in Greece. find rather, as might be expected, certain points of contact between the
later
those
These features of Anaximander's system strengthen the case against who have disparaged Aristotle's as out of the
We
fellow-citizens
and fellow-workers in
their field.
process explains the formation of the heavenly bodies. In addition to evidence already quoted, we have the following: 1
(a) Hippolytus, after the
words quoted
moon
(p. 90,
is
seen to
There follows a sentence in which some words have probably dropped out of the manuscripts, but which seems to that the circle of the sun is
say
3 twenty-seven times the diameter of the earth and that of the moon eighteen and adds that the sun is the highest of the times, heavenly bodies, and the
471.4 (DK, A 19, speaking of the planets): to discuss their sizes and distances, according to Eudemus, who attributes the first determination of their order to the Pythagoreans. The sizes and distances of the sun and moon are reckoned to this day by taking eclipses as the starting-point of our knowledge, and we may reasonably suppose that this too was Anaximander's discovery.'
()
Simpl.
De
Caelo
first
(c) Aet. n, 15, 6 (A 1 8): 'Anaximander, Metrodorus of Chios and Crates held that the sun was situated highest of all, next the moon, and beneath them the fixed stars and planets.'
(J) Ibid. 20, i (A 21 ): 'According to Anaximander, the sun is essentially a circle twenty-eight times the size of the earth, shaped like a cartwheel. The rim is hollow and full of fire, and at a certain point allows the fire to be seen
through an
of a bellows:
(A2i): 'Anaximander says that the sun is the same size as the earth, but the circle in which is its blowhole, and by which it is carried 9 round, is twenty-seven times the size of the earth. (/) Ibid. 24, 2 (A2i): 'According to Anaximander the sun is eclipsed when the orifice through which the fire escapes is shut up.' Ibid. i (g) 25, (A 22): 'According to Anaximander, the moon is essentially
I omit (a) the passage from Achilles (DK, A 21), as being obviously an unintelligently garbled version of what is described more clearly by Aetius, (K) Aet n, 16, 5 (Ai8), which as Kahn has seen (Anaximander, 59) is only an accidental repetition of the reference to Aristotle. preceding 3 Though Dreyer (Planetary Systems, 15, n. i) would take the text as it stands.
1
93
The Milesians
a
nineteen times the size of the earth, resembling a cartwheel with the rim hollow and full of fire like that of the sun, lying obliquely as does the
circle
sun's
and having a
single
blowhole
of a bellows.
It is
eclipsed
the orifice
moon
is
eclipsed
when
(A 22 omits last phrase): 'Anaximander, Xenophanes and Berosus say that die moon has its own light, in some way rarer [than the
()
Ibid. 28,
2
sun's].'
The fiery,
the mist or steam parted (doubtless under increasing pressure from caused by its own action in evaporating the watery centre) into separate
circles,
around each of which the dense mist surged and closed. Where
there are apertures in this surrounding envelope, we see the heavenly bodies themselves. Thus the sun and moon are really rotating wheels of
fire
going right round the earth, but encased in tubes of mist except
at
one point where there is a hole, through which the fire of gas through a leak in its pipe. (The modern simile is jet closer than the Greek one of air escaping through the nozzle of a pair
an ignited
of bellows.) The circles of the stars are not so easy to visualize from our fragmentary authorities, but one would suppose that each contained
streams like
as
by some modern
authori-
hardly gives an adequate explanation, though its appearance may possibly have helped to put the idea of the wheels into Anaximander's
head.
They were
evidently
all
from the
The last sentence, which occurs in Stobaeus but not in Plutarch's Epitome (Dox. 355), is obscure (and perhaps corrupt: Kahn, Anaximander, 60), but cannot be held to be a valid contradiction of the next passage quoted. a This must be preferred to the statement of D.L. n, i (DK, A i) that it gets its light from the sun. The correct view was in later antiquity attributed even to Thales (p. 49, above), and also to
Anaximenes, in whose somewhat fantastic astronomy it can scarcely have found a place. It seems to be first clearly attested in Parmenides (fr. 14), but Heath (Aristarchus^ 75 f.) is sceptical about this line and would credit the discovery to Anaxagoras. See further p. 286, below. 3 For Burnet's suggestion that there is only one * wheel of the stars', and that it is intended to explain the motions of the morning and evening stars alone (not yet recognized as one), see EGP 69 and Taylor, Timaeus, 160, n. i. Even though this would explain why the 'wheel of the stars* was smaller than those of sun and moon, it does not seem to be supported by our texts.
94
Anaximander
fixed stars.
Astronomy
(Eudemus, in passage () above, attributes the determination of the planetary orbits to the Pythagoreans. Simplicius's introduction of Anaximander in the context of the planets is confusing, as is
his apparent suggestion that
of
eclipses.)
To moon
contrary to later Greek astronomy, according to which the fixed stars are as seems most natural in the plane of the outermost
circumference of the spherical cosmos, and the sun, moon and planets revolve in different orbits beneath them. Anaximander's order raises
the question in a
very
may assume that the rings are one earth-diameter thick. The variants in the reported sizes (diameters) of the rings of sun and moon (27 and 1 8 or 28 and 19 times the size of the earth) were, since Burnet's
time
We
(EGP,
surface of the rings, until Kirk pointed out the simple fact that this requires a difference of two earth-diameters, not one. He suggests that
c
the larger figure might represent the diameter from outer edge to outer edge, the smaller one that from points half-way between the inner and outer edges of the actual felloe of air' (KR, 136). In any case the
larger figures are likely to
on the simple scheme of Anaximander expressed in multiples of three. No statement of the size of the star-rings is preserved, but since the
diameter of the earth
it
is
said to
be three times
its
looks as
1
if
these
See on this point Heath, Arutarchus, 31, Burnet, EGP, <58, Kahn, Anaximander, 89 f. Burnet suggests, referring to Homer, that in early Greek thought aer could be seen through, although it had the property of rendering invisible anything enclosed in it. Dreyer (Planetary Systems, 14) remarks that astronomical observation must have been still so backward that Anaximander had never noticed the frequent occultation of a bright star by the moon. According to the doxography (D.L. ix, 33), Leucippus also placed the path of the sun furthest from the earth, but with the stars between it and the moon. single statement in the Placita (DK, 28x400) seems to credit Parmenides with having placed the fixed stars nearest the earth. His curious doctrine of cmq>dvai may well owe something to Anaximander, from whom he might possibly have taken this feature also. It is, however, more likely that the doxographer misunderstood his
n. 2.
95
The Milesians
Anaximander has not outgrown; seems to be nine. 1
in
The
same
diameter) as the earth is, for Anaximander' s time, most remarkable. (In the next century Anaxagoras could be prosecuted for saying that it
It also causes larger than the Peloponnese.) the distance of the sun try to correlate it strictly with
its
wheel. 2
all
presented
mind, and
he was a
fearless and original thinker. Perhaps, however, the possithat the statement is not authentic cannot be altogether excluded. bility of eclipses, and of the phases of the The well-attested
explanation
and opening of the holes in the of the tubes mist through which heavenly bodies are seen, is another indication of the inchoate state of Anaximander's astronomy, and puts out of court the charitable guess of Simplicius that he might already
moon,
as
due to
alternate contracting
have been capable of using these phenomena to distances of the sun and moon.
and
of his system with any approach to certainty. Aetius speaks of the circles of the sun and
One
detail
on
this part
moon as
phrase
is
'lying obliquely', presumably to the celestial equator, and the no doubt, as Heath says, an attempt to explain the annual
ship, there is
'
Anaximander* s Astronomy
ways have been suggested
c
in
all
which Anaximander may have intended are conjectural. It is not even certain
occurring in passages which are evidently meant to apply to Anaximander among others, refers to the 2 solstices or simply, as it sometimes does, to the revolutions of the
(Tpo-rroci),
3 heavenly bodies.
In the passage of the Meteorologica quoted on p. 92, Aristotle states that the action of the heavenly fire in drying up the water caused 'winds and the turnings of the sun and moon'. Com-
menting on
this
From it [that is, that part of the original moisture which was vaporized by the sun] arose winds and turnings of the sun and moon, the notion being that the turnings (revolutions?) of those bodies too are accounted for by these
vapours and exhalations, since they turn in those regions where they receive a plentiful supply of the moisture.
a clear reference to the early idea that the cosmic fires, or heavenly bodies, are 'nourished' by moisture (for which see above,
is
Here
Further than that this second- or third-hand description will hardly allow us to go. Anaximander may have been supposing the limits of the sun's path in the ecliptic to be fixed by the abundance, in
p. 6y).
a certain region of the sky, of the moisture on which it depended for its existence; or he may have been trying to produce a theory to account for the whole fact of the cosmic revolutions, suggesting that the motion
and maintained by these currents of air which the evaporating process somehow set up. We are not offered any other explanation of the revolving motion of the cosmic circles, and the only
was
started
alternative
1
is
For which see Heath, Aristarchus, 32!?. Heidel (CP, 1912, 233, n. 4) thought it very prob' able that the ordinance of time* in the one extant fragment of Anaximander refers to the obliquity
would
which, he says, Anaximander is said to have discovered. He notes how well this with the designation of the litigants as the opposites hot and cold, wet and dry. 3 And to a parallel phenomenon of the moon, of which, however, Zeller considered that it was most unlikely that Anaximander would have been aware. Dreyer (Planetary Systems, 17,
of the
ecliptic,
fit
n. i) disagrees. 3 Arist. Meteor. 353 b 8 (quoted above, p. 92), 355325. In the latter passage Zeller pointed out that according to the most natural meaning of TOS Tpoirdcs ccCrrou Aristotle is speaking of the
'turnings' of the heaven, not of the sun. (ZN, 298, n. 4, Heath, Ari$tarckus9 33, n. 3.) For the contrary view see Cherniss, ACP, 135, n. 544. * 4 Cherniss, op. cit* 135, n. 544, disagrees, mainly because MeteoroL 355 324-5 shows definitely that it is air and not moisture which causes the turnings'. But there is certainly moisture in crfjp.
97
The Milesians
by
no
the 'eternal motion' of the Boundless, the nature of which is not In 'giving birth' to its 'offspring' the cosmos, it produced
still-born child.
specified.
Language
like this
no merely metaphorical sense. is on the whole the more Ingenuous that show to astronomy was still in its inlikely. Enough remains of someone like Anaximander fancy among the Greeks. The strength
as it sounds, this explanation
which he sketched the lay in the bold flight of imaginative reason with with outlines of a cosmos, and we may agree Dreyer that 'probably the
system never advanced beyond a mere sketch and was not worked out
5
in detail
The evidence
'
is as
follows:
And he
(F)
is
as the passage quoted on p. 90): in shape, with a breadth three times cylindrical
same context
its
depth.
earth hangs freely, not by the I, 6, 3 (AII): *The it is owing to its where of force but equal distance remaining any compulsion from everything. In shape it is rounded [see below for this word], circular,
Hippolytus, Ref.
like the
surfaces
one
is
that
resembles
The
reason
more fully given by Aristotle (De some who name its "indifference" 2
e.g.
remains at the centre had previously been Caelo, 29 5 bio, A 26): 'But there are
as the cause
of
its
remaining
at rest,
situated
and is equably related to the extremes has no impulse to move in one direction either upwards or downwards or sideways rather than in another; and since it is impossible for it to accomplish movement in opposite
at the centre
directions at once,
it
Eudemus, Astronomy, quoted by Theo (p. 198.18 Hiller, A 26) via Dercyllides: 'Anaximander says that the earth is freely suspended and moves around the centre of the universe.'
(J)
The
exact
(translated
passage ();
1
apparatus, and
*
So
Princ. Sap. 166, n. 2. Burnet and Stocks translate 6noi6Tryra; see Stocks's note adloc. in the
Comford,
Oxford
The
clear.
The Earth
1
in
Anaximander
scripts)
*
is difficult
it is
to determine.
used of a round-shouldered person in the Odyssey (xix, 246). Anaximander, if he used the word, may have meant that the surfaces of the earth are not flat but convex, as observation might
suggest, though this
convex', and
would make
column'
appropriate. The corresponding noun (yvpo$) is used of something ring-shaped, as for example a trench dug round a tree, and
less
is
another possibility
that
had a hole
bringing its shape into line with the circles of the heavenly bodies around it. Column-drums often had such a hole. 3
at the centre, thus
is
statement quoted from Eudemus in passage (W), that the earth in motion, need not be taken too seriously. In the same passage
The
Eudemus is credited with a probably exaggerated account of Thales's astronomical knowledge and with saying that Anaximenes discovered the cause of eclipses of the moon and the fact that its light is derived
sun. As Zeller suggests, and Alexander seems to have susthere has probably been a misunderstanding of the words in pected, which Anaximander expressed his highly original notion that the earth
from the
it
stationary.3
was undoubtedly to emancipate himself from the idea that the earth needed a support. The belief that it floated on water was, as we saw, an
inheritance
it
from mythology perpetuated by Thales, and intellectually was a leap forward when the argument from 'indifference' was invoked in favour of the view that it remained unsupported at the centre of a spherical universe, and that the heavenly bodies revolved in complete circles below as well as above it. Nothing shows more clearly
1
Oypdv, but
cannot agree that T& oxfjiicc uyp6v is a natural expression for *its character is moist*, especially when followed by crrpoyyOXov. * It is interesting that the Babylonian map illustrated by Kahn as a probable prototype of Anaximander's (Anaximander^ pi. i) not only shows the world as circular but has a round hole in the middle. This is explained as 'probably left by the scribe's compass*, but only because
any rate no other good explanation* (op. cit. 83). 303, Alex. op. Simpl. De Caelo^ 532. 6ff. Burnet's contrary view (EGPy 66) is bound need not avail ourup with certain other preconceptions which are not necessarily correct. selves of the emendation of Montucla KEITCCI for KiveiTcci, though KEITCCI mpl TO -roD KOO-IIOU piaov
there
3
is
at
ZN,
We
would be a very
is
quite likely,
disc of the
99
The Milesians
the independent quality of Anaximander's mind, and, as we shall see, the advance was too rapid for some of his successors. Nearly two centuries
later,
Plato paid
view,
In the
when
first
the compliment of making Socrates adopt his he said in the Phaedo (io8E, trans. A. J. Church):
him
is a spherical body placed in the place then, I believe that the earth has no need of air or any other it centre of the heavens, and that therefore 1 in all their parts, and the heavens force to support it: the equiformity of the it hold to thing in equipoise up. equipoise of the earth itself, are sufficient in incline cannot any direction, either placed at the centre of what is equiform
more or
less: it will
could not be long Clearly the recognition of the earth's sphericity in the Milesian tradition, and the delayed, but it did not appear first
mention of air
Is
material support, for they simple-minded notion that the earth needed supposed it to be buoyed up by air.
(and might in any case have assumed) that just as the a beginning out of the apeiron^ so also it will have an had world-order from which it came. end, fading back, as it were, into the formless state
the apeiron itself is 'eternal and ageless', 'immortal and indestructible*. So Aetius (A 14):
We are told
Only
Anaximander of
existing things
it all
is
Miletus, son of Praxiades, says that the first principle of the Boundless; for from this all come into being and into
perish.
But our sources nowhere explain how this will occur. It looks as if Anaximander were less interested in the end of a world than in its this beginning. The one sentence of his which we possess (if indeed is his) has been commonly held to refer to it of the sentence first part
in the words: 'Things perish into that out of which they have their being': but in fact this obviously describes the transformation of the
elements into one another, which, far from signifying the destruction of the world, is the process by which it is maintained.*
1
For
6iioi6-rT|s
as similarity in the geometrical sense see Kahn, Anaximander, 79, n. 3. this, CP, 1912, 233-4. As to the destruction of die world, Heidel
says (234, n. 3) : 'No doubt Anaximander believed in the destruction of the world, and so of the opposites also; but he doubtless thought of this as a question of nutrition/ This is very possible,
but
we
IOO
relevant
since
is
when
there will
have prevailed comleft, 1 and dried it all pletely up. This will clearly upset the balance of the universe which is maintained by the alternate and mutual encroachment of the opposites on each other, followed their recession as
fire, its
'penalty*
Anaximander says 'according to the ordinance (or assessment) of time'., to be anything other than the annual alternation of the seasons.
place as
dry would obviously disorganize Cornford connected this possibility with the
5 archaic idea of a 'great summer' and 'great winter , and assumed 'alternate destructions of the world by the Hot and by the Cold moisture'. Our world will be ultimately destroyed by fire, the next
by
is
flood. 2 This
meant, but
if so, it
from reabsorption into the something apeiron, and it is difficult to see how the Hot, having once been allowed to gain the supreme victory or commit the supreme injustice could ever be
different
its
forced to give up
state,
ill-gotten gains.
If that
A
is
cosmos
starts
from a neutral
Anaximander
apeiron as the arche rather than water or anything else, then we have indeed failed in our interpretation of him and there is little chance of success.
(7)
Origin of animal
and human
life
consistency (and complete disregard for religious or mythological modes of thought) as due to a continuation of the same process of 'separating-out' through the action of the hot and dry on the cold and moist: for life arose in the moist element through the action on it of the sun's warmth. This was theory probably connected with the persistent belief that even in
the present world
1
or elements, into their proper stations, the next stage of animal life. This is explained with remarkable
the emergence
life is
'
warmth of
9,
quoted above,
Princ. Sap. 183!". Certainly, as Cornford says, 'the notion of alternate destruction of at least agreatpartofmankindbyfireandfloodwasdeeplyrootedinGreekthought*. Cf. also p. 388, below.
101
The Milesians
an obputrescent matter, a belief doubtless based on observation * servation', as Dr W. P. D. Wightman has remarked, which must
*
familiar,
climate'. 1
The
6 (A 1 1) : He said that living creatures arose from the evaporation of the moist element by the sun; and that man originally resembled another creature, namely a fish.'
(a) Hippolytus, Ref.
6,
(i)
born
Aetius v, 19, 4 (A3o): 'Anaximander said that the first animals were in moisture and surrounded by prickly integuments,* but that as they
to the drier part, the integument split off,
and
and 98)
He says moreover
a different species, on food for themselves, man alone needs a long period of suckling; hence if he had been originally what he is now he could never have survived.'
that originally man was born from creatures of the grounds that whereas other creatures quickly find
The
interest.
references to the origin of mankind are naturally of particular So far we have nothing inconsistent with the supposition that
Anaximander was describing its gradual evolution, on Darwinian lines, from some marine species. Indeed the statement of Hippolytus, that man 'originally resembled another creature, namely a fish', would, by itself, hardly allow a different interpretation. Yet this does not seem to
have been in fact what he meant. Plutarch in his Quaestiones Conviviales
(730 E,
A 30)
says that at
first
in fish,
and makes
this
meaning by contrasting with the more plausible view that they are related to them. The guests are discussing the custom of abstaining
clearer
from
fish
on
religious grounds.
this
people Ancestor, believing, like the Syrians, that man arose from the wet element. 'For this reason,' he continues, 'they reverence the fish as
1
who do
One of them mentions examples of because they worship Poseidon as Fosterer and
Growth of Scientific Ideas, 14. Spontaneous generation seemed an incontrovertible fact to Aristotle (unfortunately for him, since it made an awkward exception to his general theory of the workings of nature), and the belief lingered on in Europe until the nineteenth century. See Guthrie, In the Beginning, 41 f. J. A. Wilson in Before Philosophy, 59, says that the modern
Egyptian peasant still believes in the life-giving power of the mud left behind by the retreating Nile. (Both these last writers quote further illustrations of the belief.) 2 9X01015, the same word which is used for the bark of a tree in the passage from the Stromateis quoted on p. 90, above. 3 Or * lived a different life* (i.e. on land). See
KR,
141, 142.
102
men were
first
born
in fish,
manner of galei and become capable of looking after themselves, they emerged and occupied the land. And so just as fire devours the matter in which it was kindled and which is father and mother to it (as
the
who
Ceyx
in Hesiod), so
father
common
and
The
same
effect (iv, 7,
A 30):
Anaximander of Miletus said that in his opinion there arose out of water and earth, when warmed, either fish or creatures resembling fish. In these creatures men were formed, and the young were retained within until the time of puberty; then at last the creatures were broken open and men and women emerged already capable of finding their own nourishment
theory of Anaximander seems then to have been that human embryos grew inside the bodies of the early fish-like creatures, and
later
The
emerged
first
as fully-formed
in the
place by deduction from the hypothesis that all life had its moist slime acted on by the heat of the sun, this being in its in origin turn only a particular stage in the evolution of the cosmos by the inter-
action of the opposites. It would acquire seeming confirmation either from observation or from the lore of Egyptians or Orientals. The first
living creatures
to a moist
human
infant
could hardly have survived under these conditions unless some special
Its logic seems to require, if Anaximander acted *just like* that he did eat fish, or approve of eating it. This would also be a satisfactory reason why his philosophy was less rntKT i$ (' humane') than that of the Syrians and others. Plutarch no
1
the
fire,
doubt knew nothing of Anaximander's actual habits of diet. But again, if this were so, he would be more likely to assume that like most ordinary men he ate fish than that he preached an abstention for which there is no other evidence at all. Yet the negative sense of Si^oAe -irp6$ seems undoubted, however much one would like it to mean *he mistreated as food* c 7270 <*nrco6ev fjnaj
:
Trp6$KivocT<i
it
must be
5iap<5cAAovresand SopF Trp6sTfiv Kcodov SiapdAouuev auroOs. If the text is sound, intended to convey that Anaximander deprecated the eating offish because it resembled
TrdQt)
*
the action of
in devouring parents, and the unreasonableness* of his philosophy consists simply in the fact that he justified the ban by his queer idea of men coming out offish rather than
fire
being 6noyVl$
ml
But
if so, it is
103
The Milesians
protection were devised, and here the example of the galeus came to his mind as a possible solution. This name was applied to dogfish or on the parental affection of gaki, sharks, and Plutarch,
commenting
says creature
(De
Soil.
itself,
Anim. 9820): 'They produce an egg, and then the not outside, but within their own bodies, and nurse it
it
as if there
Thegalei in particular reproduce viviparously, and allow their young to issue forth and feed, then take them back and enfold
P rolls 494 c:
in the
them
womb
to rest/
The species that Plutarch has in mind is no doubt the smooth dogfish
(mustelus
levis, Aristotle's yocAeos
Ae!o$), a
forms 'the subject of one of Aristotle's most celebrated descriptions, and a famous example of his anatomical erudition'. 1 Aristotle (HA^
565bi) refers to the remarkable peculiarity that 'the young develop with the navel-string attached to the womb, so that, as the eggsubstance gets used up, the embryo
is
sustained, to
all
appearances,
in the case of quadrupeds. The navel-string is long, and adheres just as to the under part of the (each navel-string being attached as it
womb
also to the
He
'galei in
general can extrude their young and take them back again' (565 bi4), a belief which persisted in the middle ages, Burnet 71, n. 2)
(GP,
thinks that Anaximander's comparison is sufficiently accounted for by the anatomical details of the placenta and umbilical cord, and that there
is
no need
to associate
him with
Much
as
one would
like to discover
owned
Greek natural philosophy, it seems hardly likely that a belief which was still seriously held by Aristotle, and which
illustration for his purpose.
2
Fishes, 41.
See
Thompson
s.v.
information.
After all this discussion, it must be pointed out that the appearance of the yoAeol in Plutarch's reference to Anaximander depends on an emendation of the MS. text, which reads wcnrep ol TrocXcciol.
adloc^ This makes no sense, and the correction may be taken as certain, especibetween the two words, to a Byzantine copyist, might be no more than that between PAAEO1 and TAAEO1. Kirk however believes (KR, 142) that the comparison may
(See
DK, crit. n.
104
Anaximander's Meteorology
(8)
Meteorology
Anaximander's reported views on meteorological phenomena provide further illustration of his principle of consistency, that events in
the present world must be attributed to the continued operation of the same forces and processes that brought about its formation in the beginning. This is especially obvious in his explanation of wind, which
he regarded
as a flow
of air, or as
is
air in
motion.
occurring
'Wind
it
a flow of
air,
when
by
are set in
motion [or
*
liquefied]
(The
finest
7 (AII): Winds are produced when the are separated off, and being gathered together are
i,
6,
action.'
As O.
Anaximander
Gilbert remarked (Meteor. Theorien^ 512), the brief note about inserted by Aetius in his section on winds seems to have
conflated Theophrastus's reports of his explanation of winds on the one other. Comparison with Hippolytus suggests that
the cosmogonic process of apokrisu is still at work. After water had been separated from earth, the sun drew vapour up from the water to
form the atmosphere. This in its turn, as the separating-out' continues, divides into two substances, a lighter (finer, drier) and a heavier
is set in motion as wind, the latter precipitated as of same operation of peripheral heat on the moist the part 2 centre which in due course was responsible for the emergence of life.
(wetter).
The former
rain.
It is all
not be Anaximander's, but put in by Plutarch as throwing light on Anaximander's theory. This is of course possible, but I do not agree with Kirk that the knowledge which it displays * is unlikely* for Anaximander. Inhabitants of an ancient seaport probably knew more about the facts of life among fishes than do the unscientific among ourselves. 1 Reading uncertain. Translated here is TTJS & yns tor& TOU fjMou dvaSiSoi^vns. Cf. Diels, note
on Dox. 560.10,
a
Gilbert, op.
cit.
406, n.
theory bears a superficial resemblance to Aristotle's, and might therefore come under suspicion of having been brought into conformity by our sources under Peripatetic influence.
The
assumption of two sorts of exhalation, a dry and a wet, Aristotle continues 'Of these the exhalation containing the greater quantity of moisture is the origin of rainwater, whereas the dry one is the origin and substance of winds.* But he goes on to emphasize that, since the two exhalations are specifically different, the natural substances of wind
Starting
from
his
(Meteor, 3 60 an):
and rain are also different, and from that to criticize those who claim that the same substance, air, becomes wind when set in motion (wvoOuevov) and rain when condensed (owiard^evov). This
105
The Milesians
Once
the air has been separated into wind (the light and dry part)
and rain-cloud (the heavy and wet), these, and in particular the wind, are made to account for thunder and lightning. Thus Aetius (A 23), in his section on thunder, lightning, meteorites, waterspouts and whirlwinds:
Anaximander says that all these are caused by wind. When it is imprisoned in thick cloud and forces a way out by reason of its fine texture and lightness, then the tearing makes the noise, and the contrast with the blackness of the
cloud produces the
It
flash.
1
e
into
would appear that, in the process of separating-out' of the air wind and cloud, some of the lighter and finer sort may find itself
so completely surrounded by the denser that it cannot easily complete * the process of gathering together' with its like. The result is a violent
by us
as thunder
and lightning.
Anaximander's belief in 'innumerable worlds' has been the subject of vexed and difficult controversy. Its natural place is earlier in the
exposition, but
its
it
for
Full discussion
demands
is
more minute
collation
sible in a general
work, but
thought. Post- Aristotelian sources speak of Anaximander as having believed in the existence of ccmipoi KOCTHOI or orrsipoi oupccvoi innumerable
is
The main
question at issue is
whether
this
means a
succession
was inevitably the view of the monist Anaximander, whose theory of progressive <5nr6Kpi<ji$ from a single original substance involves as a necessary consequence that the substance forming wind
and rain
is
Klvrjcnv dipos,
ultimately one. Cf. 349320, where the same people are also said to define wind as and see also Gilbert, op. cit. 523, n. 2. Kahn (Anaximander, 63) retains the full text
of Aet. and
1
how
(404-7).
106
existence of an infinite
that Anaximander must have taught the number of coexisting worlds. Nestle, re-editing Zeller' s history of Greek philosophy after his death, was persuaded by Burnet's arguments (ZN, 312, n.). Then in 1934 Cornford, in an
vigorously defended the original view of Zeller, subjecting the evidence to a thorough reexamination and adducing fresh arguments in favour of the conception
nowhere
Unfortunately Aristotle himself provides no definite lead. He attributes a doctrine of oroipoi x6a{ioi or ccrreipoi oupavoi
to
Speaking in De Caelo (303 bio) of philosophers who posit one element alone, 'either water or air or fire or a substance rarer than water but denser than air', he says that according
explicitly
Anaximander.
to
them
'
this
'
but
it is
passage he has Anaximander in 1 if even we could that mind, say by oupavoi he meant 'worlds'. All our testimonies therefore are later, and cannot be directly referred
at least doubtful
whether in
this
back to
Aristotle.
They
attribute to
Anaximander
oupccvoi or () crrreipoi Koanoi or (c) both oupavoi and Koajjiou It may be convenient to have the passages collected, though some of course
must be seen
investigations.
made
The
op.
(a) Aet. ap. Stob. (A 17): 'A. orn^fjvoro TOU$ dnrsipous oupavou$ 6sou$. Placita however have TOU$ aorepas oupavious deou$. See Comford,
cit.
10.
(i)
Simpl. Cael 615.15 (A 17): arreipov 6s irpcoTos urredero, iva sxrj XprjaOai TTpos Ta$ yevsaeis cxpdovcos xai xoapious 6 aroipous O^TOS Kai EKaorov
()
TCOV Koa^cov
(ii)
s,
d-TTStpou
cbs
8oKi.
Simpl. Cael.
ob$ 'A.
iJiev
apx^v
oarsipous e
aurou
1 Burner (.EGP^ 55f.) saw in the intermediate element a reference to Anaximander's and Stocks in his translation followed him, but most scholars have been against the identification, e.g. Zeller and Diels. See especially the arguments against it in Ross*s ed. of Arist. Physics,
p. 482.
I0 7
The Milesians
Tcp TrArjOei KOCTHOUS TTOISIV 6oKi, Aan<nnro$ 5s xai Arj^oKpiTos ocrreipous TCQ TrAf|0i TousKoajJious Iv OTrdpcp Tcp KEvcp xai t dardpcov TCO TrAfjOei TCOV OCTOIJICOV
owioTOcaOai
In these two passages the use of 8oKe! seems to indicate a certain first the argususpension of assent on the part of Simplicius. In the ment for the apeiron being infinite in quantity may well not have been
Anaximander's
(iii)
(A 17): ol nsv
yap
ArmoKpiTOVKaiuarEpov
auroOs Kai
ccXXcov psv
ocei
statement that there were innumerable worlds *some always coming into being and others passing away' introduces temporal
The
succession as well as spatial plurality. The atomists of course believed in both. The previous phrase, 'assumed them to come into being and
away everlastingly', would fit Anaximander on the assumption that he believed in only one world at a time. Here he is simply put with the atomists as a believer in innumerable worlds, but in (ii) above
pass
Simplicius correctly notes that the atomic world- view was different in that they recognized (a) infinite empty space and (3) an infinite number
of atoms.
(iv) Aetius (Ai4): 'A..
i$
ywaa0ai
This passage in isolation would certainly be taken to refer to successive, not coexistent, worlds.
(v) Aetius (A 17): *A., 'AvaijJiVTi$, 'Apx&aos, Atoyevris, Aeiknrrros, A-niioKpiTOs, 'EiriKoupos ocTTfiipous Koa|Jious V TCO OTTfiipcp KOTO: TTaaov
Trepiaycoyrjv.
all earlier
physical theory.
is
On
Anaximenes contrast
13,
where he
said to
108
explicit contrast to
Koapous.
Comford
See on this Cornford, op. dt. 5. Moreover, as Ps.-Plutarch not only omits the Milesians from the noted,
believers in innumerable worlds, but speaks of GoAffc KCCI o! dor' ocuroO (which must surely include Anaximander) as having believed that our world exists alone.
The words KOCTOC Traaccv Ttspiccycoyriv (or TrepioTcccnv) are rather obscure. Burnet, holding that Anaximander did believe in innumerable coexistent worlds, and that these were visible as the stars, rendered
:
'in
whichever direction
we
turn
Zeller,
more reasonably,
'in every
1CTOV
ETTlKOUpO$
CCV1C7OV 81VCCI
TO
JJIETOC^U
TCOV
KOCTJJCOV 8i6tcrn}|Jia.
The
be referred
to below.
(vii) Cicero, N.D. I, 10, 25 (A 17): Anaximandri autem opinio est natives esse deos longis intervallis orientes occidentesque, eosque innumerabiles
esse
mundos.
(viii)
Augustine, Civ. Dei vm, 2 (A 17): Non enim ex una re sicut Thales ex umore, sed ex suis propriis principiis quasque res nasci putavit* Quae rerum
principia singularum esse credidit infinita, et innumerabiles
quaecumque
mundos modo
dissolvi
existimavit) quanta quisque aetate sua manere potuerit, nee ipse aliquid divinae
mend
in his
rerum operibus
tribuens*
This passage by itself would not be inconsistent with the idea of a succession of single worlds, but no doubt Augustine's source shared the view that Anaximander believed in innumerable worlds in the same
sense as Epicurus.
I
experienced
by
deciding whether Anaximander's apeiron ought to be classed as a monistic substratum or a mixture. His thought was too
later interpreters in
primitive to recognize
its
own inconsistency.
1 6 (A 9): Aeyei 6* ocurnv uiyre OScop iriYre oXXo TI (c) (i) Simpl. Phys. 24. TCOV KocAouiaevcov elvoci oroi)(eicov, dAA* hipov TIVCC 9uaiv ccrreipov, s fjs orrcarras yivsaOai TOI>$ oupcxvoOs KQI TOI/S tv aCrrois x6aiJious.
109
The Milesians
(ii)
Hippol. Ref.
fjs
i,
6, i
911
TGOV OVTOOV
9\!raiv TIVOC
TOV
orrrEipou, 8
reproduced
the text of Theophrastus, we may take it that the meaning was, as Dox. say, not 'worlds in them' but 'order inherent in them'. (Diels,
1
DK
32 3 after lauding Hippolytus as 'fidissimum excerptorem', changed the manuscript reading to KOO-JJIOUS to bring it into line with passages
(i)
and
(iii).)
(iii)
dnroKeKpicrSai KOCI
TO drreipov...e ou 6f| 9T|<ji TOUS TE oupccvous KaOoAou TOUS arrocvras ocrreipous OVTOCS
words
This passage, in which the worlds have become 'innumerable', the sv CCUTOIS are missing, and drravrccs has been transferred from
come into
line
(Cornford,
In general, *a close examination of the doxographic tradition shows that the further it gets from Aristotle and Theophrastus, the oftener
is
i'
more
is
heard of dirEipoi
(Cornford, Hid.}. than the word orreipov, the words KOO-JJIOS and oupocvos, as used by those who were trying to interpret Anaximander, had more
No
less
than one meaning. It is perhaps more probable than not that Anaximander himself did not use xoapios in the sense of world or universe.
Basically the
word meant
'order',
it
comall,
bined with
this the
in
eyes, a beautiful thing.) Because, to a Greek thinker, the most notable thing about the universe was the order which it displayed (above
Greek
on a cosmic scale like the movements of sun, moon and was what contrasted it most radically with the chaos which he supposed to have preceded it, the word took on in addition
all
in events
stars),
and
this
the special meaning of 'world-order' and then simply 'world'. This and there are in it is difficult to which happened gradually, passages
be sure
it is
fr.
30); but
would be unequivocally
no
Innumerable Worlds*
5
in
Anaximander
understood as 'world before the fifth century B.C. It is, however, so used by Empedocles in the middle of that century. 1 Whatever Anaximander wrote, our sources are interpreting, not quoting it.
In later philosophical writing, Koapos can mean (a) world-order, universe; () a separate region within the world-order. Grammarians
say that
water,
cit. i.)
oupocvos,
air, earth,
De
Oupocvos was used in three senses, distinguished by Aristotle in Caelo (278b9ff.): (i) the outermost circumference of the universe; (ii) the heavens in general, including the paths of fixed stars,
planets,
some nearer
sun and moon, which were believed to lie in different planes, to, some further from the centrally situated earth; (iii) the
universe as a whole. This certainly seems sufficient to justify Cornford's * claim that doxographers, meeting with statements derived from
Theophrastus about a plurality of KOCTHOI or oupccvoi, might well be in doubt as to the meaning of the word'.
Briefly Cornford's view,
which
when
whatever Greek terms), of an infinite plurality of worlds, he meant a succession of single worlds in time* When he mentioned cnreipoi
oupocvoi, saying for instance that they were gods, he did not mean worlds but something different to which we shall come in a moment. Statements which refer unambiguously to innumerable coexistent
(vi),
above), or in which
it
would be
strained
not present, arose from a confusion between oupovoi and KOO-JJIOI. This confusion is not due to Theophrastus, but had its origin in assumptions natural enough once the Epicureans had
made
arising haphazard at different points in infinite space. If we agree that Anaximander held the doctrine of
an everlasting
succession of single worlds, we need not bring into it, as Cornford did, the wording of our single verbal fragment of Anaximander (discussed
above, pp. 80 f.). His statement that things perish into that out of which
1
Emped.
fr.
134,
5.
See p. 208, n.
i,
word
Ill
The Milesians
they come, because they must make just recompense to one another, seems rather to describe the cyclic, seasonal rhythm that goes to the
maintenance of a single cosmos, not the reabsorption of the separated contents of a cosmos back into the primal apeiron. But he held that the
world-order, as
had had a beginning, would also perish, and contrasted it with the immortal and indestructible character of the apeiron itself. This is doubtless the meaning of the statement about orreipoi
it
KOCTHOI in Aetius
(()
(iv),
successive worlds.
Anaximander
called the
on this view to the innumerable rings drrsipous oupocvous gods, of fire which are the stars, and which resulted from the splitting apart of the original sphere of fire which surrounded the world at its beginrefers
ning. These it would be natural to call oupccvoi, in a sense corresponding to one of those given by Aristotle, that is, any of the many heavens
which carry the heavenly bodies. Up to the time of Anaximander, the Greeks had generally supposed that there was one single Ouranos, and this Ouranos was of course a god, well known as such from the theo-
cosmogony
and become many, and it is reasonable split up that he should both have enough emphasized the fact that there were now onreipoi oupccvoi and have retained the idea of their divinity,
had
which
sophers
down
Kocl
to Plato
and Aristotle and beyond, was the belief in the When he is reported as having spoken of these
KOOVOV (or TOU$.
.
oupccvous
TOV
EV aOrot$
"heavens" being the rings of the heavenly bodies, the Koano$ or Koanot in them may be the region or regions of the world-order framed by
them' (Cornford, n). Whether or not Burnet was right in maintaining with some of
the doxographers the opposite view, that Anaximander believed in the simultaneous existence of a plurality of universes like our
infinity
to
that
The substitution of 6ccrrpa$ oupavious in Plutarch's version may represent, as Cornford suggested, a gloss on the other. If so, it is a correct interpretation.
112
The
stars are
this
If
Anaximander
also
single
worlds, and
ccrreipoi oupavoi meaning a large number of circles we which see as the stars, it is obvious that he used heavenly to misconstruction if there was open language any antecedent tempta-
spoke of
on the part of the doxographers to misconstrue him. This temptation was provided by the fact that the atomists of the fifth century did believe in the coexistence of innumerable worlds in infinite space, and in fact we find Anaximander expressly linked with them, and with their successors the Epicureans, when he is described as having held the same
tion
belief (cf.
()
(iii),
(v), above).
The
quoted above as (<5) (vi), assuming that the writer is thinking of spatial and not temporal distance (and so far as Epicurus is concerned he
doubtless had the intermundia in mind),
may
already noted between Koa^oi and oupavoi. The distances between the oupavoi of Anaximander (sun to moon, moon to stars, stars to earth)
were in
fact equal,
Cicero's sentence (() (vii)) it is very difficult to decide whether the longa intervalla are spatial or temporal, but in any case his source was
probably influenced by the Epicurean theory. We know, however, that the belief of the atomists in innumerable worlds was closely reasoned from their ideas about the nature of body and of space. Not only is there no evidence for these ideas in Anaxi-
mander, but one may say with confidence that a clear philosophic distinction between body and empty space was not made before the brought to bear by Parmenides on earlier systems. The early monists had identified all that exists (TO ov) with their primary physis, which was a material body. Their logic had gone no further, but, said Parmenides, in effect, if material body comprises the whole of that which exists (TO 6v), then
fifth
century,
when
it
resulted
from the
criticism
what
not body cannot exist, that is, empty space is iaf] 6v, nonexistent. In the face of this unanswerable reasoning (for so it seemed at the time) it required considerable boldness on the part of Leucippus
is
and Democritus
empty
space,
113
The Milesians
only do it in paradoxical terms. They said that the non-existent no less than the existent/ 1
'
exists
Having asserted their right to speak of empty space as distinct from any form of body, they went on to show that it must be strictly infinite,
using the kind of arguments which seem obvious today but had prob2 ably not been thought of before. In this infinite space they supposed there to be an infinite number of atoms of different shapes, drifting with
aimless motion. If they formed a world-order in one part of the infinite void, it was unreasonable to suppose that they would not do so
all
the cosmoi
as
The
from
state
by Anaximander
very different
this,
and
represents, as should
is
not empty space but body, and, more living and divine. This last fact gives addi-
tional support to the supposition that he did not imagine it as strictly have already seen that his mind had probably not infinite in extent.
We
grasped the notion of strict spatial infinity, and apart from that it is difficult to believe that any Greek thought of a divine being as infinite in
the divine All as a sphere, to clings spherical shape in Aristotle, who as divine and the oupovos regards says that the sphere is the only fitting shape for it on account of its perfection. Just as the earth is at the centre
extent.
being and perished within a divine and spherical apeiron. 'Vaguely imagined', let us say, for, astonishingly rational as his system was in many ways, it looks as
of the spherical universe, so Anaximander that the universe as a whole arose and
if this were something he had taken for granted because the Greek mind was not yet ready to argue out the implications contained in the notions
of the infinity or non-infinity of space. (Kirk deals with the question of innumerable worlds in Anaximander
in
1
KR,
1 2 1-6.
On pp.
nif. he argues
briefly that
6v,
Arist Metapk. 985b4ff. They called the solid T6 pc&Aov T6 6v TOU tifj 6vro$ Elvoci qxxoiv.
3
o06v
the
come from
atomists.
3
13, 2,
Democritus, A 40.
"4
mander, contrary to his previous opinion, by the arguments of Mondolfo's L* Infinite* nel pensiero dei GrecL See now Kahn, Anaximandery 46-53.)
D.
(i)
ANAXIMENES
Date and writings
about the middle of the sixth century, a
Anaximenes was
also active
younger contemporary of Anaximander and probably still a young man when Ionia changed hands after the defeat of the Lydian king
Croesus by Cyrus the Persian. He is described as friend, pupil and successor of Anaximander. 1 Diogenes Laertius (n, 3) says that he
wrote in
*a simple
style*,
and although he no
it
this verdict
allows us to
As
that the philosopher's works survived into the a criticism it contrasts with Theophrastus's
comment on the somewhat poetical language of Anaximander, and the difference in style perhaps reflects a more prosaic and scientific approach on the part of Anaximenes. We hear no more of the opposites conducting
a warfare like hostile powers or 'making reparation for an 'injustice'.
(2)
5
Air as
'arche
still
firmly set in the monist tradition. That of the nature of things was
one which showed how 'all things proceed from one and are that dogma which in the eyes of the ancient resolved into the same world went right back to their legendary poets like Musaeus (D.L. i, 3). The chief interest of his system lies in his abandonment of the almost
still
nameless apeiron of Anaximander and the reasons which led him to the choice of a different arche for all things. It was no longer to be something
1
known
On
only by
its
characteristic
in the
The
it
117-21.
that
in Mus. Helv. 1954, question of his precise date is complicated. See G. B. Kerferd rather cavalierly when he suggests p. 121 Kerferd seems to treat the word frralpos may imply no more than affinity in doctrine with Anaximander.
"5
The Milesians
baffling
we have
qualities but qualified things, but Anaximenes chose rather to give his arche a directly substantial name. It was air. Perhaps his thought went further than Anaximander's. The Boundless, when it had acquired
'bounds' and become differentiated into the variously qualified components of a cosmos, was no longer the Boundless, but air could be
denser or rarer, hotter or colder and still remain the same substance. Though conscious differentiation is still in the future, we are a step
nearer to the distinction between substance and quality, that distinction which Aristotle erroneously supposed to have been fully present to the
minds of all
difficulties
which
in
rest?
Anaximenes
',
lies
seems
mander Anaximenes should have gone back to the idea that the primary substance was one of the things known to experience and selected 'air'. But an examination of his theory shows that it was really an advance on Thales and even on Anaximander himself.
It is
not
difficult to see
it
ways of
thought, for
all
was an
intellectual
on the same level, so that if there is a single primary substance at all it must be a more primitive, a neutral and no longer perceptible state of things, from which all alike had evolved. Why did Anaximenes go back
to
one of the
familiar
how can it be
said that in so
advance on Anaximander?
Unconscious presuppositions
To introduce the motives which led Anaximenes to his choice of air, it may be useful to make a general observation, which must certainly
1
There
is
no need
To give this
was taken by Thales, even if he did call the kind of name to it after Anaximander was a different
116
Unconscious Presuppositions
be made some time, about the nature of philosophical thinking as a whole and that of the earliest philosophers in particular. Though not
new,
remind ourselves of it. Philosophy (and science) develop from two different sources. There is what may be called the scientific element proper, the combination of observation and conscious
it is
essential to
rational thought
which
is all
be using and is often the only factor taken into account by the historian. But in fact no human being makes use of rational thought and observation alone.
The second
factor
is
suppositions which are in his mind before he starts philosophizing at all, and which may be an even more powerful influence than the other
on the system which he will ultimately produce. Under this head comes the difference between one
individual and
another. William James described the history of philosophy as to a great extent that of a clash of human temperaments. Temperament
being no conventionally recognized reason, the philosopher urges impersonal reasons only for his conclusions. Yet his temperament gives
him
'
more
of opposite temper to be out of key with the world's character and in his heart considers them incompetent and "not in it"
in the philosophic business, even
dialectical ability.
.
. .
He
men
far excel
him
in
There
our
our premisses
is
never
6). Many have made similar observations, as for example Nietzsche, who in Beyond Good and Evil says that every kind of involungreat philosophy is 'the confession of its originator, a
and Aristotle were wrong tary and unconscious autobiography. Plato in naming the desire of knowledge as the parent of philosophy; in fact
another impulse has only made use of knowledge as an instrument. Like most theses, this one can be falsified by being carried to an extreme,
'
but there
is
much
truth in
it.
at
With this form of unconscious presupposition we are less concerned the moment. It is obvious that the bias of temperament will be
a man to a religious or a materialistic potent, for example, in inclining it and of the universe, may loom more largely when interpretation difference between the two main lines of we are ready to discuss the
07
The Milesians
tradition in early
Italian
or
Pythagorean. But in addition to the vagaries of individual temperament, there is another type of presupposition to which men are bom, and
which
to use
which they are compelled of current conceptions shared by all men of groundwork any given culture and never mentioned because it is taken for granted 1 as obvious*. These traditional conceptions (or it may be a new outlook
finds expression in the very language
c
that
moulded by the pressure of recent history, as in some of the forms taken by existentialism after the war of 1939) are powerful in every age, but had freer play in the early Greek philosophical systems than in most
All later systems have had their predecessors. They start by appraising and modifying the systems of others. But the Milesians had
others.
their conpredecessors. Before they embarked scious reflective activity, the ideas which filled their heads concerning the nature and working of the universe were derived from popular
no philosophical
on
pre-philosophical thought, steeped in myth, and it is perhaps worth noting that the only literature with which they were acquainted was
poetical.
in
which
all
philosophy
is
to a greater or less degree enmeshed, lay particularly heavy upon them, for they had not the latter-day advantage of reading in a variety of tongues. The degree to which they attained a rational outlook is ad-
mittedly astonishing. The mere fact of writing in prose was a great step forward. Indeed the effect of emphasizing the background of popular mythology against which these men must be seen should be
rather to increase than to belittle their intellectual stature, by bringing home the difficulties with which they had to contend. At the same time
effect
on
maturer thought, and it may sometimes hold the key to an otherwise unintelligible feature of their systems.
This reminder
may be
I
return to Anaximenes,
1
would suggest
useful at various stages of our inquiry. To that there were two kinds of
F. M. Cornford. See The Unwritten Philosophy, viii, and cf. also W. A. Heidel, Harv. Class. Stud, 1911, 114: 'Such common points of view would naturally not be the subject of discussion. Just because they constituted the presuppositions of all reflection they would be ignored, al-
to
118
Rarefaction
and Condensation
reason which led to his choice of air as the arche, one arising out of the train of thought which he was consciously pursuing, the other more
entangled in those unconscious presuppositions which were his inheritance from the current and popular views of his time.
(4) Explanation
of change:
rarefaction
and condensation
As
to the
first,
the
air,
as the Boundless of
their
which all things had and into which they were all resolved again. (E.g. Aet., B 2 ; being A But the problem which especially interested Anaxi7 in.it.} Hippol., menes was that of the process by which these changes occurred. If
Anaximander, as that out of
matter did not always remain in its primary state, was it possible to offer any natural explanation of why, or at least how, it changed and
developed the many manifestations under which it appears in the present world-order? This question of process receives great prominence in all
accounts of his system, and
we may
had
he thought
it
one which
his predecessors
Anaximander's notion of the primitive state of matter had been a fusion of the opposites so complete that their individual characteristics were entirely submerged and as opposites they could not yet be said to
exist; in his own eyes the apeiron was one. Their subsequent emergence was due to a process of separation, a kind of winnowing caused by the eternal motion of the living matrix (the nature of which motion is nowhere specified in our sources). This was a brilliant conjecture, but it was legitimate to suppose that it was entirely arbitrary. Moreover although it doubtless came to Anaximander with the force of a new idea, and he intended the word ekkrisis or apokrisis to have a purely
ourselves of something else, while recognizing that Anaximenes was in no position to use it as a criticism. have seen (pp. 68 , above) how this conception of the
scientific
meaning,
We
creation of a
as the separation of what had previously been bottom of many early mythological and poetic cosmogonies, both Greek and other. The examples are sufficient to of the human suggest that there lies behind it some universal tendency mind. It is one of those preconceptions of tradition of which I have
cosmos
mingled was
at the
spoken, and
it is
it
119
The Milesians
on
a pioneer of rational thought like Anaximander in his assertion of 'separation' as the fundamental process behind cosmogony.
Such criticism was not for Anaximenes, but he could at least lay stress on the arbitrary character of the assumption and point out that Anaximander's explanation of the changing forms of things invoked no known
and recognizable process of nature. To account for the world-order by natural causes (he seems to have argued), one must show its origin to have been due to some process which can still be verified today as
bringing about the transformation of one form of matter into another. Such a verifiable natural process was exactly what Anaximenes had to
offer, the
Aristotle in the Physics (187 a 12) divides the natural philosophers before his time into two classes. There are those who regard the under-
lying substance of things as one, identifying it with water, air, fire or an intermediate body, and generate the rest from it by a process of rarefaction and condensation; and there are those who suppose the contraries to
principle,
then be separated out. Their 'one' is therefore in among these he puts not only the pluralists Empedocles and Anaxagoras, but also Anaximander, to whose apeiron his more analytic mind
could not concede true unity. Among the first class he mentions no names, but the one early philosopher for whom the process of rarefaction and condensation is
attested
beyond doubt
is
air as his
primary principle Aristotle himself attests (Metaph. 984 a 5). Theophrastus in one part of his history of philosophy went so far as to
attribute this explanation of genesis to Anaximenes alone, a statement which Simplicius felt obliged to correct on the authority of Aristotle, who, as he says, in this passage includes a whole class of thinkers alike. There can, however, be little doubt that what Theophrastus says is nearer the truth. Cherniss has shown how Aristotle here, in attempting to accommodate the earlier natural philosophers to his own outlook, has
oversimplified
1
his
classification.
Probably,
as
Zeller
suggested,
Simpl. Phys. 149.32, Cherniss, ACP, 49 ft, 55. Here is one case at least where Theophrastus has not slavishly followed Aristotle. McDiarmicTs note (Harv. Class. Stud. 1953, 143,
1 2O
Apollonia in the next century followed Anaximenes in this respect. But at least there can be no doubt that he did say 'only Anaximenes ',
have
to introduce this theory. That was obvious, felt no need to contradict him.
A5:
companion of Anaximander, also posits a single infinite underlying substance of things, not, however, indefinite in character like Anaximander' s but determinate, for he calls it air, and says that it differs in rarity and density according to the different substances. Rarefied, it becomes fire; condensed, it becomes first wind, then cloud, and when condensed still further water, then earth and stones. Everything else is made of these. He too postulated eternal motion, which is indeed the cause of the change.'
clearly goes
back in the
last resort
to
but
is
differently
Ref. i, 7, i, A 7: 'Anaximenes, another Milesian and the son of Eurystratus, says the arche is infinite air, out of which proceeds whatever comes to be or has done so in the past or will exist in the future, gods also and
() Hippol.
Now in form the most evenly distributed (or uniform: oiicxXcoTonros) it is invisible, but it is made visible by hot and cold and wet and movement. It is in constant movement, otherwise the things which change could not do so. It assumes different visible forms as it is rarefied or condensed. When dispersed more finely, it becomes fire. Winds on the other hand are air in process of condensation, and from air cloud is produced by concenthe divine.
Everything
else is
made from
its
products.
when
it is
'
tration
(lit.
felting ).3
The
n.
cannot
1
much
(foe. cit.) misquotes Zeller into saying. sense of genesis (coming-to-be in general, and birth in particular) is probably still making its influence felt on cosmogonical thought. 3 Miletus was, after all, a famous centre of the textile industry, which may account for his even
Not
Lit.
Simplicius, as
offspring*.
McDiarmid
The double
starry vault to a
'little felt
cap*
121
The Milesians
and still further condensation earth, while stones are the most condensed form of all. Thus the most important features in genesis are contraries, hot and cold.*
The
no doubt be read
in conjunction
the odd statement get rid of a small and troublesome point first, and first has its own in Hippolytus that air everything else 'offspring',
is
To
The
in Cicero. generated from them, seems to be explained by the speaker and water other of are the air fire, and elements, earth, 'offspring*
everything else is made up of these. This suggests two stages in the making of the world, the formation of the elements by condensation
air,
rest',
by which
must be meant
chiefly organic, living nature. It has been thought that unlikely having once hit on the process of rarefaction and condensation as sufficient to explain even the genesis of stones from air,
Anaximenes should
feel the
doxography has therefore Theophrastus been blamed for reading into Anaximenes the later theory of the four elements or 'simple bodies' as such, and their combination. This
theory, expressly formulated by Empedocles and adapted by Aristotle to his own explanation of change, was not yet consciously articulated.
It
was
it
called forth
by
deliberate
But
it is
incredible
that
primary oppositions between hot and cold, wet and dry, was preparing the way for it. All our evidence about him indicates that although no
doubt there were other opposites, these four had a distinct primacy as cosmogonical agents. We have seen with what consistency he employed
the action of hot and dry on cold and wet to explain the origin of everything, from the formation of earth and stars to the birth of the
first
when he
says
(ACP^
55):* Neither
set
his "contraries"
The
'Of spring'
of Air
of opposed agencies but an indefinite number of physical ingredients.' Moreover by speaking of the arche as air, instead of simply denoting it
by
its
we
leading characteristic with article and adjective, Anaximenes as have seen took a step towards the distinction between substance
and affection. When the inconsistencies of the monistic hypothesis became too obvious to be ignored, the fourfold scheme by which
Empedocles replaced it lay almost ready to his hand in the systems of his predecessors, requiring only to be clarified and raised to the position of an ultimate. It is more than likely that Anaximenes followed
Anaximander's lead in holding that the first products of the modification
of
air
were
fire,
'elements' or the Empedoclean roots' are still in the future, these three (the fiery, the wet and the cold par excellence) had a certain primacy for him as they had had for his mythological predecessors to
whom
It
1 Ouranos, Gaia and Oceanus were primal divinities. does not of course follow that once these were formed, a different
3 process supervened to produce the contents of the natural world. What Anaximenes said about this we do not know, for our sources are com-
pletely silent about his views on the origin of organic nature. Presumably he had nothing to say on this subject comparable to the bold and
Anaximenes and Diogenes (of Apollonia) ', says Aristotle (Metaph. 984a5), 'make air prior to water and in the fullest sense the origin of the simple bodies.' The process by which they are derived from it is
simple, and
little
graphers.
its
He
needs to be added to the explanations of the doxochooses air as primary because he seems to think that in
it is
ideas of elements
Cf. Kahn, Anaximander, 133 ff., a detailed discussion of the evidence for the origins of the * and opposites. On p. 149 he writes: Whatever terminology may have been
used by the sixth-century Milesians, it is certain that their conception of the natural world contained, in potential form, a view of earth, water, air, and fire as "members'* or "portions" of the cosmos/ However, the account in Simplicius does perhaps suggest, as Kahn later notes (156, n. 2), that the tetrad was not yet exclusive, and that Anaximenes included wind, clouds, and stones among the 'primary products' of air. (My own text was written before Kahn's book
appeared.)
would not necessarily follow even if our authorities in the Aristotelian tradition supposed did. But in fact they make no mention of any process other than rarefaction and condensation, and indeed SimpHcius (De Caelo, 615 20) says that Anaximenes made air the principle,
It
that
it
dpKlv
123
The Milesians
and
would always be If left alone, so to speak, like a rubber which no force is at the moment either stretching
as
it
piece of or comin
pressing.
But
it is
not
left
Anaximander
postulating an everlasting motion as a result of which its 'uniform' state (as Hippolytus says he called it) is disturbed and it becomes rarefied or
condensed in
result.
It
on various
visible
forms
as a
was to him an obvious fact of experience that the air on a damp day becomes visible as mist, and that by a continuation of the same process the mist or cloud solidified still further into rain or other forms of water ; and we still give the name of condensation to that unof England whereby the air pleasant process so familiar in some parts
turns to water and drips down the walls of our houses. When water is heated the reverse process occurs. It turns first into visible steam, and
then mingles with the invisible air. By an extension of these familiar processes he supposed it to be on the one hand further solidified into
earth and stones, and
on
the other, as
1
it
became
rarer
still,
to
become
hotter until
it
ignited as fire.
observe that the new process was linked with Anaximander's doctrine of opposites. The hot and dry were connected with rarity, the cold and wet with density. This was done explicitly, and with an attempt
We
we learn from an interesting passage of Plutarch in which, along with the account in his own post- Aristotelian terminology, he claims to repeat one of Anaximenes's own technical
at experimental proof, as
terms:
(d) Pint.
are
De
Prim. Frig. 7, 947 F, B i : 'As Anaximenes held long ago, we either the hot or the cold in the category of substances; they
affections of matter supervening on its alterations. What is and condensed he says is cold, but what is rare and "loose" 3 compacted (that I think is the actual word he used) is hot. Hence, he said, there is
can of course detect an inconsistency here, which Plato pointed out in his Timaeus. In A. E. Taylor's words (Timaeus, 316): 'If you are really in earnest with the doctrine of cyclical transformations, you must hold that whatever it is that is invariant throughout change, it cannot be a sensible body. All sensible bodies must be on the same level ; if one of them is a "phase",
all must be "phases".* If such a thought did not occur to Anaximenes that is no doubt due, in part at least, to the second kind of motive which, as is suggested below (p. 127), led him to the choice of air as the basic principle. At the same time, in spite of what some have said, Anaxi1
common
We
menes
stance;
certainly deserves the credit of having recognized the invisible atmospheric air as a suband it is scarcely a sensible one.
124
man blows both hot and cold with his mouth, when the lips press and condense it, but when it from an open mouth it is rarefied and becomes warm.'
cooled
Since one of the minor present-day controversies about Greek philosophers concerns the extent to which they made use of experiment, a brief excursus is perhaps permissible here. It is a controversy
by which man
acquires
from
practical
he naturally tends to derive their techniques and exalt the experimental side of
),
work. Cornford on the other hand, different light, was perhaps apt to belittle
in a very
of
it.
Without
argument, one may mention a point in which done less than justice to Anaximenes, and, though not of central importance, it has a certain interest of its own. In Prindpium Sapientiae (p. 6) he wrote:
affords another instance
Anaximenes
tested.
He
density; steam
dense than
ice.
If that
hotter and less dense than water, water hotter and less is so, a given quantity of water ought to fill less space
when
Had Anaximenes set a jar full of water outside his door on a found it split in the morning, he might have found out that and frosty night ice fills more space than water and revised his theory.
frozen.
This result would certainly have puzzled him, but the fact remains was right, and if he had performed the experi-
ment and based any generalization on the results, it would only have led him into error. In general, bodies do of course expand as their contract as it falls, a principle which makes the temperature rises, and thermometer possible. Water itself expands as it is heated, and contracts
as
it is
cooled, until
it
it
reaches a temperature of 39
(4
C).
Then
for
becomes colder and passes freezing-point it ceases to some contract and begins to expand. This exception to the otherwise universal truth that bodies expand by increase of temperature is still
reason as
unexplained, that
is,
scientists
have
still
failed to relate it to
any general
125
The Milesians
law. It
perhaps hardly fair to Anaximenes to blame him if, having an almost universal truth, he failed to observe the divined correctly single exception which has hitherto baffled the efforts of scientists to
is
explain
it.
There are two points in particular in which the achievement of Anaximenes contributed to the progress of thought, (i) With him the
word
aer
first
comes
to
mean, in
its
primary
significance,
the invisible
all
we
call air
today. Although
it is
by
properly applied rather than to mist or cloud or any other of the visible forms of matter. Hitherto the word aer had generally signified
mist, fog or darkness
something
at least
and hid any objects which it surrounded. It stood for the darkness with which Zeus had covered the battle-field before Troy when Ajax uttered his famous prayer: 'Save the sons of the Achaeans from the
be but in the light/ Hearing the prayer, Zeus straightway scattered the aer and thrust aside the mist, and the sun shone out and all the battle was plain to see'. (//. xvn, 647, 649.) To Anaximander also the substance surrounding and concealing the wheels
aer.
. .
.
Slay us,
'
if it
which were the heavenly bodies was aer. For the early Greek mind darkness itself was a substance, the sacred darkness (tspov KV^CCS) of Homer. Not until Empedocles do we meet the idea that it is someof
fire
*
'
thing merely negative, an absence of light. (2) With Anaximenes apparent differences of kind or quality are for the first time reduced
to a
common
7
*
(JEGP
origin in differences of quantity. Burnet remarked makes the Milesian cosmology for the first time
consistent, since a theory which explains everything as a form of a single substance is clearly bound to regard all differences as quantitative. The
to save the unity of the primary substance is to say that all 5 diversities are due to the presence of more or less of it in a given space. Here again he is well ahead of Anaximander in clarity of thought, and
only
way
not only rounded off the Milesian monistic systems but bore remarkable
Greek and European thought. We are still at the very beginning, the first dawning of rational explanation, and there is no
fruit in later
1
G. Vlastos
criticizes
126
Significance
of Anaximenes
Theory
new
principle.
made any mathematical applications of That advance may justly be credited to the Py-
thagoreans. But by the statement of the principle the essential first step has been taken along a path which is still being followed. That physical
phenomena
in the
can be expressed colour, sound or whatever it may be form of mathematical equations in other words, that all differences of quality are reducible to differences of quantity, and only when so reduced can be regarded as scientifically described is an
assumption on which
accounting for
is
all
all
modern
physical science
is
based.
By
of matter by different degrees of condensation and rarefaction of the one basic stuff, Anaximenes
qualitative differences
we cannot say providing, but demanding a quantitative explanation. He was the originator of the idea, and such was its
already,
importance that it was perhaps an excusable exaggeration on the part of Theophrastus to attribute it to him alone'. He probably wished to
*
emphasize that the principle of condensation and rarefaction was Anaximenes's own.
(5) Air,
life,
and divinity
to his choice of air
The
wish to discover a natural explanation of the manifold variety of physical phenomena consistent with a monistic view of reality. This he thought he had detected in the processes
of condensation and rarefaction. There would
also, I suggested,
be
motives influencing him less consciously, because they sprang from the general climate of thought in which he and the other Milesian thinkers were living, and which they shared with their unphilolike Anaximander, that sophical fellow-countrymen. He assumed, the original source and fount of being (that is, for him, the air) had
been in motion from all time, and that this was what made its Theochanges possible. *He too makes motion everlasting', said that this eternal motion is the means whereby added and phrastus,
change takes
mander
this.
1
To
for like Anaxirightly say 'assumed', of (and doubtless Thales also) he offered no explanation one was Matter indefensible. seemed Aristotle the omission
place.
One may
Ap. Simpl. (A 5). So also Hippolytus (A 7), the Stromateis (A6) and Cicero (AIO).
127
The Milesians
thing, and a moving cause another, so that if matter was in motion, the natural philosopher should be able to point to some separate agent to which the motion separate conceptually at least, if not physically
this discrimination belongs to a more sophisticated stage of thought than that of the sixth century, which as yet conceived of no opposition between an inert matter on the one hand and a force
arousing it to motion on the other. The arche of the universe was not matter in that sense. It was eternal being, and because eternal and the arche of everything else, it was of necessity uncaused, or else selfcaused.
cause.
It
What then, one may 5 the description 'self-caused or 'self-moving ? The answer is soul or life (psyche). The arche was something alive, not only eternal (dfSiov) but immortal (ocfiotvcrrov) and therefore divine (0iov). So Anaxi5
and Thales too, as we saw good reason to was believe, impressed by the links uniting moisture and life. These links were so strong that it seemed perfectly reasonable, as it had through
mander
the preceding centuries of pre-philosophical imagination, to regard moisture as the original fount and cause of life and therefore of every-
thing
also
else.
In making
an
air in
still
which
air
associated, and in fact identified, breath and life. That the which we breathe should be the life itself which animates us is a
idea,
common
Among
but
the Greeks
we meet this idea both outside and inside the realm of philohave dealt with
it
1
sophical thought.
may
perhaps repeat here sufficient to show that the equation of air with soul or life was not the invention of any single philosophic or religious individual or school, but must have originated in the mists of early popular
belief.
idea that a female could be impregnated, and thus new life originated, by the wind alone goes back to the Iliad, in which the
The
by
the
wind
Zephyros. Eggs
laid
by
1
128
ir^
Life^
and Divinity
birds
Aristotle called wind-eggs or Zephyr-eggs, 'because in springtime the were observed to inhale the breezes'. This reminds us of a passage
in Virgil which, although belonging to a later age, no doubt contains the explanation of the birth of Achilles's horses in Homer. In spring, he says, the mares stand on high crags with their mouths turned
towards the Zephyr to catch its breezes. In this 1 pregnant by the winds without sexual union.
c
way
they are
made
According to the sacred poetry of the Orphics the soul enters into us from the whole as we breathe, borne by the winds'. At the opposite
extremfe
we find the materialist Democritus saying much the same thing of his own atomistic world- view: In the air there are many of those particles which he calls mind and soul. Hence, when we breathe
in the terms
e
and the
along with it, and by their action cancel of the (i.e. surrounding atmosphere), thus preventing the expulsion of the soul which resides in the animal. This explains why life and death are bound up with the taking in and letting out of breath;
air enters, these enter
*
the pressure'
upper hand, and, the animal being unable to respire, the air can no longer enter and counteract the compression.' 2 Probably for
of
by breathing acquire the life-principle. Diogenes of Apollonia took up in the fifth century the doctrine of Anaximenes that air was the primary substance, and developed in
but
at least
we
not only the origin of all things but also particular this point that it was the element of soul in the universe, and therefore had special affinities with the soul in animal and human beings. The following are
excerpts from his
among the
Simplicius
are given
by
(Diog.
frr.
4 and
on
air,
by breathing; and
it is
to
them
The
soul of animals
outside, in
which we
the same, namely air which is warmer than the air near the sun. live, though much colder than that
is
1 Lucian, //. xvi, 150; Ar. H.A. 559b2o, 56036; Virg. G. in, 271 ff. Zeus. Hephaestus a wind-child because Hera bore him without 2 The authority for both these statements is Aristotle. See De An. 4iob 28,
De
Sacrif.
calls
De Resp.
47238.
129
The Milesians
In
my
everyone
opinion that which has intelligence is what men call air, and by it is directed (Ku(3spvao0ca the verb that Anaximander applied to
his aperron\
and
it
has
power over
all;
for
ir is
just this
substance which
hold to be god.
a logical consequence of these statements that there exists a close and our own, and affinity between the divine or universal mind
It is
according to Theophrastus
genes,
this
who
y
(De Sensu
42, Diog.
A 19).
It is
conclusion was duly drawn by Diois a small portion of the god' no wonder that such a belief was made
*
to serve the purposes of a mystical religion like that expounded by the Orphics, as well as those of natural philosophy. When Aristophanes
laughs at the new divinities, Air and Respiration, and ridicules the notion of the kinship between the air and the human mind (Clouds, 627, 230), he no doubt has in mind the fashionable philosophico-religious
theories; but
it
had
caught the popular imagination, they owed much of their success to the fact that similar beliefs were rooted in folk-consciousness.
These and other examples which could be adduced, as well as the effect of evidence from other cultures, put it beyond reasonable doubt that ideas of this sort must have been a part of the
cumulative
background of Anaximenes's upbringing. They would help to the choice of air as arche a perfectly natural one, for, on the hylozoist view which he shared with the other members of the Milesian
familiar
make
same time
to
be the
stuff of life.
therefore only what we should expect when we are told that he 1 said the air was god (Cicero and Aetius, A lo). There are also, it seems,
other gods and 'divine things' which are not eternal but have their
origin
(Civ.
from air. So Hippolytus (quoted above, p. 121) and St Augustine De^ vin, 2, Aio): Nee deos negavit aut tacu.it / non tamen ah ipsis
aerem factum^ sed ipsos ex aere ortos credidit* What Anaximenes had in mind when he spoke of these other gods we are not told, and perhaps there is little point in guessing. He may have tried in this way, like
Epicurus in a
1
room
words are (N.D. I, 10, 26): aera deum statuit eumque gigni. It is a curious mistake, no doubt whatever that for Anaximenes the air as arche has existed from all time. Perhaps there has been some confusion between the primal air itself and the OeoOs Kcd 0sloc which arise from it.
Cicero's
is
but there
130
These were already associated or identified with deities in popular thought: Gaia the earth was a goddess, for water there was Oceanus, and for fire Hephaestus. What he says about the heavenly bodies makes
it
unlikely that he thought of them as divinities. There is evidence also that he drew the same analogy as his follower
Diogenes of Apollonia between the function of the air in the universe at large and that in man, that is, his soul. This appears from a passage
in Aetius
which reads
as if it
were intended
as
Anaximenes, though
Aet.
I,
this has
3, 4,
B2: 'Anaximenes of Miletus, son of Eurystratus, declared air, for out of it all things come to be
it they are resolved again. "Just as our soul," he says, "which is holds us air, together, so breath and air surround the whole cosmos." Air and breath are used synonymously.'
and into
It is
the actual
perhaps impossible to decide just how far this sentence preserves 1 wording of Anaximenes, but Theophrastus and his epitom-
be keeping to it pretty closely, nor is there any good reason to doubt that the sentence faithfully communicates his doctrine. Burnet, who accepts the fragment, has
perhaps contributed unwittingly to its rejection by later critics, for he comments (EGP, 75) that it is 'an early instance of the argument
macrocosm, and so marks the beginning of an interest in physiological matters'. Kirk adduces the same fact as an argument against its genuineness: 'The parallel between man
to the
and cosmos
1
is
first
explicitly
in the
It is
Reinhardt, Wilamowitz, Gigon and Kirk hold that it is so altered as to distort its meaning. n. i) and Praechter (Ueberweg, accepted as a genuine fragment by Kranz, Nestle (ZN, 319, with n. 55) holds 51; the other reff. will be found in Kirk, HCF, 312). Vlastos (AJP, 1955, 363 that 'though much of the wording of this fragment is doubtful, there is no good reason to doubt that it paraphrases an analogy drawn by Anaximenes himself*. Exception is taken in particular to the words cx/yKpcrrsT, KOCTIIOS and TTVSUUCC. That K6<ruo$ in the sense of world-order came into use to use this passage as evidence to only later is possible, though if anyone wished, like Nestle, the contrary, it would be difficult to prove him wrong. The same applies to TTVEUHCC, which comes under suspicion of having a Stoic flavour. If this is so, the remark of the doxographer that drip and TTVEVUOC are used here synonymously (by Anaximenes?) is curious. On the use of
see further p. 208, n.
i,
below.
131
The Milesians
fifth
century (HCF, 312). Apart from the fact that this argument comes perilously near to a petitio principii, the assumption of an cosmic divinity affinity between the soul of man and the all-pervading has no more to do with the rise of physiological and medical science than had the probable assumption of Thales that moisture was the
primarily a religious assumption, not one which appealed to the inheritors of the Olympian pantheon of Homer, but one which seems to have belonged particularly
principle of
life
(p. 62,
above).
It is
to the religious ferment that affected a different stratum of the population in the sixth century and gave rise to the sacred poetry known as
Orphic. The promulgators of teletai in the name of Orpheus were concerned in the religious sphere with the same problem of the relation
between the One and the Many which in a different form was the problem of the Milesian philosophers. In both forms it was a living
1 problem in the sixth century. If then we are^to trust to a priori reasons drawn from the climate of contemporary thought (which is all
that the sceptics would have us do), there is no need to deny to Anaximenes the analogy between microcosm and macrocosm which is
expressly attributed to him here, and is in any case a probable consequence of the simple fact that he looked upon the air as (a) the arche
stuff
In the details of cosmogony and cosmology Anaximenes can hardly be said to have rivalled the combination of reasoning power and bold
imagination which characterized Anaximander, but was in some ways more naive. As Anaximander's cosmos was surrounded by the apeiron,
which, as we have just seen, is also called breath (pneurna) in what purports to be a quotation or near-quotation. The suspicion of Stoic influence here is lessened when one sees that
so
is
Anaximenes's by the
air,
probably included
S
Hayduck (DK, A 23): oi 6 deploy [jr. -ri\v yvytf\v] cSorrep *A. Kod -rives TCOV STCOIKOOV. Anaximenes among the Irepoi TIVES of whom Aristotle speaks in De An. 405 321
:
is
dpa
\sc.
OrroXocjielv].
132
Cosmogony of Anaximenes
1 It may be inferred breathing in from a limitless pneuma outside it. that, as the analogy with the soul suggests, the world for Anaximenes
'
is
alive
and breathing.
are told (Strom.
We
m, A 6)
vouchsafed
existence,
though no further explanation is was the first part of the cosmos to come into
air.
engendered of course by compression of the and situation we have the following reports:
(a) Stromateis (A 6):
first,
Of its
shape
'As the
it
air
quite
flat;
wherefore
rides, as
"felted", earth, he says, came into being is reasonable, upon the air.'
is flat,
earth
riding
upon
the
air.'
Aetius (A 20): 'Anaximenes says it is table-shaped.* Aetius (A^O) 'Anaximenes says that it rides upon the air owing to
its
flatness.'
(e) Aristotle, De Caelo, 294^3 (A 20): 'Anaximenes, Anaxagoras and Democritus name the flatness of the earth as the cause of its remaining at rest. It does not cleave the air beneath it, but settles on it like a lid, as flat bodies
all appearances do; owing to their resistance they are not easily moved even by the wind. The earth, they say, owing to its flatness behaves in the same way in relation to the air immediately underneath it, which, not having
to
sufficient
room
to change
its place, is compressed and stays still owing to the water in klepsydraL For this power of the air to bear a shut up and its motion stopped, they bring forward
audacity of Anaximander's idea that the earth remained poised without support at the centre of the universe, simply because it was at
the centre,
The
accept
and he returned to Thales's hypothesis of a material support. The earth having been formed first, the heavenly bodies originate
it,
it,
from
visible are
now
of
fiery
in origin earthy.
(a) Stromateis (A 6, continuation of (a) above): 'And the sun, moon and other heavenly bodies originate from earth. He argues at any rate that the sun is earth but acquires great heat from its swift motion.' 3
See pp. 278 , below. Aristotle also referred to this breathing of the world in his lost book the Pythagoreans (fr. 201 Rose). On this Pythagorean doctrine see Baldry, CQ, 1932, 30 2 For the klepsydra see note ad loc. in the Loeb edition. 3 The reading of the last few words is doubtful, but the sense scarcely affected.
1
on
133
The Milesians
(i) Hippolytus (A 7): 'The stars originated from the earth, because moisture arose from it, which being rarefied gave rise to fire, and of this, as it rose aloft, the stars are composed. There are also earthy bodies in the
region of the stars, revolving with them/ that the stars are of the nature of fire, (c) Aetius (A 14): 'Anaximenes said 1 and that they enclose certain earthy bodies also which revolve together with them and are not seen.'
(f) Aetius (A 1 5):
'He
is flat like
leaf.'
This theory of the origin of the heavenly bodies from the earth, so that even 'the sun is earth', shows at least how consciously emancipated was Anaximenes's mind from any religious preconceptions; but it lacks
the cogency of Anaximander's account. His theory of 'separation* allowed for both extremes, fire and wet earth, to be produced together.
Vaporization and drying, which accounted including animal life, were then readily explicable
for
all
it
by
in Anaximenes's scheme enveloping fire on the cold wet centre, whereas seems that fire itself is to be produced from earth by a vaporization
is difficult
which
the
to explain.
air's
Why he should
suppose
it
necessary that
to earth,
first result
of the
motion was
to condense
some of it
and that the rarefaction producing fire should only result secondarily out of moisture from the earth (thus obviously passing once more
through the stage of invisible atmospheric sources do not enable us to say.
It is
air),
our fragmentary
and
fruitful
arguable that Anaximenes, having advanced his single brilliant hypothesis of condensation and rarefaction, did not pay so
much
attention to the detailed working-out of a system. If so, the of these thinkers would lead one to expect him to produce something more closely related to the mythical cosmo-
common background
all
gonies which preceded them. This is perhaps what happened. To derive the heavenly bodies from the earth sounds strange and original, but
in Hesiod's Theogony (126-7) 'Earth first bore the starry Heaven, equal to herself, that he might cover her all round'.
irepi^xei is a little difficult, but, especially in view of the Hippolytus passage, can hardly mean * (as Zeller thought) that each star contained an earthy core. Presumably they surround* them, as the air rrepi^xei the world, i.e. the earthy bodies are all somewhat nearer the centre than are the
1
stars. This would be necessary if they were intended to explain eclipses. ("Aorpcc and dorlpes are of course here used of the heavenly bodies in general.)
134
Cosmology of Anaximenes
Lacking Anaximander's curious tubes of mist, Anaximenes must have had to seek another explanation of eclipses, and many modern authorities
have thought
invisible earthy bodies in the heavens. If so, this was one helpful step on the part of a thinker to
this to
whom,
It is,
little.
The
sun, he said,
is flat like
3
a leaf (Aetius,
A 1 5), and
it
heavenly bodies 'ride upon the air owing to their flat shape, just as the earth does (Hippol. Ay). There is, however, a remarkable, isolated
passage in Aetius (A 14), in which Burnet and others have very reasonably seen some corruption:
are fixed like nails in the crystalline (or icethat they are fiery leaves like paintings.
Whatever the meaning of the last two words (the constellations Bear or Wagon, Orion and the rest?), the theory that the heavenly bodies are
'fiery leaves' is surely
them
in their revolutions
is
inconsistent
with supposing them to be fixed in a solid crystalline sphere. Some scholars (for example Heath, Aristarchus^ 42 ) infer that Anaximenes was the first to distinguish between planets and fixed stars, the former
being
'flat like
leaves*
and
free to
move irregularly,
to the solid wheeling outer circumference or dome of the universe. this view the report of Aetius (A 15) that 'the stars execute their
On
by condensed and
resistant air'
would
crystalline
heaven to
and
if fire
connected solidity with cold, rarity with heat (BI); aloft' and became the stars at the outer edge of the 'rose
to see
He
universe,
1
it is difficult
how
Kirk (KR, 1 76) thinks that the invisible earthy bodies were falsely transferred to Anaximenes from Diogenes of Apollonia, to whom they are also attributed. He asserts that in any case their function will have been to explain meteorites, not eclipses, on the grounds that this was the purpose of their introduction by Diogenes and that Anaxagoras posited similar bodies although he knew
the true cause of eclipses.
*
and
vlou? suggests that this meaning could be got from the original text (Aet. n, 14, 3) by reading a difficulty which he does (sc. dccnipas) for ivioi (in spite of the neuter aarpa immediately before,
not mention).
135
The Milesians
But the lamentably large gaps in our knowledge may us from preclude understanding how his mind worked here, and, more
frozen solid.
generally, a
on the word KpucrroAAoi8rj$ is prompted by the thought that there is no particular reason why Theophrastus or a later doxographer should have fathered it on him of their favourite unjustifiably. The risk of contamination from any
little
further reflexion
schools of thought was slight, for the later spheres of the Pythagoreans, of Aristotle and of the Stoics were not of a kind which could be
by this word. From Aristotle onwards, and probably for before him, the outer heaven was of pure, invisible fire or dither. many The notion of a hard, crystalline sphere or spheres, so dear to astrodescribed
nomers and poets of medieval and renaissance days, 1 was a rare one in Greek thought, and where it does seem to occur is a little puzzling. The common arrangement of a cosmos continued to be what it was for
Anaximander: earth
around
that,
at the centre
it,
air
or mist
and
fire,
most
place.
are,
There
docles
combined
5
however, indications that both Parmenides and Empethis arrangement with the attribution of a solid cir-
We
it
'Way of
'is
is
Seeming
'that
which surrounded'
and under
heavenly rings
comes the
fiery ring'.
Not only
is
no
little later
Aetius
saying that
uppermost and surrounds everything', and in a summary of descriptions of the heaven he lists Parmenides with others who say
that it is fiery. We are equally unfortunate in having no actual fragment of Empedocles's poem dealing with this point, but according to Aetius again he believed that fire itself had the power of 'freezing' or
solidifying. Lactantius
heaven
as
(whose source is Varro) describes Empedocles's aerem glaciatwn^ and the version of the Stromateis is that fire
occupies the space under the coagulation (irocyos) of air, a parallel to the situation of the fiery ring of Parmenides.* Perhaps then Anaximenes anticipated Empedocles here, though it is
in all probability took it over from the Arabs: see Dreyer, Planetary Systems, 289. Aet. u, 7, i (Farm. A37), n, u, 4 (A38); n, n, 2 (Emped. A 51), cf. A<5o and Ar. Probl. Lactant. in 937314; Emped. A 51, Strom. A3O.
2
1
Who
136
The Meaning of
difficult to see
Crystalline*
and loose
There
is,
however,
another possibility. In later Greek at least, the word 'crystalline' need by no means imply the hardness of ice or glass, and we need not suppose that either Anaximenes himself, if he used the word, or whoever may
have
to explain what he found in Anaximenes, intended it to bear that sense. To medical writers like Celsus or Galen the crystalfirst
it
used
line lens
known as
agutta humoris.
The word
Partium, and at one point he describes this crystalline moisture as being 5 surrounded with 'a clear moisture like that in an egg This finds a
.
who
by
the Greeks
is itself
This use of the term in a physiological setting to mean a viscous 5 transparent liquid 'resembling the white of an egg makes it at least
possible that Anaximenes was following his contemporary and associate Anaxiniander in supposing the world to be surrounded, not by a
hard and glass-like substance, but by a transparent membrane. Since we can say even more confidently than we could of Anaximander that
he regarded the world as a living and breathing creature, it is highly probable that he also used the physiological analogy in describing its
birth
and
structure.
The word
?)Ao$,
commonly
With
heavenly bodies as performing complete revolutions, carried round both above and below the centrally-poised earth in their rings which were
segments of a dissected sphere. Anaximenes revived the idea that they only go round, not under the earth. The testimonies are these:
(a) Hippolytus (Ay):
as others
'He says
earth,
have supposed, but round it, as the small felt cap turns about our head. The sun disappears not beneath the earth, but concealed by its higher us.' parts and on account of its greater distance from circle round the earth, not the 'Anaximenes stars Aetius (A 14): says ()
under
1
it.'
De Usu Part, x, 4 (vol. n, 70.9 Helmreich), Celsus vn, 7, 3 (280.2 Daremberg). For references see Guthrie in CQ, 1956, 40-4, where the suggestions here put forward are
Galen,
137
The Milesians
In view of the above, one may add the following from Aristotle in which Anaximenes is not mentioned by name.
(c) Aristotle, Meteor, n, 354327 (trans. H. D. P. Lee): 'An indication that the northerly parts of the earth are high is the opinion of many of the ancient meteorologists that the sun does not pass under the earth but round its
northerly part, and that it disappears and causes night because the earth high towards the north.*
is
and
his cap
similes cannot be said the head, Anaximenes's taste for 1 to be very helpful. However, he clearly retreated from the progressive view of Anaximander to the more primitive belief that the universe was,
homely human
effectively at least, a
had told
how the
sun,
when he
was
carried
round the
2 encircling stream of Ocean in a golden boat to rise in the east again. Under the earth was a mass of compressed air, the shape or extent of
which
its job of supporting the must reach to the earth the manner described by Aristotle, circumference of the cosmos, thus making it practically impossible for
is
if it is to
do
earth in the
theory of their
disappearance behind higher ground in the north was accommodated is something that we can only guess, and has been much
But on one astronomical point Anaximenes improved on Anaximander, for the report in Hippolytus (Ay) that according to him *the stars give no heat owing to their great distance' shows that he
disputed.
the sun.3
1 Those who wish to take the revolving cap more seriously will find something about it in H. Berger, Gesch. d. wissenschaftlichen Erdkunde d. Griechen, 79. Teichmiiller found significance in the fact that the ancients, like the members of some public schools, wore their caps on the backs of their heads. (See Heath, Anstarchus^ 41.) He does not say that they habitually wore them too large. It is the idea of movement which makes the simile so bizarre. Could the mAiov have been a turban, and arp&perai mean 'is wound* round the head? Turbans may have been worn in Miletus in Anaximenes's time as in later ages until Turkey went republican and western. 1 U. Holscher in Hermes, 1953, 413 says, on the authority of F, Boll, Zeitschr.f. Assyr. 1914,
moon go round
ix, 33),
is
Babylonian.
It
was revived
solely
by Leucippus (D.L.
who
also
138
Anaximenes: Conclusion
(7)
Meteorology
In his description of meteorological phenomena, Anaximenes seems to have followed Anaximander as closely as the difference between their
is
primary world-processes would allow. Air in swift motion, i.e. wind, already slightly condensed, and further condensation produces clouds, rain, snow and hail. Thunder and lightning were for him, just
Anaximander, the effect of a cloud being split by the force of and he apparently thought that phosphorescence in the sea prowind,
as for
vided some sort of parallel to die lightning (HippoL Ay, Aet. A 17). He also spoke of the rainbow, no longer a radiant goddess Iris but only the
effect
air,
which appeared in
moisture
full
prevailed (Ai8).
He had
also
Aristotle's account:
Anaximenes says that when the earth is in process of becoming wet or dry it breaks, and is shaken by the high ground breaking and falling; which is why earthquakes occur in droughts and again in heavy rains: for in droughts the earth is dried and so, as just explained, breaks, and when the rains make it 1 excessively wet it falls apart.
(8) Conclusion
it
needs
little
imagination to see
Anaximenes
as a well-defined character,
and
this
may
perhaps be
permitted in a summing-up. The vivid imagery attributed to him suggests a man interested in and observant of his fellows at their daily
of the more striking and picturesque phenomena of nature, though probably not in the patient and painstaking way that makes the typical scientist. The air is felted like wool, the earth reminds him of a table, the circling sun and moon of leaves borne up in an
tasks, observant also
stars perhaps of nails or rivets or warts. He recalls the phosphorescent glitter that drips from an oar-blade as it rises from the water, and the faint colours that he has seen ('but not often') in the
Meteor. 36?b6, trans. H. D. P. Lee. If the account in Ammianus (xvii, 7, 12, Anaximander, A 28) really refers to Anaximander, we have here also a remarkably close similarity between the theories of master and pupil. But more probably the single MS. which gives instead the name of Anaximenes has preserved the true attribution.
1
The Milesians
light
a true Ionian, his freedom of thought is so little inhibited by any sense of awe that he can compare the starry vault to a felt cap, and use the diminutive form in doing so. Ranging thus untrammelled, his mind later ages in its debt by hitting on the
of a
full
moon. Like
put
from a single inspired notion that if the genesis of the world was or less of more there to being substance, its changes could only be due
it
clue to
in a given space. Condensation and rarefaction provide the universal becoming and change, and if he was too impetuous to submit
himself to the detailed thought and investigation which might have produced a fuller and more consistent cosmological scheme, the central idea remains and has borne its fruit.
Religion had
little
they
all
were gods: if so appeal for him. Perhaps there must be formed from the air, which was after
uncaused motion mean?) and as the psyche which at once integrates
eternal,
this like his fellow-
lonians (and like a later secular thinker of Ionian stock, Democritus) of nature. similar belief could be the basis of a mystic's
hope, but in the face of other evidence about Anaximenes we cannot 1 credit him, as some have done, with mystical tendencies himself.
E,
characteristics
Three main points occur if one wishes to summarize briefly the chief of the Milesian philosophers and their legacy to later
rational,
evolutionary,
to be aware of the persistent effects of mythological conceptions and modes of thinking, enough has been said about
these,
and
it
should not
now
be misleading
if in a
summing-up one
emphasizes rather the revolution in man's thought about the world and
its
it
meant that the causes operating in the beginning were to be regarded as the same in kind as those which we see operating now. To one
reading in Hesiod of the succession of
1
*
human
270).
I4O
marriage of Heaven and Earth, it must have seemed that as one went back in time the world became less and less like that of ordinary experience, and governed by forces of a different kind. It is true that
up
and beyond Hesiod's day divine interference was supposed by many to account even for contemporary events to which we should assign perfectly natural causes. But take a passage from the Theogony, say the battle of Zeus and his allies with the Titans. Great rocks are
to
its
the surface of the land heaves and boils as does the sea.
and groans and Olympus is shaken to its base. Lightning and thunder, flame and thunderbolt are the weapons of Zeus, and all nature is convulsed before his enemies the Titans can be overcome and consigned
when Prometheus
were
to Tartarus deep beneath the earth. Events of those days, or the days stole the fire, were events of a different order, they
different in kind,
in the Boeotia of
Hesiod
who came
scientific
after
him.
Yet
of a more
no
alternative explanation of the past. Aristotle, who was no friend to the 'sophisms' of mythology, makes it clear that with Thales a new a spirit which the man of reason could respect. The haze spirit emerges,
of myth
is
dissipated,
things considered, a remarkably successful attempt to push back to the very beginning of things the operation of familiar natural processes like the condensation
all
of moisture. The formation of the world has become a purely natural event from which the clash of supernatural powers is eliminated, even
ways in which those powers had been formerly imagined to be admitted to have influenced the mechanism of the natural must work causes in terms of which these men were now speculating. We may be
if
the
inclined to underrate the astonishing completeness of their triumph because, thanks to the lonians themselves, their premiss quickly
all
science:
that
is,
the hypothesis that, as Henri Frankfort put it, 'a single order underlies the chaos of our perceptions, and furthermore that we are able to
141
The Milesians
comprehend that order*. Yet, as he truly comments, to act on that hypothesis was at the time to proceed with preposterous boldness on
an entirely unproved assumption.
(H)
Cosmogonies
With
the
possible exception of Orphic ideas, which never gained wide popular favour, it may be said that an evolutionary conception of the origins of the world was the only one that had so far been mooted among the
Greeks. Brought up in the religious tradition of the Hebrews, we are accustomed to associate this term with the scientific outlook of a
Darwin, but in Greece the early mythical accounts were themselves of evolutionary type. Unlike Jahwe, the Greek gods had not created the
world, and the Milesians, in so far as they thought along evolutionary it of its lines, were retaining an earlier framework though stripping
mythological covering. Mythology too had presented an initial state of confusion in which for example, as we have noted, heaven and earth
in 'one form'
order has gradually emerged. The terms of the marriages and begettings of the personified elements themselves, the philosophers ascribed it to natural causes; but neither
regarded
it
as a creation, the
work of an
original
god standing
apart
from, and working on, an original matter distinct from himself. Writing from the different standpoint of a Christian and a Platonist,
Augustine thinks it necessary to explain, after saying that Anaximenes believed in the existence of gods, that nevertheless the airy substance of the world was not created by them but they actually took their origin
from
It
it.
follows that neither the writers of theogonies nor the Milesian philosophers admitted the notion of design (Texvrj) as responsible for
the world-order.
has generative thought naturejh^rsdf and is nature meant an actual material substance power, (<pucri$) by that of which the world is made which is assumed to be alive and so
capable of initiating the changes to which it is itself subject, a fact which the Milesians expressed by referring to it not only as water or air or the
142
god or the divine. This was not an assumption with which thought could rest content. Later philosophers became dissatisfied with it, and tended in varying degrees to separate the ideas of
life
in the time
and matter and see them as residing in different entities. Anaxagoras of Pericles is the first to separate Mind explicitly as that
which ordered the universe in the beginning, declaring it to be entirely 1 apart from matter. This would seem to give more than a hint of conscious design, yet it is well known how loud were the complaints of Socrates and his followers Plato and Aristotle that although Anaxagoras
posited
when it came to working out the world had evolved he made no use the which subsequent processes by
Mind
at the beginning,
of Mind at
all,
Diogenes of Apollonia, a younger contemporary of Anaxagoras, restored for a while the unity of matter and spirit in a single living
substance which for him, as long before for Anaximenes, was air. Possibly under the influence of Anaxagoras, he laid stress on the mental qualities of this divine element, going so far as to say (fr. 3) that without its intelligence the universe could not have been ordered
everything keeping within its due bounds, summer and winter, night and day, foul weather and fine; and if you reflect, he adds, you
as
it is,
will find that everything else is disposed in the best possible manner. This seems to go a long way; yet for Diogenes as for the Milesians
intelligence
is still
is
itself subject to
have not yet arrived at the evolutionary process. so much importance, Plato attached to which of the true idea creation,
We
and which
sets
independent of each other from the beginning. The influence of the Ionian tradition was in fact in the other direc-
As the notion of a divine generative power inherent in nature became more and more difficult to retain, and the idea of art or design proceeding from the mind of an independently existing being had not yet emerged as a serious competitor, there came to be asserted
tion.
itself
the Atomists, unreasoning necessity. These were the causes invoked by in whom the Ionian succession finds its logical conclusion. Natural
i
143
The Milesians
forces
work
and from
blindly, without any conscious aiming at a particular end, their interaction there happens to emerge a cosmos. Empe-
docles too taught that the cosmos, including plant and animal life, came about by the purely random interplay of the four elemental substances.
This philosophy which exalted as first cause a 'nature' operating in a purely mechanical and non-teleological way, and looked upon and importance intelligent design as something secondary both in time
was seized on in the fifth of religion, morality framework century by opponents of the traditional and law, and threatened to exercise an influence over a far wider field than that of natural philosophy. For Plato, inheriting the moral ideas
plane,
of Socrates
beginning of the fourth century, it represented a to oppose it. spiritual peril, and he summoned all his mental powers This controversy will concern us later, but meanwhile, since the attiat the
tude so hateful to Plato undoubtedly owes its ultimate origin to the early Ionian philosophers, we may glance at his own description of it
and keep
it
in
mind
as
we
proceed.
According to them [writes Plato in the Laws (x, 889 A)], the greatest and best things are the work of nature and chance. Smaller things are wrought by art, which received from the hands of nature the formation of the great and primary works, and moulds and contrives all the smaller sort, which in fact we call 'artificial'.. .Let me put it more clearly. They assert that fire and water and earth and air all exist by nature and by chance. None of them is the
.
product of art, and the bodies next after them the earth, sun, moon, stars and so forth were produced by them acting as purely lifeless agents. Then
they drifted at random, each according to its particular capacity, fitting together as happened to be practicable, hot with cold, dry with moist, soft
with hard, as many as were combined in the mingling of opposites, of necessity and as chance ordained. In this manner and by these processes
were generated the whole heaven and everything in it, all animals also and plants. Neither intelligence, nor god, nor art, they say, is the cause, but, as I have told you, nature and chance. Art, as a product of these forces, came later. It is something mortal, from mortal origins, and later produced certain toys which have no great part in reality but are a kind of imitations resembling the
(V)
arts themselves.
the Milesians,
In speaking of the evolutionary character of nature as viewed by it has been necessary to say much about their hylo-
144
will
of Presocratic thought.
spirit
be found to run as a leading thread through the whole development For the Milesians the union of matter and
in a material substance like air
calls for
is
an assumption that
raises
no
doubts and
no argument or
defence.
As
all dissatisfied
with themselves. Gradually, but only of such a conception become apparent, and
Heraclitus for instance
fact that matter
tugging more and more strongly at the bonds which unite them, but philosophers have not yet become fully aware of where the trouble lies, nor of the necessity to separate the two. The climax comes with the declaration of
may
be explicable by the
and
spirit are
Parmenides that motion and change are impossible and inadmissible conceptions. Those who followed him were dominated by the necessity
to escape from this disconcerting conclusion, and their attempts to do so led not only to the assumption of a plurality of primary substances
in place of the single arche of the Milesians, but in the end to the hypothesis of a moving cause outside and above the substance of the
physical world.
IV
For
good
is
reasons,
which
not only obscure but highly complex, subject and its complexity demands above all a clear statement at the outset of what is to be attempted and the outline of a plan of campaign.
without
The
First, is
it
justifiable
Pythagoras was a contemporary of but school his existed, and its doctrines developed and Anaximenes, diverged, for the next two hundred years. Little can be attributed with
this early point in the exposition?
certainty to the founder himself, and much Pythagorean teaching is associated with the names of philosophers of the late fifth or early
fourth century. There is, however, no doubt that Pythagoras inaugurated a new tradition in philosophy, sharply divided in purpose
and doctrine, as in external organization, from anything that we have met hitherto, and that from his time onwards this new current is something to be reckoned with.
The
Italian
outlook
is
likely to
be influenced by
sympathy with, or reaction against, the one or the other* Pythagoras himself is mentioned by the contemporary writer Xenophanes and by
Heraclitus not many years after his death, and for an understanding of the development of thought during the fifth century it is important to have some idea of the main features of Pythagorean teaching which
to the philosophers of the period. to treat at this point only the earliest
phase of the school, leaving until their proper chronological place the developments and divergences that culminated in a Philolaus and an
No one can claim even to have plumbed what a modern scholar has despondently called the bottomless pit* of research on the Pythagoreans. In any case the scope of the present work forbids us to enter into all the detail and take part in every dispute.
*
146
occurred, and strongly individual philosophers arose within the school, it was characteristic of the Pythagoreans to combine progressive
thought with an immense respect for tradition. All revered the founder and claimed to belong to his brotherhood, and underlying any diversity of doctrine was an abiding unity of outlook. For the historian of
philosophy the important thing is to understand as far as possible the spirit and doctrinal basis of this outlook as it existed up to the time of
Plato.
is
Plato himself, on whose thought Pythagoreanism was so obviously a major formative influence. This pre-Platonic Pythagoreanism can to a
large extent be regarded as a unity. differences as and when we can, but
these, in the fragmentary state
We
it
sufficiently
distinguishable chronologically to allow the separate treatment of earlier and later phases. The best course will be that which Aristotle
himself
felt
On
previous generations of
Pythagoreans as sufficiently homogeneous to be spoken of together, but in his general treatment he sometimes refers to or criticizes a tenet
which he confines to 'some' of the school or to a named individual within it. At this distance of time we can hardly hope to do more. The obscurity which surrounds the Pythagoreans is not merely due to the external circumstance that, as with the Milesians, most of the
early records have perished. It is intimately bound up with the nature of the school itself. It was of the essence of Pythagoreanism that it
indeed to most
and a summary of the diffiinterpreters outside its own fellowship, a in will face us be culties that summary of certain characteristics part of the brotherhood itself. In this way the problem of the nature of the
evidence, always prominent at this early stage of Greek thought, takes
on here an
altogether
importance.
first
which
way of a historian of the school, secondly to indicate the resources and methods at the disposal of scholars to overcome briefly
stand in the
these difficulties, and only after that to attempt, thirdly, an outline of the most interesting and important tenets and characteristics of the school. If at this third stage it should prove impossible, without undue loss of clarity, to complicate the account by a constant citation of
authorities for every statement made, the
two foregoing sections will at least have indicated the kind of process by which the results have been attained, and hence the degree of credence which they are likely to
merit.
A.
DIFFICULTIES
With Pythagoras the motive for philosophy ceases to be primarily what it had been for the lonians, namely curiosity or technical improvement, and becomes the search for a way of life whereby a right relationship might be established between the philosopher and the universe. Plato will serve as witness to this well-known fact. In the Republic,
deploring the uselessness of poets, he
criticizes
Homer
thus (600 B) :
Do we
hear that
Homer
personally a guide to their education? Are there any who admired disciples a master, and handed down to later generations a Homeric
life,
him
as
way of
like Pythagoras,
and
his followers
who down to
on
manner
among
Pythagoras was indeed as much a religious and political teacher as a philosopher, and founded an organized society of men pledged to uphold
his teaching in practice.
one or two inevitable consequences of this. (i) In a society which is a religious sect rather than a philosophical
school, the
is
He
tends to be, if not actually deified, at least heroized or canonized, and in consequence his memory gets surrounded by a haze of legend. This
happened early to Pythagoras. Herodotus (iv, 95) tells how he was brought into relation with the Thracian figure of Zalmoxis by a story that Zalmoxis had been his slave and pupil. Herodotus himself is
148
and in
fact
Zalmoxis was undoubtedly a deity of Thrace, time Aristotle wrote his treatise
Quotations from this work speak of their 'highly secret' division of rational creatures into three classes: gods, men, and beings like Pythagoras. Aristotle told also the stories of how
Pythagoras had appeared in two places at once, how when he was seen stripped it was observed that he had a golden thigh, how once when he
was heard saying 'Hail Pythagoras! , how he killed by his own bite a snake whose bite was fatal, and so forth. He was credited with prophecies, and the men of Croton identified him with the Hyperborean Apollo. 1 For the events of Pythagoras's life we have no earlier source than Aristotle, and it is obvious that the existence of these legends tends to cast doubt on other parts of the tradition which in themselves seem credible enough.
crossed a river the voice of the river-god
9
(2)
is
not only to venerate the founder, but to attribute all its doctrine to him personally. It is 'the word of the Master'. This is not simply due to a pious desire to honour his memory, but is bound up with the religious
view of truth which the Pythagoreans shared with adherents of the mystery-religions. They were indeed philosophers, and made scientific
discoveries; but these they regarded in
revelations
much
which were an essential part of initiation into the mysteries. Many of their most important discoveries were mathematical, and there
was always in the Greek mind a close connexion between mathematical, astronomical and religious speculation. Anecdotes may not be true,
but their existence
called
is
revealing.
One about an early Pythagorean he was heavily punished either for revealing
geometry or alternatively for accepting the credit for its discovery instead of allowing it to Pythagoras. The secret is sometimes said to have been the incommensurability of the
diagonal of a square with
and of
but the traditions both of secrecy too strong for us to believe, as has been suggested in modern times, that this was only disapproved of because the discovery of irrationals was an embarrassing skeleton in the
its sides,
much
1
3
Arist fir. 191, 192 Rose, DK, 14, 7. See e.g. Cic. N.D. i, 5, 10, D.L. vin, 46.
149
1 sea or expulsion and the raising of a tomb to him as if dead. Where scientific facts are regarded thus as parts of a secret lore, there is a
all
Another motive
appreciate.
is
perhaps more
it
difficult for
modern mind
to
was considered
that a doctrine
gained greatly in authority if it could be claimed to be, not the latest word on its subject, but of a venerable antiquity. Although this applied
and indeed,
obvious
no means confined
makes
clear, there
to
it,*
was no
sharp distinction between 'scientific' and 'religious' knowledge. An the religious side is provided by the Orphic writers, parallel on
and since the religion taught by Pythagoras had much in common with these, the parallel is apt. All Orphic writings were produced under the
their
era.
DK,
was one of those who wrote under this name. A feature of the Orphic teaching was its seemingly conscious rivalry with Homer, to whose
contradiction.
conception of the relations between god and man it stood in strong But to withstand so great an authority its prophet must
claim superiority both in age and inspiration. Orpheus was the son of a Muse, and as an Argonaut he belonged to the earlier, heroic age of which Homer told, not the later age of lesser men in which Homer
gation of
historian
is
constituted
by
mystery-cults which it in some ways resembled, Pythagoreanism too had its secrets (o:ppr|Ta or drroppTyra). Aristotle speaks of them in the
fragment (192) already quoted, and his pupil Aristoxenus, who was a friend of the Pythagoreans of his day, said in his work on rules of
1
Iambi. V.P. 88 et
a/.,
DK,
18, 4.
E. Frank noted that the tendency to attribute recent discoveries to ancient wisdom was not confined to the religious schools, but was a more general fashion in Plato's time (Plato u. d. sog.
PytK. 72f.).
150
Pythagorean Secrecy
education that according to
to all
who
them 'not everything was to be divulged men'. 1 Isocrates in a bantering vein (Bus. 29) remarks that those claim to be disciples of Pythagoras are more admired for their
most famous orators
for their speech. may also for the writers are Neoplatonic quote Porphyry here, usually so ready to believe anything that their rare expressions of doubt or scepticism
We
are
all
the
cheerfully attributes
even
life
when
lamblichus, who was Porphyry's pupil, any Pythagorean doctrine to Pythagoras himself, 'the Pythagoreans' was all that stood in his source. In his
more
striking.
of Pythagoras, however (ch. 19), Porphyry writes: 'What he said no man can say with certainty, for they maintained a remarkable silence.' This is sufficiently impressive even if the words are
to his intimates,
not, like the preceding sentences, excerpted from Dicaearchus, which would take us back again from Neoplatonism to the fourth century B.cJ*
lamblichus
tells
us (V.P. 72, 94) that applicants for membership of made by Pythagoras to keep a five-year silence
is
true, the
famous Pythagorean
silence
was of two
we cannot suppose that the passages just quoted of training and no more. 3 In reply to the argument that these authorities must be wrong, because in fact a great deal of
refer to this rule
that needs to
Pythagorean teaching did become widely known, there is not much be said. It is perfectly possible for certain doctrines to be
held in awe, coupled with a feeling that they should not be spoken of, long after the religious rule of silence imposed by the founders of a
sect or cult has will
is
be stricter than others, and more deeply shocked to hear the arcana openly avowed, but the feeling ofreligio still clings. It was well described by Lobeck in Aglaophamus (65^7), where he says, with
'
De rebus quae particular reference to the Pythagoreans adeo sanctae omnes essent, religiose locuti sunt veteres neque apud
:
iis
iam notiores
in publico
nihilque in
1
arcani
resideret,
Fr. 43 Wehrli, D.L. vm, 15. Wehrli also attributes to Aristoxenus the sentence earlier in the chapter of D.L. that up to the time of Philolaus it was impossible to acquire a knowledge of any
Pythagorean doctrine. 3 Delatte assumed that they were (jfituJes, 98, n. i), but Wehrli omits them from the relevant fragment of Dicaearchus. 3 Some have of course Ritter tried, but the necessity for the distinction was convincingly put by and Preller, Hist. Phi!. Gr. 55, note a, p. 45.
Pythagoras and
iactarunt.'
the
Pythagoreans
has just quoted the story from Plutarch of how, when the guests at a symposium were discussing the reasons for Pythagorean them of the prohibitions, one of them, mindful of the presence among
He
Pythagorean Lucius
some
it
time, said
is
time
we
such as stopped it.' The other prohibitions enjoined by Pythagoras, abstention from certain kinds of food, were undoubtedly only observed
others,
true of the injunction to secrecy. It is of course more logical to observe a meatless diet, even though other members of your sect are less strict,
than
it is
Lobeck
to keep silent on matters which others have divulged; but, as has well brought out, this is not a matter of logic but ofreligio.
not freely communicated, its place is as an impediment naturally filled by baseless rumour. Its seriousness to the historian has been variously estimated, and of course we have
is
not the evidence for an exact appraisal of the extent either of the official prohibition or of its observance. Some have thought that the rule of
secrecy only applied to ritual actions, the 'things done (Bpcb^sva) as they were called in the mysteries. As a rough generalization, this seems
to have been true of the Eleusinian
5
were
and Orphic mysteries, and if it be limited. But for one thing it may be the loss so, might strictly difficult to understand a belief fully without knowledge of the act, if
was one, which embodied and illustrated it. Belief and ritual action, where they coexist, are not unconnected. For another, the
there
evidence of stories like that of Hippasus tells against this view. It has also been suggested that although doubtless certain dogmas
were included among the arcana, these will only have been matters of religious faith: there can have been no secrecy about their purely philo-
no ground
sophical investigations. The objection to this is similar: there is for separating the religious from the philosophical or scientific side in a system like the Pythagorean. In contrast to the
Milesian tradition,
it
Pythagorean Secrecy
matics was a religious occupation and the decad a holy symbol. If of matheanything, there is more evidence for the jealous
guarding
matical secrets than for that of any teaching about the gods or the soul. It is certainly difficult to believe that the doctrine of transmigration
was ever
treated as secret.
is
that the
two
extricably interwoven.
knowledge was the imperfectly kept rule of secrecy; but of its existence the evidence allows no doubt. 1 (4) These are three results of the particular character ofPythagoreanism which inevitably make
difficulties
the
legends which gathered round the figure of its founder, the tendency from a variety of motives to trace back to him all their doctrines and
discoveries, and the secrecy with which some at least of their teaching was surrounded. There are other difficulties not arising solely from this cause, chief among them being the scantiness of contemporary sources of information. The word 'contemporary is used here with the same thought in mind that it is the Pythagoreanism of the period from the lifetime of Pythagoras to the early fourth century which it would be
5
is
the Pythagoreanism
which Plato knew, and to be able to assess its meaning for him would perhaps be a greater gain to the history of philosophy than any assessment of the Pythagoreans for their own sake. Yet Plato only mentions
Pythagoras once (in the quotation on p. 148, above) and the Pythagoreans once, in another passage in the Republic (5300) where Socrates
says that they regard music and astronomy as sister sciences. Aristotle, if the reference to Pythagoras in Metaph. A, 986330, is genuine,
his extant
is
doubtful.
The
The reasons for this may have been in part political as well as religions, cf. E. L. Minar, Early Pyth. Politics) 26. As Minar shows in this chapter, the Pythagorean society had much in common with political fercnpEloci elsewhere in Greece. He can, however, produce no positive evidence that their secrets had a political content. * See Ross adloc.\ yet it seems a little hard that the rarity of the early mentions of Pythagoras should itself become a ground for depriving us of them ('The suspiciousness of the words is increased by the fact that Aristotle only once elsewhere mentions Pythagoras, and nowhere claims any knowledge of his date*), especially when one takes into consideration the fact that Aristotle's works on the Pythagoreans are lost* Even such quotations from them as we have suffice to prove untrue the statement that he only once elsewhere mentions Pythagoras; this
needs to be qualified by adding *in the extant works*.
from Alcidamas, the pupil of Gorgias, an example of an inductive argument in which the sentence 'the Italians honoured Pythagoras'
occurs.
to
When we come
it is
advisable
be cautious, since most of them are not represented as his actual words, and some in late compilers are doubtless at second or third hand. Moreover we have direct evidence that writers of Neopythagorean or Neoplatonic persuasion felt little compunction in substituting the name of Pythagoras himself for that of the Pythagoreans in
citing their authorities. If
we
we have
which
half a
Aristotle,
will
be
Their limitations
may
here be
briefly indicated.
rhenian descent,
They tell us that he believed in Pythagoras's Tyrmade passing mention of Cylon's opposition to him,
told of his miracles and the Pythagorean division of rational creatures into gods, men and such as Pythagoras, and spoke of his prohibitions,
including that of the eating of beans. Damascius credits him with the attribution to Pythagoras of a philosophical doctrine stated unmistak-
ably in his
own and
Plato's terminology,
of early Pythagorean teaching, and in the of lamblichus we have what is probably an authentic Protreptkw extract from the Protrepticus of Aristotle in which he quotes Pythagoras
Aristotelian restatement
as having said that the chief end of heavens and of nature. 1
man
is
philosophy Aristotle in his surviving works gives of explanation and criticism, though it is not always easy to plenty
understand.
Of Pythagorean
He
school as 'those
who
are called
them
'the Italians'
In
De
Italy
Caelo
'The philosophers of
who
He
also speaks
of 'some Pythagoreans' as
ArisL frr. 190 Rose (Clem. Alex.), 75 (D.L.), 191 (Apoll. Tyan. and others), 192 (Iambi.), 195 (D.L.), 207 (Damasc.), Iambi. Protr. 9, p. 51 Pist. (Ross, Arist. Sel. Frr., Oxf. trans. 1952,
45).
154
Aristotle
and Later
Authorities
maintaining a certain view, which suggests divisions within the school (such as are spoken of in later tradition) and perhaps a feeling of vagueness and uncertainty already existing in his own mind. 1 Aristotle is the earliest author to give any detailed information about
the Pythagoreans, and in trying to recover their views up to the time of Plato it will be necessary to pay the closest attention to what he says.
Of Pythagoras himself as a writer we have only the contradictory statements of much later men, some of whom say that he wrote nothing while others claim to give the names of some of his books. Knowing the
tendency of the school to attribute all its works to the founder, we shall treat these claims with well-merited suspicion. We have no fragments
of Pythagorean writings before the time of Philolaus, the leader of the school at Thebes at the end of the fifth century who is mentioned in Plato's Phaedo. Indeed Diogenes Laertius states (vm, 15) that up to
the time of Philolaus knowledge of Pythagorean beliefs was imposz sible. There exist a number of fragments attributed to him, but
unfortunately their genuineness is much disputed. Not only have we no Pythagorean writings before this time, but surviving Greek literature
from Pythagoras' s lifetime to the end of the fifth century provides only some half-dozen mentions of himself or his school. This is the more unfortunate in that their doctrines were certainly influential from
the beginning. Democritus is said (D.L. ix, 38) to have written a book on Pythagoras, yet his extant fragments contain no explicit reference to
Pythagorean doctrine.
mation originates with the revival of Pythagoreanism which began about the time of Cicero and continued until the rise of the Neoplatonic
school in the third century A.D. Indeed the Neoplatonists, who are the direct source of much of this information, absorbed many of its beliefs,
as
turn had absorbed those of the Academy. From the Neolife of Pythagoras and on the Pythaplatonists we have books on the the pupil of Plotinus and lamblichus the pupil life by
it
in
its
gorean
1
Porphyry
It is important to avoid translating the word KoXoOuevoi as 'so-called*, for it carries none of the implications of spuriousness which the English phrase suggests. On the dangers of this see the sensible remarks of Chemiss, ACP, (Also Gnomon, 1959, 37.) 2 This observation, which also occurs in Iambi. V.P. 199, probably goes back to Aristoxenus
^4^
(p.
151,0.
i,
above).
from two
related faults:
arose in an age very different from centuries B.C., an age when men felt themselves
It
world so large that they had lost their bearings and looked to philosophy for an anchor on which they could outride the storm. Philosophy tended to become wholly religious in character, and religion
was all too often degenerating into superstition. There was a remarkable
recrudescence of primitive religious phenomena.
instance,
which
is
equally likely to be a product of the declining intellectual primitive, standards of this age of credulity, which are amply vouched for by the
Roman
times.
The
religious
and
magical element, though undoubtedly the beginning, was thus easily exaggerated.
(ii)
present in
Pythagoreanism from
a natural corollary to their religious and superstitious later writers exhibit a singular lack of any critical these character, faculty in compiling their accounts. Their interest in Pythagoras was
As
very different from ours, namely to use him as an inspiration for their own age, not to achieve a strictly historical account of him and
after all
his school;
schools that
and when one considers the number of philosophical by this time existed for them to play with, it is not sur-
prising that earlier and later, Pythagorean and non-Pythagorean * material are thoroughly mingled in the Pythagoreanism' which they present. Plato and Aristotle, Stoic and Epicurean all play their part,
and sometimes a doctrine attributed to an early Pythagorean can be easily recognized as an innovation of Aristotle or the Stoics. Whole
books are extant, like the treatise on the World-Soul attributed to Timaeus of Locri, which are associated with the names of individual early members of the school but can be recognized from their content
as pious forgeries
revival.
Early Evidence
B.
METHODS OF APPROACH
are the resources at our disposal, and what methods can we employ, to overcome these difficulties and arrive at a modicum of fact in the concerning the history and nature of
What then
Pythagoreanism
period
from Pythagoras
to Plato?
(i) Sources
of the
sixth
and fifth
centuries
The
first
thing to do
is
lamentably scanty,
it is
to note every scrap of early evidence. Though of value both for itself and as a touchstone to
testi-
apply in a critical investigation of later information. The few monies of the sixth and fifth centuries may be dealt with here.
(a)
Xenophanes of Colophon must have been born within a few years of Pythagoras, though he probably outlived him for a good many. He left his native Ionia as a young man, and spent the rest of his life as an exile, in and largely Sicily Italy. The tone of his poems is highly satirical in their treatment of others, and Diogenes Laertius (vin, 36, Xenoph. fr. 7 DK)
quotes four of his elegiac lines as having been written about Pythagoras. They ridicule his doctrine of the transmigration of souls by telling the story
of how he saw a
it is
man beating a dog, and exclaimed: 'Stop, do not beat him: the soul of a friend, I recognize his voice.* () The life of Heraclitus also in all likelihood overlapped that of Pytha-
goras. In a passage designed to illustrate his proud and contemptuous nature, Diogenes gives the following as a quotation from his book (D.L. ix, i,
Heracl.
it
fr. 40 DK): 'Much learning does not teach insight (voov); otherwise would have taught Hesiod and Pythagoras, and again Xenophanes
and Hecataeus.' There is also fr. 129, which runs, literally translated: 'Pythagoras son of Mnesarchus practised inquiry most of all men, and
having made a selection of these writings contrived a wisdom (crocpiiiv; perhaps better "learning" or "cleverness") of his own, a polymathy, a 1 worthless artifice.' The rather obscure words 'having made a selection of
these writings', if they are a genuine part of the fragment and correctly transmitted, cannot refer to writings of Pythagoras himself as Diogenes
TTu6ocy6pr|$ Mvr^adpxou taroplriv ^aicricrev dv0pc>7rcov iidAicrra TT&VTCOV Kal fecXe^dpLEvos Tcanras TOS ovyypoKp&s hrot^aaro kcv/rov <soy{r\v t iroXvuocOtTiv, KOKOTgxylT\v. The authenticity of the frag* ment has been questioned in the past, but recent opinion rightly accepts it: certainly genuine* dass das mit recht Ansicht die 'Trotzdem durch, Fragment edit y dringt (Kirk, 390);
1
HCF
sei'
(Kranz,
DK,
i,
p. 181, n.).
1 1,
See also Wilamowitz, Gl. <L Hell, n (1932), p. 188, n. and for earlier views Delatte, Vu de. Pyth. 161 ff.
i,
Cameron,
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
supposes (vm, 6: he is disputing the view that Pythagoras wrote nothing), 1 but seem to constitute a charge of plagiarism. about 490, perhaps little (c) The many-sided writer Ion of Chios was born in the Peace of Aristoline a later than the death of Pythagoras, and from
it
by 421 when
that play
was
produced. According
which
after the
Pythagorean
to Diogenes, he said in his philosophical work Triagmoi fashion he exalted the cosmic importance of
the triad) that Pythagoras had produced some writings under the name of Orpheus (D.L. vin, 8, Ion, fr. 2 DK). Diogenes also quotes elegiac lines
of his on Pherecydes in which he alludes to the teaching of Pythagoras on the soul (i, 120, Ion, fr. 4): 'So he, endowed with manliness and modesty,
has for his soul a joyful
all
life
even in death,
of the
if
things, truly
the minds of
last
men/ There
is
some
lines, but they certainly will be rewarded after man a that to for the doctrine good Pythagoras appeal
two
(fr. i)
shows
that
2 strongly suggests that he made use of Orphic Pythagorean ideas, or wrongly, were in his time ascribed to Pythagoras. poems which, rightly No doubt it was in these that he found the doctrine of rewards (and presum-
and
fr.
ably punishments) after death for which in his elegiacs he claims Pythagoras as the authority. 4
was an almost exact contemporary of Ion, for it is fairly he was born in 485/4. In book iv, ch. 93-4, he describes the religion of the Thracian Getae, who are remarkable for their belief in immortality. They think, he says, that they do not really die, but at death are transported to their god Zalmoxis (who is also mentioned as a Thracian god
(J) Herodotus
certain that
by
The
region have a
different story
about
Greeks, however, who live in the Black Sea this Zalmoxis. They say that he was a
human being, who had been Pythagoras's slave in Samos. Having gained his freedom and made a fortune he returned to his native people, and, finding them
In spite of Kranz, Hermes, 1934, H5f. To provide an antecedent for TocOras, Gercke (see Delatte, op. cit. 162) seems to have taken dyflpcbircov irdnraov as a possessive genitive after loropiriv, ' thus: *P. worked over the researches of other men, and making a selection of these writings
* In L 3 Mr F. H. Sandbach has suggested the simple and convincing emendation (10965 65 for 6 0-0965: * If Pythagoras was truly wise, he who knew and understood the opinions of men about all things.' This might have been written with a sidelong glance at Heraclitus, fr. 129 (Proc.
1
Camk
3
Even
invoke somewhat
to refer
later
evidence than
we
have hitherto
enough
on
this
De
Caelo,
Cf.
W. Kranz in Hermes,
1934, 227f.,
where also
discussed.
158
Fifth-century Evidence
* primitive and stupid, determined to improve them. Since, then/ Herodotus *he was continues, acquainted with the Ionian standard of life and with habits
more civilized than those of the Thracians, having lived among Greeks and indeed with one of the most powerful of Greek teachers, Pythagoras, he constructed a hall in which he received the leading citizens, and in the course
of a banquet instructed them that neither he nor his guests nor their descendants would die, but they would go to a place where they would live for ever and enjoy all good things.' This Greek story went on to tell of a trick which
Zalmoxis played to gain credit for his
secret underground
new
teaching.
He
retired
into a
chamber for three years, during which time the Thracians believed him dead. In the fourth year he reappeared, thus seeming to demonstrate his immortality. Herodotus himself is sceptical about the story, maintaining that if Zalmoxis were indeed a man and not a god, then he must have
lived a long time before Pythagoras.
Of
represents as having been accompanied by human sacrifice, owed nothing to Greek influence. The interesting thing is that the Greeks
it
and the teaching of Pythagoras, and much else, they had been the
common belief in
transmigra-
to
the reappearance of Zalmoxis in a body more than three years after his death seems to demand something of the sort. Similar beliefs were in
any case common among these northern peoples, and entered from them into Greek mythology. Thus Aristeas of Proconnesus (another figure familiar to 'the Greeks who live by the Hellespont and Pontus') reappeared seven years after he was thought to have died, and again
took the body of a raven (Hdt. iv, 14). If there was borrowing here, it is far more likely to have been the other 1 way round.
240 years
after that,
and
also
Herodotus, besides what he says about Pythagoras, provides the first extant mention of a Pythagorean sect. Opinions differ on whether
Cf. E. R. Dodds, The Greeks and the Irrational, itff. Admittedly the parallel is not in a different body. complete, since in Pythagorean belief the soul was commonly reborn Pythagoras had lived previously as Aethalides and Euphorbus, not himself.
1
159
Pythagoras and
he
as
is
the
Pythagoreans
he uses
speaking of Pythagoreans or Pythagorean rites, since the adjective it might be masculine or neuter, but this at present is un-
important. The passage (n ? 81) has been in its detailed interpretation the subject of prolonged controversy, into which our present purpose does not compel us to enter. 1 Herodotus has been saying that though the
Egyptians (who are the subject of this whole second book) wear wool in ordinary life, they do not wear it in temples nor are they buried in it,
against their religion. He continues: 'The Egyptians agree in this with the Orphics, as they are called, and with the Pythagoreans;
for this
is
for
takes part in these similarly against the rule for anyone who are the subject customs rites to be buried in woollen garments. These
it is
of a sacred book/
It
was a
beyond both truth and probability, that the Greeks had borrowed their most notable religious ideas, and even their deities, from the Egyptians. It would be captious not to mention here the place in which he gives as Egyptian, 'but borrowed by the Greeks both earlier and later', a more
detailed version of the doctrine of transmigration
which there
is
good
reason for thinking was shared by the Pythagoreans and the Orphics cite the Pythagoreans by (il, 123). But since Herodotus does not here
name (only remarking, to the disgust of "the modern historian, that he knows the names of the Greeks concerned but is keeping them to
himself), this
must
find
no emphasis
early references.
One may
in the present brief survey of simply add that the doctrine was certainly
knew nothing of
trans-
have
left until
the
last,
slightly out
little
who was
sopher and shared with the Pythagoreans an enthusiastic belief in transmigration: Empedocles. This is because, although there can be no reasonable
doubt that the subject of his eulogy is Pythagoras, he leaves him unnamed, and it is in keeping with our present strict canon to mark the fact. Our
1
I.
M.
pp. 38-50.
The
translation
which he
finally gives
may be
except that it seems unnatural, despite his arguments, to suppose that Herodotus meant to refer * the sacred book* to the Egyptians. With the exception of the last sentence, then, I give Linforth's translation.
160
them (quite impossibly) to Parmenides, we must suppose that the was bestowed anonymously. 1 They are as follows (fr. 129): 'There was among them a man of surpassing knowledge, who possessed vast wealth
of understanding, capable of all kinds of cunning acts; for when he exerted himself with all his understanding, easily did he see every one of all the
things that are, in ten and even twenty
human
lives.*
and
his pupils
chronological divisions in this preliminary survey are inevitably arbitrary. Plato was born in 427 and when he spoke of the Pythafifth century knew what he was talking about.* Plato's close associate for twenty years. Nevertheless it is as well to regard Plato and his contemporaries as reflecting a period
The
goreanism of the
Aristotle
was
of their own, different in spirit and intellectual content from that of the early and mid fifth century and again from the new era of research into
which philosophy enters with Aristotle and those trained in his school, and which gives to his evidence a distinctive stamp. Moreover his
surviving treatises are in themselves so rich a source, comparatively speaking, that at this stage they can only be mentioned. Later they will be used.
153) that Plato only once mentions the Pythagothis but single reference is of great importance. In the seventh by name, book of the Republic, discussing the course of study which is to be laid down
(a)
reans
for the philosophical Guardians, Socrates comes to astronomy, and explains that it is not to be limited to a study of the stars and their visible motions.
1
may be
cited: Against:
For: Delatte, Zeller, Sityungsb. Preuss. Akad. 1889, 989 f.; Rathmann, Quaestt. Pythag. 42, 138. Vie de Pyth. 157, n. I ; Rohde, Psyche, 406, n. 96, 598; I. Lvy, Reck, sur les sources de la legende
de P. 6, n. 2; Nestle, PhttoL Woch. 1934, 409; Cameron, Pythag. Background, 20 ; Verdenius, Mnemosyne, 1947, 282. Mondolfo (Fit. d. Greet, n, 329 f.), Diels, Burnet and Cornford also agree that the reference is to Pythagoras (see Cornford, Princ. Sap. 56). 3 Heidel adduces no evidence for his statement (AJP, 1940, p. 7) that although Plato and his
school
owed much to the Pythagoreans, and Socrates had among his associates men who were somehow affiliated with them, 'it was, however, a revived Pythagoreanism in both cases'; and
no clear meaning. On the other hand it is reasonable to assume a certain amount of development within the various branches of the school, and that is what the paragraph above is intended to imply.
161
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
These must only be used as a means of reaching beyond them to the mathematical principles and laws of motion which they illustrate, but which, as visible and material objects, they cannot embody with perfect exactitude. The philosopher's aim must be to understand 'the true realities; that is, the movements and bodies in movement whose true relative speeds are to be found in terms of pure numbers and perfect figures, and which are perceptible
and thought but not visible to the eye'. From astronomy Socrates then passes, by what he claims is a natural transition, to harmonics (5300): *I think we may say that, just as our eyes are made for astronomy, so our ears are made for harmony (Ivapnoviov 9opdv), and that the two are, as the Pythagoreans say, and as we should 2 to this study, agree, sister sciences.' Because of the attention they have given Socrates continues, we must be prepared to learn from them. Nevertheless their work in this sphere shows a failure analogous to that of contemporary
to reason
1
workers in astronomy, in that 'they look for numerical relationships in audible concords, and never get as far as formulating problems and asking which numerical relations are concordant and why'.
Although there is no other mention of the Pythagorean school as such, Plato has something to say about Philolaus, who stayed for a time in Thebes after the anti-Pythagorean revolution in Italy and was later believed to have been the first to put Pythagorean doctrine into writing. (I have omitted his
have been
Philolaus.
fragments from the certain fifth-century evidence owing to the doubts that felt about their authenticity.) In the Phaedo, Simmias and Cebes are introduced into the conversation with Socrates as Thebans and pupils of
When Socrates speaks of people who hold suicide to be unlawful, Cebes asks him to explain, and he expresses surprise that his friends, who have listened to Philolaus, have not heard all about matters of this sort from him, Cebes replies that he has indeed heard Philolaus and others express
this view, but that they did not seem to make their reasons clear. Socrates then goes on to expound what he calls 'the account of it given in secret 3 teachings', a phrase strongly reminiscent of the well-known reticence of the
in custody,
Pythagoreans. According to this account we are in this world as men held from which it is not right to try to free ourselves or run away,
,
human beings
translations here given are Sir Desmond Lee's. * Archytas, Pythagorean and friend of Plato, wrote of astronomy, mathematics, and music, TocOra y&p T& naOifaorra SOKOUVTI Tjuev <5c6eX<j>6c5t (fr. i, DK, I, 432, 1. 7. On the genuineness of
5290. The
the
frr.
p. 335, n. 3).
For the meaning of harmony* or 'harmonics' at this period cf. I. Henderson in the New Oxford History of Music, i, 340: 'Harmonics meant tuning, or acoustic theory. Greek postulates were melodic and heterophonic, and ignored "harmony" in our sense/
3
6 v drroppi^Tois Aeyduevos
Trepl
162
The
religious
explanation can hardly be separated from the injunction itself, and its message agrees with what we know of Philolaus from later sources,
1 including an actual quotation attributed to him by Clement of Alexandria. (&) Isocrates, the rival of Plato and his elder by a few years, repeats for
his
all
not very philosophical purposes the legend that Pythagoras owed wisdom to Egypt.* In his rhetorical exercise in praise of Busiris he repeats a number of Greek commonplaces about the Egyptians, including the
his
own
and example. for time', he continues (ch. 28), 'could tell many wonderful tales of their holiness, which I am not the only nor the first o"ne to observe. Many have done so both of present and past generations, among them Pythagoras of Samos, who went to Egypt, and having become their pupil was the first to introduce philosophy in general to Greece, and showed a more conspicuous zeal than other men for sacrifices and temple rites; for he reckoned that even if this led to no reward from heaven, among
belief in their religious genius
men at least it would bring him the highest reputation. And so it turned out. His fame so surpassed that of others that while all the young men wanted to
be
his disciples, the older
would
company
own affairs. The truth of this cannot be doubted, for even those who claim to be his disciples win more admiration day
than do those most noted for the gift of speech/
by being
silent
the ordinary Greek's remarks on Pythagoras and his school, broadening sometimes into a more or less tolerant contempt. They were a favourite butt for the writers
of the Middle Comedy in the late fourth century, who ridicule chiefly their abstention from flesh and other ascetic (and unhygienic) practices. (DK, i,
478-80.) (c) Heraclides of Pontus was a pupil of Plato, who joined the Academy at about the same time as Aristotle, and a notable philosopher and scientist in
his
own right
some length with Pythagoras and his school, and there are signs that they exercised considerable influence on him. 3 Although his works are lost, later writers provide several quotations on this subject. They are referred to here
in the
numbering of F. Wehrli's edition of the fragments of Heraclides. Porphyry (De Abst. 1, 26) cites Heraclides among other authorities for the statement that the Pythagorean ban on flesh-eating is not absolute.
Fr. 40.
See frr. 14 and 15, DK, i, 413 , and further on this subject pages 309-12, below. is Naturally Isocrates did not invent this legend, and it cannot be doubted that Pythagoras one of those whom Herodotus had in mind at n, 123 (p. 160, above). 3 Cf. Daebritz in RE, vin, 473, Wehrli, p. 60. For divided opinions on Heraclides in antiquity
*
1
see
I.
de Pyth. 22 f.
163
Pythagoras and
Fr. 41 (Lydus,
the
Pythagoreans
De
Mens.
iv, 42, p.
Pythagorean ban on beans by the curious superstition that if a bean is laid in a new tomb and covered with dung for forty days, it takes on the appearance of a man.
Heraclides attributes to Pythagoras the statement that happiness consists in knowledge of the perfection of the numbers of the soul.
Fr.
44 (Clem. Strom,
II,
84
St.).
ostensibly on the authority of Pythagoras himself, of his successive incarnations. He was once Aethalides, who, when his father Hermes offered him any gift except immortality, chose
Fr. 89 (D.L. viii, 4).
Heraclides
tells,
to retain
both in
life
and
in death the
i,
to him.
640 ff.)
Homeric hero
Euphorbus, wounded by Menelaus, who was wont to recount the wanderings of his soul in animals and plants as well as human bodies, and tell of the fate
of souls in Hades. Next his soul entered Hermotimus, who authenticated the story of his previous life by identifying the rotting shield of Menelaus in the temple of Apollo at Branchidae. It then became a Delian fisherman
finally
it still
the
memory of
(v, 3, 8) tells from Heraclides the story of 1 the ruler of Phlius. with Leon conversation Leon, admiring Pythagoras's the genius and eloquence of Pythagoras, questioned him about his art. He
replied,
however, that he was not a master of any art, but a philosopher. This word was strange to Leon, and, to explain to him what it meant,
Pythagoras employed a simile which has become famous. Life, he
said, is
motives: to compete
-spectators.
Olympic festival, to which people flock from three for the glory of a crown, to buy and sell, or simply as
to
So
in
life,
which we come ex
some
enter the service of fame and others of money, but the best choice
that of
those few
who spend
is,
of nature, as lovers of
wisdom,
that
philosophers.
is
The
last
quotation
is
to
be confined
undoubted independence as authorities for Pythagothen it is time to reanism, stop, for we have already entered the region of controversy. Heraclides wrote dialogues (see frr. 22ff.) ? an d tio doubt the conversation between Pythagoras and Leon occurred in one
to passages of
1
lines 5-10.
The other ancient references to the story are collected by Delatte, Vu de PytL 109, notes to Phlius was known to Plato as a centre of Pythagoreanism, Cameron, Pyth. Back-
164
Evidence of Heraclides
of these compositions which, like those of his teacher Plato, would have a moral rather than a historical purpose and could contain elements of free invention. Moreover the distinction between the three of
types
and corresponding types of humanity, was a favourite theme of Plato's, expressed most concisely in Republic, ix, 5810; and it is probably the prevailing view today that in this story 'Heraclides is pro5 1 A. Cameron, on the jecting Academic ideas on to Pythagoras other hand,2 has ably defended the view that Heraclides is relying
life,
.
on fifth-century material. The value of learning (crocpia, u6c6o$, eecopioc) was deeply rooted in Greek consciousness, as is amply illustrated in Herodotus, and tragedy elsewhere, and Pythagoras was early
largely
regarded as an outstanding exemplar of it (Heraclitus, Herodotus). Transmigration was a Pythagorean belief long before it was Platonic, and the notable thing about the presentation of Pythagoras's philosophic ideal in Heraclides is that it is firmly linked to that belief. In this it goes naturally with his other soul which story of how the
single
store of
pilgrimage through several lives its turn reminds us of the testimony of Empedocles, fr. 129, even more strongly than of Plato. Jaeger's dismissal of the words nos...in
et
'nothing but*.
He
of the three "lives" was Pythagorean, on the ground that the transmiof souls a was gration demonstrably Pythagorean view'; but since the
transmigration of souls was a demonstrably Pythagorean view, we cannot with any greater certainty infer that the doctrine of the three
lives
are, as
strong arguments to suggest that it was.3 This does not of course amount to saying that the simile goes back to Pythagoras himself, but only that the Greek ideal ofphttosophia and
1
giere,
a
So Wehrli, 89, Jaeger, On the Origin and Cycle of the Philosophic Ideal of Life, A. J. FestuLes Trots Vies. Both Wehrli and Festugiere ignore the strong arguments of Cameron.
*
'
' Pythagorean Background, ch. 3 : The Theoretic Lifein Pythagoreanism of the Fifth Century. ' See also the sensible and well-written article of J. L. Stocks, Plato and the Soul (Mind, Tripartite
1915). 3 Cf. also J. S. Morrison, CQ, 1958, p. 208 : 'Jaeger's rejection of the story as a fabrication of the later Academy is quite unwarranted.*
165
Pythagoras and
tkeoria (for
activities
the
Pythagoreans
which we may compare Herodotus's attribution of these to Solon, i, 30) was at a fairly early date annexed by the
doctrine of transPythagoreans for their master, and linked with the one considers that both this doctrine migration. At the same time, when
and the outstanding zeal for knowledge were known to be characteristic of Pythagoras in his own lifetime (Xenophanes) and very soon after that the causal linkage (Heraclitus), it would be rash to deny outright
From
this
survey of the
explicit
references to Pythagoras
it
and the
Pythagoreans down to the time of Plato, have been lost and how difficult it is to form any comprehensive idea of their history and beliefs in this period from contemporary sources. Nevertheless it is something to know that, even if we were to take no
will
account either of later evidence or of anything in earlier writers which is not attributed by name to the school but may with great probability
be referred to
(and to employ neither of these resources would be the following: unnecessarily defeatist), we could still assert
it
Pythagoras himself taught the transmigration of souls (Xenophanes, rewards for the lending credibility to Heraclides Ponticus), and posthumous
1.
meritorious (Ion).*
2.
He was known
man of
prodigious
learning and an
Heraclitus, crcxpicmfc
Herodotus 3 ),
knowledge was
Heraclides).
3.
and in
all
probability
By
the fifth century the veneration of his followers had already exalted
him
him
tales
as
crediting
him
with miracles (Herodotus; and the not his invention but traditional).
1
repeated
by Aristotle were
naturally
may well agree with Burnet here (EGP, 98) : 'It would be rash to say that Pythagoras expressed himself exactly in this manner; but all these ideas are genuinely Pythagorean, and it is only in some such way that we can bridge the gulf that separates Pythagoras the man of science
from Pythagoras the
a
We
religious teacher/ Vlastos has dealt adequately with the unreasonable scepticism of Rathmann (Phitof. Quart.
1952, no, n., referring to Rathmann, Quaestu Pyth. Orph. Emped. 3-11). 3 Vlastos (op. cit. xii, n. 64) and Rathmann think this word means here no religious sage. They compare Eur. Rhesus, 949, where, however, the word means
line
more than a
f
poet', as in
v, 28,
use*
166
compare Heraclides on eating flesh and beans: here at any rate there is no contamination from Academic doctrine, and the prohibitions are of course
much
5.
older). Silence and secrecy were prominent features of their behaviour (Isocrates, and compare Aristotle's reference to drr6ppT)Ta).
a society of their own, practising what was to their a distinctive and extraordinary way of life (Plato, Rep. contemporaries
6.
They formed
600 B).
7. Philolaus, a leading fifth-century Pythagorean, preached the wickedness of suicide, basing it on a secret logos of which the purport was that men 1 are not their own masters but belong to the gods (Plato, Phaedo).
8.
As
to the
more
scientific side
of their teaching,
we have
learned from
Plato that they were the acknowledged experts in astronomy, harmonics and the science of number. They regarded all these studies as closely allied,
because in their view the key to the understanding both of the movements of the stars and of the notes in the musical scale lay in the establishment of a
We may allow ourselves to note that the actual union of and harmonics in the remarkable theory of the 'harmony of the astronomy spheres', adopted by Plato, is described and attested as Pythagorean in the same century by Aristotle.* This is the view that physical objects moving as rapidly as the heavenly bodies must necessarily produce a sound; that the intervals between the several planets and the sphere of the fixed stars correspond mathematically to the intervals between the notes of the octave, and
numerical relation.
that therefore the
The importance of even these scanty items of information becomes evident when we remember that for Plato the problem of the possibility
of knowledge was
since the
central,
it
unknowable, such awareness of truth as we acquire in this life must consist in the recollection of what we
world of experience
strictly
depends on the doctrine of reincarnation. for the fragmentary state surprise, even allowing
i.e. it
is
knew
was
it
Philolaus used
3
Ask
Socrates. It
was he who
said it
iv drropp^Tois.
De
Caelo, n, 9.
The Pythagoreans
On this
below.
167
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
discoveries (let alone passage, there is no mention of Pythagorean discoveries of Pythagoras himself) in mathematics or music. Of the famous doctrine that 'things are numbers' there is not a whisper before
Aristotle.
So
much of what we
Pythagoras and his school is missing in our evidence until the latter 1 half of the fourth century. Rohde went so far as to say that Pythagoras
himself was not a philosopher at
all,
To
him it seemed an important argument ex silentlo that even Aristotle and his pupil Aristoxenus knew nothing of any physical or ethical doctrines of Pythagoras himself. The sole allusion in the period so far considered
to his personal interest in mathematical explanation is Heraclides's attribution to him (in fr. 44) of the statement that happiness consists in
knowledge of the perfection of the numbers of the soul, and since this does smack strongly of Academic doctrine it seemed more prudent to omit it from our summary. As for Aristotle, the only safe conclusion
to
draw from
his silence
is
that
at
all,*
had already become a legend and his critical mind could not feel satisfied that any specific doctrine was to be traced with certainty to the Master himself. Once we speak of the Pythagoreans, however, it might equally well be argued that by Aristotle's time at least they had become
a purely scientific school, since it is only as such that they appear in his extant treatises. 3 This argument has in fact been used, but is of little
weight.
The
simple answer
is
and philo-
sophy were relevant to Aristotle's subject-matter in his extant treatises. The meagre fragments of his lost works are sufficient to show that he knew of another side to their teaching. As for the silence of our early sources on Pythagoras as a philosopher and mathematician, it is enough
to say that
all
obviously preserve
that the authors
*
hope of
Rh* Mus. 1871, 554f. But he seems partially to retract on pp. 556-7. Yet it is not now quite true to say that he shows no awareness of Pythagoras as a physical philosopher. In a fragment of the Protrepucus (Iambi. Protr. ch. 9, p. 51 Pistelli: see die Oxf. trans, of Aristotle's fragments, p. 45) he tells a traditional story of Pythagoras, that when asked what is the end of human life he replied *to observe the heavens', and that he used to say that he was an observer of nature (0ecop6v TTJS 90aeoos), and it was for this that he had entered on life.
2
3
De AwmC)
4O7bi2.
168
Post-Platonic Sources
learning anything about him. Nevertheless to begin in this way, so that statements of genuine antiquity are clearly marked off both from
later testimonies
ally
sound.
(3) Post-Platonic sources
This general heading brings together sources of very disparate date and unequal value. But all alike can be sharply distinguished from earlier
material in that they are to a far greater extent the inevitable subject of and are doubt. The reasons controversy briefly these.
Two
pupils
extensively about the Pythagoreans. Aristoxenus (who, as it is not irrelevant to note, was an expert on music) wrote whole books on
Pythagoras and his acquaintances, on the Pythagorean life and other Pythagorean matters, and we are told that he personally knew those
the last generation of the Pythagoreans, that is the pupils of Philolaus and Eurytus including Echecrates. 1 Dicaearchus
was a scientific researcher of great learning and independence of mind. Here then are two further fourth-century sources of information who would seem to merit a high degree of trust. In the first place, however, their works have not come down to us, and what they said is known
only through quotations in the Neoplatonic lives of Pythagoras by Porphyry and lamblichus and similar compilations of the Christian era.
Although these writers frequently cite their fourth-century predecessors by name, there is often dispute about the actual extent or the
accuracy of their quotations, especially as these are not thought to have been made at first hand. Rohde, for instance, in his work on the
sources of lamblichus, 2 concluded that he made direct use only of the works of Nicomachus of Gerasa and Apollonius of Tyana, the former a
mathematician of about A.D. 100 whose work was imbued with Neo-
and pythagorean number-mysticism, the latter a Neopythagorean sage we have as earlier. a wonder-worker of perhaps half century Secondly, seen with HeracUdes Ponticus, members of the schools of Plato
already
and
1
Their names are given by D,L. vm, Rh. Mus. 1872, dof.
46,
frr.
19 and
Wehrli).
169
Pythagoras and
the,
Pythagoreans
1 Platonic doctrine with that of the Pythagoreans. In general the separation of early Pythagoreanism from the teaching of Plato is one of the
historian's
most
difficult tasks, to
which he can scarcely avoid bringing own. If later Pythagoreanism was coloured by that Plato himself was is equally undeniable
but in deciding the deeply affected by earlier Pythagorean beliefs; extent to which each has influenced the other, most people have found extent of their admiration it impossible to avoid being guided by the his originality. minimize to for Plato and consequent unwillingness
is
Another source from the turn of the fourth and third centuries B.C. the Sicilian historian Timaeus from Taormina. He had intimate knowledge of affairs in Magna Graecia, where the Pythagorean society
had played an important political role, and seems to have been unbiased by any personal attachment to the school. In his case therefore the one serious disadvantage arises from our fragmentary and indirect
knowledge of his
known through writers of the Graeco-Roman period, we have from now on to lean heavily on studies in source-criticism. The source-critic starts
from passages which are expressly ascribed to an earlier writer, and, by comparison with these and passages of known origin elsewhere, endeavours to detect other derived material and assign it to
its
original authority.
He may
of ancient
it is
imbedded by
testing
it
against what-
known as certain
Stoic, post-Aristotelian philosophy permeates the literature of the Graeco-Roman period that a passage containing no trace of it may suddenly stand out. Its freshness and
he
is
dealing with something earlier. The delicacy of this work, and the element of personal judgment inseparable from it, are mitigated by the
*
Aristoxenus]
9 <Sf.
3
Wehrli, Aristoxenos, 59: *Hauptmerkmal der 'Atroipdcreis [i.e. the TTu6cxyoptKal 611:09. of ist aber die Beanspruchung akademisch-peripatetischen Gutes fur die Pythagoreer.'
this attitude to
Exaggeration of
Aristoxenus
in n. 6;
is criticized
by E.
L. Minar, Early
PytL
3.
Politics,
err.
52 with
reff.
von
Fritz,
I7O
like lamblichus.
made no attempt to rewrite and weld their sources into a new and homogeneous whole, but simply copied out extracts side by side, even repeating conflicting accounts in different parts of their work. Thus in
his Protrepticus, for example, lamblichus inserts passages
from the
Phaedoy Gorgias and other dialogues of Plato practically verbatim without the slightest acknowledgment of their authorship. Ingram Bywater
in the last century, encouraged by this, and observing that other parts of the work also seemed to belong to a pre-Hellenistic stratum of thought
as well as being
marked by an individual style which was certainly not was led on to the discovery that they
belonged to the lost Protrepticus of Aristotle, considerable portions of which have been in this way recovered for us by Bywater himself and
others following in his footsteps. It cannot be denied that the methods employed in source-criticism, and die nature of the task itself, leave
plenty of room for individual differences of opinion; but a solid foundation of generally acceptable results has gradually been obtained, of which the recovery of the Protrepticus fragments, though not relevant
to our immediate subject,
instance.
1
may
The
(4)
'a priori*
method
Besides the actual information about the early Pythagoreans which we may extract, directly or indirectly, from ancient writers, there is
another resource. This has been made use of in the past, and it will be it is not so appropriate to make a brief statement of it here, thought
much
a fresh source of evidence as a means of testing, and perhaps inference expanding, the positive testimony.
by
The method
is
number of explicit
likely
statements about what the Pythagoreans of a given period actually what they are said, and argue a priori, or from circumstantial evidence, to have said. It starts from the assumption that we possess a
certain general familiarity with other contemporary schools
1
and
indi-
See
now
I.
Diking,
Fritz,
Aristotle's Protrepticus: an attempt at reconstruction, Goteborg, 1961. be Pytk. Politics in S. Italy> is so exceptionally lucid that it
may
taken as a model introduction to source-criticism, whether or not his results are accepted
171
it is
have held doctrine A, and that it is impossible for them at that stage of thought to have already evolved doctrine B. Examples of the application of this method in recent English scholar-
menides are
on 'Mysticism and Science ship are the two articles by F. M. Cornford in the Pythagorean Tradition' together with their sequel in his book
1 Plato and Parmenides, and their criticism by J. E. Raven. In arguments of this type, considerable weight may be attached to
the generally acknowledged existence of two main streams of early Greek philosophy, the Ionian and the Italian, and the equally well established fact that the fountain-head of the Italian tradition was
Pythagoras. Individual philosophers were open to the influence of one or the other of these streams, and whichever it was, being aware of the
existence of both they are either openly or implicitly critical of the other. Empedocles the Sicilian is deeply imbued with the Italian ideas.
with good reason believed to have started as a philosopher of the Italian school, and to have rebelled against its teachings. Parmenides indeed, the most original and profound of all Presocratic thinkers, abandoned the fundamentals of all
is
irrational
alike, declaring any form of monistic cosmogony to be and impossible; but if he had been of the Italian persuasion himself, it seems natural that he should have had its tenets particularly
earlier
systems
in
mind
in his criticism.
In such ways as these the development of Pythagorean thought may be reflected in the agreement or disagreement of other thinkers, and it
may be
the time of Parmenides, of Zeno the Eleatic, or of Empedocles. Clearly, however, such a method may only be used with the greatest
possible caution.
Raven, Pythagoreans and Eleatics. In mentioning these works purely as examples, I of course at this stage expressing any opinion on the correctness of their results.
1
am not
I 72
Life of Pythagoras
C.
LIFE OF PYTHAGORAS
OF THE SCHOOL
No one who has read the preceding section will suppose that an account
of the
and achievements of Pythagoras can rest on anythan thing stronger probabilities; but the evidence is interesting, and certain conclusions may legitimately be drawn. 1
life,
character
The dates of his life cannot be fixed exactly, but assuming the approximate correctness of the statement of Aristoxenus (op* Porph. V.P. % DK, 14 8) that he left Samos to escape the tyranny of Polycrates at the
.
570 B.C. or a few years earlier. The length of his life was variously estimated in antiquity, but it is that he a lived most to old and agreed fairly ripe age, probably he 3 died at about seventy-five or eighty. His father Mnesarchus of Samos
age of forty,
to Herodotus and Heraclitus3) is described as a and it would be in accordance with regular Greek gem-engraver, custom for Pythagoras to be trained in his father's craft. We read of travels in Egypt and Babylonia, the former first mentioned by Isocrates in his Bitsiris. The nature of this work does not inspire confidence, and
(the
the tradition connecting Pythagoreanism with Egypt may be thought to have arisen from the general Greek respect for Egyptian wisdom, especially religious wisdom.^ But the same cause would naturally drive a man like Pythagoras to seek enlightenment in that quarter, and that he did so is very likely. According to Diogenes (vm, 3), Polycrates (whether
before or after his assumption of power we do not know) gave him a letter of introduction to Amasis, the Pharaoh who was the tyrant's
friend
and
ally.
may well be
*
of it did
See also J. S. Morrison, Pythagoras of Samos*, CQ, 1956. See esp. Rohde's analysis of the tradition about Pythagoras's dates in Rh. Mus* 1871, pp. 568-74, and E. L. Minar, Early Pytk. Pol. appendix. 3 And may be taken as certain, like the Samian origin of Pythagoras for which Herodotus also JL vin, i, etc.) may speaks. The tradition that he was of Tyrrhenian origin (Aristoxenus op. be reconciled with this (ZN, 380), but may, as Delatte, Vie de P. I47f., and Wehrli, Aristolore. xenos, 1945, 49 conjecture, have been suggested to explain his possession of secret religious This would be a parallel to his reputed connexion with Zoroaster and the Magi (HippoL Ref* I,
a
2, 12,
4
5
14.9, Porph. V.P. 6, 12; Hdt. n, 8 1, 123. T. Lenschau in RE, xxi, 1728.
DK
11).
173
To his reign prosperity and power but also of technical achievement. belong the famous tunnel of the engineer Eupalinus (rediscovered in
1882)5 the great temple built by Rhoecus and the harbour mole whose line may still be traced in the water, as well as the flourishing practice
of those
All that
arts to
celature and in which Pythagoras and his family were directly concerned.
or can guess, of Pythagoras suggests that he would be intensely interested in both the artistic and the commercial progress of the island, and in all probability, with his mathematical genius and
we know,
craftsman's
skill,
He encouraged the luxury material with and dissipation which grew naturally prosperity, and in attaining his ends he could be brutal and unscrupulous. The atmosphere
But there was another
in
Anacreon and Ibycus felt at home was not one to conappeal to a preacher of the ascetic life. Whether or not political siderations played their part Polycrates was the enemy of the old
which poets
like
landed aristocracy of Samos we know too little of Pythagoras's connexions and outlook to say; but political considerations are unnecessary to explain the discontent of a religious and philosophical genius at the court of a tyrant of this type?
To escape life under the tyranny, he migrated to Croton, the leading Achaean colony in South Italy. What determined his choice we cannot say, but he may have been encouraged in it by Democedes of Croton
who was court physician to
effects
Polycrates.3
Croton was
still
suffering the
of her defeat by the Locrians at the river Sagra, demoralizing and historians of the Greek West observe a marked improvement after the arrival of Pythagoras.4 Arriving no doubt with his reputation made,
1
(or toreutic)
a
P. N. Ure in C.A.H. iv, 926, C. T. Seltman, Approach to Greek (1948), pp. 13, 37. Celature was a free man's art, Gisela Richter in AJA> 1941, 379, quoting Pliny, N.H. xxxv, 77. The experiences of the present century make one disinclined to agree with Minar when he
An
writes (E.P.P. 4): 'This [Pythagoras's departure] of course shows that a specifically political difference existed between Pythagoras and the democratically-disposed tyrant.'
3 It is interesting to notice this evidence that a school of medicine existed at Croton before the time of Pythagoras (Burnet, EGP> 89, n. 2). Democedes had practised in Athens and Aegina, and attained such fame that he was employed by Darius as well as Polycrates (Hdt, in, 131-2.
For further
4
346
below).
T.
J.
174
Life of Pythagoras he appears to have attained without delay a position of authority and influence in the city and founded his school there. From now on the name of Pythagoras is linked indissolubly, not with the Ionian or
Eastern, but with the Italian, Western schools of thought of which he
is
the fountain-head. Stories going back to Dicaearchus 1 this impressive and much-travelled man arrived he so
tell
elder and ruling citizens with his eloquence that they invited him to address also the younger men, the school-children and the women.
2 Dicaearchus, it is said, as a champion of the practical life exaggerated the political activity of Pythagoras and his school, but the evidence
overwhelming. The NeoPythagoreans, who embroidered his story in the light of their own more visionary ideas, liked to represent him as absorbed in religious and
that they took a leading part in politics
is
contemplative thought, but no outstanding thinker in the small society of a sixth-century city-state (as Dunbabin remarks, op. cit. 361) could
nor do any of our earlier sources suggest that Pythagoras had any desire to do so. What we may say, from our knowledge of the Pythagorean philosophy, is that his
affairs,
motive in acquiring power (like that of his near contemporary Confucius) was not personal ambition but a zeal for reforming society
according to his own moral ideas. There is no reason to doubt the general statement which we find in Diogenes (vm, 3) that he gave the
Italians a constitution
state so well
that
it
deserved the
sense.
its literal
name of aristocracy C government of thejsgat*) in Dunbabin gives an excellent summary of the position
(op.
cit.
61) :
His political influence was, however, a secondary consequence of his teaching. The moral regeneration which he wrought was the necessary condition of
Krotoniate expansion, political and otherwise.
.
.
His influence was invited to address the citizens on his arrival at Kroton. .There is no reason to doubt that the was no doubt more gradually felt.
. .
Pythagorean
IrotipsTai
(Von
Fritz,
94 ff.,
did for the first half of the fifth of Kroton and most of the other South Italian cities. Minar, i5ff.) This they will have done through the
[political clubs]
1
Porph. r.P.
Burnet,
18,
DK,
14-
8 a.
EGP,
175
89, n. 4.
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
existing forms of government; the part of the ircctpeiai in determining the policy of the State may be roughly compared with that of a party caucus in
parliamentary government.
gorean society of
Srccipefa
The importance
the history of the revolts against the Pythagoreans, indicate sufficiently clearly that real power was in their hands. In what form this applies to the
must be noted that eroctpoi are spoken of in connexion with the events of 510 (Iambi. V.P. 177). Further, one of the followers of Pythagoras was the athlete Milon, general of the victorious army which defeated Sybaris (Strabo, 263).
sixth century is uncertain, but
it
The tendency, as well as the reality, of Pythagoras's political influence maybe illustrated by a narrative of Diodonis (xn, 9, DK, 14 14). Telys,
.
the leader of the popular party (8imocycoy6s) at Sybaris, persuaded his city to banish five hundred of its richest citizens and divide their
Croton and Telys threatened war if they were not given up, the Crotonian assembly was at first inclined to give way, and it was Pythagoras who intervened and persuaded them to protect the suppliants. The
result
must not be overlooked is that Pythagoras may have both introduced and designed the unique incuse coinage which was the earliest money of Croton and the neighbouring South Italian
possibility that
cities
of numismatists by its combination of a remarkable and difficult technique with outstanding beauty of design, and Seltman claims that
sudden appearance with no evolutionary process behind it postulates a genius of the order of Leonardo da Vinci: 'for the latter half of the
its
is
As
only one name to fit this role: Pythagoras*. would himself have been a practising
* This theory was put forward by the Due de Luynes in 1836, and though it has met with much opposition (partly no doubt because as Seltman says it seems 'too good to be true'), it has
recently been vigorously revived by C. T, Seltman (*The Problem of the First Italiote Coins', Num. Ckron. 1949: his arguments must be read in full to be properly appreciated), and Miss
M. White accounts
it
*the
(JHS
1954, 43).
The
most reasonable explanation yet proposed for these curious coinages' Belgian P. Naster has even identified the technique of the coins with one
therefore attributes
introduced
e*migre*
them to an
who wrote
was not written by Homer but by another poet of the same name.
176
Life of Pythagoras
artist,
and of his genius there can be no doubt. One begins to appreciate the dictum of Empedocles that he was 'skilled in all manner of cunning
put the theory in its mildest form) that can have had Pythagoras nothing to do with this apparently contem1 porary coinage; and this throws a light on his social position and
It is scarcely possible (to
works*.
which is not without its bearing on his philosophy. have been responsible for the adoption of coinage, he must have belonged to the rising mercantile class with experience of the interpractical interests
To
is
wealthy party (TOV/S TrAouaicoTcrrous) Sybaris, and finds support in two statements of Aristoxenus which are
seldom quoted. He writes that Pythagoras 'extolled and promoted the study of numbers more than anyone, diverting it from mercantile practice and comparing everything to numbers*, and in another place
attributes to
the Greeks.3
him the introduction of weights and measures among Even the earliest accounts of Pythagoras contain legen-
dary accretions, but these prosaic statements hardly have a legendary ring, nor would the Pythagorean friends of Aristoxenus have any
of the Master.
One may
1 It used to be objected that there exist in this same distinctive series coins of Siris, a town which was destroyed about 550 B.C., that is, at least twelve and possibly twenty years before the migration of Pythagoras. But Seltman has shown (op. cit. 2, citing a parallel case) that the coins in question do not belong to Siris but to the town of Pyxus, which called itself Suinian probably because founded by fugitives from the destroyed city. This is a more likely solution to the question of date than to put Pythagoras's arrival considerably earlier, on the grounds that *the tyranny of Polycrates* does not mean what it says but only *the tyranny in Samos* (M. White,
JHS,
*
1954, 42).
So G. Thomson, The First Philosophers, 263. Sutherland noted that the silver used for the coins had to be imported from Corinth. Arguing as a Marxist, Thomson regards Pythagoras's mercantile interests as the key to his interest in mathematics because trade leads to a purely to the qualitative criterion of the quantitative interest in the variety of material goods, as opposed consumer. The words of Aristoxenus, that he diverted the study of number <3nr6 -rfjs TWV &Tr6pcov an ancient precedent for this view, which is Xpetocs, though not quoted by Thomson, provide also supported by a Chinese scholar: '[The Greeks] were primarily merchants. And what
merchants have to deal with first are the abstract numbers used in their commercial accounts, and only then with concrete things which may be immediately apprehended through these numbers. . . .Hence Greek philosophers. . .developed mathematics and mathematical reasoning* (Fung Yu Lan, Short History of Chinese Philosophy, 25). On the whole, however, the evidence is in favour of supposing that Pythagoras's impulse towards mathematics originated rather from his
interest in musical theory.
3
Aristox.
frr.
See pp. 220 ff., below. 23 and 24 Wehrli, also in DK, 5882 and 14. 12.
177
Pythagoras and
leader
the
Pythagoreans
was not simply of the old land-owning type, but had strong connexions with trade. 1
The ascendancy of Pythagoras and his followers was uninterrupted for some twenty years, during which Croton extended her influence
and in many of them the leading positions were occupied by members of the Pythagorean brotherhood. At the end of this period a Crotonian named Cylon stirred the people to 2 revolt. According to Aristoxenus he was a wealthy and loose-living
over the neighbouring
cities
nobleman who acted from personal spite, having been refused admission to the Pythagorean order on moral grounds.3 Others, however, more of the ultraplausibly allege political opposition on the grounds
conservatism of the Pythagoreans, reinforced by the suspicion and doctrines. The jealousy aroused by the strange and secret nature of their
upshot of the somewhat confused account which lamblichus (V.P. 4 25 5 ff.) retails from Apollonius seems to be that opposition came from
both
sides,
classes
by the Pythagoreans of attempts at popular reform. This combination offerees seems to have been due on the one hand to popular discontent
with the concentration of power in the hands of a few, coupled with the ordinary man's dislike of what he considers mumbo-jumbo, and on the
other to the native aristocracy's suspicion of the Pythagorean coteries
(&Tcapeioci),
whose assumption of
have been hard
knowledge
must
1
at times
to bear.
Dicaearchus (fr. 34 Wehrli) tells a story that when in his flight from Croton he came to Locri, a Locrian deputation met him at the border with the polite but firm request that he should go elsewhere. They admired, they said, his cleverness (ao96v jiev avSpa ae KOC! Seivov OCKOUOUV),
but were
satisfied with their present condition and had no desire for any change. Whether this story is true or only blen trouve, it is perhaps just worth recalling that Locri had no coinage until the fourth century: 'this suggests that the Locrian economy was in the archaic period different
them were
limited'
(Dunbabin,
op. cit.
The earliest extant mention of Cylon as the opponent of Pydiagoras is in Aristotle, according D.L. n, 46, who claims to be quoting 'the third book On Poetry'. 3 Iambi. V.P. 248 (DK, 14.16), Porph. J^.P. 54. Aristoxenus got his information from fourth-century members of the Pythagorean school who had migrated to Greeceafter persistent persecution in Italy (D.L. vin, 46). This means that as to facts, chronology, etc. he could hardly have been better informed, but in moral and political judgments his account may be unduly
to
is
more complex
question.
Cf.
von
Fritz,
Pyth.
Pol
in S. It.
56 ff.
178
Death of Pythagoras
In the Cylonian conspiracy a number of leading Pythagoreans were rounded up and killed (the details are variously given), and it seems to
to find a resting-place. As usual, fact and legend mingle in the story of his fate. Aristotle preserves the version that he left Croton before the
attack, but since the object
it
of this story
is
to demonstrate his
power of
seems to belong to the legend. According to the most prophecy, credible accounts, he finally reached Metapontum, where he died.
About
number of more or
less
romantic
stories, but the most probable seems to be that of Dicaearchus (D.L. vin, 40, Porph. f.P. 57), that he was forced to take refuge in a temple
of the Muses, where he starved to death. The rebellion of Cylon, which must have taken place about the turn of the sixth and fifth centuries, seems to have caused only a very
temporary check to Pythagorean activities, and their influence was even extended over the next forty or fifty years. But it was a troublous period
break in the middle of the
that
of growing unrest, which led to a second, major anti-Pythagorean outfifth century. In this the house at Croton
said to
1 according to Polybius the revolutionary movement spread through the whole of Magna Graecia. Pythagorean meeting-houses were destroyed,
the leading men of each city perished, and the whole region was in turmoil. This catastrophe, which is dated by Minar to 4543.0. about the first emigration of Pythagoreans to the (pp. cit. 77), brought
mainland of Greece and led to the establishment of Pythagorean centres at Phlius and Thebes. Among the youngest of the refugees
Aristoxenus (Iambi.
much
was
14.16) mentions Lysis, who later at Thebes became the teacher of Epaminondas. Another
V.P. 249,
DK,
Philolaus, mentioned in the Phaedo as having taught the Thebans Simmias and Cebes 162, above). Even now, the Pythagoreans
(p.
a certain amount of political stayed behind seem to have regained life as a society, chiefly their continued to have and influence in Italy,
who
at
Rhegium. Later
1
still,
however, when in the words of Aristoxenus all are said to have left
n?
39>
I *~4-
179
Pythagoras and
Italy except
the
Pythagoreans
Archytas of Tarentum. It is impossible to date this final Fritz would put it as late as 390. but von exodus, We see, then, that the life of the Pythagorean societies was by no
that
South
effect
philosophical tradition
was naturally
Porphyry
(57ff.)
and
lamblichus (252f.) preserve a description of what happened which went back through Nicomachus to Neanthes in the third century B.C.
must contain a great deal of truth, and goes far to account for the inadequacy and obscurity of our material on Pythagorean doctrine.
It
According to
prominent Pythagoreans who lost their lives knowledge with them to the grave, for it
had been kept secret, only those parts being divulged which would have conveyed little meaning to outsiders. Pythagoras had left no writings of his own, and only a few dim sparks of philosophy were kept alight by men like Lysis and Archippus of Tarentum who escaped, and
any
who were abroad at the time of the troubles. These exiles were so cast down by events that they lived in isolation, shunning the company
of their fellow-men. Nevertheless, to avoid incurring divine displeasure by allowing the name of philosophy to perish altogether, they collected
in note
form whatever had been written down by an older generation, supplemented by their own memories. Each one left these commen-
taries,
was
wife, with instructions that they be kept within the household. The trust faithfully kept, and the notebooks handed down for several
generations, but our sources agree that as an active sect (ocipscri$) the Pythagorean society practically died out during the fourth century B.C.
They preserved their original ways, and their science, although the sect was dwindling, until, not ignobly, they died out.' Thus was their epitaph
written
fi
by Aristoxenus
this
(op. Iambi.
who
were
his contemporaries
and acquaintances.
troubled history, first, that the Pythagorean through the classical period of Greek thought
exist
in the sixth to the fourth centuries B.C., and secondly, that from the middle of the fifth century it existed in the form of separate, scattered
1 80
only natural
lines,
and that
we
we do from
Aristotle, that
certain doctrines
allegiance to the
least it
others, although all acknowledged same founder. This does not lighten our task, but at means that inconsistencies are no cause for despair, or for a
less
be a
faithful reflexion
of historical
fact.
D.
Pythagoras has been regarded by some scholars as no more than the founder of a religious sect, upon whom were foisted in later days
mathematical discoveries made long after his time: he may have 1 played in a superstitious way with 'number-mysticism , but no more.
5
Others have emphasized almost exclusively the rational and scientific side of his thought. Both these portrayals are too one-sided and extreme
to be plausible. The religious doctrines of immortality and transmigration are assigned to Pythagoras on incontrovertible positive
and philosophical cosmology, attested by such early and impregnable sources, the only reasonable explanation of the unique
name on subsequent
and
he was from
own life-
many
by
his followers,
violently attacked by others, but ignored by none. The attempts to minimize one or the other side of his nature arise from the difficulty
in reconciling adherence to a
com-
set of religious and superstitious beliefs with the paratively primitive rational pursuit of mathematical science and cosmic speculation; but in
the sixth century B.C. such a combination was not only possible but natural. What we may safely say is that for Pythagoras religious and
The most
outstanding
Pytkagoreer.
181
Pythagoras and
destined
life
the
Pythagoreans
from the
fulfil
start to
and
struck
when we
understand
its aim, we may make this our starting-point. Philosophy for Pythagoras and his followers had to be first and foremost the basis for a way of life: more than that, for a way of eternal salvation. When
the study of man and the cosmos is undertaken as a means of help and guidance in right living, the resulting system of nature must be one that
will afford such help.
To
philosophy was that which taught of man, of the nature of the human soul and its relations with other forms of life and with the whole. This therefore will be dealt with first. After that it will be in place to say something of Pythagoreanism as a philosophy of form under which
,
fall its
Pythagoreanism contains a strong element of the magical, a primitive feature which sometimes seems hard to reconcile with the intellectual
depth which is no less certainly attested. It is not on that account to be dismissed as a mere excrescence, detachable from the main system.
All
who work on
the border-line of philosophy and religion among made aware of a typical general characteristic
of their thought: that is, a remarkable gift for retaining, as the basis for mass of early, traditional ideas which were often
same time transforming their build on them some of the most profound and
at the
on human life and destiny. This was true of the Orphic writers, whose religious teaching was almost identical with that of Pythagoras,* and the same genius for combining conservatism with innovation, introducing new wine without breaking the old bottles, was
particularly strong
1
among
the Pythagoreans.
is
no more than
a rationalization of beliefs held before the inquiry begins, let me add that although this is in many cases a fair judgment, clear thinking itself may be a philosopher's aim as much as anything else.
If so, this does not
2
less
important.
of Orphic thought cf. Guthrie, Orpk. and Gk. Ret. I29f., and for the relations between Orphic and Pythagorean, ibid. 216-21. As early as the fifth century Ion of Chios could attribute Orphic poems to Pythagoras himself (Ion, fr. 2 DK).
characteristic
For this
182
Magical Elements
Their retention of primitive material is well illustrated in their collection of sayings called Acusmata or Symlola. Although adopted by the sect, many of these precepts are obviously older than Pythagoras, and some are found in non-Pythagorean contexts as well, for example in Hesiod, the sayings of the Seven Wise Men, and the Delphic
are straightforward moral precepts, but others had to be later explained as having a hidden/ora^^'^^ning in accord with
precepts.
Some
Pythagorean moral or
political ideals.
The
Diogenes, Porphyry, lamblichus, Hippolytus may be said with confidence to go back to a collection made by Aristotle in the work which he
is
explicitly
quoted as the
Out of many
Not Not
to pick up what has fallen from the table. to stir the fire with a knife.
To
on a bushel-measure. wear a narrow ring (also given as "Not to wear a ring'). to have swallows in the house. To spit on one's nail-parings and hair-trimmings. Not to make water or stand on one's nail-parings or hair-trimmings. 3 To roll up one's bedclothes on rising and smooth out the imprint of
to
body.
To
1
when
it
thunders.
C. W. Goettling (Ges. Abh. vol. i, 278-316) contended that these latter alone were the oOnpoAcx (for it is of the essence of a ounpoAov that its true significance does not appear on the surface), die others forming a separate class of dKoOaporro. The hypothesis was somewhatweakened by the number of times that he had to assume a saying to have been wrongly classified by the
ancient authorities.
His general interpretation ('quam to tarn ethicam esse debere ostendi*, vol. u, 280) was easier to uphold in the middle of the nineteenth than of the twentieth century. Their real nature was first explained in detail by F. Boehm, De Symbolis Pythagoras^ in the
in The. Golden light of the anthropological material of his time, and especially of that contained Bough. Boehm's competent short work scarcely deserves the slighting expressions of Delatte more weighty as well as more recent critic describes his application of in Vie de Pyth. 186-7.
the comparative method as 'circumspect' (Nilsson, Gesch. d. gr. R&L I, 666, n. 3). For the dKotiauaroc in general see Nilsson, 665-9. * D.L. vni, 34. Cf. Delatte, Etudes, 273 (following V. Rose and Rohde), Nilsson, Gesch. I,
665 f.
3 Only this and the previous one defeated the moralizing zeal of Goettling: *Ich bin nicht Stande, aus dieser Vorschrift irgend einen vernunftigen Sinn zu entnehmen' (p. 315).
im
183
The moral interpretations attached to these picturesque sayings in our sources show plainly enough that they had nothing to do with them in
the beginning.
to be content
on
up the bedding
famous and widely commented-on Pythagorean injunction was that which prohibited the eating of beans, and many different explanations of it were offered, some of which may at first sight seem obscure.
Beans resembled
testicles:
whole universe (all their stems were hollow throughout and unjointed (D.L. vin, 34; from beneath Porphyry connected this fact with the return of souls the earth, Antr. Nymph. 19): they are of a windy or breathy nature and
(D.L. vui, 24) they contain the souls of the dead (Pliny, N.H. xvm, 118). When in the creative chaos at the beans and beginning of the world life arose out of the primeval slime, 2 of form the same from their had human beings primal matter. origin
or the they resembled the gates of Hades, D.L. these were recorded by Aristotle, vin, 34):
hence
full
of the
life-force
would undergo
if
Heraclides Ponticus
is
reported as saying that it would assume human shape. writers we learn that it would be assimilated to a child's
From
later
head or the
if
female pudenda.
(In saying that they resembled the universe' the Pythagoreans doubtless had in mind their belief that it was animate.) Such a connexion may well have been primitive, and at the
soul.
There were other explanations too. See Plut Quaest. Conv. 7278. lamblichus warns that the interpretations were Pythagorean (V.P. 86). It is of course by no means improbable that in taking over these primitive superstitions Pythagoras himself interpreted them in this
not
all
1
Porphyry and others adduced the belief that the sun a bean would give off an odour of semen.3
all
have in
common
symbolic way*
*
jRef.
2,
14 (Diels,
(i.e.
Dox.
557),
Porph. V.P. 44. Cf. the unintelligibly abbreviated version in Hippol. where Pythagoras is said to have learned this from Zoroaster;
n.) op.
also
Diogenes
Lyd.
De Mens.
iv, 42,
pp. 99-100
184
The 'Acusmata
same time
reflects
genuine Pythagorean
interests.
also
was
Pythagoreans themselves, but its artificial character is obvious, nor had it ever the wide currency nor the central importance in Pythagorean
was accorded the connexion with life and the doctrine of transmigration. There was a Pythagorean saying in the form of a hexameter
lore that
verse (also attributed to Orpheus, which keeps it in the same circle), to the effect that to eat beans is equivalent to eating the heads of one's
and various paraphrases of it are quoted repeatedly in late antiquity, and another hexametric version of the prohibition was not only included in the Orphic poems but used by
parents.
line
1
Empedocles in the
fifth
Wretched, thrice
* wretched, keep your hands from beans. Many of the other examples cited betray their origin in sympathetic magic, which assumes a close, quasi-physical relationship between things
It exists
between
man and his picture or image, or even the imprint of his body in a bed,
had once been a part of him like nail-parings or
hair-trimmings. These must be treated with respect because owing to the intangible bond which unites them the treatment to which such
things are subjected will be reflected in the welfare of the
man himself.
By gaining possession of them, an enemy can do much harm. The taboo on wearing any unbroken rings about the person, which applies
also to knots,
is
And by
Kudxucov <3nro
X^P ^ x
iv
^vncovros SSEcrroO,
Emped.
at
fr.
141
DK (from
Gellius).
Taboo on beans
is
and
See Boehm,
found in many parts of the world, op, cit. 14-17 and index
185
Pythagoras and
physical effect. which underlies
the
Pythagoreans
The
all
of transference, general belief in the possibility the taboos of sympathetic magic, rests in turn on an
is
foreign to civilized beliefs associated with a totemic thought- It appears again in the tribe is conscious of a kinship, even the where of society, organization between itself and a non-human species of animal. an
identity,
or Symbola has brought Beginning the account with the Acusmata in Pythagoreanism much of into prominence the initial connexion with primitive magical ways of thinking. The essentially magical conor sympathy, in a more or less refined and of universal
ception
kinship
its
universe and the relationship of its parts. To be aware of this will assist an understanding of its mathematical conception of the natural world as
well as of
its
human
soul.
Porphyry
DK,
14.80):
for certain, since they preserved What he said to his disciples no man such an exceptional silence. However, the following facts in particular became universally known: first that he held the soul to be immortal, next that it migrates into other kinds of animal, further that past events repeat
is
new
in an absolute sense,
and
living things as kindred (onoyevf}). These is said to have been the first to introduce
^
Apart from the fact that Porphyry's informant here may have been Dicaearchus/ this passage contains several reassuring features. His language shows unusual caution, an effort for once to confine himself to what
he believes he may regard as certain. More important, the immortality of the soul, and its transmigration into various animal bodies, are vouched
for as beliefs of Pythagoras by his own contemporary Xenophanes Moreover the doctrine of the kinship of all animate (p. 157, above).
nature appears in Empedocles, a philosopher of the Italian tradition in the early fifth century B.C.* may assume that this doctrine, no less
We
Dicaearchus
is
mentioned byname some sixteen lines earlier. Cf. Rohde,.#A. Mus. 1872, 26,
and
n. 2, p. 151, above.
3 The other theory mentioned by Porphyry, that of the exact recurrence of events, does not immediately concern us, but is vouched for as Pythagorean in the fourth century B.C. by Eudemus (ap. Simpl. PAys. 732 Diels, DK, 588 34). See p. 281, below.
1 86
Only
men and
family could
make
body and
now
now
a man's
In the extraordinary Pythagorean attitude to beans we have already seen an example of the way in which these tenets had their outcome in
mysterious embodiment of the universal life-spirit (and a evidently particularly close connexion with human life) which the Pythagoreans saw in this vegetable led to its prohibition as food. Still
practice.
The
more
must be the connexion between dogma and practice in their abstention from animal flesh, not only the most notorious, but also the most controversial of the commandments of Pythagoras. The chief
close
7 (D K, 1 4 9) Eudoxus in the seventh book of his Description of the Earth says that he [sc. Pythagoras] exhibited such purity and such abhorrence of killing and killers that he not only abstained
(a)
Eudoxus
ap. Porph.
F". P.
do with cooks or hunters. () Onesicritus ap. Strabo xv, 716 (DK, ibid.}. Onesicritus was a Cynic philosopher who accompanied Alexander to India, and is recounting his meeting with an Indian gymnosophist who questioned him about Greek doctrine. Onesicritus told him among other things that Pythagoras 'comto
manded men to abstain from animal food'. (c) The poets of the Middle Comedy of the
turies B.C. indulge in various jibes at the Pythagoreans of their time. that the suggest that these had taken a leaf out of the Cynics* book (or
Some
comic
poets chose to bait them by maliciously making the confusion), caring nothing for appearances but going about unwashed and in filthy rags. They include, however, digs at their vegetarianism, for example the obvious joke: 'The eat no living thing.' 'But Epicharides the Pythagorean eats
Pythagoreans or bread and dog!' 'Only after he has killed it.* 'They eat vegetables drink nothing but water' is the general verdict, though Aristophon might amuse himself by observing that some of the modern hangers-on of the sect, in spite of their professions, were ready enough to wolf down fish or meat if you set it before them. (The relevant fragments of Antiphanes, Alexis,
DK,
58s, vol.
i,
187
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
According to these heterogeneous sources the eating of animals was entirely against Pythagorean principles, whatever backsliding might
Others, among whom is cited Aristotle, suggest that religious abstention was certainly practised, but that it was limited to certain
occur.
species.
(d) Aristotle, Ross frr., p. 138 (ap. D.L. vin, 34, DK, 5803): 'Aristotle in his work on the Pythagoreans said that Pythagoras counselled abstention from. .white cocks because they are sacred to the lunar god or to
.
the month, and are suppliants [presumably because white was the colour worn by suppliants] sacred to the lunar god because they announce the hours. Moreover white is of the nature of good, black of evil. Also to
abstain
from any
tures should be assigned to gods and to men/ (e) Aristotle, Ross ibid. (D.L. vin, 33, DK, 5861 a):
.
achieved
by cleansing rites and. .abstaining from meat and flesh of animals that 9I have died, mullet, blacktail, eggs and oviparous animals, beans
(/) Iambi. y*P. 85 (DK, 5804) tells us that according to the Pythagorean acusmata only animals which it is proper to sacrifice may be eaten, because only into these does the soul of a man not enter. This
genuine Pythagorean reason than the incompatible explanation attributed to Aristotle that it was not right for men and gods to share the same creatures. (It does not follow that the actual prohibition of
like the
sounds more
which doubtless were not sacrificed eating sacred fish attributed to the Pythagoreans.)
(g) Porph.
is
not rightly
goras:
*Of
sacrificed animals
privy parts, marrow, feet or head.' Porphyry adds as the reason Pythagoras's symbolic interpretation of these parts. They signified for the animal respectively the foundation, genesis, growth, beginning and end. Together these are the leading parts (fjysjjioviai) of the body. He added that they must
abstain
from beans
'as
human
flesh*.
Finally we find in a few passages a determined attempt, which seems to go back to Aristoxenus, to deny altogether the existence of
the prohibition.
(fi)
DK,
1
Aulus Gellius in his Noctes Atticae, iv, n writes (partly quoted in 14.9): 'There is an old and erroneous, but strongly entrenched,
Aristotle,
but
it is
Ross renders
not quite clear that it does not belong ppcoTcov 'meat that has been nibbled*.
188
Prohibition
of Animal Food
belief that the philosopher Pythagoras habitually abstained from animal food, and also from beans, which the Greeks call KUCCUOI. This belief
made Callimachus
in his first
write: "I too bid you, as did Pythagoras, keep your Of the same opinion was Cicero, who
book On
tells
us to go to bed
in such a condition of
that there be nothing to induce wandering or disturbance of the mind. This is commonly thought to be the reason why the
body
Pythagoreans are forbidden to eat beans, which have a flatulent tendency inimical to the pursuit of mental tranquillity." So much for Cicero. But Aristoxenus the writer on music, an industrious student of ancient literature
and a pupil
in philosophy of Aristotle, in the work which he has left us on Pythagoras says that beans were Pythagoras's favourite vegetable on account of their purgative and relieving properties. [Here Gellius quotes the original
words of Aristoxenus.] The same Aristoxenus reports that he included young pigs and sucking kids in his diet, and he seems to have got his information from the Pythagorean Xenophilus who was his friend, as well as from older men who were nearer to the time of Pythagoras. Alexis the poet also
of animal food in his comedy The Lady Pythagorean. 1 The origin of the mistake about the eating of beans appears to be that in the poem of Empedocles, who followed the teaching of Pythagoras, there
treats
*
'
it
commonly
care and insight say that in this context it signifies testicles, which after the enigmatic and symbolic style of Pythagoras are called beans (xuapioi) because they bring about pregnancy (KUEIV) and are the source of human to dissuade men generative power. Thus Empedocles in this line is trying
not from eating beans but from sexual indulgence. 'Plutarch too, whose authority in the history of philosophy carries great that Aristotle said the weight, reports in the first of his books on Homer abstain from eating not did same about the Pythagoreans, namely that they
this is contrary to the animals, with the exception of a few kinds of flesh. As "Aristotle words: says that the general opinion, I append his actual and from sea-anemones and the the womb abstain from heart,
Pythagoreans
certain other similar creatures, but eat the rest.". . .However Plutarch in his After-dinner Questions says that the Pythagoreans also abstain from the fish called mullet.'
and
I,
p. 479),
this
189
kids and sucking pigs, with special avoidance of lambs. Aristoxenus on the other hand said that he allowed the eating of all other living creatures except the ploughing-ox and the ram/
that whereas other (/) Porph. y.P. 15 says of the athlete Eurymenes athletes kept to the traditional diet of cheese and figs, 'on the advice of
first
to strengthen his
body by
()
figs
on
Iambi. V.P. 25 claims that the substitution of a meat diet for dried the part of athletes was due to a namesake of Pythagoras, the son of
it is
wrongly
attributed to Pythagoras
son of Mne-
D.L. vm, 12: 'He [Pythagoras] is said to have been the first to train on meat, beginning with Eurymenes, as Favorinus says in the third Others say it was a trainer called Pythagoras book of his Commentaries. who used this diet, not our philosopher, who in fact forbade the killing, let alone the eating, of animals on the ground that they share with us the right
athletes
.
.
to a soul.'
be seen that none of these testimonies antedates the fourth century B.C., by which time the prohibition of flesh had already become
It will
a matter of doubt and controversy. They fall into three classes. First, those that affirm the prohibition of animal food without qualification,
like
poets. Secondly, those (among them Aristotle) who describe the prohibition as selective, certain species or parts of animals being forbidden
on
creatures mentioned
common enough
Examples are collected by Boehm in the work already referred to. Cocks for instance were forbidden to epileptics, who were supposed to be daemonically possessed, and Caesar notes that the British held it
are expressly linked
impious to eat them.The religious reasons adduced by the Pythagoreans by some of our authorities with their belief in
transmigration. Sacrifice was limited to certain animals, and these might be eaten because of a belief that the soul of a man never enters them.
that
Perhaps the same, or perhaps a different, school of Pythagoreans held even of sacrificial animals certain parts were to be avoided, in190
Prohibition
of Animal Food
eluding those, like testicles and marrow, which were particularly associated with the vital force.
Finally we have the categorical denial that Pythagoras imposed on his followers any ban at all on the eating of flesh or beans. The statements to this effect have a positive and polemical tone which suggests
that, as Gellius in fact says,
in this direction was evidently Aristoxenus. This man, a Western Greek from Tarentum, who became a member of the Lyceum under Aristotle and Theophrastus, was also a friend of the last generation of Pythagoreans. 1 Since his chief claim
received belief.
to
fame was
his
work on
was in
fact generally
known by
the distinguishing epithet of Musicus\ it was natural that interest in that school which gave music a
philosophy and was universally recognized as having been responsible for the most fundamental discoveries in musical theory. The friends to whom such a man attached himself would of
course belong to the most scholarly and intellectual wing of the school, little use for the old superstitions to which its more
devoutly religious members clung. By this time the school was split into a number of groups divided both locally and by the character of
their thought,
and since
all
of
Pythagoras for their teaching, the more philosophically-minded would which they reject the idea that he lent himself to superstitious practices
themselves had outgrown. In this connexion- may be mentioned the distinction drawn
writers between
by later
two types of Pythagorean, the acusmatici and the mathematicL Accounts of this are given by the Neoplatonists lamblichus and Porphyry as follows:
V*P. 81, 87 (also De Comm. Math. Sc. p. j6.i6S. Festa). been explaining that Pythagoras instituted various grades has lamblichus his according to their natural talents, so that the highest
(a) Iambi.
disciples
among
secrets
of his wisdom were only imparted to those capable of receiving them. Even the way of life was not the same for all: some he ordered to hold all their possessions in common, but there was an outer circle of those who
1 D.L. vm, 46. The Suda says that he was a pupil of the Pythagorean XenophHus before joining Aristotle. See this and other authorities for his life at the beginning of Wehrli's Anstoxenos.
191
of those who had part in it, the acusmatici and the mathematicL Of these the acusmatici are admitted to be Pythagoreans by the others, whereas
classes
they themselves do not accept the mathematics claiming that their activity 1 The philosophy does not originate from Pythagoras but from Hippasus.
.
of the acusmatici consists of undemonstrated sayings, without argument, enjoining certain courses of action. These and other dicta of Pythagoras they
endeavour to preserve as divine revelations, making no claim to say anything of their own. Indeed they hold it would be wrong to do so: those of their number are accounted the wisest who have learned the greatest number of
acusmata.*
() Porph. F".P. 37 (DK, 18 2) His teaching took two forms, and of his followers some were called mathematici and some acusmatici. The mathematici
.
were those who had mastered the deepest and most fully worked-out parts of his wisdom, and the acusmatici those who had only heard summarized precepts from the writings, without full explanation.*
The account reproduced by lamblichus implies a claim that the division was instituted by Pythagoras himself in order that justice
might be done to those of greater and lesser philosophical capacity. Probably Porphyry was relying on the same sources and meant to say
the same, although taken by itself his statement might imply no more than what was probably the truth. In view of the universal Pythagorean
practice of attributing everything to the founder, we cannot attach much historical value to the claim. What seems to be obviously true is
two forms', or
at least
had two
sides.
The
genius of Pythagoras must have possessed both a rational and a religious quality such as are rarely united in the same man. It is not surprising
his school attracted two different types, on the one hand for the promotion of mathematical philosophy and on the enthusiasts ' other religious devotees whose ideal was the Pythagorean way of
that
he and
life',
the
life
of a religious
its
of the Orphics
and justifying
practices
by a
The
philosophical wing inevitably neglected, or secretly despised, the simple superstitious faith of the devotees, but could not deny that it had played
by Pythagoras. These
therefore admitted
Sc.,
The translation follows the order of words in De Comm. Math. (DK, 18.2) in which acusmatici and mathematici are reversed.
192
'
the belief that both wings of the school had their origin in the teaching methods of the Master himself. That at least seems the most
probable explanation of the tradition, which serves an obvious apologetic purpose for the mathematici. The split is unlikely to have occurred before the second half of the fifth century, when it would be fostered
by
the geographical dispersion of the school. It may provide the Aristotle in his more of cautious moments explanation why speaks
'some Pythagoreans'
goreans as a whole.
Rohde noted
that the
physical doctrines which Aristotle reports as Pythagorean, as well as the ethical precepts of the friends of Aristoxenus, show no connexion
with Pythagorean religious beliefs. This point has some substance, though it must not be pressed too far. It was the physical and matheinterested in,
matical philosophy of the Pythagoreans that Aristotle happened to be and reference to its religious basis would have been out of
place in his purely philosophical discussions. The two in fact could never have been completely separated. Consider for example the reference to their numerical philosophy in such a passage as this from
theDe
the whole world and all things in it are summed up for in the number three; end, middle and beginning give the number of the is the triad. Hence we have taken this number from number and their whole,
it
were one of her laws, and make use of it even for the worship of
Nevertheless the thesis that there were two kinds of Pythagoreans, the
one
and
inherently probable
the other in preserving the religious foundations of the school, is both and supported by a certain amount of positive evidence,
been quoted concerning the views of Pythagoras reports that have just 1 on religious abstention from certain foods.
has been preserved, on Porphyry wrote a work in four books, which
Mus. 1871, With this paragraph cf. Delatte, Pol Pyth. 22f., tudes, 272-4, Rohde, to deprecate the assumption of a clear-cut 558-62, Minar, Early Pyth. Pol 31-3. Minar is right division between two hostile and mutually exclusive sects, but goes too far in belittling the scientific achievement of the mathematici.
1
RL
193
more
final
may be
conclusions on the subject. 1 assigned to the fourth or early third century B.C. Porphyry, who is of course arguing in favour of abstinence, begins by stating in full the
case of his opponents, of men* (6 iroAOs xcd
whom he describes as
'
the ordinary,
common run
5T}iacb8ri$ avOpcoiros). In their name he produces a string of arguments, ending with the claim (i, 15) that meat-eating does no harm to soul or body, as is proved by medical opinion and by
the fact that athletes eat meat to improve their condition. Immediately he continues: And as strong evidence that Pythagoras was wrong, we
*
may mention that no wise man believed him the eyes of the common man, the wrongness
.
of Pythagoras evidently
consisted in the prohibition of meat. In ch. 23 the same common man Pythagoras the eating of pork and beef was
equivalent to cannibalism, but in ch. 26 he supports his case by reference to the story that Pythagoras allowed, and even introduced, meat in the diet of athletes, and adds: 'Some report that the Pytha-
goreans themselves taste flesh when they sacrifice to the gods/ In n, 4, when Porphyry is arguing his own case, he rebukes his
opponents for assuming that because it is right for some men, like athletes, soldiers and manual workers, to eat meat, therefore it is
proper for philosophers. We may take it that in his view Pythagoras might indeed have approved of meat for someone who would never
a philosopher (cf. passage (y) on p. 190, above), but still forbade own school. The friends of Aristoxenus who rejected the ban will then have made their point by an illegitimate generalization. Later
it
make
to his
in the
1
same book
it
(ch. 28),
he says
Most of
Alst.
II,
EGP
95, n. 2,
and compare
especially
De
ToO
\tf\
5elv dOeiv
arlv TCOV 6eo<ppdorou TOUTCX. The Pythagorean irpooicEiiJi^vcov Kod cruvrgrirniifrcov, arguments adduced by Sotion for the same purpose (ap. Seneca, Ep. 108 (bk. xvm, 5), 17 ff.), which may be compared with Porphyry's, also appear to contain much early material. (Cf. Rostagni, Verio di P. i<S<5ff.)
3
is
So also Plut, Qu. Conv. 7290. The common source here Heraclides Ponticus (Burnet, loc. ciV.). 3 Porphyry uses the imperfect tense in speaking of them.
194
life:
he brings the taboo into explicit Since then all animals are our kin
the
relatives is rightly
relation
if it is clear that,
said,
man who
his
condemned as unholy/ Porphyry then, whether he is speaking in his own person or through
own
the
mouth of an imaginary
general Pythagoras forbade his followers to eat flesh, that his reason was the kinship of all life, and that as a result the Pythagoreans were life-long vegetarians except for a ritual mouthful on occasions of
sacrifice.
His account gives a clear hint of how, when a rationalist wing it claimed as authority for neglecting the bah a
story which, whether true or not, was never originally intended to grant a dispensation to philosophers, that is, to Pythagoreans. Taking all this in conjunction with the evidence previously discussed, and with
the primitive character of the demand itself, we may conclude that abstinence from flesh, on the religious ground that to eat it is a form of
cannibalism, was a tenet of Pythagoreanism from the beginning. sacramental tasting, on special occasions, of the flesh of the forbidden
animal
not an exception; rather it brings the system into line with universal primitive practice, as Burnet noted (EGP, 95).
is
the rationalists and the devotees tended to take separate roads, it was " to membership of the school. In
rto^
of Acragas reasoned
of souls a
own son
abstention
or his
To those whose minds run on these lines the soul is obviously someIt occupies place entirely thing of paramount importance. in the scheme of things from that which it has, for instance, in the
1
an
different
Emped.
Laws,
vi,
fr.
137
little later
Plato,
7820.
195
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
by
Homeric epics, which set the tone for so much in later Greek religion. For Pythagoras it was immortal (ot0dvcnro$), and this implied much more than mere survival. In Homer too the psyche survived after to his heroes-The/wycAe death, but that thought brought no consolation itself was the merest simulacrum of the man, lacking strength and
wits,
association with the body. It is to a twittering compared to a shadow, an image, a dream, to smoke, bat. The only thing that could give it a temporary return to something
both of which
it
owed
to
its
to absorb a draught of blood, that is, to be reanimated momentarily by renewed contact with the life-giving ele-
more
was
ments of the body. This was a natural creed for the men of a heroic age, who equated the goodness of life with bodily prowess in battle, feasting and love. The real self was the body. Death meant separation from the body,
life
in
fighters could
human
soul as immortal
was
blasphemy. Only the gods were immortal, and they were exceedingly would go ill with a mortal who jealous of their immortality. It claimed it for himself, for that would be to set himself up against
Zeus and the Olympians. We need not here consider in detail the powerful influence on later Greek thought of this conception of the relation
between men and gods. Herodotus, the tragedians, Pindar and others are full of the necessity to remember one's mortality and 'think mortal
thoughts'. 'Seek not to become Zeus are fittest' (Pindar, Isth. v, 14).
Homeric religion is a product of the Ionian spirit, and shares its matter-of-fact and rational outlook on the world. Indeed, while from
the religious point of view
its
all,
they are
probably outweighed by the immense service it did to the mind of Greece by ridding it of so much of the dark underworld of magic and
which plagued the life of many other ancient peoples. It was by no means out of tune with the rationalism of the Ionian tradition in philosophy. Similarly the Italian philosophical tradition is not somesuperstition
thing existing in intellectual isolation, but the philosophical expression of a much more general mode of thought. Side by side with the
Olympian
religion
which may be
called
196
official cults
of the Greek
states as well as
being
accepted
by most of the
men and
soul.
1
relationship
human
The
what
artificial
much
less
all, was particularly suited to the someand short-lived society for which it was intended, and so to the Greek of later centuries. Living a life ordinary
quite unlike that of the Homeric hero, he was subject to certain longings and stirrings of the heart from which the hero had been free. The idea
of capricious, all-too-human
with material
certainty that they
deities,
whom
gifts offered in
a bargaining
would make the expected return, began to seem less Victims of injustice in this world turned their satisfying. eyes to the
of finding redress in another. Moreover, to meet these the means were at hand in numerous popular and resurgent needs, ancient cults of an agrarian character which had only been thrown
possibility
into temporary eclipse by the dominance of Homeric ideas. The most notable was the mystery-cult of Eleusis, raised from obscurity to Panhellenic repute when its mother-town was Athens
incorporated
by
(probably towards the end of the seventh century) and its worship taken under Athenian patronage. By initiation into the mysteries of
their
wor-
shippers believed that they could be actually adopted into the family of the gods, and by this adoption secure for themselves not mere
survival
which in some
sense, as
we have
seen,
was the
lot
of every*
but a far better and happier fate in the life to come. Blessed among men who dwell on earth is he who has seen these things; but
one
he
lot
who
is
uninitiated
rites
when he has died and passed beneath the dank darkness/ 3 At Eleusis initiation was all that mattered. The participants returned
homes and
lived their ordinary lives, secure in the
to their
imparted by
1
fully in
3
can only be sketched very briefly here. I have dealt with it more The Greeks and their GoJs, where references to other literature will be found. Homeric Hymn to Demeter, 480 ff. From internal evidence we can say that this hymn was
by Athens.
myth concerning
and
earthly.
It
initiators went teaching of the Orphic writers and For them the hope of immortality was based on a complex the nature of the human soul as a mixture of divine
The
by
through life, to develop and elevate the divine element and subdue the but the rites must be periodicearthly. Initiation was an essential part, with observance of ally renewed and life as a whole lived differently,
ritual prohibitions
among which abstention from meat was, as with the of Pythagoreans, of the greatest importance. The whole religious side
movement, which included an elaborate cycle of rebirths, cannot be and to make the attempt separated from that adopted by Pythagoras, would probably be unhistorical. The Pythagoreans not only used the
this
books promulgated under the ancient name of Orpheus: prominent members of the school were named in later antiquity as the authors of some of them, and the tradition ascribing some to Pythagoras 1 himself goes back, as we have already noted, to the fifth century B.C.
religious
tilings
example of a type of belief that accompanied hundreds of more obscure agricultural cults all over Greece, and the elaborate eschatological
schemes of the Orphics
is
Owing to the religious foundations of their thought, they were even less isolated than other philosophers from the current beliefs of their
time.
To recognize the existence and interaction of the two great streams of philosophical tradition, the Ionian and the Italian, is of the
importance for an understanding of Presocratic philosophy: but it equally important to become aware that they stand in their own
first
is
Greek mind whose conflict and interplay form an essential and fascinating aspect of the study of Greek life and literature in general. These two strains in their turn find their explanation partly in the fusion of
races that
went
to
make up
the Greek people of historical times, and them there now would take
in the
words
OVT^TOC
9poveTv
hand and
P. 182, n. 2, above, and for the names of other Pythagoreans see Kern, Orph. Fr. p. 52. See The Greeks and their Gods, esp. pp. 301-4.
198
'Strive not,
my
soul, for
an immortal
61), whereas Empedocles the Sicilian, without the apparently slightest heed to such a warning, shouted to his fellow-citizens of Acragas; 'I tell you I am a god immortal, no longer
(fr. 112.4). to this second strain, to the idea of assimilation to the divine as
life,
a mortal'
It is
the force of a philosophical and allegiance, as well as a religious, genius. In this last clause lies the mathematical,
it
and he supported
with
all
is
where
it
transcends the
more
widespread idea of 'God shalt thou be instead of mortal' which preexisted and formed the soil out of which it sprang. Eleusis taught that to was be obtained immortality through the single revelation, after
suitable preparation, of the mystic objects or symbols; the Orphics added the need for carrying out in daily life an elaborate system of religious, possibly also moral, prohibitions; to Pythagoras the way of
salvation lay through philosophy. Aristoxenus2 said of Pythagoras and his followers: 'Every distinction they lay down as to what should be
conformity with the divine. This is their starting-point; their whole life is ordered with a view to following God, and it is the governing principle of their philosophy.'
at
This brief excursus into religious history was necessary, for in the idea of the purification of the soul we come near to the link which joins
the religious and the philosophical sides of Pythagoreanism and enables us to see them as two sides of a single unitary system. Hence to
system the first essential is to appreciate the religious of which it arose and against which it must be seen. out background
understand
this
1
Kaibel
The first sentiment, in the above or similar words, is frequent. Cf. e.g. Epicharmus, 263 (DK, 23 B 20, vol. i, p. 201) 0vccr& xp^l *r6v 6var6v, oCnc dedvorra TOV 6var6v 9poviTv and Soph.
Tr. 473. For the second phrase see Plato, Theaet. lytfA 816 KCCI ircipaoecxi xptj Sve^Ss IKEIOE 9&>ytv OTI Tdxiara. 9uyf| 8 6polcocris deep Kara TO Suvanr6v, and cfl the true statement of Arius Didymus (?) ap. Stob. Eel. Eth* II, 7, p. 49 Wachsm. : ZcoKpcfrrns TTAdrcov TCCUT& TC|> TTvBoydpqc,
T&OS
2
djjiotcoaiv
0co.
Ap. Iambi. V.P. 137, DK, 5802. The translation is Cornford*s (C<2, 1922, 142), except for the word 6noAoyfccs. Cornford prints 6inAta$. So Nauck, but this is due to Scaliger: dpoAoyfos is in all MSS. If it is the true reading, it raises a suspicion that the sentence as it stands is not a word-for-word quotation from Aristoxenus, for 6noAoyta in the particular sense required became Aristosomething of a technical term of the Stoics. Wehrli does not include the passage in his xenos. Nevertheless it gives a true description of the Pythagoreans of all periods.
199
Basic
is
same time under the necessity of opposing the extreme view that even vegetables should be avoided, since logically they were included within its scope. 1 For Empedocles everything had a share of
self at the
10 . 10), and even the universe as a whole was in the 2 eyes of the Pythagoreans a living and breathing creature. The Pythagorean Ecphantus (if we may trust an amended text) described the
consciousness
(fr. 1
world as a form
(iSscc)
book of his
lost
work On
the
Philosophy of Pythagoras, he probably attributed it to Pythagoras himself, and since the belief was already abroad in the sixth century we may
safely
1
do the same. In
this respect
differ
The
ouyyiveicc
logical difficulty is obvious, once the attempt is made, as Pythagoras made it, to fit the of all nature into the framework of a philosophical system. The distinction between
things that have life only (scorj) and those that have HAJ^ (p. 202, below) suggests that the Pythagoreans were conscious of it The feeling that animal, but not vegetable food must be avoided at
its
ultimate explanation in the ancient and deeply-rooted horror of the by bloodshed, which the Pythagoreans inherited from un-
philosophical predecessors. Empedocles, like Pythagoras, made a conscious effort to justify this revulsion on philosophical grounds, but an earlier age is evoked by his agonized cry (fr. 139):
oliioi,
Sn
oO
irp6<70ev p
8icbAe<7E
vrjAfifcs Tjiiocp
popoj
Empedocles does indeed also issue a command to "keep off bay-leaves' (fr. 140: although the words are quoted in Plutarch simply in a context of picking leaves off the plants, I presume that Empedocles had consumption in mind as in the similarly-worded injunction about beans, fr. 141) ; but the bay, Apollo's sacred plant, occupied a rather special position. In fr. 127 he pairs it with the lion, king of plants as the Hon is king of beasts. Each forms the best lodging in its kind for
a
human souL
3
For the universe as breathing, AT. Phys. 21 3 b 22 and in a fragment of the De Philos. Pythagorae (DK, 58330; see p. 277, below). Cf. Sext. Emp. Math, ix, 127 of \&v o\5v -rrepi r6v TTu6ay6pav Kai Tdv 'EjnreBokXfe Kal TGOV 'iTaXcov Tt\fie6$ 9001 nfj p6vov fjjilv irp6s dXX^Aous tccd TTpos ToOs $oO$ clvod Tivcc xoivcoviocv, dAA<*t xod Trp6s TOE fiAoyoc T&Sv jcpcov. 2v y&p OrrApxeiv -irvaJ^a t6 616: TTOVTOS TOU K6cniou KEivoc. Similarly Cicero Sifjicov ^vOC^S TpdTrov, TO ml fcvouv f|n&s TTp<5$
1922, 140, n. 2), in saying that this passage, though employing later terms, is substantially true, follows Delatte, Vie de Pyth. 204: *I1 faut bien admettre que c'est la une
doctrine de Fancien Pythagorisme/ 3 DK, 5 1 . i See their apparatus and pp. 324^ below. The MS. reading is obviously corrupt. The date of Ecphantus is uncertain, but at the latest he was a contemporary of Archytas (ZN, i , 604, n.
.
5)
200
from the
Milesians,
who
as
we saw assumed
as a sufficient explanation
of the original generative motion that the stuff of the world was instinct with life. Anaximenes even accepted the corollary that the air which
constitutes the human soul is the same substance as that of the god which we must suppose the universe to be. But, so far as we can tell, he treated it in the Ionian way, as an interesting scientific fact. He certainly did not regard it as the basis of a religious way of life. We know 1 both how
universal
air,
was the early belief that the soul was of the nature of breath or and also what widely different conclusions could be drawn from the
according as one's inclinations were towards a scientific or a religious conception of the world. Democritus combined it with what
fact,
was
that
for practical purposes a materialistic atheism, but the Orphics subscribed to it no less. The concluis, a mystical religious sect
sion drawn both by them and by the Pythagoreans was that if the world was a living, eternal and divine creature, and lived by breathing in air or breath from the infinite around it; 2 and if man too got his life by breathing (which was evidence that the human soul itself was air);
and macrocosm, must be close. divine. Men were many and divided, and they were mortal. But the essential part of man, his soul, was not mortal, and it owed its immorthis circumstance, that it was neither more nor less than a small tality to
fragment or spark of the divine and universal soul, cut off and imprisoned in a perishable body. Diogenes Laertius quotes an account of
man and the universe, microcosm The universe was one, eternal and
Pythagoreanism which Alexander, a contemporary of Sulla surnamed Polyhistor on account of his encyclopaedic activities, claimed to have
this
account
it is said,
Pp. 128 ff., above. * See pp. 277 ff., below. E. Frank held that Aristotle learned of this Pythagorean* doctrine from 'Philolaus', both in inverted commas because he believed this pseudo-Philolaus to have been a Platonist, probably Speusippus. For his present point he refers to the citation of Philoa
laus*s
views in Anon. Londinensis (DK, 44x27), although in fact that passage only speaks of ordinary animal life and to make his point he has to add on his own account: 'Nun ist aber fur Philolaos der Mikrokosmos ein treues Abbild der Weltganzen* (Plato it. d. sogenn. Pyth. 327-8). It will not be expedient to refer at every turn to the extreme sceptical views expressed in Frank's
book, and this may serve as an example. 3 D.L. viii, 24ff. The part quoted here is from ch. 28. Alexander seems to have been an industrious and unoriginal collector of facts, free from the fantasy that characterized the later The nv6ccyopiK& Cnrojivfincnra which 9 1, 1449-52.) Neopythagoreans and Neoplatonists. (See
2OI
It is
life,
and
it is
immortal
is
immortal.
was homogenes not only united way men in the ties of kinship with animals, but, most important of all, it taught them that their best nature was identical with something higher.
the doctrine that
off the gave them an aim in life, namely to cultivate the soul, shake individual taint of the body, and rejoin the universal soul of which their
It
souls were in essence parts. So long as the soul was condemned to remain in the wheel of transmigration so long, that is to say, as it had to enter a
it
had previously tenanted so long was it still impure. By living the best and highest type of human life it might ultimately shake off the
to be citing recall the CnroiiVTjticrra KE9a\ccici>5T] handed down by the last generation of Pythagoreans in the fourth century B.C. (p. 180, above). However, the date or dates of the contents of these chapters have been variously estimated by scholars. Rohde (JRh. Mus. 1872, 47) remarked on their relatively modest content, as indicating an early date. Zeller (ZN, 471 and n. i) treated Alexander's account with some respect, but attributed his source to the second century and considered it an heir to Platonic and Stoic teaching. M. Wellmann (Hermes, 1919, 225-48), though not always sufficiently critical in his use of late sources for comparison, argued persuasively for its fourth-century origin, as also did Delatte {V. de P. I98ff., 232!?.), and they were followed by Cornford (P. and P. 3). Diels was converted by Wellmann, whose arguments nevertheless appeared to Wilamowitz (Platon, n, 84, n. i) to be *ganz verfehlt*, though he says
he claims
no more.
I. Levy (Sources de la Legende de Pyth* 75) also thinks the third century the earliest possible date. But see also Raven, Pyth. and El. 159-64. An exhaustive analysis of the extract has been made by A. J. Festugiere in RJ5G, 1945, 165. It may be difficult to deny his conclusion that the immediate source is a Hellenistic compilation
collected can
incorporating elements of diverse dates, but his further argument, that none of the doctrines so have antedated Speusippus, does not seem so inescapable. One misses also any
suggested explanation of the title TTufrxyopiKd \rno\ivr\\urta. According to Clement of Alexandria, Alexander also wrote a work rapl TTvtfoyopiKcov ouup6Xoov (RE, i, 1451). To give an example of the differing conclusions which may be drawn from the same material, Cornford adduced in favour of an early date that *no later writer could have escaped the influence of Plato himself and in particular of the Timaeus*. For Festugiere the extract displays an arrangement of material of which Torigine est incontestablement le Timie*. (Cornford attributes
dyad* for the Pythagorean 'unlimited* Cornford, saw elements in the account which would be 'certainly impossible in any philosophy influenced by Platonic thought', and concluded that even though some of its parts show the influence of later philosophical terminology, it contains elements of genuine early Pythagorean doctrine. (CP, 1946, 34.) With this judicious conclusion
to Alexander himself.)
EL von
Fritz, like
agree.
dordcnracrpia occurs in Plato (PAaee/o, 1136), but its use to describe the relation of individual souls to the Universe seems to have been Stoic. Cf. Chrysippus ap. D.L. vii, 143,
Hie word
by
Epictetus, n, 8, 10, M. Aurel. v, 27. Nevertheless the doctrine concerned, like the Stoics, did not originate with them.
many others
held
2O2
body
bliss
its
altogether, escape from the wheel of rebirth, and attain the final of losing itself in the universal, eternal and divine soul to which by own nature it belonged. 1 The conception of god or divinity, as so
far
adumbrated,
that, in so far as
may seem decidedly vague, and it must be admitted we rely on any trustworthy sources for the Pytha-
2 goreanism of Plato's time or earlier, it must remain so. The Pythagoreans certainly did not reject the contemporary polytheism, and their
particular patron was Apollo, to Pythagoras was believed to stand in a special relation. Some at least revered him as an actual
whom
incarnation of this
god
9
of the divine, however, by no means ruled out at this stage the conception of 'the divine (TO 0sTov) in general, a conception which had
its
of the universe) and to the mystic, whose deeper longings it satisfied. 3 What exactly the Pythagoreans meant by the soul, and how they
reconciled
its
immortality with certain presuppositions about its also a difficult problem, which is best left until after an
it is
intimately
bound up.4
That then is the situation. Each of us is shut up in his separate body and marked with the impurity of the lower forms of matter. How are we to shake this off and bring the moment nearer when our own small
part will reunite with the whole and we shall be god ourselves? What is the way of salvation? Eleusis offered it by way of the revelation,
epopteia, granted to the initiate after suitable preparatory purification.
The Orphic sought it through some form of sacramental orgia or teletai and the observance of taboos. Pythagoras retained much of this, but because he was a philosopher he added a method of his own.
As positive evidence that this was a Pythagorean belief we have so far seen only the statement of Alexander Polyhistor that the soul was an dir6aTraapiacxt0lpos. He also says that all within the uppermost air is divine (ch. 27) and that pure souls go ni T&V uyiorov (ch. 31). Add that Delatte (Vie de Pyth. 225 ff.) shows it to have been a belief at least of later Pythagoreanism, that it was already common in the fifth century, and that there is reason to think it was adopted by the Orphics. See Guthrie, The Greeks and their Gods, 262 , 324.
Cf. ZN, 565-6. Similarly (and doubtless under Pythagorean influence) Ernpedocles gave the name Apollo to his highest god, to whom he explicitly denies all anthropomorphic features. See fr. 134, with
3
1
203
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
sophic
There are good grounds for thinking that Pythagoras Introduced and made familiar a new meaning of the words philosophos and philoHeraclides Ponticus (referred to on p. 164, told The
story
by
*
actual inventor
first
of the words.
As given by
of Phlius, as Heraclides Sicyon with Leon the tyrant of that city or Muliere De his in Ponticus relates Exanmi; for, he said, no one is 'wise
save
God/
This
early,
used quite
probably not strictly true, in what one might call an Ionian rather than an Italian
is
words
are
sense, although
attribution.
just possibly
support the
into a great
Heraclitus (fr. 35) said: Philosophers must be inquirers number of things/ This may indicate that the word was in
personally at Pythagoras, 'the for polymathy, or inquiry into many things, was in the eyes of Heraclitus folly, and elsewhere (fr. 40, quoted above, p. 157) he censures name for indulging in it. 1 Zeno the Eleatic is also said
may on the other hand be aimed man who called himself philosopher';
it
Pythagoras by
to have written a
which almost certainly means the Pythagoreans. On the other hand Herodotus already uses the word in what I have called the Ionian' sense, without any of its
Philosophers^
*
as travelling
about
to
see the
information of
all
sorts
(i,
(EGP,
83):
On the 'In Ionia philosophic, meant something like "curiosity" other hand, wherever we can trace the influence of Pythagoras, the
word
has a far deeper meaning. Philosophy
ideal as stated
is itself
We
by Aristoxenus. Philosophy in this sense Pythagorean is the Plato's of Phaedo, where Pythagorean influence is subject-matter obviously strong and seems to be acknowledged by the references to
Philolaus. *I
1
my
Kirk (HCF, 395) agrees that this is a possibility. Wilamowitz thought that the word 9iAoa<$9ovs was not a part of the actual fragment of Heraclitus, but both Bywater and Diels-Kranz reasonably retain it. See note ad loc. in DK, and cf. Cornford, Princ, Sap. 115, J. L. Stocks,
Mind., 1915, 220.
5
On fr.
Stocks,
loc. at.
Philosophia
thinking that the
and
the
Idea of Limit
life
man who
to philosophia
is
of good courage when death approaches, and strong in hope that the greatest of good things will fall to his lot on the other side when he dies/
For Pythagoras then the purification and salvation of the soul depended not merely, as in the mystery-cults, on initiation and ritual purity, but on philosophia; and this word, then as now, meant using the
powers of reason and observation in order to gain understanding. In what way, we may ask, was the connexion established? Does the
philosophical side of Pythagorean teaching link up with the religious beliefs of which we have seen something already?
Pythagorean religious beliefs were founded on the world-wide and primitive idea of universal kinship or sympathy. The more philosophical side of the system rests on something which belongs particularly to the Hellenic outlook and is typified in the character of the most Hellenic of the gods, Apollo, to whose worship the sect was devoted. That is, the exaltation of the related ideas of limit, moderation,
It was not accidental that they chose as their divine patron on whose temple were inscribed the words Nothing too much', 'Observe limit', and other precepts in the same sense. The Greek
and order.
the god
genius, in thought and art, represents the triumph of A6yo$ or ratio, which has been defined as meaning on the one hand 'the intelligible,
determinate, mensurable, as opposed to the fantastic, vague and shapeless', and on the other 'the proportions of things both in themselves
and
as related to a whole'.
Of this genius
and
insisting
mensurable
characteristics,
with one another, the Pythagorean philosophy provides the outstanding example. Their philosophico-religious synthesis was, however, in one respect audacious. From their insistence on the cosmic significance of limit and order they
both in
and in
their relations
did not infer the same consequences for human life and aspirations as did the popular thought and the poets of their day. Dominant in the literature of the sixth and fifth centuries is the idea already referred to,
E. Fraenkel, Rome and Greek Culture (Inaugural lecture, Oxford, 1935). I may be forgiven for quoting such an aptly worded description of the Greek genius, although in the context Professor Fraenkel is in fact attributing these qualities of ratio to the Romans, to explain their
success as the preservers of Greek thought.
1
205
and content himself with a mortal's life. Between mortals and to immortals, gods and men, a barrier was fixed, and it was hybris and and the cross it. Nothing too much, observe limit; immortality limit appointed for man. This the were divinity unquestionably beyond as also the fact that by the prevailing view has already been noted, sixth century there existed a mystical movement which denied it. That
movement was
plates
Western Greeks.
To
the
evidence already mentioned we may add those verses which, scratched of gold, were buried with the initiates of a mystic sect in on thin
instructions the dead man graves of Magna Graecia. Here among other to the is told that if he can guardians of the nether prove his credentials
world, they will welcome him with the cry: Happy and blessed one, thou shah be god instead of mortal.' To attain this goal he had lived
a
life
who made
persuasion was Pythagoras, with of of mortal his denial the propriety thoughts for mortal men. Assimilation to God was for him, as we have seen, the goal of life. At the same
time, unlike the Orphics and their kind, he and his followers united with these aspirations a philosophy rooted in the twin ideas of limit and
order, peras
if at all, that
Of this
and kosmos.
It is
we
philosophic ideas.
This bridge was constructed by the following train of thought: that untranslatable world which unites, as (a) the world is a kosmos
perhaps only the Greek spirit could, the notion of order, arrangement or structural perfection with that of beauty. ($) All nature is akin,
therefore the soul of man
universe, (c) Like
is
is
known by like,
intimately related to the living and divine that is, the better one knows some-
thing the more one is assimilated to it. Hence (d) to seek through philosophy for a better understanding of the structure of the divine
1 The gold plates have been many times discussed. See Guthrie, Orpheus and GL ReL 171 ff. The oldest may be dated to the fourth century, and the poems from which they contain extracts
206
state
this
of our knowledge of early Pythagoreanism is such that part of evidence must be indirect, that is, taken either from contemporary
sympathy with them, or one whom they exercised a powerful influence. Yet he would be a hardened sceptic who would deny its total weight. Limit (peras) and the Unlimited (apeirori) were, as will appear more
philosophers like Plato on
to be in
240 ff., below), set by the Pythagoreans at the very beginof things as the two contrasting principles by which the world ning evolved; and of them they saw peras as good and apeiron as evil.
fully later (pp.
To
( 1 1 06
b 29)
It
'
:
this, Aristotle says in the Ethics Evil belongs to the unlimited, as the Pythagoreans surmised,
limited.'
is
living
of these because
it is
component
parts. Full
and efficient
their parts
depends on organization.
call
we (like Aristotle)
arranged and subordinated as instruments (prgand) towards the end of keeping the whole being alive and enabling it to perform its functions. So with the world. Were it unlimited, it would have no telos^ would be
ateles
teleion,
'endless'
but the major cosmic events are marked by their regular order. Dawn and sunset, summer, winter and the intermediate seasons follow one another in unvarying
this
view. There
may
be minor
irregularities,
succession.
larity
was provided by
perfect example of this eternal reguthe wheeling stars, which exhibited (as was
down
to,
and including,
One can Copernicus) an everlasting and perfectly circular motion. see the reason for the paramount position assigned by the Pythagoreans
to
astronomy among the sciences. In short die world is in the full sense a kosmos, and we may allow ourselves to note a statement about Pythagoras which, whether literally true or not, is a significant pointer to doctrines which were regarded as
1
What is
dreAls is Srreipov,
cf.
207
he was
traditionally
to apply the
it
name kosmos to
1
which
displayed. The idea of the kinship of all nature has been sufficiently
shown to be
and the Pythagorean and to underlie the doctrine of transmigration in Empedocles.* prohibition of animal flesh. It recurs in these connexions
TCOV oXcov irepioxfiv Koauov k T% v aurcp II, i, i (DK, 14,21) IT. irpcoTOS rf>v6naae tfjv See also D.L. vm, 48 (from Favorinus). Other references in Delatte, Vie de. P. that KOCTUOS 203. The attribution has been contested by some modern scholars on the ground * with the meaning world* did not come into use until very much later. Our knowledge of the actual language used by Presocratic philosophers is terribly meagre, but the position may be
1
Act.
T&^ecos.
summarized
thus.
Whether or not Anaximander used the word K6ajios (cf. p. 1 10, above), it was already being used by philosophers to mean the world (of course in its aspect as an ordered structure) in the
2va Kdauov), it early fifth century. In Empedocles fr. 26.5 (dAAore p^v 9iAoTTyn ouvepxousv" ei$ means only 'order' or 'arrangeclearly, as Mr Kirk says in his discussion of the term (HCF, 313),
ment*, but when in fr. 134 . 5 he speaks of the divine mind as 9povrtcn KOCTHOV onrccvrac Korrafaaouaa eojjow, he must mean that it darts through the whole world. The choice of word is still significant: it emphasizes that the world is an ordered structure; but even much later, no Greek could
have described the world by this term without having somewhere in his mind the consciousness that it exemplified the combination of order, fitness and beauty. These associations K6auo$ never lost. Of K6ovov TovSe in Heracl. fr. 30 Kirk's own conclusion is (ibid. 316, 317) that it means 'things plus order*, that is, 'the natural world and the order in it*. "The natural world* is also the plain meaning in Diog. Apoll. fr. 2 Tctlv Tc55e Tcp xoaiicp 6vra vOv, and (as Vlastos seems to me to have shown, AJP, 1955, 345) in Anaxag. fr. 8. Kirk points out that 'the parallel between man and cosmos is first explicitly drawn in the fifth century*, and even if we reject the word itself in Anaximenes, fr. 2 (and I for one should be prepared to maintain that the comparison between man and the world at least is his : pp. 1 3 1 f., above), the phrase quoted from Democritus (fr. 34 Iv T$ dvepcbmo uixpq? x6an9 6vn KOTCC A-npixpiTOv), which seems genuine, shows that K6o|io$ = 'world-order* was by his time a familiar notion. The development of the word through the stages (a) order or arrangement of anything, (f) order in the world, 6 TOU TTOCVTOS K6apo$, as used for example in Emped. 26. 5, Eur. fr. 910, (c) the world as an order (Emped. fr. 134. 5), (</) the world in general, with no special reference to its ordered structure, must have been a gradual one; the new shades of meaning came into use beside the older without replacing them. Once the step had been taken from (a) to (), there is
little
point in trying to pin down further developments to any particular date or person. The decisive moment came when the world was first seen to exhibit a rationally comprehensible order,
and as such Anaximander had already described it before Pythagoras, though the latter greatly developed and enriched the conception. This first step constituted, in Jaeger's words, 'the spiritual discovery of the cosmos*, and, as he rightly says, it entailed a radical break with current
religious beliefs. (PeaJem, 1, 1 58 f.) It is hardly too much to say that it marked the dividing line between religion and philosophy. It would certainly not be surprising if the discoverers themselves added emphasis to the new truth by actually giving the name KO<JUO$ to the world. Tradition ascribes this linguistic advance to Pythagoras, and we know that it was made by Empedocles, who followed him in so many things and at no great distance of time. For discussions of this point, with further examples and references to earlier scholars, see especially W. Kranz, PhUokgus^ 1938-9, 43off.; Kirk, HCF, 313^5 G. Vlastos, AJP, 1955, 345 f. with n. 19.
3
The
sufficiently clear. It is
reason for so frequendy calling in the witness of Empedocles may not have been made twofold : (a) the religious ideas of Empedocles are demonstrably almost
208
The words 'since all nature is akin' occur in Plato in the exposition of a religious doctrine for which he is careful to disclaim originality, ascribing it to 'priests and priestesses whose concern it is to give a reasoned account of their undertakings' (Meno, 8ic and A). This idea
and the conception of the world as a fcosmos occur together in a most instructive passage, where again they are ascribed to others, and who should these others be but the Pythagoreans? The wise men tell us
*
heaven and earth, gods and men are bound together by kinship love and and orderliness and temperance and justice; and for this reason, friend, they give to the whole the name ofkosmos, not a name immy
that
all
me
to
pay no attention
to this,
powerful influence of geometrical equality among gods and men' X (Gorg. 507 E). The association of man not only with the lower forms of
life
is
expressed in the
Pythagorean documents quoted by Alexander (p. 202, above), which find some support in Aristotle (DK, 58330), and the potential divinity
of
man
That
is
also
emphasized by Empedocles.
like is
known by
like
was held
even physiological) doctrine in the fifth century, exemplified by Empedocles's theory of 'effluences' from sensa fitting into 'pores' in the
body of the
On
'
is
described
by
Plato in the
Meno
(76 A).
With
earth
we
see earth,
he wrote in an extant fragment (109): with water water.' It follows that if we have
knowledge of the divine, it cannot be in virtue of any sense-organ the (fr. 133) composed of the lower material elements that circulate in
sublunary sphere; it must mean that we have in ourselves a tincture of the divine element by some equated with pure fire or with aither
with those of the Pythagoreans, () his date is a sufficient answer to those who suspect quote, as we so often must, fourth-century sources for Pythagorean beliefs, they may be referring to beliefs which only entered Pythagoreanism at that time (e.g. as a reflexion tradition going back to Timaeus in the fourth century B.C. and Neanthes in of Platonism). the third (D.L. vm, 54-5) said that Empedocles was a Pythagorean who was accused by the
identical
that
when we
School of appropriating and making public their doctrines. 1 Aristotle (if we may take the Magna Moralia to represent his views) had little use for this * mixture of morals with mathematics (MM> uSiaii): Pythagoras also attempted to treat of virtues to numbers he rendered his investigation for the but referring by virtue, misguidedly, irrelevant to its subject: justice is not a square number.' This passage confirms, if any further
confirmation were needed, that the 0090! of Plato are in fact the Pythagoreans.
209
Pythagoras and
which enters our world from
the
Pythagoreans
outside. This is the physical aspect of the doctrine of Pythagoras that, since God alone is wise, the philosophos or seeker after wisdom is developing the god-like in himself, and gives further content to Aristoxenus's statement about the Pythagoreans
(p.
their
whole
life
conformity with the divine, and and philosophy ordered and governed with a view
aim
is
who
us
by
unites the philosopher to the divine (that is, breathing Whole) is the element of kosmos in both.
what
In the Republic he writes of the philosopher 'who has his mind fixed on
true reality' (5000): 'Contemplating things and immutable, which neither do nor suffer
wrong but
are
all
in order
by
become
assimilated to them.
Do you
not think
it
it
inevitable
come
which
delights
is associate? Hence the philosopher through association divine and orderly (kosmios) becomes divine and orderly (kosmios) in so far as a man may/
to
For Plato the objects of the philosopher's contemplation are the ' transcendent Forms at which he had arrived by bringing Pythagorean
'
notions to bear upon the Socratic search for moral certainty, but the framework into which he fitted this new content of knowledge is
its
level,
that is, the movements of the regular and ordered aspects heavenly bodies will have the same effect of emphasizing our kinship
sophy
possible, for
By giving us sight, he says, the gods have made philoit was given us 'in order that we might observe the
of intelligence in die heaven and profit by them for the revolutions of our own thought, which are akin to them, though ours be troubled and they are unperturbed; and that, by learning to know them
circuits
to
compute them
revolutions of the
3
.
god and
Comford.
2IO
and
the Philosopher
A. E. Taylor held the view that throughout this dialogue Plato was doing no more than reproduce a fifth-century Pythagorean account of the world. Few would go all the way with him in this, but we have seen enough to give assent to the following sentences from his
commentary
(p. 133):
in Plato's
oral teaching, is common enough in the dialogues and seems to have been as characteristic of both Socrates and Plato as it was of the Pythagoreans. It is
the foundation of the whole scheme for training the souls of the young 'guardians' of Republic n-m into moral beauty by surrounding them with
the loveliness which appeals to eye and ear. The main principle of this 'early education *, that the soul inevitably grows like, takes on the character of, that
which
it
contemplates,
is
manifestly Pythagorean.
is it
when
it
and becomes a question of the philosopher growing like the divine object of the most worth-while contemplation of all. We may recall
the Pythagorean comparison of life to a festival or fair, at which some are present to take part in athletic or musical contests, others to buy or
sell,
'but the best as spectators*. 1 So in life, slavish natures strive for money or glory, but the philosopher seeks the truth. He seeks it with
a definite aim. Just as the universe
is
composed of material elements reduced to an ordered structure because they are pervaded by a divine life and reason, so we are kosmoi in miniature, organic structures comof the same stuff and the same posed reproducing principles of order. But we shall only reproduce them satisfactorily, so far as in a mortal body one may, if we cultivate the freedom of the divine element of reason of which we too possess a spark, and, by studying the order displayed on a grand scale around us, learn to reflect it in the motions of our own lives. The philosopher who contemplates the kosmos becomes
kosmios in his
own
soul.
The simile of spectators at a festival might seem to suggest that the Pythagoreans adopted a purely passive attitude to the world.
(Cf. also p. 164, above.) Cf. Bertrand Russell, The Problems of Philosophy (H.U.L. 1912), p. 250: philosophy is to be studied 'above all because, through the greatness of the universe which philosophy contemplates, the mind also is rendered
ot 61
tecrrcd,
1
ys plX-noroi ?pxoVTca
D.L. vni,
8.
great,
and becomes capable of that union with the universe which constitutes its highest good*.
211
(a) It
meant
music and particularly in the fields of number-theory, geometry, will bring understanding of astronomy, for those are the studies which
the ordered and lasting movements taking place in the heavens, and of the structure of everything which they contain. ($) It involved an
actual change in the philosopher's own nature, for it is by this active the divine contemplation (Oscopioc) that the aim of assimilation to
(ouolcoms Oeco)
is
attained.
(2)
was not an object suitable for experinot an object at all. It was alive was ment, analysis, exploitation. with certain mysterious and powerful forces, and man's life still possessed a richness and a dignity which came from his sense of participation in the movement of these forces. 1
natural world
It
the above quotation comes is a study of some modern Greek poets, and the passage refers directly to the Greek peasant of Turkish times, from whom the author is claiming that his poets, and Sikelianos in particular, inherited a living tradition. Else-
it
and in
description of the Pythagoreans. It might be thought more appropriate to the previous section of our discussion, but it stands here for
was made
to remind us of a characteristic of their philosophy which to a great extent persisted even in their work on number and mathematics, but which in dealing with this aspect it would be easier to forget.
It is
a dark and
difficult subject,
make
clear,
is
and some general remarks are necesand to some extent justify, the policy
that the Pythagoreans
we
shall pursue.
There
no doubt
were
responsible for important advances in the science of mathematics. Nevertheless, as the above quotation was intended to hint and as
has, I hope,
1
clear
212
was utterly different from that of a mathematician of today. For them numbers had, and retained, a mystical significance, an inde-
pendent reality. Phenomena, though they professed to explain them, were secondary, for the only significant thing about phenomena was the way in which they reflected number. Number was responsible
*
harmony', the divine principle that governed the structure of the whole world. Numbers not only explained the physical world, but also
for
symbolized or stood for (but the Pythagoreans said 'were') moral qualities and other abstractions. It was no hard-headed mathematician
who
number four (on the grounds that and justice essentially reciprocity reciprocity was embodied in a 1 square number), and marriage five, and Aristotle had some reason for his complaint (Metaph. 986 a 3): 'Any agreements that they found
declared that justice 'was
the
was
between number and harmony on the one hand, and on the other the changes and divisions of the universe and the whole order of nature,
insisted
these they collected and applied; and if something was missing, they on making their system coherent/ There follows his complaint
that they invented a non-existent planet to make up the total to the sacred number ten. Again in De Caelo y 293 a 25: they invented the counter-earth 'not seeking accounts and reasons to explain the
phenomena, but forcing the phenomena and trying to fit them into arguments and opinions of their own Such an attitude to science is no
5
.
more than
the solemn and religious tone with which he sometimes speaks of mathematics, and the fact that they have for him a metaphysical as well as a purely mathematical
No
to be struck
by
significance.
Arithmetic
it
anyone to
offer
never allowing draws the soul upwards, for discussion mere collections of visible or tangible
.
'
not subject to change and decay , and it tends to draw the soul towards truth and to produce a philosophic intelligence for the directing upwards of faculties which we wrongly turn earthwards (52yB). As to
5
abstractions with
numbers
last
MM,
below.
ii82an
(all
in
DK,
see Arist. Metaph. 98 5 b 29, 1078 b 21, compare EN, ii32b 23. Cf. pp. 301 ff.,
213
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
astronomy, which is to be studied purely as a branch of mathematics 'in terms of pure numbers and perfect figures. .perceptible to reason
.
and thought but not visible to the eye' (5290), it too must turn the not literally to the sky, but to the realm of 'real soul's gaze upwards
being and the
paedeutic
is
goreans
(whom
next study in the philosopher's proPlato's only criticism of the Pythahere harmonics, and he mentions name) is that they are too much ininvisible'.
The
by
plainly Pythagorean, is a legacy from the same physical view of mathematics here displayed nor could it well be doubted that much of school. No one doubts
arithmetic, geometry, astronomy, harmonics and we need not be afraid to say that the meta-
the doctrine of the Timaeus, which Plato puts into the mouth not of Socrates but of a visitor from Locri in South Italy, is Pythagorean. In this dialogue a 'harmony' made up of series in arithmetical and
harmonic progressions is used in the creation of the soul of the world (35sff.), and the existence of two mean proportionals between two
cubic numbers serves as the reason
fire
may justly be
used to
illustrate
Pythagoreans, for whom, as for Plato, the acquisition of knowledge partook more of the character of a religious initiation than of mere
1 instruction or research.
Our primary
must always be
more
scientific side
of Pythagoreanism
Aristotle, the best qualified, and for most of it the earliest informant. In his extant works he mentions the school only in
own
sequences which, though they have sometimes been exaggerated, must be taken into account: but whatever he says was based on a special
fruit in a treatise
lost,
and we have only a few quotations from background may legitimately add to our confidence that in dealing with the Pythagoreans he knew what he was
That treatise is
it,
but
its
existence in the
B. L. van der Waerden, *Die Arithm. d. Pyth.", Math. Annalen, 120 (1947-9), 680 ff., Heath, Thirteen Bks. ofEucl. n, 294. Even Comford, who so strongly opposed Taylor's theory that the entire Timaeus was a document of fifth-century Pythagoreanism, wrote that much of the
doctrine
no doubt
is
3).
214
Aristotle
1 talking about. It should be added that the quotations that we have are sufficient to refute the suggestion, based on the extant works, that
it
was purely a
scientific
system.
Moreover, while the different generations of pre-Platonic Pythagoreans may prove almost impossible to separate, we must do all we can to distinguish between Pythagoreanism up to Plato's time and the philosophy of Plato himself, which certainly owed much to it, and
which tended to be read back into Pythagoreanism by its contemporaries and successors. For this purpose no guide can be as good as Aristotle, since the man who was a member of the Academy for twenty years of Plato's lifetime certainly knew the difference between the two and refers to it more than once. Here again we must allow for a certain
amount of
those
who
philosophical prejudice, though without going so far as speak of a perpetual desire on Aristotle's part to belittle the
2 originality of Plato.
There
is
who
said that
it
was hard
for
no need to accuse of hypocrisy the man him to criticize the Platonic doctrine of
who espoused it were his friends (EN, 1096312). That would be out of keeping with his high regard for two things, friendship (one thinks of the poem in honour of his murdered friend Hermias, which was made the occasion of his own exile) and truth. If
he 'passes so rapidly' over the features which distinguish Plato's philosophy from that of the Pythagoreans, it must be remembered that
he was simply making notes for the instruction of members or exmembers of the Academy to whom such matters would be perfectly
1
of the Pythagorean derivation of the world from (a) After a brief account in MetapL numbers and their respect for the number ten, with a reference to their astronomy including the counter-earth, Aristotle himself concludes (986 a 12): *But I have dealt with this more fully
elsewhere,*
()
in the
(c)
work on
.
Alex, in Metaph. 98633 (p. 41 . i Hayd.) : 'He deals with this the opinions of the Pythagoreans.'
:
more
fully in
De Cado and
ally,
Ibid. 75 15 'Of the order in the heavens, which the Pythagoreans constructed numeriche writes in the second book on Pythagorean doctrine/ (d) Stob. EcL i, 1 8, ic (DK, 58630): 'In the first book of the treatise on the philosophy of
. .
Pythagoras he writes .
.*
* 386.22 Heib.: As Aristotle himself records in the second book of his collection of Pythagorean beliefs.' (/) Ibid. 511 .30: 'For so he himself says in the treatise on Pythagoreanism.* Others could be quoted. See Rose's ed. of the fragments, nos. 190-205. There is also evidence of a treatise on the philosophy of Archytas (Rose fr. 207). 3 Raven, P. and E. 186. See also Cherniss, ACP^ 392.
0) Simpl. De
Caelo,
"5
From our point of view the brevity is to be regretted, but it is not attributable to malice. That his own philosophical point of view
familiar.
should colour his accounts, whether of the Pythagoreans or Plato, is of course inevitable, but to make allowance for this is not difficult, and
when
may
done, his personal criticism or way of putting the matter sometimes reveal, rather than conceal, some characteristic feature
that
is
of the
earlier philosophies.
critically,
one
the cirmay regard his information as invaluable. His date and cumstances of his life guarantee that what he says about the Pythawill be free from contamination not only with all Hellenistic or
still
goreans
with Platonism; his intellectual stature justifies considerable confidence (due allowance being made for known factors) in the accuracy of his reports; and his knowledge of
also
the Pythagorean school goes back at least to the first half of the fifth century, that is, to within at the most fifty, and perhaps fewer, years of the death of Pythagoras. 1
Perhaps the
first
is
how
far
it
seemed to him
split into sects
Pythagoreanism changed during holding mutually inconsistent views. He most frequently speaks of the school as a whole, though sometimes he limits a * doctrine to certain Pythagoreans' and occasionally (all too seldom) to
that
its
history, or
well as
an individual by name. The conclusion to be drawn has been put as it can be by Mr Raven (P. and E. 157):
There can,
I think,
be
little
doubt that in
this as in
with Pythagoreanism Aristotle is content for the most part to lump the whole of it together, but occasionally inserts into his generalizations a remark or
criticism, such as that about Eurytus, which applies only to a particular individual or group. ... It is perfectly reasonable to maintain simultaneously that Aristotle regarded the succeeding generations of Pythagoreans as suffi-
ciently akin to be usually grouped together, and that he yet included in his remarks some that were not capable of universal application. Only so, it seems to me, can we do his testimony the justice it deserves.
when we
This procedure of Aristotle's seems even more likely to reflect the facts take into account the conservatism and respect for tradition
a natural consequence
1
which were
below.
216
clung
to the older,
(p.
Pythagoreans
standards
is
more primitive side of the teaching were true 192, above). Modern scholarship with its exacting
unwilling to accept any doctrine as being earlier than the whom it is explicitly ascribed in a
source considered trustworthy. This clinging to certainties is of course to an uncritical confusion. Nevertheless KOTOC -rf}v infinitely preferable
uArjv 01 Aoyoi ccrrcciTT)Tioi
subject admits of
it
one can only demand proof in so far as the and if we are to speak of Pythagoreanism at all,
remain content with probabilities.
It is there-
fore permissible to remark that the known character of Pythagoreanism must lead us to expect the greatest possible continuity of doctrine.
Failing definite evidence that it would be impossible, the earlier existence of a tenet attested, say, for the late fifth century is more probable than
not.
It is
commonly
Greek mathematics.
tions,
held that the Pythagoreans laid the foundations of Undoubtedly they made remarkable contribu-
but in assessing their originality two considerations must be borne in mind: the state of mathematics in countries further East at
and before the time of Pythagoras, and the contribution of the lonians. Progressive decipherment of cuneiform inscriptions has put the mathematics of the Babylonians in a new light. The traditional ascription to Pythagoras of the famous theorem about the square on the hypotenuse
of a right-angled triangle was long doubted on the grounds that it was difficult to assign it to so early a stage of mathematical development.
Now, however,
that
it
Ham-
murabi, the case is different. According to later tradition, Pythagoras Strabo (xiv, 638) spent some time both in Egypt and in Babylonia.
of Polycrates, he left says simply that observing the growing tyranny Samos and went on a voyage of study to these two countries. In the
Theologumena Arhkmeticae attributed to lamblichus
DK
1
I,
p. 100),
we
no
On the attribution
502. Heath
d.
'
I, 3
sees
of the theorem to Pythagoras see Heath, The Thirteen Books of Euclid^ sufficient reason to question the tradition*. Also B. L. van der Waerden,
'Die Arithm.
217
made 500
are
by modern
standards of
little
but
we know
mid
such
journeys on the part of an active Samian were neither improbable nor difficult. Assuming then an acquaintance on Pythagoras's part with the
achievements of the peoples to the east and south of his native Ionia (and the same was also asserted of Thales earlier), we may say with
Neugebauer
they did
basis.
come not
at the
They
though
much
As
to systematize and put it on an exact and universal in astronomy, they adopted the most valuable achievements
culture, but developed
of Mesopotamian
them. 1
Next, the lonians. There is a temptation to speak of Pythagoras as if he were a figure of great antiquity, even of doubtful historicity, a
Hermotimus. Considering the religious reverence in which he was held, and the rapid growth of an aura of
shadowy
legend about his name, this is by no means surprising; but it must not obscure the fact that he was not only a historical person but one who
lived later than Thales and Anaximander,
and
that of Socrates
little
and between whose death more than a hundred years had passed
admittedly a momentous century in the history of thought. So far as the evidence goes, Pythagoras had serious predecessors in mathematics not only in the East but among the Ionian Greeks, for Thales was credited with a number of geometrical theorems (p. 53, above).
Apparently Aristotle's pupil Eudernus, when he wrote his history of geometry, felt no difficulty in ascribing them to an earlier thinker than
Pythagoras, and indeed
1
it
must be confessed
that
Cf. van der Waerden, Arithm. d. Pyth. 132. According to him (131) the Pythagoreans Introduced Babylonian algebra into Greece, and turned it into geometrical form, the reason for the transformation being the discovery of irrationals. The relative antiquity of Pythagorean mathematical discoveries could not be exhaustively discussed here, even were the present writer
so. It must be sought in such works as those of Heath, Greek Math.-, K. ReideDie Arithm. d. GriecAen; O. Becker, Die Lehre vom Gerade. w. Unger. im IX. Buck Jer Eukl. Elemente. For the relationship of Greek mathematics to Babylonian see Neugebauor, Stud. . ant. Algebra and The Exact Sciences in Antiquity.
competent to do
meister,
218
Ionian Mathematics
matical
authority.
knowledge of Pythagoras himself is attested by so good an W. A. Heidel, who drew attention to these facts/ also pointed
out with justice that this interest in number and geometry always remained alive in the Ionian tradition. The arrangement of Anaxi-
mander's universe,
like that
of the Pythagoreans
later,
had a numerical
The
tunnel
just
the island, presupposes definite geometrical propoPythagoras sitions. The map-making of Anaximander and Hecataeus points in the
same
century. matical passage of any length is Eudemus's account of the quadrature of the lune by Hippocrates of Chios, another fifth-century Ionian? Even the Pythagoreanizing lamblichus says (V.P. 88, DK, 18.4) that
The
legendary punishment of Hippasus it was Theodorus of and Gyrene Hippocrates who did most to advance mathematical studies in Greece, and Theodorus's brilliant pupil Theaetetus was an Athenian,
after the
whom
Proclus in his commentary on Euclid (p. 61 Friedl.) gives a list of Euclid's precursors in the composition of geometrical hand-books, of Hippocrates was the first and the others are largely lonians. There are no good reasons for supposing that all these men learned from
the Pythagoreans, and, as Heidel noted, Archytas the friend of Plato is the first Pythagorean whom we can name with confidence as having made notable contributions to mathematics. Pythagoras himself, in
spite
of the absence of positive early evidence, was no doubt responsible for considerable advances, but he was after all a Samian, and quite old
to have studied mathematics before he left the East; and
it
enough
seems certain that a strong mathematical tradition continued in Ionian lands no less, if not more, than in the brotherhood which he founded
in the West. It
of Ionian thought to be less bemused by the religious associations of number and more purely rational
would be
in the spirit
in approach.
Pythagoreans cosmology,
Heidel, p. 18,
AJP,
1940, 1-33.
On
n. 33,
Freeman, Companion, 217 (/. probably c. 430). Ar. Meteor. 34^35 clearly implies that he was not a Pythagorean, whatever may have been said to the contrary.
219
numerical explanation of reality as well as transmigration, universal man to god all belong to it in its kinship, and the assimilation of himself. original form as taught by the Master
is
know (pp. 209 ff., above) that the motive for studying the kosmos have to bring our own selves into closer conformity with its laws. of the kosmos the nature now to ask what such study reveals. What is
We
We
and on what
principles
is it
constructed?
What
school have to set over against the archai of the Milesians? The answer often attributed to them by lies in the implications of the doctrine so
Aristotle that 'things themselves are numbers', or that they 'imitate' or 'represent' numbers, or again that 'they supposed the elements of
numbers
whole heaven to be a
The word harmonia, a key-word of Pythagoreanism, meant primarily the joining or fitting of things together, even the material peg with which they were joined (Homer, Od. v, 248), then especially the
stringing of an instrument with strings of different tautness (perhaps thought of as a method of'joining the arms of the lyre, see Kirk, HCF,
208),
and so a musical
fifth
scale.
Its
the early
century
B.C., as
we
musical meaning was established by see from Pindar (Nem. iv, 44 f.) and
fragments of the lyric poets Pratinas (4^ Diehl) and Lasus (i). That the harmonia which the Pythagoreans equated with number had this
musical connotation
we know from
Aristotle's explanation
of their
theory of the harmony of the spheres (De Caelo, 290 b 12), and may assume also from the statement of Plato that they 'look for numerical
relationships in audible concords' (Rep. 531 A).
u; 9863
i.
22O
covery made by Pythagoras himself. So for instance Bumet (Gr. Phil i, 45): lt may be taken as certain that Pythagoras himself discovered the numerical ratios which determine the concordant intervals of the scale.' Taylor (Comm. on Tim. 164 and 489) speaks of 'the discovery of Pythagoras that the fundamental musical intervals core
ratios' and 'the success of Pythagoras in numerical laws for the relations of the notes of the octave and finding ',
by
flash
it
Brunet and Mieli exhibit slightly more caution (Hist, des Sciences, i. Antiquite, 121, quot. Farrington, Greek Science, I, 48) : It is to Pythagoras himself that tradition ascribes this and in this case one
'
with
still
all
may,
Ross
is
more
cautious
(Ar. Met. vol. i, 145): 'Pythagoras is said to have discovered the elements of the theory of musical harmony, and Burnet is inclined to
credit this/
the scholars quoted give authority for their categorical and in of statements, spite Taylor's further assertion that the determi* nation of the ratios was to unanimously ascribed in
antiquity
None of
Pytha-
goras ',
early,
seeing discovery the origin of the numerical explanation of the world. Aristoxenus, the friend of fourth-century Pythagoreans, wrote in his treatise
must be admitted, first, that none of the extant evidence is very and secondly, that antiquity was not unanimous in in this
it
on arithmetic that Pythagoras derived his enthusiasm for the study of number from its practical applications in commerce. This is by no means
an improbable supposition. The impact of monetary economy, as a comparatively recent phenomenon, on a thoughtful citizen of mercantile Samos might well have been to implant the idea that the one constant
factor
by which
was the
quantitative.
fixed
may
drinking-cup.
of the musical discovery to Pythagoras occurs in the following passage from Porphyry's commentary on the Harmonica of Ptolemy (p. 31 i During):
The
earliest attribution
Xenocrates says, discovered that the musical intervals also owe their origin of necessity to number, because they consist in a comparison of one quantity with another. He further investigated in what circumstances the intervals are concordant or discordant, and in general the origin of all harmony and
disharmony.
The whole
being mentioned
cited.
passage
is
it
quotation in which
a Chinese-box arrangement of quotation within no means always easy to see exactly who is is
by
the Heraclides expressed doubts whether or is Heraclides Ponticus another, though During is no 2 doubt right in dismissing them. But in any case the statement is
all probability) one of his quoted from Plato's pupil Xenocrates by (in belief in Plato's time. This contemporaries^ and was thus current
the discovery itself may well together with the brilliant nature of the genius of the founder. In to due it was that justify the confidence
later centuries
of course, when writers freely substituted Pythagoras for the Pythagoreans of their predecessors, the attribution was usual. Theo Smyrnaeus will serve as an example (Math. p. 56 Hiller): 'It
was the first appears [or is generally believed, SOKEI] that Pythagoras to discover the concordant notes in their ratios to one another/ There
follows a statement of what the ratios were.
The
strings
1
relevance of
explained
by
to contemporary music has been simply Burnet (Gr. Phil, i, 45-9). In the seven-stringed lyre, four
fixed intervals,
number
were tuned to
See p. 177, above. G. Thomson, The First Philosophers (263), makes this point without reference to the single ancient passage which supports it. Aristoxenus also believed that Pythagoras gave the Greeks their weights and measures (D.L. vni, 14, DK, 14.12). * See his discussion of the passage in Ptol. und Porph. tiler die Musiky i^ff. It is fair to
mention that according to him 'Pythagoras ist naturlich bei derartigen Zitaten ein Sammelnamen*. 3 According to D.L. iv, 13 Xenocrates wrote a TTv0oy6pia. Heraclides might also have been quoting something that he heard him say.
222
one tone higher. These four strings thus provided the three intervals which the Greeks regarded
to
fourth.
OU^CDVOUVTES <p06yyoi): octave, fifth and In addition the interval between the two middle strings was
a tone. 1
harmony
(c)
in our sense.
was no such thing as Harmonia meant (a) tuning, () scale and Greek music was melodic, without the use of
chords.
temporaries of Pythagoras referred to melodic progression. The essential point, however, is that the three intervals of octave, fourth
and
fifth were regarded as primary, as the elements out of which musical scale or any composition was built. To Pythagoras went the
of perceiving that this basic framework depended on fixed numerical ratios 1:2 (octave), 3:2 (fifth), 4:3 (fourth).
credit
These numbers, of course, represent the rate of vibration of a string, or of the column of air in a pipe. It is doubtful whether Pythagoras
and in any case he had no means of measuring the rate (see pp. 226 F.). Apocryphal stories were current in later antiquity of how he
this,
knew
made the discovery by listening to the varied notes produced by blacksmiths' hammers ringing in turn on an anvil, and then comparing
the relative weights of the hammers; or producing different tensions in strings by suspending them and attaching various weights. Nicomachus
reports that weights of 12 and 6 units produced the octave, of 12 and 8 or 9 and 6 the fifth, of 12 and 9 or 8 and 6 the fourth, and weights of 9 and 8 units gave the tone. These stories are repeated by several
writers, but cannot
Beating a piece of iron on an anvil with hammers of different weights produces little or no difference in the
be
true.
would be propor-
a reference to these ratios in Aristotle, Metaph. 1093329. C also An. Post. 90318 * What is a concord? A commensurate numerical ratio of a high and a low note/ out full in Philolaus, fr. 6, which uses ovAAocpd for the fourth (later 5t& -recrcrdpcov), are in set They 61* 6eiov for the fifth (later Side "nivrre) and dpuovloc for the octave (later 5i& Trocacov). On the fragments of Philolaus see below, pp. 330 ff.
There
is
(Oxford
trans.) :
223
square-roots.
Theo, however
and
similar,
more or less dubious, methods ('tension induced by turning the pegs or more informatively by attachment of weights; in wind instruments the width of the cavities or variation in the force of the breath; or by as with gongs and vessels'), dismisses them means of size and
weight with the words: 'For present purposes let us be content to illustrate The kanon was it by the lengths of string on the kanon^ as it is called/ an instrument of one string which could be stopped by the
a
monochord, moveable bridge,* and if the discovery is indeed Pythagoras's, it was no doubt on this that he carried out his experiments. Tradition credited
him with
invention (D.L. vm, 12). The rate of vibration being of the string, if two strings at the inversely proportional to the length same tension are plucked, then if one is twice as long as the other it
its
and
this
Since the native Greek stringed instruments, the lyra and cithara, had existence of these numerical ratios would strings of equal lengths, the
to the naturally occur to the maker, or the pegs by a method of player as he picked out the notes, turning of makers trial and error. Even the pipes may have proceeded empiric-
not be obvious.
It
would not
ally,
between the holes.3 The discovery of Pythagoras, that the basic intervals of Greek music could be represented by the ratios 1:2, 3:2 and 4:3,
made
1
it
by means of the
order and beauty was imposed on the first four integers i, 2, 3 and 4.
See e.g. Nicom. Harm, in Jan's Mus. Script. 245 ff., Iambi. V.P. 115, Boethius, Inst. Mus. I, and for comment W. H. Stahl's translation of Macrobius, Somn. Scip. (Columbia, 1953), p. 1 87, n. 6, where also are collected further ancient references. 3 If the string was stretched over an open box, as in the medieval form of the instrument (see Th. Gerold, La Musique au moyen age (Paris, 1932,), 387), the contact of the bridge would not noticeably disturb the tension. That the instrument was not perfect, however, was noted by Ptolemy, who devoted a chapter of his Harmonica to its disadvantages (n, i2 ? irepi TTJS Suaxpnorias TOU novoxopSou KOVOVOS). He describes a form of it in I, 8. 3 The opposite view has been held, but it does not seem necessary to agree with a writer like E, Frank that the discovery of the mathematical relationships must have been familiar to every Greek instrument-maker, still less with G. Junge that every piper or lyre-player must have known them* (Frank, Plato u. d. sog. Pyth. 1 1 ; Junge, Classica et M&diev. 1947, 184). There were twentyfour notes on the aulos (Ar. Metaph. 1093 b 2-4; see Ross adloc.).
'
224
Music:
These add up
to 10,
the Tetractys
which provided striking confirmation, if it was not the actual ground, of the Pythagorean belief that the number ten 'was something perfect, and contained in itself the whole nature of number'
(Arist.
became
graphically by the figure known as the tetractys, which a sacred symbol for them. The followers of J
Pythagoras were said to swear by him (thereby acknowledging his superhuman status) in a formula whose
antiquity
it is difficult
tetractys, source
'By him who handed down to us the and root of everlasting nature.' 1 Certainly a primitive element of number-mysticism survived, along with genuine matheto doubt:
which men feel at an early stage of culture in mentally separating objects numbered from numbers themselves as abstractions, in forming the concept of a number 3 as distinct from its
It
difficulty
visible manifestations in
groups of three trees or three stones. This outlook is reflected in language, and the criticism of it which we should be
inclined to
is exactly that which was levelled against the more advanced Greek thinker like Aristotle. Pythagoreans by a we allow for must certain survival of primitive modes If, however, of thought, we must remember also what irrefutable confirmation, on purely rational grounds, they must have seemed to acquire in the minds
make
ourselves
a
of these early Pythagoreans from such discoveries as that of the independent existence of a numerical scheme behind the musical scale. The
existence of an inherent order, a numerical organization within the nature of sound itself, came as a kind of revelation. It is not too far-
modern
physicist
when confronted
laws,
which
own
ment which we
all
thought, really hold in nature. And that deep amazeoften feel over the inner order of nature is connected above
that, as in the case
of
crystals,
we have
already
1 in the Golden Verses^ Quoted, with slight variations, by Porph. V.P. 20, Iambi. V.P. 50, sur la litt.pytL 249-68. 47 f., and elsewhere. Cf. A. Delatte, *La tetractys pythagoricienne', in t. By 'number-mysticism* in the next sentence is meant the attribution to numbers not only of a sacred character but also of a substantial, even physical, reality.
1
225
necessity.
In the sphere of music, the Greek was in exactly the same position of having been long familiar with the effects of the 'mathematics of
nature* before his
stand
it is
it;
and
if today it still
2 not surprising that its effect on him was even greater. Might it not be that in number lay the key, not only to musical sounds, but to
It must be remembered that what the Pythafind out was not the basic material stuff of the to were goreans trying universe, nor yet primarily the physical changes by which it had come into being, but first and foremost the explanation of the order, the kosmwtesy which to their eyes it displayed and to their minds, for
reasons in large part religious, was the most important thing about
Additional Note: 'Speed* and pitch
it.
A relationship between the pitch of a note and its 'speed* was assumed
from the time of Plato and Archytas onward, and no doubt earlier. Some of the language used is, however, very vague, and it is not always
easy to
know
exactly
what the
describing.
(a)
be
Theo
Archytas posited a numerical ratio between the concordances. They agreed with others that the ratios lay in movements, a swift motion being highproduces a continuous succession of blows and stabs the air and a slow motion low-pitched because more sluggish.' () Archytas, fr. i : The mathematicians seem to me to have shown true insight. . First of all they considered that there can be no sound without the striking of one thing against another, and that a blow occurs when moving
pitched since
it
more
sharply,
'
C. F. von Weizsacker, The World-view of Physics, ai. physicist's choice of crystals as an example acquires a certain incidental interest from a conjecture made a good many years ago about the origin of Pythagoras's number-doctrine. Sir Wm. Ridgeway suggested that since Pythagoras was the son of a gem-engraver, and there2
The
all probability a gem-engraver himself, it would most naturally arise from his observation of the regular geometrical forms of minerals (CR, 1896, 92-5). Pyrites crystals in the form of dodecahedra are found only in S. Italy, where he lived, and on Elba (RE9 2. Reihe, v A 2, 1364).
fore in
226
blow or because of their distance from or even because of their excessive strength; for the loudest sounds do not penetrate our hearing, just as if one pours a liquid in great quantity over the
which
reach us quickly and (strongly) from the impact give the impression of high pitch, but those which come slowly and weakly seem low. If a stick is taken
and moved slowly and gently, the sound made by its impact is low, but if swiftly and violently, high. .Again, in playing a pipe the breath from the
. .
mouth when
on die holes near the mouth gives out a higher note on account of the strength of the pressure, but on the further holes, a lower note. This makes it obvious that the swift motion produces a high note, slow motion a low one. The same thing happens with the rhomboi [bull-roarers]
it falls
.
used in the mysteries. When swung gently they give a low note, when ..' violently a high one Finally Porphyry, who quotes this passage, adds: * After further remarks on the notion of sound as made up of intervals, he
.
sums up
notes
his
move more
argument thus: "It is clear then from many proofs quickly and low notes more slowly."
*
that high
(c) Plato in the Republic (5300) speaks of 'harmonic motion* (ivocpjiovios 90pd), and in the Timaeus goes into detail. Tim. 67 B (trans. Cornford): 'Sound we may define in general terms as
by air on
on
motion
the brain and blood through the ears and passed it causes, starting in the head and ending in
the region of the liver, is hearing. rapid motion produces a high-pitched sound; the slower the motion, the lower the pitch.'
(/) 80 A: 'This principle [i.e. the principle of the "circular thrust"] will also explain why sounds, which present themselves as high or low in pitch according as they are swift or slow, are as they travel sometimes inharmonious because the motion they produce in us lacks correspondence,
when
sometimes concordant because there is correspondence. The slower sounds, they catch up with the motions of the quicker sounds which arrived earlier, find these motions drawing to an end and already having reached correspondence with the motions imparted to them by the slower sounds on
their later arrival. In so doing, the slower
they introduce a fresh motion; rather by joining on the beginning of a slower motion in correspondence with the quicker which is now drawing to an end, they produce a single combined effect in which high and low are blended.'
*
(e) One may compare [Arist.] De audibilibus 803 b 40 (Oxford trans.): The same thing happens, too, when two notes form a concord; for owing to
y
the fact that the two notes overlap and include one another and cease at the same moment, the intermediate constituent sounds escape our notice. For in
227
air are
caused
by
the shriller
note,
owing to the quickness of its movement; the result is upon our hearing simultaneously with an earlier sound produced by the slower impact. Thus because, as has been said, the ear cannot perceive
strikes
all
we seem
continuously/
extracts (of which a full explanation is given by s Plato Coniford, Cosmology 320 ff.) are very likely to be dependent on the velocity of the Archytas, and bear out the verdict that he 'confused
',
The Timaeus
motion which produces a sound with the velocity of the sound itself, which leads him to conclude, from observations correct in themselves, that higher tones are propagated more rapidly than lower ones' (van der Waerden, Science Awakening^ 152). The passage from Archytas himself suggests that he was also not very clear in his own mind about
any distinction between speed' and 'violence' of movement. Adrastus (second century A.D., quoted by Theo, p. 50 H.), in a very lucid account of the Pythagorean theory, clears up this latter obscurity, which may
have been only due to carelessness of expression: 'The Pythagoreans give the following account. Every melody and every note are sounds,
is a blow inflicted on air which is prevented from disTherefore there can be no sound, and hence no note, where the persing. air is undisturbed. But when a blow and a movement occur in the air,
*
and a sound
then
if it is swift the
is
note produced
is
high, if slow
it is
low;
if violent
the noise
may
or
may
another. If they do not, the sounds are disproportionate and discordant, not to be called notes but mere noises, whereas motions that stand in a
simple numerical relationship, or such that one is a multiple of the other or superparticular to it [i.e. containing the whole plus a fraction with i
for
its
Some
numerator], produce genuine and mutually compatible notes. deserve to be called only this, but those constructed according to
the primary,
ratios are
currency, in the fourth century, of the confusion between the velocity of the motion producing a sound and that of the sound itself
The
'
between pitch and velocity, and hence of a numerically expressible ratio between high and low sounds. The high-pitched sound, he says
(fr.
it
89, p. 189
it
did,
Wimmer), does not differ in speed from the lower: if would reach our hearing sooner. He argues therefore that
of pitch are
qualitative,
differences
(Ii)
of the
doctrine
Aristotle refers to the Pythagorean number-doctrine in three forms 5 * (p. 220, above): things are numbers, things 'imitate or represent*
are, in translation:
(a) 98yb 28 :
more
fully in
many of
not separately existing numbers, but that existing things to be numbers are of numbers. Their reason was that numerical actually composed things
properties are inherent in the musical scale, in the heavens, and in
many
being
other things.*
owe
their
to imitation (mimesis)
(c)
of numbers.*
Since the nature of everything else seemed to be entirely assimilated to numbers, and numbers to be primary throughout the world of nature, they assumed the elements of numbers to be the elements of all that
98 5 b 32:
exists,
On
the
two passages
it
should be noted
(i)
together in the same context, (ii) that this context is a criticism of the Ideas of Plato, in the course of which Aristotle says that when Plato
spoke of the 'sharing* or 'participation' (methexis) of individual things in the being of the changeless Ideas, he meant to indicate the same relation as that expressed by the Pythagorean term mimesis, which is
commonly
translated 'imitation'.
difficulty
Unnecessary
1
by
the assumption
1
So especially Cherniss, ACP, 386: 'The distinctive feature of the school according to Ariswas its assumption of number as the principle; but the account he gives of this doctrine is, as has been seen, self-contradictory, for he represents it as identifying numbers and physical of existing things, and as objects, as identifying the principles of number with the principles making things imitate number.* See also the other views summarized in ZN, 454, n. i.
229
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
first, it is
To
if
take the
first
an object x
consists
itself is
elements, then the elements of y are also the elements of x. If a statue is made of bronze, and the bronze is an alloy of copper and tin, then one may speak either of bronze or of copper and tin (the elements
of bronze) as being the elements of the statue. Aristotle's own philosophy provides an exact parallel. All physical bodies are made of the
four simple bodies earth, water, air and fire. These, though the simplest of independently existing substances, can themselves be analysed further
Consequently he can of either of fear without self-contradiction, things consisting of speak, the four simple bodies or equally of matter and form, the elements of
into the elements of prime matter and form.
the simple bodies, as the ultimate elements of everything. In comparing the first and second statements, the fact that Aristotle was able to equate Pythagorean mimesis with Plato's notion of physical
objects as sharing in' the Ideas (which Plato himself elsewhere describes as 'patterns' for the world of sense) should put us on our 5 guard against the simple translation "imitation . The fact is, of course,
that even Plato,
*
express
new
the Pythagoreans, were struggling to and difficult conceptions within the compass of an in-
and
still
more
adequate language. We may take a hint first from K. Joel (Gesch. d. ant. PhUos. 364), who points to the trouble that the Pythagoreans must have
experienced in clearly differentiating the concepts of similarity and
identity, *a defect
which
and
still
because it is rooted deep in the Greek consciousness : even their language has only one word for "same" and "similar" (onoios)'. He continues (I translate): 'Are things imitations of numbers or numbers themselves?
alive to the
Aristotle ascribes both views to the Pythagoreans, and whoever is mind of Greece will also credit them with both and agree
them numbers served alike as real and as ideal principles.' Mimesis meant acting as much as imitation, mimetes was often and mimos always an actor. The relation between an actor and his part is
that for
He
gets inside
it,
words and
gestures.
There is more to
'Mimesis*
ritual,
and
we
if
we
allow/ourselves to forget that it too was primarily religious. In the earliest and simplest dramatic representations men impersonated gods
or
for religious ends, and what spirits they supposed to be happening can be best illustrated from contemporary ecstatic worship like that of Dionysus. The leader of his thiasos, the band of god-intoxicated
worshippers, impersonated, or imitated, the god. So we might put it, but to him and his fellow-worshippers what happened was that the
god himself entered into him, took possession and acted through him. Hence he was called by the god's name Bacchus, and all who genuinely
felt
the
god was
themselves. This
from another point of view ekstatikoiy outside only one example of what was repeated in a large
ecstatic kind.
number of
attended
cults
of the same
In
myth
the
god was
a band of daimones, and in performing the ritual the not worshippers only acted the parts of, but for the moment were, the himself and his divine attendants Bacchoi, Kuretes, Korybantes god
by
or whatever the name might be. Pythagoras and his school, with their belief in universal kinship and the underlying notion of magical relationships, in transmigration and
in assimilation to
god
as the
of these religious
'
ideas.
end of human
Pythagoras. Was Pythagoras now Euphorbus, did he in some way * imitate or represent him, or how was the relationship to be expressed?)
Pythagoras himself quickly achieved the status of a daimon, intermediate between man and god, or even an incarnation of the Hyper-
borean Apollo. These are the kind of men who claimed to have made the tremendous
discovery that the world of nature was constructed on a mathematical at one plan. It need cause no surprise that they expressed this by saying existed mimesis time that things were numbers, at another that they by
rational classification,
and
the contempt for religious or superstitious ways of thinking which went it was all naturally with a newly-won emancipation from them,
exasperatingly illogical.
The modern
scholar or scientist
may view
it
more
sympathetically.
231
something
refers.
theories to
which he
The
back beyond the Pythagoreanism with which he was familiar went time of the atomists Leucippus and Democritus. His general account of of the Metaphysics Pythagoreanism in chapter 5 of the first book follows immediately on a description of the theories of these two, and begins (98 5 b 23) with the words:
Contemporaneously with and before these men, the Pythagoreans (as they are called), who were the earliest to apply themselves to mathematics, at the
same time were making advances in this subject and, because of their abof mathematics to be the principles of sorption in it, assumed the principles
everything.
Similarly in a later
says, speaking
of the virtual
by
Socrates:
Of the natural philosophers Democritus barely approached the conception with his quasi-definition of the hot and the cold, and before him the Pythagoreans applied it to a few things, which they defined with reference to numbers.
The
in
chapter in the
first
book
affords
some
connexion with the table of ten pairs of contraries (on which see below, p. 245). This table Aristotle ascribes to some, but not all
Pythagoreans (986322: 'Others of the same school say.
.
.*).
Alcmaeon of Croton [he continues] appears to have had the same idea, and he borrowed it from them or they from him, for he gave a similar exposition to theirs: he says that most of the things affecting human beings go in pairs, though he does not draw up a specific list of contraries as these men do, but mentions any chance pairs such as white and black, sweet and
either
good and evil, great and small. He made vague remarks about the other 1 contraries, but the Pythagoreans laid down how many and what they were.
bitter,
by
5) that a general doctrine of opposites in the Pythagoreans with the lonians and Greek
have omitted (with Ross and others before him) the words descriptive of Alcmaeon's he was in his prime in the old age of Pythagoras *, which are missing from the Laurentian MS. and absent from the ancient commentators. Heidel in AJPy 1940, 5 gives further reasons for
I
date, that
rejecting them.
'
If,
however, they are a later addition, one may nevertheless agree with Ross that enough to be true*. Cf. also ZN, 597, n. 2, and see pp. 341 ff., 3 57 ff. below.
232
and
it
therefore appeared to
him
to be a
profound
why
it
necessary to suggest
borrowed
from Alcmaeon or
vice,
versa.
The universality of
Alcmaeon taught it is not easy to assess on the meagre information given here by Aristotle, but if what Heidel says is true,
seems to be strong circumstantial evidence that Aristotle in fact knew of a connexion between Alcmaeon and the Pythagoreans, though
this
the view as
he was uncertain which should be credited with the priority. (It is worth noting in passing that, according to the list of his works in D.L. v, 25, Aristotle had studied Alcmaeon sufficiently to write a
treatise in criticism
say is that Aristotle regarded the Pythagoreans who put forward the ten pairs of opposites as having been contemporary with Alcmaeon, so that it was possible
of his thought.)
borrowed a doctrine of contraries from the other, Alcmaeon generalizing from the Pythagorean list or the Pythagoreans
for either to have
selecting certain items
and
if,
as Heidel says,
the Pythagorean table as relatively late, 1 an equally strong consensus has tended with reason to believe that Alcmaeon was a younger con-
We may
goreans in general goes back to before the time of the atomists, say to the middle of the fifth century when Philolaus was a leading representative, and that he knows of some Pythagorean doctrines which
belong to an
earlier
Nor
whom,
I
long to the
turn
now to
it
numbers, as
the Pythagorean explanation of the world in terms of appeared to the best informed extant authority. Re-
membering
1
that he
was
in one
way too
near,
far off
In fact Raven (P. andE. ch. 3) gives strong reasons for supposing that it was already known
to Parmenides.
2 This conclusion accords with that of Raven (P. and E. n): 'When we pass. . .to the views of "others of this same school", Aristotle's surmise that these Pythagoreans borrowed their doctrine of the opposites from Alcmaeon, or else he his from them, strongly suggests that the transition is from a later to an earlier generation.' As Raven also notes, it is only very rarely that Aristotle explicitly recognizes a distinction between one school or generation of Pythagoreans
and another.
233
Pythagoras and
from them to achieve a
find that his
full
the
Pythagoreans
and sympathetic understanding, we may very puzzlement and irritation throw considerable light
on
their mentality.
In addition to his statements that the elements of number were the * elements of all things, that things were numbers, and that they imitated'
(a)
as well as Speusippus] Metaph. io8ob 16: *The Pythagoreans also [sc. but not as existing recognize a single type of number, mathematical number, the Platonists of in general], the view apart from sensible things [sc. which was fact in construct the whole which they regard as being composed of it. They monadic universe out of numbers, not however truly numbers, for they
By 'monadic' Aristotle means, as his commentator Alexander says, unextended and incorporeal. The notion of incorporeal reality was not or any of their contemporaries. yet grasped by the Pythagoreans
() Metaph. 986315 (this and passage (W) are from the chapter on the Pythagoreans): 'Evidently they too regard number as a principle both in the sense of matter and of temporary or permanent states.'
'too* Aristotle can hardly mean that other Presocratic thinkers had regarded numbers as principles, but more probably that the Pytha-
By
goreans were
With
this passage
may
the chapter in which it formal aspects of a concrete object. This is easy enough, says Aristotle, when the same form is realized in different materials, as the form of
circle in
be compared one in book Z. The purpose of occurs is to distinguish the material from the
It is less
easy
when
the
form
is
always found in the same matter, as for example the form of man in flesh, bones, etc. The theoretical possibility of the distinction is
recognized, but there are cases where it is difficult to pin down. He continues (here Alexander states, and the content shows, that he is
space
[i.e.
adduced
in the
to regard these as their formal characteristics], but that these are same capacity as the flesh and bones of a man and the bronze
or stone of a statue/
234
Aristotle on the
Nature of Number
(<T) Metaph. 987313: *The Pythagoreans similarly posit two principles, but add something peculiar to themselves, namely that the finite and the infinite are not attributes of other natural substances like fire or earth or some-
thing similar. Rather they hold that the infinite itself and unity itself are the substance of that of which they are predicated, and this is why they say that number is the substance of all things.'
(e) Similarly in the following chapter on Plato he writes ^Syb^i): 'But in saying that the one was substance, and not something else which was called one, he was speaking like the Pythagoreans, and it was also in
agreement with them that numbers should be for other things the cause of
their reality/
It
must be remembered
it
word
cause'
meaning than
something
is
made
is
one of its
*
Moreover, if it be granted them, or demonstrated, magnitude is derived from these principles [sc. limited and unlimited, odd and even, which in Pythagorean theory, as we shall see, are the elements of number], even so how can some bodies be light and some heavy? To judge by their assumptions and statements, they are speaking of sensible bodies no less than mathematical. Hence they tell us nothing about fire or earth or other bodies of this kind because, unless I am mistaken, they have
(/) Metaph. 990312:
that spatial
nothing to say about perceptible bodies as such.* (g) Metaph. 1090330: 'In this respect [sc. in denying that numbers have an existence separate from things] the Pythagoreans are in no way at fault, but when they construct physical bodies out of number things which possess
they appear to lightness and weight out of elements which possess neither be talking about some other universe and other bodies, not those that we
perceive.*
(A)
(A
De
Caelo, 300316.)
Metaph. io83b8: *The Pythagoresn way of thinking in one W3y but in another it presents fewer difficulties than those previously considered, has separate that number adds fresh difficulties of its own. Their denial
existence
removes many impossibilities, but the statement that bodies are composed of numbers, 3nd di3t this refers to msthematical number, is incredible. It is false to say that there are indivisible magnitudes, and even if
there were, units do not have magnitude. And how could a magnitude consist of indivisibles? But arithmeticsl number is monadic [sc. consists of
hand identify real things abstract, incorporesl units]. They on the other their number. At any rate they apply speculations to bodies as if they
sisted
with
con-
235
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
Pythagoreanism had the
From
following characteristics:
(1) All things consist
of number, in the
literal
themselves are
ultimate,
it
1
made of numbers;
said that
may be
numbers themselves are not the elements of numbers are the elements of
or, since
everything. (2) Units for the Pythagoreans possess magnitude. (3) Instead of saying that things are numerically characterized, they spoke as if number were the actual matter of which things are composed.
(4)
one* or
'it is finite'
'it'
being substantially
the other
something
thing
else.
else like
wood
or metal.
The Pythagoreans on
hand
regarded unity and limit as substances forming the basic element of every-
of thought
were formulated on the basis of his doctrine of the 'four causes'. To understand the nature of reality, the philosopher must be able to analyse any class of objects into its logical components, of which the primary
pair
were matter and form, and to account for their existence by detecting the efficient cause and (since for him nature acted teleologically)
the purpose of their being. In nature the formal, final and efficient causes usually coincided, for instance in the male parent which engenders the offspring and also provides the pattern according to which
it
grow. Thus the primary opposition remains that between matter and form in a bronze disc the bronze and the circular shape, in a man
will
the material components of the human body on the one hand and on the other (at the highest level, on which 'form' is a very wide conception)
that
difference
Obviously number, whether thought of arithmetically, geometrically or as manifested in musical intervals, is a formal component; hence
Aristotle's chief complaint against the Pythagoreans
is
More
specifically
goreans,
In one place (De Caeto, 300316) Aristotle says: * Certain people, like some of the Pythamake the natural world out of number.' The phrase 'some of the Pythagoreans* has
been made the basis for theories of a division within the school, particularly between an earlier and a later generation (Raven, P. and E."). But in view of its isolation among the numerous passages which ascribe the belief to the Pythagoreans without qualification, it is unlikely to have any significance (ZN, 450 f. suggest explanations of it, and cf. Raven, P. andE. 55).
236
he puts
it still
more
In studying the Presocratics, one often has the feeling that they world of thought from our own. When we come to
those which most of us (though not the most scientifically advanced) follow today. His basic outlook is one which we should still regard as that of commonsense.
If there
socratics, he,
a curtain dividing our minds from those of the Prethough a Greek himself and almost their contemporary, is
is
on our side of it. Failing someone equally at home in both worlds, this makes him probably the most sympathetic informant that we could hope for. He finds them difficult and irritating, and sometimes
already
may we, and for reasons astonishingly he has drawn conclusions from their probability utterances which they did not explicitly draw themselves, and given as
fails
to understand them.
So
similar.
In
all
Pythagorean statements what are in fact inferences, in his eyes inescapable, but no more. Yet on his and other evidence it seems
actual
certain that they
saw no
difficulty in
making a mental
leap
from an
abstraction like a geometrical solid to the concrete physical bodies of the world of nature, and it is with a mentality which saw this continuity as natural that we, like him, have to come to terms.
As we have seen
'
(pp. 225
above),
it
was
in
all
covery of the mathematics of nature' doing its hidden work in the formation of the musical scale that led them, by an audacious stroke of
generalization, to explain the whole of reality in mathematical terms. a mind like that of Pythagoras, not only mathematically but also
On
mystically inclined, to which 'all nature was akin', the impact of this discovery of an independent numerical order inherent in the nature of
temporary science,
it is
no wonder
that
phrases as 'Things are number', 'Things represent numbers', 'Whatever numbers are made of is what all things are made of.
Our understanding
is
helped
when
own
the same time terminology, that for the Pythagoreans numbers were at had The Milesians of formal causes the material and sought to things.
237
matter aside and define things in terms of their form. Provided the numerical proportions were right, it did not matter whether notes were
produced by die motion of a stretched string or of air in a pipe: they were the same notes. This in itself was a great advance, both from
of view and in general Aristotle always upholds the of form, insisting that to define a thing properly it is necessary primacy to give its logos or formal structure: and this opinion would presumably be shared by a modern mathematical physicist. The trouble about
Aristotle's point
Pythagoras and his followers was that they were not quite aware of what they had done. The distinction between form and matter had as
yet received no clear formulation. Consequently, though they were in in itself a perfectly fact describing only the structural scheme of things
they believed that they were describing their legitimate procedure material nature too: that it was possible to speak of things as made up as arithmetical units, entirely of numbers, regarded in a threefold way
geometrical points, and physical atoms. In their excitement at having discovered the importance of the quantitative aspect of things, they ignored entirely the qualitative, which had hitherto had all the emphasis laid upon it, and to which Aristotle by temperament a naturalist rather than a mathematician returned. Thus
he demanded petulantly (MetapL 1092 b 1 5) How indeed can qualities white, sweet, hot be numbers?' Looking back, it seems as if it was
*
:
Aristotle
who was
leading science
on
to the
wrong
track.
Today
the
scientific description
colour, disappear and are replaced by numbers representing wave-lengths or masses. For this reason a historian of science has claimed that Pythagoras's discovery changed the whole course of
heat, light,
of numerical equations.
sound
accept this, and yet not be surprised that at that of early stage thought, unprovided with any system of logic or even of grammar, he and his school announced their great idea by saying
history.
that 'things are numbers'.
1
We may
20.
Generation from
(c)
Numbers
of things from numbers
stages In the
Numbers and
So
far
process of generation, that of numbers from certain prior elements and that of 'things' from numbers. 1 It soon appears, however, that there
are in fact three: generation of numbers
from
limit
figures
might well be asked whether in speaking of generation the Pythagoreans thought of an actual process in time, or simply of logical
being regarded as logically prior and elemental to B simply priority, because the existence of B is inconceivable without can whereas
be thought of as existing without B. Is their description simply an analysis cast into the form of a temporal process, as many suppose the
account of the creation in Plato's Timaeus to be? The question can only be answered, if at all, in the light of the scanty references to the physical
aspect of their cosmogony, which must
come
no doubt that Aristotle, at least, supposed their references to generation to be intended literally (MetapL 1091 a 13, 989 b 34; below,
There
is
He may,
"
on one occasion, in a context which must certainly include the Pythagoreans, 2 he puts very clearly, on their behalf, the argument of logical priority. The passage, which is of considerable interest, is
from Metaphysics B, in which he sets forth dialectically the arguments for and against the chief metaphysical theses (iooib26). Those here
given do not represent his
own
view:
related problem is whether numbers, bodies, surfaces and points are substances or not. If they are not, there is no saying what is reality and what are the substances of existing things, for attributes, motions, relations, states
and
ratios
do not appear
all
if we predicated of a subject, and none of them is an individual thing. And take what would most properly appear to indicate substance water, earth,
fire
1
and
air,
are
made
and
'Things* for the Pythagoreans includes both the physical world and its contents and also abstractions such as justice, marriage, etc. (Ar. Metaph. 98 5 b 29, 990322, ioy8b2i;
MM,
n82an).
1 Ross ad lac* follows Alexander in thinking that both the Pythagoreans and Plato are meant; Bonitz wished to confine the reference to the Pythagoreans.
239
body is less substantial than surface, surface than line, line than unit or point; for by them the body is bounded, and it would appear that whereas they can exist without body, it cannot exist without them. Hence
the other hand
earlier philosophers, like the
On
man
and substance
with body, and the principles or elements of body with those of real things; but later and reputedly more subtle thinkers saw reality in numbers.
The most
Plato had
likely
is
no
between
logical
and and
the
Aristotle.
by chronological priority, which was of shift from one to the a conscious not be would fully They
formulated
Plato
other.
On
the other
hand
all
work was on
analysis of things into elements logically prior, and at least we need not them to have seriously imagined that there was a time when
of numbers from
The elements of numbers are, ultimately, unlimited, and secondarily the odd and the even
scheme the unit was regarded
but not as
itself
and the
unit. In this
as the starting-point
belonging to it, because every actual number must be either odd or even and the unit, curiously
series,
of the number
enough, was conceived as combining in itself both oddness and evenness. The reason why the unit occupies such an anomalous position in Greek
is no doubt that zero was unknown. Consequently the unitmade to fulfil a double function was It was both one-dimensional point unit of construction and non-dimensional point of contact between two
thought
sections.'
MetapL 9863 17: The elements of number are the even and the odd, and of these the latter is limited and the former unlimited. The One is composed of both of these (for it is both even and odd) and number
(a) Aristotle,
have
whole
987315 (quoted above, p. 235) says that for the Pythagoreans the and the One are the actual substance of things, and not
is
by
Aristotle.
240
own
discussion of the
word
apeiron (unlimited) and its various uses, Aristotle says that all philosophers worthy of the name have had something to say about it, and all regard it as
first principle.
treat
it
as
an accident or attribute of a
physical substance like water or air, 'some, like the Pythagoreans and Plato, speak of it in itself, not as inhering in something else but as being itself a
substance. But the Pythagoreans (a) place
it among sensible things (for they separate from these), and () say that what is outside unlimited.' After pointing out that in these respects they
Plato,
he continues
it is
when
They say moreover that the unlimited is the enclosed and limited by the odd provides the un:
'
limited element in existing things. This is illustrated by what happens when gnomons are placed around numbers: when they are placed round the one,
and without the one, in the one case the figure produced varies continually, whereas in the other it is always the same. Plato on the other hand considered the unlimited as a duality, the great and small.'
Aristotle, criticizing the Pythagoreans for their of motion, asks how it can be accounted for 'when inadequate explanation the only things assumed are limit and the unlimited and odd and even*
(J)
At Metaph. 990 a 8
is
considering, these
The
in a
gnomons
will
be discussed
moment. Heidel cast doubt on Aristotle's accuracy in claiming that the Pythagoreans regard the One and the unlimited as substances and not as attributes, though he offers no reason for this beyond remarking: to them (AJP, 'Possibly he was transferring Platonic expressions Aristotle is with in a which this about passage 1940, 12, n. 22). To say the greatest care distinguishing between the Pythagoreans and Plato is
5
astonishing, apart
that
he of
all
men
should make such a mistake. This does not mean that he had a full from understanding of what went on in their minds. He looked back
the point of view of one who could take his stand on certain basic distinctions such as those between substance and attribute, abstract and
procedure
concrete (compare for instance his lucid description of mathematical in Metaph. K, 1061 a 28 ff.), and tried to apply these clear-cut
as yet
by no means
fully
Hence
his bewilderment
and
irritation at their
241
Ross has remarked (Ar. Phys. 541), they did not to an abstraction, but rather failed to recognize the
as
the cold, the dry, the moist, etc.) probably tended to perpetuate this lack of distinction between abstract and concrete. Anaximander in
as something material, positing the 'unlimited' was mainly aware of it whereas a Pythagorean saw rather its formal characteristics. But neither
could put to himself, or have put to him by a contemporary, the question whether he meant by the phrase something which was without
limit or the quality
of being unlimited.
Limit and the unlimited are the ultimate notions, as being wider genera within which fall the odd and the even. The first passage quoted
seems to make
even though elsewhere Aristotle's language unlimited. suggests that odd and even were identical with limit and No doubt the language of the Pythagoreans themselves left room for
this clear,
ambiguity. In any case the connexion does not seem to us to be obvious. It is explained by Aristotle in terms of certain figures formed with
visually as dots. To metrical patterns was regular Pythagorean practice, as it was probably 1 the earliest practice among both the Greeks and other peoples. The
the numbers must be thought of represent numbers thus in the form of geo-
gnomon
1
its
name from
Burnet, EGP, 101, Cornford, P. and P. 8 (Nicomachus), and the statement of D.L. (vni, 12) that Pythagoras studied especially the arithmetical aspect of geometry. a The essential characteristic of a gnomon appears to have been that of making or containing
a right angle. Thus in Herodotus it is the upright pointer on a sundial, which must be at right angles to the surface. Secondly it was used for a carpenter's set-square, from which came its
Aristotle.
is
Again in the
it is
put round
does not alter* (i.e. in shape: it remains a square). The gnomon here is of the shape of the accompanying diagram. Cornford is not quite accurate when he says (paraphrasing a sentence of Heath's with reference to 15330): "The gnomon
by Aristotle as the figure which when added to a square increases but does not alter its form* (P. and P. 9, n. i). Aristotle's sentence does not exclude, as it would if it were a definition, the possibility of oblong gnomons. That the gnomon was essentially right-angled is illustrated by the terminology of Oenopides of Chios (mid fifth century : see DK, 41 13) as quoted by Proclus: *He calls the perpendicular in the ancient fashion "gnomonwise", because the gnomon also is at right angles to the horizon.' Euclid (Bk. n, def. 2) extended it to all parallelograms, and his language suggests that he was the first to do so. Later its use was even more widely extended. For fuller details see Heath, The Thirteen Books of Euclid, I, 171.
is
defined
its size
242
be represented by the
following:
Aristotle
meant by the words irepl TO Iv KCCI what? Or 'when the gnomons the other case') will probably never be
3
way
put
When
the series of
odd numbers
is
round the unit in the form of gnomons, the resulting figure is always a square (remains 'the same'); when the even numbers are set out in the same way, the relation between the sides of the figures formed offers
infinite variation.
(MetapL 986322,
the headings of 'limit' and 'unlimited' respectively. Later writers offer other explanations of the Pythagorean association of odd with limit
and even with unlimited, for example that even numbers can be divided into equal parts leaving, as it were, a blank in the middle^ whereas any attempt at halving an odd number is baulked by coming up
4 against a unit.
precise reason for the association is of interest to historians of mathematics, who may follow it up in the references here given, but is perhaps no longer to be ascertained with certainty. In any case it
The
originated in the visual, geometrical representation of numbers to the Pythagoreans. may proceed from
We
Since every number partakes of the nature of odd or even, these are the basic elements of number and in their turn exemplify
1
Ross
CR,
on Metapk. c>86ai8
Cornford, P. and P.
Kevf) XEbreroci
x&P
^ see ps.-Plutarch
$L quoted by
Burnet,
EGP,
288, n. 4.
In tine light of other texts this seems to be the most likely explanation of the superficially absurd statement preserved by Simplicius (JPhys. 455 .20) that what can be divided into equal and Taylor, y 288-9 parts can be bisected adinfinitum. For texts and discussion see Burnet,
4
EGP
CR, 1926,
i49f.
243
rise first
of
all
to the unit,
which
which it is the regarded as standing outside the number-series of 3 of odd and nature the itself in as combining 'principle (arche\ and
even.
from Aristotle's book on the Pytha(p. 22 Killer) quotes added to an even number it makes that the when goreans explanation it odd, but when added to an odd number makes it even hardly
Theo
as
a satisfactory explanation, since it applies to every odd number much as to the unit. 1 It does not seem possible to extract from
Aristotle's
c
words
at
that
the
Monad
is
opposite principles,
Metaph. 986 a 17 the meaning sought by Cornford, or product of, the two prior to, and not a resultant Odd or Limit, and Even or Unlimited'. 2 Cornford
of all things quotes Theo's description of the monad as 'the principle and the highest of all principles . that out of which come all things but
. .
which itself comes out of nothing, indivisible and potentially all things'. But Theo's testimony can hardly stand against Aristotle's. He was a Platonist, and elsewhere describes the monad in plainly Platonic terms as 'the intelligible form of the one'. The primacy of the One is asserted by other late writers, notably Eudorus (first century B.C., ap. Simpl.
Pkys. 181.10) and Alexander Polyhistor (D.L. vni, 24), but their testimony on the point has been shown to be more than doubtfuU The
and Neopythagoreans of their time were, under Stoic inclined to monism; this can be as definitely asserted influence, of Eudorus as of Theo. 4 With but a little subtracted, the later origin
Platonists
much
Rostagni in // Verio di Pitagora (pff.) makes great play with a fragment of Epicharmus DK), which in his submission implies a knowledge on the part of the comic poet of every detail of this Pythagorean scheme, thus vouching for its existence in the first half of the fifth century. The lines in question run: 'But if to an odd number, or if you like an even one, someone chooses to add a pebble, or to take one away from those that are there, do you think the number would remain the same?* To draw such far-reaching inferences from this bare sentence is hardly permissible, yet the existence of the doctrine at that time is not improbable. 2 CQ, 1923, 3 with n. i. He translates f djji<poTipcov elv ToOroov 'consists of both of these*, not
(2 in
from both*, while admitting that 'proceeds* is appropriate to the immediately following 5" dpiOpov k TOU &>6$. But even if this translation were possible, the One would still be a product of the Odd and the Even, and could in no sense be prior to them. 3 By Raven, P. and E. 14$. lamblichus claimed to have found it in Philolaus (DK, 4488), but his authority in such a matter is very doubtful. It was prominent in the Neopythagorean Nicomachus. 4 On Eudorus see H. Dorrie in Hermes, 1944, 25-39. *&s value as a source for pre-Platonic Pythagoreanism may be judged by the following extracts from this article: (p. 33) *Much of what Eudorus reports concerning Pythagorean doctrine comes directly from the Timaetts. . Many Platonic features appear in this account, much of it even reads like an anticipation of actual
proceeds
words, TOV
Neoplatonism.'
'
is
a Pytha-
244
the
Opposite?
'
of all principles ', itself out of Theo's account becomes consistent with Aristotle's; for nothing'), since all things are made of number, and the principles of number are the principles of all things, the unit, as the immediate principle of
likely ('highest
more than
number, may certainly be described as 'the principle of all things' and 'that out of which all things come*. That there are even more ultimate
principles does not affect this, any more than Aristotle's statement that things are made of numbers conflicts with his statement that the ele-
ments of numbers are the elements of all things. In this connexion, however, we find in Aristotle a reference to two divergent Pythagorean theories. Immediately after the passage we have been considering, he continues (986 a 22):
Others of this same school say that there are ten principles, which they arrange
in twin columns, namely:
mentioned
.How these principles may be brought into line with the causes we have [sc. Aristotle's own four causes] is not clearly explained by them;
but they appear to class the elements (oroixaoc, presumably referring to the pairs of principles enumerated) as matter, for they say that substance consists of and is formed from them as from internal constituents.
In
this
is
It is
though other
gorizing exegesis of the Phaedrus-myth*. One has also to take into consideration Eudorus's 34-6). attempt to read an esoteric meaning into Plato (Alex, in Met. p. 59 Hayduck, In general scholars would do well to heed the warning of H. D. SafTrey (Le TT. <JHA. dAristote^ sur la connaissance que nous pouvons avoir de etc., 1955, p. xi) : *J*avoue que je suis sceptique
Dome
1'ancien pythagorisme;
en tout cas je ne crois pas que Ton puisse se fonder sans d'infinies pre"cautions sur les Merits pythagoriciensdes premiers siecles de notre ere: ce sont tous d'inextricables melanges de ne*oplatonisme, de n&Dpythagorisme, de ne*oorphisme etc., et comment distinguer le
grain de
1'ivxaiel'
bon
245
all
thought
manifestations.
For
rooted in values; unity, limit, etc. appear on the same side as goodness because they are good, whereas plurality and the unlimited are bad. The religious belief in the essential unity of nature, and the
sophies
are present religious ideal of a unity of the soul with the divine kosmos, in every part of the system. So Aristotle wrote in the Ethics (iO96b 5) : 'The Pythagorean account of the good is more plausible, 1 in that they
column of goods', and again (no6b29): *As the Pythagoreans surmised, evil is a form of the unlimited, good of the limited/ One may go further and say that limit and unity are to be
equated with the male, the unlimited and plurality with the female element in nature. It is thus possible, when the time comes to describe
the making of the universe in physical terms, for the unit to appear in the form of a sperma (Metaph. 1091 a 16) reminiscent of the gonimon of
Anaximander
It
would appear then that the ultimate principles are the two contraries limit and the unlimited. With these are equated numerical oddness and evenness respectively, and they thus form the principles of the
number-series which in turn
things.
is
all
existing
Of the treatment
Aristotle:
some Pythagoreans derived it from a combination of limitodd with unlimited-even, whereas others constructed two columns of
which the unit appeared alongside limit, goodness, etc. These columns contain all their principles (in contrast to Alcmaeon, the Pythagoreans 'laid down how many and what they were'), and therefore include the principles of numbers, which all exemplify oddness
contraries in
Sc. than the Platonic: everywhere Aristotle distinguishes with assurance between the two, which is only to be expected and would not be worth mentioning were he not so often accused of confusing them.
1
246
Status
of the Unit
all
and evenness.
It is
Pythagoreans alike
defined (apeiron).
The
limited in opposition to the infinite or unonly difference between the two schools of
it
thought of limit
is
itself,
the other
saw
it
as the first
imposing
itself
on the
undifferentiated
of order and limit which was necessary to a kosmos within it. It has been thought (e.g. by Comford) produce that the Pythagoreans believed simultaneously in two distinct grades of unit or monad, the One which was a first as principle and
regarded
and the unit which began the number-series and was a product of higher principles. This is the view of Neopythagorean and Platonic 1 writers of Augustan and later times, like Eudorus who writes:
divine,
is one thing, and which opposed another, they call the monad/ (Aristotle uses one and monad' indifferently when speaking
One which is
is
c
of everything
is
of the Pythagoreans.) But since there is no warrant for this in Aristotle, for whom the varying status of the one reflected a difference of opinion between different branches of the school, its application to the Pythagoreans of Plato's time and earlier is very dubious. The way in which
Aristotle brings the table of contraries into connexion with Alcmaeon shows that the view which it represents was an early one, probably formulated within the lifetime of or soon and
his introduction
Pythagoras after; very of the main account, from which this is a divergence, as that of men 'contemporary with and earlier than* Leucippus and Democritus gives some ground for supposing that that account
represents a slightly later phase. In what sense the entities mentioned were principles, causes or constituents was something which baffled Aristotle , (pp. 237
above).
The
best illustration
is
probably the whole idea originated. The general principle applied by the Pythagoreans to the construction of a kosmos is that of the imposition of limit (peras) on the unlimited (to apeiron) to make the limited
Ap. SimpL Phys. 181 .28. The introductory SfjXov 6n betrays an inference of his own. uses the Platonic term *dyad* for what earlier Pythagoreans would have called apeiron. Eudorus see p. 244, n. 4, above.
1
He
On
247
Owing to the brilliant exposition by Pythagoras said have (if enough to justify giving him the credit) of the numerical, * of the scale, music proportional structure of the concordant notes now provided the paradigm of this principle at work. The whole field
{to peperasmenort).
I
9
of sound, ranging indefinitely in opposite directions high and low on this continuum when represents the unlimited. Limit is imposed
is
it
divided according to the relevant system of ratios, which reduces the whole to order, starting from the octave (sc. i :2, the unit and the first even number, both of which have their places in the table of archai). 'The infinite variety of quality in sound is reduced to order by the exact and simple law of ratio in quantity. The system so defined still
contains the unlimited element in the blank intervals between the notes;
is
no longer an
orderless continuum;
it is
confined
1 within an order, a cosmos, by the imposition of Limit or Measure/ That the Pythagoreans, as later sources affirm, reverenced the One
very probable. There would be no inconsistency in believing in two contrasting principles, both ultimate, but one good
as
God, or
divine,
is
Dox.
God
The
this dignity on the good one. That the verdict of the doxographic tradition (Aet. i, 7, 18, 302): 'Of the principles, Pythagoras said that the Monad was and the good, the true nature of the One, Mind itself; but the
indefinite
dyad
is
a daimon and
evil,
juxtaposition of
some
good and evil principles in this passage affords for rejecting the version of a first-century evidence positive
Eudorus that the One was
sole principle and the Unlimited secondary.* At this point, it is true, one begins to ask what 5 * precise sense of primary and 'secondary* one has in mind. Hitherto
Platonist like
or from
the one is not primary if we trust our earliest authority. Since, however, it stood for all that the Pythagoreans held in highest esteem limit, form,
goodness,
divine,
1
it
and in all probability was even at this period accounted certainly took the primary or highest place in the hierarchy,
etc.
Cornford, CQ, 1922, 145. Pointed out by Raven, P. and E. 18. Eudorus naturally connected the divinity of the One with its primacy among the principles (Simpl. loc. cit. L 19). The statement that it is divine is
*
repeated
by Hippolytus
(Ref.
I,
2, 2).
248
Monism
or
Dualism?
and the unlimited, evil, material principle with which it combined in the creation of numbers and the physical universe, though coexistent, was of secondary value and This would make all the easier
later modification
its
all else was derived, the doctrine which finds culmination in the inexpressible first principle of a Plotmus. On the interpretation here offered, Pythagoreanism before the time of Plato was frankly dualistic in its account of ultimate
principles,
unlike the Milesian systems, which were in intention monistic, although as we have seen the monism of this early stage of rational thought could not bear a critical The scrutiny. opposite view was taken by Cornford. He saw the Pythagoreans as believing in an ultimate One behind all else. From this were derived limit and the unlimited themselves,
although
unit
this ultimate
is
which
the
first
clearly described as
distinguished from the number, point or physical atom, since that is a product of these two opposite principles. Corn-
One
or
Monad must be
ford depended largely for this interpretation on the account compiled by Alexander Polyhistor from certain 'Pythagorean commentaries'
and excerpted by Diogenes, the dating of which has been the subject of prolonged controversy (see p. 201, n. 3, above). The conclusion reached here, which is essentially that of Mr Raven in his and
Pythagoreans
Ekancs, has the advantage of relying exclusively on Aristotle, with whose statements the idea of a fundamental monism is indeed hard to reconcile. Raven has shown that it is by no means necessary to see it even in Alexander's account (P. and E. I34f.)- The monistic theory,
involving as
it
One and
the unit
surely Platonic in character. Can we not point to its author, namely Speusippus, the Pythagorizing nephew and successor of Plato? In paraphrasing what Aristotle says about him at MetapL iO28b2i, his Greek commentator 1 attributes to
him a 'One-itselP
connexion
1
it is
(ocuroev) at tie head of the scale of reality. In this of interest that a tradition going back to Aristoxenus*
Metaph. 462.34. (See p. 257 n. i, below.) hence doubtless to Aristotle, whose pupil he was. Aristotle not only wrote books on Pythagoreanism, but was also interested in Persian religion. He wrote that according to the Magi there are two archai^ a good dcamon and an evil, the name of the one being Zeus and Oromasdes, and of the other Hades and Areimanios (Aristotle, fr. 6 Rose, p. 79 Ross, D.L. 8).
[Alex.] in
And
I,
249
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
associated Pythagoras with Zoroaster. It may be, as is generally thought, without historical foundation, but at least it is evidence that a resem-
blance between the Greek and Persian systems was remarked by the fourth century; and in the latter the powers of good and evil, light and
darkness,
pendent. the strength of the tradition are appended in a note below. Something must be added here to do justice to Cornford's point of view, based as it was on a singular insight into the minds of early
Ormuzd and Ahriman, were certainly coexistent and indeAs the matter has a certain intrinsic interest, some data on
which can best be described as the gift of a poetic imagination. there could not at any period instinctively, and rightly, felt that have been a real inconsistency between the scientific or rational side of the Pythagorean system and its religion. And as he says (P. and P. 4)
thinkers
He
'As a religious philosophy Pythagoreanism unquestionably attached central importance to the idea of unity, in particular the unity of all life,
divine,
human and
Unity was exalted and revered as the highest and best in the cosmos and the supreme object of human aspiration. Therefore, he argued, in their cosmogony also it must have been the sole starting-point, just as
the single arche of the Milesians was also the divine element in their
how
this
could be
so.
that
of the Milesians, he once said of it (in an unpublished lecture): 'The antagonism of the Many is harmonized and held together by philia
(that
is,
the
bond of kinship)
in this unity/
Here
his
own words
set
one wondering whether the unity which the Pythagoreans exalted as divine, and held forth as an example for men to follow, was perhaps not
an arche in the full Milesian sense but rather
as indeed
he seems to be
saying the unity of the complete and perfect kosmos^ which because it is a harmonia deserves above all are here things the name of God.
We
fill for ourselves the gaps in our of this nor is it to is meant what knowledge early period, easy express in our own terms. But is that for these my suggestion people the
principle of limit did indeed exist in the beginning, but was opposed by the formless and evil principle of the unlimited. By imposing itself on in a which I shall to later this, way try explain (pp. 266 ff.), it
produces
250
haphazard character, but in its main structure, as displayed to man by the harmonious motions of the heavenly bodies, it has achieved the
unity of a perfect organism.
beautiful (that
is
The kosmos, by virtue of its ordered and cosmic) nature, is divine. The good is in the end, the telo$i not the arche in the sense of the beginning. The point seems to be clinched by Aristotle, when we read (Metaph. lojzb^o): 'The
Pythagoreans suppose that supreme beauty and goodness are not present in the beginning: for, although the beginnings of plants and
animals are causes, beauty and perfection are rather in their outcome.' 1 In this way the religious need to identify unity with goodness and
words
does
divinity is satisfied without positing a unity Iv dpxtl, if we take those to mean 'in the beginning'. The goodness of the living universe
lie
in
its
is
unifying and harmonizing principle unlimited from the beginning; but it unity
is
only when
work
is
done that
achieved.
The
possibility
excited interest, and attempts have been made to establish connexions not only with Persia but also with India and even China (see ZN,
590, n. 2 and Ueberweg-Praechter, 26). Concerning these latter countries the remarks of Zeller (5 89-92) have not lost their force: the positive evidence is weak or non-existent, and the resemblances in doctrine are too general to warrant any definite conclusions, and were certainly current in Greece from a period which makes the hypothesis
of borrowing from the further East unlikely. In India some have been impressed by the occurrence of transmigration^ abstinence from no one can fail to flesh, and number-mysticism, and as for China,
be struck by the
1
superficial
Yang
are
doctrine to
phenomena
produced by
Curiously enough, this translation is CornforcTs, which he gives on p. 5 of P. and P. He uses it in the course of an argument about unity as the sole original principle in which it is difficult to follow him, for the religious need for unity in the beginning seems to vanish as we
read
it.
251
Pythagoras and
the interaction of the
the
Pythagoreans
or forces
two cosmic
140):
principles
whose
Chinese Philosophy
138.,
YANG
.Sunshine or light
masculinity
activity
Darkness or shadow
femininity
passivity
heat
cold
dryness hardness
wetness
softness
odd
Later
even
members of the Yin-Yang school tried to connect the five elements (water, fire, wood, metal, soil) with the Yang and the Yin are odd, of Yin even, and the through numbers. The numbers of Yang elements are produced from numbers. Dr Fung notes the remarkable
resemblance to Pythagorean theory, but emphasizes that this feature of the Chinese doctrine did not appear till later. G. Thomson (The First
out that there are differences as well as Philosophers, 266) has pointed
resemblances.
originate
if it
The
later
is a question which, the scope of this study. beyond case for Persian influence must be taken
lies in
more
though
the danger
overstating
it
The Greeks of
days were strongly inclined to represent their early philosophers as the pupils of the Orient, partly from the sense of age-old and
allured its western neighor Graeco-Roman, Hellenistic in their because own, bours, and partly times a syncretism between Greek and Oriental, in which philosophy
mysterious
tended to lose
the day*
itself in religion
fact the
order of
Consequently it of voyages study to a Thales or a Pythagoras. At the same time, since the sixth century B.C. was an enterprising age in which communications
to attribute oriental
were well developed and lengthy voyages freely undertaken for commercial and other purposes, such stories cannot be dismissed as improbable*
251
about Pythagoras, some acquaintance with the principles of the Mazdaean religion of Zoroaster is traceable in Greece to the fourth
century, not only, as
Koster, ancient sources.
J.
(W.
W.
have seen, in Aristotle, but also in Eudoxus Mythe de Platon, etc. 25 ). But let us turn to the
we
(i)
2, 12
(DK, 14
1)
unknown
went
litde later in the same chapter Hippolytus says: 'Pythagoras is said to have forbidden the eating of beans because Zaratas taught that in the original formation of the universe the bean was produced when the earth was still
9 in the course of solidifying and still putrid. This statement presumably does not go back to Aristoxenus, since he denied that forbade beans
Pythagoras seems to be an unintelligibly mutilated version of the tenet that beans and men had a common origin (Porph. FIP. 44, p, 184^
(p. 189, above).
It
above).
'Pythagoras consorted with the best of the Chaldaeans and Magi/) (c) Plut. De An. Procr. 2: 'And Zaratas the teacher of Pythagoras called this [sc. the indefinite dyad] the mother of number and the One its father/
We may compare the presence of male and female in the Pythagorean table
contraries
of
on
Whether
Plutarch had any warrant for attributing this to Zaratas is another question. (</) Apuleius, Flor. 15 (p. 21 Helm): 'Some say that when Pythagoras was taken to Egypt among the prisoners of Cambyses, he had as his teachers the Persian Magi and in particular Zoroastres, the master of all secret religious
lore.' (e) Id. ApoL 31 (p. 36 Helm): 'Most people believe that Pythagoras was a disciple of Zoroaster and correspondingly versed in magic.* (/) Porph. V.P* 12: 'Besides consorting with the other Chaldaeans he
went to Zaratas, who purified him of the defilements of his previous life and taught him the means whereby good men maintain purity and the explanation of nature and what were the first principles of all things/
Pythagoras and
(2)
the
Pythagoreans
General references
to
Magi and
Persia
.
.went to the Persian Magi.' and Magi.' (b) D.L. vin, 3: 'He also journeyed among the Chaldaeans to all above speak the truth, things (c) Porph. V.P. 41 : Pythagoras taught from the Magi, he learned as 'for God: for this was the one way to resemble resembles call the body of the god, whom they light, and his Oromasdes,
(a) Cic. Fin. v, 29, 87: 'Pythagoras.
soul truth'.
One
(J)
is
Iambi V.P. 19: Taken prisoner by Cambyses's men he was brought to Babylon, There he spent his time with the Magi to their mutual satishow to worship faction, was instructed in their sacred teaching and learned the gods in the most perfect way. In their company he also mastered the science of number and music and other subjects of study.' of the dead because as a (e) Ibid. 154: 'He forbade burning the bodies follower of the Magi he did not wish what is mortal to have any part in
anything divine/
One may compare further Pliny, N.H. xxv, 5, xxx, V.P. 6; Lydus, De Mens. p. 21 Wiinsch; Iambi. V.P. 151
Latins, as well as
thrace, etc.).
2; Porph.
(in
which
Chaldaeans and Magi are mentioned along with Celts, Iberians and
more homely
Samo-
tradition, in origin
certainly to Aristotle, that Pythagoras was directly instructed in religion by Zoroaster or some of the Persian Magi. Nevertheless any details
are
only from writers of Graeco-Roman date, and create a distinct impression that the belief was no more than a conjecture based
real
known
or fancied resemblances of doctrine. In fundamental principles there is a certain resemblance, if we are not disturbed by the fact that
ultimates in Zoroastrianism are personal gods, not impersonal even find an uncertainty principles like those of the Pythagoreans.
on
the
two
We
strictly described as
monotheistic or
Pythagoreans and
we
have upheld the monism of the have ourselves concluded that the principle of
how some
unity or limit was at least of higher value and importance than the other. 1 Similarly J. Duchesne-Guillemin writes of the Persian system: *Ce
1
254
avant tout
perieur aux deux Esprits qui s'affrontent. Il est le createur de toute chose D'un autre point de vue, le systeme apparait comme un dualisme: Ahura Mazdah est declare identique a son Esprit Benefique,
et c'est
en
effet celui-ci
il
cree seulement
un bonheur
les
hommes
la rebellion
des mediants.
.
du malheur.
Mauvais
that
is,
a deux maitres, deux createurs/ In stronger resemblance to Pythagoreanism, e in the subordination of theory to practice: Mais, plutot que de
still
Ainsi done, le
monde
disputer du monotheisme ou du dualisme de Zarathustra, il faut constater Fambiguite de son systeme et se rappeler qu'ii avait d'autres soucis que theoriques. Sa mission est d'agir et de faire agir: il reforme
les rites,
il
on
killing
and animal
On
the
existence des
other hand an essential belief of Pythagoras is lacking 'La preames n'est attestee en Iran que tardivement (op. dt. 101)
5
a fundamentally Hellenic character about Pythagorean philosophy which makes it unlikely that it owed much to Oriental
and there
sources.
is
bution to
As Duchesne-Guillemin justly says, it had its own contrimake to the formulation of that problem which the Greeks
above
rational
bequeathed to later Europe: the problem of reconciling the and die sensible worlds, the realms of being and of becoming. This problem arose from the incompatibility of two modes of cognition,
all
des inventions grecques, bien etrangeres a 'qui, tous deux, etaient Tlran: la connaissance mathematique (Pythagore) et la connaissance avaient developpe ces deux (les loniens). Cest parce qu'ils
physique
certain
sciences que les grecs, setds dans Fhistoire du monde, ont pu, a un moment, apercevoir la difference qui separe la connaissance
sensible et la connaissance rationnelle' (p. 98). So far as concerns mathematics, the statement that they
were a
Greek invention
is,
as
we have
seen, an exaggeration. In
this respect
Pythagoras and
from
(ii)
the
is
Pythagoreans
undeniable; but
it
did not
come
Second "stage: generation ofgeometrical figures from numbers* In his account from 'Pythagorean commentaries' Alexander Polyhistor
whole process of genesis by saying that from the monad combining with the unlimited spring numbers, from numbers points, from points lines, from lines plane figures, from plane figures solids;
describes the
and
finally,
from
of numbers from the prior elements limit and unlimited, as exemplified has now been dealt especially in oddness and evenness, and the unit,
with. Leaving until later the final stage, we have next to see whether the generation of geometrical figures from numbers can be traced back
form of Pythagoreanism which Plato knew, and whether anything can be said to make it more intelligible. Understanding is assisted if we remember the early habit, which lasted long with Greek mathematicians, of representing numbers in visible form, by rows of dots,
to the
letters
1 or pebbles arranged in regular patterns. It gave their arithmetic a geometrical flavour, and ensured that arithmetic and geometry were
for long more closely allied than they are today. Even now, the fact that a formula or equation can be represented geometrically as well as algebraically is often an aid to the mathematician, for whose under-
standing the double representation no longer digs the pitfalls which beset the pioneers of rational thought. I shall continue on the assumption that it is sufficient for our purpose
Pythagoreans in Aristotle, since he has of proved perfectly capable distinguishing non-Platonic Pythahis from of the master. (See in particular pp. 241, goreanism teaching
if
is
a belief
246, n.
i,
above.)
start by considering a passage which has already been in quoted part (p. 234). At Metaph. 1036 b 8 Aristotle says:
We may
Some are even in doubt about the circle and the triangle, surmising that it is not right to define them by lines and continuous space, but that these are
'Calculation with pebbles* (presumably on some sort of board or abacus) is mentioned by Herodotus as the normal method (n, 36). We still talk this language when we speak of numbers as and 'calculation* conceals the Latin word for pebble. 'figures',
1
the
name of Alexander of
says that this refers to the Pythagoreans, as is indeed for the plain, only other possibility is the school of Plato, and Aristotle distinguishes this in the immediately following lines with the words:
Aphrodisias
"But those
clear
who
'
gives a
Some
triangle.
They hold it wrong to define these in terms of lines, saying A circle * is a surface bounded by a single line', or A triangle is that bounded by three lines', or again, *A line is a continuous length extended in one dimension'.
For a line is to a circle or triangle as underlying matter, and so is continuity to a line, just as flesh and bone are to a man and bronze to a statue. If then we do not define a man in terms of bone and flesh, because these are his
material parts, neither
must we
nor
a line in terms of continuity. For this reason, viz. that the line and the continuous are as matter in the triangle, etc., they reduce all these to numbers,
which are not material nor have any substratum analogous to matter, but exist independently. Thus they say that the formula of the line is that of the number two; for seeing that two is the first product of division (i.e. the unit first divided into two, then into three and the numbers after that), if, they maintain, we are defining a line, we must say, not that it is a quantity divided [or extended] in one dimension* but that it is 'the first product of
*
division
for 'the
is.
first* is
line,
as continuity
According then to Aristotle, the Pythagoreans had a dim idea that or structure, things must be defined in terms of their essence, form and not of the material in which they were embodied: a statue is not but of its design and properly described in terms of bronze or stone
what
it
represents.
To them extension or
metrical figures, and the form could only be expressed in terms of numbers. Allowing for Aristotle's preoccupation with his own
scheme of causation,
this
means
1 Alex, in Met. 512.20 Hayduck. Only the commentary on books A to E is genuine, but in work. any future references the name of Alexander will be used for the whole
257
Pythagoras and
imposed on
is
the
Pythagoreans
extension in itself belonged to the realm of the unlimited, and limit was
it
numerical, pattern. I take next one of the passages in which Aristotle professes himself baffled by the confusions in Pythagorean thought (Metaph. 1092 b 8):
We
find
no
clear distinction
substance and being. It might be (i) in the sense of boundaries, as points are of magnitudes. In this sense Eurytus fixed the number of each entity,
one for man and another for horse, by imitating the forms of living things with pebbles, in the manner of those who attribute numbers to shapes like and everything triangle and square; or (2) because musical harmony, man, not are numbers That substance, nor else consist of a ratio of numbers
obvious : substance lies in the ratio, whereas number is the material constituent, e.g. number is the substance of bone or flesh only in the sense in which one says three parts offire to two of earth Again, a number,
the cause of form,
is
* *
.
whichever always the number 0/things portions of fire or earth, or is the ratio of one quantity to another in a mixture. substance whereas units
it is, is
ratio or
mixture of numbers,
According to Aristotle here, this might mean that all combined in a certain proportion. physical things consist of elements This was the method followed in the first half of the fifth century by
everything.
Empedocles,
especially
who though
certainly in the
Pythagorean tradition,
on
originality.
the religious side, was a philosopher of considerable In his fr. 96 he describes bone as being formed of a
harmonia of two parts of earth, two of water and four of fire. But then, Aristotle objects, it is this proportion (e.g. the whole formula 2 3) that
:
is
is
the essence or form, not the numbers two or three themselves. This an unfair distortion of the Pythagorean view, but although he tries
numbers are the material mind his more general and of the Pythagoreans, that they speak of numbers
by maintaining
that
The obvious meaning of Spot in the context If it needs defence, Raven, P. and E* 104.
this
by
were matter
endowed with
size
and
weight.
to Aristotle of establishing the doctrine that things are numbers was to suppose the structure of things to be on geometrical shapes, which in their turn could be described dependent
second method
known
in terms of numbers, each figure being assigned the minimum number of points required to contain it (two for a line, three for a etc.).
triangle,
mentions the attempt of the Pythagorean Eurytus 1 to apply this type of description to living creatures, which he characterizes explicitly
as
like triangle
He
By the use of his own terminology, Aristotle imports an unnecessary confusion into the thought of the early Pythagoreans. It is no use his
putting the question whether they employ numbers as the material or the formal causes of things, since they were innocent of the distinction.
Their more primitive meaning is clean Things are numbers, or, if you like, the basis of nature is numerical, because solid bodies are built up
their geometric
of surfaces, surfaces of planes, planes of lines and lines of points, and in view of number the Pythagoreans saw no difference
between points and units. 3 The essential concept is limit. In a number of other passages of the Metaphysics Aristotle tells us this plainly:
(a)
limits
of bodies, such
as surface
and
line and point or unit, are substances, rather than body and the solid.' ' () io9ob 5 : There are some who, because the point is the limit and end of a line, the line of a surface and the surface of a solid, hold it to be inescap-
See also 1 002 a 4 (second paragraph of quotation on pp. 240 f.), noticing how, as in the first passage here, unit and point are treated as synonymous when the Pythagoreans are in question.
(c)
Having
established as already
known
(i)
that
the line, from for the Pythagoreans the unit-point came first, line surface and from surface solid, and (ii) that they equated these with of the line, we numbers, one being the number of the point and two
from
it
For
whom see pp. 273 f, below. that must wait until Or, indeed, between unit-points and particles ; but
As Ross ad loc.
Alex,
notes, their
462.. 16) is
later
(Stage 3 of the
view
is
later.
(w Met.
mistaken.
259
may allow ourselves to consider other texts which by themselves might be thought to have less authority than Aristotle but do not in fact go beyond him, though they may show up further details of the scheme. The tenth chapter of the Theologumena Arithmeticae attributed to
lamblichus deals at length with the Decad, and contains, as might be of Neopythagorean expected, much mystical and theological matter
is carefully assigned type. In it we find, however, one passage which c sister Potone, who of Plato's the son to its source, namely Speusippus, succeeded him in the Academy before Xenocrates'. He is said to have
1
composed an elegant little work which he called Pythagorean Numbers, doctrine and especially incorporating the choicest parts of Pythagorean the writings of Philolaus'. The entire second half of this work was devoted to the properties of the number ten, with the object of showing that it thoroughly deserves its Pythagorean title of the full and perfect
number (cf. p.
wrote that
it
225, above), and in the course of his account Speusippus contains in itself, besides all the basic ratios (this seems to
the line, surface and solid; for one is a point, two a line, three a triangle and four a pyramid, and all these are primary and fundamental to the other
figures in each class'.
little later
he put
it
thus:
'The point
is
the
first principle leading to magnitude, the line the second, surface third and solid fourth/ 2 Aristotle gives us ample warrant for saying that this
doctrine did not originate with Speusippus; in all probability he found it in the writings of his favourite author Philolaus, who like any Pytha-
gorean would
embody much
source might be Archytas, for whom a work on the Decad is actually recorded (by Theo Smyrnaeus, DK, 44611). The scheme described, represented graphically as the Pythagoreans thought of it, is this:3
F. E. Robbins (writing in the introduction to d'Ooge's translation of Nicomachus's Intro A. Arithm. 1926, Sif.) argued that it is based almost entirely on Nicomachus. 2 TheoL Arith. pp. 84 and 85 de Falco. 3 As is more fully explained by Sextus, adv. Math, x, 280 (trans. Bury, with slight alterations) : * When three points are set down, two at an interval opposite to each other, and the third midway
260
The same
described
(c.
numbers and geometrical figures is by Neopythagorean writer Nicomachus of Gerasa 1 A.D. 100) in his Introduction to Arithmetic. In bk. n, ch. 6 he writes;
the
correlation between
Unity, then, occupying the place and character of a point, will be the beginning of intervals and of numbers, but not itself an interval or a number, just as the point is the beginning of a line, or an interval, but is not itself line or interval. Indeed, when a point is added to a point, it makes no increase,
for
is added to another non-dimensional not thereby have dimension Unity, therefore, is nondimensional and elementary, and dimension first is found and seen in 2, then
when
it
a non-dimensional thing
thing,
will
in 3, then in 4, and in succession in the following numbers; for 'dimension' that which is conceived of as between two limits. The first dimension
called 'line', for 'line' is that
is
is
which
is
Two diwhich
is
mensions are
directions.
that
which
is
extended in two
Three dimensions
And in
The
point, then, is the beginning of dimension, but not itself a dimension, and likewise the beginning of a line, but not itself a line; the line is the beginning of surface, but not surface, and the beginning of the two-dimensional, but not itself extended in two directions. Naturally, too, surface is the beginning of body, but not itself body, and likewise the beginning of the three-dimensional, but not itself extended in three directions. Exactly the same in numbers, unit is the beginning of all number that advances unit by unit in one direction; linear number is the beginning of plane number, which spreads out like a plane in more than one dimension; and plane number is
the beginning of solid number, which possesses a depth in the third dimension besides the original ones.
In the
first
no magnitude
passage Nicomachus emphasizes that the unit-point has at all, just as the line (or two) has no breadth and the
no depth. This was certainly a refinement on the belief of Pythagoras and his earliest followers, who clung to the more naive notion that a point was the smallest magnitude, and therefore that two
surface (three)
in the line formed from the two, but in another dimension, a plane is constructed. And the solid number four. For when the three points figure and body, like the pyramid, are classed under the are placed as I said before, and another point is placed upon them from above, there is constructed
it
Trans. d'Ooge.
26l
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
shortest line. points in juxtaposition were sufficient to constitute the Raven suggests (see especially P. and E. 161) that this too was a preand that the advance was the outcome of the Platonic
development,
If this
and in his annoyance with what he considered to be in any case an illogical philosophy would not be too scrupulous in keeping them apart. Referring to the Pythagorean 1 statement that 'two is the formula of the line', he says that continuity
Aristotle would be aware of both views,
is
number
Probably
line
of men
who
was
that
which stretched
between two
two points
line. placed side by side in themselves constituted a In the view, or views, so far described the progression has been read also of another method of building up arithmetical (i, 2, 3, 4).
We
geometrical figures,
(i, 2, 4,
totle,
is
which
8, i.e.
was known
to Aris-
of genuinely Pythagorean
but there must always remain a slight element of doubt whether it origin, as has been assumed with little or
2 recent English scholars. The context in Aristotle does not suggest this, Sextus Empiricus (adv. Math, x, 282) calls the method
no argument by
Pythagorean but a
Fried!.)
one than the other, and Proclus (EucL p. 97 describes the other as 'more Pythagorean'; and it must be
later
made
in the
freely accepted as
Pythagorean by most
later writers. Since, however, its pre-Platonic remains origin possible, it must be examined more closely. In the first book of the De Amma^ as part of the preliminary review
criticizes the
of the theories of his predecessors on the nature of the soul, Aristotle * theory that it is a self-moving number', which he not
unreasonably stigmatizes as 'much the most absurd'. After pointing out in a sentence or two the chief difficulties which he sees, he proceeds
(409 a 3):
surface,
lines,
Moreover since they say that a moving line generates a and a moving point a line, the movements of units will also be
is
'
Metaph. 1036!) 12, quoted above, p. 257. Cornford, P. and P. 12; Raven, P. and
K 106.
262
argued (i) disjointed, nonof the treatises (lecture-notes, etc.) that form the Aristotelian corpus this assumption is by no means necessary, (ii) that as he did in indivisible believing lines, Xenocrates could not without fundamental self-contradiction have held the doctrine here described.
literary character
may
Rodier (De An. 1900, n, 141) sees this possibly Xenocrates may have got over it
indivisibles
in his
of time and movement, a theory referred to in Arist. Pfys. 263 b 27. His translation, however, seems to reflect a continuing doubt e
mind
En
generally known as the fluxion theory, and is so referred to by Proclus (Joe. cit. p. 262, * above) in the words: Others have different ways of defining a line, some as the fluxion of a point, others as magnitude extended in one direction/ After a brief comment on these, he returns to what he calls
The theory
the 'more Pythagorean account' according to which the point is comto the the line to the number pared unit, two, the surface to three and 2 the solid to four. Sextus refers to fluxion in a number of He
places.
method, and twice he seems to confuse the two. His reference to fluxion in Math, vn, 99 is: We imagine a line (which
*
is
a length without breadth) as the flowing of a point, and breadth (i.e. surface without depth) as the flowing of a line; and by the flowing of a surface, body is generated/ At x, 281, after a description of the
point-line-triangle-pyramid sequence,
we read:
is formed from one point. This point by flowing by flowing makes a surface, and this when moved (Kivt|0ev, the same verb as is used by Aristotle in the De Ardma) into depth generates body in three dimensions. But this scheme of the Pythagoreans
that
body
produces a
line,
the line
e.g. Plut.
these passages
Pyrrh. in, 19 and 154, Math, iv, 4 f., vir, 99, x, 281. seem to rely on the same source.
that all
263
from
that
The
is only what we should expect, since Cornford it is (P. and P. 12) saw in this clearly a refinement on refinement the immediate answer to the criticisms of Zeno of Elea,
That
it
came
later
which were
directed against the primitive Pythagorean conception of of discrete points which magnitudes as formed by the juxtaposition must themselves have been conceived as having extension. In Mr
in contact to the conception of it as that consisting solely of two points which stretched between two points. This advance he puts down to the
not yet the fluxion theory, which he would attribute to *a generation of Pythagoreans approxiit from them' mately contemporary with the Platonists who borrowed for seen admitting yet grounds (P. and E. 109). We have perhaps
generation of Philolaus and Eurytus.
It is
another possibility, namely that it was elaborated in the Academy of Plato's time, possibly by Xenocrates, Like much other Platonic
doctrine,
1
it
The Platonic term for what the Pythagoreans called the unlimited (Ar. Metaph. 987 b 25). may be of some interest to compare a view of Isaac Newton, who wrote: *I consider mathematical quantities in this place not as consisting of very small parts, hut as described by a conIt
tinuous motion. Lines are described, and thereby generated, not by the apposition of parts, but by the continued motion of points; superficies by the motion of lines; solids by the motion of superficies; angles by the rotation of the sides; portions of time by a continual flux; and so on in other quantities/ These geneses', Newton adds, 'really take place in the nature of things, and are daily seen in the motion of bodies." (Two Treatises on the Quadrature of Curves, and Analysis by Equations of an Infinite Number ofTerms, trans. John Stewart (London, 1745), * Quoted by M. G. Evans, Journ. Hist. Ideas, 1955, 556.)
*
264
in Pythagoreanism,
made
their
a position to know the true state of affairs is Aristotle, and in his single reference to the fluxion theory he not only does not attribute it to the
it is
is that the fluxion theory of the generation of or whether not Zeno's geometrical figures, arguments had anything to do with it, is designed as a solution of the problem of incommensurable 1 magnitudes. This arose from the discovery of the incommensurability
What
seems certain
of the diagonal of a square with its sides, which would follow on the > 'theorem of Pythagoras (whenever that was first enunciated by * Greeks) and dealt a blow to the earlier Pythagorean view that things
are numbers',
i.e.
No
proportion
*> V I 7> t^iat of ^2 being akeadyloiown before Ws time. Most probable the conclusion of van der Waerden (Math. Anna/en, 1948, 151-3) that the proof of the irrationof their theory ality of */2 was made before 420, perhaps about 450, by Pythagoreans, on the basis
of odd and even numbers. (Cf. the proof given by Aristotle, An. Pr. 41 326, that if the diagonal were commensurable the same number would have to be both odd and even.) The late dating of E. Frank (not before 400, Plato u. d. sog. Pyth. 228 f) is now generally discredited. For any interested in following up the question of irrationals in Greek thought, the following additional references may be useful: Heath, Hist. Gr. Maths. I, 154-5; Taylor, Timaeus, 366$.; O. Becker, Gnomon, 1955, 267; E. Brehier, tudes de Phil. Antique, 48 (discussing the views of P.-H. Michel); G. Junge, Class, et Med. 1958, 41-?*; A. Wasserstein, C<2, 1958, 178 f.
165
(cosmogony).
'From
solid figures
come
The solids Pythagorean notebooks used by Alexander (p. 201, above). themselves were imagined as built out of numbers, and so, as Aristotle of number not, like the Platonists, 'as says, the Pythagoreans conceived
as being composed existing apart from sensible things, which they regard of it. They in fact construct the whole universe out of numbers, not
however
monadic numbers, for they suppose the units to have magnitude' (Metaph. io8ob 16, quoted above, p. 234). Aristotle cannot conceal his contempt for this misguided and illogical How can it be right to treat numbers and their elements as
truly
procedure.
if
they had magnitude? Even granted this, bodies with physical properties like weight?
tell us nothing explanation account for motion and change? 'They about fire or earth or the other bodies of this kind because, unless I am
as such.' mistaken, they have nothing to say about perceptible bodies It is easy to share Aristotle's irritation. So far, we have seemed to
abstractions, in
of solids out of points, lines and legitimately speak of the construction and solids. If surfaces, or the progression of points into lines, surfaces
we
'from solid figures sensible could as easily grant the next step bodies* we could see plainly how, for the early Pythagoreans at
least, 'things
were numbers'.
How was
it
done?
of Pythagorean cosmogony. Moreover, inadequate as the sources are, they leave no doubt that (as might be expected in the circumstances)
was no single, consistent system to discover. Different people, not necessarily at different periods, offered different accounts of the relation between the physical world and numbers (geometrical figures).
there
by assigning to each of to is, presumably, elementary particles of them) the shape of one of the regular solids. The fifth of these, the dodecahedron, was assigned to the enveloping cosmos or ouranos itself. It has
the four elements (that
Metaph. 990 a 1 6. Since there is no doubt that the Pythagoreans did say something about and the other physical elements, I take Aristotle to mean that they had nothing to add to our knowledge about them, because in his view to relate each one to a mathematical solid threw no light whatever on their real nature. One may compare the common use of the phrase o\)5v Agyeiv.
fire
1
266
Solids
and Elements
been thought unlikely that this theory could have been held by Pythagoras or his immediate followers, on the grounds that the regular solids
were probably not all recognized until later and that the four elements 1 appear to have been first explicitly distinguished by Empedocles. The
geometrical structure of the elements is not mentioned as a Pythagorean doctrine by Aristotle, though he criticizes it at length as it is
given by Plato in the Timaeus (De Caelo^ m, chh. 7 and 8), and knowledge of it doubtless lies behind his strictures on the Pythagoreans for
giving only mathematical accounts of physical bodies. Even if the date of the doctrine cannot be finally settled, to discuss it raises some problems of considerable interest in themselves. Aetius (based on Theophrastus) ascribes
*
it
5,
DK, 44^5):
There being
goras says that earth is made from the cube, fire from the pyramid, air from the octahedron, and water from the eicosahedron, and from the
dodecahedron
is
made
The
attribution to
Pythagoras himself is common form and can be ignored. But the doctrine recurs in words attributed to Philolaus, and since it is undoubtedly Pythagorean, known to Plato and yet hardly primitive, it
must be accepted
it
need not prejudge the question of the authenticity of other accept * fragments.) The fragment of Philolaus runs: The bodies in the sphere of the sphere.' 2 It implies the regular solids of the Aetius passage, and prima facie at least would seem to correlate them with five elements. The question is,
are five:
fire,
air,
and
therefore,
known
of the regular solids are employed by Plato in the cosmogony Timaeus, where, as in the passage quoted above, four of them are
The
fifth
this point, however, cf. the remarks on pp. inf., above. Fr. 12, text as in Bumet, EGP, 283, n. 3. The normal meaning of 6Axd$ was a cargo-boat. LSJ think its meaning here is active, that interpret it as passive (*a ship which is towed*), but
*
On
DK
which
z
cosmic sphere, comparing & yfjs OXTJPWC in Eur. Tro. 884. Wilamowitz (Platon, n , 91) emended to 6Aic6$, which can mean a coil (volumen), and so the rounded mass of the sphere * itself. Perhaps cf. rather OrpL Hymn 87, 3 H^OC^lv . . . Kod CTGOUOTOS 6XK6v ? in the sense of the body's
carries the
bulk* (not, as Rostagni takes it, as a synonym for yvtf\). It is of course a peculiarity of the five solids that they can be inscribed in a sphere.
267
Pythagoras and
whole.
the
Pythagoreans
therefore thought that the scheme was Plato's invention, falsely ascribed by later compilers to the Pythagoreans. It is more probable that Plato was here, as in so much else, adopting and
Some have
elaborating Pythagorean notions. The statement in Aetius must go back to Theophrastus (though with 'the Pythagoreans' in place of 'Pytha5
goras
n. 2),
on
this point.
Simplicius,
who is unlikely to have been mistaken too, who had Aristotle's treatise on the
fire is
composed Pythagoreans to draw on, notes that according to them of pyramids. 1 The elaboration with which Plato works out the scheme,
and the immense authority of the Timaeus, would naturally lead to the
appellation 'Platonic figures' in later antiquity. Proclus says that Pythagoras himself 'discovered the construction of
the five cosmic figures' (EucL 65 Fried!., DK, 14, 6 a). Their theoretical construction must have come much later, and that of the octahedron
and eicosahedron
is
369
B.C.
scholiast
on Euclid
book xin
says that the so-called five Platonic bodies did not originate
with Plato, but that the cube, pyramid and dodecahedron came from the Pythagoreans, the other two from Theaetetus (EucL v, 654 Heiberg). The tradition is difficult to evaluate, since the construction of
the octahedron
is
known long
dodecahedron, and could certainly have been carried out on principles before Theaetetus? The latter is, however, elsewhere
placed earlier in Pythagorean history by the story of the punishment of Hippasus because he 'first drew the sphere constructed out of twelve pentagons' (Iambi. V.P. 88, DK, 18, 4). Both Plato and Philolaus (if
the doctrine of the fragment be rightly attributed to him) equate the dodecahedron and the sphere, and this passage is more explicit about the
of the phrase in the Phaedo in which Plato compares the spherical earth made of twelve pieces of leather*. They are brought in
something
familiar, so
it
practice in Plato's
time to make balls by stitching together twelve pentagonal pieces of leather in the form of a dodecahedron, which when stuffed would fill
1
Simpl.
*
De
Cornford, P. and P. 23
f.
Cf.
on
this Burner,
EGP,
268
Using the same phrase as Plato, Plutarch brings the figures together when he describes the dodecahedron as being, with its blunt angles, "flexible, and becoming by distention round like the balls made of twelve pieces of leather* (Qu. Plat. 10030).
different colours.
two
Much
which
discussion has been devoted to the question of the date at 1 the theoretical construction of the regular solids was achieved.
But to equate them with the elements no more is absolutely necessary than a knowledge of their existence. This might have been gained in the first place from observation of their occurrence in nature in the
form of mineral
crystals.
To
may have
accomplished be raised objection, admittedly, might against the claim that the Philolaic' scheme need imply no more than a know-
One
ledge of the existence of the solids: they are referred to in the fragment as 'the bodies in the sphere*, and if this is a reference to the regular
solids at
all, it
all
be
inscribed in a sphere. In Euclid, however (xm, 13), the construction of the solids and their inscription in a sphere are treated as one and the
same problem. The objection is perhaps not fatal (though it does suggest that the actual wording is not Philolaus' s), and on balance the evidence inclines us to believe that the correlation of solids and elements
for Philolaus.
More than
that
it
The
which
It
Philolaic fragment speaks of five bodies in the sphere, four of are the four elements as recognized since the time of Empedocles.
if its
looks therefore as
fifth
element, and one would trine described by Aetius did the same.
and
what
is its
bearing on the ascription of the doctrine to Philolaus? To base a cosmogony on the five regular solids, it was not absolutely
1
For a
full
RE,
s.v.
'Theaetetus*,
2. Reilie,
VAI,
Raven, P. and E. 151. Note also that, in the opinion of Heath, the method by which Plato constructs the solids in the Timaeus contains nothing that would have been of the regular beyond Pythagoras or the Pythagoreans provided that they knew the construction io<Sff. pentagon. See also discussion in Manual of Gk. Math. 1 P. 226, n. 2, above. Moreover a regular dodecahedron of Etruscan origin, discovered in to date from before 500 B.C. (Heath, Manual of Gk. MatL 107). Italy near Padua, is thought
1363 ff.
More
briefly
269
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
Plato in the Timaeus reproduces necessary to believe in five elements. the Philolaic scheme so exactly as to have given grounds for the sus-
picion that
it
originated with
this dialogue associate the dodePythagoreanism. Yet he does not in cahedron with a separate element, although he says that it was used by of the four elements but as the shape of the the Creator not for
any whole cosmos which contains them all. The earliest unambiguous mentions of the fifth element in extant literature are in the Epinomis Plato himself is by an immediate pupil) and of course if not
(which
by
in Aristotle;
"
identify
it
with
aither.
In the
classified as a species
is
of air. 1
The
fifth
body'
(Tretrrrrov
oxoua)
who
its
in the second
and
third chapters
its
existence
and describes
nature.
which had earlier been thought to consist of fire. For Aristotle the elements were distinguished by having different natural places and
natural place of aither is at the circumference of the and its natural motion is not, like that of fire, rectispherical universe linear in an upward or outward direction, but circular. This is the
motions.
The
earliest
*
body, but in the Epinomis (Joe. cit.} we read: There are five bodies, which we must call fire and water, thirdly and fifthly aither. air, fourthly earth, Can we take this teaching even further back? Apart from the
reasoned case for a
fifth
9
not wholly disproved, that the Epinomis itself, which has come down to us under Plato's name, might actually be a work of his
possibility,
old age, there is excellent evidence that, in spite of what he said in the Timaeus , he himself came to believe in a fifth element. It consists of a
direct quotation
from
his pupil
on
because Plato [Aristotle] call it a fifth substance? Surely too declares the substance of the heaven to be distinct from the four sublunary elements, since he assigned to it the dodecahedron and delineated
He too
is
who
in his
life
of Plato
De
27O
'Thus then he classified living creatures into genera and species, and divided them in every way until he came to their elements, which he called five shapes and bodies, dither, fire, water, earth, and air.' So for Plato too the aither is a separate fifth simple body apart from the four elements.
Simplicius himself seems to argue that because in the Timaeus Plato employs the five solids, he must necessarily have posited five elements.
This would indeed be reasonable, if only the text of the Timaeus did not seem to deny it, and it is difficult to believe that Plato remained to the end of his days in the uncomfortable position of having five ele-
mentary solids and only four elementary bodies to relate to them. Here Xenocrates, who ought to have known, steps in with the positive
information that at some time Plato himself distinguished the aither from the other elements. It is not usually remarked that the doctrine
of the five elements in the Epinomis is not identical with that of Aristotle,
is
For
Aristotle, dither
the top of the scale, the divine substance of which the stars are made. In the Epinomis the 'visible gods' who constitute the highest
',
of divine being have bodies of fire. Aither is the substance of the daimones, a slightly inferior class of divinity intermediate between those
class
latter.
Indeed one
made
to
do
Although five kinds of body are distinguished, this is not far from the point of view of the Timaeus^ where aither is 'the brightest and clearest kind of air', which in its lower reaches tails off into fog and murk. In
thought aither had of course been identified both with air (we find the words used interchangeably by the poets) and with fire, as by
earlier
Anaxagoras.
element in Greek thought was a gradual process. In bare outline, a common conception of the universe seems to have been shared by most religious and philosophical
truth
is
The
that the
emergence of a
fifth
The cosmos, a sphere bounded the the the contains conflicting 'opposites' (that is primarily by sky, in more the which the and the wet developed dry), hot, the cold,
thinkers in the centuries before Plato.
thought of Empedocles became the four root-substances earth, water, air and fire. The mutually destructive nature of these elements ensures that the creatures compounded of them shall be mortal. But this
271
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
cosmic sphere is not the whole of existence. It floats, as it were, in a circumambient substance of indefinite extent. This 'surrounding' and (irepiexov) was of a purer and higher nature, everlasting, alive,
intelligent
air of Anaximenes and Diogenes of apeiron of Anaximander, the of Heraclitus (pp. 470 , Apollonia, perhaps also to the logos-fire
below).
The Pythagoreans
it
and there are grounds for (pp. 277 ff., below), for Orphic or similar religious thinking that the dogmatic basis 1 the same, Thus the Italian scholar systems of a mystical tendency was was justified in writing, with reference to the opinion of
Rostagni
Eva Sachs:
Now
a question of doctrine in the true and proper sense, something as the doxographers understood it, the author is schematized formal and of Platonic and Aristotelian in saying that this is the fruit certainly right
if it is
experience.
this doctrine
were
all
in exis-
the primitive Pythagoreans, inastence, under varying formulations, among much as they answered to a universal mystical intuition. In fact the irepiexov of Anaximander, the dip ('air') ('surrounding') and the oorsipov ('infinite') of Anaximenes, the orrapov Trva/noc ('infinite breath') of the Pythagoreans and so forth were essentially one and the same thing that which sooner or
later
was
called aither
and the
fifth
element.
When
therefore
we
universe began 'from fire and the fifth element' (n, 6, 2, Dox. 333), we need not dismiss the statement as wholly anachronistic in substance,
because the Pythagoreans before Plato's time would not have used the 5 * as Aetius a little phrase fifth element . They probably spoke rather, later in his epitome (n, 6, 5) makes Pythagoras speak, of the four bodies
and the sphere of the whole. This no doubt implies that the sphere is of a substance different from the four, as do the words of Plato also.
When Plato
made
out of four of the regular solids, and used the fifth for 'the whole', then whatever he may subsequently say about the nature of dither, we
For further evidence on this matter see Guthrie, Harv. Theol. Rev. 1952, 87 ff. It is perhaps worth remarking that Phaedo, IO^A-IIOB contains as vivid an expression as one could wish of the distinction between aer and either as different substances. * Verio di P. 58, n. I (translated).
1
272
we may
was known
to
Theophrastus
tion
was
correct.
genuine Pythagorean doctrine, and that his informaIt may have originated with Philolaus himself, but
2
on
that
positive.
Most of the
from
their ultimate
arche to the infinite variety of nature by two stages. From the arche y or original 'everything together', there evolved first the primary
opposites, or in later systems the four elements; and from them again the world of organic and other natural substances. For the Pythagoreans further stages were involved, since their archai went back even beyond
number
to the elements of
number; but
they derived from these archai first of all, through the medium of geometrical figures, the primary forms of matter, or physical elements. One at
least
creatures like
of them tried to apply the numerical framework further, to organic men and horses. This was Eurytus, who according to our
sources (which go back to Aristoxenus) was a Pythagorean from South of Pythagoreans, Italy and a pupil of Philolaus, The last generation
including Echecrates to
last
whom in Plato's
hours of Socrates, were said to have been disciples of these two.3 Theophrastus learned of the theory of Eurytus from Plato's contem-
porary Archytas of Tarentum, who was presumably Aristode's source also. In one of his numerous complaints about the Pythagoreans,
Aristotle says (Metaph. lopibS):
it
clear in
of
substances and of existence, whether as boundaries, in the way that points are of magnitudes, and after the manner of Eurytus, who laid down which
1
De JS,
Cornford seems to have wavered. See Plato's Cosmology (1937)* *io *So far as we know, the assignment of these figures to the primary bodies is due to Plato and had not been anticipated by 15, n. 2, *It is not impossible that the shapes of the regular any earlier thinker*, and P. and solids may have been associated with the elements before Plato*.
Some may even yet remain unconvinced that the whole thing was not an invention of Plato.
(DK,
45, i,
44 A 4).
273
Pythagoras and
number belongs
that
to
the
Pythagoreans
number of a man and
which thing
of a horse
(like those
who
with pebbles representing the forms of living things reduce numbers to triangular and square figures) or ----
by
brief essay on MetaTheophrastus makes a similar statement in his have laid down a physks (ed. Ross and Fobes, p. 13). When people he says, one might expect them to go on to first principle or principles,
explain
all
that follows
and then stop; 'for this betokens a competent do what Archytas once said Eurytus did by arranging certain pebbles: he said (according to Archytas) that this is the number of man, this of
horse, and this of something else'.
made less
Assume
360.
red,
curious) in
explained in
(DK,
45, 3):
number of man
is
Having put this forward he would take 250 pebbles, and in general of a great variety of colours. Then he coated the wall 1 with whitewash and, having made a shaded drawing of a man or a plant, he stuck pebbles in it, some in the face, others in the hands, and others in other off the sketched-in representation of a man with parts. Thus he finished a man. pebbles equal in number to the units which in his view defined
As
a pupil of Philolaus, Eurytus must have been living and working about the end of the fifth century. He seems to have attempted an extension to natural species of the particular Pythagorean doctrine
which explained geometrical figures numerically by equating the line with 2, triangle with 3 and pyramid with 4 because these are the
points required to define their structure. The projection of this doctrine into the physical world by the construction of the physical elements out of regular solids would encourage the
minimum number of
belief that a simple counting of boundary-points could explain organic nature also. Hence his demonstration of the 'number of man* by the
minimum number of points necessary to ensure that the surfaces formed by joining them would represent a man and nothing else. Admittedly
was a method of drawing which at a distance produced the but when looked at close up was unintelligible. It was occasionally used for an outline-drawing, but that is much the less likely meaning here.
that awaypt^pta
illusion
1
Usage shows
of solid
reality,
274
Eurytus
this is
times been accused, namely drawing pictures with pebbles and claiming that thereby he was determining the number of unit-atoms that they
was not the way he worked is proved by Aristotle's who treat numbers as boundaries (opoi). 1 At the same time, the arbitrary and subjective nature of the method (even granted the use of different-coloured pebbles) shows the naivete of which a Pythagorean was capable, even in the late fifth or early fourth century, when it came to applying his mathematical explanations
association of him with those
to the nature of the physical world. Aristotle very seldom mentions an individual Pythagorean by name, which suggests that Eurytus's demonstration of how 'things' could be
numbers was
peculiar to him.
Immediately after
it
he mentions an
alternative explanation, that the differences between qualities like white, sweet and hot are attributable to different ratios of numbers. He
illustrates this in the careless
is
often content
these, to him, rather ridiculous beliefs are in question: 'The essence of flesh or bone is number in this way: three parts of Ike to
when
two of
For Pythagoreans the essential difference between different kinds of body lay in the harmonia or logos in which the elements were blended. The elements themselves were put together from
earth.'*
mathematically defined figures, and so 'the whole universe is a harmonia and a number'. This is how the limit is composed which makes it
a cosmos and so good, and in so far as the elements are not mixed in mathematical proportion we have a residue of chaos, evil, ugliness, illhealth and so forth. It is a view of the world of which the best extant
exposition
objections
is
Plato's Timaeus.
felt
by
Aristotle to such a
that
number and
1
ratio are
The interpretation
That those of
See Metaph.
whom Aristotle is speaking did indeed think in this way he makes clearer elsewhere.
I028bi6 and 1090!) 5 (quoted above, p. 259). a So Ross. Jaeger's version of the text is olov crapK6$ f^ 6oroO dpi6&i6s* fj 8* oOola oOrco, Tpia is that for flesh Trupos yfis 6 5uo, which I find difficult to translate. Whether the ratio mentioned or bone Aristotle does not deign to make clear, but since Empedocles is nowadays often brought in at this point, it should be noted that the formula which he gives for bone is not this, but 4 of fire to 2, each of earth and water. (See fr. 96.)
275
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
into everything else/ that the good in a mixture has nothing to do with its being in a strict arithmetical or geometrical proportion: 'honey-
water
is
no more wholesome
if
These only help us to form an opinion of what the doctrine is likely to have been. In essentials it is a view which was basic to Pythagoreanism from its even if the correlation of elements with regular
beginnings,
solids
was a
later refinement.
some valuable
'
hints in Aristotle,
later writers.
certain extent
from
and pay close attention to they speak of the generation of the universe, with abstract, of events the actual course *, mistakenly confusing physical
numerical
reality.
Elsewhere he says a
little
more about
this process.
The
(a) Metapk. 1091312: 'It is absurd, too, or rather impossible, to suppose the generation of numbers, for they are eternal. Yet the question whether or not the Pythagoreans suppose it admits of no doubt. They say plainly that
when
to be drawn in and limited by world and wish to be understood in a physical sense, we must examine them in that connexion and dismiss them from the present inquiry* \sc* which is
whether from planes or surfaces or the nearest parts of the infinite at once began the limit. However, since they are making a
concerned with abstract principles], (b) Phys. 20336: 'But [sc. in distinction from Plato] the Pythagoreans for they do not reckon number place the infinite among perceptible things
and say that what is outside the heaven is infinite.' 3 (c) Metapk. 1092332: Here, in the course of considering, and rejecting, a number of ways in which numbers might be thought to be generated from prior principles, Aristotle says: 'Should we think of it as from seed? But nothing can emerge from that which is indivisible. (J) To the mentions of seed in two of the above passages may be added
separate
from these
Raven suggests (P. and E. 162) that the mutual transformation of the elements may in fact have been already a feature of Pythagorean theory. It is ascribed to it by Alexander Polyhistor in terms which some have thought to smack of Stoicism: T& oroixelcc. .& nerocpdAAsiv xod TpliTa6oci Si' 6Xou (D.L. vin, 25).
.
Or
firoipov F,
SimpL; retained by
276
Cosmogony
p. 97 Hiller. Here in his list of different interpretations of the Pythagorean tetractys Theon says: 'The sixth tetractys is that of growing things. The seed is analogous to a unit and a point, growth in length to 2 and a line, in breadth to 3 and a surface, in thickness to 4 and a solid.'
(e) Aristotle, Pfys. 21 3 biz (during a general discussion of the opinions of his predecessors on the subject of void): 'The Pythagoreans also said that void exists, and that it enters the universe from the infinite breath, the
Theon of Smyrna,
universe being supposed to breathe in the actual void, 1 which keeps different kinds of things apart; for they define void as that which separates and
divides things that are next to each other. This happens
first
in
numbers; the
void divides
their nature/
(/) Simplicius in his commentary paraphrases the passage of the Physics thus (651 .26): 'They said that the void enters the cosmos as if it breathed in a sort of breath from that which lies outside.'
(g) In illustration of the same passage Stobaeus quotes
from
Aristotle's
own
verse
lost treatise
first
*In the
is
on Pythagoreanism (Stob. EcL I, 18, ic (DK, I, 460, 3)): book on the philosophy of Pythagoras he writes that the uni-
which
(Ji)
unique, and that from the infinite it draws in time, breath, and void distinguishes the places of separate things' (Ar. fr. 201 Rose). Aet. n, 9, i (Dox, 338): 'The followers of Pythagoras say that outside
is
cosmos breathes.*
elements of the world are numbers. These, as we know, limit and unlimited, odd are themselves constituted of prior elements
The prime
but from the point of view of cosmogony *in the beginning was the One*. 'They suppose their monads to have magnitude,'
and even
(MetapL io8obi9),
'but
how
the
first
5
unit with magnitude was constructed they seem at a loss to explain. Their accounts did not satisfy him, but he is not likely to have invented
of planes, in
which case
it
complex
as
a pyramid. On Pythagorean principles this might be expected to be the number 4, not i, and Theon may have been more correct in Aristotle is obviously speaking carelessly, equating it with the point. but the Pythagoreans themselves were highly arbitrary and inconsistent in their equation
1
tions
1
Ross in retting the MS. reading TTVEUIKXTOS. Diels's seem unnecessary, as well as having no authority (for the amounts to nothing; see Ross*s note ad loc^).
I follow
E* of apparatus
277
solid,
fire.
is
to Aristotle
interesting.
The first
unit
consisted of a seed, the seed of the world, like \htgonimon attributed to What follows in passage (a) above, as well as what is
number in
(1}
to
be understood,
as
and elsewhere, shows that this is how the unit both a number and the nucleus of the physical
world.
old poetic analogy between the world and a living creature can be traced from the anthropomorphic Ouranos of Hesiod through the
Presocratic philosophers
side
The
down
idea
their belief in the kinship of all life. The well put by Sextus in a statement which, as Cornford and Delatte recognized, preserves the genuine spirit of early Pythagoreanism. 'The
of Pythagoreanism and
is
followers of Pythagoras and Empedocles, and most of the Italian philosophers, say that there is a certain community uniting us not only with
each other and with the gods but even with the brute creation. There is in fact one breath pervading the whole cosmos like soul, and uniting us
with them.' 1 Nothing could be more natural than that the world should grow from seed like any other living creature. The formation of a
as the imposition
equally as the impregnation of female matter by the form-giving sperm of the male. One may compare the inclusion of male with limit and
female with unlimited in the table of opposites. 2 How the unit-seed was sown in the Unlimited we know no more than
Once there, it grew by drawing in the Unlimited outside it and assimilating it, that is, conforming it to limit and giving it numerical
Aristotle.
physical side of this process (which mathematically the generation of the number-series) resembles breathing, the Unlimited being called pneuma as well as kenon (emptiness, void).
structure.
The
is
considered
As the first act of die newly-born universe, this has some resemblance 3 to the account of animal birth given by the Pythagorean Philolaus.
Math, ix, 127. C p. 200, n. 2, above. P. 245, above. See Comford, P. and P. 19 for the importance of the image of father, mother and seed In early philosophy. 3 Preserved in the extracts from the medical doxography of Aristotle's pupil Menon which we have in the papyrus Anon* Lonfmensis (ed. Diels, Berlin, 1893, W. H. S. Jones,
1
Cambridge,
8 . 8 S.
278
Cosmogony
the whole body of the Hence "immediately after birth the animal draws in breath from outside, which is cold, and then again discharges it like a debt*. This is done in order that the heat of the body may be cooled
new-born
creature.
1 'by the drawing-in of this imported breath'. The parallel in all probability extends to the heat, the unit-seed of the world being imagined
cosmogony too, therefore, one purpose of the breathing of the nascent cosmos may have been to cool this fire in order to generate the other elements; but of this the sources say nothing.
In detail, the cosmogony that we are now considering was probably more primitive than that of Philolaus, though in its beginnings his was no doubt sufficiently similar to exhibit the same parallel with his ideas on animal birth. Some features of the present accounts seem to belong more nearly to the beginning than the end of the fifth century,
thus bringing us fairly close to the lifetime of Pythagoras. The failure of the earlier natural philosophers to distinguish empty space from some
form of corporeal substance was one of the things which laid them open to devastating criticism from Parmenides, who argued that space or what exists', i.e. does not exist, and that without it there can be no movement. The atomists were the first to distinguish explicitly between body and space, in fact Empedocles reiterated
void
is
'not
Parmenides's denial that empty space could exist (fr. 14); but the idea of 'infinite breath' surrounding the universe can hardly have been
maintained after Empedocles had taught that air was only one of four elements all on the same level of existence, and not even the outermost
of them (which was fire, fr. 38, 4). It is nearer to Anaximander and Anaximenes, both of whom believed in an unlimited basic stuff in
which, by its differentiation
the universe but gave
at a certain point, the cosmos had its origin. For Anaximenes that stuff was air or breath, which not only surrounded
it life.
The
originality
lie
mass of unformed the so much him meant not which for matter, imposition of numerical organization upon it as the turning of it into numbers. Numbers (as we
1
if)
fr.
201
lrrecT<5cyEa 6cn 6* IK
i
TOU
eu0u$ (as
above 'immediately
after
TOU onrdpou
.UTTO
TOU
-niporroj.
279
unlimited, ubiquitous and animate air was of course a defended* tacitly accepted inheritance rather than a concept expressly Aristotle In passage (e) above, and Simplicius in his comment on
matter.
it
The
(/), seem to say unmistakably that the Pythagoreans in question identified void, breath, and the Unlimited. This has been doubted,
in Aristotle's partly through uncritical acceptance of a modern alteration text and partly on the ground that it would be inconsistent with the quotation
from
Linguistically there
is
no
difficulty.
The
repeated
KOCI
in the
to join different
descriptions of the same thing. But can we really say not only that void and breath are identified but that both are identified with time? Yes, for that too (or strictly speaking the
Pythagorean only another aspect of the Unlimited. As physical matter, it was that on which the nascent cosmos fed and by which it
grew;
as space, or extension,
it
was
that
imposition of mathematical form; but it had also a temporal aspect, as anything apeiron had. Until the middle of the fifth century the different
senses of this word 'unlimited' or 'endless' were not distinguished, and the Pythagoreans would not be the first to distinguish them. As mere duration also, or chaotic movement, it was waiting to be taken into the
cosmos and
limited, that is divided up into the nights, days, months and years which in Greek eyes alone deserved the name of chronos (time), and which were unimaginable without the ordered and recur-
moon and
'
stars.
andE. 49 : Nobody would venture to maintain that time, the relation of which was clearly the same as that of the void, was actually identified with it/ Admittedly Comford*s translation in P. and P. (p. ai, 'time and breath or the void") seems to take something for granted, but since Raven nowhere tackles the question of the Pythagorean
Raven,
-P.
to the unlimited
conception of time, his abrupt denial also calls for justification. It is interesting that Alcinaeon of Croton, who according to ancient tradition had connexion with the Pythagoreans and in any case was a contemporary and fellow-citizen of the earlier among
them, identified
Cognition^ 93f.)
3
KEV<$V
with
<5rfjp
ofElem.
Since this
is
more
fully in
an appendix,
pp.
3366% below.
280
the
evident (and passages still to be considered will confirm growth of the cosmos proceeded from the centre outwards.
it)
that
We also
we go on from cosmogony to cosmology, or the structure of the completed universe, that for the Pythagoreans the centre was occupied by fire. The unit-seed, then, physically considered, was of the nature of fire, and we can see what lay behind the brief doxographic statement in
find, as
element'.
material
Aetius that 'Pythagoras derived the world from fire and the fifth The active or formative element was the fiery unit; 1 the living
on which
it
fed
was
identified
by
later
(TO irepisxov) in which most of the Presocratics believed, and which cosmologists distinguished as a separate fifth element (pp. 271 ,
above).
Once in being,
in inferring
is
it
the cosmos
was
in
all
lasting. We have no direct statement of the fact, but Zeller was justified
which
vouched for
Pythagorean by Eudemus,
from the
is
third
cited to
between merely
specific recurrence, as
of one
spring or
events.
summer after another, and the recurrence of actual individual The relevant sentence is: 'But if one may believe the PythaI shall
be
my
stick as
you
sit
else
it is
itself.'
of dogmas which in his opinion may Porphyry to be back referred safely Pythagoras himself (probably taken from
also, in the brief
list
Dicaearchus, see p. 186, above), cites the belief 'that past events repeat themselves periodically and nothing is new in an absolute
sense'.
Taylor (Comm. on Tim. 87) went astray in connecting this with the theory, characteristic of the lonians, of the alternate creation and
dissolution of the world. Eudemus's illustration includes a reference to
Cf. Simplicius's remark that according to the "more genuine* Pythagorean doctrine fire was at the centre as a 'creative power* (STMJuoupyiKfjv Suvctniv, De Ca&lo^ 512.91!., quoted below,
p. 290). Further considerations are in
3
1
ZN,
I,
550, followed
732.26
(fr.
88
Wehrli).
28l
of history (which Is a common one in Greek thought) is linked with 1 that of the indestructibility of the world. The Pythagoreans were
doubtless
among
those censured
by
world could have a beginning and yet be everlasting (De Caelo, 279 b 1 2)5 and their notion of a cyclical repetition of history would
accommodate itself naturally to that of a Great or Perfect Year. This was the period (variously estimated in antiquity) required for the sun, moon and planets to reach again the same positions in relation to each other as they occupied at a given moment. Plato defines it in that most Pythagorean of his dialogues, the Timaeus (390), and a version of it
was
(cT)
Cosmology
with the sun was a detail in comparison with setting the earth to revolve In an orbit. The centre of the whole system the Pythagoreans believed
be occupied by a fire which we do not see because the side of the earth on which we live is turned away from it. The same system included, along with sun, moon and the other known planets, a 'counterearth' Invisible to us for the same reason. The relation of the sun, as a
to
See Guthrie, In the Beginning^ 63 ff. This theory of retour eternel has been held in more also. M. Capek in,/. PkHos. 1960, 28996, writes of its appearance in Nietzsche, Poincar6 and C. S. Pierce, and shows how it has only been put out of court by the most recent
1
1
modern times
developments in physics.
nothing of the basis on which it was have been a full Great Year as described above, since it consisted of a mere 59 years with 21 intercalary months. The Great Year of which Plato speaks, though variously estimated by ancient astronomers, was an affair of 10,000 years or more. There was also a cycle as brief as eight years, correlating the [solar and lunar years only. See further p. 458, below, and Guthrie, In the Beginning, 64 and 134, n. 2On the connexion of the Great Year with the exact repetition of events in sublunary history see B. L. van der Waerden, Hermes, 1952,
Censorinus,
calculated, this cannot
By
282
of reflexion
of the moon's light from the sun. That is the system in outline. I shall take first the passages of simple description, and afterwards (p. 287) consider what Aristotle and
like that
others have to say about the reasons which led these other questions to which it may give rise.
(a) Aristotle,
men to
it
and any
De
Caelo,
there
is
whole
universe
say that it lies at the centre, but this is contradicted Italian school called Pythagoreans. These affirm that the centre is
by
the
occupied by
it
fire,
is
one of the
stars,
and
creates night
and day as
about the centre. In addition they invent another earth, * our own, which they call by the name of counter-earth*, not lying opposite seeking accounts and explanations in conformity with the appearances, but
travels in a circle
violence to bring the appearances into line with accounts and of their own . .' opinions De () Caeby 293 b 15 : 'This then is the opinion of some about the position of the earth, and on the question of its rest or motion there are conform-
trying
by
able views.
at the centre
Here again
suppose
all
that
it
do not think alike. Those who deny that it lies moves in a circle about the centre, and not the
earth alone, but also the counter-earth, as we have already explained. Some even think it possible that there are a number of such bodies carried round the
centre, invisible to us
owing
them too
as a reason
why
to the interposition of the earth. This serves eclipses of the moon are more frequent than those
of the sun, namely that it is blocked by each of these moving bodies, not only
by
the earth.*
(c)
4 (Stobaeus's version, DK, 58836): (On eclipses of the 'Some of the Pythagoreans, according to the investigations of moon.) Aristotle and the statement of Philip of Opus, say that they occur by the
Aet. n, 29,
interposition sometimes of the earth, sometimes of the counter-earth/ a (<f) Simplicius in his commentary on De Caelo (511.25) quotes
slightly fuller account taken
from
Aristotle's
own
he
lost
work on
is
the Pytha-
goreans, but
1
this
adds
little.
The
counter-earth,
says,
so called because
who are the 'some* who accounted for the frequency of lunar eclipses
circling round the centre, but, according to Simplicius may (515.25), Alexander of Aphrodisias identified them as being among the Pythagoreans. assume that he knew, especially as the explanation seems to be linked with the idea of a planetary earth, which so far as we know was not held outside die school. Probably the
by
inventing a
We
Pythagoreans.
283
opposite to this earth. It lies nearest the central fire, the earth taking the second position and the moon the third. The earth in Its revolution round the
centre creates night and
*
day according
A number of later passages refer this system by name to the Pythagorean Philolaus.
Aet. in, ii, 3 (DK, 44Aiy): Philolaus the Pythagorean says that the fire is at the centre, calling It the hearth of the universe^ second comes the and the inhabited earth which in Its revolution remains third counter-earth,
(e)
*
opposite the counter-earth, wherefore the inhabitants of this earth do not see those of the other.*
(/) Aet. in ? 13, 1-2
that the earth
Is
the
fire
moon/
(g) Aet. n, 7, 7 (On the order of the cosmos) (DK, 44Ai6): 'Philolaus teaches that there Is fire In the middle lying about the centre, and he calls it the hearth of the whole, the home of Zeus, the mother of the gods, the altar
and
sustalner
is
another
fire
sur-
rounding the universe at the uppermost limit. The middle is primary in the order of nature, and around It dance ten divine bodies: the heaven and the
after them the sun, under It the moon, under that the earth, and under the earth the counter-earth. After all these comes the fire which occupies the position of hearth at the centre. The uppermost region of the surrounding heaven, where the elements are at their purest, he calls Olympus; kosmos he uses for the region below the circuit of Olympus, in which the five planets, the sun and the moon have their positions; and ouranos for the sublunary region beneath these and sur2 rounding the earth, the home of change and becoming.* (A) Aet. n, 20, 12 (On the nature of the sun) (DK, 44A 19) : Philolaus the
1
planets,
fire
Pythagorean taught that the sun is like glass. It receives the reflexion of the in the cosmos and filters through to us both the light and the heat, so
1
Unfortunately there
is
some
difficulty
(JPox. 337) prints oOpowcV fts -srAoviyras, the reading of F, noting that omits TE. He suggests that these at least slightly incorrect texts may conceal a reference to the five planets (TOU$ i irAoWITOS) which are mentioned as such a little lower down, and notes that in Philolaus's terminology as given here o&pm>6$ did not refer to the outermost heaven of the fixed stars but to the sublunary
the other hand a reference here to the fixed stars seems necessary if the bodies total ten, and it seems preferable to assume (with Zeller) that the doxographer is using odpov6s in the way natural to himself. * The author of the Epin&mis^ when he writes errs xdouov el-re 6Xuuirov SITE oOpovov Iv fiSov^j -rep
world.
On
mentioned are to
(9778), seems to
distinctions
their pedantry.
284
which
reflected
The
is
is
which
either described
the
fire,
anonymously or assigned to Philolaus. At the centre and our earth moves in the second orbit from the centre, the
nearest being traversed by the counter-earth. Next come moon, sun, the five planets, and lastly the sphere of the fixed stars which bounds the whole and is fiery like the centre. It is known that the moon's light
is
life
1
planetary bodies. The moon is of similar substance to the earth, and has on it of a larger, more powerful and more beautiful type.3 This is
idiom allowed
using 'sun* in the sense of sunlight", as when we speak of sitting in the sun*. Greek this too. Burnet rightly says that this is not a part of the doctrine, but only a captious criticism on the part of Theophrastus from whom the report comes. So also ZN,
I.e.
*
note on pp. 371 f. * The phrases T6 VTCO K6a\x$ m/p andro VT$
oOpccvcp irupcoSes
to refer to
the central fire (Burnet, EGP^ 298, n. i), in spite of the doubts felt by Heath (Aristarchusy n<>). The use of 8iTi9ouvra in Aet. II, 20, 12, as well as krcnrrpoeiSIs, may seem to imply that the sun is
simultaneously being described as a kind of burning-glass through which rays pass and also as a reflecting mirror. What Philolaus himself said is scarcely recoverable with certainty, but if the
sun collected the heat and light from the central fire, and not from the circumference of the heavens, I think that he can only have intended to imply reflexion. 3 The statement attributed to Philolaus has a curiously exact parallel in that quoted by Athenaeus (n, 50, 57 , see DK, i, p. 404, n.) from Herodorus of Heraclea that *the women of the moon are oviparous and those bom there are fifteen times our size*. Philolaus and Herodorus must have been contemporaries, and it would be interesting to know if either learned this from the other or both were relying on an earlier source. There is no other certain evidence of so early a belief in an inhabited moon. According to D.L. n, 8 Anaxagoras said it had 'dwelling-places*
but on this see Guthrie, Orph* and Gk. ReL 247, n. 10. theory that the moon-animals are fifteen times as strong as those on earth was no doubt also connected in the minds of its advocates with the fifteen-day lunar day, on which see Heath,
(otKt'icrEis),
The
Aristarchus,
n8
285
Pythagorean innovation, but otherwise the system follows current philosophico-religious belief in teaching that the further *up* one goes in
5
The
placing of fire
and more nearly immune from change and decay, are the substances which one finds.
Milesians and Heraclitus had highly fanciful notions on the in late writers on behalf subject of eclipses of the moon. Isolated claims of Thales and Anaximenes cannot stand against the evidence that down
The
by
exception 1 the sun. This seems to have been a discovery of Anaxagoras, though he like the Pythagoreans whom we are considering retained the
to the time of Anaxagoras and Empedocles no one (with the doubtful of their near-contemporary Parmenides) knew that it was lit
primitive belief of Anaximenes (p. 134, above) in 'earthy bodies' revolving with the stars, seeing in it a possible part-cause of the moon's
eclipses. The same truth was known to Empedocles (fr. 42), who also had a curious theory about the sun which may possibly have assisted
more
own (Aet. n, 20, 13, DK, A 56; A 30). Unfortunately we do not have it in an actual quotation from his poem, and some points in the account are obscure; but he said that
the Pythagoreans in forming their
cf.
there
that
we know is
the reflexion of
the other hemisphere of the universe. Though not identical with the Pythagorean, this theory makes the points that there may be
fire filling
said to
its
light
It is the
way
about
this.
All this amounts to sufficient evidence that the cosmology attributed by Aristode to the Pythagoreans, and by later authorities to Philolaus
in particular,
with the work of Anaxagoras and Empedocles, that is, in the latter half of the fifth century. It can well be a part of the same scheme which
related the structure of the physical elements to the regular mathe1
decisive.
Admittedly it is a question of balancing evidence, but Plato, Crat. 409 A C Heath, Anstarckus, 78 fl, 7?f.
may be
taken as
286
What
We
The Pythagoreans make a further point. Because the most important part of the universe which is the centre ought more than any to be guarded, they call the fire which occupies this place the
(a) Aristotle,
De
Caelo, 293 b
'
Guardroom of Zeus.*
Aristotle
mathematical
centre of anything
For nor to
is no need for them to be alarmed about the universe, for its mathematical centre; they guard ought rather to consider what sort of thing the true centre is, and what is its natural place.' () SimpL De Caelo 512.12 (on the above passage of Aristotle): 'Some
'
this
reason there
call in a
[sc.
of the Pythagoreans]
call
the
fire
the
his
work on
others the
Throne of Zeus/
Metaph. 98633 (after the statement that the Pythagoreans supposed the elements of number to be the elements of everything, and the whole universe to be a harmorda and a number):
Aristotle,
(c)
Any
the one hand, and on the other the changes and divisions of the universe and the whole order of nature, these they collected and applied; and if something
insisted
on making
53 f)
their
would have it that the PhHolaic* system is actually of the revolution of the heavens as only apparent (*Der Fixsternhimmel steht namlich nahezu still*) is *a very bold idea* which could only have ensued upon an advanced and carefully elaborated geocentric astronomy on the lines of the Timaeus; (f) that in the Phaedo Plato portrays Philolaus as a 'wandering prophet*, not an astronomer, and one who did not make his meaning dear (the implication is rather that Simmias and Cebes were not his brightest pupils, and there is no reason why he should not have combined, like Pythagoras, astronomical and mathematical genius with mystical beliefs about the soul. These, not astronomy, happen to be the subject of the Phaedo passage); (c) that the fragments of Philolaus (which may or may not be genuine) indicate a second-rate and muddled mind. None
post-Platonic,
He argues
of these arguments compels us to deny the possibility that PMlolaus may have hit upon a brilliant and audacious idea, and his motives show just the mixture of intellectual acumen and religious mysticism which one would expect of a Pythagorean.
287
40 Hayduck) says : Because they thought the decad the perfect number, but the phenomena showed them that the revolving spheres were nine (seven for the planets, eighth the sphere of the fixed stars, and ninth the earth, which they believed to travel in a circle also
(J) Alexander
this
on
'
passage
(p.
round a stationary hearth, which according to them is fire), they added in their own doctrine what they called the counter-earth, which they supposed to be situated opposite the earth and for that reason to be invisible to its inhabitants. He [Aristotle] goes into this In more detail in the De Caelo and In his work on the Pythagoreans.*
Of this
was invented
in order to
bring the number of revolving bodies up to ten, Burnet says that it is 4 a mere sally, and Aristotle really knew better ', and Heath was of the
eclipses,
If, however, our account of Pythagoreanism up to this point has been even remotely correct, it has shown that in the minds of
Pythagoras and his followers the preservation of mathematical harmonia must always take the first place. 1 Nor must it be forgotten that their
science
was pursued with a religious aim, to discover the perfect kosmos of the world in order to reproduce it in one's own soul. This is borne out by the religious titles lavished on the central fire, and leads to the
all
conclusion that
credited did in fact carry weight with them. cosmological system which posited a central
the arguments with which the Pythagoreans are The reasons, then, for the
fire, a planetary earth, and a counter-earth were threefold: (i) the number of revolving bodies must show forth the perfection of the decad; (2) fire was regarded with religious awe and had therefore to be assigned the central place, where
It
tides as
Throne of Zeus,
system
could be said
The
1
remind ourselves that prominent among the meanings of harmoma was * octave*, that the octave for the Pythagoreans was constructed out of the first four integers, whose sum is ten, and that the decad (in the form of the tetractys) thereby acquired supreme significance as a
religious
We may
symbol
288
Philolaic
and
Geocentric Systems
from the
scientific character
answer the objection that, if the earth were displaced from the centre, the phenomena of the revolving heavens as we see them could not in fact be accounted for. This is attested by their critic
they tried to
Aristotle himself, in the continuation of a passage of the
De
Caelo
hemisphere
not in any case the centre, but distant by its whole from the centre, they do not feel any difficulty in supposing that the phenomena are the same although we do not occupy the centre as they would be if the earth were in the middle. For even on the current view there is nothing to show that we are distant from the centre by
is
[Le. radius]
We have seen that the 'Philolaic' world-system could not well have
been evolved before the time of Empedocles, and is likely to have been due to Philolaus himself. It may be asked, are there traces in our
authorities of
an
earlier
goras or his immediate followers? One would naturally expect such 5 a scheme to be geocentric, and in the 'Pythagorean notebooks
And
from them
[sc.
ments] a living, intelligent, spherical cosmos, containing the earth at the centre, spherical like itself and inhabited; and that there are antipodeans who
call
'up'
what we
call
'down*.
difficult to date,
but
we may
earlier
the earth a planet, not necessarily because to our own ideas it is 'more primitive' or 'less sophisticated' (that might be a dangerous
criterion),
this is in line
with what
we know of the
history of early Greek thought. For Anaximander the earth was and neither Thales certainly at rest in the centre of a spherical universe,
nor Anaximenes, Heraclitus, Parmenides nor Empedocles can be supposed to have believed in a planetary earth. A reading of Aristotle's
De
Caelo,
was
13 leaves no doubt that a geocentric universe in until the Philolaic system was promulgated. believed universally
book n, chapter
D.L. vin,
25.
p. 201, n. 3,
above.
289
was a
short-lived aberration,
1
in tradition
(Aristotle's
own
reluctance to mention
Eudoxus, Heraclides Ponticus, and Aristotle himself placed the earth firmly back in the centre, from which it was not moved
again until Aristarchus suggested the heliocentric theory. then, Alexander refers to a Pythagorean system which was
No
still
doubt,
current
in the fourth century. There Is no other direct statement of a geocentric Pythagorean view, but certain passages have plausibly been taken to refer to it. Simplicius,
after
Ms own explanation of the Aristotelian text describing the revolution of the earth about a central fire, goes on like this (De Caelo
512,9):
is Aristotle's account of the Pythagorean view, but the more of the school mean by fire at the centre the creative power adherents genuine which animates the whole earth from the centre and warms that part of it
This then
cold. Hence some call it the Tower of Zeus, as Aristotle says in his work on the Pythagoreans, others the Guardroom of Zeus as 2 here, and others the Throne of Zeus. They called the earth a star as being
Itself
it Is
creates
by being lit up on
the cause of day and night. Day it is turned towards the sun, and night
through the cone of Its shadow. Counter-earth* was the name given by the Pythagoreans to the moon (as also 'heavenly earth*), both because it blocks the sun's light, which is a peculiarity of earth, and because It marks the limit of the heavenly regions as does earth of the sublunary.
Simplicius then,
Aristotle's lost
who do
Caelo.
Yet they
not believe in the system just described by Aristotle In De still spoke of 'fire at the centre', and the only reason-
able interpretation of the following words is that they meant a core of fire at the heart of an earth which Is itself (save for having this fiery
centre) In the middle of the cosmos.
(c
'mean* above)
is
SimpEcius's.
290
we
should expect that both types Similarly Proclus (In Tim. in,
141, ii Diehl; 143, 26), after mentioning that the Pythagoreans called the centre of the cosmos 'the Tower of Zeus', goes on to say that this
Tower of Zeus
is
The
fact that
star, and the phrase with which they defended this appellation, suggest that they were post-Philolaic. Astron seems to be used polemically.
(' You may call the earth astron if you like, but without supposing it to be one of the revolving bodies. ) The phrase 'instrument of time*, and the statement that in spite of being central and stationary it may be said
3
language in the Timaeus (41 5, 40B-c) too strongly for coincidence; but we hardly have the evidence to decide whether Plato was here (as in so much) following the Pythato create
recall Plato's
goreans, or the Pythagoreans in question were already acquainted with the Timaeus, or, finally, Simplicius was confusing the Pythagoreans and
Plato or regarding the Timaeus as a legitimate source of Pythagorean doctrine.
Most expositors slide rather quickly over the application of the term 'counter-earth' to the moon. It seems incredible that this was its
original reference,
and
it is
best explained
on the same
lines as the
designation of the earth as a star: these more conservative members of the school took the words out of the mouth of Philolaus (if it was he),
The
had
is fire
inference
The Greeks
also a more potent reason for it. It was commonly believed among them that all life, animal and human as well as vegetable, originated from within the earth. Going back to the immemorial worship of earth as the Great Mother, this belief survived to be rationalized and clothed in scientific terms by the philosophers. 2 At the same time the
of life were universally held to be heat and moisture, the former the active agent which animates a passive, moist material.
essential elements
Two other examples of yvVjoios in this sense: Xenocrates is called 6 yvriaicirrcrros TCOV TTX<5rrcovo$
by Simplicius (Phys. 1 165 .34), whereas Diogenes Laerrius accords this place to Aristotle
i
djcpoarcov
in the
2
words 6 yvqcacbraros TGOV TTA&rcovos vusfoyrcSv (v, i). For a full treatment see Guthrie, In the JSegtnning, chh.
and
2.
291
Pythagoras and
of heat mentioned
traces
is
the
Pythagoreans
living
myth and philosophy preserve came from inside creatures were formed and whence
This was the teaching of Empe-
light.
docles, though for him, in the period of Strife's ascendancy which he is describing, the fire within the earth must be thought of as trapped
there,
and
striving to join
its like at
the periphery. So
fr.
62:
Come now,
of miserable
hear
how fire, as it was separated, raised up the darkling shoots men and women. Not erring nor ignorant is the tale. Wholefirst
natured forms
fire
arose from the earth, having a portion both of water and sent up, wishing to come to its like.
That
is,
under the influence of Strife, which represents the tendency of and shun foreign substances, the heat in the earth
at the circumference
of the cosmos.
'
(c
its
whose thought,
on
religious side,
had much in
common
with Pythagoreanism, and in his native Sicily both volcanic eruptions and hot springs were familiar phenomena. Plato, who in the Phaedo
(HID)
within the earth, explicitly compares this state of things liquid with Sicilian Etna.
mud
is
by no means
inconsistent with the generation of the cosmos from a fiery seed or unit in the centre of an undefined mass of air or vapour. Moreover the
generative
power of
naturally, in the geocentric scheme, with the universal belief in the generative power of the earth, in which the activating principle was
Early Pythagorean cosmogony and cosmology can be perhaps dimly seen united in an admittedly superficial and confused account of the late mathematical writer Anatolius: 1
always heat.
Moreover the Pythagoreans said that at the centre of the four elements there a fiery monadic cube In this respect the followers of Empedocles and Parmenides and indeed most of the ancient sages appear to follow the Pylies
1
From his
treatise
On the Numbers up
to
Teny
292
thagoreans, for they say that the unitary substance Is situated in the middle and maintains the same position on account of its even balance.
to the earth in these terms:
Euripides, too, like the disciple of Anaxagoras which he had become, refers 'Wise mortals deem thee hearth.'
The
monadic cube' 1 suggests the generative fiery unit, and by the comparison with Empedocles and Parmenides, whose cosmologies were
fiery
'
is
all alike
The unmetrical misquotation from e one of a number of instances of the name Hearth' only Euripides (Hestia) applied to the earth in Greek literature, which perhaps attests
gave a fiery interior to the earth.
is
fire at its centre, just as we are told that Philolaus, the earth from the centre of the cosmos, transferred having displaced the name to the central fire. Sophocles gave earth that title in his
who
Triptolemus^ and it may be taken as certain that the goddess Hestia in Plato's Phaedrus "abides alone in the gods' dwelling-place',
while the other gods circle the heavens, personifies the central and stationary earth.3 Plutarch speaks of Cleanthes the Stoic asserting that
Aristarchus deserved punishment because with his heliocentric theory he displaced the hearth of the universe'. The evidence collected in the last few pages suffices to show (a) that,
*
vogue among the Pythagoreans a geocentric scheme in which the earth was believed to have a core of fire, (1} that this belief agreed with one already current in popular thought and shared by certain other philosophers.
also in
was
question that naturally arises at this point is that of the shape of the earth in relation to the history of Pythagoreanism. The date of the discovery of its sphericity has been the subject of much discussion,
which cannot be
1
fire
Why a cube, it would be hard to say. There is no evidence that the Pythagoreans equated with any other figure than the tetrahedron, and for the atoinists an atom of fire was spherical. The idea may have originated with someone who held the fluxion theory of the generation of solids, according to which the first, or simplest, solid was not a tetrahedron but a cube. * ferriccv Si a* ol CToq>oi pporcov dvojidjoucnv. The correct version is given by Macrobius (Eur.
944 N.) :
{3pOTo5v
3
KoXouoiv fju&Tjv v
ec!0pi.
Soph,
fr.
293
it
century.
There are
certainly
was not put forward until the late fifth no good grounds for attributing it to
Pythagoras himself. For this the only evidence is (a) a doubtful a passage of Diogenes Laertius (vin, 48, quoting Favorinus, polymath of the second century A.D.) which uses the ambiguous word 'round'
and in the same sentence quotes Theophrastus as giving the credit not to Pythagoras but to Parmenides; and () a statement in
(crrpoyy\jAT]v)
Aetius (in, 14, i , Dox. 378) which credits Pythagoras with having divided the earth into five zones on the analogy of the sky. But even if these
writers categorically attributed the discovery to Pythagoras, that would
(According to Diogenes, even Anaximander said the earth was spherical, which must be false; c the evidence on p. 98, above.) It is probable,
it
that
was known
as a
Pythagorean
tenet.
though not certain, that Parmenides and Empedocles believed the earth to be flat, 2 as did Diogenes of Apollonia, Anaxagoras, and Democritus.
De
294 b 14) is especially significant, for he was one of the scientific giants of the second half of the fifth century. Strictly speaking,
Caelo^
he seems to have taught that the earth was a disc with a concave surface (Aet. in, 10, 5, DK, A 94), presumably in an attempt to explain the
observable changes in the horizon as one's own position changes (which finally of course became a proof of its sphericity; see Aristotle,
De Caelo, 297 b 30$".). This reason is explicitly attested for his approximate
contemporary Archelaus (DK, 6oA4), and the view of the earth as a 'kneading-trough* gets a contemptuous mention from Plato (Phaedo,
99 B). Aristotle provides evidence that the flat-earth theory lively defenders in his own time (see De Caelo^ z^b^S.).
still
had
Thus
goreans of
whom
Aristotle
who
taught that the earth Is spherical, belonged to the last two generations of die school, in the late fifth and early fourth centuries. This
points
Herodotus mentions tales of men who sleep for six months and of Phoenicians who circumnavigated Africa and found the sun on their right while sailing westward. Both stories he dismisses as incredible (Hdt. IV, 25 and 42). Dreyer {Planetary Systems, 39) says they show that * akeady some people must have been able to perceive the consequences of the earth being a sphere'; but all they show is that these phenomena were observed. It does not follow that they were correctly explained.
*
1
Against Bumet,
EGP
AJP,
1940, i4f.
294
in the centre
ordinary theory of the 'harmony of the spheres', which so caught the fancy of later generations in the ancient world and at the Renaissance,
not
least among the English Elizabethan writers. Its details varied in accordance with changing theories of planetary motions quae (to
quote Censorinus)
si vellem in
unum
in angustiis versarer*
itself is
perhaps the supreme example of the Pythagorean attempt to explain the whole vast cosmic plan by reference to the basic discovery of the founder: the all-pervading influence of, and intimate connexion between, the laws of mathematics and of music. As Plato approvingly
c
expressed
it:
made for astronomy, so are our ears two sciences are sisters, as the
we
at
agree/
went so
own myth
he incorporated the melody of the the end of the Republic, and that is the first
far that
3 exposition of it in extant Greek literature. Since he cannot touch such a theme without adorning it, he adds, as a picturesque embroidery to
myth, that the sounds are produced not by the moving stars themselves, but by the voice of a Siren stationed on the circle of each; but a clear and critical account is given by Aristotle in De Caelo (29ob 12 IF.
his
but only
1
That the theory is Pythagorean he does not explicitly state at this point, later when he has passed to criticism of it and speaks, at
HOB axnrEp at ScaSscdoKuroi a<pcnpca. Mr J. S. Morrison (Pkronesis,
is
1959, 101 ff.) argues that not described as spherical I am not convinced. In particular it seems unlikely that in the comparison with the balls we are meant to think only of their colours to the
Readers interested in the finer points of Greek astronomy may be referred to the still standard work of Heath, Aristarchus, and to B. L. van der Waerden, Die Astronomic der Pythagoreer^ 2937* The speculations of G. Junge in Class, et MedievaUa^ 1947, i&$&. are best avoided. 3 The suggestion of G. Junge (Class, et Me<L 1958, 66) that the whole theory might have our originated in Plato's mind assumes an incredible ignorance on the part of Aristotle, even if
other authorities are ignored.
295
earth do so, although they are neither so great in bulk nor moving at so high a speed, and as for the sun and moon, and the stars, so many in number and
enormous
1 in size, all moving at a tremendous speed, it is incredible that they should fail to produce a noise of surpassing loudness. Taking this as their
their distances, hypothesis, and also that the speeds of the stars, judged by are in the ratios of the musical consonances, they affirm that the sound of the
stars as
they revolve
is
concordant
the difficulty that none of us is aware of this sound, they account for it by saying that the sound is with us right from birth and has thus no and silence are perceived by contrasting silence to show it up; for voice contrast with each other, and so all mankind is undergoing an experience like
that of a coppersmith, around him.
To meet
who becomes by
Set beside this part of the comment of Alexander of Aphrodisias on the passage of the Metaphysics (985b32ff.) in which Aristotle characterizes the
all
things to
numbers or
c
whole universe
as
(p.
39.24 Hayduck):
whole universe is constructed according to a musical what he means to indicate by the words and that the whole universe is a number'), because it is both composed of numbers and organized numerically and musically. For (i) the distances between the bodies revolving round the centre are mathematically proportionate; (ii) some move faster and some more slowly; (iii) the sound made by the slower bodies in their movement is lower in pitch, and that of the faster is higher; hence (iv) these
They
scale (this is
separate notes, corresponding to the ratios of the distances, make the resultant sound concordant. number, they said, is the source of this har-
Now
naturally posited
number
as the principle
on which the
Plato, or an immediate pupil, says in the Epinomis (983 A) that the sun
is
296
Of these one
1
is
especially
worth quoting,
that
of Cicero in the
Dream
I
ofScipio:
at these
wonders; but when I had recovered, I said: and sweet sound that fills my ears?' 'That', replied he, *is a sound which, sundered by unequal intervals, that nevertheless are exactly marked off in due proportion, is produced by the movement and impulse of the orbs themselves, and, commingling high and low tones,
gazed in amazement
'What means
this great
causes varying harmonies in uniform degree; for such swift motions cannot be produced in silence, and nature ordains that the extremities sound low at
one end, high at the other. Hence the course of the starry heaven at its where the motion is exceedingly rapid, moves with a sharp, quick sound; while the moon in its course (which is the lowest of all) moves with a heavy sound; for earth, the ninth of these bodies, biding immovable in one place, ever holds fast in the centre of the universe. Now these eight revolutions (whereof two possess identical powers) 2 form seven sounds, distinguished by their intervals; and this number seven is the bond of well-nigh all things. Learned men, imitating this with strings and with songs, have opened for themselves a way back to this region, even as others have done, who, thanks to outstanding genius, have all their Hves devoted themselves to divine studies.'
highest,
Cicero goes on to give the Pythagorean explanation of why we do not hear this music, substituting for Aristotle's simile of the copper-
lives
whilst this
Doth
should manage to be so genuinely Pythagorean in sentiment, and yet, according to these authoriPlut. Qu. Conv. 745 E ties, not in fact the explanation which the Pythagoreans offered. But c (id: 8* c&ra TCOV) jiv -TrAfiarcov irepicxXfjAnrroa xcci KarornirrXaaTai aapidvois ii^>pdypacn xod Tf&6oiv
which my attention was drawn by Mr F. H. Sandbach). was a Pythagorean belief that Pythagoras himself, that semi-divine being, could hear the heavenly music. See Porph. V.P. 30 and Simpl. De Cado 468.27 TO!S TTvQoyopeiois . .T6v
(to
It
.
mm
Tffc
297
Pythagoras and
In our
the
Pythagoreans
*
mathematical-muslcal-cosmological synthesis.
fashion reproducing to the divine. back'
own
it,
we may open
source in spite of his Hippolytus, generally a good doxographical doctrine (Ref. i ? 2, 2, of the statement a heresy-hunting, gives simple
Dox. p. 555): In this way Pythagoras showed the monad to be god, and having made a profound study of the nature of number he asserted that the cosmos sings and is harmoniously constructed, and he was the first to reduce the morion of the seven planets to rhythm and melody.' The Pythagoreans, said Eudemus, were the first to investigate the
*
another. It is clear also that they positions of the planets relative to one believed the ratios of their relative distances to correspond to recognized
musical intervals, and that according to the most commonly received form of the theory the intervals in question were those that made up a
scale. This is the general burden of the the cosmos is most frequently In which post-Aristotelian evidence, had this compass, and as which compared to the seven-stringed lyre
Zeller says In his long note on the doctrine, consonances* of which Aristotle himself speaks
by
we
variants occur
as
stand anything else but these Intervals. Although in the later sources which make the notes cover more than an octave, these,
Heath says
later
body
or bodies
which can be identified both from their descriptions and from the names supplied In the Epinomis as follows: moon, sun, Venus, Mercury,
Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, fixed stars. The scheme is of course geocentric. Plato continues: 'The spindle turned on the knees of Necessity. Upon
SimpL De Casio 471 . 5 Tf]v -rife eioicos Tdiv. The sentence, in which the Pythagoreans are contrasted with Anaximander, is translated on p. 93, above. * ZN, i, 538, n. i. Hie cumulative effect of this late evidence can be gauged from this note,
1
octave*.
(#i 463, n, 2) quotes Aristoxenus, Mus. n, 36To5v ^rrroxopScov & k&Aouv dppovlccs and Nicom.
oi TraAoadrocToi.
,
pv KaAowres T^V
Sia
TTOCCTGOV.
See further n.
on
Or spheres. Plato's description is not evidence on this point, since they have to be circles conform to the purely mythical image of the composite whorl turned on the knees of Necessity. In the case of the fixed stars, at least, the circle must presumably symbolize a sphere. In fact they are the circular rims of a nest of hemispherical bowls, but only the rims are taken into account and
to
KUK^OI is the
word
used.
298
stood a Siren,
with
its
ment, uttering a single sound on one note, so that the concords of a single scale.' 1
is
the eight
movemade up
To a modern mind the most pertinent question that arises over this one which, unfortunately, it is impossible to answer satisfactorily: how could the Pythagoreans have supposed that all eight notes of an
octave sounding simultaneously would produce a concordant and tantus et tarn calls it? The question dulcis sonus as Cicero pleasing effect, was raised by Martin in his tude$ mr le Timee de Platan as long ago as
was useless for Burnet to pretend (EGPy 307, n. i) that force in Martin's observation that the sounding of all the notes of an octave at once would not produce a harmony. There is no
it
1841, and
is
'there
no
harmony in the modern sense, but only of attunement to a perfect scale/ It may be true, as Bumet has said else(ccpnovioc) where (6>. Phil, i, 45), that 'when the Greeks called certain intervals
concordant
(ovpcpcovcc)
question of
in succession',
and that 'the word "harmony" (ocpjiovia) means, in the Greek language, first "tuning" and then "scale"*. Nevertheless in the
it is
present instance
obvious that (a) the notes are sounded simultaneously, since the heavenly bodies are all revolving all the time, and
(i)
we
combined
effect
would be
Yet no explanation is offered, nor is this particular objection raised by even the most unsympathetic of ancient critics. It is true that classical Greek music was melodic,
not harmonic, and this in itself may have entailed the consequence that they were not so alive as we should be to the effect of sounding as
1 Late authorities frequently compare the Pythagorean cosmos to the heptachord or instrument of seven strings. This should take into account only the seven planets', omitting the sphere of the fixed stars, yet some even retained the simile while increasing Ae number of singing bodies to nine by giving a note to the earth. Others again criticized them for doing so. See e.g. Alexander *of Aetolia* quoted and censured by Theo Smym. pp. i4o Hiller. Yet he still kept
*
within the octave (16 TTOV vvsdxop5ov cn/viorrjcnv, If p&nroi T6vous ircpi^xov). The allotting of the same vis to two of the planets by Cicero seems to be a way of overcoming this difficulty. The heptachord and octachord alike spanned an octave, but in the heptachord either the two
terrachords of which it was composed were joined by a string common to both (owa^), or, where they were separated by a tone (5i<5rguit$), one of them was defective by one string. This was the instrument in use in Terpander's time (seventh century), but the octachord was introduced by the early fifth century at latest, and was familiar to Plato and Aristotle, both of whom obviously have it in mind in their exposition of the heavenly harmorda. The attempts to retain a seven-stringed scheme were probably prompted by the ancient sacredness of the number seven.
299
by
Aristotle'.
It
may
its
manner of its growth helped to obscure for the followers of Pythagoras what seems to us such a serious difficulty. W. Kranz has argued with some cogency that the application of the rational musical intervals to the distances between the cosmic circles or spheres was due
that the
to Pythagoras himself. 2
transformed
Its
orbits are in question, those of relationship. In this scheme only three the moon, sun and stars, the planets not being distinguished in
respect of their orbits from the fixed stars (p. 94, above). The intervals could therefore be identified with the three primary consonances, the
fifth (2:3), and fourth (3:4), which would be supposed to correspond to the distances from the earth of the three most anciently recognized orbits. The existence of such a scheme at some time is
octave (1:2),
(octave),
which
this is
Because
is
a scheme of only three intervals, in which the sphere of not distinguished from the orbits of the planets as in
it is
Pyrrh.
ill,
I,
95.
Heath (Aristarchus, 107) contradicts it, maintaining that Pythagoras 'certainly distinguished the planets from the fixed stars* and that *the original form of the theory of the "harmony of the spheres" no doubt had
GP,
10.
reference to the seven planets only*. One may at least query the word 'certainly*. Few things are certain about Pythagoras, and this is not one of them. Heath's only evidence appears to be Theo Smym. p. 150 Hiller (cf. his article on astronomy in the OCD, no), but the words Ka0d
r]as
little
or no value.
300
This
the seven-stringed lyre only these were marked by strings of fixed were the tuning. They stationary (ecrrcoT$) strings. The others were
adjustable to the type of scale required and hence were called movable 1 (Kivounevoi). It is therefore highly likely that in the first attempt to fit
his musico-mathematical discovery to the
himself should have had the "concordant intervals' in mind, die simultaneous sounding of which is at least less obviously discordant to our
ears than that of the seven or eight strings of a complete diapason. Another thing of which we have no certain knowledge is how Pytha-
goras and his followers calculated the relative distances between the heavenly bodies. Plato, by allowing varying breadths to the rims of the
whorls on Necessity's spindle, appears to be stating an order of magnitude governing the distances between the various heavenly bodies; but he offers no statement of actual ratios. 3 Some writers of Graeco-
Roman date, for example Pliny and Censorinus, offer definite numerical
schemes, which, however, obviously belong to a later epoch. Alexander of Aphrodisias, in continuation of the passage quoted on p. 296, above,
seems to
feel that
offer a
illustration: *For suppose (9p shrew) the distance of the sun from the earth was double that of the moon, that of Venus triple and that of
Mercury quadruple, they assumed that for each of the others also there was an arithmetical ratio, and that the movement of the cosmos was
harmonious/
(e)
distractions as numbers
To
They
included what
we
should
Bumet, Gr. PW. I, 46; OCD, 587. See Rep. 6i6E in Comford's translation and the notes thereto; also Comford's Plato's Cosmology , 79: Probably Pkto intentionally left the meaning vague. He would not commit himself to any estimates that had actually been made on very insufficient data.* 3 This is of course an inadequate translation of Kmp6$, but its exact meaning makes no difference here, and it may be allowed to stand as a more convenient term than, say, *the right time*.
*
*
301
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
ment of human thought. "Unmethodical and capricious', said Zeller and E. severely, and one must agree with Mr Raven when he writes (P. 57): 'It is true that for a certain type of mind this number-symbolism
has always had an attraction; but there is litde to be learned, from the Pythagorean addiction to it, of the scientific system with which to
they
somehow attempted
to re-
was indeed
ment; but
if the interest
a scientific blind alley, and not worth lengthy treatof a historian of philosophy is not simply in
is
written
on
that assumption),
will
be worth while
down some
Aristotle refers to this practice at several places in the Metaphysics. At 1 093 a i he makes the general criticism that 'if everything must
partake in number, many things will turn out to be the same'. Since 4 is equated both with the tetrahedron and with justice, there seems to be
this objection, at least for a strictly rational mind. that for the Pythagoreans 'such-and-such a disposi-
tion of numbers was justice, another was soul and mind, another opportunity and so on'. At loySbii he is discussing how far his predecessors
sought universal definitions: The Pythagoreans did in a few cases, the formula of which they linked with numbers, as when they asked what is opportunity or justice or marriage.' The Magna Moralia (probably the
work of an
n82an
'Pythagoras
was the first to treat of virtue, but erroneously; in reducing the virtues to numbers he made his researches irrelevant to their subject, for justice
is
not a square number.' To return to the Metaphysics, at 99oai8 Aristotle has been criticizing the Pythagoreans by asking how numbers
can be the causes of things and events in the universe and at the same time the constituents of the material cosmos. He then (1. 22) puts the
and
question differendy: how can numbers be opinion, opportunity, etc. at the same time the substance of the material universe?
For the Pythagoreans, opinion and opportunity are located in a certain quarter, and injustice, separation [perhaps 'decision'], or mixture a little above or below. But they demonstrate this by saying that each of these is a
302
Abstractions as
number, and there happens to be already
Numbers
in this area a multitude
of magni-
tudes so constructed (because these modifications of number belong to the 1 several regions). Is, then, the number which one must suppose to constitute
is
difficulties
part from their inability to draw a clear distinction between abstract and concrete: to Aristotle their language suggested that they allotted the same number to (say) air and opinion without making it clear that they existed on quite different ontological planes ? and even spoke of
qualities as situated in space. Aristotle has other matters to pursue, and wastes little time over what was to him a manifest absurdity: but his commentator Alexander of
moral
He
also reveals
number
to
and found
first
this to exist in
justice
was the
2 square number ;
same
for in every kind the first instance of things having the formula had in their opinion the best right to the name. 3 This number
said
some
every
first
was
4, as
being the
it is
first
way
equal, for
twice
2.
square, divisible into equal parts and in Others, however, said that it was 9, the
square of an odd number, namely 3 multiplied by itself. 4 Opportunity, on the other hand, they said was 7, because in nature the
man
1
*
times of fulfilment with respect to birth and maturity go in sevens. Take for instance. He can be born after seven months, 5 cuts his teeth after
Constructed* (OWIOTCCIJ^VCDV) probably means constructed out of numbers like the abstracand the reference will be to the physical elements which were also
by way of
Ross's
com-
Cf. Aristotle, EN, 113^21: *Some think justice is simply requital, as the said: they defined justice simply as requital to another/ Note that TO dvnirETrcwOo? (requital or reciprocity) was in use as a mathematical
'reciprocally proportionate*, e.g. at EucL vi, def. 2 and probl. 14. 3 Cf. Aristotle, Metaph. 987 a 22 obpisovro TE yap rrnroAcda>$, xai 6po$, TOUT* elvai Tfjv oOcrlav TOU irp&ypiorros ivoptsov.
4
Pythagoreans
term meaning
irpocrrcD Orrdp^iisv
Aex&ei$
of reasoning with respect to the see Aristotle himself, Metaph. 10933131!. 5 Cf. the Pythagorean Hippon as cited by Censorimis, VH, 2 (DK, 38Ai6): Nippon Metaponwws a septzmo addecimwn mensem nasci posse aeswnavit; nam sepumopartumiam essematurum y
number 7
etc.
Cf. Solon,
De Heldom.
436 Littr).
303
5,
because
it is
the union of
male with female and according to them male is odd and female even, 3 and the number 5 arises from the first even number (2) and the first odd number (3). . Mind and being they identified with the unit, for soul he [presumably
.
Pythagoras]
It
classified
with mind.
difficult
goreans seriously when we the numbers 4 and 9, mentioned by Alexander, 8, 5 and 3 were also Identified by some of them with justice. As to marriage, the Theolo-
to take this aberration of the Pythalearn from other late authorities that besides
gumena Arithmeticae
gives
its
:
number
as
3,
Nicomachus
as
io. 4
These 'resemblances' (oidoicbuocra) between things like Justice and the properties of numbers explain why Aristotle sometimes says things represent
(fii{jiicj0at)
sensible
body, as
we have seen, can be said to be the unit-atoms composing it; but if a man says
is a square number', he cannot mean that Justice is a plane figure four unit-points; obviously he means that the square figure is a of composed symbol which represents or embodies the nature of fairness, just as when an
that 'Justice
honest
imagined that
his figure really had four comers. The two modes of describing the relation of things to numbers are perfectly compatible, being respectively appropriate to different orders
of 'things'.
This, however, is probably to take an unwarrantably favourable view of Pythagorean rationality. The explanation of the equation of justice
f-rioi, if correct, might just possibly mean 'Pythagoras says'. Much more probably it refers to Aristotle, and is an indication that Alexander (as is in any case likely) is taking all this information from Aristotle's lost treatise on the Pythagoreans, Note the different tense of slra at 39 . 14
1
below.
*
Konp&v,
3
i.e.
the
same word as
is
translated 'opportunity'.
This
is
and Hayduck;
See
4
correspondences alleged between numbers and physical bodies were scarcely less capricious, if we allow any truth to the statement of [Alex.] in Met. 767 Hayduck that body in general was equated with 210, fire with 1 1, air with 13 and water with 9, and try to fit in these
statements with
The
304
Abstractions as
Numbers
with a square number by the notion of reciprocity or requital does indeed show, if that were necessary, that the equivalence is in part
symbolic; but it does not account for the conception of justice as extended in space, It is not even true that Aristotle uses the language of
resemblance rather than identity when speaking of the relationship of these abstractions to numbers. More helpful at this point in elucidation
of the mode of thought of fifth-century Pythagoreans is a comparison with the Love and Strife of Empedocles, which he conceived as sharing * the cosmic sphere with the four elements, equal in length and breadth'
to them (fr. 17, 20), and capable of direct physical action. The alter9 9 nation of language between 'identity and 'resemblance is rather to be accounted for, as we have already seen, by an ambiguity inherent in the
Greek word
*
OJJLOIOS,
which
in
common
similar'
and 'same'. 1
Perhaps the most useful outcome of drawing attention to these numerical fantasies is that it reveals how much specific Pythagorean
which we
teaching lay behind the curiously mathematical approach to ethics find in Plato. In the ethical discussion of the Gorgias,
is
upholding the ideals of justice and self-restraint against the drive for power and personal gratification advocated by Callicles, he adduces as an important part of his argument the following
where Socrates
(507 E):
Wise men say that heaven and earth and gods and men alike are held together by community, friendship, orderliness, self-control and justice, which is why
they
fail
call this
temperance. But
not disorderliness or inuniverse a world-order (kosmos) I fear you ignore them, wise though you are yourself, and
power that is wielded among both gods and men by geoHence your defence of selfish aggrandisement: it arises
result
1 P. 230, above. Cf. F. H. Sandbach, quoted by Raven, P. andE. 57: the confusion between the different types of proposition involved in the equation of, say, the moon and opinion with a "* number would be facilitated by the use of the Greek word Spoio?, the ambiguity ofwhich between
iTpo<T<ppf|s
the senses, that is to say, of 6 ocCrrds or laos on the one hand and absolute and partial similarity** on the other "is responsible for many fallacies and logical puzzles in Greek
thought***.
305
determine what the Pythagoreans believed about the nature of the soul might seem to belong to the earlier section dealing with their
religious views
To
and the
relation
We can indeed
make use of much information already gained; but one problem in particular remains which we were not in a position to tackle until we
had investigated the number-doctrine. Nor is it a bad thing to let the wheel come full circle as a further reminder that in Pythagorean philosophy the religious and scientific sides cannot be considered in isolation
from each other without grave distortion of its outlook and aims. We have seen (pp. 157, 186) that Pythagoras himself taught transmigration, and
soul
may
also
bound up:
its
human
kinship
its
immortal, that
it
owes
immortality to
it
may hope
to return to
cases
Pythagorean where he
when purified. may also quote Aristotle for the belief in transmigration, although this is one of the rare
is
We
not our
earliest
informant:
De
is
An. 407 b 20: 'All that these thinkers [Platonists and others] try to do of the soul; of the body that is to receive it they add no
description, just as if it
were
possible, as in the
1
Pythagorean
stories, for
any
little earlier
in the
De Anima
'some Pythagoreans' the opinion that the motes in the air constitute soul, whereas others said that it was 'that which moves them*. As with
primitive people in general, the phenomenon of apparent self-motion immediately suggested to the early Greeks the presence of life, and so
the reason for this crude notion was no doubt what Aristotle goes on to suggest: 'because the motes are always seen in motion, even when the
air is
completely
still: all
who
which moves
itself
tendency'.
in close
That this remark could have been made, as has been suggested, without reference to die doctrine of transmigration is impossible.
306
The Sold
connexion with the similar doctrine of the atomist Democritus, who, however, used the motion of the motes as a simile. The motes were not
the soul-atoms
far
all,
and
like
below the level of perception but they must be assumed to be them and to have a similar motion, self-caused as that of the motes
appeared to be.
The first form of the Pythagorean view mentioned by Aristotle sounds the more primitive, and the second a refinement on it in a spiritual direction, though 'what moved them* was no doubt still
thought of in what we should call material terms as the indeed it is), identified with pneuma or the breath-soul. 1
Since
air
(which
we have no
it.
further information
its
on
more can
be said about
In either of
forms
it fits
versally-held belief, adopted by the Pythagoreans as by their near relations the Orphics (Arist. De An. 4iob27), that the soul was of the
and we have already seen this be pressed into service by how belief could 129, above) general
air-
materialists
affected the question of the soul's immortality either one way or the other.
Another doctrine mentioned by Aristotle, in his review of previous theories, was that the soul is a harmonia. Although he does not here
mention the Pythagoreans, the word harmonia itself is sufficient guarantee of its authorship.3 What Aristotle says is (De An. 407^27): Its There is yet another theory about the soul supporters say that
6
the soul
1
is
harmony
is
a blend or composition
Dodds
(Greeks and the IrrauonaL^ 174) notes that the view of the soul as a tiny material of primitive parallels, and goes on to say that this is the persistent, 'occult*
*
soul and
is quite distinct from the breath-soul which is the principle of life on the ordinary empirical level*. As will appear later, the distinction which Dodds draws between the "occult* * and the empirical* soul is true and important; but it is difficult to understand why the view at
present under discussion should refer to the occult one. * * c 3 Cf. the closely related opinion of some of the Pythagoreans that some animals are nourished
by
3
smells* (Arist. De Sensu^ 445 a 1 6). In fairness one must quote the opinion
n. i), to
probably assent: 'Aristotle never suggests that the doctrine was Pythagorean; it was most probably a late reinterpretation of some Pythagorean doctrine of the soul as number worked out by the physicians or musicologists. . .in the late fifth or early fourth century and not ascribed to Pythagoreans until even later.* J. Tate (CR, 1939, 2-3) thought it belonged to no philosophical school but was simply a widespread and popular view, that of 'anyone and everyone who thinks that the soul begins and ends with the organic union of the bodily parts*.
307
cases in mind; which have motion and position, where harmony means the disposition and cohesion of their parts in such a manner as to prevent the introduction into the whole of anything homogeneous with it, and the secondary sense, derived from the * former, is that in which it means the ratio between the constituents so blended.
two forms
In another brief reference to the view he again distinguishes between in which it was held (PoL I34ob 18): 'There seems to be in
us a sort of affinity to musical modes and rhythms, which makes many philosophers say that the soul is a harmonia^ others that it possesses
harmoniaJ That the soul should be a harmonia seems a very natural belief for the Pythagoreans; indeed one can scarcely suppose that they
it otherwise, and it would cause no misgivings were it not for the use to which it is put by Plato in the Pkaedo. There the doctrine
viewed
that the soul is a harmonia is used as an argument that it cannot be immortal but must perish with the body. That is the problem that we have to face.
If we leave the
fits
happily
together.
The
whole cosmos
ultimate elements of everything are numbers, and the owes its character as something perfect, divine and
permanent to the fact that the numbers of which it is made up are combined in the best possible manner according to the rules of mathematical proportion as Pythagoras's studies had revealed them. In short the cosmos owes all these desirable qualities to the fact that it is a
harmoniay and
in the majestic movements on a cosmic scale of the sun, moon, planets and fixed stars. The heavens do not declare the glory of God, they are the glory of
this
is all
harmonia
God;
by
a living god, welded into a single divine unity the marvellous power of mathematical and musical harmony.
is
If then our individual souls are essentially of the same nature, though separated by impurity in our incarnate state, then surely our identity
(Oxford
translation).
308
with the divine must consist essentially of numbers in harmony, and we are still in need of the purification of philosophy it must
the element of impurity, in other terms, an element of discord, a jarring note caused by a flaw in the numerical order of our
call
be right to
souls
or, to put it in yet another Pythagorean way, an element of the Unlimited as yet unsubdued by the good principle of Limit. This is genuine Pythagorean doctrine. Now let us see what is said
in the
Phaedo (86s,
trans. Hackforth):
(Simmias speaks): And in point of fact I fancy that you yourself are well aware, Socrates, that we mostly hold a view of this sort about the soul: we regard the body as held together in a state of tension by the hot, the cold, the
dry and the moist, and so forth, and the soul as the blending or attunement \harmonid\ of these in the right and due proportion. Now if the soul really is a kind of attunement, plainly when our body is unduly relaxed or tautened by sickness or some other trouble, the soul, for all its divine nature, is bound forthwith to be destroyed, just as much as any other attunement or
adjustment in musical notes, for instance, or in a craftsman's product; whereas the bodily remains will last for a considerable time, until they are burned or rot away. So see what answer you can find for us to this argu-
ment, which insists that the soul, being a blending of the bodily constituents,
is
the
first
is called
death.
this passage,
and
it is
no doubt impos-
sible to bring irrefutable proofs of any one of them; but one may try to give a probable account, and indicate the arguments in its favour. What is difficult to believe without irrefutable proof, knowing what we do about Pythagoras and the general conservatism of his foEowers in
religious matters, is that any who claimed to say that the soul was mortal.
him
as master
were prepared
thought that
1
it
Philolaus.
Against
EGP, 295, Gr. Phil* i, 92 Wilamowitz (Platan^ n, 90) was also inclined to think that Philolaus denied the immortality of the soul on the ground that it was an attunement of the
*
bodily parts, though he could not quite make up his mind. For Comford, on the other hand, there is no doubt that Philolaus held both that the soul is, in some sense, a harmony and that it is immortal* (CQ, 1922, 146)- *It is probable*, he thought, 'that the objection was first raised by Plato/
309
do not seem
one may make two points. In the first place, Simmias and Cebes to have been very assiduous or understanding disciples.
Earlier in the dialogue Socrates has expressed surprise that they are not familiar with the idea that suicide is contrary to religion, since it was
something taught by Philolaus. Have they not heard (6iD.) 'Nothing at all clear*, says Cebes; and a moment
it
from him?
'Yes, to
later,
answer your question, I have heard, both from Philolaus and from others, that one ought not to do this; but no one has ever made it clear to me/ Secondly, these views on suicide, which are expressly
attributed to Philolaus, are said
by
Socrates to depend
on the idea
contained in a 'secret doctrine' (drr6ppTjTO$ A6yo$) that we are put into the world by the gods and looked after by them; that therefore we
must not leave it until they give the word; but that when they do permit is it, death comparable to a release from bondage or imprisonment. It is
hardly likely that these are the beliefs of a
soul
man who
at death.
may note also the attitude to Simmias's objection of Echecrates, 1 a Pythagorean from Phlius and pupil of Philolaus to whom Phaedo is relating this conversation of the day of Socrates's death. It is one of
great uneasiness (88 D):
is a kind of attunement of us has always had and has a strong hold upon me, and when you uttered it I was, as it were, reminded that I too had believed in it. And now, as if I were starting from
We
now
me
the beginning again, I am terribly in need of another argument to persuade 2 that the souls of the dead do not die with them.
Here
fail
is
to be?)
a Pythagorean who is attracted (as what Pythagorean could by the idea that the soul is an attunement, yet believes in its
immortality and wishes to be reassured by other considerations that this one is (as presumably he has hitherto regarded it) not fatal to his
belief.
As
that
we know from
if
the Phaedo
he forbade
and
why
should he do this
characteristically
The
o^ 57 A, Aristoxenus, fr. 19 Wehrli (ap. D.L. via, 46). translation is that of A, Cameron, Pythagorean Background, 45
this
310
dialogue?
The
is
diminished
by
its late
The words of Philolaus are worth quoting. This Pythagorean says: "The ancient theological writers and prophets also bear witness that the soul is yoked to die body as a and buried in it as in a tomb.*** punishment, (b} Claudianus Mamertus (Christian writer of fifth century A.D.), De Statu
m,
17
also
A. Engelbrecht, 1885, p. 105 (D K, 448 22) : * Before deciding on the substance of the soul, he [Philolaus] discourses marvellously on measures, weights and numbers in conjunction with geometry, music and
Animae, n,
3, ed.
arithmetic, proving that the whole universe owes its existence to these . . . 2 (p. 120). Concerning the human sotd he says this: the soul is set in the body
later: the soul loves the
by means of number and an immortal and incorporeal harmony. And a little body, because without it it can make no use of the senses. But when separated from it by death, it leads a disembodied life in
the world.'
(c)
i,
14,
19
doctrines attributed to Philolaus in Clement are paralleled in detail not only in the Phaedo but also elsewhere in Plato, where we find
references to incarnation as a punishment and to the body as both a prison and a tomb (Gorg. 493 A, Crat. 4000). In the Cratylus these
The
notions are ascribed to Orpheus and his followers', that is, to "ancient theologoi* as by Philolaus. In view of all this we may agree with Nesde (ZN, 442) that the coincidence with the Phaedo affords no
ground for regarding the quotation from Philolaus, at least in substance, as a forgery.3 Similarly the passage from Claudianus Mamertus,
in spite of its traces of later Greek terminology in Latin dress,4 contains
61 E, 628. *No ancient author who wrote about Philolaus ever questioned his attachment to the religious background of his order* (Cameron, Pytk. Background^ 45). One can do no more than state what seems sensible and then in honesty report the fact that other scholars can disagree.
1
Thus Hackforth
(cf. s
this
oOSv ooffe
61 AS) anything as to PMolaus*s religious views." The word 'humana* is accidentally omitted by DK.
3 Wilamowitz (Platan^ n, 90) was more suspicious, mistrusting the word Moddnrep as he may well have been right to do. But his view is coloured by the belief that the doctrine of <yuxfj~ dpuovicc attributed to Philolaus by Macrobius is necessarily inconsistent with belief in immortality.
Since, however, Macrobius assigns it at the same time to Pythagoras, this is obviously not so. 4 F. Bomer has discussed this passage in detail in D&r latein. Neuplat. u. Neupythagoreismus,
14354, where references to many other modem opinions will be found. Bomer, however, who regards the doctrines here ascribed to Phiiolaus as Neopythagorean, goes astray in several places,
311
that
chief fault
cannot be paralleled In pre-Aristotelian Pythagoreanis that it is fragmentary and leaves serious gaps.
Points to note are that according to this account Philolaus elaborated his cosmology, with its demonstration that everything in the world is dependent on number, before approaching psychology. He then
no exception, but even when incarnate is organized according to number and to an attunement which is immortal and incorporeal That the soul in this life loves or clings to the body,
showed
is
seduced by sensual
something that we learn also in the of Plato's dialogues. One thinks in particular parts of the soul in the Phaedo (81 B) which "has always associated with the
gratification, is
more Pythagorean
filled
with
its lusts
and so bewitched by
its
passions
and pleasures as to think nothing real save what is bodily, what can be touched and seen and eaten and made to serve sexual enjoyment'. Death, we are told finally, is not extinction of the soul. It lives on in a
disembodied
incarnation.
state *in the
world'
(in
mmdo\
is
that
is,
The
but the soul that has loved the body, of whom Plato says that it is compelled to wander about the visible world until once more fettered
to a
body (Phaedo
81 D).
all
that need
be said
is
that since
he couples the name of Philolaus with that of Pythagoras, this Neoplatonist evidently did not think the doctrine of soul as harmony to be
incompatible with belief in its immortality. Putting together our scattered evidence from Plato onwards, it seems that Philolaus was a
true follower of Pythagoras in holding that the soul
else
of
real
particularly in his interpretation of the ckuse 'diligitur corpus ab anima* and the words 'in mundoV As to the terminology, Claudian doubtless chose the words *de mensuris ponderibus et
numeris* for their correspondence with the words of scripture to which he compares them:
*Mensura pondere et numero omnia disposuisti." (See Wisdom of Solomon xi. 20.) But this casts no doubt on the obvious truth that Philolaus, like any true Pythagorean, did explain the cosmos by number and measure. Again, the word *incorporalern* (doxbiiarov) would probably not have been used by Philolaus himself, but describes well enough the kind of harmonia that he must have had in mind. H. Gomperz in Hermes, 1932, 156 does indeed defend the fragment, dacbucnrov and all, but is criticized by Bomer, 153. 1 It may be true that die best authenticated of Philolaus's views are those contained in the papyrus which records extracts from Menon's history of medicine. But the argument which
312
What then of the argument brought forward by Simmias? The view of the soul which he propounds, hoping to have it refuted by Socrates, has been generally recognized to have a strong affinity with the theories of the medical writers of Magna Graecia, and in with the
particular
chief of them,
Siintnias's
language
may be
compared Alcmaeon,
Alcmaeon
4 (Act.
v, 30, i):
said that what preserves health is the equilibrium of the powers wet, dry, cold, hot, sweet and so forth whereas the unchecked rule of any one of them engenders disease: the rule of a single contrary is destructive
Health
is
So far as it concerns the causes of health and disease, Alcmaeon and Simmias are clearly describing the same theory; yet Alcmaeon does not go on to identify the equilibrium or balanced mixture of the opposites
with the soul, nor argue that as the one can be destroyed so can the other. In spite of his views on health and disease, he believed the soul
to be immortal. So Aristotle,
An. 405 ai9 (see DK, 24^12 for this and supporting passages from Cicero, Clement and Aetius): He says that the soul is immortal because it resembles the immortal beings in
c
De
that
always in motion; for all the divine bodies likewise are in continuous and unceasing motion the moon, sun, stars and the whole
it is
heaven.' 1
Empedocles in
first
time the ancient 'opposites* were given more concrete form as the
four imperishable 'root-substances* earth, water, air and fire, and he defined each separate organic substance in terms of a mixture of these
(fr. 96, Arist. De An. 4o8ai8ff.). At the same time, f in obedience to the principle that like is known by like', he taught that the soul, at least in its empirical aspect as that with which we perceive
in a certain ratio
the world around us, was composed of the material elements themselves
Nestle based on this fact is absurd: *Der echte PMlolaos Hegt in den neuerdings bekannt gewordenen Ausziigen aus seinen medizinischen Schriften in Menon's latnka. Darnack war PhHoloQs weruger PMlosoph als Ar^ty und zwar gehorte er zur Krotoniatischen Artztschule* (ZN, 437: my italics). If nothing of Aristotle had been preserved save part of the Poetics in another man's history of literature and a few fragments on other subjects of doubtful authenticity, it would have been as reasonable to argue that he had been *not so much a philosopher as a literary critic*. We know at least enough about PhUolaus from other sources to save us from this
mistake.
1
313
De
his criticism
of the soul-as-attunement
make Empedocles appear illogical and confused, and we have not the relevant parts of his poem as a check; but he does seem to have described
the soul as a particular tension or equilibrium of the bodily parts and also said something which might be construed as meaning that it
vanished
when
this balance
was
3IA85)
coming
which man
is
In spite of
general Italian
body and soul'. imbued as he was with the Empedocles, deeply tradition, wrote a religious poem whose theme was the
to
common
immortality, transmigration and ultimate apotheosis of the human soul. He therefore affords an interesting parallel to Alcmaeon, although the
question of how,
if at all,
1
his doctrine
Burnet himself regards the soul-as-attunement theory as evidence that the Pythagoreanism of the end of the fifth century was an adaptation of older doctrine to the new principles
left until later.
must be
introduced by Empedocles.
The problem is certainly difficult, and it can hardly be wrong to detect here a certain tension existing within the school. Scattered as they were by the fifth century in Italy, Sicily and Greece, the Pythagoreans did not all develop the doctrine of their master along identical lines. For medical men, such as Alcmaeon was, 2 the body and its states
field.
Their
disease
in particular bodies,
and
they tend to be impatient with the more metaphysical pronouncements of philosophers. Their business was with the physical opposites of
belief
which the body was composed, for their practice was founded on the that health depended on a due and surely a Pythagorean one
hot and rightly proportioned mixture of these opposites in the body wet and dry, bitter and sweet and others. Inevitably they would
life
cold,
at
any
rate
depended on these
See, however,
*
Kahn
in Arch. f.
GescL
d. Pkttos*
Of course, like any serious thinker of his time, he was more than this,
irAElcrrd
but
& Kod
we may
perhaps
frfo-re.
9vaioAoyei
3*4
the physical elements of the body. And the identification of psyche with the physical life was deeply rooted in the Greek mind, so that the
temptation lay close at hand to say that the psyche could not outlive the dissolution of the body. Dicaearchus the pupil of Aristotle, who though not a Pythagorean himselfwas the friend of Pythagoreans and acquainted
with their teaching, went the whole way and called the soul explicitly 'an attunement of the four elements*. It could not therefore exist in
separation from the body, for
it
own
but was
simply a way of describing a characteristic of the body (namely life, or the power to act and feel) when constituted in a certain way. 1 It is
was something that could gnaw at the mind of a Simmias, even though he was the disciple of a Pythagorean
legitimate to suppose that this
teacher, but
it
it
I have already" stated, but lest it Pythagorean teaching. be thought to be merely a personal opinion I should like to quote other authorities. Cornford wrote:
As
it is
De An. A, iv, is clearly thinking of the Phaedo and is moreover assuming his own doctrine of the synthesis of simple bodies in compounds, Hicks ad lac.) who speak of the soul-harmony as a harmony of the bodily opposite*. We are
nowhere
entails the inconsistency
told that the Pythagoreans so defined it, and it is this definition that with immortality. Zeller accordingly infers that
Philolaus cannot have meant a harmony of bodily opposites, but more probably the view attributed to him by Claudianus Mamertus, that the soul is connected with the body by means of number and harmony?
Not the mortality but the immortality of the soul depended on its being harmony, but a harmony in the sense in which the cosmos was a harmony. That is, a harmony not ultimately of physical opposites but of numbers. Not that the Pythagoreans in the fifth century drew a
a
clear distinction
between the material and the non-material. We have But there were already seen that they were not in a position to do so. and degrees in these matters. Numbers were nearer to the ultimate,
therefore to the divine, than physical opposites like hot and cold.
1
See Dicaearchus,
fir.
7-12 Wehrli.
553-
ZN,
315
of experience as soul things, stands in the same relation to the world 1 does to body. And in the Pythagorean system the primary nature is
not the physical opposites or a more primitive form of body like the air of Anaximenes: it is number. We may compare Plato's description
foundation.
of the world-soul in the Tmaeus, which certainly has a Pythagorean It is described as invisible and having part in harmonia
and reason' (36E), and is constructed according to the numerical intervals of a musical scale based on one form of the Pythagorean tetractys. At the same time its priority and superiority to the
body of
Taylor
said
the cosmos are emphasized in every way (cf. 346-0). As ' (Comm. on Tim. 136), the cosmic soul is not (as it would be
according to the formula of those Pythagoreans who are refuted in the Phaedo) a harmonia of the corresponding body, but, being wise and
good,
3
it
its
own structure,
has music in
itself
That the soul was for the Pythagoreans a state or arrangement of numbers is what Aristotle says in the Metaphysics. After explaining
that they were the first to make considerable advances in mathematics, and as a result became absorbed in the subject and assumed that mathematical principles underlay everything, he continues (98 5 b 26):
Numbers are the simplest of these, and it was in them that they thought they saw resemblances to the things that are and come to be, rather than in fire and earth and water. Thus such-and-such a disposition of numbers is justice, and another is soul and mind ....
On this view the soul is a harmony of its own parts, not of the parts
of
the body, just as music is a harmony of the numbers i, 2, 3 and 4, and not of the frame and strings of the lyre; so that Simmias's analogy, even
if some
it,
was
in fact
by
genuine Pythagorean reasoning a false one. In Pythagoras's experiment, perhaps, the numbers i, 2, 3 and 4 happened to be embodied in,
or represented by, strings of varying lengths; but this
is
accidental, as is
shown by the fact that they may just as well be represented by columns
1
izSff.,
above.
316
in the Republic^ and can see how much he friends. There (43 iff.) the virtue of
owed
to his
Pythagorean
is
'temperance* (sopkrosyne)
said
be the virtue of the soul as a whole, the result of the smooth working together of all its parts. But Plato speaks in Pythagorean language of it
to
*
singing together through the whole octave , and straight out a harmonia. The man who possesses it
calls
*
is
sophrosyne well-tuned'
and
(flpnooyivos; note that this has nothing to do with his state of health), it is achieved 'by bringing three parts into accord, just like the
highest, lowest
and middle' 1
that
is,
In the case of the soul, the three harmony that have to be into accord are of course reason, passion parts brought (0i/no$) and desire. The soul is a harmonia, but not a harmania of bodily
achieved.
parts or physical opposites. Neither therefore does its well-being (arete) consist in bodily health. Its parts are psychical faculties like desire, courage and intellect, and its arete is a moral virtue, temperance. For
the physical psyche, if I may use that term to connote mere animal life, euharmostia of the bodily parts results in health, anharmosna in disease
or death. But for the divine and iinmortal/wy^ which it was the object of the Pythagorean to cherish and purify, euharmostia was of its own parts and resulted in moral virtue, anharmostia in vice. This, one may
suggest, has the true Pythagorean flavour. It will not be forgotten that for the Pythagoreans moral virtues too, like justice, were equated
with numbers, so that this conclusion is not inconsistent with believing that it is numbers of which the soul is a harmowa.
Were there
good
own
The
To appreciate the full Pythagorean, musical flavour of the language it must be read in Greek:
rniKc5$ l^ovra/<i>iJE0a fipTi &$ dtpiiovia -rivi fj aco^pocruv-q cbpoiamxi . . . 432 A 5i* 5ATj$ drexvoSs TTOCTOCI 6ia tracroSv irapexoulvTj aw<Sovra$; *ro$$ TE daikvECTTcnrous TOUTOV KCX! TO*J$ layypor&rous Kod
431 E
TOU$ nkro\j$.
. .C&OTE 6p06rcxT* &v <}>alpv . . .Kcrrcr <piK7iv axpcpcoviav. 443 D KCC! jikrq$caenrep 6pov/$ Tpel$ dptiovtas OTEXVCOS, vsdrTjs TE Kod Cnr&TT}$
317
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
existence of such a belief has long been recognized. R. Ganszyniec in 1920 characterized the two souls of early Greek thought as (a) breath-
soul 0|A^(T|) and (K) image- or shadow-soul (siScoAov), and quoted * 9 1 also called the life-soul . parallels from Africa. The breath-soul he
The
with
clearly in Empedocles, and a comparison of this Italian philosopher the first half of the fifth century should throw some light and excuse a brief anticipatory summary at this point.
duality
So
thorough
world was concerned, Empedocles was a even extending this outlook to the psychic
functions of sensation and thought. Aristotle (De An. 427321) says that he looked on sensation and thought as the same and both alike as
corporeal, and this
is
bome
writings (frr, 105, 109). to the body which he calls not psyche but daimon an exile from the gods to whom it longs to return (fr. 1 1 5). For its release knowledge is
None
out by the remains of Empedocles's own the less he believed in a divine self alien
necessary, but not the knowledge of the empirical part of us, whose objects, like its foundation, are physical, confined to the lower parts of
man who has gained the riches of known (fr. by like, so to know the divine is to become divine, and the divine is not something which we perceive with any of the bodily senses (fr. 133). Evidently we have other means
the cosmos.
divine
But 'blessed
is
the
is
wisdom*
132). Like
of attaining knowledge, means more like those described by Socrates in the Pkaedo when he speaks of the soul of the philosopher seeking the
truth
'all
by
body behind.
faculty by which we do this is not the psyche in the earlier and popular sense of mere animal life. It can be called a daimon, and there was much earlier lore about daimones, on which Pythagoras and
The
Empedocles could
with
theos,
build.
is
used interchangeably
a distinction, as in Plato's Symposium, daimones are a race of intermediate beings dwelling in the elements
there
god. Where
between heaven and earth (compare Empedocles, fr. 115). Hesiod knows of how they go up and down over the earth clad in mist or
darkness
(i.e. invisible),
Golden Race.
1
It is
and he says they are the souls of the men of the evidently this part of us which in stories of strange
u. d.
Arch. Gesch*
<L
Naturwiss*
See&ngZau&e
bd
u.
318
temporarily in search of divine knowledge. It is the image of life or time (or whatever ocicovos elSooAov may mean) of which Pindar speaks
when he
is
body of every man goes the way of death, 'but there yet image, for it alone is from the gods. It sleeps when the limbs are active, but to men asleep it reveals in many a dream the 1 pleasant or painful issue of things to come/
says the
left alive this
Two different notions of soul, then, existed in contemporary belief, the psyche which 'vanished like smoke* at death, and which medical writers (including no doubt some and therefore heretical
sceptical
made up
Both survived
side
by
of religious
combination of mathe-
goreanism.
E.
INDIVIDUAL PYTHAGOREANS
After Pythagoras himself the history of Pythagoreanism is, for us, to a large extent anonymous. For this reason it has seemed best to treat it Philolaus in particular, also generally, although certain individuals
little
who
have found a place in the expositionmore than names, like Cercops and were said to have written poems in the
*
Orphic corpus, Paron the Pythagorean who called time stupid* because it makes us forget (Arist. Phys. 222 b 18), or Xuthus, of whom
Aristotle reports (Phys. 2i6b24) that in his opinion there must be void to allow of compression, without which either there could be no motion or 'the universe would heave like a wave*. Simplicius in his
comment
Some, however, whether already mentioned or not, deserve a closer look, which has been reserved for this section.
1
Pindar,
(vi,
fr.
640
Littre),
C the language of Hippocr. De Victu^ iv, init. which may, however, be later than the middle of the fourth century (Kirk, HCF,
319
26f.)-
Hippasus
What we have
as a
already seen of Hippasus of Metapontum suggests that Pythagorean he was something of a rebel. There were the stories
of his punishment for revealing mathematical secrets (pp. 149 and 268, above), and the allegation by one of the two divergent types of
Pythagorean that the other owed its origin not to Pythagoras himself but to Hippasus (p. 192). There are other indications that he overlapped the lifetime of Pythagoras and was by no means a docile pupil.
In the events leading up to the democratic conspiracy of Cylon and Ninon (pp. iy8f.) he is mentioned as having, with others, urged the
adoption of democratic measures at variance with the oligarchic policy of the school. Again, to stir up popular feeling against the Pythagoreans Ninon is said to have read from a pretended sacred logos of Pythagoras
*
9
to
It is
times a similar forgery, from similar motives, was attributed to him, probably by transference from the story of the conspiracy with which he evidently had some
going back to Sotion's Successions (c. 200 B.C.) says that the 'Mystical Logos' of Pythagoras was really written by Hippasus to defame him (D.L. viu, 7).
sympathy: a
tradition
first
had been
DK,
historical value,
put
compatible with his having been a personal rival Whatever be the truth about the authorship of the Mystical Logos \
'
first
century
Hippasus
no writings (D.L. vin ? 84, DK, 18, i), so presumably none existed in Hellenistic times. The teaching traditionally attributed to him supports
the belief that he did not simply follow an orthodox Pythagorean line, since from Aristode onwards (MetapL 98437) he is regularly coupled
with Heraclitus as a proponent of the doctrine that the arche Theophrastus (ap. SimpL, DK, addition that both men held the
1
is fire.
18, 7) enlarged
on
this
by saying
finite,
in
and
(DK,
56^
32O
Hippasus
both produced existing things out of fire by condensation and rarefaction and resolved them into fire again. Since this standard Peripatetic description
of a monistic cosmogony misrepresents Heraclitus (pp. 455ff., below), we cannot well trust it for Hippasus, but must content ourselves with the knowledge that he gave the primacy to fire: but seeing that for all his independence of mind he is regularly agreed to have remained a Pythagorean, it be that he meditated may supposed
on
status assigned
power residing in the original fiery unit, and the divine 1 by the Pythagoreans to the fire still burning at the centre. The doctrines of Hippasus and Heraclitus seem to have been much
later ages.
the creative
confused in
in Simplicius's version of Theophrastus, 5 'by some necessity of fate are added and
3
cosmos completed its changes in a limited time. The same phrase occurs where however the words it appears to be referred to Heraclitus and connected with his saying that everything is an exchange
*
for
fire'.
the statement
inappropriate. It does, however, describe very well the Pythagorean doctrine of the cyclical repetition of history (p. 28 1 , above),
refer to Hippasus.
even if trustworthy (which is doubtful) contains nothing original. Naturally he is coupled with Heraclitus as teaching that the soul was of a fiery nature, but being a Pythagorean he
also
him
thought of it as a number. Claudianus Mamertus also ascribes to the ideas that one would expect from a Pythagorean: he said that soul and body were very different things, that soul is active when the
is
body
x
inactive
and
alive
when
it is
dead.3
DK, 1 8,
911 8
xpovov cbpiopivov
slvai TTJS
TOV Koapou
psrajiJoAfjs.
Cf. Tlieophr.
ap.
18,
7 already quoted).
3 say that the passage of Clement, Aetius and Claudjanus Mamertus. See DK, 18, 8-xo. Claudianus Mamertus is from a Neopythagorean forgery, but even if so, it contains no doctrine that could not be paralleled in the fifth century B.C, With corpora torpentz viget cf. Pindar, fr.
DK
321
again suggested
by
a story of Aristoxenus
he produced the concordant intervals (fr. 90 Wehrli, DK, discs bronze whose thicknesses were in the proportions four by striking
18, 12) that
4:3, 3:2, and 2:1* (Compare the story of Pythagoras in the blacksmith's shop, p. 223, above.) lamblichus (DK, 18, 15) says that Pythagoras and the mathematicians of his time recognized the arith-
and harmonic means, but called the last-named was Archytas and Hippasus who re-named it harmonic. hypenantiai There is no suggestion in the passage that Hippasus was a contemporary
metical, geometrical,
it
of Archytas.
(2) Petron
All that
we know
of Petron
arranged in a triangle.This is be of great interest if we knew anything of the arguments or evidence on which he based it: but we do not. We do not even know that he was
a Pythagorean; in fact the main object in giving space to him must be destructive rather than constructive.
he said there were 183 worlds a striking enough statement, and might
is
that
Our sole authority is Plutarch in the treatise De Defectu Oracidomm. At 422 B one of the speakers in the dialogue tells how he met in the
neighbourhood of the Persian Gulf a mysterious stranger, not a Greek, who was a kind of desert prophet. This man told him, together with
a great deal of mythology about the gods, that there are 183 worlds (kosmoi) arranged in the form of a triangle. Each side of the triangle has 60 worlds and the remaining three are placed at the corners. They
are in contact with one another and revolve steadily as in a dance. To this another of the company retorts that the stranger was a fraud, a pilferer of other men's thoughts and obviously a Greek well versed in
contact according to element* he does not explain further, nor does he add
it
more
plausible (4220,
DK,
16).
322
Petron: Ecphantus
guess
Wilamowitz (in Hermes, 1884,444) that when Plutarch mentions Hippys of Rhegium he means Hippasus of Metapontum, because both Petron and Hippasus were Pythagoreans. On this one cannot do better than
quote Cornford (CQ, 1934, i4f.)r
Against
this conjecture there
left
is
2
nothing in writing.
of Rhegium,
PW, vin,
mean Hippys, it is more likely that he meant Hipparchides of Rhegium (Iambi. Vit. PytL 267), who has at least the advantage over Hippasos of
coining from Rhegium.
lived far
I
why
Phanias,
into the third century, should not have quoted Hippys (whom places in the first half of that century), or why Hippys should not
eccentric view.
It
on
was not unusual for historians to no better evidence than this for ranking Petron among the 'earliest Pythagoreans*. He may have been a contemporary of Leucippus or Democritus or Plato.
refer to cosmological speculations.
There
is
(3)
Ecphantus
The very existence of this philosopher has had to be defended. Voss in 1896, followed by Tannery in 1897 and later, put forward a theory that
he and Hicetas (no.
below) were imaginary characters in a dialogue by Heraclides Ponticus, later mistaken for historical figures as was the Timaeus of Plato. The thesis rests on the known fact that Heraclides
4,
wrote dialogues, together with a certain similarity between the doctrines attributed to the three men. In the case of Hicetas, this applies only to
the theory that the earth rotates. In addition Ecphantus shared with Heraclides an atomic theory of matter. Voss and Tannery were followed
by Heidel in 1909 (though by 1940 he had become more cautious and would only say that 'perhaps' Ecphantus was an imaginary person),
and cf. 109. ^ 6o, Contemporary of Cicero and friend of Atticus. The work of his which Diogenes Laertius cites was one devoted to distinguishing between writers of the same name, a very necessary task in the confusion of Greek nomenclature.
3
323
Pythagoras and
the
Pythagoreans
Heath in 1913, and Frank In 1923. More recent scholars have on the whole followed Diels, Wellmann and Daebritz in rejecting this 1 scepticism., e.g. Praechter (1923), Taylor (1928) and Vlastos (I953). The theory can hardly stand. Against it may be said first that both
in his doxohim as his names graphical work, apparently as real persons. Cicero authority for Hicetas, and for Ecphantus we have statements from both
by Theophrastus
Aetius and Hippolytus, whose common source can have been no other. And as Vlastos says, 'it seems most unlikely that Theophrastus would
present the view of a fictitious character in a dialogue of his own contemporary Heraclides in a form that would lead the doxographers to
mistake these views for those of a historical thinker. There is no parallel for such a mistake in the doxographic tradition; the case of Timaeus is
surely evidence to the contrary/ Apart from this, the supposed resemblance in doctrine between
Heraclides and Ecphantus is only partial. Heraclides was known for having given up the term 'atoms' and substituted 'disjoined particles*.
from Democritean atoms by being subject to nothing like this of Ecphantus, and his belief that change. the atoms move not by weight nor impact but by a divine power which he calls mind and souP is not noticeably the same as the one attributed
These were
2
said to differ
We hear
by Cicero
says, 'applies the epithet divine to the cosmos, now to mind, and again attributes divinity to the planets, deprives his god of perception and conceives him as changeable in form '.
to Heraclides,
who, he
now
The
and worth
is
slender in amount,
51.)^
it
DK,
was not
them
1
as
we
believe
them
to be.
He
Some references on both sides: Voss, De HeracL Pont, vita et scripds (diss. Rostock, 1896), 64; Tannery, Arch. Gesch. PhiL 1898, 266, REG, 1897, 134-6, Rev. de Phllol. 1904, 233 ff.; Heidel, A, 1909, 6, AJP, 1940, 19, n. 36; Frank, Plato u. d. sag. Pytk. 138 f.; Heath, AristarcnuSy 251. Contrast Wellmann, s.v. 'Ekphantos* in RE, v, 221 $ ; Daebritz, s.v. 'HeracL Pont/
TAP
in RE, vin, 477; Ueberweg-Praechter, 345, n. i; Taylor, Timaeus, 239; Vlastos, Gnomon, 1953, 32, n. i. See also ZN, 606, n. 3. As Nestle points out, even the appearance of these two as characters in a dialogue by Heraclides would be no evidence against their historical existence*
2 3
ovctppoi Syxoi frr. 11820 Wehrli, Tro6-nT<i as opposed to ocrra0r[ fr. 120. The fragments of a work On Kingship attributed to Ecphantus by Stobaeus
late Hellenistic times.
(not in
DK)
are
production of
324
Ecphantus
visible bodies
which
size,
shape,
is
and power.
not
Out
2
of them
divine
and
their
number
limited,
infinite.
These bodies
owe
of
their
power which he
calls
movement not to weight or external impact but to a mind and soul. The cosmos is a form [or maniwhich reason it has become, by divine power, of the cosmos and moves about its own
festation, t8cc]
this 3 for
The
earth
(K) Aet. i, 3, 19: 'Ecphantus of Syracuse, one of the Pythagoreans, held that the principles of all things were indivisible bodies and the void, for he was the first to declare that the Pythagorean monads were corporeal.*
(c) Aet. n, i, 2 includes Ecphantus in a list of philosophers who believed the cosmos to be unique. * (W) Aet. n, 3, 3 : Ecphantus held that the cosmos was composed of atoms,
Ecphantus the Pythagorean make the earth move, not in the sense of changing its location but turning about an axis like a wheel: it revolves round its own
centre
from West
is
to East.'
positive evidence for the date of Ecphantus, but if the reports of his beliefs are in general trustworthy, he must have been at least late enough to come under the influence of the atomists, and prob-
There
no
last
generation of Pythagoreans
who were
con-
He was a Pythagorean who saw the possibilities of combining the Pythagorean evolution of a world from numbers with genuine atomism as taught by Democritus. The words he was the
c
first
to declare the Pythagorean monads to be corporeal* have been taken, on the assumption that Ecphantus is a fourth-century figure, as
invalidating Aristotle's
1
as to
signify little more than quality, but always in an active sense. That is to say, in using the word a writer would always be thinking of what it described in terms of producing an effect, e.g. of a
colour the effect which it produces on the eye. In the medical writers it was frequently applied to the characteristics of a disease, which in an obvious sense are active powers at the same time. Cf. the note of W. H. S. Jones, *Ai!nrayii$ in scientific writings*, in Anon. Lonnensisy 9 10. a Keeper's emendation Kod OUK drreipov (for the nonsensical iced TOVTO &) gives the most probable sense. It
was accepted by
Zeller
(ZN, 605, n. 2) and more recently by Kranz in Convivium^ of the clause establish the material point that for Ecphantus the
The translation follows Keeper's emendation (printed by DK) TOUTOU nlv o&v TOV K60|iov given
\&> o&v T. K. dSivai ISelv.
325
Pythagoras and
tude in earlier times.
statement
is
the
Pythagoreans
(if Aetius's
In
fact,
to be trusted)
how
between
Pythagoreans were not aware of the inconsistency involved in building a universe out of numbers. They treated numbers as if they were corporeal ( had magnitude'), but they did not say to themselves 'numbers are corporeal , having neither the words in which to say it nor a grasp of the dichotomy which the words imply. Numbers for them could
5
exist
on both the mathematical and the physical planes at the same time. Ecphantus, one may suppose, belonged to the period when the distinction was emerging into consciousness, and having therefore to make the choice he declared the monads to be corporeal, thus giving Pythagoreanism a push in the direction of atomism of the Democritean type.
The
(frr.
first
know-
ledge of
7-9); but the addition ofdynamis to size and shape as a differentiating property of the atoms was a striking and original contribution.
For the 'weight and external impact' of the atomists he substituted life and mind as the cosmogonic force, possibly borrowing from Anaxagoras the idea of nous as primary motive cause, though passages (a) and (J) suggest that he allowed it a more continuous role. In Anaxagoras's system mind simply set the wheels going and then withdrew, leaving the cosmos to continue under its own momentum, subject to purely mechanical laws. For Ecphantus the Pythagorean the cosmos
itself is
way in which
links
divinity causally with its sphericity is strongly reminiscent of Plato's Timaeus. In view of the textual uncertainty we cannot attach
its
much weight to this, and even if it is correct there is not the evidence to account for it with certainty. It might be a Platonic reinterpretation of
Ecphantus's own doctrine and due to the doxographer, but the giveand-take between Plato and contemporary Pythagoreanism was such
that the debt might have been Plato's, or again a debt indirectly to Plato by Ecphantus himself.
owed
directly or
also differed
Ecphantus
of the atoms
finite.
contained an infinite
space.
number of worlds scattered about the vastness of Once again Ecphantus has modified atomism into something
more
in keeping with the religious requirements of Pythagoreanism. Philolaus, it seems, was the first to make the momentous suggestion
that the apparent daily rotation of the heavenly bodies is affected by the actual movement of the earth from which we observe them. 1 He
explained
central
this,
fire.
however, as a planetary revolution about an invisible little later Ecphantus and Heraclides (there is not the
evidence to assign priority between them), and probably also Hicetas, brought the new idea more into line both with earlier philosophy and with common sense by restoring the earth to the centre and supposing
it
to rotate about
its
own
axis.
It is interesting to note that Copernicus, in the preface to De Revolutionibus Orlium Coelestium, quotes Aet. in, 13, 1-3 (the theories of
Philolaus, Heraclides
as
and Ecphantus about the movement of the earth) him the having given courage to consider seriously (quamvis alsurda
terrae aliquo motu*
be explained posito
suggests that the indivisible bodies of Ecphantus, possessed oJynamis and activated by divine power, may have been a direct influence on the
monads of Giordano Bruno (themselves containing their own kind of cosmogonic spiritual power) and through him on the monads which Leibniz posited as forces primitives*. Not only would Bruno have read Copernicus, but Hippolytus's Refutation was also well known in the Renaissance period. Little as we know of Ecphantus, it does seem that his Pythagorean version of atomic theory was an original and
*
Of Hicetas we know
as follows:
(a)
first
even
less
than of Ecphantus.
The
testimonies are
D.L.vm,85 (DK,44Ai):*Phiiolausis also supposed to have been the moves in a circle, though some say it was
1
pp.
z86,
above.
327
moved
axis at
by turning upon
about
its
were stationary
Act
in, 9, 1-2
(DK,
50, 2)
that there
was one
Pythagorean
counter-earth/
a minority
who
carry no weight. Van der Waerden (Astr. d. Pyth. 55) has, it is true, attempted to find the theory of a planetary earth in the words of Cicero, which he translates not 'about its axis' but 'about the axis of the universe'.
There
'i.e.
is 5
as
'its',
axem y
"about an axis", or, in my opinion, "about the axis" (of the universe)'. But this argument is more naturally reversed. In the
absence of any qualifying word at all, it is much easier to suppose that * circum axem. . se convertat means turns around its own axis' than to
.
To
make
is
to offer
(c),
which
is
highly suspicious. compiler has practically condensed his Theophrastus (or an intermediate source) to nonsense, for it is absurd to confine belief in the uniqueness of the earth to Thales and
The
most improbable that in a brief enumeration like where this, only the chief representatives of a theory are being mentioned, the name of Philolaus should not occur in connexion with the
his followers. It is also
counter-earth with which he was so generally associated. Boeckh went so far as to suppose that the name of Philolaus had fallen out in tran-
and his conjectural emendation was accepted as probable by Whatever the explanation, it is safest to trust to Cicero's version of Theophrastus, and to group Hicetas with Ecphantus and
scription,
Zeller.
1
1
ZN,
elvcti
530, n.
i.
ploy
TTIV yffv, 1.
Boecklfs suggestion was that the sentence originally ran 0. 6 TTueay6pios (fiiav, 0>iA6Aao$ 5 6 TTu0ay6peios> 50o, KrX.
KCC!
ol drr' ocCrrou
Hicetas: Philolaus
Heraclides as one of those
who
system by sup-
posing the earth to rotate 'not in the sense of changing its location'. Nothing is known of Hicetas's life, but if the above interpretation is
is, as Zeller remarked (ZN, 530, n. i), much to be said for Boeckh's conjecture that he was a younger man than Philolaus. Boeckh thought it also probable that Ecphantus was his pupil.
right, there
(5) Philolaus
Philolaus
a Italy, according to some The best evidence for his date is the Phaedo, The words of Cebes at 61 E, I heard
*
',
Thebes but
left it
The upheavals
in South Italy,
by Minar on good grounds to about and tradition to Aristoxenus (the friend of some of his 454, going back 1 pupils) said that he was then a young man. The statement of Diogenes
laus's exile to
that Plato
met
when he
visited
the
West about
388, rests
on no good
it
on
this reckoning.
Other evidence
accord, and
we may take
is not impossible P. E. and (cited by Raven, 94) is in that Philolaus was born about 474, that is,
authority, but
perhaps no more than 20 to 25 years after the death of Pythagoras. Aristotle, like Plato, mentions Philolaus once only, and in a rather
discussing voluntary and involuntary action, and suggesting that one must take into consideration what a man's nature is able to bear. For some the
is
compulsion of anger or desire may be so strong that acts committed under its influence cannot be said to be voluntary, 'but, as Philolaus
said, there are logoi
even
tell
us that
which are too strong for us*. 2 By itself this does not Aristotle knew a book of Philolaus, for sceptical
out that so brief and gnomic a saying
failed to point
E. L. Minar, Early
PytL
1225330. I
am
accepting the
now
EE is an early work
of Aristotle
himself.
For the exact interpretation of the saying, it is unfortunate that such a maid-of-all-work among words as logos should have been used. Diels, approved by Wilamowitz and followed by Mondolfo, * rendered it motives', which is perhaps as near as one can get.
329
as
one of his
obiter dicta.
But one
may
agree with Mondolfo (see below) that doxographical testimonies going back to Aristotle's pupils Theophrastus and Menon (p. 278, above) are
sufficient
his
quoted from Hermippus, the Alexandrian scholar of the third century B.C., but it has shared the disrepute attaching to the obvious invention with which
is
it is
name on a variety of subjects. The statement that Philolaus wrote one book*
is,
work
without acknowledg-
treatise
on Pythagorean
Philolaus,
DK):
opening sentence (D.L. ilid., was constructed out of cosmos in the 'Nature
its
unlimited and limiting factors, as was the whole cosmos and all things in it/ Bywater, however, emphasizes that Demetrius was a writer of
the
first
which
the time of the revival of Pythagoreanism in Cicero's friend Nigidius Figulus played a leading part, a revival
century
its
B.C.,
and eager acceptance of spurious writings. A number of authors and compilers of the Christian era claim to quote verbatim extracts from Philolaus, and it is primarily around these
notable for
credulity
5
'fragments
modern times
for almost a
century and a half. In this century the chief proponents of opposing views have been E. Frank and R. Mondolfo, and anyone wishing to
trace the history of the
2
argument in detail will find full references to date in their accounts. Short of an unlikely discovery of fresh evidence, the question will no doubt never be settled in a manner which all
scholars can accept as final. Here we can only pause for a few observations which make no claim to decide it.
wording Diogenes suggests that Hermippus knew the book, but would by no means go bail for the story (pipXlov fv, 6 9TJOIV *E Xfyav -nvi TWV ouyypa^cov tIA&rowoc TOV (piAoaofov . . .cbvr[aaa0ai). Frank, Plato u. d, sag. Pythagoreer, esp. 263-335; Mondolfo in his Italian translation of Teller-Nestle (1938), i, 2, 367-82. Of recent discussions in English one may mention A. Cameron, Pyth. Background^ 46, n. 29, and Raven, P. and E. 92-100. A lively defence of the fragments has been undertaken by de Santillana and Pitts, Isis, 1951, 112-20. For the latest conspectus of the controversy see TheslefT, Pythagorean Literature, 41-5.
DJL vin, 85. The growth and variations of this legend are set forth by Bywater in J. Pfiilol. 1868, 27* It *s a pity that their well-founded indignation at this calumny has led some scholars to of deny that Pythagoreanism had any considerable influence on Plato at all The
1
330
Philolaus
to be at their best
on
1868, 20-53)
employs arguments which are hardly worthy of that great scholar. The question, he says., resolves itself into a somewhat narrower one: are
the Philolaic fragments on number metaphysical rather than arith* to that is Platonic in their origin rather than Pythagorean? metical, say,
decessors.
We
A 5)',
he writes,
*a general
of ch. 6, after predecessors/ the is: 'To the describing Pythagorean philosophies, philosophies described there succeeded the work of Plato, which in most respects
Aristotle says at the beginning
What
it
had some
features of its
own
apart
from
Again, in
fr.
14 Philolaus attributes Orphic doctrines about the soul and seers*. To speak in this way of 'the
Orphic societies of the fifth century B.C/, says Bywater, would have been natural to a writer of the age of Cicero, but not to a writer who
himself lived in that century. Apart from the fact that the existence of anything called 'an Orphic society' in the fifth century is doubtful, the
doctrines got their
to
in verses ascribed
certainly ancient and venerable in fifth-century eyes. Equally absurd is the argument that to say that the body is the soul's tomb is 'diametrically opposed* to the description
who were
of it as linked by way of punishment to the body, because in one case the soul must be supposed to be dead, and in the other alive! The
doctrine expressed is simply that to be confined in a body is a grim business for the soul and prevents it from enjoying its true life. There is
no contradiction
illustrate the
were used to
same
In conclusion Bywater says that forgeries of this sort were easily acceptable in antiquity, but not now, because 'criticism has learned to
see continuity even in the
world of thought;
331
we assume
that ideas
do
whose philosophy, it may with equal plausibility be argued, could not have been what it was had not the soil and atmosphere been prepared for him (as his pupil Aristotle
apply
this salutary principle to Plato,
tells
us that it was) by the Pythagoreans. The position maintained by Frank is a difficult one. Those who (like Bywater) suppose the spurious work of Philolaus, from which our
'Timaeus on the World-Soul*, 'Ocellus Lucanus and other similar 1 of Frank is that the forgeries, have an easier time; but the thesis
forgery was perpetrated in the immediate circle of Plato's own disciples. This leaves a limited field, from which his own choice is Speusippus,
Plato's
well-known
what one wrote to somebody else (p. 277), which was practice' of the Academy. Yet the fact that it was established practice, it would seem, was not enough to save even Speusippus's own contemporaries like Theophrastus from falling into the trap of supposing that Philolaus had really written what Speusippus put forward in his name. When Frank goes so far as to entertain the possibility that Philolaus may be no more than a fictional character in Plato's Phaedo
'the
(p. 294),
raises
to handle evidenced
None of this affords any positive evidence for the genuineness of the
fragments.
1
strongly assailed
on grounds both of
Though of course the knowledge of a book of Philokus on the part of Hennippus has to be explained away. See Bywater, p. 28. 1 P. 334- *Also haben wir wohl in Speusipp den wahren Verfasser unserer Fragmente zu
erkenneii.*
The passage of the Tkeol. Arithm. from which comes our information about the relation of Speusippus's work to Philolaus's has been translated on p. 260, above. Wilaniowitz, who also believed the fragments to be spurious, nevertheless argued in a way directly contrary to Frank:
3
In the Tkeol. Math, [sic] is an extract from a work of Speusippus IT. TTu0. dpiOn&v, which according to the anonymous writer (or rather Nicomachus) is taken largely from Philolaus. There is not the slightest ground for attributing this statement to Speusippus* (P/aton, II, 88). Contrast Frank, p. 277: But out of all these [sc. the disciples of Plato] only one had represented his numberspeculation as
*
drawn from
332
Philolaus: Archytas
language and of content, and a detailed reply on both counts is offered by Mondolfo, to whom a reader must be referred for the best defence
possible. Here the aim has been to reconstitute as far as possible the flexible structure of Pythagorean philosophy up to the time of Plato,
it has been described (for reasons stated at the beginning) in general terms rather than as a series of separate achievements by individual philosophers. In this reconstruction we have relied largely on a critical
and
use of the information supplied by Aristotle. The opinions of Philolaus have been introduced only where they were necessary contributions to
the
in each case as
this
it
arose
have
him with Following procedure belief in the soul as an immortal harmonia (309-12), and have seen him as the authority of Speusippus in constructing solids out of points,
attribution.
we have
credited
(260), as probable author planetary earth and central fire (284-7, 327),
lines
and surfaces
Eurytus (273).
regular solids and the question of a fifth element (26773) and considered his embryology particularly for the light it throws on the micro-
macrocosm analogy
Pythagorean thought (278 f.). The rest of the testimonies and fragments (which would in any case add little to our
in
sketch of fifth-century Pythagoreanism) have been left out of account owing to the continuing doubt of their authenticity.
(6)
Archytas
Archytas of Tarentum brings Pythagoreanism down to the time of Plato and the Academy. More than that, with him Pythagoreanism
makes a direct and personal impact on Plato himself, for the two men formed a lasting friendship. He may well have contributed to the
central thesis of the Republic that philosophers should rule, for he
seems
to have been a
at
most
successful statesman
to that
Tarentum comparable
of Pericles
Athens.
the law against holding the supreme office of strategos for more than one annual term was waived in his favour, and that he held it seven times; also that as a commander he was never defeated in battle. Several
authorities stress the mildness
if
Strabo
is
to
be
made
older or younger than Plato. three visits to the West, first at the age of about forty
much
388/7), then again after an interval of twenty years, and thirdly six his first journey he visited the Italian cities before years after that.
On
to Sicily, and in all probability made the acquaintance of then. At any rate by the second visit he had established Archytas relations with him and the Tarentines as well as with the tyrant of
going on
2 Syracuse, Dionysius II: in his efforts to persuade Plato to come to Sicily a third time Dionysius sent a trireme with one Archedemus,
Plato
would value
as that of an associate of
hostility
On
of the
to Archytas and life, he got word his other friends in Tarentum, and they sent a ship to Syracuse and
fear for his
persuaded Dionysius to
let
him go.
Plato's seventh letter.
It
says nothing of any interchange of philosophical ideas, but the statements of later writers, used by Cicero, that one of Plato's motives in visiting the
Western centres of Pythagoreanism had been to learn more of that philosophy, have everything in their favour.3 Discussion of this point
will
be more appropriate in connexion with Plato, but it is likely that the shock of Socrates's death, and further reflexion on his methods,
not stand unless defended and supported by a metaphysic and a psychology which Socrates himself had been neither able nor concerned to
provide.
In his search for these he was immensely attracted Pythagorean outlook on mankind and the cosmos.
by
the
Our
1
D.L. vm,
4).
Diogenes
at least
Aristoxenus,
seems to tion about Archytas should be well founded, for in addition to Aristoxenus Aristotle himself wrote a work on him in three books (DK, A 13) and for his mathematics our authorities quote the history of Eudemus. In Ep. vn, 3380, he claims to have acted as a successful intermediary in bringing about ^evlov xcd (piXiocv between these parties. 3 See the passages quoted by Field, Plato and his Contemporaries, 223 f.
who was born at Tarentum and wrote a life of Archytas. His father Spintharus have known Archytas personally (Iambi. V.P. 197, DK, Ay). In general our informa-
334
Archytas
relates chiefly to the
advances which he
made
ized branches of
an outstanding mathematician, who in addition to other successes solved the problem of the duplication of the cube, as formulated by Hippocrates of Chios, by an construction which the excites admiration of modem historians elegant of mathematics. 1 In harmonics he carried on the work of Pythagoras
knowledge* He was
by determining the numerical ratios between the notes of the tetrachord in three types of scale: diatonic, chromatic, enharmonic. 3 He was also said to have been the first to apply mathematical principles
to the study
vn,
14,
DK,
of mechanics (D.L. vm, 83 and Vitruvius, praefatio 17) and to have been an inventor of mechanical toys.
fly (DK, AIO<Z), and became is and 'Archytas's proverbial already mentioned by * Aristotle {Pol. I34obi6 DK, AID), who describes it as a toy which they give to children so that by using it they may refrain from breaking
rattle'
?
One
things about the house; for young things cannot keep still'. This goes with other stories about his consideration for children and slaves
(DK, A 8).
Although the testimonies, and any fragments
Field's
1
be
we need
not share
doubts
For convenient descriptions see K. Freeman, Comp. to Presoc. Pkilf. 236 , or Heath, Manual ofGk. Math. 155-7. Fuller information about Archytas's mathematics will be found in Heath's Hist. ofGk. Math. vol. i. Van der Waerden in his article on Pythagorean arithmetic {Math. Annalen, 120, 1947/9) gives an interesting appraisal Archytas, he concludes, was 'an inventive geometer and outstanding in mechanics and musical theory, with an unlucky love of logic and
exact arithmetical calculation' (p, 150). a Freeman, op. cit. 238. His theories
(pp.
226
above).
3 The prevailing opinion is that the mathematical fragments are genuine, the rest spurious. Cf. the opinions of Zelier (ZN, I, 375-7), Wellmann in RE, n, t.v. and Ross, s.v. in the OCD. Frank was less sceptical about Archytas than about Philokus: he regarded the 'fragments* in
(contrast his arguments about Philolaus, p. 332, above), but considered the authenticity of the 8 B* section (actual quotations in Doric) a question that cannot be decided. He admitted, however,
that in this case a resemblance to Plato is no bar, 'because here Plato evidently follows Archytas closely' (Plato u. die sog. Pytk. 384, n. 413). andJustice, which had been A* Delatte defended the fragments in Stobaeus of the work On rejected on the grounds that they presuppose the peculiarly Platonic theory of Forms (Essai sur
Law
on his arguments by Bivaud (MeL Glot^j 14654). (In general, however, Rivaud's argumentation concerning the extent of Pythagorean participation in politics is perverse*) Minar on the other hand strongly supports Delatte (Early PytL PoL 1 1 1).
1932, ii,
(1925),
335
There
is
he not only gave chief place to mathematics and music but also related them to wider themes. In fir. i we find him repeating the Pythagorean claim that mathematics is the key to all nature, both as a whole and in
detail
He
infinite
extension
beyond the cosmos by asking the pertinent question: 'If I were at the extremity, say at the heaven of the fixed stars, could I stretch out
hand or
staff
my
or could
not?' 1
The
Aristotelian Prollemata
(DK,
and
question the parts of plants and animals, other than the organs, round? One passage from his mathematical works (generally agreed to be
interested in biology, but in a typically abstract that it occurs to him to ask is: way, for the
Why
genuine) deserves at
Greek thought.
Pythagorean
It
number and calculation are the ruling force not in the world but also in human relations and morals, and natural only only in so far as they are heeded can society be harmoniously organized. At the same time we are reminded how much of the thought of Plato is
belief that
formed in the Pythagorean mould, for it is precisely this mathematical conception of the ordering of human affairs which impresses, and sometimes disturbs, us in his works.
The discovery of calculation ends faction and promotes unanimity. Where has entered, unfair advantage is impossible and equality established, since is what enables us to agree over our contracts with one another. Through
it it it
the poor receive from the powerful, and the rich give to those in need, for both are confident that thus they will have their rightful share. 2
APPENDIX
Time and the Unlimited
*
The universe is unique, and from the Unlimited it draws in time, breath, and void which distinguishes the places of separate things' (from Aristotle's
treatise on the Pythagorean philosophy, cited by Stobaeus, See pp. 277, 280.).
1
Ed
i,
18, i.
A 24 (from Eudemus). The answer to the question as given by Eudemus contains Aristotelian terminology, but Archytas must certainly have asked the question, and no doubt Eudemus gives the gist of his reply.
3
From
33 6
Time and
the
Unlimited
In dealing with Anaximander (p. 86, above) I had occasion to remark that the drawing of distinctions between different meanings of
the same
to a fairly advanced stage of thought. When he spoke of the arche of all things as the apeiron the Unlimited, or
word belongs
Infinite he meant by this not only that there was an indefinitely large amount of it but also that (in contrast to the cosmos which was formed within it) it had no beginning in time. The same confusion can be seen
in the middle of the fifth century in Melissus. This follower of Parmenides, who like him denied the possibility of any process of be-
coming, stated first that what exists, 'since it did not come into being, is and always was and always will be, and has no beginning or end but is apeiron\ Not only does he here use apeiron in a temporal sense; he
goes on to argue openly from
as
it
must be for ever apeiron in magnitude. To his way of thinking, all that has to be shown is that it has neither beginning (arche) nor end*. If this is shown in one respect, it holds good in the
exists for ever, so it
'Nothing which has a beginning and end is either evera proposition which he treated as convertible. 1 lasting or apeiron* We may be sure that the Pythagoreans of the same period drew no
other also.
clearer distinctions,
must also be true that the limiting of the Unlimited by the imposition on it of number (regularity, measure, or due proportion), which is
what is meant by the generation of a kosmos, applies in both spheres. In the sphere of extension, this means the imposition of geometrical proportion whereby the formless 'Unlimited* becomes differentiated into the several distinct forms of matter which we know; in duration, it means that by the creation of the heavenly bodies and their regular, recurrent and harmonious motions, time becomes subject to measure and in place of mere succession we have the orderly and predictable series of days, nights, months and years.
A
Plato
1
make
this clearer.
Since
Melissus, fir. 2, 3 and 4. These quotations have been interpreted differently (e.g. by Cherniss, ACP, 67-^71), but I cannot myself see that Melissus is to be absolved from the confusion. His thought will be discussed in detail in voL n.
337
it
will at
demonstrate that
distinguish
possible to think in this way, that is, to time (xpovos) from mere succession (TO irpoTspov KCCI
it is
*
uorspov) and so to speak without absurdity of a time before time existed. For Plato time came into existence together with the heavens'
*By ordering the heavens, the Creator made an everlasting image, moving according to number, of the eternity which abides in unity. This image it is which we call time; for there were no days, nights, months or years before the birth of the heaven, but by putting it together he contrived to bring them into being' (370, E). So from the
(383).
'
god's intention to create time, in order that time might be started, sun, moon? and five other stars called "wanderers" were created to mark off
and maintain the number of time' (380). There follows immediately the description of their intricate circular paths.
Earlier in the dialogue Plato has said that to create the cosmos, the
but
in discordant and disorderly motion, and brought it from disorder into order* (30A). Summarizing at a later stage, he says that there were
Being (the ideal model of the future cosmos), Becoming (the disorderly mass) and Space, these three, even before the generation of the heavens
(ral irpiv oupocuov ysv&jdoci, 520).
Putting these statements together, A. E. Taylor used them as an argument in favour of dismissing the whole temporal element in the
Timaeus as mythical, on the ground that 'no sane man could be meant to be understood literally in maintaining that time and the world began together, and also that there was a state of things before there was any
world' (Commentary on the Timaeus, p. 69). How far Plato's account of creation is to be understood literally is not a question to be decided
here, but
we need have no
objection as irrelevant.
We
translate
XP VO$ by
'time*, but
it is
not
surprising that two words belonging not only to different languages but to different civilizations do not coincide exactly. Time for us embraces the whole field of 'before and after', but Aristotle says: * Before and after are involved in motion, but time is these in so far as
they are numbered' (Pkys. 223 ai8). Elsewhere he defines time as 'the number of motion in respect of before and after', and he can seriously
be nothing counted. ... If nothing can count but soul, and within soul mind, there cannot be time without soul, but only the substratum of
(ibid. 21^2^ 223 a 22). To put it another way, we speak of a clock as an instrument for measuring time. In Plato's and Aristotle's
time'
scheme of
is itself
passage of events but a standard by which that passage can be measured. At one point, Plato notes that whereas the revolutions of sun and moon
are universally recognized as time-keepers
month and year, those of the other planets, being less conspicuous, are not made use of in this way. 'Indeed', he continues, 'men scarcely
realize that the journeyings
of these planets are time/ 1 One could not indication that for Plato time is actually to be
with the planetary motions. 3 is movement, or the measure of movement, when regular and recurrent, and it is obvious that there can be movement when there is not time. After Plato, the distinction has perhaps been
Time then
most
clearly expressed
by
Plutarch,
who
writes (10070): 'Hence Plato said that time came into being together with the heavens, but there was motion before the generation of the
heavens. There was not then time, for there was no order or measure or distinction, only indefinite motion which was as it were the shapeless
Our
say time
itself'.
is the movement of the whole, others that it is the sphere The first view is obviously Plato's, and it is hardly necessary for
Simplicius to
cite, as
The second
some
ancient
though Simplicius rather obscurely suggests that 'perhaps' these have misunderstood a sentence of Archytas. According * to Aetius Pythagoras [that is the Pythagoreans] said that time was the
authorities also said,
OUK lacccnv xp&>ov SVTCC Tds ToOnrcov irA 3$>c 6$ fires slTTEtv Arist. Phys. 223!} 21 5i6 Kod Soicel 6 XP&vo$ ilvai fj -rife o^odpas idvricns, ai fiAXoa KiWjaets Kod 6 XP^voS Tonirrq TTJ KivfjaEi.
3
1
5n TocCm}
yrrpov/vrm
339
that everything is in time and everything is in the sphere of the whole; but the statement is too childish for us to go into its impossibilities/
which Aristotle habitually adopts towards the Pythathe goreans, and theory itself bears their characteristic mark of a fusion between concrete and abstract, the cosmic sphere and the measure of
is
The tone
that
cosmic motion.
We
treatise
from
Aristotle's
the Pythagoreans, that according to them the universe in from the Unlimited time and breath and the void. draws (o&pocv6$) The cosmic nucleus starts from the unit-seed, which generates mathe-
matically the number-series and physically the distinct forms of matter. To do this it feeds on the Unlimited outside and imposes form or limit
on it. Physically speaking this Unlimited is unformed matter, imagined as breath or air; 2 mathematically it is extension not yet delimited by
number or
figure.
full sense, it
But it had a temporal aspect too. As apeiron in the was movement or duration without beginning, end or
internal division
not time, in Plutarch's words, but only the shapeless and unformed raw material of time, just as it was the unformed matter
number is imposed on it
As soon, however, as it the unit, or limiting principle, by and at once it is time in the proper sense. Thus
figure.
in saying that 'the nearest portions of the Unlimited were drawn in and limited by the Limit' the Pythagoreans were describing what to us
might seem three unrelated processes, though to them they were only three aspects of a single process: the Limit, that is the growing cosmos, breathed in matter for its physical growth, it imposed form on sheer
extension, and
by developing
repetitive circular
motion around
into time
itself.
21, I, DK, 58833 : TTu6oy6pas T6v xp^vov T^V aqxflpav TOU Ttspilxovros given. Self-moving, no doubt, and therefore animate, soul as well as body. TTiis is an important point for Pythagorean doctrine as a whole, but not for the present limited discussion.
*
340
ALCMAEON
Alcmaeon of Croton was by some late writers called a Pythagorean. 1 Aristotle, however, who thought him of sufficient importance to compose a work in refutation of him (irposTd "Afaqjccicovos, D.L. v, 25), expressly distinguishes him from the Pythagoreans, and is borne out in this by some of the doctrines attributed to him. His citizenship of Croton,
together with his belief in the immortality of the soul and its kinship with the divine, and in the divinity of the stars, and a general emphasis on the role of opposites in nature, would be sufficient, in the opinion
of uncritical Neopythagorean and Neoplatonic writers, to warrant the Pythagorean label In fact, however, he seems to have displayed considerable originality of thought, 'without', as Heidel put it, recognizable affiliation with any special group of natural philosophers*.
*
date
This comparative independence makes it difficult to determine his by assigning him a probable place, on internal testimony, in the
succession of Presocratic philosophers. Of positive evidence we have only one sentence of Aristotle's Metaphysics^ which is, however,
Ab
In ch.
tinues (986327):
the ten Pythagorean pairs of opposites (p. 245, above), and con'Alcmaeon of Croton appears to have spoken in the
same way, and either he took this doctrine from them or they from 2 him; for as to his period, he lived in the old age of Pythagoras/ Admittedly the Greek of the last clause is vague (c Wachder, op. cit. n. i on p. 342), but at least it means that the lifetimes of Pythagoras and Alcmaeon overlapped. On the other hand the words long ago came
under suspicion of being a later interpolation, though the editors of DJL vin, 83 says TTu6oy6poi/ SI^KCUO% Iambi. F".P. 104, 167 includes Mm in a list of
1
Pythagoreans. So also Pfailop. De An* p. 88 Hayduck, schoL on Plato, Ale. /, HIE. Simpl. (Z?e An. 32.3) reports objectively that Orr6 ulw <3&Ao3v &s TTu0ay6pao$ TrapaS^orai but that
Aristotle denies this.
* This is the evidence for saying that in Aristotle's eyes Alcmaeon himself was not a Pythagorean. Three lines lower down he goes on to say that Alcmaeon did not in fact conceive of the opposites in the same way as the Pythagoreans (oOx <&<nTip oCrot).
341
Alcmaeon
Aristotle admitted
'are omitted
b by A
them until Ross, who writes (note adloc.} that they and there is no trace of them in Alexander; they ,
are probably a later addition, though the statement is likely enough to be true'. Since then the first clause of Ross's sentence has been accepted
to put the readily than the last, and there has been a tendency in 1942: wrote lifetime of Alcmaeon later and later, until L. Edelstein
more
Generally speaking,
Alcmaeon
cannot possibly have been a man of the sixth century. One must probably go still further than did those who contested this date and assume that Alcmaeon
belonged to the Pythagoreans [sic] of Socrates's time or even later; all the convictions ascribed to him seem indicative of such an attribution. Certainly,
at the
end of the
fifth
century
B.C. instead
of the
by
Stella
plausible though far less original. Whether this traditional itself will have to be modified as a result of an inquiry into the genuinepicture
would be more
nobody can
as yet say.
be
In favour of the genuineness of the words in the Metaphysics it may b said (i) that, on the general authority of A , Ross's own researches
Of his
opponents Wachder
coram
b 4): *suo iure codicem (pp. optimum metaphysitestem esse contendunt'. Contrast Ross (Metaph. clxv):
b EJ nor A should be followed exclusively. But the weight of the Greek commentators and of the medieval translation is decidedly on the side of EJ, and I have accordingly followed this group of where the evidence of the Greek commentators, or the manuscripts, except or or Aristotelian .turns the scale in favour of Ab ; sense, grammar, usage
AJP,
1942, 372-
Before Ross, Brandis, Zeller (ZN, 597, n. 2) and others had suspected the words in Aristotle, but Eke Ross, Zeller had thought them an accurate approximation to Alcmaeon's date. J.
Wachder, in what
is still
the best
Crotoniata,
ad
&.)>
defended their genuineness, as also in recent times does Skemp (Theory ofMorion in Plato's Later Dialogues, 36), and they are retained in DK, 24x3 (with Diels's conjectural addition of vtos). But many modern writers reject them, as does Jaeger in his Oxford text of 1957.
half of the
date, Wellmann (Arch.f. Gesch. <L Medvpn, 1929, 302) suggested the first century, and Deichgraber (Hippokr* tiler Entstehung u. Auflau des Menschl. Korpers, 37) the middle, as also does Heidel in Hippocr. Medicine, 43 (' Judging by his opinions, one would naturally take [Alcmaeon] for an unusually intelligent physician living about 450 B.C.*).
As
to
Akmaeon's
fifth
Mr G. E. R* Lloyd in an unpublished thesis has written that 'all lines of evidence would point to a date about the middle or end of the fifth century*. But the remarks of Edelstein, Heidel and
Lloyd are
all
made
Date
(2) that the silence
of Alexander means
little
(see Wachtler,
),
and
Asclepius includes the words in his commentary (39.21 Hayduck); (3) that the reference to Alcmaeon's date undoubtedly gains point from Aristotle's next sentence, in which he expresses uncertainty whether Alcmaeon or the Pythagoreans can claim priority for the particular
doctrine in question. Zeller's remark that the
idle' is unjustified.
words stand there rather Moreover we must reject one argument advanced by
Ross and repeated by Jaeger, namely that the words are suspect because they mention Pythagoras by name, and Aristotle only does this once elsewhere and nowhere claims any knowledge of Ms date. This
ignores the fact that Aristotle wrote treatises
on the Pythagoreans
which
which certainly gave some account of Pythagoras since the genuineness of the remark is by no means However, the best universally admitted, hope of assigning an approximate date to
are lost, but
himself.
Alcmaeon must
lie in the nature of his views, and so cannot well be discussed until the evidence for these views, such as it is, has been considered. For the moment we may simply say that if the mention
of his date
is
not
Aristotle's, that is
not in
Itself
of Pythagoras, but only that we can no longer claim Aristotle himself as a witness to the fact. Favorinus the friend of Plutarch (quoted by Diogenes, vm, 83) said
lifetime did not overlap that
rather absurdly that Alcmaeon had the reputation of being the first to write a natural philosophy (fuaiKov Aoyov). Galen twice mentions
him along with Parmenides, Melissus, Empedocles and others as author of a book which passed under the title On Nature. This work was no longer available to commentators of the Christian era, 1 who were dependent on Aristotle and Theophrastus for their information about Alcmaeon. Aristotle presumably had the book in order to write
and Theophrastus summarizes at length its it, account of sensation, obviously at first hand. Wachtler (pp. dt 32 f.) has argued that it probably survived in the Hellenistic library at
his polemic against
as with Philolaus, Diogenes (vin, 83 and of Demetrius 85, following Magnesia) quotes the first few words of his book, and this seems to go back to the practice of Callimachus, who
Alexandria.
With Alcmaeon
Simpl.
Probably not to Galen himself, Wachtler, p. 32, For the Aristotelian commentators c De An* 32.6 and Philop. De An. 88. Hayduck.
esp.
343
Alcmaeon
in his catalogue of the library regularly gave
title
followed by opening
words,
Diogenes writes of Alcmaeon (vra, 83): 'Most of what he says concerns medicine, though he sometimes treats of natural philosophy, This farrago is saying, "The majority of human things go in pairs"/
of the compiler, who could have illustrated the 'physical* side of Alcmaeon's thought very much better than by tearing this particular sentence from its context in Aristotle. Alcmaeon had indeed an intense
typical
and physiology, which influenced the whole Ms of tendency thought, but he lived before the age of specialization. The study of the human body was still only a part of philosophy as a whole, and he did not hesitate to pronounce also on the nature of knowinterest in medicine
ledge, soul.
the
treatise were: 'Thus says Alcmaeon of the son of Croton, Peirithous, to Brotinus, Leon, and Bathyllus. Concerning things unseen, and concerning mortal things, the gods see
Many Presocratic philohave the key to knowledge. are certain that sublimely they sophers Alcmaeon opens on a humbler note : certainty is only for the gods. They know the truth directly, but men can only follow the signs2 given to
clearly,
far as
but so
men may
judge,
..
them
feel their
way
towards the unseen. Comford has shown in Principium Sapientiae that in Ms certainty the early philosopher shows himself the successor of the
seer-poet, speaking under divine inspiration, whereas the humbler attitude towards knowledge was inculcated by the nascent science of
medicine with
its
detailed observation
its
aware-
the spirit
The asyndeton in the first six words of the second sentence is awkward,
TWV evrjr&v may well conceal a corruption (see app. crit* to DK, 248 1 for suggestions), but the general contrast between divine and human knowledge is unaffected. The Medication* (Bumet*s word is not too unsuitable) to the Pythagoreans Brotinus, Leon, and Bathyllus affords some slight confirmation of Alcmaeon's early date, since Brotinus is only
and
spoken of as an early Pythagorean, either father-in-law or son-in-law of Pythagoras, or married to a woman who was one of Pythagoras's pupils (authorities in DK, 17). The dates of the other two, who appear in lamblichus's list of Pythagoreans, are unknown. * Taqi^pio. On -rscpafpeoSai in this sentence Professor T. B. L. Webster says rightly that it means *to use the signs that are given to us to interpret what is unseen* (Acta Congr. Madvig. ir, Copenhagen, 1958, 36). Cf. Thuc. I, i, 3 ffo^ws pv eOpelv dSOvorra fjv,
344
Philosophic Character
treatise On Ancient Medicine^ the writer of which * 9 the deprecates study of unseen and doubtful matters like 'what goes on in the sky and under the earth*. Philosophers who do this may
of the Hippocratic
claim to
no standard of verification. 1
All that we know of Alcmaeon's views points to this preference for the concrete, a solid basis of observation, and dislike of airy hypotheses and over-simplification. He had no use for the contemporary fixation
which everything could be reduced. If die doxocould have fastened such a notion on to him, we may be sure graphers they would have done so. But though they tell us in their schematic
single arche to
on a
way of the
Hippon
sort.
arche of even
fire
the water of
we read nothing of the Like the Pythagoreans he made great use of opposites, and applied them to human nature and destiny. Aristotle's evidence on this is as
or the
of Hippasus
Alcmaeon says
that most human things go in pairs, but he speaks of the oppositions not, like the Pythagoreans, as limited in number but hap-
hazard, e.g. white-black, sweet-bitter, good-bad, large-small. He threw out indefinite suggestions about the rest, but the Pythagoreans specified how
many and what the contraries were. From both therefore we may understand
which they
that the opposites are principles of existing things, but their are, we learn only from the Pythagoreans.
number, and
One way in which he applied his doctrine of pairs of opposites to mankind is shown in a doxographic paragraph, printed by DielsKranz as an actual fragment or quotation. In fact it is in indirect speech, and Diels himself noted (Dox. 223 ) that some Peripatetic and Stoic terms have crept into the expression. Also the text is by no means perfect. All this enjoins a certain caution, yet the thought and much of
the language have an archaic tone, especially perhaps the use of the 2 and monarchia to describe political terms uonomia (equality of rights)
1953.
345
Alcmaeon
one of them. These are foreign to later medical writers, but would spring to the mind of one who lived when rivalry between popular and despotic factions was a familiar feature of city-state life. There is
no reason
to
Diels-Kranz
doubt that the theory was Alcmaeon's own. The may be rendered thus (4):
text
of
Alcmaeon taught that what preserves health is equality between the powers moist and dry, cold and hot, bitter and sweet and the rest and the prevalence of one of them produces disease, for the prevalence of either is
destructive.
The active cause of disease is excess of heat or cold, the occasion or insufficiency of nourishment, the seat of it blood, marrow or 1 the brain. Disease may also be engendered by external causes such as waters or local environment or exhaustion or torture or the like. Health on the
of it
surfeit
other hand
is
This passage, together with other more striking instances of Alcmaeon's empirical approach to the study of physiology, sensation, and kindred subjects, explains why in his treatment of contrary qualities
he
from the Pythagoreans in the way indicated by Aristotle. could They specify a rigid and exclusive list of opposites because they were constructing a theoretical system on predominantly mathematical
differed
scientist,
who saw
that there
indefinite
qualities rather
and
right, limited
doctor cannot ignore, is less tidy, less cut-and-dried, than the a priori system of the mathematical philosopher.
Croton was from an early date famous for its medical men. Herodotus (ni, 125 ff.) tells the story of Democedes son of CalBphon, a Crotoniate and 'the best physician of his day*, who practised first in Aegina and
Athens, then was employed by Polycrates of Samos until the latter' s death at the hands of Oroites the Persian in 522 B.C. Brought to Sardis as a prisoner, Democedes cured Darius of a dislocated ankle and his
wife Atossa of a growth on the breast, and finally managed to return to his native city, where he married the daughter of Milo (the athlete
Of this man Herodotus says that 'he was for the mainly responsible high reputation of the medical men of
and
frieiid
of Pythagoras).
In
this sentence
346
The
from
character of Alcmaeon's physiological science may be judged a summary in Theophrastus's De Sensu (25 , DK, A 5):
those
who explain sensation by dissimilars, Alcmaeon begins by the difference between men and the lower animals. Man, he says, clarifying differs from the others in that he alone has understanding, whereas they have 1 sensation but do not understand: thought is distinct from sensation, not, as
Among
it is
for Empedocles, the same. then proceeds to each sense separately. Hearing is through the ears because they contain void, which resounds. Sound is produced in the cavity
He
[sc.
Beare],
and the
echoes
air [of
id.}
to the
brain in the act of breathing. Tastes are distinguished by the tongue, which being warm and soft melts the object by its heat, and owing to its porous and
delicate structure receives
when
is,
it is
struck,
and
it
latter
by means of the bright element a reflexion, and the purer back gives
sees
element
the better
it sees.
to the brain,
and for
this
reason
disturbed or shifted, for it obstructs the passages through which the sensations take place. Concerning the mode or the organs of touch he has nothing to say. This
if it is
then
is
This account (to which the doxographers, naturally enough, add nothing material) is not altogether easy to translate, and no doubt it is
inevitable that the inchoate physiology of
Alcmaeon should
at certain
Our knowledge
The word used, fuvi&ca, means literally *to put together*, and traces of this basic meaning probably survived in the mind of a Greek writer of the fifth century. All animals have sensation, but only man can make a synthesis of his sensations. 3 The subject of tKAj&inrev is friip. Cf. Arist. De Sensu^ 437324. 3 Le, the fire and the water both play their part (Wachder). Beare, rather against the sentenceconstruction, refers both epithets to water on the ground that oriXfkiv applies more appropriately to it than to fire (Gk. TL ofElem. Cogn. n, n. 3). This seems to make the introduction of fire improbably otiose, but that of course may be a fault in Theophrastus's epitomizing.
347
Alcmaeon
little by descriptions In other medical writers, and criticisms in Aristotle, of theories which are probably Alcmaeon's or similar. Those interested in the details may be referred to J. I. Beare's Greek
merited a
Theories
cited.
From Empedocles,
ofElementary Cognition and Wachtler's monograph previously the nearest writer in time and space whose
views on these subjects have survived, he differed in several ways. In general he thought of sensation as resulting from the interaction of
unlikes, whereas
affection
of
like
Empedocles explained it by a belief in the natural by like: 'With earth we see earth, with water water ,
5
and so on
activity
(fr.
109).
For Empedocles,
was centred
Alcmaeon
in the head.
first
For
this reason,
part of the embryo to be formed (DK, A 13: there are several testimonies to his interest in reproduction and embryology: see A 13 17,
B 3 ). remarkable signs of independence from his contemporaries is the drawing of a clear line (though we do not know where or how) between sensation and thought: 'Thought is distinct from
for Empedocles, die same', and this for Alcmaeon provided a criterion of distinction between man and the other animals. In De Anima^ n, 3, Aristotle says that the other view was general
sensation, not, as
it is
among
earlier thinkers,
is
but
is
by
Alcmaeon
Intellect and thinking are believed to be a sort of sensation . . .and the older philosophers maintain that thought and sensation are the same, as Empedocles when he says 'the wisdom of men grows with reference to what is before
All these regard intellect as a bodily function just like sensation. . them* But that sensation and thinking are not the same is obvious, for the first
is
common
to
all
by
a few only.
him
cites as
evidence
the superiority of man to the other animals. That he does not mention
accidental (he is in general annoyingly parsimonious with references to particular predecessors) or possibly due to a feeling that Alcmaeon, though he made the distinction, had
1
Contrast Emped.
fr. 1
10, 10 TT&vrrot
yip
348
The explicit recognition of the brain as the central organ of feeling and thought was another striking contribution of Alcmaeon. 1 In connexion with the sense of sight we have the information in Chalcidius's
commentary on the Timaeus (DK, A 10)
undertake the
scientific excision
that
to
of an eye. This would make it possible for him to see the nerves running from the eye to the brain, an achieve-
though he same sentence. From Theophrastus we know that he spoke of passages' (tropoi) leading from sense-organs to the brain, and by these he may have intended nerves, inferring from
certainly attributes to him,
mentions two
those which he could see the existence of those which he could not.
Plato refers to Alcmaeon's discovery (though without naming him) in the Phaedo (966), where Socrates, running through a list of various physical philosophers, says ('whether it is the blood with which we
fire, or none of these, but) the brain is what provides 3 the sensations of hearing, sight and smell . In the Timaeus Plato himself followed Alcmaeon's example, unlike Aristotle, who less wisely retained
think, or air, or
the heart as
common
sensorium.
that
Alcmaeon's ideas were uncommonly influential is provided by the subject of sleep. Aetius reports (DK, c A 1 8): Alcmaeon says that sleep is brought about by the retirement of
the blood to the larger blood-vessels, whereas waking is their rediffusion*, and in Aristotle's own haematology we find this (H.A. in, 521 a 1 5): When living creatures are asleep, the blood becomes less plentiful near the surface, so that if they are pricked it does not flow so
copiously.* It looks as if he rated the authority of Ms predecessor higher than the evidence of observation and simple experiment.
c
Another indication
of some general interest that in his account of hearing Alcmaeon with air. This emerges from Theophrastus, and he must have been one of those whom Aristotle had in mind when he
It is
fjysnoviKeSv
Aetius (A 1 3), using Stoic terminology (but cf. Plato, Tim. 410), says that for Alcmaeon T& was in the brain, and that semen was a part of it. Cf. also the words of Chalcidius
.
(AIO):
summa
et principals*
349
Alcmaeon
wrote in
De Anima (4^33):
'Void
is
the condition of hearing, for by void is meant air, which is indeed This cause of hearing when it is moved in a single continuous mass/ and Alcmaeon between link identification of air with void is of course a
the Pythagoreans (p. 280, above). On the soul Alcmaeon had an important contribution to make.
follows from its resemblance to the immortal says that its immortality of being in everlasting it which a resemblance possesses by virtue beings, and for ever, to wit move also divine the all continuously for things motion; sun and stars, and the heaven as a whole (Aristotle, De Anima, the
He
moon,
405 a 30).
Cicero and Clement repeat Alcmaeon's belief in the divinity of the and Aetius reproduces the argument for heavenly bodies (DK, A 12),
the soul's immortality, adding to the everlastingness of its motion the
fact that
it is
self-caused.
These are
all
their information,
c
and elsewhere in
De Anima (404320)
him-
self speaks
of those
who
which moves
itself,
no
and Xenocrates.
of nature at large, based on its vague belief in the animation eternal and apparently self-caused motion, was ancient and not con1 In Anaximenes and the Pythagoreans this fined to philosophers. becomes the basis of a close relationship between macrocosmic and
life. The divinity of the heavenly firmly stars and men also which in established brought popular religion, men of dead souls the in the belief that the latter were
microcosmic
bodies was
together
But Alcmaeon had thought these ideas (Aristophanes, Peace, 832f.). a rational way. towards further a out-and went step presenting them in
fact of movement, we may suppose him Starting from the observable to have inferred the everlasting and self-caused motion of psyche from that the ultimate cause of motion must be the presence the
assumption Life then in some form or other must have existed uninterstarted or ruptedly from all time or no motion could have been either
of
life.
maintained. Aristotle divides his predecessors in psychology into two of soul in classes, according as they saw the essential characteristic
1
350
movement or in sensation. Of the former he says (De Am 403 b 28): 'Some maintain that soul is eminently and primarily the mover; and assuming that what does not move itself is incapable of moving anything
later
they conceive of soul as something in motion/ And a little (404321): 'All those who define the soul as self-mover seem to
else,
think that
movement
is
the
most
essential characteristic
of
soul,
and
is
moved by
soul,
but soul by
itself,
for they
observe no agent of motion which is not itself in motion/ This argument for the immortality of the soul was developed
All soul
by
Alcmaeon
argument and
set it forth
more
logically.
The ever-moving
is
im-
mortal, the self-moving is the ever-moving, therefore the self-moving is immortal. Soul is the self-moving, therefore soul is immortal. 1 Alcmaeon (to judge by the reports) relied more naively on the analogy
with the heavenly bodies, which (as everybody believed) were divine and immortal, and could be observed to be in perpetual motion. More of his premisses are suppressed or half-suppressed, because he is nearer
to the unquestioned assumptions of pre-philosophical thought. There is a saying attributed to Alcmaeon in the Aristotelian Probh-
mata which
the end/
startling
DK): 'Alcmaeon
says
why men
The language
its familiarity, but in fact the image behind Alcmaeon's one of phrase great weight and remarkably wide application in early Greek thought: it is the image of circular motion. 2 The outer shell of
is
from
all
Cf. Zaiw, 89 5 E
&
5fj vfA/xfs
TOUVQUCC,
TO^TOV X6yo$;
ixotiev
oAXov
irAfjv
TOV vuvSf)
-r)6evTcc,
circle
351
Alcmaeon
of circles that has continued with regular visibly in a complicated pattern recurrences from time immemorial, as was known from the records of Babylonian astronomers.
It
revolutions were the cause of a circular repetition of events on earth. Summer gives place to winter but will return inevitably as the sun
and this seasonal recurrence brings completes his circuit of the ecliptic, about a cycle of birth, growth, dying and new birth among individual into the plant, which flowers, fades and dies, The seed
things.
grows has dropped new seed from which the cycle of life will be repeated. Philo of Alexandria was perpetuating a very ancient idea when he wrote:
it
was God's will to prolong the existence of nature by immortalizing the kinds and allowing them a share in eternity. Hence he brought, indeed
It
return to the hastened, the beginning to the end and caused the end to the from it as were beginning the beginning; for from plants comes the fruit, the itself within plant, that is, end, and from fruit the seed which contains
in the seeding
just as
end
and beginning are the same point on thing else which traces the shape of a circle.
end are common* (Heraclitus,
fr.
103).
The
farious
and chronological, as well as geometrical, and this is not the moment to trace them all out* But physiological let us look at the context in the Prollemata in which Alcmaeon's
astronomical
remark
of time, and subject is the circular character the question whether 'before' and "after* have any absolute meaning. If time is circular and recurrent, we may just as well be described as
is
introduced.
The
Eving before the Trojan War as after it. The analogy from the circling heavens to the history of living things is explicitly drawn (916324):
As
of the heaven and of each star is a circle, why should not the and death of perishable creatures be similar, so that the same things come * into being and decay? Human life is a circle', as the saying Is. To suppose
the path
birth
1
Philo,
3
De
Much may be
mander and
Opif. Mundt, xin, 44, quoted by Kahn (see next note), 27, n. 13. learned on the subject from the iUumiijatiiig article of C, H. Kahn, *Anaxithe arguments concerning the firrrsipov*.
Circularity in Greek
indeed that those
Thought
who come
would be foolish, but a specific identity is more acceptable. Thus we ourselves would be the earlier, and one may assume the series to be arranged so
back again to the beginning, to act continuously and always follow same course. Alonaeon says that the reason why men die is that they cannot join the beginning to the end a clever saying, if we take it that he is speaking in a general sense and not with strict accuracy. If life is a circle, and a circle has neither beginning nor end, none can be earlier by being nearer the beginning, neither they earlier than we nor we than they.
as to turn
the
The connexion of thought between the circular paths of the heavenly bodies and the eternal recurrence of history was made by means of the
concept of the Great Year
larity was appHed
(p. 282,
in particular to the
that 'the coincidence of beginning and end was a theme of special interest to doctors'. 2 The Hippocratic De Fzctu, in a series of far-
fetched parallels designed to show that in the arts man imitates the * natural functions of the body, says (i, 19): Weavers work In a circle,
starting
body
In
beginning and end alike; for when a circle has been beginning cannot be found/ To recapture as far as possible
is
the thought behind Alcmaeon's dictum we must, as Kahn has noted, bear in mind not only the eternal celestial motions to which the Proble-
mata
refer,
(Trepio8o$) of the body. "In the human subject, which is of primary concern for a doctor like Alcmaeon, the maintenance of life depends
upon
whole.
the circular knitting-together of all parts into one continuous When this link is snapped, death occurs' (Kahn, op. cit. 26).
The individual human soul, in its action on the body, is trying to reproduce in its
as
own way the eternal circular motions of the divine stars, for,
Alcmaeon himself said, 'all divine things also move continuously and for ever, the moon, sun and stars, and the heaven as a whole'.
1
As some at
Kirk,
least
HCF*
of the Pythagoreans did, p. 281, above. 114, wlio quotes the Hippocratic examples.
353
Alcmaeon
It Is difficult
Alcmaeon.
We
not to believe that Plato was deeply influenced by have already seen the similar proof of the soul's im-
mortality of which he made use in the Phaedrus and Laws. The Timaeus teaches that the activity of the soul of the living cosmos
consists of circular motions. In a
of the same nature as the world's soul though of inferior quality, 'the circuits of the immortal soul* are confined 'within the flowing and ebbing tide of the body'. The shock of submitting to the exigencies of
bodily nourishment and rapid growth distorts the circles of the soul, which were originally constructed by the Creator according to strict laws of geometrical and musical proportion. By the assaults of matter
they were twisted in all manner of ways, and all possible infractions and deformations of the circles were caused, so that they barely held
together* ^D-E), and this accounts for the irrational behaviour of infants. In adult life a certain equilibrium and calm are attained, and the
*
revolutions proceed more regularly. What then did Alcmaeon really believe about the nature of the soul?
There is no further evidence, and to suggest a coherent doctrine one must resort to inference. This may be worth attempting, for it will shed some light on Greek ways of thinking, even if only dubiously on
Alcmaeon's.
Since soul
is
immortal,
it
death; and if men die 'because they cannot join the beginning to the 5 end , it follows that the soul, which is immortal, does join them. Thus
we have
already implicit (and for all we know explicit) in Alcmaeon's philosophy the doctrine that the soul imitates the divine stars and
heavens not only in self-caused motion but in circular motion. 1 So far we may follow Rostagni (Verlx) di P. 136). But when he goes on to say
that the circle in question is the circle of births or cycle of reincarnation
lore, he goes beyond the reach of legitimate inference. There is no hint that Alcmaeon believed in transmigration, and it has more than once been pointed out that the
radical distinction
rather against
1
it.
It
which he draws between men and animals tells may not be easy to imagine how he conceived of
This conclusion has been reached here independently of the arguments of Skemp in The ofMonoa w Plato's Later Dialogues (Cambridge, 1942), ch. 3. I do not think the objections of Festugiere {REG, 1945, 59-65) to Skemp's arguments are fataL
Theory
354
thinker,
saw no
difficulty in describing its revolutions as going on inside our a heads, procedure unconnected with the belief in transmigration,
also. further conjecture of Rostagni's, that the to motion only subject only 'moves itself at all when it enters the world of incarnate being, and is in its own nature unmoved,
it.
testimonies might suggest that Alcmaeon had a double conception of the soul like that of Empedocles which has been discussed in
The
connexion with the soul-harmony* doctrine on pp. 3178". Sensation and thought both belong to the body, being dependent on the brain: c yet the soul is immortal, and must therefore be not the empirical*
soul but the divine daimon temporarily incarcerated in a
fi
human body
his
it
maintained
by
Rostagni, in
belief in the soul's immortality to *the mystical currents pervading the sixth century B.C.* (pp. dt. 102 ff.). *The immortal soul that he concedes
is
the
is
the mystical soul, very different from the body and from the soul of body centred in the brain* (p. 154). On the other hand (a) there
no evidence for it, nor any hint that Alcmaeon Eke Empedocles used the word daimon or any other second word when speaking of the human soul; () it seems to have been a cardinal point of difference between Alcmaeon and Empedocles that Empedocles said that thought and sensation were the same*, so that even the lower animals possessed some faculty of thinking (Aet. iv, 5, 12, DK, 28A45). ** e therefore insisted at every turn on the Pythagorean belief in the close kinship of men and the lower animals, whereas Alcmaeon distinguished between mind and the senses and regarded the possession of intelligence as marking off humanity from the beasts. Perhaps the most likely supposition is this. Psyche for a thinker of the fifth century meant not only a soul but soul; that is, the world was permeated by a kind of soul-stuff which is better indicated by the omission of the article. Soul animates the cosmos, and its characteristic manifestation is the unceasing and self-caused motion which it performs
c
Alcmaeon thought,
and imparts to the heavenly bodies. Portions of this soul-substance, inhabit the human body, and in particular the
355
Alcmaeon
where they naturally attempt to carry out the same circular motions, but are hampered by the crasser material In which they are now implicated. In the end the uneasy partnership breaks down, the composite creature as a whole can no longer preserve the integrity of the circle, and the immortal soul deserts the body, which thereupon
brain,
perishes.
A doctor's task
is,
librium in the body of the physical opposites wet, dry, cold, hot, bitter, sweet and the rest; but in general terms his aim may be described as the
establishment of conditions in which the soul
the
body from
is
equilibrium
as physical carrying out its natural revolutions. So long is able to impart to the body, by soul the preserved,
means of its own regular motions, movement and the powers of sensation and thought.
Our
sources do not
tell
soul after death. Probably, however, it was released to join die pure to the aither^ body to the earth* soul-substance among the stars 'spirit
a notion which in one (Euripides, Suppl. 533f.) popular in the fifth century and not confined to
any one
religious or
philosophical school.
had an important place in Plato's philosophy and haunted the cosmology and theology of Aristotle. It is argued at
book of the Laws, where at 898 A we read that motion performed in one place must always be about a centre, like a well-turned wheel, and is in every way so far as possible closest and
length in the tenth
*
of intelligence*. In the Timaeus the of the world-soul is intelligence synonymous with its revolution, that * supreme* outermost revolution of the Same which affects all interior motions of the cosmos: and at 40 A, describing how the Creator set the
similar to the revolution
stars in this
intelligence
most
them
all
of the supreme. .to keep company with it, distributing round the heaven*. The word 'intelligence*, instead of sphere
or circuit, comes as a shock, but for Pkto the two were interchangeable.
As he
says a few lines later of the axial rotation of the stars, they 'have one motion in the same place, as each always thinks the same thoughts
356
Circular
about the same things
difficult to
9
.
Motions of Soul
say
how
far Plato
Evidently this analogy (or symbolism; it is meant his language in the Tmaeus to be
taken
literally)
maeon
did not begin with Plato, and so far as was the first to give it philosophical expression.
we know
Ale-
tell
us
anything about it, which is very little; see A 4) Alcmaeon is credited with a repetition of the crudities of Anaximenes and Heraclitus: the
moon is eclipsed because it is bowl-shaped and the bowl turns sometimes at an angle to us. Nevertheless he followed the rather than the Ionian line in regarding the stars as living Pythagorean
sun
is flat,
the
and divine, and Aetius says of him that he 'agreed with the mathematzci' in teaching the independent movement of the planets from
West
According to the typical Ionian view (Anaxagoras, Democritus) they were lifeless masses of earth or stone carried passively round by the universal vortex, whereas the possibility of independent
to East.
and contrary movement was closely bound up with their divinity. Both
were taught by the Pythagoreans, of whom mathematici is an appro1 priate description, and Alcmaeon could have picked up the doctrines
at
if
phrase in Aetius does not suggest origithe other reports of his astronomy are true, he is not so
Croton.
The
likely to have been original in this as in his special fields like physio-
Can anything be usefully added about Alcmaeon's date? First, that the disputed clause in Aristotle's Metaphysics does not make him out * to be so early as some think. Edelstein suspects that he cannot
to believe that
possibly have been a man of the sixth century*, but no one is asking us he was. Aristotle says nothing more definite than that
he existed in the old age of Pythagoras. Pythagoras probably died about 490, perhaps even a little later, and whether or not we concur in Diels's
the text, the statement conjectural addition of the word young (vso$) in that than 510. He may Alcmaeon earlier be born any does not demand
divinity of the heavenly bodies we liave seen plenty of evidence. The contrary the planets is taught by Plato in some of his most Pytliagorizing passages, and attributed to diem in later times ([Geminus], [Eisagoge], p. Manitius; see van der Waerden,
1
For the
movement of
357
Alcmaeon
any time between the ages of thirty and seventy, i.e. between 480 and 440. The dates of the Presocratic philosophers are no more than approximately known, but this would make
have written
his
book
at
Heraclitus,
roughly contemporary with those of Empedocles and Anaxagoras. He would be older than Democritus, nor do we find any trace of the atomic viewpoint in his remains. The identification of void and air
suggests that he was
If
earlier.
accept this date, there is nothing in his medical and physiothe antiquity of logical science to cause surprise, especially considering the Crotoniate school of physicians. Comparison with the Hippocratic treatises
is
we
a dubious aid, in
sifted the
view of
their
own
uncertain date.
question most thoroughly would date On Ancient Medicine (FTkf) between 450 and 420,* and its view of the role of opposites in disease (see especially adinit* and ch. 15) reflects a
But some
who
have
as a
very well (it says) to prescribe but these do not exist in isolation, remedy,
it is all
Similarly with
VM's
it necessary to make assumptions about what goes on in the sky and under the earth. Alcmaeon is already imbued with this spirit, he has the mind and method of a true physician,
school of doctors
who
think
yet he
life:
still
he
is
the things in the sky' and relates them to human only half-way towards the strict empiricism of the Hippostudies
cratic writer.
Empedocles, as well from him in ways already noted. Resemblances and differences alike suggest that they belonged to the same period, and
He has
something in
Sicilian
as differing
perhaps exchanged ideas, rather than that either followed the other. Both made use of 'passages' (iropoi) in their explanations of sensation,
but in quite different ways. It is perhaps to be noted that not even the doxographers, to whom such language is natural, describe Alcmaeon as
1
De Fane.
W. H.
S. Jones, introd. to
p. 5. G. E. R. Lloyd (unpublished) thinks the author a contemporary of Plato of his use of eTSo$ and inrr60ms, but there remain objections to this dating.
358
Date: Conclusions
working with the concept of the four elements introduced by Empedocles: we read only (as already with Anaximander) of the hot, the cold, etc., not of fire, air, water and earth, which e.g. the later physician Philistion mentions (fr. 4 Wellmann) when he is treating of the causes of disease. Much the same may be said about the relation of Alcmaeon's
remains to those of Anaxagoras.
As we have
seen,
Alcmaeon
which were
later
the soul as self-mover, the analogy of circular developed by it motion but became clear that these ideas were present in the thought
Plato
century or earlier, and needed only the application of an and intelligent perceptive mind to give them more definite form. All in it is more to believe that Alcmaeon, as we are told, was reasonable all, already alive in the old age of Pythagoras, and was a thinker of con-
of the
fifth
siderable
power and
all.
manhood of Plato
original at
influence, than to push his lifetime down into the in order to show (on little evidence) that he was not
359
VI
XENOPHANES
This
is
the
way
to speak
around the
fire
In winter,
*
on a
Drinking sweet wine, and crunching hazelnuts: Now tell us, sir, your name and home and age. How old were you the year the Mede appeared?'
(fr.
22)
Now is
the floor swept, hands and cups washed clean; Fresh- woven garlands crown our heads, and now The fragrant unguent-bottle makes its rounds.
The bowl
good
fail
cheer,
And
here's another
wine
Incense
distils
is
And
water, cold and sweet and clean. See the brown loaves, and on a worthy table
there
centre-piece an altar, thickly strewn flowers. Song and revel fill the hall.
stories
With pious
Then, due
meet for righteous men to hymn, and pure words, the god.
libations paid, with prayers for strength act aright (our plainest duty this), It is no sin to drink so much, that all
To
Not weak from age may come safe home Praise him who after drinking can relate
alone.
1 Fine deeds, as memory serves and lust for good. Give us no fights with Titans, no nor Giants
Nor Nor
Centaurs, which our fathers falsely told, brawls, in which no profit is. But to be mindful of the gods is good.
civil
(fr. i)
DK:
m&v dvcKpodvTj,
&$
dA* ehrcbv
of
uvrinooOvn
KCtl
H. Frankel,
360
included
may well be asked why the writer of these cheerful lines is among the philosophers. The first quotation recalls a
to be
scene
Greek lands from the time of the Odyssey to our own. All possible personal information is to be extracted from the stranger, but the duties of hospitality come first. Only when he is fed,
familiar to travellers in
over the nuts and wine, is it proper for the questions to begin. The second sets the scene in vivid detail for a typical symposium, at which
the Greek
would always give the gods first place, and liked to mingle and serious elevating conversation with the entertainment of song and dance that was also provided. This poem conforms to a type, and what
is laid
in the latter part scarcely goes beyond the limits of conventional piety. The stories of the gods are to be purged of their more
down
this
was equally
insisted
on by
Xenophanes is indeed a reminder of the artificiality of the barriers which the need for selection forces us to set up between other Greek writers and those whom at this early period we choose to call philosophers. He is a poet, the only one whose genuine writings find a place both among the Presocratic philosophers of Diels and in the lyric anthology of Diehl; and like every Greek poet he was a teacher with a message to convey. Poetic form is no bar to philosophy. Though the
Milesians used prose,
we
shall find
bodying highly complex intellectual systems in verse, as in the Roman world did Lucretius. But from the passages quoted it looks as if
philosophy was not his only or his chief concern. Thoroughly at
home
in social gatherings, he loves to depict them and, as singer and honoured guest at the same time, to prescribe some of the rules according to
which they were customarily conducted. Yet among later Greeks he had the reputation of being the founder of the Eleatic school, to which we owe the first attempt to base an ontology on strict deductive logic.
The
who
opinions of modern scholars vary widely: *A poet and rhapsode has become a figure in the history of Greek philosophy by
mistake';
regarde drop comme un veritable philosophe, alors ' qu'en realite c'est bien plutot un poete humoriste'; Represents the only true monotheism that has ever existed in the world'; Clearly
'On
le
'
Only
as a theologian can
he be really
Xenophanes
understood*; 'He would have smiled
if
he had
link
known
that
one day he
investi-
was to be regarded
gations and
as a theologian';
*A
between Ionian
The
list
could be
lengthened.
writings
errors,
can make up our own minds. At least he is the first Greek philosopher (if we may account him such) of whose undisputed we can still read an appreciable quantity. There may be textual
Perhaps
we
we
are in
no doubt whether a
in particular of passage is direct quotation or paraphrase (that bugbear the study of Heraclitus), and the quotations amount to about 118 lines.
(i)
About the
actual date of Xenophanes there is a certain conflict of the historian of Sicily (p. 170, above), an island Timaeus evidence.
which Xenophanes certainly visited, described him (according to Clement of Alexandria) as contemporary with Hieron and Epicharmus (A8). Hieron reigned in Syracuse 478-467 and Epicharmus was there
at the time.
i.e.
(ix, 20) gives his floruit as Ol. 60, a about birth 575. This is not impossible to 540-537, suggesting we do not know), since words reconcile with Timaeus (whose actual
Diogenes Laertius
we have
poems
that
the invaluable information from one of Xenophanes's own he was alive and writing at the age of ninety-two (fr. 8;
see
A 7).
Diogenes does not mention his source, but it is almost certain to have been the chronicler Apollodorus. On the other hand Clement
(A8) quotes Apollodorus against Timaeus as having put the birth of Xenophanes in Ol. 40 (620-617) and added that he survived 'to the
time of Darius and Cyrus . This is a strange phrase, since Cyrus died in 529 and Darius succeeded to power in 521, and it gives ground for
1 suspicion that sources have become distorted. Clement (like Sextus, AS) has probably copied a mistaken report of Apollodorus's estimate, which we are fortunate to be able to correct through Diogenes. It
would be
1
like
Diels, It is true, explained the order of the names as due originally to exigencies of metre. (Apollodorus wrote in iambic trimeters.) See Zeller, 640, n. r.
362
Life
date of Elea,
1
closely
connected in
We may therefore assume, as the most likely dates for his long life,
approximately 570-470. He would then have been born about the same time as Pythagoras (of whom he writes in fr. 7), but probably outlived him for twenty or thirty years. Heraclitus, who criticizes him by name,
will
have been some thirty years younger, and Parmenides perhaps sixty. Since we do not know at what age he wrote his various poems,
his exceptionally
long life makes it impossible to place them within narrow limits.* any He was born in the Ionian city of Colophon, which fell to Harpagus
the
Mede
after Cyrus's
Mede', which he
conquest of Lydia in 546. 'The coming of the drove him from his native land to
some autobiographical
lines
8) :
Fr. 3, too, shows experience of the way of life of the Colophonians before their downfall. That he was twenty-five at the time of the conquest fits well enough with the approximate date here assumed for
his birth.
Exiled from his country/ says Diogenes (ix, 18), 'he lived in Sicily at Zancle 4 and Catana/ His name also became associated with Elea,
which lies some way up the west coast of the Italian mainland, owing to the common assumption that he founded the 'Eleatic school' of philosophy; for Parmenides of Elea, its undoubted founder, was thought to
1
Le. about 540 and not later than 535 (RE, 2. Reihe, vni, 2400). Bowra has pointed out that fr. 2 was probably written before 520. It seems to mention
all
the
main events of the Olympic games, yet omits the race in armour which was introduced at that time. H. Thesleff, On Dating Xenophanes, probably puts him too late. See G. B. Kerferd in CR, 1959, 72, and for a brief summary and appraisal of the evidence for Xenophanes's dates von
CP, 1945, 228, n. 25. That this was the occasion of his migration is certainly the most reasonable conclusion. Cf. H. Frankel, Dichtung u. PhUos. 421, n. 2 and Hermes, 1925, 176, n. I. 4 Le. Messana. The older name Zancle was in use until c. 480 (JR~E9 xv, 1221), and its use here may mean, as Burnet pointed out, that the information is from a poem of Xenophanes himself.
Fritz,
3
363
Xenophanes
have been taught or inspired by him. In fact the only positive evidence connecting him with Elea is the inclusion among his reputed works of an epic poem on its foundation, along with one on that of his native
Colophon; but it is of course possible that he spent some time there soon after its foundation, or even that he arrived in time to take part in it. One may sum up by saying that he was an Ionian who lived
that according to tradition his sojourn included Messana, Catana, Elea, and, late in his life, the court of
Hieron at Syracuse.
(2) Social
and outlook.
living.
Fr. i
shows him
home
singer of the elegiac song which opened a symposium in archaic or classical times was by no means necessarily the hired
The
at rich
men's
meal
and a present.
A phrase in
1
Diogenes that he
'recited his
this,
(eppccvj/cb8si, ix,
There seems to have been a class of elegiac poems sung at the beginning
of symposia and including advice to the guests on behaviour or 1 deportment, and the singers were at least the equals of their fellow-
Xenophanes indeed, as a man with a message of his own, with a special air of authority, but without overstepping the speaks bounds of contemporary aristocratic taste.
drinkers.
In another
poem
(fr.
2)
*my
art':
material prosperity both of which we must therefore to furthered the be suppose by poet. This claim is characteristic of a of the and would have been made equally by Solon or time, poet
nor to
its
disparagement of physical prowess has been seen as anti-aristocratic, evidence already of the 'inevitable clash' between the
Theognis.
The
old ideals and nascent philosophy with its more humanistic, democratic and even revolutionary outlook. But the cult of success at the games
1
at Feasts'.
364
General Outlook
was neither traditional nor peculiarly aristocratic. It had gained immense popularity with all classes, and tyrants courting the favour of
the poor regarded it as of political importance to compete and win themselves. In a well-reasoned article Sir Maurice Bowra argues that
Xenophanes looks back to a past when words were more honoured than athletic success, and his language, though not specifically political, belongs to an aristocratic order of society in which any far-reaching change which seemed to promote the unworthy was regarded as
concludes: 'He was a high-minded member of a society which was conscious of social and moral obligations. In the sixth century Greek aristocrats were neither all so reactionary as Alcaeus nor
ocSiKov'.
He
so
homogeneous
in their opinions as
some
social historians
have
thought, and the intellectual vigour and range of a class which produced 1 Pythagoras and Heraclitus found a characteristic voice in Xenophanes/
Moderation, an enjoyment of the good things of life without any ostentatious display of wealth, was a part of the same ideal, and it was quite in accord with it that Xenophanes should condemn the luxurious
habits of his
(fr.
3)
And
they learned dainty, useless Lydian ways still from hated tyrants free.
all scarlet
to the assembly
went
(3)
Writings
Xenophanes wrote his poems in hexameters, elegiacs and iambics (D.L. ix, 1 8). The extant fragments are in hexameters and elegiacs, with one example (fr. 14) of an iambic trimeter followed by a hexameter.
Elea,
He
is
which temporary and recent history. (D.L. ix, 20; but cf. Burnet, EGP, 115, n. 2.) He was also famous for his Silloi, a title (probably bestowed on them later) indicating poems of mockery or parody. They are no doubt
1
credited with epics on the foundation of Colophon and if true makes him the earliest Greek poet to treat of con-
'Xenophanes and the Olympian Games ',28, 37. For the opposite view see Jaeger,
Pozcfeza, r,
171
365
Xenophanes
the same that Athenaeus referred to as 'the parodies' (Xenoph. fr. 22). His example was followed (and the name perhaps invented) by the sceptic
Tlmon of Phlius in the first half of the third century B.C., an admirer of criticism of earlier Xenophanes who dedicated to him his own satirical of this he cast into the form of a philosophers (Sextus in A 3 5). Part
underworld related in the Odyssey and elsewhere, in which Xenophanes played the role of Homer's of shades. Late writers mention a Tiresias, the wise guide to the land of Xenophanes (frr. 21 a and 42), Silloi of the fourth and a fifth book
Nekyia, a parody of the
visits to the
is
which could have contained hexametric as well as elegiac pieces, and it come from the collection so named. likely that most of our fragments also to 'Xenophanes in his work on Writers of the Christian era refer
nature \ and
it is
come
from a separate work with this tide, or formed part of the Silloi. One must at least admit justification for Deichgraber's statement that 'in the Hellenistic age there was a poem of Xenophanes with the title "On Nature" (irspi <pvaeoo$), in other words a poem which in the
judgment of the grammarians and librarians deserved
as die didactic
times'.
this title as
much
When,
of earlier (Lehrgedichte) of other philosophers whether this or at on to he length argue however, goes
poems
that fragment belongs to the Silloi or the irepi seems to have little point.
(4) Tradition
<pucreco$,
the exercise
long the complete works of Xenophanes survived, but certain that many of our authorities for his teaching possessed no more than extracts, or even depended entirely on the
It is
impossible to say
how
reports of others. Since Theophrastus and hence the later doxographers who copied him took their cue from Aristotle, it is unfortunate that
Aristotle himself felt some contempt for Xenophanes as a naive
and con-
separate liexametric work on natural philosophy was assumed by Zeller, Diels and Reinhardt, and strongly upheld by K. Deichgraber, Rh+ Mtts. 1938, 1-31. The contrary view has comment (p. 166) that been favoured by Bumet and Jaeger (TEGP, 40, and n. n, p. 210).
KR
a formal work on physical matters 'seems questionable, though not so impossible as Burnet would have us believe*. 3 At least in the treatises which became canonical after the edition of Andronicus in the time of Cicero and so have survived until today. It should not be forgotten that he probably wrote a
366
A 31). This
rejection
may have
more serious poems into obscurity or rarity. From Cicero onwards no one shows unmistakably by his comments that he had the actual poems
in his hand,
and in the second century A.D. both Sextus Empiricus and Galen use expressions indicating that they had not. SimpHcius in the sixth century was a learned and careful commentator to whom we owe
philosophy, and
who
always
to primary sources if he could and castigated those who neglected to do so. But for Xenophanes he relies on Theophrastus and
Melissus, Xenophanes and Gorgias (MXG\ and at one himself unable to explain the exact meaning of a line of point professes Xenophanes about the earth (fr. 28, r. 2) 'because I have not come
the treatise
On
Xenophanes on
this subject'.
So
far as
cosmology is concerned, probable that the complete poems had become difficult if not impossible of access by the beginning of our
it is
era.
still
A
The
problem
is
created
by
MXG,
included in the Aristotelian corpus but was certainly not written by Aristotle and probably not before the first century B.C. 2
which
on Xenophanes professes to give a full exposition of his if it could be relied on would be an extremely which arguments, valuable source. It does, however, make him out to be a systematic
section
short
one book) 'Against Xenophanes*, the title of which appears in Diogenes's list. the spurious On MeKssus, Xenophanes and Gorgias exists to remind us that productions could borrow the illustrious name (see P. Moraux, JLes Listes andennes des
(in
work
367
Xenopkanes
thinker using logical argument of a type impossible before Parmenides,
and anything
else that Is
that the picture is a true one. Diels's assessment of accepted, that the writer had no first-hand knowledge
generally
of the poems:
his primary interest was in the Eleatic school, and as the name Eleatic had stuck to Xenophanes he has simply read into a few words of
Aristotle a great deal more than they said. It will be best to get this point out of the way before starting our own account (as proper
method demands
that
we
should)
in the surviving remains of his own writings. The earliest extant reference to him is a contemptuous remark of
Heraclitus
(fr.
much
learning
it
him sense. The next is in Plato's Sophist (2420-0). The chief speaker in the dialogue, an unnamed visitor from Elea, complains that philosophers who have professed to determine the nature and number of real substances
(among
whom he singles
can be
like children
who
One
it
begetting like
stories
But our
own
Eleatic tribe, starting from Xenophanes and even earlier, relates its on the basis that what are called "all things" are really one/
earlier*
show that the remark is rather casual, and not seriously intended to mark out Xenophanes as the historical founder of the school. All one can conclude is that in some sense he
unity of reality. Aristotle, in the review of his predecessors which occupies the greater part of the first book of the Metaphysics, speaks (986b loff.) of
asserted
the;
one in a
of
different sense
reality nevertheless
movement and change, whereas the thinkers in question denied movement, and so by Aristotle's criterion disqualified themselves from being classified as philosophers of nature at all. He proceeds:
Yet so much it is relevant to note at present. Parmenides seems to be concerned with logical unity, Melissus with material. That is why the former says it is finite, the latter infinite. But Xenophanes, the first of these
368
whose disciple Parmenides is said to have been, in no way made himself clear, neither does he seem to have had a grasp of either of these con2 ceptions. He simply considered the whole world and said that the one exists,
namely the god. These men therefore, as I said, may be omitted from our present inquiry, two of them Xenophanesand Melissus altogether, as being somewhat primitive, though Parmenides indeed speaks with more insight.
would expect from Aristotle, is a careful and informative statement, to which we shall have to return. But it is utterly different from what is said about Xenophanes in the treatise y
This, as one
MXG
how a not very perceptive writer, bent on making Xenophanes an Eleatic in the full sense, could have evolved it out of an unintelligent reading of the present passage.
although one can see
at the
same time
Aristotle
tells
us,
that
have been* Xenophanes's pupil chronoa logically perfectly possible relationship. In an age which loved
'said to
Parmenides was
among the philosophers, this would strengthen the impression gained from Plato that Xenophanes was the real founder of the Eleatic school. Again, Aristotle's negative verdict that Xenophanes did not distinguish between material and non-material, nor (as
clear-cut 'successions'
implied) between finite and infinite, is absurdly twisted by the later writer into a positive statement that the divine unity of Xenophanes was loth moved and unmoved, both finite and infinite. He then prois
duces sophisticated arguments from Eleatic and even later logic in favour of each thesis in turn. This distortion may have been based not
directly
on
Aristotle but
more
1
liable to
misunderstanding.
TO 6v
TTpooTos TOUTCOV
EV elvca
Alexander as
described the
viaa$, a neat phrase difficult to match in English. It is explained shrcbv. The context shows that by TOUTCOV Aristotle means those
by
who
sum of things as a unity now and always, in distinction from those who assumed an original state of unity out of which a plurality has been generated. a I.e. logical and material unity, not finitude and infinity as Burnet thought (EGP, 124),
though that also follows from the previous sentence. What Aristotle says here is true: only after Parmenides could the distinction between abstract and concrete, logical and numerical unity,
begin to emerge. 3 See Simplicius in A3i:
uTroT{0e<T0crf
<pr\a\v
tilocv
ours
-rrerrEpocaulvov
oure
6 0e6<ppaoro$.
5vo9CxvTiv T6v KoAo<pcbviov TOV TTcrpiievloou SiSdoxaAov Note that Xenophanes has now become 'the teacher of
Parmenides' sans phrase. This whole nexus between Aristotle, Theophrastus and the writer of affords an illuminating insight into the growth of a myth of philosophical history.
MXG
369
Xenophanes
Karl Reinhardt in his book Parmenides raised a lone voice in vigorous
MXG. Admitting that its arguments this difficulty by reversing the he solved must be post-Parmenidean, order of precedence between Xenophanes and Parmenides and making
defence of the trustworthiness of
Xenophanes the
it
demands the
of ancient testimony, impossible to accept. is the accuracy with which His strongest argument in favour of is confirmed by comparison This of Melissus. it records the teaching
rejection of every scrap
MXG
with the extant fragments of Melissus's work. Why then, demanded Reinhardt, should the same man report Melissus faithfully and Xeno-
phanes with wild inaccuracy? The answer is perhaps not very far to Parmenides and his seek. He was a keen student of the Eleatics
Zeno and Melissus and steeped in their tradition. Consequently when he was dealing with genuine Eleatic thought he reported it correctly. When, however, he was writing of a man whom legend had made into an Eleatic though in fact he was a thinker of far less sophistication, his acceptance of the legend made it inevitable that he should misinterpret him in accordance with Eleatic logic; and seeing that Parmenides brought about one of the most fundamental revolutions in philosophical thinking, the misinterpretation was naturally farfollowers
reaching.
(5) Destructive criticism
Xenophanes was
satirical criticism
chiefly
known
and denunciation, and the extant verses provide evidence that such was indeed his attitude to poets, philosophers, ample and the ordinary run of men. His passion for reform has appeared
already in the social and autobiographical pieces. He recommends expurgation of theological myths at the drinking-party, fulminates
against the cult of athleticism, and denounces the luxurious habits of his former countrymen. Among philosophical and religious teachers Thales, Pythagoras and Epimenides are specially named as having
lines
aroused his opposition (D.L. ix, 18), and we can still read his satirical about Pythagoras and his doctrine of reincarnation (fr. 7; see
p. 157, above).
But the
fullest
Hesiod, the
weight of his displeasure was reserved for Homer and as Herodotus said had determined for the
37o
nowadays
difficult to
appreciate, especially
when we
read
Homer,
for
we
enjoy the Iliad and Odyssey as marvellous poems and exciting tales of warfare and travel showing great insight into human nature, but it
may not occur to us that they can ever have been regarded as much more. Yet in Greece, whatever may have been the intentions of the bards who had created them, they became at an early date the
foundation of religious and moral, as well as literary, education. Herodotus was justified in his remark, and so was Xenophanes when
he wrote
'
(fr.
10) :
What
all
men
learn
is
shaped by
Homer from
the
beginning.'
Both
in
on
religious
the gods play a prominent part, and it is Xenophanes launches his attack. His main
charges are two: that they portray the gods as immoral and that they
cast
them
in
human
shape.
ascribed to the gods
all
deeds that
among men
(fr.
are
n)?
its
is,
for
its
time, even
more remarkable
in
objectivity;
Ethiopians imagine their gods as black and snub-nosed, Thracians as blueeyed and red-haired (fr. 16).
as
and horses or lions had hands, or could draw and fashion works do, horses would draw the gods shaped like horses and lions like lions, making the bodies of the gods resemble their own forms (fr. 15).
But
if oxen
men
Men suppose
shape
that
birth,
like their
own
and
their context in
6,
mind
when he wrote
interest in
in his
Xenophanes's views, but "solely as an example of a particular form of argument): As for instance Xenophanes used to argue that to
c
Hdt. ii, 53: *It is they who created a theogony for the Greeks, gave the gods their names, distributed their privileges and skills, and described their appearance.* z The indifferent verse into which the fragments have so far been translated was intended to
fix in
a reader's
precise
mind that it is in fact poems that are in question throughout. From now on the wording of a translation may be more important, and prose will usually be adopted.
37!
Xenophanes
say the gods are born way it follows that there
is
as
is
impious as to say that they die; for either a time when they do not exist.' This may be
made by much
fir-trees as
later writers
Xenophanes upheld the eternity of God. Another line from the Silloi runs: 'And
1
Bacchi stand
It is quoted by of Aristophanes in the following context: 'Not only Dionysus is called Bacchus but also those who perform his rites, and the branches
a scholiast
on the Knights
carried
by
the initiates.
Xenophanes mentions
'
not the occasion to expound the psychology of the Bacchic the purpose of its orgiastic rites religion, but it may be said, first, that
This
is
was
to
become
and so
'
at
and called 472 N.) Bacchus.' The worshipper could have his life taken up into that of the god who stood for the essence of life itself. Bacchus, god of the grape,
(fr.
was
sanctified
was god
He made
a pliant, green and sappy bough and a dead, dry and brittle one, as also between the living creature with blood coursing through its veins and the
stiff
and
lifeless
corpse.
As such
his spirit
as in his
human
worshippers.
Classical art
with the god's mask hanging on them, and it is not at all surprising that fir-trees which decorated a scene of Bacchic rites should have been
given the name of the god.* Although the line of Xenophanes has no context of its own to help us, we may be sure that its purpose was to heap further ridicule on popular forms of religion. Gods with human
clothes and bodies, gods with snub noses or red hair, god in vegetable form !
and
now
The
different people
discrepancies between the religious beliefs and customs of began to make a deep impression in the fifth century,
Fr. 17 (Schol. Ar. Eq. 408) &rraoiv 6* iA&rqs <pdicxoi> TruKiv6v irepl Scopcc. So DK. Lobeck hamuS) i } 308, note (i)) emended more freely to ionracnv 8* IXonrcov -nvKivol irepl Scbpcxra Fortunately the sense is assured by the context in the scholiast (quoted in full by Lobeck
The
fir
tipped with
its
had particular associations with Dionysus. The thyrsi carried by bacchants were cones, and in the story of Pentheus the Xdrri plays a significant part (see Eur.
Bacchae> 1064).
372
much
its
mark
the
inference that
foundation of social anthropology, with a power of observation and is matched in the study of nature by the same philosopher's remarks on fossils (pp. 387f.,below). His condemnation of the poets for ascribing immoral acts and unworthy sufferings to the gods
was
it
particularly influential, not least through the ready response which aroused in the questing mind of Euripides, as in the following lines
This passage is so obviously modelled on Xenophanes that we may use the latter part as confirmation of yet a third charge which he brought
against the poets: deity
must be
self-sufficient,
hier-
archy within
page), this
is
it.
Though
perhaps implied
by
a line like
25 (see next
nowhere
Euripides
vindicates
the
Eusebius, where we read (A 32): 'Concerning the gods he shows that there is no government among them, for it is impious that any of the
gods should have a master; and that none of them lacks anything in any respect/ Cicero (see A 52; also in Aetius) mentions yet a fourth
way
in
namely
together, these charges exhibit a surprisingly high level of religious thought for the sixth century B.C. in Greece. They show that
if
Taken
Xenophanes believed
in a
god
must be non-
anthropomorphic, morally good, everlasting, completely self-sufficient and independent. One might well ask whether a rejection of so much
1 Eur. H.F. 1341 ff. The lengthy outburst against athletes in an even more obvious imitation of Xenophanes.
fr.
I,
p. 139) is
373
Xenophanes
in the beliefs of Ms contemporaries carried with it the abandonment of in any kind of god? religious belief altogether. Did he believe
He
did,
is
hardly diminished
when we
if
turn to the
The
extant verses in
which he
sacrifice
may
be translated as follows,
we
26 and 25 : Always he remains in the same place, not moving at all, nor indeed does it befit him to go here and there at different times; but without toil he makes all things shiver by the impulse of his mind.' 3
Frr.
Xenophanes is still thinking of Homer. In the last line (fr. 25) KpccSodvei means literally makes to shake \ which recalls the way that Olympus shook when Zeus nodded his head (//. I, 530): the true god does not even need to nod. Homeric gods, in order to affect the course of events on earth, were constantly flying down from Olympus to intervene personally; but the true god remains always in the same place. Aeschylus, another whose conception of deity was ahead of most of
*
his time, appreciated these thoughts and took them over in the Supplices (100-3): 'All divine action is without toil. Sitting still he
1
el$ 9eo$,
mind a complete
on
sis
*One god*. But the couplet was certainly in Xenophanes's and Greek omits the copula as naturally as English inserts it One 'There is one god*, but with a risk of diminishing the great emphasis placed
by
its
Diogenes says (ix, 19, DK, AI): 6Aov 5 6pov xod 6Aov This omits SAov VOEIV, and KR would seem to be wrong in saying * (p. 170) that it implies that the concluding words were not oOAo$ 6 T* dKoOsi but oO uivroi dvomvei '. From his use of the term cNpoipoeiSifc, one may assume that Diogenes was one of those who equated Xenophanes's deity with the cosmos, and his last words must be meant to contrast it with the breathing world of the Pythagoreans. One cannot be certain whether the actual words were in Xenophanes's poern, but it is probably not accidental that they form the ending of a dactylic hexameter. (Cf. also Kahn, Anaxzmandery 98, n. 2: 'The accurate paraphrase of fr. 24 shows the hand of Theophrastus, and thus guarantees the concluding reference to breathing.') He may have been making the point that the one divine spherical universe contains all that there is: there is
Reporting
jifi
fixoOfiv,
plvroi dvornvEiv.
nothing besides the One, therefore no infinite breath* outside for it to absorb. (For a contrary view, with which I disagree, see Heidel, AJP, 1940, 2. Heidel argues that because Xenophanes himselfvs he believes did not identify god with the cosmos, therefore this cannot be directed
against the Pythagoreans. He supposes it to refer to popular anthropomorphism: eyes or ears, so why should he need lungs?)
3
god needs no
von Fritz,
On voou <f>pcv{ cf. //. ix, 600 v6ei <ppof (KR, 171); also Snell, Discovery of Mind, 316, n. 16, CP 1945, 229! To bring out the full meaning of the words, von Fritz would translate:
9
*by the active will (or impulse) proceeding from his all-pervading
insight*.
374
Frr. 23 and 24 are complementary to the criticisms of anthropomorphic divine beings in frr. n, 14, 15, 16: god is not in 1 any way like man, he needs no separate organs of perception.
23 leaves no doubt that to and essential. Nevertheless to see it in was Xenophanes important perspective it must be understood that the question of monotheism or
is
God
one.
this
polytheism, which is of vital religious importance to the Christian, Jew or Moslem, never had the same prominence in the Greek mind.
(For that matter, even Jehovah was not always without his divine rivals and foes.) Immediately after his emphatic proclamation of the unity of god, we have the phrase 'greatest among gods and men*. This is dealt with nowadays by the device of giving it a label: it is merely a
'polar expression'. Nevertheless its use by one for whom monotheism was a religious dogma would argue at the least a surprising carelessness. 2
It is often said that in other places also Xenophanes allows himself to speak of gods in the plural in the conventional Greek way. Looked at individually, however, these passages amount to little. In fr. i he is
the genial arbiter bibendi, and naturally sees no harm in conforming to the traditional custom which indeed it is his function to enforce.
when
Consequently he speaks at the end of being 'mindful of the gods', and in line 13 he mentions theos in the singular, that is no doubt
explained
altar set
by
two
lines earlier.
It
would be an
up to a particular god Dionysus or some other in whose honour therefore the hymns are sung. Whichever it is, he has nothing to do with the 'one god' of fr. 23, nor should we look for serious
theology in
1
this
drinking-poem.
6110(105 seems worded to contradict such Homeric descriptions of human beings as Senas elKvia 6erjcn (//. viu, 305), 8nas dOccvdroiaiv 6uolos (OcL vui, 14). So Deichgraber, Rh. Mus. 1938, 27, n. 45. 2 The idea is that such * polar expressions' are simply cliches used for emphasis and not intended to be taken literally. KR, 170 compare Heraclitus, fr. 30, where 'no god or man made difference would seem to be this cosmos* is only a way of saying that it was not created at aU. that in Heraclitus the polar expression, if it were taken literally, would still state what its author * wants to say. In Xenophanes it contradicts it. Neither god nor man made it* is as much as to
In
fr.
say
'.
becomes
nonsense.
Kahn (Anaximander^ 156, n. 3) suggests that *in all probability the plural "gods" of Xenophanes are the elements and the sun, moon and stars ; the greatest deity is the world itself, or its
everlasting source*.
375
Xenophanes
The
wrong
critical
fragments are
all
negative.
to depict gods as thieves and adulterers; it is wrong to believe that they are born and die, that they have human bodies., voices and that there is one god only, clothes. From all this the message of fr. 23
and he in no way resembles man may follow without contradiction. The same may be said of fr. 34: 'No man has known or will know the that I speak of/ Fr. 18 is plain truth about the gods and about all
all things in the equally negative: 'The gods did not reveal to men out better/ find beginning, but in course of time, by searching, they
man's
This is tantamount to saying that the advance of knowledge depends on own efforts and not on any divine revelation (p. 399, below). In
extant fragment does
'
no other
Xenophanes refer to gods in the plural. ' This is Fr. 38 begins: If God (theos) had not made yellow honey not evidence either way. It is a conventional phrase in which a Greek
either singular or plural, existed*.
'if
honey
Doubtless Xenophanes did not condemn the worship of gods outright, provided men's notion of them was stripped of anthropo-
morphic
crudities
if this
and immorality. He is emphatic that god is essentione god was, as will be argued here, the living and
divine cosmos, then he probably thought that the spirit of this universal being manifested itself to the imperfect perceptions of man (fr. 34) in
many
forms.
'in no way like usually assumed that the words of fr. 23 mortals in body' prove that the god of Xenophanes was not incorporeal but had a body of his own, only not of human shape. Even if this inference is perhaps not certain, there is nothing in his remains or
It is
the tradition to suggest that he was so far ahead of his time as to have advanced to the notion of incorporeal being, an inherently unlikely supposition. His one god, then, had a body. What was this body, and of what shape? No relevant quotation has survived from Xenophanes himself, but most ancient authorities say that it was spherical. Texts
are:
(a)
semblance to man.
D.L. ix ? 19 (DK, AI): 'The being of the god is spherical, with no reHe sees as a whole and hears as a whole', etc. We may
376
()
MXG,
977 b
(</)
Hippolytus (A 33)
He says
.
that the
in all directions
(e)
his parts/
Sextus (A 35) : 'Xenophanes asserted. . .that the all is one, and god 1 consubstantial with all things, and that he is spherical, impassible, unchanging, and rational/
CO
'He
was one,
spherical
and
finite,
not generated but eternal, and altogether unmoved/ Here the spherical shape elsewhere ascribed to god is given to the total sum of things. Comparison makes it obvious that Theodoret is referring to the same being as
the others: he
that
it is
is
a matter of indifference to
the universe
Between them these passages make two points: the god of Xenophanes was spherical, and he was identical with the universe. Let us
take
for
them one by one. With such a strong consensus of ancient evidence sphericity, one might suppose that even though we do not possess
it
A
word
is
Galen,
The translation is R. G. Bury's (Loeb). cru^mfe (lit. growing together') is used * with the dative in various ways, meaning adapted to* (Arist. De An. 42034), 'attached to* (id. P.A. 6<5ob28), or 'coalescing with*. In the last sense Plato speaks of the visual ray that shoots forth from the eye coalescing or not coalescing with the air around it (Tim. 45 D), and Plutarch says that Lycurgus taught the Spartans to live not for themselves but Tq> xoivcp oviKpi/ets, integrated or identified with the community (Lye. 25). Only the last sense is possible in the present context.
The meaning therefore is the same as when ps.-Galen says (A 3 5) that Xenophanes 'asserted only
that all things are
one and
source
this is
god
a
finite, rational,
unchanging*.
Gal.)
*
The
is clearly
common one
(cf. also
which stated that Xenophanes identified god with the universe. few recent opinions. Sphericity *goes beyond the fragments and is highly dubious* (KR, 170); 'obviously due to a later interpretation of 823 under the influence of Parmenides* (Jaeger, TJEGP, 21 1, n. 23) ; *Peut-tre faut-il aller plus loin et dire que, de" ja, cette unite" cosmique et divine est concue comme sph6rique* (Dies, Cycle Mystique, 75 ); *Dass Xenophanes seinem Gott die Kugelgestalt gab, scheint mir sicher schon im Hinblick auf 823* (Deichgraber, Rh. Mus. 1938, 27, n. 45); *He regarded his god as a sphere* (Snell, Discovery of Mind, 142).
Reinhardt also accepted sphericity. 3 The uses of this word have been discussed under Anaximander, pp. 83 ff., above.
377
Xenophanes
with the epithet spherical' Hlppolytus and Theodoret all combine that of 'finite*. Simplicius, however, after quoting the statement of Alexander also that the arche of Xenophanes was finite, adds that Nicolaus of Damascus (first century B.C.) said it was apeiron and
*
unmoved. Aetius
(n,
i, 3,
DK,
among
those
who
in an undiscriminating list which posited an infinite number Qikosmoi^ the two divisions certainly contains some errors and admits only c 'innumerable kosmoi* or a single kosmos\ and Diogenes (ix, 19)
credits
belief (a
in
view of what
we know of
him).
god
as infinitum.
Theophrastus, either directly or indirectly, but for Xenophanes there is the complication of MXG, whose writer had a particular interest in the Eleatics and put forward
interpretations of his
sentence from Theophrastus himself (A 31): Theophrastus says the hypothesis of Xenophanes was that the arche was one, or the universe
finite
is
nor
infinite,
little
Here
as often Theophrastus
doing
Aristotle, to
nor an
*
authority for saying that Xenophanes believed in an infinite universe infinite god, nor, as I have tried to show, is there any solid
and
finite',
gent
classification
and they must be believed. Neither the unintelliof Aetius^ nor the contemptuous remarks of Cicero's
Epicurean deserve credit against them, and this leaves Nicolaus of Damascus the only one out of step. One instance of the word apeiron in Xenophanes's own remains must be mentioned. He says of the earth
it 'goes downward indefinitely' (e!$ onreipov). This will be discussed later, but I would venture the opinion that it does not involve
that
With
term meaning 'precisely similar*: the MSS. differ). That the elaborate logic which he attributes to Xenophanes did not come from Theophrastus emerges clearly enough from SimpL Phys. 22. 26 ff. (DK, A3i). 3 On which see Cornford, 'Innumerable Worlds*, CQ, 1934, especially 9-10.
*
Hicks) or
378
a shape, but suppose that beyond this Xenophanes only described him in negative terms. This is unsatisfactory. If Xenophanes was positive
tion of Xenophanes's god as spherical do not propose They rightly insist that this god had a body, and the
any
alternative.
1
body
enough
to state that his god had a body, he probably indicated its The only argument produced against this is that Parmenides shape. his One Being to a sphere and owing to the tendency, from compared
Plato onwards, to
historians
Eleatics,
Greek
were apt to
of Parmenides.
an
illegitimate importation
from Parmenides
It is true that
But does
MXG,
which
one of the sources for sphericity; but it is that this was one of the initial similarities which likely existed to make the tradition possible at all. 2
absurd lengths,
much more
must have
We
have
still
To
on 'He
never occurs to Xenophanes to suggest Greeks gave their philosophical attention to these matters, the problem of the form (uop9i\) of the divine was one that never lost its importance.'
particularly this
*It
Note
that
In this I agree strongly with Deichgraber (Rh. Mus. 193$, 2.7, n. 45): 'Xenophanes muss uber die Gestalt des einen Gottes Angaben gemacht haben und gerade in Hinblick auf den 6X05Begriff scheint das Pradikat c^cnpoeiS^s das einzig mogliche.* Those who regard the mention of a sphere as Parmenidean cite the phrases of Timon of Phlius
about Xenophanes, that his *all' (r6 irov) irdcvn-i &peXK6pvov uiov elj ^Ooiv forocQ* 6yo(Tiv and that te6v hrA&acrr' loov drrdvTQ. These, it is argued, are really a misappropriation of the description of the One in Parm. 8, 4433 vz&atfav lacnroctes Trdirrn, and gave rise to the idea that the One God
of Xenophanes was spherical. This is tortuous reasoning. It is not denied that Parmenides was an Italian Greek who lived later than Xenophanes. Why then reject the more natural supposition * that he took something from his predecessor? Timon, who repeatedly praised Xenophanes and went the length of dedicating his Silloi to him* (Sextus: see A3 5), knew his poems better than we do. In anycase the idea of a spherical divine universe is hardly surprising for the sixth or early fifth century. There is no suggestion that Xenophanes anticipated the pure intelligible One of Parmenides, though his insistence on unity (which is fortunately attested by actual quotation) represents an advance which no doubt gave an impetus to the even subtler thought of his
successor.
379
Xenopkanes
concentrated his attention on the whole heaven (ouranos} and said 1 that the One exists, the god/
This sentence suggests to the imagination a rather magnificent picture of the philosopher-poet standing alone in a wide empty landscape
on a
and crying, 'The One exists, God'; that is, looking up at the heavens and declaring that the world was one and divine. Something like that I believe he must have done, even if we concede that Aristotle's
and
it is
words do not necessarily imply it. The verb used, though a compound of 'to look*, was commonly used metaphorically of a mental process. Aristotle is saying that by fixing his attention on the nature of the universe Xenophanes came to the conclusion that the One was God. If this does not necessarily mean that he actually identified the universe with the
unitary divinity,
Aristotle,
it
we may remind
ourselves, characterized
Xenophanes
as
to posit a unity in a stricter sense than did the Milesians, but nevertheless a more primitive thinker than the genuine Eleatics Parmenides and Melissus, one who had not yet grasped the distinction
the
first
logical unity
and for
this
make
his
concept altogether clear. That he did in some way advance the notion of unity we may assume both from this and from Plato's mention of
ways of thinking; and Aristotle tells us in what the advance consisted, namely in supposing the cosmos to be ungenerated. He and his successors 'are not like some of the writers on nature who regard reality as one but nevertheless assume generation out of the one as matter. They speak in a different
as
him
having given a
way, for the others, since they generate the universe, add motion, whereas these men say it is unmoved* (MetapL 986b 14).*
1
E!$
crrropA&j/ccs
TO
Iv etvctf <pf]ai
*.
.that the
One
was the god*.) The precise meaning of some of the Greek words is important. It is true that oOpovos here must be used in the sense of 'universe* rather than merely *sky*. Nevertheless it has associations quite different from, say, TO TTOV or 6 KOOIIOS. Ouranos was die sky, and he was also a god, even if the word had come to be used when the sky was being thought of particularly
as the envelope of the world and even as that envelope with its contents. The central idea in ocrropA^rrgiv si* is that of looking away from all other things and so only at a particular object, to concentrate one*s gaze. Its classical usage is by no means confined, as Heidel
would have confined it here, to treating something as a model. z It may seem odd that in De Caelo (279 b 12) Aristotle should say so emphatically of the world ysv6nvov pv oCrv omxvrEs elvoi 9ocoiv, but the words of Metaph. A Ixtfvoi pv yop irpoondioffi
380
the world
say the universe (TO TTCCV) is unmoved; and we have it in Xenophanes's own words that the One God is unmoved (fr. 26). The world
They
is
(fr. 14).
It is
some additional confirmation, if that were needed, of the conclusion which has now become inescapable, that Xenophanes identified God
and the world and to that extent
may be
called a pantheist.
But one or
two
difficulties must be faced before attempting to sum up his view. The pantheism of Xenophanes has been denied on various grounds or none. Cherniss writes (ACP^ 201, n. 228) The fragments give no
c
inferred for him from the unity which he predicated of God/ This implies that if the god were spherical, that would be an argument in favour of the identification. Reinhardt on the other hand (Farm. n6f.) accepts his sphericity, and denies the identification on that very ground. He cites the statement of fr. 28,
god was
which, he claims, says that the earth (and a fortiori the universe) stretches downwards to infinity. This point has been mentioned already.
The
is
strongly in favour of a
1
finite
universe,
'infinite*.
A
fr.
more
H.
26.
serious difficulty is the immobility ascribed to the god in Frankel writes (Dicht. u. PhiL 428): 'The scope of this pro-
nouncement only becomes plain when it is recognized that in Greek " philosophy the word motion" covers every kind of change. Hence in the sphere of God no physical event takes place at all; only when his
influence "without toil" reaches our world,
is it
transformed into
Kivnmv, yewoSvrls ye TO irov, oCrroi Si &dvr|Tov elvcd <pacnv are unambiguous, and Xenophanes is included among the oC/rou Presumably he has only <pvoioA6yoi in mind in De Caelo, from whom Xenophanes and the Eleatics are expressly excluded owing to the novelty of their conceptions.
down
Cornford, Princ. Sap. 147, n. i : 'Frag. 28, stating that the underside of the earth reaches "indefinitely" ($ cnrEipov) can be explained as denying that the earth floats on water (Tholes) or on air (Anaximenes), or that there is any hollow Tartarus beneath it. The earth
extends downwards, unlimited by anything else^ to the bottom of the sphere (Gilbert, Meteor. Theor. 280, 671). The sun, according to Xenophanes, moves in a straight line eij firrreipov, 7 "indefinitely", not "to infinity"; it burns out in a short time (Zeller, I , 669).* The addition to
28 in the Stromateis (A 32), (T^V yfjv Smipov elvoci) Keel v$\ KOCT& irov iilpos Trepi^xaj^ot UTTO dipos, presumably means that air cannot enclose it all round as it did the free-floating earth of Anaximander. I take it to he a doxographer*s gloss.
fr.
381
Xenophanes
movement and events/ Kirk (KR, 172) thinks that Aristotle's statement on Xenophanes clearly implies that god is identical with the
*
world*, but that Aristotle must be wrong because the god could not be motionless if identical with a world which is itself implied to move
(in
fr.
25).
to right answer to this problem lies, I think, in a challenge ' Frankel's generalization that 'in Greek philosophy' the word motion'
The
covers every kind of change. It did so for Aristotle (which is probably one reason why he found Xenophanes obscure), and he methodically divided it into locomotion or change of place, qualitative
(kinesis)
change, quantitative change, and birth-and-destruction or change between being and non-being. But such precision is hardly found
before his time, and certainly not before the time of Parmenides, whose confrontation of Being and Becoming, with its proofs that what is can
neither become nor perish, neither grow nor diminish, nor yet change in quality nor move in space, marked a turning-point in Greek thought. Before that, the word kinesis was not a technical term, but used in
relation to its context
local
motion or disturbance.
The context shows that this is how Xenophanes is using it in fr. 26. *Not moving at all' means that the god 'remains in the same place'. He must not be thought of as 'going to different places at different times*. This is consistent with imagining him as the universe itself in
1 aspect as a living and conscious being. universe itself (or sum of things, TO TTOV) was
its
for
Xenophanes, but he is not necessarily he is using the word in the sense of ungenerated. This too Xenoit
phanes believed the world to be, but he is not referring to appears rather in fr. 14 ('Gods are not born').
I
here. It
conclude that for Xenophanes the cosmos was a spherical body, living, conscious, and divine, the cause of its own internal movements
tradition.
is not a denial of any change inside the world. It probably means that, unlike other which must move about to seek their food, the world, needing no sustenance, stays where it is' (Comford, Princ. Sap. 147). 2 * " Fr. 25. 1 agree with Cornford again when he says (loc. cit.) : The word sways" (KpccScrfvei) need mean no more than "moves**." Its choice was doubtless motivated, as has been suggested
This
animals,
the divinity and therefore had no beginning or dissolution but was everlasting. This gave it unity in a new and more absolute sense which he himself regarded as important (* One god. /), and which in the eyes of Plato and Aristotle justified a view of him as the spiritual
.
further
whose contribution to philosophy was to be a of all plurality. Probably his 'unifying* of things went than this. He was not only, or even primarily, a natural
philosopher, as Theophrastus perceived (p. 367, above), and certainly not a logician like Parmenides. He was a poet who took the didactic
function of poetry seriously. What impressed him was that if Ionian hylozoism, or anything like it, were correct, this proved the falsehood
of Homeric theology; and since the lessons of that theology were morally undesirable, it provided the intellectual basis for a lesson of
which mankind was much in need: they must be shown that conception of deity was altogether unworthy.
(8)
their
The
behind the poems. I am not one of those who would dismiss this remarkable figure as a mere rhapsode undeserving of the name of
philosopher:
able.
we
aims were quite different from those of an Anaximander, and it is very possible that this made for a certain lack of precision, even
Yet
his
of consistency, in his description of the physical world. We must not press him too hard, nor, while making every effort to understand him,
necessarily conclude that our sources or our own reasoning are if they fail to produce an altogether coherent picture.
wrong
all
As an example we may
things,
all
(fr.
27) :
it
From
earth
come
to
be genuine, 1
we
have
of Anaximander and
(fr.
Homer, and its general sense much the same as that of the Diogenes of Apollonia (p. 88, above), and the olcxKi^a of
Heraclitus
64).
The genuineness of this line, which conies from no earlier authority than Aetius (and if known to Theophrastus was not interpreted by him as by Ae*tius), has been frequently denied,
383
Xenophanes
no context to guide us in its interpretation. The words were used quite early to classify Xenophanes with the first monists as one who simply
In the Hippocratic work On the Nature of Man (vi, 32 Littre: probably early fourth century B.C.) we already read: One of them calls this universal unity The last can hardly be air, another fire, another water, another earth/
air.
anyone but Xenophanes. So in a later age Olympiodorus (DK, A36): No one believed earth to be the arche except Xenophanes of Colo6
tradition, however, as represented by the Stromateis and Hippolytus (A32 and 33), suggests that it was not as simple as that. In the collection of opinions which (with little attempt
unlike originates from earth' occur side by side with statements that, he denied and Anaximenes, coming-into-being Thales, Anaximander and passing away, and asserted that 'the whole was not only one but
5
'always the same* and 'exempt from change*. Theodoret, bothered by the inconsistency, says simply (A 3 6) that he forgot his statement that
'the whole* was imperishable when he wrote the line 'From earth come all things, all things end in earth*. Sextus (Math, x, 313), though
he too quotes the line itself, adds only that 'according to some' this meant that earth was the 'origin of becoming' in the same sense as
water for Thales or
air for
Anaximenes.
Nature of Man): 'I do not say that man is altogether air like Anaximenes, or water like Thales, or earth like Xenophanes in one of
the
On
his
poems/ This
is
A 36), who
line,
which he does not reject, is that it 'has indeed nothing to 211). It would be more helpful if he had said what it has
384
and Water
his opinion,
making such a
declaration.
.and
if this
had been
Theo-
Aristotle himself, reviewing earlier philosophers in the Metaphysics (98935)5 says that 'none of those who posit a unity makes earth the element ', and in De Anima he repeats (405 b 8) that all the other
of the Milesians, and might be supposed to exclude Xenophanes for that reason, since he distinguishes him from them. But his reason for
making the distinction was that Xenophanes believed the cosmos to be eternal, and so could not have believed in any arche at all as the
Milesians understood
it.
so our line must have meant something different, as it easily can. It is now time to bring two other fragments into the discussion:
Fr. 29: 'All that is born and grows is earth and water.' Fr. 33: 'For we are all born out of earth and water.*
These have been solemnly regarded as offering a different account of origins from fr. 27, so that there is a task of reconciliation to be per-
formed between them. Deichgraber for instance, on pp. I4f. of his Hermes article, suggests that 'all things* in fr. 27 means the cosmos as
a whole, but in the other lines means the individual things and creatures within it. These are born from earth and water, but water itself derives
from
earth,
which
is
is
the
reverse of the explanation offered earlier by Freudenthal, who thought it probable that other things had originated from earth alone, but earth itself from water: hence all things could be said to be born, at one
remove, from earth and water. When the solutions of two good scholars cancel out so neatly, one may suspect that there is something wrong with the posing of the
problem.
Now
all
living things were originally born among the Greeks. This was their
way of getting over the difficulty of bringing life into being in the first place, when it could not have been produced as it is now, by procreation
from already existing animals and men. It was the more easily adopted because to them it seemed a fact of observation that certain small
385
Xenophanes
creatures like
first
maggots were still spontaneously generated. To bear the animals and men, the earth had to be made fertile, and the vehicle of fertility was moisture. The transformation of dry, barren soil by
rain or irrigation
was an obvious
fact
of their
own
rationalists.
For those
who
preferred
was a person, the goddess Gaia, die Great Mother, and her fertilization took the form of
religious or mythological explanations, the earth
marriage with the sky-god, Ouranos, Aither, or Zeus. He by his rain became the father of men and animals as well as plants, and the Earth
was
their mother,
to birth
when
who
all
things are born from Earth, the common mother, and so they frequently did. But it was equally correct to say that they are born from earth
and water,
Neither the mythologists nor Anaximander nor any other philosopher believed that. Hence earth alone may be mentioned, or water and earth,
(v, 805):
Turn
tibi terra
dedit
primum
mortalia saecla.
arvis.
Xenophanes's, had been lost, and an ancient authority had quoted the first line without the second, some literal-minded scholar might have argued from it that mortal creatures were supposed
poem,
like
born from dry earth alone, and that therefore any reference to birth from earth and water must apply to something
to have been
different.
We may conclude, then, that all three lines describe the same thing,
namely the origin of organic life from the earth, which, in order to produce it, had to be moist. The arche of the cosmos is not in question because, being everlasting, it has no arche. In accounting for the origin of life, we may be sure that Xenophanes followed the rationalistic rather than the polytheistic path, and in fact his motive seems to be still the same to discredit Homer in whatever ways he can. He can hardly have
:
Eur.
chh.
i
fr.
839.
The
subject
is
In the JBeginning,
and
2,
386
Evidence of Fossils
written
fr.
Achaeans
(//.
who
*
33 without a thought for the curse of Menelaus on the lacked the courage to respond to Hector's challenge
vn, 99) :
all
* !
That
is
just
what
we
are' ?
Xenophanes seems to
(9) Alternation
say.
According to the doxographers (there is no mention of it in the fragments) Xenophanes believed that the earth was subject to alternate encroachments of land on sea and sea on land. The evidence is as
follows:
(a) Stromateis, iv (A32):
'He
of time the
earth
(fr)
is
many
gradually moving into the sea.' Hippol. Ref, i, 14, 4-6 (A 33): *He said that the sea is salt because mixtures flow together in it. Metrodorus accounts for its saltness by
continuously slipping
down and
it is filtered through the earth, but Xenophanes thinks that a of earth with sea takes place and that in course of time it is dissolved mingling by the wet element, claiming as proofs that shells are found in the midst of the 2 land and on mountains; and in the quarries at Syracuse, he says, the impressions of a fish and of seaweed 3 have been found, on Pares the impression of
all
These, he says, were formed when everything, long ago, was covered in mud, and the impression dried out in the mud. All men
1
Behind
illustrated
But I
this odd saying in Homer there may well have lain originally the popular belief, by the Prometheus myth and others, that men are in fact made of these two substances. doubt if the poet was very conscious of this. 'Sitting there each one of you like dummies
(lifeless, ^pioi)' are the next words, 'inglorious and helpless.* Primarily the phrase seems in* tended to mention anything inanimate, to mean no more than You might as well be stocks and
stones*.
* Xenophanes was not the only one to observe this. Speaking of Egypt, Herodotus (n, 12) mentions xoyx^Xia T& <paiv6uiva rrl ToTs Spgai. Xanthus of Lydia (ap. Strabo i, 3, 4, p. 64 Meineke), active during the middle part of the fifth century B.C., both observed fossils and drew the same conclusion that the land was once sea. These writers are slightly later than Xenophanes, but probably he was drawing on common knowledge which may even have been available to Anaximander. 3 Or 'seals'? <j*oKo5v MSS., DK; <JUKV Gomperz, Burnet, Heath, KR, etc. Reinhardt rejects Gomperz's suggestion with the typical flourish: 'Wo kamen wir schliesslich hin, wenn wir die
Texte nach den Mitteilungen der Fachleute berichtigen wollen?' 4 The occurrence of plant-fossils on Paros was once thought impossible, and Gronovius wished to emend B&pvrtf to <5wpOr|S. Others have thought that other places than the island of Paros were
intended
(DK ad /be.).
It now appears, however, that the text offers no palaeontological diffi1956 ed.; F. Casella in Mcua> 1957, 322-5; KR, 178; M. Marcovich in CP9
1959, 121).
387
Xenophams
are destroyed
mud, then a
worlds.*
when the earth is carried down to new generation begins. Such is the
foundation
of
all
the
and in different description of fossil remains, of various kinds that the sea as evidence places, is impressive, and was reasonably taken once covered what is now dry land, and that the solid rock was once
soft
The
mud,
for
which the
plant-fossil
it
mony. All
this,
so far as
retreat^ but Hippolytus makes it clear that the process is a cyclic one, and in fact from his account and the Stromateis together we must
conclude that
we
At
Greek mythology was familiar with disasters which had wiped out all or most of the human race. Whether by flood, as in the story of
in Polybius's words, as the records
Deucalion, or scorching heat, as in the story of Phaethon, men perish, c tell us has already happened and as
reason suggests to us
Egyptian priest says to Solon (i2B-c): There have been, and will be hereafter, many destructions of mankind, the greatest by fire and water,
though other lesser ones are due to countless other causes/ Philosophers took these stories seriously. Aristotle believed that the 'socalled flood of Deucalion' actually took place, and hazards the theory that 'just as there is a winter among the yearly seasons, so at fixed intervals in some great period of time there is a great winter and excess
of rains* (Meteor. 352a3o); a theory evidently connected with a Great Year (pp. 282, above and 458, below).
that
of
In Anaximander's cosmogony the earth began by being wet and is gradually drying out, so that the sea is even now continually shrinking
and eventually
1
will
dry up completely
Very probably
TOUTO iraai TO!$ wSapois yiva6ca KarrapdAAav MSS.; ToCrniv . . . prrapoX^v DK; TocOrnv . . . Kccra^oAfjv H. Lloyd-Jones (KR, 177). One might compare Matt. xiii. 35 <5nr6 KarccfioAfis K6oyou, remembering that Hippolytus was a bishop.
iced
Fr. 37 consists of die simple statement: 'And in some caves water drips down.* This has been taken as Xenophanes's own illustration of the transition between earth and water, referring either to the formation of stalactites (water to rock) or to the ooze and dampness so frequently met in caves (earth turning to water). It may well be so, but in the absence of context we can never be
sure,
388
Alternate
Xenophanes owed something to his predecessor here, though there are important differences. Anaximander was speaking of the origin of the
world, and, so far as our evidence goes, there is no trace of a return to the ascendancy of water. 1 Xenophanes is not speaking of the origin or destruction of the cosmos. The cyclical process which he describes is
confined to the earth, and even that is never destroyed. have no details, but it is clear that when the sea has advanced sufficiently to
eliminate
We
and turn the earth to mud, it retreats to allow the reemergence of dry land and of life. No reason is given for this, but the process will have been a repetition on a larger scale of the annual
life
and dry in summer and winter. That Xenophanes believed the cosmos as a whole to be ungenerated and indestructible we have already seen. The alternative, in his time
alternation of wet
and before, was to believe that it took shape at a particular time out of some sort of formless chaos, as described by Hesiod and in more rational terms by the Milesians. Once generated, it might either be
destroyed again (so, in all probability, the Milesians, and certainly a little later the atomists) or last for ever as in Pythagoreanism
With the belief in an everlasting universe, whether generated or not, went normally the idea of a cyclic repetition of history punctuated by disasters. This was the teaching of the Pythagoreans and of Aristotle himself, and evidently also of Xenophanes. The first
(pp. 28 if., above).
attested cyclic
scheme involving repeated destruction and rebirth ofthe whole cosmos occurs later in the fifth century in Empedocles. Anaxi-
absorbed into the apeiron and that later; but there is little positive evidence for
and
it
the central place in his thoughts that the cycle of worlds had in the elaborate philosophico-religious scheme of Empedocles, to which it
was essential. These alternative views, current in the sixth and the destructibility of the cosmos have been briefly
order to
fifth centuries,
of
show how
easily
1 KR remark (p. 178) that the sea was receding round Miletus, but in Sicily was supposed to have engulfed the land-bridge which became the Messina strait. a Some further information about them will be found in Guthrie, In the Beginning, ch. 4.
389
Xenophanes
centuries,
'all
could, of course, at least in earlier Greek, mean only "world arrangements", i.e. of the earth's surface' (KR, 179), but I have little doubt that the bishop was thinking of the formation of new worlds. If so, it
is
was mistaken. 1
Aristotle was emphatic that all the natural philosophers believed the world to have had a beginning in time (De Caelo, 279 b 12), and Xenohis own view that it jphanes must have been the first to anticipate has always existed, coupling it like him with the theory of a cycle of
terrestrial disasters
and the periodic renewal of human life and culture. That being so, it was perhaps unfair of Aristotle to dismiss him as summarily as he does. Yet the actual verses in which these notions were
embodied may well have been highly fanciful and lacking in anything that Aristotle would recognize as serious philosophical argument.
(10)
The doxographers
offer
meteorological theories of Xenophanes, which however is for several reasons less worthy of attention than the topics already treated. For
one thing,
practically
none of
it is
supported
by
poet, so that its reliability is difficult to check, and the language of the reporters does not always inspire confidence. Where Aetius does
quote a few words (A46), it has been argued that they contradict his 2 Moreover, some of the views described are interpretation of them. simply taken over from the Milesians and others are rather nonsensical. If correctly reported, they suggest that Xenophanes did not take these
matters very seriously, but was probably chiefly concerned to ridicule religious notions of the heavenly bodies.
In general terms, the view expressed is that all the heavenly bodies, * as well as meteors and rainbows, are in fact luminous (or fiery') clouds, that clouds are formed by evaporation from the sea, and that
therefore
1
all
these heavenly
phenomena
originate
f.
from the
level
of the
6) thinks
differently.
390
of Clouds
far distant
from
it.
them up
Aet. in, 4, 4
(A 46):
Xenophanes says
regions
is
of what happens in the upper drawn up from the sea and the
sweet part owing to its fine texture is separated out and being thickened into a mist forms the clouds and by compression (lit. 'felting') causes dripping showers and by vaporization makes winds.* For he says explicitly: *Sea is
the source of water/
The most
direct quotation
noticeable feature of this passage is the meagreness of the on which the whole construction is apparently based.
the importance of the sea some actual verses have survived, though unfortunately mutilated in parts (fr. 30). They are quoted by
On
a scholiast on the lines in the Iliad (xxi, 1 96) which characterize Oceanus
as the source of
wind and Anaximenes (pp. 105, 121, above), and the further step of regarding sun, moon and the other heavenly bodies as fires produced from cloud seems to rely particularly on Anaximenes. In his view, as reported by Hippolytus (DK, 13 Ay), air 'when dispersed more finely becomes fire. Winds on the other hand are air in process of condensation, and from
is produced by "felting". The continuation of this process water. . . / In the direction of rarefaction this same process produces in accounts Xenophanes for the production from water of wind, cloud
and they rivers, sea, springs and wells the source not only of rivers but also of rain, and clouds. This does no more than repeat ideas of Anaximander
all
water
is
air
cloud
and fire. Anaximenes had also taught that the heavenly bodies originated from the earth, when moisture rising from it was rarefied and became fire (A6 and 7, quoted on pp. 133 , above).
His reported views on die sun are that
it
consists
of a collection of
translation)
many
1
small
(iffr
'firelets' (m/pi8icc:
'sparks'
Stc
9* fjAlov druiSos).
Why Diogenes wrote of vapour from the sun, rather than drawn
would be hard
to say. Heidel wished to alter the text; see
sun,
it
ZN,
With
Siomxtseiv
T<Jc
irvstoarra c
early philosophers :
T<b
irpoorov
Oyp6v .
Arist. Meteor. 353 byE, describing the views of unnamed . . Cmr6 TOU f|X(ou ripaiv6pvov T6 \v Siorrjiiaocv nvEtiiwrroc . . .
06Aorrrav;
elvcxi.
391
Xenophanes
and
same time of cloud. The two descriptions were not thought source. The testicontradictory, for they occur together in the same
at the
'He says
() Hippol. Ref, i, 14, 3 (A33): 'The sun comes into being daily from small sparks collected together.' * the sun consists of ignited (c) Aet. ii, 20, 3 (A4o): Xenophanes says that
clouds. Theophrastus in his Physics wrote that it consists of sparks collected from the damp exhalation and composing [lit. collecting or assembling] the
sun/
held that by a following Anaximenes, Xenophanes evidently was water continuation of the same process whereby vaporized into cloud, clouds in their turn could ignite and turn to fire. Why these
Still
into many little fires, which particular clouds should be disintegrated 1 have to be 'assembled' to form the sun, is not explained. In this
that the
account sun and clouds seem to be mutually dependent, which, seeing world had no beginning, is not unreasonable. The stars have
the same composition (A 32). They are made of ignited clouds, and like the sun are renewed daily: "being daily quenched they rekindle at
night like embers; their risings and settings are ignition and quenching' (Aet. n, 13, 14, A38). The moon also is cloud 'felted'; it has its own
light,
2 put out each month as it wanes. The same composition is asserted for comets and shooting stars: they are accumulations or movements of ignited clouds, and the phenomenon
this light is
known
clouds glimmering in virtue of the kind of motion that they have'. Lightning occurs 'when clouds are made bright by the movement'. 3 On the rainbow, alone of celestial phenomena, we have two lines of the poet himself, which bear out
as St
Elmo's
fire is 'little
(fr.
32):
2
3
Possibly to account for the tiny, sparklike appearance of the stars. Aet. n, 25, 4, etc. (A43). The word iremAriu&ov recalls Anaximenes again.
2,
u,
n, 18,
x,
m,
3, 6).
392
Celestial
Since
Iris,
Phenomena
besides being the rainbow, was a fully anthropomorphic goddess, messenger to the other gods, the familiar motive of dis1 crediting traditional religion is probably at work. Xenophanes is credited with other beliefs about the heavenly bodies which are strange indeed and scarcely comprehensible. In the absence
of the original writings it is practically impossible to judge them. Since the sun is a kind of cloud-formation amassed each morning out of
water-vapour and then catching fire, only to die out at night, it is natural (as we are told more than once) that there should be an infinite number of suns. One would suppose them to succeed one another in
time, but
what
is
9,
^41 a)?
Xenophanes says there are many suns and moons corresponding to the 3 3 regions, sections and zones of the earth, and at a certain time the disc is banished to a section of the earth not inhabited by us, and so stepping into a
hole, as the sun
it
phenomenon of an
4
eclipse.
He
moves forward
indefinitely,
but seems to go in a
circle
because of
the distance.
1
Probably. But
personification,
it is
Ipis in Homer more than once means the rainbow without any hint of and the quotation from Xenophanes occurs in a scholiast on IL xi, 27 in which
on Agamemnon's
IL xvii, 547 and 551, where Athena is said to have descended from heaven like a purple rainbow which Zeus 'stretches out* (no personification here), and simultaneously described as covering herself in a purple cloud. As with the role of Ocean as source of all other waters, Xenophanes in matters which were not of prime concern to him may have owed sometoncdTss. Cf. also
his
was not bothering head very much. Anaximenes could certainly have taught Kfrn. a more sophisticated explanation of the rainbow, as we know from several sources, the fullest being a scholiast on Aratus (DK, 13.08, going back through Posidonius to Theophrastus: see Diels, Dox. 231): *Anaximenes says that the rainbow is produced when the beams of the sun fall on thick close-packed aer (air, mist, or cloud; Aetius calls it v&pos and adds the epithet 'black'). Hence the anterior part of it seems red, being burned by the sun's rays, while the other part is dark, owing to the predominance of moisture.' This can certainly be summed up by calling the rainbow a coloured cloud, but so far as is known the causal detail was omitted by Xenophanes. 3 Besides the general confusion, this anachronistic reference to kMncrra and joovoa of the earth gives further ground for suspecting these sentences as a report of Xenophanes's belief. Those divisions were only possible when the sphericity of the earth had been established, and were probably not made before Eudoxus in the fourth century. See J. O. Thomson, Hist, of Anc* Geog. 116. (xAfuara 'expresses the fact that a place is warmed by the sun according to the "inclination" of its horizon to the earth's axis'.) Frankel explains the passage by the nearness of sun and moon to the earth (Dicht. u. Phtt. 43i): 'Die Sonne- und Mondbahn legte er so nah an unsere Erde heran, dass er fur die verschiedenen Erdzonen besondere Sonnen und Monde annehmen musste.* 3 Presumably of the suns, though for all we are told it might equally well be of the moons. 4 els <Jnrapov. Not *to infinity', for it burns out each night.
impression
The
393
Xenophanes
In another passage (n, 24, 4, A4i) Aetius has classified under eclipses a statement of Xenophanes which must have referred to the sun's daily in this one, but there is little setting. There may be similar confusion
1 hope of straightening it out. On the other hand, the final sentence about the sun's movement is interesting as evidence of observation and of a power to reason from appearances rather than simply accepting them at their face value: objects or creatures travelling through the air in a straight line do appear to descend in the sky as they recede. Here
is developed in already is a hint of that distrust of the senses which Heraclitus and reaches its climax when Parmenides denies outright that the senses can ever bring mankind into contact with reality.
lines
of Xenophanes:
At our
feet
It is therefore
those
who
unnecessary to consider the paraphrases of Aristotle and followed him. The compatibility of this statement with a
2
spherical universe has already been noted, and the only other point of interest is that the lines are obviously describing a flat-topped, not a
spherical earth.
*It seems probable that the plurality of suns and moons is simply due to their being renewed each day; that Xenophanes explained eclipses as caused by the sun withdrawing to another region of the earth; and that the two ideas became confused* (KR, i?4f.)- See the rest of this paragraph
1
in
KR for further suggestions about this obscure passage and the possible
by Xenophanes.
'fantasy
and humour*
displayed
It
mankind
sounds nonsensical to say that when the sun comes to a part of the earth not inhabited by it therefore (wd oOrco?) steps into a hole (lit. 'treads on emptiness') and goes out. Tannery, whom Heath follows (Arutarchus^ 56), said briefly that it is *un singulier emploi du principe de finalit" (Pour V'fust, de la sc. hell. 137). Presumably (though he does not say so) he connected it with Aet. n, 30, 8 (A42): "The sun is useful in generating the cosmos and the living creatures in it, but the moon is redundant.*
*
P. 381, n. i, above. The passage is referred to by Aristode, De Caek, 294*21. For this and the doxography see DK, A47, 32, 33. Simplicius, confessing honesdy that he has not seen the relevant lines, feels a doubt whether Xenophanes meant to say (a) that the earth is genuinely at rest because its own lower parts extend indefinitely, or () that the space beneath the earth extends indefinitely, and therefore, though it appears to be at rest, it is unceasingly moving downwards.
Once
this strange
tKvelToa)
doubt had entered his mind, the phrase would hardly have set it at rest.
in
Xenophanes himself
(els
drreipov
394
famous in antiquity
Certain truth has no
(fr.
34) r
man seen, nor will there ever be a man who knows immediate experience] about the gods and about everything of which [from 4 I speak; 3 for even if he should fully succeed in saying what is true, even so he
11
5
it,
but in
all
things there
is
opinion.
The Sceptics of the fourth century B.C. and later seized eagerly on these lines as an anticipation of their view that knowledge was unSextus mentions two current interpretations. First (Math. vn, 49ff.)> Xenophanes was thought to mean that everything is in6 comprehensible (TTOCVTOC ocKOcrdAriTrra) : nobody knows the truth, for
attainable.
even
if
he should
hit
upon
it
by chance, he
still
does not
know that he
hands
has hit
upon
it.
containing
many
Some
will lay
So it, but they will have no means of confirming their discovery. with philosophers searching for truth the one who lights on it may
To our knowledge they were quoted in whole or in part by Sextus Empiiicus four times (Adv. Math, vii, 49 and no, vm, 326; Pyrrh. Hyp. 11, 18); also by Plutarch (Aud. Poet. lyE), Galen, Proclus, Diogenes Laertius, Epiphanius and Origen (full references in Karsten, Xen. Reftqii. 1830, 51). H. Frankel analyses them in detail in Hermes, 1925, 18492,. The Greek text
as given
1
on
by
DK is:
Kcd T&
iiisV
o\3v aowp^s
oOn$
fkrrcci
d
2
yctp Kod TCI nctfaarra Tfyoi TsreXEap&ov elmov, olSe, 86x05 8" kid iraai TTVKTCXI.
cit.
immediately followed by diwpl eoov, the continuation is probably xcd irepl * -irdvrcav&aaot Ayco. Grammatically of course il6cb$ could take dcraa as direct object: knowing. . . all that I say about everything*. 4 TETE\EOVVOV, a typically Homeric word. 5 The contrast is between olSe and 66x0$: no knowledge but only seeming or opinion. This
*
seeming*
later
may be close to
(i.e.
the truth, or
assumed
it may not. The sense is unlikely to be what the Sceptics know when he is speaking the truth and when he is not*), but
simply that though he may hit upon the truth his conviction cannot be absolutely certain, though he may have good grounds for believing that his opinion is near the truth. The Sceptics* version makes Xenophanes anticipate the sophistic dilemma posed in Plato*s Meno (80 D): *How will you look for something when you don*t know what it is? Even if you come right up against it, how will you know that what you have found is the thing you didn't know?* 6 According to D.L. ix, 20, this was in particular the interpretation of Sorion.
395
Xenophanes
well not believe his luck. Secondly (ch. no), Sextus speaks of 'those him differently'. They claim that he is not abolishing all who
expound
comprehension
and every criterion, but substituting The possibility of opinion for knowledge as a criterion of judgment. error cannot be dismissed, but it is right to accept what is probable*
(KcrrocArjvpiv)
There
pretation
is little is
less
first depends had acquired a different shade of which words of certain understanding 1 between meaning by the time they were quoted. Yet the difference them is only one of emphasis. His observation of the widely differing to the conclusion that none of beliefs of mankind had led
Xenophanes he puts forward what he personally feels is the truth, yet in all modesty and honesty he must confess that as all men are fallible, so may he be. He firmly believes in his one god,
their place
whole, eternal, unchanging, non-anthropomorphic; but he cannot claim to have reached the complete and certain truth. This position he states in an isolated line which Plutarch quotes: 'Let these things be
believed (or opined) as resembling the truth.'* Later writers supply the information that the four lines of
fr.
34
God give the first half of an antithesis: men can only surmise, but knows the truth.3 When Alcmaeon made the same distinction between
human conjecture and
divine certainty (fr. i, p. 344, above), his words are sometimes interpreted as distinguishing between the subject-matter of the two. There certainly seems to be, in the probably corrupt text,
5
and
See H. Frankel,&cc. cwt.and the contemporaryand earlierparaUels which he quotes: e.g in line 2 is closely connected with TSev in line r, and its meaning still closer to *see for oneself* tiaan to 'know*. It means to be acquainted with something from personal experience or investigation,
ehrev.
from which Frankel concludes that ol5e in line 4 cannot mean oTSEv 6n im&gau&ov Again, by T0xoi...ehrc!>v Xenophanes probably meant 'succeeds in saying', without intending to introduce any notion of chance. * Fr. 35. The mood of SeSofdoflco is due to Wilamowitz: 86Sodo6ai PluL, SsSofaarai Karsten,
The
(Th.
3
perhaps deliberately aimed at Hesiod, whose frrvrpcHcnv 6uola are in fact vysuS&x used in Plutarch to encourage a bashful speaker. (a) Arius Did. op. Stob. EcL n, I, 17 (DK, A 24) : 3L. . .-tf\v aOrou irapioT&rros etrA(5cpei<w, 65
line is
2,7).
It is
4pa
6e6s
uv
otSe
-rfiv
more probably
neuter).
() Varro
op.
Aug.
Cm
(presumably taking Traai as masc.: it is Dei, vn, 17: scribam. . .ut Xenophanes
Colophonius scripsit. . .hominis est enim haec opinari, Dei scire. The dichotomy which Frankel introduces into these passages ('aber Gott hat ein echtes Wissen auch von den transzendenten Dingen*, loc. ch. 190) is not in the originals.
extends the realm of seeming to the gods and everything ofwhkh I speak . It is true that Sextus introduces the distinction into his paraphrase of the
fragment/ but it was a familiar one to the Sceptics who had adopted Xenophanes, and his witness on the point has no weight. Perhaps the strongest evidence in favour of this division between the objects of
divine and
human knowledge
it
is
the line
(fr.
36):
As many
is
things as
Though
the context
lost, it
seems
so experienced by mortals. It has been accepted as evidence that Xenophanes drew a distinction between direct sensible experience, which
gives certainty, and other objects of cognition about which none can be certain save God. These would include theology itself, and perhaps
view of 'everything of which I speak in fr. 34) all theory, speculation or inference; e.g. one might suppose that the visible presence of fossils in certain localities was something 'known*, but
also (in
the theory of wet and dry eras which Xenophanes himself based it was for a human being only opinion.
upon
Yet one cannot say with confidence, as Frankel does, that Xenophanes 'separates cleanly and fundamentally from one another* the
Earthly,
still
less that
he regarded
empirical data, If what he said about the path of the sun has been correctly reported, he was one of the first to suggest that the sense of sight may be deceptive.
1
The
optical illusion to
which he
T6 ye
by FrankeL See MatL vii, 51 : T& pfcv oiJv <5ftTjtes Similarly in vm, 325 ff. he contrasts T6 -rrpdSiiXov and T6 &6TjXov. Deichgraber (Kk. Mus. 1938, 20) takes lie opposite view to that taken here. * For daopdoerOcci as covering the whole field of personal experience and investigation see Frankel, he. clt. 186.
in this connexion
Frankel adduces
(loc*
clusion, that
i.e.
God
bears
no resemblance
at. 191) in favour of this that Xenophanes's own theological conto man, was reached on purely empirical grounds,
fact that different
different
gods in
Surely this gives an improbable twist to his train of thought. On the contrary, the fact that Africans believed in black gods and Thracians in red-haired must have led him to the conclusion that the immediate perceptions of an individual or a limited group of human beings
their
own images.
were likely to lead to error. His own conception of deity can hardly be said to have an empirical basis, yet he regarded it as, to say the least, more probable than those of other men.
397
Xenophanes
notorious straight stick (or oar) appearing bent in water which was made so much of by later writers in their attacks on the truthfulness of
sense-perception. Taking all the evidence together, but relying particularly on the actual fragments, we cannot affirm that Xenophanes posited two realms
of existence, of one of which men could have certain knowledge, and of the other only opinion. He said that men could have no certain
knowledge
truth, but,
at all: that
so,
was reserved
even
God. They may discover the limitations that they can say no more
for
than
mean
of criteria was not equally probable. Such a wholesale abandonment for the man who said to his fellows: "All your conceptions of the godhead are wrong; it is not like that but like this.' We must not take
appearances at their face value, but penetrate as near to the reality behind them as our wits will allow. When we feel that we have reached
truth,
we have won
It
(fr.
35).
was already a commonplace of poetry, expressed in invocations to the Muses and elsewhere, that mankind had no sure knowledge unless 1 the gods chose to reveal it. But Xenophanes was more than a poet,
and may fairly be said to have introduced this antithesis into philosophy. Gone are the all-too-human gods of the poets. God is not like man
either in shape or in mind: he thinks, sees and hears 'as a whole', without the aid of separate bodily organs. This is a product not of poetic imagination, but of rational thought, and its influence on later
*
philosophers
is
plain.
insight,
(fr. 78). Parmenides speaks of 'mortals who know nothing' (6, 4); and when he wishes to discover not only 'the beliefs of mortals in which is no true conviction' but also 'the unshaken heart of truth', he has resort to a goddess as his informant. Empedocles,
of the
and the
closest to
Xenophanes,
is
0eol 5
For further treatment of this topic see Snell, Discovery of the Mind, ch. 7: 'Human knowledge and divine knowledge among the early Greeks/ Among prose-writers, Herodotus puts the sentiment into the mouth of Xerxes (vn, 50, 2) elSfrca 8 &#panrov &VTCX KOOS xp^l *r6 P^cnov;
:
398
life,
Thus these things are not to be seen or heard by men, (2, 7) the mind/ We know nothing truly/ said Democritus nor grasped by
:
and Ecphantus
the Pythagorean,
above), echoed
who was probably under his influence (p. 325, this, we are told, in the form that 'it is not possible to
them
as
lines
on human
cognition, and especially from the last line of fr. 34, which was of tremendous consequence for the development of Greek thought: the
first explicit
confrontation, as
two
seeming.
No
the beginning. The earliest philosophers in Miletus determined the direction of subsequent thought when they first tried to set aside the
seeming variety of the world and reach the true and single nature (pkysis) which underlay it; and as a result this has been the quest of
European philosophy and science ever since. But it is just the explicating of the implicit, the conscious realization of what philosophy has
up to now been trying to do, which makes possible the next step forward. Heraclitus owed something to it, in spite of his belittlement
of his predecessor
(fr.
40),
but above
all it
menides, whose whole doctrine is based on an assertion of the antithesis between knowledge and opinion, truth and seeming; and through Parmenides it had an indirect part in shaping the thought of Plato himself. Plato was not devoid of historical sense when he saw in
Xenophanes the beginning of the Eleatic tradition, however much his casual remark to that effect may have been exaggerated later by less
perceptive writers.
Two more quotations from the poems complete the evidence for his
views on
human knowledge.
Fr. 18 says:
men all things in the beginning, but in course of time, by searching, they
find out better.'
The emphasis on
time, marks this as the first idea of progress in the arts and sciences, a progress dependent
1
personal search, and on the need for statement in extant Greek literature of the
on human
Democr.
fr.
117.
Cf. also
frr.
7-9. Ecphantus,
DK,
51, i.
399
Xenophanes
effort
and not or at least not primarily on divine revelation. It foreshadows the praise of human ingenuity and perseverance in Vinctus of Sophocles's Antigone (332 ff.). Here and in the Prometheus
Aeschylus
tlie
Aeschylus mankind is said to have been taught by Prometheus, whose name means Forethought' and who declares that the first thing he 1 of divine intertaught them was to use their own minds. The fiction vention is becoming transparent, and it may be assumed that Aeschylus was consciously drawing on sources which ascribed scientific and 2 technical progress to human ingenuity alone. This is done openly by
*
Protagoras in the account of the origin and development of human life put into his mouth by Plato. On the very existence of the gods Protagoras declared himself an agnostic, and the account must be 3 supposed to represent the substance of his real views.
Two
classical
*
Greece.
in conflicting views of human development were current The first, that it represented a degeneration from an
Hesiod (Works^ 109 ). These early men were both good in themselves and happy in their circumstances, for nature produced its fruits in abundance with no toil on their part. According to the second, more realistic view the earliest men were ignorant and brutal in character,
and and
at the
all
Gradually learning by bitter experience, they improved both morally in their conditions of life, as one by one the arts of building,
weaving, domestication of animals, agriculture, and above all of combining in communities for mutual protection, were discovered and mastered. This less mythical version rapidly gained ground at the
expense of the other during the
already mentioned, spite of the lack of detail,
1
we
find
fr.
it
fifth century. Besides the authorities in Euripides, Critias and Moschion. In 18 of Xenophanes seems to give the same
<ppevo5v hrr^Xous, line 444. E.g. the account reproduced in Diodorus, I, 8, in which men's only teacher is said to have been 'expediency* (f6 ov^pov). This account probably goes back to pre-atomistic fifth-century
*
thought (p. 69, n. i, above.) 3 Plato, Prot. 320 cff. On the question of its authenticity see Guthrie, In the Beginning, 140, n, 8, and, for an analysis of the account itself, ch. 5 of the same work. Protagoras chooses to put it in the form of a n06o$ as being more agreeable to listen to, but says that it could just as well be explained in a A6yo$, i.e. without the divine apparatus.
400
good reason
for attributing
it
in the first
men would
think figs were much sweeter/ This too is presumably intended to emphasize the limitations of human judgment, but introduces incident-
men's assessment of a particular sensation depends on the sensations which they already happen to have experienced. Here again we have the first hint of an idea which was taken
ally its relative character:
up and developed
below)
satiety,
we
(fr. in, p. 445, call the we health, things only appreciate pleasant in relation to their contraries disease, hunger and
philosophically of contraries
by
was
later writers.
Heraclitus, for
central, noted
weariness. Protagoras generalized the idea in his famous dictum that man is the measure of all things, their existence or non-existence, by
which he meant that each man's sensations are true for him and for no one else.* Since no two men can have precisely the same sensations
and experiences,
logically
this doctrine
it
may
himself.
(12) Conclusion
whom
in the past. Apart from the details of cosmology, which probably interested him only as a stick with which to beat Homeric theology, he definitely points forward rather than
back.
The mistake made by some ancient critics was to accept as fullyfledged doctrines what were no more than pointers, germs brought
to fruition under other hands, and their manifest exaggeration has led to a belitdement of his genuine originality. Regarded as seminal, his
philosophical importance
felt.
1
is great,
and
its
influence
was immediately
He
fr. 6 Nauck. On the idea of progress in classical and 6. 3 am aware that these passages have aroused interminable discussion, but see no reason to doubt that Plato had understood Protagoras correctly. As Lewis Campbell said in his edition of the Theaetetus (p. 37), the repetition of the same language in both passages affords a presumption that the explanation, as well as the original saying, is Protagoras's own.
25
DK, Mosch.
5
401
Xenophanes
theology.
for a stricter notion of unity which excluded the possibility of a generated cosmos, taught of a single god who worked by intellection alone,
and posited an essential connexion between divinity, eternity, reality, and spherical shape. For all this the Eleatics, and Heraclitus as well,
between knowledge and seeming or opinion and the idea that all sensations are relative. Popular thought may have had an inkling of some of these things, but
are
in his debt, as also for the distinction
much
Xenophanes put them in a more philosophical setting and ensured that they were taken seriously. The effect of his conception of knowledge as progressing steadily and gradually from small beginnings, through
men's
of discovery and invention, may be seen in many fifth-century authors, both philosophers and poets. In short, with him philosophy breaks new ground in more than one direction, and sows
own powers
new
seed,
from which a
fruitful
402
VII
HERACLITUS
(i) Difficulties
and policy-
PL discussion of the thought of Heraclitus labours under peculiar difficulties. His own expression of it was generally considered to be
highly obscure, a verdict fully borne out by the surviving fragments. Both in the ancient and the modern worlds he has provided a challenge
to the ingenuity of interpreters
resist.
Perhaps not altogether unfortunately, most of the ancient commentaries have perished, but the amount written on him since the
beginning of the nineteenth century would itself take a very long time to master. Some of these writers have been painstaking scholars, others
philosophers or religious teachers who found in the pregnant and picturesque sayings of Heraclitus a striking anticipation of their own 1 If the interpretations of the latter suffer from their attitude beliefs.
ofparti pris, the former may also be temperamentally at a disadvantage in penetrating the thoughts of a man who had at least as much in him of the prophet and poet as of the philosopher.
army of commentators, no two of whom are in Nor are the doubts confined to the elucidation of a agreement. of writing. Diels-Kranz present 131 passages as fragments given body
There
is,
then, an
full
a matter of lively argument how far they reand how much is paraphrase or addition by words produce the ancient writer in whose works they are found or a previous writer in whom he found them. Given an established fragment, there may remain to be resolved a doubt of its grammatical syntax, before one can
of Heraclitus, but
it is
his actual
is
an inevitable
style,
and was
Justin Martyr included him, with. Socrates, Abraham and others, among those who had lived with the Logos and must be regarded as Christians, and I have personally known a man who claimed to have been converted by reading the fragments. Lenin on the other hand wrote of one * fragment: A very good account of the elements of dialectical materialism* (see G. Thomson,
is
well
known.
403
Heraclitus
noticed as early as Aristotle (Rhet.
i^ybn, quoted below, p. 407). of the fragments in translation needs no difficulty expounding further emphasis: to translate is sometimes to have taken sides already
The
in a disputed question of interpretation. To take account of all previous scholarship, even if possible, would be undesirable here. What will be attempted is a fresh exposition in continuous form, relegating as far as possible to footnotes any necessary references to other opinions. Since any interpretation of this paradoxical thinker must be to some extent a personal one, the footnotes
in this section will
usual,
well advised to read the text through without them, in order to keep track of a necessarily complex situation and seize the general picture
that
is
being drawn.
try to achieve a convincing account out of both fragments and tesumonia^ that is paraphrases, summaries and criticisms of Heraclitus in later writers. I shall not hesitate to quote a testimonium before a fragment bearing on the same point if this leads to a clearer
I shall
actively
contradict any certainly or highly probably attested fragments, they must be discarded in favour of Heraclitus's own words.
others
The common assumption of recent scholars is that philosophers and from Plato onwards, when it is a question of stating their premust be adjudged guilty unless they can prove
their innocence. This assumption, at least for Aristotle and his successors,
on an impressive amount of study of their own outlook and the questions in their minds, which were inevitably different from the habits of mind and problems of earlier and less sophisticated thinkers.
rests
Aristotelian outlook imposed itself and made certain assumptions almost second nature in those who came later. 1 In the case of Heraclitus
The
the further complication that some of his ideas were adopted and remoulded by the Stoics, so that in later sources there is always the possibility of Stoic colouring creeping into what purports to be an
original thought of Heraclitus. While these considerations must
1
we have
is
For
steiner's article in
a clarification of the Peripatetic approach to Heraclitus and Hermes, 1955, is particularly to be recommended.
Jula Kerschen-
404
known
philosophical prejudices
may
or
may not be relevant in a particular instance. The procedure adopted here, and doubtless the results attained, will not commend themselves to all. This need trouble us less when we
consider that no account of Heraclitus yet put forward has universal approval as a faithful reflexion of his mind.
(2) Sources
won
by G.
S.
may
would
may be
added, however,
particular source, the Christian apologist Hippolytus, bishop of Rome in the third century, who is not singled out by Kirk in his
on one
The account of Heraclitus forms a part of his Refutation which he seeks to show that the chief Christian of heresies are in fact resuscitations of pagan systems of thought. At the beginning of Book ix he deals with the opinions of Noetus, who taught
introduction.
all Heresies^ in
identical, the
in the person of the Son ('patripassianism'). This heresy Hippolytus claims to be rooted in the philosophy of Heraclitus, so that his account
of the latter obviously has a particular tendency and purpose. Neverthehe is our richest single source of actual quotations, and his approach was methodical enough. 'My next purpose*, he writes (ix, 8, i, p. 241
less
to expose the erroneous teaching in the beliefs of the Noetians, first explaining the tenets of Heraclitus the Darkj and then demonstrating that the details of their system are Heraclitean/ This two-
Wendland),
*is
Cambridge, 1954: Introd. m, 'The Ancient Evidence on Heraclitus's Thought'. Although body of this book deals in full only with fragments 'describing the world as a whole rather than men in particular', many others are mentioned incidentally, and the introduction on date, life and sources is a model introduction to Heraclitus as a whole. Kirk's book is, within its chosen scope, the most detailed, factual and sober study that has yet appeared, and will be made use of frequently in the succeeding pages.
the main
405
Heraclitus
fold division of his scheme
is
adhered
to,
and
in the course
of the
first
a critic part he gives so many actual quotations that even so cautious as Kirk considers he 'had access to a good compendium, if not to an actual book by Heraclitus' (p. 185, cf. 211). Kirk could not go
he does not believe that Heraclitus himself wrote a book, but the Italian Macchioro argued (more plausibly than he did on many
further, since
and
before him, topics) that Hippolytus had the actual work of Heraclitus that all his quotations are taken from a single chapter or section of it. Macchioro placed considerable reliance on the statement of
Hippolytus
all
his real
mind
at once',
244 Wendland): 'In this section he revealed and claimed that the quotations are full
enough to allow a reconstruction of the all-important chapter referred 1 to. At the least Hippolytus supplies a number of indisputably genuine
statements of Heraclitus, instead of only a second- or third-hand version of Theophrastus's epitome filtered through a Stoic mesh;
and even
them,
it
if
is
Stoicism and Christianity enter into his interpretation of based on these texts which he has been conscientious
enough
(3)
It is
Writings
not even agreed that Heraclitus wrote a book at all. Such a book is indeed referred to in antiquity from Aristotle onwards,* but some have guessed
sayings, writes (p. 7) :
it
to be
made perhaps
I hazard the conjecture that Heraclitus wrote no book, in our sense of the word. The fragments, or many of them, have the appearance of being isolated statements, or yvcojjicci: many of the connecting particles they contain
V. Macchioro, Eraclito, ctu i (see, however, Kirk, 349-51, i84f.). W. Kranz also emphasizes Hippolytus's accuracy in citation, and agrees that *ganz ohne Zweifel benutzt er hier. . . eine vollstandige Heraklitausgabe* (Philologus^ 1958,
are ovyypcwct (first in Axist. Rhet. 1407 bi 6) and pipAfov. Examples: 'He grew up haughty and supercilious, as his book itself shows*; ix, 5 'The book of ix, his which is in circulation (T6 ^spdiievov ccCrroO ptpxiov: perhaps only "the book which circulates as his") is from its general subject-matter a work on nature, but has been divided into three parts*.
3
2<j2.L).
DJL
The parts are then named, and conform to a Stoic classification, and there follows the story that he deposited the book in the temple of Artemis; ix, 15 *The commentators on his book are numerous*.
406
His Book
belong to
later sources.
In or perhaps shortly after Heraclitus's lifetime a was made, conceivably by a pupil. This was the
'book': originally Heraclitus's utterances had been oral, into an easily memorable form.
This
is
ckwigen %u Heraklit, 8) argued that the carefully composed fr. i must from its style have been the prooemium of a formal (redigienen) book,
on which Kirk comments (p. 45) It is the longest continuous piece of Heraclitus's prose which we possess, and Gigon may be justified. against the opinion of Diels and others that the "book" was simply a
:
view.'
collection of yvcouoci or aphorisms. Nevertheless, I incline to Diels's The fact that many ancient authors wrote commentaries on
work leaves Kirk unmoved, since, as he points out with the lack of anything but a random collection of sayings attrijustice, buted to him has in no way deterred modern scholars from doing the
Heraclitus's
same thing. Many have taken the opposite view. K. Deichgraber wrote (PJalologus, 1938/9,20):
Regenbogen (Gnomon, 1955, 310) says that both Plato and Aristotle had the whole book of Heraclitus in their hands. Mondolfo (Phronesis,
1958, 75), after quoting Cherniss, a highly critical scholar, for the * statement that Aristotle had the books of [the Presocratics] presum-
ably in their complete form', goes on to say that 'where Heraclitus is concerned, Aristotle himself declares his full and direct knowledge of
the text'.
Roberts as follows:
It is
a general rule that a written composition should be easy to read and therefore easy to deliver. This cannot be so where there are many connecting
clauses, or
words or
clitus.
To
where punctuation is hard, as in the writings of Herapunctuate Heraclitus is no easy task, because we often cannot tell
407
Heraclitus
whether a particular word belongs to what precedes or what follows it. Thus at the outset of his book1 he says ---- (There follows fr. i; see
p. 424, below.)
cogent evidence, and even if Kirk can write (p. 7) : Of course it cannot be proved that Heraclitus wrote a book, or that he did not',
This
is
the onus must, in face of a passage like maintain that he did not.
(4)
this, rest
The absolute date of Heraclitus of Ephesus is difficult to determine with precision, but, in spite of his dubious methods, Apollodorus may have been approximately correct in estimating that he 'flourished'
(i.e.
was aged
(OL
69
503-500; Apollodorus
will
may
completed by 480, when according to this reckoning he would be in conforms with his mentions of Pythagoras, Hecataeus
and Xenophanes, and the probability that his work was already known to Parmenides, who would be his junior by about twenty-five years.
Some of the language used by Parmenides seems only explicable on the assumption that he is deliberately echoing phrases of Heraclitus in a spirit of criticism. 2
Except perhaps for his membership of the royal clan at Ephesus we know nothing of the externals of his life. All else must be regarded as
apocryphal anecdote arising for the most part out of his sayings.3 Some have thought that the familiar label of the weeping philoso*
The most striking passages are fr. <5, 8~io, fr. 8, 57-8, fr. 4, 3-4. Diels adduced a number of ZN, 685, n.), but some of his comparisons are far-fetched and weaken his case. Though many have argued to the contrary (e.g. Zeller, ZN, 926 with n., Reinhardt, Farm. ijjff., Gigon, 33, Raven, P. andE. 2$), I find it impossible to deny that there is an intentional
other fragments (see
one of these passages. See especially G. Vlastos, AJP% 1955, 341, and Kranz, Hermes, 1934, i ryf. Kirk's views are on pp. 2, 21 1. Among nineteenth-century commentators Bernays, Schuster, Steinhart and Patin considered that fr. 6 was aimed at Heraclitus,
allusion to Heraditus in at least
n. 1 1,
(EGP, 130). The controversy to date is summarized by Nestle, ZN, 684, n. i, 688, n. See further N. B. Booth, Phronesis, 1957, 93 , and most recently G. E. L. Owen, 1960, 84, n. i. The question will be dealt with more fully in the next volume in connexion with Parmenides, but in any case no one now believes Reinhardt*s contention that Parmenides was the
as also did Burnet
CQ
earlier.
3
D.L.
ix, 3-5.
The
by Kirk,
3ff.
408
'melancholy but rather 'impulsiveness*. Yet this seems an improbably slender foundation for the story so well known in later antiquity which
couples his name with Democritus, saying that whereas the one wept, the other laughed at the follies of mankind. 1 Strabo (xiv, 632) tells the legend that Ephesus was founded by Androclus son of Codrus the King of Athens. Hence it became the centre of the Ionian kingdom, and in Strabo's own time the family
supposed to be of this royal descent were still called kings and entitled to certain privileges, in part religious. Heraclitus was of this family, * and presumably its head, since he was entitled to the kingdom *, but
ceded
to his brother out of pride. 2 (and, unlike other stories about him,
it
it
invention),
it sets the tone for all that we know about his character, the evidence of his own writings: an aristocrat of the highest including rank and ancient lineage, whose pride was so exceptional that he saw no value in the privileges bestowed by his own people, for whom he
had a
run of mankind
everywhere.
An
when he was
found playing dice with the children, and the citizens asked him why, he replied: 'Why are you surprised, you good-for-nothings? Isn't
this better
than playing politics with you? (D.L. ix, 3). Such anecdotes do no more than indicate his reputation, but he himself declared
*
(fr.
49)
him
to fury.
obey the counsel of one.' Equalitarian ideas roused 'Every grown man of the Ephesians', he said, 'should
hang himself, and leave the city to the boys; for they banished Hermodorus, the best man among them, saying, "Let no one of us excel, or if he does, be it elsewhere and among others' Y3 Again: 'Insolence
c
EN, H5ob25
1
3
of Heraclitus, Theophr. ap. D.L. ix, 6. See also Kirk, 8, quoting Aristotle, for the meaning of pi\ayxoA{cc. References to the weeping Heraclitus and the
e.g. in the TT. 6pyfjs
De
Tranqu. xv,
2,
of Sotion (the teacher of Seneca, quoted in Stob. Juv. x, 28 ff. See also Lucian, Vit. Auct. 14.
Antisthenes of Rhodes (second century B.C.), Successions, quoted by D.L. ix, 6. Fr. 121, attested by a number of ancient writers: Strabo, Cicero, Diogenes. This Hermodorus is said to have gone to Rome and assisted in drawing up the laws of the Twelve Tables
(Burnet,
EGP,
131, n. i).
409
Heraclitus
must be quelled more promptly than a conflagration' (fr. 43). His consame as that of Theognis, ception of hylru must have been much the
the lower orders to keep their proper station. right-minded people will defend the law as they would their city's walls (fr. 44), that law which is the counsel of one man. This follows
namely a
failure
by
are derived from inevitably from a higher principle, for all human laws themselves show the one divine law (fr. 1 14), and few men capable of views were clearly the reverse of that. His
understanding
political
democratic, and though his character was highly complex it is not out of place to begin by emphasizing his austere aloofness from his fellow-
men.
(5)
His reputation for obscurity was practically universal throughout couched in antiquity. He delighted in paradox and isolated aphorisms,
metaphorical or symbolic terms. This love of paradox and puzzle, without the genius, was inherited by a school of followers, and Plato
has an amusing account of their exaggerations of their master's idiosyncrasies. Socrates has remarked that the doctrine that everything is
in continuous motion has led to considerable controversy.
agrees, and adds:
it is actually growing in violence. The followers (iroclpoi) of There Heraclitus lead the quire of this persuasion with the greatest vigour is no discussing these principles of Heraclitus or, as you say, of Homer or
Theodoras
In Ionia indeed
still
more
ancient sages
who
profess to be
them; you might as well talk to a maniac. Faithful to their own treatises, they are literally in perpetual motion; their capacity for staying still to attend to an argument or a question . .amounts to less than nothing
familiar with
.
put a question, they pluck from their quiver little oracular aphorisms to let fly at you; and if you try to obtain some account of their meaning, you will be instantly transfixed by another, barbed with some newly
forged metaphor. . . There is no such thing as a master or pupil among them. . .Each one gets his inspiration wherever he can, and not one of them thinks that another understands anything. 3
.
When you
in
Socrates has humorously suggested that the doctrine of universal flux has an early champion that he made the water-gods Oceanus and Tethys the origin of all
it is
things. This does not affect the seriousness with which, as a philosophical doctrine, ascribed to Heraclitus and his followers,
*
here
Theaet.
i^vfL,
trans.
Comfbrd. As
Zeller says
is
(ZN, 936f.): *Heraclitus*s school conour witness that at the beginning of the fourth
4IO
Dark
This
to be
is
caricature,
but in
many
they were only aping their was style already remarked on by Aristotle (p. 407, above), and a sentence of Diogenes which can safely be referred to Theophrastus says, after mentioning some of his beliefs: But he sets out nothing clearly.' * In later antiquity this obscurity became proverbial. The title of 'the Riddler' was bestowed on him by Timon of Phlius early in the third century B.C., and another favourite epithet was 'the Dark'. 2 To Lucretius (i, 639) he was 'clams ob obscuram linguam', and Plotinus complained (Enn. iv, 8, p. 468): 'He seems to
self-inspired)
leader.
The
obscurity of his
speak in similes, careless of making his meaning clear, perhaps because in his view we ought to seek within ourselves as he himself had successfully sought' (cf.
Certainly in reading the fragments one is sometimes tempted to agree with the Cotta of Cicero's dialogue that he hid his meaning intentionally, and even to follow his advice and
fr.
101).
intelligi
noluit,
omittamus'
(N.D.
i,
which impressed
But there is another side to the picture, not at least one of the ancients.
In Diogenes ix, 7 we find: 'Occasionally in his treatise he fires off 3 something of brilliant clarity, such that even the dullest can easily
grasp and experience an elevation of spirit; and the brevity and weight ' of his expression are incomparable.' As he said himself (fr. 22) : Those
who
seek gold dig much earth and find a little.' The gold is there for the persevering, even though we may occasionally sympathize with the feelings ascribed to Socrates in a doubtless apocryphal story (DX. n,
enjoyed a considerable vogue in Ionia, and especially at Ephesus.* Wettmann agrees though his added qualification is probably wise: *But we hear nothing of any pupil worthily representing or developing the master's system.' Indeed Plato's satirical remarks suggest that they were all most wnworthy followers, but there is nothing in them to suggest that his references to a Heraclitean sect at Ephesus were not intended to be taken literally at aU, as
century
it
(RE,
viii, 507),
Kirk believes
1
(p. 14).
Since this corresponds both to the universal verdict of antiquity and to the impression made * by the extant fragments, there seems no reason at all why Kirk should take this to mean primarily
that Theophrastus's sources
*
odviKTTjs
Timon
op.
were inadequate* (p. 27). D.L. rx, 6; cn<oTEiv6s e.g. Strabo, xrv,
25, p. 642. *H. 6 OK. KotXoOyiEvos, 15 If. cognomento qui OK. perki-
[ArJ
letury quia de natura ntmzs obscure memoravit. 3 fecpdXAsu Cf. tKpdAAovm in Plato, Theaet. i8oB. In
leled, significantly
modern times this praise has been paral* enough, by Nietzsche: Wahrschemlich hat nie ein Mensch heller und leuchtender geschrieben* (quoted by G. Burckhardt, HerakKt, n.d., p. 15).
411
Heraclitus
Asked by Euripides what he thought of Heraclitus's book, he no doubt also what I didn't replied: What I understood was fine, and
22).
*
needs a diver to get to the bottom of it/ Conformably with this, he was thought to have held the great his own majority of mankind in contempt. This is borne out by
understand; but
it
Other men are unaware of what they do while awake, just as they what they do when asleep. Fr. 17. Many do not understand such things, indeed all who come upon them, nor do they mark them though they have learned them; but they seem 1 to themselves to do so. Fr. 19. Rebuking some for their unbelief, Heraclitus says: Knowing
Fr.
i.
forget
neither
how
to hear nor
how
Fr. 29.
The
best renounce
all
But most
men
stuff
them-
Fools
when they
The saying
*
describes
mankind to be children's a the reminiscence of story quoted on p. 409, above, or playthings'. (Perhaps
conceivably
Fr. 104.
its
them: though present they are absent. Fr. 70. Heraclitus adjudged the opinions of
origin.)
What
sense or
their trust in
popular
2
mob
most men
are bad,
Frr. 2, 56, 72
and 87
may also be
compared.
Much
Wise Men*
(see
Stok
Eel.
m,
i,
DK, i,
p. 65).
In
fr.
39 he speaks of Bias in
complimentary terms.
412
contests
One or two further fragments sound similar, but in the light of others can be seen to be more probably an illustration of a different side of Heraclitus : his religious sense of the worthlessness of human knowledge
Such is fr. 28 (text as emended by Diels): 'The knowledge of the most famous of men is but opinion/ This must be read in the light of fragments like these:
in comparison with divine.
78. 79.
83.
Human nature has no insight, but divine nature has it. Man is infantile in the eyes of a god, as a child in the eyes of a man.
Compared with God,
all else.
beauty and
102.
To God all things are fair and good and just, but men have assumed
The
it is
something that is there for all men to grasp common*), yet most men are too stupid to see it,
is
him
had their own 'private' wisdom (fr. 2). It is not for demean himself by using language that fools can understand, nor could the truth be so expressed. He that hath ears to hear, let him
and
live as if they
to
hear. 2
A second reason for obscurity will appear in due course, namely that
the content of his thought was itself of a subtlety exceeding that of his contemporaries, so that the language of his time was bound to be
inadequate.
Nor can
it
be doubted,
thirdly, that
which
leads naturally to
1 Hesiod made Hemera daughter of Nyx (Theog. 124). The criticism of Hesiod in fr. 106 be a distorted version of this (Kirk, 157-9). * Clement (Strom, v, 14, p. 718) actually compares fr. 34 with this saying of Jesus.
may
413
Heraclitus
a prophetic rather than a dialectical
it is
without contempt is the Sibyl, for 5 1 all her 'raving mouth' and 'mirthless and unadorned phrases (fir. 92). More interesting is what he says of the Delphic Apollo (fr. 93): 'The
the oracle at Delphi neither speaks nor hides his meaning but indicates it by a sign/ That is, it is a feature of the oracular
style to suggest a thing
whom
by an image
rather than
name
it
outright.
We
may recall the response given to the Spartans about 'a place where two winds blow by the force of necessity, and there is blow countering
blow, and woe
(Hdt.
i,
lies
on woe*
in other
61). Equally characteristic is the deliberately ambiguous stateof which the most famous example is the reply given to Croesus ment, that he would destroy a great empire. Just this imagery and double
Heraclitus's own style, and he was evidently oracle's the example.* Many things in the fragments suggest following the religious rather than the philosophic teacher, for instance his
combination of pride and humility. He has seen the truth as no man before, yet he is only its vehicle: 'Listen not to me but to the Logos'
(fr. 5 o).3
he obviously regarded as
In spite of his condemnation of poets, whose claims to inspiration false, he was convinced that he had an inward
(fr.
inspiration of his own. 'I searched myself is his boast Pindar contrasts favourably the knowledge which comes
101),
and
from a man's
is
acquired
by learning
(the 'polymathy'
Exactly
be sure; but c
oOv 0cp,
*
15, p.
&XA&
etc.
The parallel between Heraclitus*s style and that of the oracle is developed by U. Holscher in 'Festschrift Reinhardt', jz. B. Snell, Hermes, 1926, p. 372 brings into connexion with it the story that Heraclitus told about Homer (fr. 56, related p. 443, n. 2, below). Its religious significance
3
is
To
well brought out by P. Merlan in Proc. 2 ith Int. Congress of Philosophy, vol. XII, 56-60. this extent one must modify the interpretation by Gigon of fr. 28. He would explain it
fr. i (p. 344, above) or Xenophanes, fr. 34, as *an expression knowledge*. When Heraclitus belittles human knowledge in comparison with divine, one cannot, in the light of other fragments, suppose that he would always include his own. To one who looks upon himself as ^.prophetes there is no inconsistency in this. Jesus, who could say 'He that hath seen me hath seen the Father*, would at another time say "The words that I speak, I speak not of myself*.
(p. 128) in
of wise
self-limitation in
414
Prophetic Character
be understood by theprofanL We cannot and should not expect such a man to have the rationalistic outlook of the Milesians.
blind to the inner significance thing around them. 'The many' are aware of these things through the
men is the same. They are both of their own nature and of everyagainst
all
senses, but cannot interpret them. To the passages already quoted may be added fr. 107: 'Eyes and ears are bad witnesses to men if they have
souls that understand not the language.' 2 Philosophers and poets are worse, for they have amassed knowledge and still do not understand.
significance,
wisdom
seems to have been a popular one. There is a line of Archilochus which has a proverbial ring, and indeed is quoted as a proverb and attributed to others as well: 'The fox has many tricks but the hedgehog one big
one. In a similar vein Aeschylus wrote: 'Not he
9
things
is
wise, but he
profitable.'^
place the thought of Heraclitus in the philosophical succession, seeing it as determined by the influence of this one or that among the other Presocratics. Thus K. Reinhardt thought it an attempt
the
Find.
OL n, 836. Pindar's metaphor of arrows in his quiver is the same as that used by Plato
(i.e.
man utters, but since he does not know Greek can attach no meaning to
3
poppdpouj vfuxds gxovcnv. The&zr&x/w is onewho hearsthe sounds that a civilized them.
fr.
Greek)
Archil
103
D.
fr.
390 N.
415
Heraclitus
of Xenophanes. 1 Neither attempt has met with much approval. Heraclitus wrote before Parmenides, whose poem
key In the
direct influence
almost certainly contains a slighting reference to him (p. 408, above). The statement quoted by Diogenes (ix, 5) from Sotion, that 'some
disciple
of Xenophanes',
he mentions Xenophanes it is Gigon be said to have made out a strong general case on internal evidence. More recently G. Vlastos (AJP^ 1955, 354ff.) has propounded the thesis that to understand him we must link his thought
with that of the Milesians Anaximander and Anaxinienes.
of no value, 2 and when in a highly critical vein (fr. 40); nor can
is
But no
attempt to link Heraclitus directly and positively with his predecessors has much chance of success. In all probability he was a far more isolated thinker than such attempts presuppose. To be so was at any
rate his intention,
is
borne out by his own statements^ his universal contempt for his fellow-men, both philosophers and others, and the highly individual character of his thought.
(8) Philosophical methods: self-search
So Heraclitus preached his message, which he regarded as an eternal truth, from a pinnacle of self-sought isolation. *He was no man's disciple/ writes Diogenes (ix, 5), 'but said that he had searched himself
and learned everything from himself.' We have now some conception of the two great schools of thought which were started in the sixth
century, Ionian and Italian, and the contrast of inspiration and tendency which they present. Later systems can often be best understood in
relation to these two, either as developments of one or the other, as attempts to combine them, or again as reactions against them. It is as
is
primarily to be explained, if
Reinbardt, Parm&udes, 155*!".; Gigon, Unters* %u H. 1935. See review of the latter by W. Broecker in Gnomon, 1937, 530 ff. Reinhardt has been criticized by many, including Gigon
himself!
3 3
'Offenbar schief',
ZN,
To fr.
101
787, n.; 'not probable', Bumet, EGP, 131. See also Kirk, p. 6. 74, not to act 'like children of our parents*. This is
in Heraclitus's Delphic manner, 'not speaking out but indicating by a sign', and Marcus Aurelius, who quotes the phrase (rv, 46, note to Bywater's fr. 5), was no doubt right in interpreting it to
signify 'following tradition*. Snell also (Hermes, 1926, 358) takes the injunction to be that one own experience, not on tradition or what one has taken over from others.
416
I Searched Myself*
it is explicable in the light of his predecessors at all. Acquainted with the doctrines of both, he wished to follow neither (as in fact he wished to follow no man), and reacted with particular asperity against Pytha-
goras.
We have seen how he includes Pythagoras in his condemnation of 'polymathy' without understanding (fr. 40). In fr. 129 we have: * Pythagoras son of Mnesarchus practised inquiry (or research:
made
a
historic)
most of all men, and having selected from these writings (?) 1 his own, a polymathy, a deceit.' Fr. 81, again, implies that Heraclitus called Pythagoras 'prince of cheats', and another fragment (35) runs: *Men who are philosophers must be inquirers
wisdom of
many things indeed/ In view of his known opinion about historic, and his contempt for the knowing of many things instead of the one truth that matters, these words must be heavily ironical.
(fustoras) into
take into account also his singling out of Pythagoras as the arch-practitioner of historic, and the probability that at this time the
When we
*
word
philosopher' was applied in particular to Pythagoras and his followers (p. 165, above), it appears pretty clearly who is the target.
(On this fragment cf. also p. 204, above.) From all this disparagement of others we can learn in negative terms what his own method was. It was not historic, such as was practised
by Hecataeus and a little later by Herodotus; that is, travelling all over the known world, questioning all sorts of people, and amassing factual
knowledge, or studying external nature the heavenly bodies, meteoroas the Milesians had logical phenomena, earthquakes and so forth
done.
Nor was
it
a study of the poets, who in Greece were the recognized teachers of men in theology, morals and other matters including even arts and
crafts.
The
essence of his
:
own
*I
procedure
is
searched myself.' This pronouncement was already quoted (fr. 101) quoted by several ancient writers. Plutarch (Adv. Colot. 1 1 1 8 c) adds to
it
Know thyself'. 2
1 I agree with e,g. Burnet (EGP, 134) and Kirk (390) in seeing no reason to suspect the genuineness of this fragment. The exact translation is doubtful, but it is clearly uncomplimentary in the
same sense as
fr. 40, with the added charges of plagiarism and imposture. For some attempts at complete interpretation see A. Delatte, Vie de Pyth. 159, 161-3. a If Diels's fr. 1 1<5 cannot actually be by Heraclitus, it is perhaps more likely to have originated in fr. 101 than in fr. 2 as Kirk thinks (p. 56).
417
Heraclitus
has two main meanings: (i) to look for, as in //. iv, 88 'looking for Pandarus, to see if she could find him anywhere", or Theognis, 415, (2) to question, inquire of somebody, find
(oijrjpiai)
out.
another passage in Herodotus, vn, 142. When the Persian invasion was imminent, the Athenians sent to Delphi for advice and received the famous counsel to rely on a wooden wall.
After the messengers had returned with this reply, 'many opinions were
1 expressed as they sought the meaning of (Si^svcov) the oracle'. Heraclitus was certainly 'looking for himself in the sense that he was
trying to discover his own true nature. But the pregnant use of the word in Herodotus's seventh book probably illustrates his meaning
best.
they had done that and received their answer. But like questioning a hidden meaning, and they all oracular replies it had a superficial and
V/QTZ probing
truth.
it to get beneath the surface and discover the underlying Socrates did exactly the same when, having been told of a Delphic response with, on the surface, a much plainer meaning, he
it?*
immediately asked himself the question: 'What is the riddle behind 2 That there should be such a riddle, or hidden meaning, in the
Pythia's answer
was only
normal
practice.
To
to be expected, for it reflected the oracle's find the explanation of the world, the true nature
of reality, was to Heraclitus an analogous process, for 'reality loves to conceal itself '.3 This explanation moreover was contained in a logos
Holscher in Festschrift Reinhardt, 76 says: 813^0601 wird im lonischen vor allem von der Befragung des Orakels gebraucht* But the examples which he cites (Od. xv, 90, xi, 100) do not by any means necessarily bear this out, and he does not quote the Herodotus passage, where the word, though used in connexion with an oracle, does not mean consulting it. z -rt TTOTE cdvhTEToi; ApoL 21 B. Scholars who have thought that the object of Socrates's * mission was to prove the god a liar' are naturally puzzled and annoyed when he goes on to describe himself as acting *in obedience to the god* and performing a 'service* to him. But they have misunderstood him. He was only doing what any sensible man did with a Delphic response: looking past the obvious meaning for what was hidden underneath. 3 Fr. 123 <pCrars K00* *H. Kpforrea0ai <piM. Quite enough has been written on the meaning of <pOcns in this passage. Kirk, 227-31, has a full discussion of earlier views, and himself concludes * that it means the "real constitution of things. With this I am in full agreement, but I cannot feel so strongly as he does that, as a consequence, the English word 'nature* is an altogether misleading translation.
1
*
418
which we
shall
come
next), that
is,
pursued by thought and grasped by insight. It could certainly be seen in external nature, if one had the insight to grasp it, but not by the mere piling up of knowledge; and it was exemplified equally fully in oneself.
Thus by
'I
the
turned
my
two words of fr. 101 Heraclitus meant, I suggest, first, thoughts within and sought to discover my real self;
secondly, 'I asked questions of myself '; thirdly, *I treated the answers like Delphic responses hinting, in a riddling way, at the single truth
knew
is
that if
understood
my
self I
which
the real constitution of everything else as well'. It is not surprising that a man with this outlook made few contributions to what
we
should
call science,
rather than
and that his conclusions are based on intuition on observation and analysis of data. The later philosophers
dimension to his
The Logos
Heraclitus believed
first
Logos, which, he says, determines the course of all that comes to pass. It is reasonable to assume (with Gigon) that the other fragments which speak of the Logos in this same sense also belonged to the
introductory section of the work.
try to understand
what
a point to be noted in preparation. When he says that * everything comes to pass in accordance with this Logos* (fr. i), or speaks of 'the Logos which orders all things*
this
is
(fr.
word in a specialized sense. On the common word which in current use covered a
it
wide
field
as
anyone
else
would.
credible that even -^hen he appropriates it for a concept peculiar to his own philosophy he should divorce it completely from its ordinary uses. In the following sentences there is no difficulty
it is
Nor
Heraclitus
illustrated
from other
all
could be found
logoi I
'
this.
Fr. 87:
'A
fool
is
excited
by every
below).
Fr. 39: 'Bias . . .who was of more logos than the rest' (' account', 'worth'; sense 2, below). Fr. 31: 'Earth. . .has its measure in the same logos as existed before it
became
For these reasons it is as well to begin with a brief outline of the ways in which the word was currently used in and around the time of
Heraclitus.
(i)
Logos in the
whether
fifth
Anything
i?
(Hdt,
141),*
said (or for that matter written). story or narrative fictitious or a true history (Thuc. i, 97 of his history
of the Peloponnesian War). An account of anything, explanation of a situation or circumstances (Find. Ol vn, 21, PytL n, 66, iv, 132, Stesi1 1, i Diehl). News, speech (Thuc. 1, 22, i, tidings (Eur. Bacch. 663). describing his policy in writing up speeches; perhaps not common till the late fifth century, though Hdt. vin, 100, i comes very near it). Talk, con-
chorus,
versation in general
472, Hdt. in, 148,
(//.
i).
xv, 393, Od. i, 56, Find. Pyth. iv, 101, Ar. Wasps, Of the response of an oracle, Find. PytL iv, 59.
(Batr. 8, Thuc vi, 46, 5, Hdt. 1,75, 3), something commonly or proverbially said (frequent in the tragedians, e.g. Aesch. Ag. 750, Soph. Tr. i). Mention, notice. Thus the slave Xanthias, standing by with the baggage on his back while his master confers with Heracles, complains:
Rumour, report
my aching shoulder there's no logos' (Aristoph. Frogs, 87). So also things are said to be worth logos. (In the Scythian winter 'there is no rain worth logos , Hdt. iv, 28, 2. 'Greater than logos in Thuc. n, 50 means 'beggaring description'. It is easy to see how we shade off here into the meaning 'worth', 'esteem', which I have separated as (2) below.) Very commonly of mere words, as opposed to action or facts. So Soph. El. 59: 'What does it harm me if I die in logoi, but in fact am safe?* Hdt. iv, 8, 2: They say in their logos that Oceanus encircles the earth, but do not prove it
9
9
*But of me and
in fact
1
also,
fr.
82,
Anaxagoras,
fr. 7.
No
more thorough
see
in Arck.f. Begrifsgesch. 1958, 8*f * I give at least one example of each use, although examples could run into tens or hundreds.
H. Boeder
some of course
are so
common
that the
420
Logos
in the Fifth
Century
This may be connected with the fact that in the earliest literature it seems to be used most frequently of deceptive talk (Od. i, 56; Hes. TL 229, 890, Ergo,
78, 789;
Still
H. Herm. 317; Theogn. 254). under the heading of things said or written, we have the terms of a treaty or agreement (Hdt. vu, 158, 5); a command (Aesch. P.F". 40, Pers. 363); a section of a written work (Hdt v, 36, 4, vn, 93, and compare the
distinction
fr.
i
*
between one logos and the next in Hesiod, Ergo, 106, Xenoph. DK, Find. PytL x, 54); an account in the financial sense (Hdt. in, 7, You will render a logos of the money which has passed through your 142, 5 and so generally or metaphorically Hdt. vm, 100, 3: 'rendering a hands'), of their deeds' (facing the reckoning, paying the penalty). logos
esteem, reputation; also
already noticed leads naturally to that of worth, fame (Find. Isthm. v, 13 and 26, PytL vin, 38). In Soph. O.C. 1163 the protection of a god is said to be of no small logos. This is common in Herodotus, as for example to be of logos in someone's
(2)
eyes
120, 5), in the King's eyes (iv, 138, i), of much or little logos (in, 146, 3; i, 143, 2, etc.). To hold or put a man 'in logos' is to honour him
(i,
(Tyrtaeus, 9,
Diehl).
In Aesch. P. V. 231 it is said that Zeus had no logos of mortals. The same meaning could have been expressed by saying that they were of no logos in his eyes, but used as it is the word probably comes under the next heading of
'thought': Zeus had no thought or care for mortals, recked not of them. (So also Find. OL vm, 4, Hdt. i, 117, i, etc. In i, 62, 2 the Athenians at first
'had no logos of Pisistratus', i.e. did not worry about him.) (3) To the Greeks the notion of taking thought, weighing up pros and cons, commonly presented itself as holding a conversation with oneself.
Hence logos takes on that meaning too. 1 Eur. Med. 872 shows the transition, for Medea's way of saying *I have thought it over' means literally 'I had a
talk to myself' (cf. Tro. 916). As early as Parmenides, logos in this sense can be opposed, as thought or reasoning, to mere sensation, though elsewhere the same writer uses it of his true account of things (8, 50) or, in the
plural, to
(i, 15).
'
the meaning of in their logos (Hdt. vm, 6, 2), shown by the ' context to mean opinion *. The logos (in this case that the Greek fleet should be
Close to this
'
wiped out) is what they would have said if asked, and did say to themselves. (4) Another easy development from the spoken or written word is the notion of cause, reason or argument. 'Why did she send libations, from what 9 9 logos? (Aesch. Cho. 515). 'Why do you keep silence for no logos? (Soph. Ph. 730). So to have logos, of a neuter subject, means to be arguable or
1
i,
421
Heraclitus
reasonable (Soph. EL 466): from the fourth century at least we find it with a personal subject in the sense of the French avoir raison (Plato, ApoL 346).
Clouds of Aristophanes has the dispute between the Better and the Worse Logos (argument, case). Presumably because it is basically a spoken reason,
The
it is
sometimes
alleged, a pretext (Soph. Ph. 352), and (as indeed in Aesch. Cho. 515) it is difficult to be sure whether a
which is only
genuine or trumped-up cause is intended. ' (5) In contrast to the meanings of empty words* or 'pretext',
9
we have
the phrase 'the real logos (Hdt. I, 95, i; 116, 5), meaning the truth of the 9 matter, somewhat as in I, izo, 2 true kings are 'kings in the true logos , The meanings so far considered melt easily into and out of one another.
Others are a
little
more
specialized.
*
Hdt. in, 99, 2 : Not many of them reach the logos of old age.* Cf. Thuc. vii, 56, 4 (the full number). (7) Correspondence, relation, proportion. Aesch. Sept. 5iyf.: Hyperbius
(6) Measure,
full
or due measure.
1
has Zeus emblazoned on his shield, his opponent's device is Typhon. As Zeus defeated Typhon, so he will give victory to Hyperbius 'according to the logos of the blazon' (corresponding, conformably to). Theognis, 4i7f.:
as gold rubbed on lead, there is a logos of superiority in me/ Hdt. II, 2 If an Egyptian's allotment of land was reduced by the Nile, he paid tax 109, on the remainder 'in (or according to) the logos of the tax originally assessed'.
'I
:
am
In vii, 36, 3 Herodotus speaks of two ropes of flax and four of papyrus. Their thickness and quality were the same, but the flaxen were in logos heavier.' (In proportion: absolutely the two would weigh less than the four papyrus
ropes.) Later, in Plato, this sense is common, and is also generalized so that adverbial phrases with logos can mean no more than 'similarly*.
in Plato
In the sense of strictly mathematical proportion or ratio logos is frequent and Aristotle, but there is perhaps no indubitably attested example
surviving from the fifth century nearer than Hdt. vii, 36 just quoted. However, from the accounts in Aristotle of the fifth-century Pythagoreans, it is impossible to believe that they did not use the word in this sense.
Two other senses of the word are particularly relevant to our coming ' ' examination of its use by Heraclitus : general principle, law, or rule and the faculty of reason*. These do not seem by any means the same thing, yet the
'
same word logos occurs in contexts where it is difficult to decide which would be the best translation. Another point to remark is the rarity of instances in the fifth century where either translation is indubitably right.
contexts, as
1
(8) General principle or rule. Logos means this in some fourth-century when Aristotle speaks of 'the right logos 9 in the Ethics. Some
In this case
it is
//. xi,
225 T$T]$.
. .
-fixero jihrpov.
422
Logos
examples from the
in the Fifth
Century
fifth century seem to have been erroneously so translated. For instance LSJ quote under this heading Find. OL n, 22, where it seems to mean 'this saying *, and Nem. iv, 31. In the latter Pindar says: 'He would
show himself a
is like
tyro in battle who did not understand the logos: achievement to bring suffering with it* The last words are one form of a Greek commonplace, and no doubt it is true that to the Greek mind they represented
a general principle, an aspect of the normal workings of the world; but the * sense does not require that logos should mean anything more than saying'.
The passage, however, is a good word may well, to the people who
to others are
illustration
use
it,
convey
two distinct ideas because they would use different words to them. So too in Epicharmus, fr. 2, 12 express (supposing the fragment to be genuine), A6yo$ can well be translated 'law* as by Diels, but equally well
DK
'argument* (Hicks). More probably than either, the use of KOCTOC Aoyov here approximates to Plato*s in (7) above: 'You and I are different now from
what we were yesterday, and similarly in the future we shall be different again* (a sense developed from 'in the same ratio*). The nearest fifth-century instance is no doubt the statement of the philosopher Leucippus that 'nothing comes about at random, but all from logos and by necessity*. Burnet translates 'ground', and perhaps Leucippus means little more than that there is a reason for everything; but since the statement has a universal, cosmological significance, it comes very near to saying that
governed by general laws. Possibly Democritus, fr. 53, conies close to the meaning: 'Many live according to logos though they have not learned logos\ but here 'right reason', as in (4) above, seems a better rendering. Similarly in Plato,
everything
is
Rep. 5000, the philosopher in studying the Universe is contemplating what is well ordered and according to logos, and again one might be tempted to
suppose that the word means natural law; but Jowett and Cornford are no ' doubt right in translating it according to reason and where reason governs
'
'
respectively.
(9)
The
and
(4), and is regular in fourth-century writers, for whom man is distinguished from the other animals by the possession of logos. We see it also in the passage of the Republic just quoted. Yet a clear instance in the fifth century might be hard to find, unless some verses which passed as by
1 Epicharmus belong to that century.
1
is
ap-
57 DK. They are attributed by Athenaeus to a certain Chrysogonus the be a contemporary of Alcibiades. (See DK, I, p. 194.) Diels described them as 'poor poetry, with Heraclitean and Pythagorean echoes*. At the best they are late in the
Epicharmus,
fr.
flute-player, said to
century.
423
Heraclitus
fr. 53, quoted in the previous paragraph. (Herapreached by Democritus, clitus himself is of course being excluded from this survey.) in the fourth century which it would be (10) Another meaning common difficult to pinpoint in the fifth is that of definition, or formula expressing the essential nature of anything. This is regular in Aristotle, and is of course to give an account or description of only a refinement of an earlier usage:
something approximates to defining it. The important thing shreds as always is that whatever sense is uppermost when the word is used, For mind. writer's the and of the other uses will be clinging to it influencing or for Plato and mean 'reason, cause', example, logos as we have seen can includes it unless not is Aristotle the logos (definition) of anything complete
the reason for
(i i)
its
to notice here
existence.
is
one of the commonest in Greek, and it is therefore not used in certain contexts where there is no surprising to find it sometimes idiomatic word-for-word English equivalent. Such are Hdt. i, 141, 4: 'The
The word
rest
common
vm,
68 : 'those
9
who
of
(who
allies).
So too
under (5):
'those
who
(who
word and thought inevitably tends to obscure, that notions which the Greeks conveyed by one and the
more closely linked in their minds than in those of people who lack a word of the same coverage. In reading Greek it is difficult, and sometimes wrong, to draw a hard and fast line between them. Nor is was intended by the writer. it always easy to know exactly what
as follows:
for ever, Although this Logos [sc. which I shall describe] exists (or is true) men prove as unable to understand it when once they have heard it as before
1
v Ti3 dpx^3 ocOrou TOU ovyyp<5tWKrros Ari.st.Rhet. 1407^6. Sext. Adv. Matk. VH, 132 says The words are Heraclitus's introduction of his subject. Ivopx^iiEvos yofr> Ttov "irEpl <pOaco$ 3 Ever since Aristotle (Joe. cit. pp. 407 f.) noted the ambiguity of <5zi without resolving it, scholars
have disputed whether it should qualify &VTOS (as Hippolytus thought) or d^Overoi. For the chief names on both sides see Kirk, HCF, 34, adding Bitter and Preller (Hist. Gr. Phil. 320) and Comford (Princ. Sap. 113) to those who have taken it with I6vros. Kirk himself takes it with d^jvrrou Argument will never settle the question finally. I can only say that I myself find it unnatural and impossible to separate dri from &vro$. The difference matters less in that Kirk writes that iovro$ c&ei 'certainly expresses something which Heraclitus believed; it is to be
424
For, though
all
things
come
they experience such words and things as I set forth, distinguishing each thing according to its nature and telling how it is. The rest of mankind are unaware of what they do while awake just
Logos,
as they forget
asleep.
Listening not to
me but
to the
Logos
it is
wise to agree 2
things are one/ These two fragments tell us that the Logos is (a) something which one hears (the commonest meaning), () that which regulates all events, a kind of universal law of becoming,3 (c) something
with an existence independent of him who gives it verbal expression. Fr. 2 takes us a little further. One must follow what is common;
c
but although the Logos is common, most men live as if they had a * private understanding of their own.' This notion of the common' is
elaborated in
fr.
114:*
to
intelligence
and
trust in
what
all
is
common
all,
laws are nourished by one, the divine, which extends its far as as it will and is sufficient for all and more than sufficient/ sway
human
rejected only on the ground that dsi goes with dfuveroi' (p. 35). It is also possible to construe ToOSe as predicate with S6vros and the phrase as a genitive absolute: 'The Logos being as I say
it is.'
Cornford (Princ. Sap. 113) is no doubt right in detecting allusions to the language of the mysteries here and elsewhere in Heraclitus. With d^Irveroi c Theo Sra. p. 14 Hiller: debarred from the mystic revelation are those who have unclean hands and are Tfiv 9covfjv duveroi. This is
elaborated in Isocr. Paneg. 157: the proclamation of the Eumolpidae and Heralds at Eleusis excludes murderers and pdp^apoi (echoed in Heraclitus, fr. 107 pappdpous VJA/XOS ^vrcov). firreipos (especially in connexion with X6yos) recalls the version of the ritual prohibition in Ar. Frogs, 355
Sons
2
firreipos TOICOV
A<5yoov.
Cf. also the reference to the kykeon in own A6yo$ into conformity.
fr.
3 I omit here fr. 72, which speaks of X6ycp TCO TCC 6Xa SIOIKOUVTI, because Burnet rejected these words as an addition of Marcus Aurelius who quotes the fragment. Kirk also (HCF9 44) describes the fragment as 'genuine quotation interlarded with Marcus's own comments'. For myself, however, in view of fr. i and fr. 64, 1 see no reason to suppose it a Stoic paraphrase. 4 Which may have stood in Heraclitus's text between frr. i and 2 (Kirk, HCF, 48 f.). 5 The pun fuv v6cp. .wc|> drives home the identity of what is common with intelligent reflexion (i.e. the Logos). No doubt the connexion is also in his mind when he uses the verb uvilvai as in fr. 51. Heraclitus in many places shows that he is still at the stage of thought when verbal similarity appears fraught with a greater significance than would now be allowed it.
.
Cf. Kirk, 9 198. Snell (Hermes^ 1926, 368, n. 2) compares Aesch. Ag. 1081 (ApollonDestroyer), 689 (Helen~Avous), and Sept. 405 and 829 (the 6p06v or h^Tuucv of a name). Cleanthes recalled this fragment in his hymn to Zeus, 20 f.:
oOr* laopwcn QeoO xoiv6v v6nov oOre kAOovcriv,
ffF
$ KV irei66|Jievoi
ouv
vco {Mov
cr9A6v lxoiEV *
Other Stoic echoes are also quoted by Kirk, HCF^^L (Considering the methods of some modern scholars, one may be grateful that they have not tried to reverse die relationship.)
425
Heraclitus
it is
common',
Heraclitus claims to be
grasped
this
common Logos.
all
peculiar to oneself. Paradoxically, the only, or practically the only, man to have But that is the fault of the others, for the
wisdom
to see, but, as
he says in
all
fr.
The togos
common
to
and what
is
common
intelligence or
1
. .
on 0v voco insight. This emerged from fr. 1 14 (with its pun It is thus an additional aspect of the Logos that it includes
Sjuvcp).
the act of
2 thinking or reflexion. have noted Heraclitus's deliberately oracular style, and the dis-
We
jointed and picturesque character of the pronouncements in which he conveyed his message. To draw from them a consistent world-view or
system of thought is inevitably to supply connecting links which are not in the fragments, and to that extent must be speculative. Moreover
is
so alien to his
Homer
*see*: //. in, 21, 30; v, 590, 669, 711, etc.) include the power not only to perceive with the senses but to recognize the identity or significance of what is perceived. early uses of the words see K. von Fritz in CP, (1943), XL and XLI (1945-6). To take one illustration, in
On
xxxvm
IL in Aphrodite has appeared to Helen disguised as an old woman of her retinue. Soon, however, Helen sees through the disguise and realizes that she is in the presence of the goddess. The verb for this is ivor^ae (v. 396). So also Epicharmus wrote (fr. 12 DK): 'It is nous that sees and nous that hears; the rest are deaf and blind*, i.e. the senses by themselves, without the supra-sentient power to interpret their message, tell one nothing. As Heraclitus himself truly says (fr. 40), it is possible to learn many facts without having the nous to grasp their significance. Fr. 34 comes even nearer to Epicharmus. The equivalence of *the common* to right thinking is repeated in fr. 113 fw6v krn iraon T& <ppovfeiv, which, however, Kirk supposes to be nothing but a short and inaccurate version of the general sense of fr. 2 in particular (HCF, 56). I do not find his objections conclusive. * 3 Kirk writes (p. 63) that the universal Reason, in which men share*, is the Stoic interpretation of the Logos, and that 'there is nothing in this which corresponds to what Heraclitus appears to have meant by his A6yos*; for Heraclitus, he thinks, it describes an objective state of things, common to all things and to all men, but with no epistemological implications. The Stoics certainly developed and laid especial emphasis on the concept of Logos as Reason, but this seems to go too far. It is impossible that Heraclitus, for all his originality, should have so rigidly divorced his objective use of X6yo$ from the usages of the same word current in his own time, especially as he was not a logician, but, to quote Kirk again (p. 396), * lived, as his language shows, in the tradition of poetical thought*. I doubt whether it can be altogether reconciled with Kirk's remark on p. 396 that *for him there was no rigid distinction in kind between the Logos as comprehended in a human mind and the Logos operating in nature*. In any case I should say we have seen evidence that for Heraclitus the Logos was not only * comprehended in a human mind*, but included the mind's active power of comprehension.
426
impression that
of his message. Nevertheless I share with others the many of the fragments fit together in a way that one
would not
what seem
to be isolated
and meta-
phorical utterances are in fact integral parts of a unified conception of the universe and of man as a part of it. It is discouraging, certainly, to
note
of this world-view have been put forward in the past and continue to be put forward; but one can only
Some
Presocratic systems
it is difficult
circles,
seem so much the product of a single them in a continuous exposition. of which Heraclitus said that beginning and end
to clarify
'
(fr. 103), or as Porphyry paraphrased it: 'Any point you can think of is both beginning and end.' 1 One can break into them at
in the
end
to see
the system complete. To pick the best starting-point, the clearest order in which to present these parts of a single whole, is not easy, but we
try.
men
hours as
'It is
if they
were asleep.
act
If we
like
wrong to
and speak
does
logical connexion between this criticism and the in fr. 2 to 'follow the common'. To be told to wake up and injunction pay attention is usual enough, and does not normally give any informa-
not seem to be
much
which our attention is demanded. Yet here it is a part of it. The link is in a passage from Plutarch: Heraclitus says that the waking share one common world, but when asleep each man
tion about the doctrine for
'
must now follow a train of thought to a private one/3 which will explain Heraclitus's conception of sleep and wakefulness, and their connexion with the principles by which the world is governed.
turns
away
We
bring out something which is of great importance for an Hitherto appreciation of his position in the history of Greek thought.
It will also
This peculiarity of their systems was even noted by at least one of the Presocratics themParmenides wrote (fr. 5): *It is all one to me, the point from which I begin; for there I will arrive back again.* * Kirk thinks it more probably only Marcus Aurelius's paraphrase of the end of fr. i. 3 De fr. 89), rejected by Kirk as a conflation of the last parts of Superst*, i66c (Heraclitus, frr. i and 2, but vigorously defended by Vlastos in AJP, 1955, 344-7*
selves.
427
Heraclitus
the material and spiritual worlds have been united without much misone another. giving. Later they became clearly distinguished from
obscurity of Heraclitus results from the fact that his more subtle thinking had really brought him to a stage when matter and
spirit,
Much of the
as separate, but
or equally the concrete and the abstract, require to be thought of he is still too much in the groove of previous thinking
to effect the separation consciously. Before this could be achieved philosophy had to suffer the intellectual jolt which it received from
Parmenides. As Kirk observes (HCF^ 53), Heraclitus would have been unable to define any other type of 'being' than corporeal being. It is easy to forget how close to the concrete, material world his conceptions
much
in terms
of
abstractions.
seen evidence that the Logos is both human thought and 1 the governing principle of the Universe. It represents in fact the nearest
that Heraclitus
We have
commonly
of his predecessors, 2 which combined both characters. This was true of Pythagorean
came
to
an arche
like that
thought, and appeared in more plainly material terms in the Air of Anaximenes, which was at the same time the divine and living stuff of
the Universe and the element of soul and mind in us. In Heraclitus
Being universal and all-pervading, this Logos the law by which the world is ordered, and which can be comprehended in human
minds
that
is
of course
part-spiritual force
Presocratic thought
from navigation
1
is
rational order. In the language of or all 'steers' things. This metaphor 'guides* used in fr. 64: 'The thunderbolt steers all things*
On the former point Kirk disagrees. His description of it in the latter aspect is worth *" The organized way in which (as Heraclitus had discovered) all tilings work " ; quoting (HCFy 3 9) : "plan" (in a non-teleological sense), "rule", even "law" (as in "the laws offeree") are possible summaries. "Principle" is too vague; I suggest the less ambiguous if more cumbersome phrase "formula of things" as a translation of A6yos in frr. i, 2, 50. In tliis formula the idea of measure
is implicit.'
Cf. Gigon, Unters. %u H. 3 f. Gigon notes the contrast in fr. i between die Logos as bang (&fcv) and the world of becoming (yiyvoji&cav) which follows its pattern. Kirk (p. 41) doubts whether Heraclitus deliberately drew the contrast between eTvai and ytyvecrdcn, but it was a possible one for his age. Cf. Simonides, 4, lines i and 6 Diehl, with the comments of H. D. Verdam (Mnemos. 1928, 299-310) and L. Woodbury (TAPA, 1953, 153-63).
428
Spiritual
(that
is,
weapon of Zeus the supreme god, used naturally for which drives the Universe), and also in fr. 41. Unfortunately power text and meaning of the latter fragment are body disputed, but Vlastos
the fiery the
has
made out a reasonable case, against Kirk and others, for keeping to the rendering: 'Wisdom is one thing, to know the Thought by which 1 all things are steered through all things/ The rendering favoured by Kirk runs: '. . .to be skilled in true judgment, how all things are
not in doubt, and, as Kirk says (p. 390), one is reminded by it of fr. 64, and 'it must be something akin to fire which "steers all things through all" The whole course
steered through
all
things'.
The
steering'
is
which a mind
is
That the divine force which brings rational order into the Universe at the same time a physical, material entity is only what we should
expect from the general climate of early fifth-century thought. It follows that we get our share of it by physical means, which include breathing and the channels (iropoi) of the sense-organs. There is in
no wholesale condemnation of sense-perception like that in Parmenides, for whom the mind does better to ignore the senses altogether. They are only 'bad witnesses' to those whose souls have
Heraclitus
though
kind.
this,
He
(fr. 107) indeed, in his opinion includes the vast majority of man' goes so far as to say (fr. 5 5) Things that can be seen, heard,
what I prefer', and judges the relative value of firsthand experience and hearsay in the words (fr. ioia) 'Eyes are more accurate witnesses than the ears'. Though he has nothing but contempt for those who can only amass data without the nous to draw the right
learned
these are
SiocKvpepvccv.
For reading and translation of fr. 41 see Kirk, HCF, 386-90 and Vlastos, 9 1955, Kirk's construction of yvcb^v as internal accusative after frrriaracrSai instead of direct object (in which he follows Heidel, Reinhardt and Gigon) is based on the conviction which he shares with
Heidel that to equate yvcburj with the Logos and make
Stoic idea.
1
AJP
it
is
This seems to give back a good deal of what Kirk has taken away by refusing to equate with the Logos and regard it as a divine principle.
429
Heraclitus
is
underlies
and explains them (c Kirk, HCF, 61). The senses, then, are for human beings the primary channels of communication with the Logos outside. Here we must supplement the
actual fragments of Heraclitus
Sextus Empiricus,
whose
though
it is
expressed in
terminology.
He
describes 'the
become
of
divine Logos, by sharing in which we the standard logikoi (capable of thought)'. It is for Heraclitus
common and
truth,
frr.
and
2,
which he
quotes soon
it is
"what appears to
in
common
is
The
draw windows through which 'the mind (nous) in us' in our waking hours thrusts forward and, making contact with that which surrounds it, 'puts on the power of thought'. In sleep however these sense-channels (atcrOriTiKoi iropoi) are closed, and so the mind 'is prevented from
growing together with what
nrspiexov ovn9Utoc$).
is left
senses are channels, through which, as well as by breathing, we in the Logos in a literal, physical sense. They are compared to
lies
TO
Since
we still
the severance
is
not complete.
means of contact with the outside source of Respiration life, 'like a root', says Sextus. We are still taking some part in the cosmic activity, which is presumably why 'Heraclitus says' (so Marcus Aurelius tells us) 2 'that even sleepers are workers and co-operators in what goes on in the world'. Respiration, it seems, is sufficient to
as sole
preserve
its
fr.
life
but not
rationality,
In sleep we each retire into a private world. No one shares our dreams as our waking experiences are shared. And dreams are unreal. Thus for
vii, I26E, DK, 22 A 1 6. Kirk agrees that the ideas are genuinely Heraclitean, at the extent that *for HeracKtus the soul's efficiency depended on contact with the outside world and with the material Logos, possibly by the medium of breath, as Sextus tells us* (HCFy
1
Math,
least to
34 1 )as fr. 75, but hardly a word-for-word extract from Heraclitus. vi, 42, quoted by obscure the sense by omitting the xorf
*
DK
(DK
430
'Private*
Heraclitus three ideas are essentially connected: (a) living as if one had a private wisdom of one's own, () falsehood, (c) sleep and dreams. To retire into a world of one's own is to starve the rational element
by
shutting
feed.
1
from the universal and true Logos on which it should The many who do this are, compared to a man with an insight
it
off
into the
common
Logos,
like sleepers
compared
to a
man
awake.
it
to follow the
Common,
to hold fast to
with
one's might.
If this interpretation is correct, it would seem that Heraclitus already had a dim foreshadowing2 of the truth which was later to be explicitly formulated by Protagoras, that each man is the judge of his own
sensations, for they are his alone and not the same for any two persons. There is a common world of truth (here he would differ from Pro-
tagoras), but
only to be attained by going beyond individual and disconnected sensations and drawing conclusions from them by
it is
It is
understandable therefore
that in certain
state
moods he could praise the senses (since in our bodily are the channels through which in the first instance and in an they are brought into contact with the Logos), and in we elementary way
others, with seeming contradiction, emphasize their limitations or even abuse them. In such a context of thought he could well have said that * seeing is being deceived' (fr. 46, suspected by Kirk, p. 281 as an
improbable statement for Heraclitus). After all, mere seeing and hearing * are precisely the activities of the many* whom he lashes so unmercifully
for their refusal to understand the truth (see the examples
on
p. 412,
above).
The
1
as
we might
call
them
psychical
The word Tp&povrcti in fr. 114 (Tp&povroi irdvrgs ot dvOpcbireioi v6yioi \rnb v6$ TW flelov) Is probably not entirely metaphorical for Heraclitus. See Kirk, HCF, 536 and 69: "The "divine law" which is akin to the Logos is described in material terms which are probably not just due to
personification.*
Cornford has pointed out how with his notion of sleep Heraclitus contradicts yet another popular view, namely that in sleep the soul is more open to divine influences and so may have prophetic truth revealed to it in dreams (Princ. Sap. 150, referring to Find. fr. 131 and Aristotle, fr. 10 Rose, p. 84 Ross). * 2 I do not wish to deny what Kirk says on p. 74 of his book, that there is no indication in the this view on for him such based Heraclitus conclusions that any epistemological fragments
facts
were not
essentially different,
431
Heraclitus
processes
it
is
carried into
even further
detail,
clarity
may be
as well to follow
point things which on. The doxographers say that Heraclitus's first principle was fire. They speak as if it were the arche mdpfysis of things in the Milesian sense,
e.g.
up the topic, at the risk of introducing at this will find their proper place for full discussion later
Theophrastus (op. SimpL Phys. 23.33, DK,A5): 'Hippasus of Metapontum and Heraclitus of Ephesus. . .made fire the arche^ and
fire
they produce existing things by thickening and thinning, and resolve them into fire again, on the assumption that fire is the one
out of
underlying physis; for Heraclitus says that all things are an exchange for fire' (cf. fr. 90). Aristotle himself (MetapL 9%4&i) lists the fire of
Heraclitus as his
'first
Anaximenes and Diogenes of Apollonia, and the four primary substances of Empedocles. The primacy of fire in Heraclitus seems also
to
We shall have
to consider whether these later writers correctly interpreted the role of fire in Heraclitus, but about its primacy there can be no question, and he himself said that the whole world-order is an ever-living fire
(fr.
It
it
with
the Logos, and agree with the Stoics and Hippolytus when they say that the- fire of Heraclitus is 'rational, and responsible for the government of the whole world'. 1 This, clearly, is what in Sextus's account
'surrounds us and
is
rational
and
intelligent'
It
{Math, vn,
127).
tion, *fire
hot and dry. Though not a mere symbol for an abstracrepresents for Heraclitus the highest and purest form of
is
matter, the vehicle for soul and mind, or rather soul and mind themselves, which in a more advanced thinker would be distinguished from
It
as a visible
flame or glow, but rather a kind of invisible vapour, as Philoponus says ' commenting on Aristotle, De Anima, 405 325 : By fire he does not mean
flame:
fire is
Si
the
name he gives
iced
see fr. 64
(so
9p6vinov itvoi TOUTO T6 m/p, Kcd -rffr SIOIK^CTECOS TOV 6Xcov ofriov (Hipp. IX, 10: Stoic, but the sense Heraditean, as Kirk agrees (HCF, 3 5 1 ff.,
we may conjecture)
it is -wise').
43*
The
Dry Soul is
Best
Thus if Heraclitus is consistent, foolishness and death be connected with cold and dampness; and so it is. 'The dry soul is wisest and best' (fr. 1 18). This explains among other things the effects
of intoxication:
2
*
man when he
is
is
led
by
ny).
knowing whither he goes, for his soul is wet* Death itself is a turning of the soul to water (fr. 36). It is
infer,
is
not rash to
drunkenness, temporarily overcome the soul, which is restored to a drier and warmer state on waking.3 Since bodily pleasures lead to a moistening, that is a
though no fragment actually says it, that sleep, like an intermediate state in which moist vapours have
weakening, of the soul, we can understand why Heraclitus should say (fr. no): 'It is not better for men to get all they want'; for unfortunately
'it is enjoyment for souls to become moist '.* The same thought must be behind one of his most striking aphorisms (fr. 85, known to Aristotle; see Eth. End. 1223 b 22): 'To fight with desire is hard:
it
whatever
wishes
is
it
buys
at the price
of soul'
and cyclic change, and the soul takes its in mutual the conversions of the elements. 'It is part quite naturally death to souls to become water, death to water to become earth, but
Everything
in continual
soul'
(fr.
36).
By substituting
emphasized the substantial of each the two. Since element lives identity by the death of the other, or as we might put it devours the other, it is quite in order that souls,
though
their
proper nature
after
is
Immediately
1
quoting what
hot and dry, should live on moisture. all accept as a genuine fragment of
*Recte hunc locum explicat Philoponus* (Hitter and Preller, Hist. Ph. Gr. 38 ). For a contrary view see Kirk, HCF, 275, n. i. I cannot agree with Gigon that it is wrong to identify the Logos with fire. He writes (Unters. %u H. 59f.): *Dass die Seele aus trockenster Siibstanz besteht, hat H. zwar gelehrt. Aber dass sie feurig sei, ist damit noch gar nicht gesagt, und uber-
haupt durfte das sinnlich-banale Einzelwesen vyu^ nicht mit dem kosmogonischen Urfeuer gleichgestellt werden.* This is very un-Heraclitean language. He also thinks it wrong to identify the Logos with fire (p. 60) : 'Dies folgt der Neigung der Stoa.* Is it not evident that in this as in
certain other respects the Stoa followed Heraclitus? Gigon's further claim on p. Trockenheit ist nicht Attribut des Feuers, sondem der Luft* is simply wrong.
a
no
that 'die
Whether
why one
is
something
3
we
never know.
'Sleep was generally regarded as due to a reduction of organic heat*, Vlastos in AJP, 1955, 365, with references in note. The obscure fr. 26 seems to bring sleep and death close together. 4 Fr. 77. Much of this fragment is highly obscure, but so much at least seems certain. As
Gigon
says (JJnters. %u
H.
be spurious.
433
Heraditus
Heraclitus, Cleanthes
1
from
moist things'
Gigon, mind, not only water but blood and other bodily humours. In the same way some of the 'Heraclitizers' were said to teach that the sun
be explained, with (fr. 12). The plural is probably to as indicating that Heraclitus, like Thales, had various liquids in
own cosmic
The sun
draws up moisture and feeds on it, but being a hot body converts it into heat, a theory which makes use of elementary observation of the
the same.
of Heraclitus's views (whose complete accuracy one would perhaps not like to vouch for) are only particular applications of the general law enunciated in fr. 36 and also in fr. 31 (p. 463,
below) j and given the equivalence of souls and fire, the analogical behaviour of the sun and animals is natural and inevitable.
be more to say about the soul, but the present excursion into psychology is intended to further an understanding of the com-
There
will
plexity of the Logos-conception in Heraclitus. To sum this up, it is first of all the everlasting truth to which he is giving verbal expression, but which is independent of his utterance of it (frr. i, 50). Next, it is
the subject of that truth, the One which is everything (fr. 50). And this One is at the same time the divine, intelligent principle which surrounds
us and causes the ordering of the cosmos, and that within us to which we owe whatever intelligence we possess. In us it is adulterated with
it is
what corrupts
it
in us
is its
encounter with
moisture and cold. Questions (all closely related) which remain to be considered in their due place are: (a) What is the content of the Logos, considered as the true explanation of the changing world? What is this
*
its
principle* in accordance with which, says Heraclitus, everything has becoming? () In what sense are 'all things one' for him? What is
the
are
all
bond of unity between them? Is it as with the Milesians, that they made out of the one material stuff, which remains the permanent
their existence?
(c)
ground of
life
What
exactly
is
the role of
fire
in the
of the cosmos?
1
{HCF
367).
434
Besides the Logos, and intimately connected with it, it would appear that the fundamentals of HeracKtus's interpretation of the world
are contained in three general statements.
we must
deal with
For convenience of exposition them one by one, but none can be fully understood
without the others, indeed they are only different ways of explaining the same truth. These three statements are: (a) Harmony is always the
product of opposites, therefore the basic fact in the natural world is strife. (&) Everything is in continuous motion and change, (cr) The
world is a living and everlasting fire. Consideration of these statements will make it possible to return to the Logos, as the law of becoming, with better understanding, and grasp the limitations which it imposes
discussed in connexion
with the Pythagoreans (pp. 220 ff., above). We may assume that both its application to music and its general use, as the fitting-together and
construction of a complex whole according to rational principles and in due proportion (which is one of the meanings of logos'), were familiar
to Heraclitus.
sense, as when we speak of living in harmony or of a harmonious effect in architecture, painting or other spheres. It might however be unwise to leave it to stand generally for harmonia in a Heraclitean context,
after explaining the Greek word, because it carries psychological overtones which are biased in a Pythagorean direction. 1 Since the harmonia of Heraclitus is the very reverse of the Pythagorean, this could not fail to be misleading.
even
A number of Heraclitus' s
of the harmony
offered
*
sayings illustrate his novel interpretation of opposites*, but perhaps the best starting-point is
by a comparison of two passages in Plato. In the Symposium^ the doctor Eryximachus is taking his turn to sing the praises of Eros, and puts forward the current view of his craft as that of reconciling
logical application
more influenced by Pythagoreanism than we always realize. The psychoof the musical concept is seen for instance in the line from the Merchant of Venice; "Such harmony is in immortal souls*, which occurs in a definitely Pythagorean context.
1
Our thought
is
435
Heraclitus
the opposites in the body.
transl.
The good
practitioner,
he says (i86D,
W.
Hamilton), 'must be able to bring elements in the -body hostile to one another into mutual affection and love;
such hostile elements are the opposites hot and cold, wet and dry and the like; it was by knowing how to create love and harmony between
these that our forefather Asclepius, as our poets here say and as
believe,
I
founded our craft'. These ideas of health as a harmony of physical opposites belonged to the Western school of medicine, being taught by Alcmaeon the fellow-townsman of Pythagoras and by some at least of the Pythagoreans (pp. 313-15, above). That Eryximachus has learned from the
Pythagoreans
in the next
is
confirmed by
sentences.
Ms development of the
continues:
musical example
few
He
That the same is true of music is plain to everyone who gives the smallest attention to the subject, and this is presumably what Heraclitus meant to say, though he is not very happy in his choice of words, when he speaks of a
unity which agrees with itself by being at variance, as in the stringing of a bow or lyre [cf. fr. 5 1, pp. 439-5 1, below]. It is, of course, quite illogical to
speak of a concord being in discord, or of its consisting of factors which are still in discord at the time when they compose it, but probably what he meant to say was that the art of music produces a harmony out of factors which are
first in
surprising if, after the insults that he hurled at Heraclitus should be doing his best to say that he agreed Pythagoras,
It
would be very
with him, only not managing to express it very well. His view was in fact a contradiction of the Pythagorean, and this is a particularly instructive example of something which has constantly happened to
Heraclitus: the sharp edge of his teaching has been taken off, and it has been blunted into the similitude of someone else's. Here Plato
represented as a pompous and not very subtle-minded person, by putting the misunderstanding into his mouth. Elsewhere he shows that he knew perfectly well what Heraclitus meant,
satirizes the doctor,
is
who
first
of his
in
To
say that
chronological succession, and represented a reconciliation of elements formerly hostile but no longer so, was to assert precisely what Heraclitus
436
Harmony in
Tension
had denied. This Plato makes clear in the Sophist (2420). The chief speaker has been talking about the dispute between those who hold that the world is many and those who maintain it to be one. He goes on :
Later, certain Muses in Ionia and Sicily perceived that safety lay rather in combining both accounts and saying that the real is both many and one and is held together by enmity and friendship. The stricter of these Muses [i.e, the Ionian, by which Plato means Heraclitus] say 'in drawing apart it is always being drawn together'. The milder [Le. the Sicilian, who stand for
Empedocles] relax the rule that this should always be so and speak of alternate states, in which the Universe is now one and at peace through the power of Love, and now many and at war with itself owing to some sort of Strife.
Empedocles^
who
by
and
plurality.
(This
is
fully
bome
with his
'stricter
elements necessarily and always involved a tension or strife between the opposites of which it was composed. The tension is never resolved.
there
Peace and war do not succeed each other in turn: always in the world is both peace and war. Cessation of struggle would mean the
disintegration of the cosmos. Plato's grasp of this essential point, which eluded so many of Heraclitus's would-be interpreters, is an
excellent guarantee of his insight, and warrants confidence in anything 1 that he has to say about this difficult thinker.
too
to his understanding of such an oracular and poetic truth. Heraclitus appeared to be breaking the law of contradiction, therefore he cannot have meant what his words seem to say. And so in De Caelo,
an obstacle
279 b 14, he classes him along with Empedocles, ignoring the distinction which Plato had been at such pains to point out. Some, he says, hold
that the that
it
world
is
'
it
will perish;
others again
alternates,
.
being
one time as
it is
and perishing,. .as Empedocles of Acragas and Heraclitus of Ephesus say'. However, he sometimes comes closer to Heraclitus's words,
1
In showing
this
differs
from
that of
Kirk.
437
Heraclitus
full
DK):
what
harmony is composed of differing comes into being by way of strife', a sentence which
1
is
paraphrases more than one fragment of Heraclitus. Heraclitus makes free use of picture-language, and
it is
not sur-
almost as many interprising that his sayings have been subject to sermons preached on pretations as isolated texts of the Bible in the
impossible not to be struck by the similarity between his use of paradox and parable and that of Jesus. Needless to say, there
them. Indeed
it is
is
no question of any comparison of doctrine, but spite ference in meaning, an expression like 'he that findeth his
in
it'
of the
dif-
life shall
lose
apart from
(Matt. x. 39) is remarkably HeracHtean in style (e.g. fr. 21), and * actual coincidence (compare Mark viii 18 Having eyes, see
ears,
hear ye not, and do ye not remember?' with Heraclitus frr. 19, 34, i), to convey the heart of his message the answer to the question: 'What is the Kingdom of God?' Jesus has
to
make
like
of symbol and comparison. It is like a mustard seed, seed broadcast on different kinds of ground, like leaven in bread,
free use
or hidden treasure, or a candle: or think of a master with an unsatisfactory servant, a vineyard let to criminals, a man hiring labourers,
money given
and
their lamps.
Similarly Heraclitus, to bring home his new idea about the workings of nature and the constitution of things, finds himself compelled to
a river,
structure of a bow or a lyre, of warfare, of of a road (which is the same road whether it takes you from North to South or from South to North), of sea-water (a healthy
say:
element for
straight
fishes,
and crooked
3
inflicts
sharp
E.g. frr. 51, 80, 10. In the first phrase (r<b dvriouv ov^pov), Kirk notes (HCF, 220) * that the Ionic word dvri^ow must be accepted as Heraclitus's own. Helpful* is the common
meaning of crvp<ppov, and the one which the context leads us to suppose was in Aristotle's mind. In the Hippocratic J>e F"ictu, i, 18 (TOC TrXETarcc Si&popa tidXicrra ovpuplpei) it includes the meaning *is of use in producing But it recalls also the Sia9ep<$iaevov dcel crup^perai of the pleasure*.
Symposium passage (187 A). The play on words is very much in Heraclitus's manner, and in spite of the change to the active mood (for which the word-play would be a motive) the whole brief a Frr, 30, 51, 53, 60, 6i ? phrase may well be his. 59, 58.
43 8
was
at
to express,
and
in his
so novel as to outrun the resources of contemporary This made the resort to a variety of symbols inevitable. It is language. for us to see whether we have the 'ears to hear', that is, the ability to
The
war
is
the ruling and creative force and a right and proper state
of
affairs.
(i)
Everything is made of opposites^ and therefore subject to internal tension. After quoting fr. 50 Hippolytus continues: 'And that all men do not understand or admit this, he complains in terms of this sort
(fr.
51):
"They do not
grasp
how by being
at variance
it
itself,*
1
bow
I use tension* in its widest sense. Vlastos complains (AJP^ 1955, 349) that 'there is much ** of tension" in Kirk's and others' interpretations of Heraclitus, but none of it is grounded textually on anything beyond the disputed iroXlvrovos in B 51 *. But how can it be claimed that the idea of universal tension is absent from such phrases as 6ia<pp6psvov cv^perai or Sfwiv fpiv?
talk
'in
Or more literally (if we accept the reading ov^lperai for 6poAoyfei, see crit. n. in Kirk, 203): being drawn apart it is drawn together*. As here translated the verb has no expressed subject,
this is
but
3
same sense
alternatively *an adjustment of opposite tensions*. 'Adjustment* (Vlastos, AJP, 1955, 350) is a good rendering of dpnoviri in a context like this. The variant readings TrotAivrpoTros and TTocMvTovos for the epithet with dptioviq go back to ancient times, and modern scholarship shows
Or
an impressive array of champions on either side. For a summary of the controversy see Kirk, noff. Since Kirk wrote, and himself came down on the side of mxMvrovos, Vlastos (AJP, 1955, 348-51) and Kranz (Rh. Mus. 1958, 250-4) have both argued in favour of TraAivrpoiros. The question cannot be finally settled. The fact that Homer uses the epithet TrcxAivrovos of a bow certainly makes that the lectio facilior, as Vlastos says, but is also an argument in favour of Heraclitus having used it, just as he borrows Homeric language in calling war uv6s in fr. 80. (Cf. //. xvm, 309.) Nor is it more difficult to apply it to the dpiiovfrj of a bow than to the bow itself. But the arguments on both sides are endless. For my part I believe that whichever epithet Heraclitus used, his image is that of a bow which is strung but not actually being drawn, and a lyre tuned but not actually being played. This (the fitting-together or structure of something) is after all what Apuovfri means. If he wrote TraMvrovos he was thinking of the 4puov(Ti of the bow or the lyre as consisting in the opposed pulls of the string or strings and the wooden frame: if * TToAlvrpo-rros, which means turning in opposite directions* (Vlastos, loc. cit. 350), he had chiefly in mind, so far as the bow is concerned, the tendency of the springy framework to turn away from the string. In the lyre, the word seems an excellent description of the relation between the strings
439
Heraclims
against a wall.
static object,
is
No movement
rest.
it,
is
visible.
To
the eyes
it
appears a
completely at
But in
fact a
going on within
is
it
as will
become evident
if the string is
enough, or
bow
will
vantage, snap
itself,
had been putting forth effort all the time. The harmonia was a dynamic one of vigorous and contrary motions neutralized by equilibrium and
so unapparent.
similar, as
The
state
of a tuned lyre (or for that matter violin) is string has broken knows to his chagrin.
And the point is that the functioning of both instruments, their very nature as a working bow or lyre, is dependent on this balance of forces, which is therefore good^ as will emerge below in the fragments considered
under (c). For Heraclitus bow and lyre symbolize the whole cosmos, * which without such constant warfare' would disintegrate and perish. 1 Well may he say (fr. 54): 'Invisible harmonia is stronger than (or
and the pegs used to tighten them. The pegs are turned in one direction, which is the opposite to that in which the strings are (as one might say) trying to turn them. This will be evident if a peg should work loose, when its string will turn the peg back until it has slackened itself. This destroys the dpuovbi, which was dependent on the balance of the opposite-turning forces and may appropriately be described as a TroXivrpoTroj Apuoviti. Efforts to explain the image in terms of the opposite tensions' created when the bow is being drawn or the lyre plucked have always led to difficulties. Vlastos is definitely wrong when he says (/oc. ct. 351) that the bow and lyre only yield a dynamic image if we assume that dpnoviti refers to their modus operandi. (See text.)
*
The phrase auu<pep<Hiivov SicapepripEvov occurs yet again in the exceedingly difficult fr. 10, and with other contrasting pairs is ultimately generalized in the sentence K TTCCVTGOV Iv Kod f v6$ mfcvTcc. I can add nothing useful to the careful and perceptive work of Snell and Kirk on this fragment, and I agree with them that the last sentence need imply no successive temporal stages in the formation of the cosmos, which would contradict the denial of cosmogony in fr. 30
(p. 454, below). One point in Kirk's interpretation makes me slightly uneasy. He regards the passive sense of ovAActyigs (which he adopts in preference to the ouvdyis? of DK's text) as made probable by the plural and 'justified by the very close analogy of ouAAapV (HCF
>
173).
Since these are two different verbal formations from the same root, mere seems to be little valid analogy between them. Verbal forms ending in -ens commonly indicate an action or process (&vyl$acris, xivqcns, etc.; and the plural Kiv^crgis is common enough). There are of course exceptions (&pocns in Homer, 960-15 and others), but the passive sense is much less frequent, and
(perhaps
more important)
apprehending or arresting.
440
The
superior to) visible/ As far as visible connexion goes, the bow might be naturally bent and the string simply tied to it at either end; the invisible connexion between them is the element of struggle, of dynamic
1 opposition. So it is that 'Nature loves concealment' (fr. I23). There is a standing temptation to interpret Heraclitus's statements
now
is
in this direction,
now
in
most ancient authorities as having believed that the whole cosmos arose from a different initial state, exists for a while and will then be resolved once more into its arche, especially since this was familiar to his readers as the stock conception from the Milesians onwards, which had been developed into an elaborate periodic scheme by Empedocles. But his own words put us on our guard against any such simple and unoriginal explanation. In view of all this one is justified in paying especial attention, not to the accounts which make him a conformist, but to any hint in our authorities that he was struggling, against the limitations
not surprising therefore that he
represented in
was so
of his language, to express something new and different. His thought difficult and to later antiquity unexpected, and his expression at
times so ambiguous, that it would have been no surprise if his ancient interpreters had missed the point entirely. But Plato grasped it, and from later antiquity there is a passage of Plutarch which although it is
most part only a paraphrase of Heraclitus, and makes use of the philosophical terminology of a later age, reveals in contrast to most
for the
contemporary testimony the true Heraclitean conception (De E, 3923-0; given by DK as fr. 91 of Heraclitus). Plutarch's speaker is
One cannot, according to Heraclitus, step twice into the same river, nor lay hold twice of any mortal substance in one permanent state. Owing to the
impetuosity and speed of change, it scatters and brings together again, or rather, not again, nor later, but at the same time it comes together and flows
retreats.
1 Or as Kirk more accurately renders it (HCF, 227): 'The real constitution of things is accustomed to hide itself/ It is, however, a real loss if we give up the pithy, Delphic style of Heraclitus's sayings, and the element of personification which was probably present.
441
Heraclitus
Heraclitus did not of course deny the occurrence of internal temporal changes within the universe hot becoming cold, age following on
youth and death on life and so forth. As we shall see, he cited them as in themselves part of the evidence for the identity of opposites. But To grasp aware. were 'the of even were which many' they something
the simultaneous operation of opposed tendencies
difficult
(ii)
and more
identity
essential.
The
at
offspring of night.
of opposites. Hesiod in his Theogony called day the This earned him the censure of Heraclitus, who hits
*
him and at his favourite target, the unenlightened multitude, wotds (fr. 57): Teacher of most men is Hesiod. They are sure he knew most things, a man who could not recognize day and night;
both
in the
1 for they are one.' Again, Porphyry, possibly making slight changes in Heraclitus's wording (see Kirk, i8o), attributes to him the statement
that to
some
God all things are good and fair and just, but men have assumed 5 to be unjust and others just (fr. 102). This statement has several sides, Including obviously a theological and a moral one, but for the
let
moment
men
habitually
separate and contrast are to be identified. Hippolytus mentions a number of contrasting pairs, of both nouns and adjectives, whose
identity he claims to have been asserted by Heraclitus, including 'good and bad'. He produces no actual quotation with these words, but cites
being both bad (painful) and good (curative).* The identity of good
by Aristotle (Top. I59b3o, It is unlikely that he stated it in so many words (cf. the
Simplicius passage quoted by Kirk, p. 95), but it is a reasonable inference from a fragment like 102. To argue that on these grounds he
many' or to tell them to follow the Logos, and bad are the same no kind of behaviour would be good better than any other, would be, as Kirk jusdy says, 'to show a grave lack of historical sense as well as an over-literal interpretation of
criticize 'the
had no right to
because
if
Heraclitus's language
1
106,
criticism
made
in the
same
context as
*
So much
both
58,
though in
and interpre88
,
tation
raise
many thorny
HCF
442
To
identity of opposites are paradoxical in the sense that they remain difficult to credit even when made explicit. buttress their credibility he also gave illustrations in which the
identity of what
is commonly contrasted might seem admissible to the once it is ordinary man, pointed out. Up and down are opposites, but, he says (fr. 60), 'The road up and the road down are one and the
use
same*. Since the meaning in this example is especially plain, we may it to help opr understanding of what he meant by *the same*.
not yet the absurd By baldly stating consequences of neglecting them, he unintentionally paved the way for their recognition. From one traverses the same ground as from to A^ but this
What was for him an exciting discovery was only possible at a thought when many logical distinctions, now obvious, had
stage of
become apparent.
AtoB
does not mean that to go in one direction is the same as to go in the other. The material road of earth and stones is the permanent substratum of both journeys, as philosophers would say from Aristotle on, and it is sometimes difficult to explain Heraclitus without resorting
to that 'anachronistic but convenient term'
(HCF^
197).
second example of this type is fr. 59: 'The track of writing is 1 straight and crooked/ The pen or stylus follows a straight line across
the page or tablet, but yet in the course of it traces out all sorts of convolutions in forming the letters. Once again a statement is seen to be (a) only an apparent paradox, and () to our minds only a very loose
and equivocal use of language. One of Heraclitus's ancient nicknames was 'The Riddler', and some of his statements do indeed bear a resemblance to children's riddles and are solved in a similar way.
('What
is it
that
3
is
at the
same time?
A line
of writing.')
1
Retaining as the first word the ypowpkov of the MSS., which has been convincingly defended by Kirk feyff.). In any case, as Kirk says (p. 104) Even if the reading yvopkov or yvcwpelcp (DK)
* :
were right and the reference were to a carding-roller or even a screw-press, the import of the fragment would remain roughly the same.' * Evidently he did like actual riddles. One that Hippolytus says he related is amusing enough to quote (fr. 56, and for the riddle in full see ps.-Plut. De Vita Horn. 4, quot. Walzer adfr.}. Homer, it runs, saw some children fishing, and asked them what luck they had had. They replied: What we have caught we left behind, and what we didn't catch we take with us.' The answer was that having got bored with catching no fish, they had been delousing each other. To Heraclitus the whole of nature was a riddle, in which the hidden meaning was more important than what
*
(frr.
123, 54).
443
Heraclitus
In the fragments so far quoted, Heraclitus teaches that two apparently contradictory things or epithets in the same genus are in fact identical:
and unjust, up and down, straight and crooked. Fr. 67 is more comprehensive and takes us further: 'God is day and and hunger "all night, winter and summer, war and peace, satiety
just
is
but he changes
2 just as fire,
when
it is
mingled with perfumes, is named according to the scent of each/ Just what Heraclitus understood by God must be left till later. For
present purposes
least
we may
he
is
'somehow
that here at accept Kirk's remark (p. 187) identified with or inherent in the whole world*.
collection of
with each other, but the whole apparently disparate phenomena displays to the discerning mind an essential
unity. This is the true Logos, listening to which 'it is wise to agree that all things are one'. The question which Kirk thinks worth raising
on one of the
described as
pairs mentioned,
fr.
namely
(p. 187):
"peace" when of and Homer was rebuked for his prayer that "strife may all", king from perish gods and men"?' does not really arise. Heraclitus uses
53 asserted that
words
This
is
in his
own
sense, a sense
which
that
is
war
men in their ignorance long for: rather is The man who said 'In changing it is at rest'
(fr. 84*2) would not have hesitated to say 'In war it is at peace*. On the level of common-sense, of course, war and peace succeed one another as do the other pairs in this saying; so however, on that level,
do change and
1
rest.
sensible one,
the
fragment.
is missing in the MSS. 'Fire* is the suggestion adopted by Diels. Another one is H. Frankers olive-oil*. Pkto in the Timaeus (5OE) describes how the makers of unguents took care to see that the liquid base to which the perfumes were to be added should be as free as possible from all scent of its own. Whichever noun we choose, the lesson of the fragment is the same. (Discussion and references in Kirk, 191 ff.) The notion of a permanent substratum which can assume different qualities is not far off in this sentence of Heraclitus. Fr. 7 ('If all existing things were to become smoke, the nostrils would distinguish them') may have a similar sense to fr. 67 and others indicating identity in difference. If all things turned to smoke, we should see only one thing (smoke), but the nose would distinguish their different scents. So Reinhardt, Farm. 180, n. 2, Gigon, 57.
5
The noun
attractive
444
The
'identity*
all
relationships,
of which he
of opposites includes for Heraclitus several different is aware of and explains or illustrates,
faith in his
all
'the
hunger and
satiety.
Relevant also
day and night, summer and winter, 126: 'Cold things grow hot, hot
things cold, moist dry, dry wet.' That this reciprocal change was to him evidence of identity is brought out by fr. 88: *The same thing in us (?) is
living and dead, and the waking and the sleeping, and young and old; for these things when they have changed are those, and those when they have 1 changed are these.'
The sea is the Relativity to the experiencing subject. So fr. 61 : and most and for drinkable fishes, undrinkpolluted water, salutary purest * able and deadly to men.' In this sense also Aristotle interprets fr. 9: Asses
()
would choose rubbish
rather than gold*,
namely
different things,
no
essential
between pleasant and unpleasant. 2 (c) In the sphere of values, opposites are only appreciated in relation to their opposites. Hence although men commonly call the one good and the other bad, neither would be good without the other. So fr. in: 'It is disease that makes health pleasant and good, hunger satiety, weariness rest.'
That this relationship amounted in Heraclitus's eyes to identity we may conclude from the identification of hunger and satiety in fr. 67, and possibly c also, with reference to weariness and rest, from the paradox of fr. 84*2: ln
3 changing it is at rest.' "What is said here adds point to the assertions of frr. no and 102 that it is not good for men to get all they want and that, whereas
1
It is
it is
but
last,
2 Arist. EN, 117635. Kirk, 81-6 treats the fragment in detail, though in view of his own conclusion about its purport (83-4) it seems a little hard to say that Aristotle's use of it has no bearing on its original context. Cf. also fr. 13: *Pigs take pleasure in mud rather than in clean water', which Sextus (Pyrrh. Hyp. 1, 55, Bywater on fr. 54) brings also into relation with fr. <5i. 3 84^ (xdiicnxSs Son TOIS ccOrots pox&slv Kod fipxioOcxi) is taken by Kirk (p. 252) and others to
as change is rest, so lack of change is weariness. But like Gigon I find ? the saying puzzling. What is to be made of UOX&TV xcd <5px (jeai * One would rather expect him to * say (on die lines of war and peace, hunger and satiety, etc. are the same*) that toil is rest rather than weariness. If lack of change is the only point, then one must stress TOIS oOroTs almost to the
fr
exclusion of the following words, and it would have been more to the point if Heraclitus had said T$ ccCrrqS nfrsiv, fipsuEiv or the like. Perhaps indeed the vagary is to be explained (as Kirk tenthe weariness of working always for tatively suggests) by the existence of a popular saying about the same master. This would be quite in Heraclitus's manner, but we know of no such saying.
445
Heraclitus
men
c
call
some
is
good. This
i.e.
things just and others unjust, to God all things are just and probably also the significance of the vaguely-worded fr. 23,
They
[sc*
men
these things [sc, recognize a "right" way because of the examples that they have of the existence of a "wrong" way.*
(</)
would not have known the name of right if wrong things] did not exist.' So Kirk (p. 129): 'Men only
in general]
'identical'
because only
different aspects of the same thing, the point at which Heraclitus gets nearest to the later distinction between permanent substratum and mutable characteristic.
but not
it is
one and
In the philosophers of Greece one can often detect not so much a completely original idea as the effect of a powerful, analytical mind on a mode of thought typical of the age. The Heraclitean doctrine of
the simultaneity of opposites and its paradoxical consequences is the result of intense concentration on a mental phenomenon common in
the early Greek world, to which the name 'polarity' has been given. c Thus for example H. Frankel writes of a thought-form which after
was the dominant one, namely the polar mode of thought: qualities cannot be conceived
Homer,
War
an obvious consequence of much that we have seen already, and is stated in fr. 53 :' War is father of all and king of all, and some he reveals as gods, others as men, some he makes slaves, others free.' By calling War 'father and king of all', Heraclitus deliberately recalls
This
is
and so suggests that War, not Zeus, is the has been supreme god. thought that here he has only in mind the limited, literal sense of war, though of course using it as an illustration
titles
Homer's
for Zeus,
It
of the universal
fits
conflict
which
for
it
him
makes some slaves and others free, but leaves the mention of gods and men more difficult to explain.3
1
fr.
48: *The
name of
the
bow (165)
an
is life (pio$),
is
essential attribute
named. See Kirk, 116-22. Dlchtung u. Pkilos. desfruhen Griecftentums, 77. 3 See Kirk, 246 flf. To read into this brief phrase a reference to the apotheosis of those in battle, even if Heraclitus believed in this, seems a little far-fetched.
446
'
War is
Father of'All*
Whatever the reason, the statement does look as if it were confined to gods and men and their affairs. Apart from the second half of the
fragment, the reminiscence of the Homeric Zeus, Father of gods and * men', suggests that the word all* is masculine. But he may yet be thinking of war in its wider aspect, as creating opposition and tension
c
between opposed
fr.
classes
everywhere, of which gods-men, slavesIn any case the general principle is stated in
80:
all
One must know that war is common, and justice strife, and that things come about by way of strife and necessity/ With this must
be taken a passage from Aristotle (EE^ 1235 a25 ? DK, 22A22) which runs: *And Heraclitus rebukes the poet who wrote "Would that
1 might perish from among gods and men"; for there would be no melody without high and low, nor living creatures without male
strife
and female, which are opposites.' Simplicius adds the comment, after the line from Homer, 'For he [Heraclitus] says that everything would
2
disappear/
By
At
is
common*
(more probably the same time he gets in another covert attack on Homer, who had also called war common*. Homer's line 3 says that war strikes down all
*
slain*.
It is
c
blows impartially
all
round.
respecter of Common*, as we
no
now know,
by
alluding to
profundity had escaped him. War is common because the Logos that is the law of all becoming (fr. i) is a law of strife, of simultaneous opposite tensions. 'That strife
is
universal follows from the assumption that whatever exists is in 4 change with the added assumption that all change is strife.' In saying
is strife he probably shows himself aware also of Anaximander's teaching (pp. 76 ff., above), which branded the warfare of the opposites as a series of acts of injustice. On the contrary,
Horn.
//.
For
//.
later versions
xvin, 107. of Heraclitus's rebuke, which omit the reference to high and low, male
309 uv6j *Evu<ic\ios xod -re KTocvfovra Kcniiaa. The phrase was copied by Archi38 Diehl). Possibly this is one reason for the censure of Homer and Archilochus together in fr. 42 that they could utter such words and yet remain ignorant of the true Logos.
3
xvm,
(fr.
Vlastos,
AJP,
1955, 357.
447
Heraclitus
retorts Heraclitus, it is the highest justice.
Once again an
erring pre-
tacitly corrected. The kernel of Heraclitus's quarrel with other thinkers seems to lie in his revolt against their ideal of a peaceful and harmonious world.
is
decessor
This was in particular the ideal of Pythagoras, of whom, it is relevant to remember, he speaks more than once with particular harshness
(see especially p. 417, above).
state
was
one in which opposite qualities were so blended by a law of proportion that their oppositions were neutralized and they produced, for example, euphony in music, health in the body, kosmos order and beauty in
the Universe as a whole. These states of peace between elements which had been at war, brought about by the imposition of limit (peras) on
were
evil.
Heraclitus rejects
'
pusillanimous.
belong' (Aet. I, themselves no more good than their opposites, and their goodness only appears when set against these opposites. The co-existence of
all these value judgments, which seem to him Rest and quiet? Leave them to the dead, where they 23, 7, DK, 22A6). Health, peace, rest, he says, are in
what a Pythagorean would regard as good and bad states is necessary and right. *To God all things are good and fair and just/ In fact it is all a matter of point of view, and good and bad are entirely relative notions. Sea-water is pure and good to fishes, foul and poisonous to men.
no
reluctance
to be blended in a harmonia, but found rest3 and, as one might say, contentment when they were contributing to a perfect krasis, as in a
This possibility is strengthened by the addition of the words xal TO xp&v at the end of the (a) this is the correct text and () the words KOTO T6 xpecov in Anaximander's fr. i genuinely belong to him. 3 Some scholars will say that we know too little of the opinions of Pythagoras to make statements like this. That the ideas are Pythagorean they might admit, but would argue that we cannot know whether they were current before the late fifth century. However, unless we are going to deny any original ideas to Pythagoras himself (in which case it is a little difficult to account for his reputation), his teaching must have been on these lines. The full justification for attributing them to Pythagoras (or at least an early generation of his followers, contemporary with Heraclitus) lies of course in the earlier chapter on the Pythagoreans, where each reader must assess it for himself. For a contrary view to that here given see Kirk, HCF, 218 f. 3 In the Pythagorean table of opposites (p. 245, above), resting* (fjpeiiouv) is to be found on the 'good* side, along with Tripos, 9005:, dyo06v ? etc.
fr., if
*
448
have reached a
adjustment of opposite tensions* is what locked, as it were, in an internecine struggle keeps in being the
opposites,
in an
whose union
world as we
know
is
it.
(3)
Everything
in continuous motion
and change
The doctrine that 'harmony is of opposites* has already led to this conclusion, which Heraclitus drives home once again with a familiar illustration. well-known drink or posset in Greece from Homer's time onwards was the kykeon^ made by taking a cup of wine and stirring
into
it barley and grated cheese. These of course would not dissolve, so that the mixture had to be kept in motion until the moment it was
not being stirred/ 1 Kirk's comment on this fragment cannot be improved on: 'The fragment is of greater importance than at first appears: it is the only
drunk. 'The kykeon\ he said,
'falls
apart if
it is
was
Heraclitus's declared
even though only in an image' (but this way of announcing the most fundamental
truths, p. 414, above), 'the consequences of an interruption in the The illustration itself was not so entirely reciprocity of
opposites/
homely as it might seem, for in addition to other uses the kykeon was drunk at the Eleusinian mysteries in commemoration of the myth of Demeter, who would accept no other refreshment during her sad search for the lost Persephone. This would give it a special significance
in Heraclitus's eyes.
1
Fr. 125. On the text see Kirk, 255 Horn. HymnDem. 210, Clem. AL Protr. 1, 16 St., Nilsson, Gesch. Gr.Ret. 1, 622 f. For Heracfitus and the mysteries cf. p. 425, n. i, above.
,
449
Heraclitus
One
river twice/
of his most famous sayings is: 'You cannot step into the same 1 Plutarch (Qu. Nat. 9120) adds the explanation, which
1 given by Heraclitus himself: 'for fresh waters are flowing on'. Concerning the meaning of this parable our authorities are pretty well agreed. Plato (Crat. 402 A) says that it is an allegory of
and
its
lesson
is
'that everything
moves on
and nothing
is
at rest'.
That
this
was
and
he repeats that in the view that crowd' all things move 'like
still a young man, became and 'the Heraclitean theories that all sensible
things are for ever flowing *;3 and reflexion on these theories led him to the conclusion that knowledge of the sensible world was impossible.
Since he could not tolerate abandoning the possibility of knowledge altogether, this gave rise to the characteristically Platonic doctrine of
transcendent Forms.
is
mentioned
See Appendix, pp. 488 ff., below. The statement of the flux-doctrine which has become almost canonical in later ages, Trdvroc E!, occurs in the ancient authorities only in Simplicius (Phys. 1313.11), and is unlikely to have been a saying of Heraclitus.
Plato was fond of calling Homer the ancestor of certain philosophical theories because he spoke of Oceanus and Tethys, gods of water, as parents of the gods and of all creatures (//. xiv, 201, 246; see Craf. 4028, Theaet.loc. c*V., I52E, i8oc-D). Aristotle followed him (Metaph. A, 983 b 30), and neither of them can be supposed to have been very serious in this. Plato, as Ross * remarks on the Metaphysics passage, jestingly suggests that Heraclitus and his predecessors derived their philosophy from Homer, Hesiod and Orpheus*, and he adds that Aristotle himself admits that the suggestion has no great historical value. (This is an understatement. See also
p. 56, n. i, above.) The reference to'Ourjpov xcd *Hp<5xAiTOV xod TTOV r6 TOIOUTOV <pGXov suggests a similar levity, but the nature and frequency of Plato's allusions to the 'flux* theory of Heraclitus
*
and his followers are a guarantee of his sincerity. Admittedly he liked to make game of them for it (e.g. Theaet. I79E KOT& T& cruyypdpiiocTa 9ipovrai; at 181 A he calls the philosophers themselves ot 4ovTE$), but there was a basis for his jibes. Moreover we have the testimony of Aristotle that he took it seriously, and indeed that it was a formative influence on his own philosophy.
3 Metaph. 987332. Cratylus, Aristotle tells us (ibid. 1010313), carried the views of Heraclitus * to their logical extreme by correcting the sentence You can't step into the same river twice* to 'You can't step into it once*. Between the instant when your foot touched the surface and the
when it reached the bottom the river at that point had already changed. Cratylus was a Heraclitean heretic (one of TOOV 9ooic6vToov fipoocXEiTijeiv as Aristotle calls them) who was so carried away by the idea of uninterrupted change that in the end he thought it best not to speak (presuminstant
ably because to make a statement about anything would give a spurious impression of permanence : by the time the statement was out of his mouth its object would have changed), but only waggled his finger! Although the continuous motion and change of sensible things was a dogma of
Heraclitus,
it
was not
D.
J.
Allan in
AJP
450
in a state of
the earliest natural philosophers] held that in general everything becoming and flux, and that nothing is stable, but that there
persists,
is
is
these things have evolved natural transformations. This seems to have been the meaning both
all
out of which
by
of
(How
Heraclitus
off!) In the Physics he not that some things are in motion and
is
our perception.'
particular form,
cliteans, and, as
always moving, though this escapes Here we have the doctrine in its more strict and
refer (with Simplicius) to the
which we must
Kirk says
Hera-
Trying
to explain their meaning, Aristotle says it is like the argument (which he thinks fallacious) about a stone being worn away by of water
drops
or
the roots of a plant. According to this argument, if we notice that over a period of months the drops have made a visible
split
by
it
removed an
Aristotle's
be
seen. It is plain
from
Mo
this
question complaint not define the kind of motion they are talking about', that illustration was not used by Heraclitus. Nevertheless it seems
that
the
thinkers
in
to represent just
what he had
must imagine
rather than separate drops. That the rock is changing every instant we cannot see with our eyes, but it is what their evidence suggests if we
apply 'minds that understand the language*. To supplement their evidence we need that understanding (voo$) which few men have but which is essential if the senses are not to lead us astray, for by itself
the eyesight
is
deceptive
is
(frr.
imperceptible change Heraclitus did not use this simile, but he said the same thing
107, 46, 40; and c 104). The continuous a natural inference from the observation.
by means
of the image of the bow and lyre. The strung bow appears static to the would be only the consequence eyes, but if the string should snap, that
451
Heraclitus
Df what the
all
known
the time: that its true condition had been a continuous putting forth of effort in contrary directions, corresponding to the abrasive action of 1 the water and the resistance offered by the hardness of the stone.
doctrine of the continuous change of physical things is closely linked with that of the identity of opposites, as appeared in particular
The
from
fr.
is
a to I
parently change into something else before must have been in a way the same
fresh conclusions
is cyclic, from mind what could apand then back into what it was
all the time. He is drawing from a common Greek conception on which the Milesians had already relied, the circularity of time, based on observation of the recurrence of seasonal changes year after year. Cold
summer
gives
way
is
1 I am truly sorry to adopt an interpretation which in the eyes of Kirk is Very far indeed from the truth* and 'entirely contrary to what Heraclitus tells us in the fragments" (pp. 376 f.). 'Our observation', he says, 'tells us that this table or that rock are not changing at every instant; there is nothing in nature to persuade us that they are so changing; the very idea would be repulsive
The fragments that he cites in support of this are 107, 55, 101 a, and for comparison 17 and 72. 55 must, however, be read in the light of the important proviso in 107, and 17 and 72 seem to support the interpretation given here. The whole misunderstanding, Kirk thinks, arose from Plato's assertion that according to the Heracliteans 'everything is undergoing every motion all the time', which he considers a disastrous misinterpretation. To speak of 'every motion* is no doubt to import distinctions which Heraclitus had not consciously made: thinkers like him, says Aristotle, did not define the kind of motion they had in mind. But with that trivial qualification I believe that Plato was right. This would seem the place to say also that I believe not only that the flux doctrine was true for Heraclitus, but also that it occupied a central position in his thought: in short that Plato, as knowledge of him would lead one to expect, had a pretty good insight into Heraclitus's mind, and did not go seriously astray even in the matter of emphasis. I know that this will seem reactionary to more than one scholar for whom I have great respect.
to Heraclitus.'
how Heraclitus is
it
Snell for instance writes (Hermes, 1926, 376; I translate): 'Only now will it become quite clear misinterpreted when he is made the teacher of TTCCVTOC el.* I can only say that
has not become clear to me. Of course Trdvra >t is not the whole of his message, but, as I hope to show, the other side of the picture is the confining of change within measures, not (at least in the sensible world) the exaltation of stability (for there is none) at the expense of change. 'The
dominating idea in Heraclitus is rest in change, not change in apparent stability.' So Kirk, paraphrasing Reinhardt's view. But what Heraclitus says in fr. 840 is that for this world change is rest, which, as I hope I have shown already, is something different. To put it briefly, I find that from Plato onwards all our authorities attribute to Heraclitus the
ob$ <5rm5nnxov TCOV daeiyro&v dd fcdvrcav. Those who take the prima fade improbable line that Plato grossly misunderstood him and every subsequent Greek interpreter meekly followed his lead, in spite of possessing either Heraclitus's book or at least a much more comprehensive
doctrine
collection of his sayings than we have, may be expected to produce incontrovertible evidence from the fragments that their conclusion is inescapable. But in fact the extant fragments offer no
452
have
its
year. Anaximander spoke of the warfare and mutual 'injustice' of the opposites, followed inevitably by reparation, and in Heraclitus it takes
new
turn.
Three passages
him a statement
that
each of the four elements, as they were called later, 'lives the death' of another, or that the death of one is birth for another. Marcus Aurelius
become water, and the death of water to become aer, and of aer to become fire, and the reverse'. In Maximus of Tyre we have: 'Fire lives the death of earth and aer lives the death of fire, water lives the death of aer, earth that of water.' These statements are rejected by most modern scholars, chiefly on the ground
puts
it
that
'it is
among the
'elements', and
it is
generally believed
is
Its absence from frr. 31 and 36 taken as confirmation of their inaccuracy, though this point has been countered by Gigon. 2 Without necessarily sharing these doubts, we
first
was
done by Empedocles.
leave the statements in question in view of the impressive consensus of opinion against their authenticity, and turn to another set of passages in which the cycle of natural changes is described, in particular
may
frr.
31 and 36.
At
1
However, we cannot well approach these fragments immediately. this point one feels acutely the difficulty of reducing the 'barbed
reference, devoid of context, to 'the seasons which produce all things* may be an indication that Heraclitus explicitly acknowledged the source of the general conception (see fr. 100, discussed in detail by Kirk, 2943".).
together
Gigon, Unters. %u H. 99. The three passages (the third is from Plutarch) are grouped as fr. 76. The mention of <Wjp was held to condemn them by Zeller (ZN, 85o), by and although Nestle disagreed (85 1, n. i), most scholars have followed Zeller, including in recent times Snell (Hermes, 1926, 361, n.) and Kirk (see his full discussion, 342*?".), but not Gigon. The three versions are differently worded, and there is no means of knowing whether any one of them reproduces Heraclitus with complete verbal accuracy. Probably not, but I do not think the * mention of <Wjp is necessarily a blunder. Heraclitus had no theory of elements*, whether three or he may just as well its transformations four. Only fire had a certain primacy, and in describing have mentioned <5rf|p as earth or water. His description of change is based on observation, and in has a natural place as an intermediate particular on the phenomenon of evaporation, in which <W|p does not, mean 'air*. stage between water and fire. The word need not, indeed most frequently The Loeb translator of Plutarch in the relevant passage (De E, 3920) translates it with some
DK
Kahn's AnaximandeT has appeared. I agree with his defence of the but Milesian, and the word is fragment on p. 152, n. i, where he writes: 'The <Wjp is not Stoic, used in the regular sense by Xenophanes, Anaxagoras, and Empedocles.' See the whole note and
its
context.
453
Heraclitus
arrows* of Heraclitus to an exposition in continuous prose, which of a time, when what is necessity deals with points successively, one at
wanted
earlier
spoke second of which was that everything is constantly changing, while the third described the cosmos as fire. In fact these are different aspects of the same truth, but to state them
is
of three
together calls for the style of the Delphic oracle or Heraclitus himself. It will therefore be best to introduce now the notion of the cosmic fire,
in terms of which the further statements of the law of change between
1 opposites are made.
(c)
The world an
Fr. 30 is a
ever-living fire
pronouncement 'solemn,
its
elaborate,
and portentous,
style
which
reveals
The monumental
This world-order [kosmos\ the same for all, 2 none of the gods nor of men has made, 3 but it was always and is and shall be: 4 an ever-living fire, which is
being kindled in measures and extinguished in measures.
Cf. Walzer, Eracfito, 71 : 'Soltanto merce" la dottrina delle cose opposte il ruoco diviene una entita equivalente al cosmo.' 2 TOV OCUTOV ccrrdvTcov. Rejected by Reinhardt, Kirk follows, but Vlastos (AJP^ 1955,
1
whom
345 with n. 18) believes the words genuine. For the genitive cf. w6v drrdvrcov in fr. 1 14. Drawing attention to this fragment, Vlastos takes dnrdirrew as masculine. The real world is 'the same for
opposed to the dream-worlds which most men make up for themselves (pp. 430 , above). (JJnters. 55) understood the phrase more widely: this order is 'the same for everything* (alle exzstierende Wesen), i.e. for all the things comprehended in it. Kirk (309) asks what then will be the point of -r6v our6v. I think myself that this translation quite probably represents Heraditus's mind, and it is the one which occurred to me independently. The 'order* in question is, as we know, an arrangement of opposite and warring tensions, a 'harmony of opposites* which is universal (TOV ocOrov dcrrdvTcov). To emphasize its universality is not superfluous because the ordinary man perceives it only in a few things and is quite unaware of it in others. He cuts himself off from "the common*.
all*,
as
Gigon
(Walzer, p. 70, n. 4), as in Anaxagoras, fr. 12 irdvra 8i6x6anot of course creation ex rdhilo, an idea quite foreign to Greek thought, but only the creation of Kckrpos out of previous disorder. The denial is no doubt primarily aimed at the parcelling out of the world into sky, sea and earth, symbolized by the distribution (6oTu6s) between the chief gods, of which the old poets spoke (//. xv, 187 ff., Hes. Th. 74, 885). This is the kind of thing that the masses believe because they have no more sense than to listen to the popular bards (fr. 104). Kirk (311) rightly notes that the addition of (Jcvftpcfcrrcov is formulaic and has no significance. 4 The reasons adduced by Kirk (jiof.) for punctuating with a colon after Harm seem
KdKTiiov.
.
.rroiT}oi
= 5tK6opiTjCT
is
p,T)0E
vouj.
What is
denied here
convincing.
454
'the natural
has been discussed earlier (p. 208, n. i). It it' (Kirk, 317). The notion of
is still essential, and that is one reason why this seems decisive the from Stoic derived fragment against assumption, and all later he accounts of that Theophrastus Heraclitus, pervading
order or arrangement
believed in a periodic destruction of the world by a general conflagration. The formulation of Diogenes Laertius (ix, 8) may be taken
as typical: 'The cosmos is born out of fire and again resolved into fire 5 in alternate periods for ever. It could be argued that the essential
substance of the universe, which Heraclitus after all called 'fire', was not destroyed or brought into being by the alternation of conflagration and renewal of the world, but only altered in its manifestations.
type of cosmogony Aristotle wrote (De Caelo, 280 an): *As for the view that the world is alternately put together and dissolved,
this
Of
as if
just the same as making it eternal, only changing its shape. It is one were to regard the coming-to-be of a man from a child and a child from a man as involving at one stage destruction and at another
that
is
be of the primary substance, is equated with the kosmos of the existing world it becomes impossible to call it 'ever-living' and at the same time speak
true that
existence/ Yet
however
may
it
Although the question whether Heraclitus believed in a periodic on which ecpyrosis (destruction of the cosmos by fire) is a difficult one, universal agreement will never be reached, the view will be taken here
and must override obscurer and that certain fragments, which have testimony, been thought to imply ecpyrosis^ must be interpreted in its light. Such are fr. 65, which says that Heraclitus called fire 'want and satiety ? and
that
fr.
30
is
all later
'
66:
is
For fire, he
says, will
also the phrase 'from all things one and from one all things' in the difficult fr. 10. Fr. 65 seems to be no more than another statement of
the identity of opposites, like the list in fr. 67, where 'the god' (who may be safely equated with the living fire) is identified with satiety and
pairs.
Fr. 66
455
Heraclitus
Its language is in any case figurative, and if Heraclitus wrote he need only have meant to emphasize the primacy of fire and the truth that at some time everything must become fire, which shows up
359-61).
it
speaks of an
unnamed
thinker,
with
justice.)
In the same
way
who must be
that Heraclitus 'said that everything at not have had ecpyrosis in mind. 1
fire*,
need
The
originality of Heraclitus (I
would
repeat)
his
expression of it so difficult, that any hint of a less usual interpretation may be given extra prominence against the mass of later testimony
which would make him conform to the expected. Such a hint is Aet. n, * Heraclitus says that the cosmos is subject to 4, 3 (DK, 22Aio):
generation not in time but conceptually.' The later phrasing reflects the controversy over the genesis of the world in Plato's Timaeus
it
literally
or figuratively
and the
But
difference
of course to a
interesting
more
it is
that, in spite
words did suggest to someone at least that the cosmos was not at any time brought into being from a different state of things. Plutarch, too,
Whether or not Chemiss is right (ACP^ 29, n. 108) in taking trup as subject and forocvra as no necessary reference to ecpyroszs, for even without it everything at some time becomes fire (note the present) in the course of the constant change that is going on in the cosmos. That Aristotle did, however, adopt the ecpyrosis view of Heraclitus is very probable. Cf. Kirk, 321 f. Certainly that view was taken by Theophrastus and after him by the Stoics, who
predicate, there is
1
On pp. 335ff. Kirk summarizes the arguments for and impossible. Since he wrote, ecpyrosis in Heraclitus has been defended once again by Mondolfo in Phronesis^ 1958, 7582. One of the strongest pieces of evidence against it has always been Plato, SopL 2420 (p. 437, above, and see Burnet, EGP,
adopted
against
it as
their
own
(Kirk, 3i8ff.).
it
it.
He
himself believes
I58), Mondolfo endeavours to argue that even this passage is consistent with ecpyrosis, on the ground that fire is in itself a unity of opposites for Heraclitus, therefore the simultaneous convergence and divergence insisted on by Plato would in fact be maintained even if fire had absorbed
all
literal conflagration.
convince. Part at least of the evidence for the contradictions inherent in fire, in Heraclitus's eyes, was the everlasting maintenance of balance (iJ^rpa) in its changes, whereby an absorption into
literal fire in one part of the cosmos is inevitably counteracted by a quenching of it into vapour or water in another part. A destruction of this balance would be incompatible with the unity of opposites in fire, and is therefore unthinkable for Heraclitus. (Kirk has replied to Mondolfo in
Pkronesisy 1959, 73-6.) That Heraclitus believed in a temporal beginning and end of the present cosmos has been most recently argued by Kahn (AnaximanJer^ 225 .)- He, however, is convinced that the eternity of the world-order is a purely Aristotelian invention, a thesis that is difficult to sustain.
456
The Doctrine of
'JEcpyrosis
makes a character in a dialogue say: *I see the Stoic ecpyrosis spreading over the works of Hesiod as over those of Heraclitus and Orpheus*
(Def. Or. 415 F).
Moreover, Theophrastus and the writers who followed him would have quoted supporting statements from Heraclitus himself if they could; but what they do quote seems rather to weaken their view. In
Simplicius for instance
we
find this: 1
'Hippasus of Metapontum and Heraclitus of Ephesus also believed the substance of the universe to be single, in motion, and finite; but
arche,
made
fire
the
and out of fire they produce existing things by thickening and thinning, and resolve them into fire again, on the assumption that fire is the one underlying physis'y for Heraclitus says that
all
fire'.
The
statement that
all
quoted below, pp. 460 f.), and would hardly be adduced today to support the
fire is
as Heraclitus's
things are an exchange for (or exchanged for) by other authorities (see fr. 90, discussed
alternate destruction
and rebirth of
general grounds also it is unlikely that anyone devising a cosmology on Milesian lines would have chosen as arche an extreme like
fire. The arche of the Milesians was always something intermediate between two opposites, owing to their assumption that it contained and concealed both members of the pairs of opposites which could
On
from
it
air,
*
by later writers as something rarer than water but denser 2 than air'. Whether or not he thought of the apeiron in this way (and
described
it
seems a rather naive objectification of what was in fact a remarkably subtle conception), it must be true that Anaximander regarded the
of things as something neutral and therefore mediate: he seems to have seen even more clearly than the others that it could not be qualified by any one of the opposites in actuality.
Fire
initial state
not contain
1
own
an opposite itself, an extreme, which does it ever existed solely in opposite, and could not, if
is
Pkys. 23.33-24.4, quoted Dox. 4755. as from Theophr. Phys. Opinions. E.g. Alexander, in Metaph. 60.8 Hayduck: rfjv 'Avaip<5cv5pov 66av, 6s &PX^1 V SOero TTJV |iTav 9uaiv dpo$ TE Kal irupos ^ depos TE KOC! u5aros- Aeyerai y&p d^oTEpco*.
3
457
Heraclitus
the form
into
two
opposites.
his
of what Heraclitus could or could not have thought are reinforced by own statements of the inevitable coexistence of opposites. 1
Some, of whom Zeller was one, have connected the ecpyrosis with the idea of a Great Year, mentioned earlier in connexion with the Pythagoreans (p. 282, above). It is attested for Heraclitus by more than
its length is said to have been of the Great Year along with In this estimate 10,800 years. giving those of others, Censorinus also gives its definition as the time in which
moon and planets return together to the same positions as they 3 occupied at a given previous time. He then introduces into his account
the sun,
the Stoic ecpyrosi$) saying that in the summer of the Great Year the universe is burned up, and in the winter it is destroyed by flood, 4 It is likely enough that Heraclitus himself connected the astronomical
cycle with a cyclic renewal of the universe, as did the Pythagoreans with their disturbing notion of an exact repetition of history. If so, he most probably had in mind, as Vlastos has put it, 'the time required " " for every part of the fire which takes the downward turn at any given moment to return to its source, or, to look at it the other way round, the
interval after
which every part of water and earth existing at any given time wiU have been replaced '.5 Such a cycle can of course be imagined
1 That fire *is* the opposites does not invalidate this view, as I have argued against Mondolfo on p. 456, ru i. The cosmic fire, equated with divinity, is day and night, summer and winter, etc., precisely because it appears in these contrasting forms, kindled in measures and extinguished in measures*. To equate it with physical re alone is impossible, 3 Censorinus, De Die Nat. xvm, 1 1 and Act. n, 32, 3 (latter as emended by Diels, DK, 22 A 1 3). 3 cum ad idem signum ubi quondam simidfuerunt tma referuntur. Even though Censorinus be muddled in his examples, there is really no evidence at all for separating Heraclitus's Great Year from the majority by giving it a human rather than a cosmic reference. See Kirk, 300 and
*
Vlastos,
4
in Aristotle,
composition of the number io,Soo. He thinks that the ease with which this cycle of worldrenewal could be mistaken for the commoner cycle of world-creation and destruction is probably
what led Aristode astray. That Theophrastus was also misled he doubts, quoting as the only words to be attributed to him on the subject these from Simpl. (Pkys. 24.4): -rroigt S Keel TOCIV TIVOC Kcd xpovov copicrij^vov T% TOU Kocrjiou HTcc{3oAf}$. This could indeed be a statement of what
we have just put forward as the actual belief of Heraclitus, but its context gives a rather different impression. J. B. McDiarmid has also expressed the opinion that Theophrastus did not share Aristotle's mistake (Tk. on the. Presoc. Causes, n, 28, pp.
458
Cyclic
as starting
Change and
the
Great Year
likes to choose, a
feature
tied.
and finishing at any moment that one which it shares with the astronomical
parallel to
which
it
was
Returning to fr. 30, we notice first that the fire which is the cosmos is not only everlasting, but ever-living, which prepares us for its identifi-
shows
cation with psyche^ the life-principle. The last clause of the fragment how the paradoxical expressions of Heraclitus resulted from the
of the ideas he was trying to express. Fire in its normal exists when it is : kindled acceptation extinguish it and there is no longer fire. But fire in the generally accepted sense is not what Heraclitus
difficulty
intends
by the word:
tells
us that he
is
not asking us
to accept a factual paradox, or flat contradiction of the evidence of our senses, by supposing the world to be a perpetual bonfire like the burning
bush of Moses. The ever-living fire of the cosmos is being kindled (the present participle is used) and extinguished in measures. I agree with
Kirk against Gigon (to mention only two of the latest partisans in a long controversy) that the general sense of the fragment is all against
understanding these measures temporally as successive periods affecting the whole world. Heraclitus is describing the cosmos in its present
state, which is sustained in two ways, to which we have already been introduced as aspects of the identity of opposites. First, in different parts of the world it is being alternately kindled (becoming fire in the
form of water or
popular sense, or an even hotter vapour) and extinguished (taking the earth), and all within fixed measures or limits which
ensure the balance of opposites necessary to the maintenance of universal cosmic order. Secondly, it is maintained in the subtle way which
Heraclitus found so difficult to express and which
is
bution to cosmological theory: by the simultaneous interaction of contrary forces tending in opposite directions, as in the structure of
the
bow
theory
He
fire
Heraclitus
was the
D.L.
arche or element (oroixelov; I am following the version of ix, 8), out of which other substances were formed, as in Anaxi-
menes, by condensation and rarefaction. Since he immediately adds: 'But he explains nothing clearly ', we may feel justified in departing from this interpretation if we will. Diogenes Laertius does however
reproduce some of Heraclitus's terminology, and
that the
we
learn
from him
the same',
'way up and down', which Hippolytus tells us was 'one and was the name given by Heraclitus to the process of change. 1 Putting together these two references to the way up and down, we find them echoed by Plato in the words: Everything is always flowing 2 upwards and downwards/ In the light of other fragments (especially
'
51),
'stricter
Muses' in Soph.
242 D
what
later
it is
drawing
together'), this
as the prosaic
and
rational
some
Greeks thought, that some things are on the upward path while are on the downward, but that all things are moving both upIt is
not surprising that Aristotle accused Heraclitus of breaking the law of contradiction; or rather (since to his logical mind such a thing seemed impossible) said that some people
supposed him to be doing so. 'It is impossible for anyone to suppose that the same thing is and is not, as some people think Heraclitus said'
(Metaph. 1005 b 23)^ The way up and down
is
forms of matter, and presumably things made by their mixture, into one another. Heraclitus did not of course use the word 'element'
(oroixelov) of
also quoted
fire,
but the
way
in
which he expressed
fully
its
primacy
is
by
Plutarch
(fr.
90): 'All
6S6v fivco xdroo. I see no good evidence to make us reject this statement as Kirk would have us do, though he says himself (p. 328) that *the specific physical application of these terms would not, it is true, be unsuitable*.
PJulebus, 43 A (not assigned by name to Heraclitus, but impossible to attribute to anyone but him or his true followers). Kirk in his discussion of this sentence says that in its context it refers to changes of fortune, but this is not correct: the reference is purely general. I have given reasons already for trusting what Plato says about Heraclitus. The strongest is that from Aristotle
*
their best to
make him
whereas Plato's remarks, casual though they are, give the clue to his originality; and that he was original stares us in the face from every fragment. * 3 Aristotle perhaps had in mind fr. 490: We step and do not step into the same rivers, we are and are not*, on which see Appendix, p. 490.
460
The
Way Up
and Down
things are an exchange for fire and fire for all things, as goods for gold and gold for goods/ 1 Once more he can only express himself by a simile, and hence to some degree imprecisely, but if he had wanted to describe fire as simply the basic substance which changed its shape or
appearance in becoming earth or water he would have used a different comparison. (He could easily have said, for example, 'as gold is
fashioned into coins, necklaces or cups'.) In mercantile transactions the essential thing is parity of value: a certain quantity of gold will buy a certain quantity of goods. This is no doubt the primary thought,
in
mind, as Kirk says, die single homo(fire) as opposed to the manifold kinds of
goods (physical things) for which it can be exchanged. We need not expect Heraclitus's thought to be by our standards
completely logical or self-consistent. From what we know of him that would be surprising. He seems to be saying that although in the cosmos as he sees it fire has a definite primacy, grounded in its divinity
and perpetual
life,
yet
it
is
same though
changing in its modifications. Such a permanent physis would contradict the law of flux, and introduce rest and stability into a world from
which he thought they should be banished. There was law in the universe, but it was not a law of permanence, only a law of change, or, in something more like his own picturesque phraseology, the law of the
jungle, since everything
War is
lord of
Fire
all.
flame may particularly well suited to embody this law, in it is and as a but candle, unchanging, appear steady constantly re-
was
newing
itself
by
sometimes smoke. The river-statement expresses the same truth, of apparent, or formal, stability coupled with continuous change of material.*
Heraclitus also expresses his conception of change
1
by saying
that
See on
this
fr.
Kirk, 345-8.
what sounds like a reminiscence of Heraclitus, links the flow of water and of flame together in a comparison expressive of continuous change within the limits of the same form and quantity: <5cd y&p SXXo xcd &XAo ytyveroi TO\>TGOV eKorarov [sc. air, fresh water, and fire], TO 6* eI5os TOU ifkffiovs IKOIOTOV TO\>TCOV U^VEI, Kcxe&rrEp T6 TCOV fcdvroov 05<5rroov xcd TO Tffe 9Xoyos jSev/na, Meteor. 3 57 b 30 (Kirk, 379 ).
It is interesting that Aristotle, in
461
Heraclitus
each form of matter makes
its
We
76,
the various forms of the suspected 5 'souls substituted for the expected
in this
fr.
c
fire'.
way of the death of the elements, although they contrasted the eternal nature of the arche with the arising and passing away of the
transitory things
its
modifications.
Heraclitus
was
is
clearly
groping
something
different,
though
to say "groping*
modern demand for rational and intellectual justification. To himself he was one who had discovered the divinelyit. appointed truth, and was therefore divinely charged to proclaim He had not Aristotle's severe eye for the law of contradiction, and
to betray the
We know
that fire
was
intelligent
and
vital.
life,
brings a
dimming
(save
of the flame of
and of life
mark
in his misconception of the arche) when he says that for Heraclitus the arche was not only fire, but psyche, and that he described psyche as an
of Heraclitus's physical theory, e.g. fr. 12 (p. 434, above) : Souls are exhaled from moist things.' 1 According to Diogenes, Heraclitus * reduces nearly everything to exhalation from the sea', and this, he
says, is the
2 upward way. The
sun,
to
be
quenched every night and renewed the next day (fr. 6), and also the 5 stars, consist of 'bright exhalations from the sea collected in certain
If
'bowls' or cavities in the sky, where they turn to flame (D.L. ix, 9). we may trust this, it gives us some idea of the process involved in
* 5
1
the death and birth of the elements mentioned in fr. 36, which seems to
Whether
Heraclitus used the
word
dva0un{aai$ is doubtful.
See Burnet,
EGP,
151, n. 2
and Kirk, 274. Kirk thinks dr^s a more probable word for him. * Diogenes continues with a reference to the theory (expounded by Aristotle) of two kinds of exhalation, a bright one from the sea and a dark one from the land. Kirk (272 f.) suggests that Heraclitus's theory was of a single exhalation (from the sea), and that Aristotle was responsible for its
the
462
Fire, Life
and Exhalation
(as in Anaximenes, and perhaps not independently) on a theoextension of the observed process of evaporation. On the one hand moist vapours are drawn up from the sea by the heat at the world's
be based
retical
circumference, become dry and bright themselves and renew the heavenly bodies. On the other hand soul too arises out of moisture,
and
way by exhalations from the watery element. showed the double nature of the way, up as well as down. This entails that the death of anything, though it implies complete 1 loss of its character as that thing fire dies and becomes mist or
is
Fr. 36
extinction.
vapour, soul dies and turns into water is nevertheless not complete Nothing is permanent, not even death. Everything must
continue to
comments on
move on the upward and downward path. Philo rightly fr. 36: 'What he calls death is not utter annihilation, but
2 change into another element/ One can understand a circular path of becoming on which fire changes to steam, then to water, then to earth, then back to fire through
same stages reversed; and soul pursues a parallel series of transformations manifested in sleep and death. Anaximenes took a not dissimilar view. But Heraclitus is obviously struggling to say something
the
He ignores the law of contradiction, he insists The way up and down is one and the same,
everything flows upwards and downwards simultaneously. This is why (fr. 32) 'the one wise thing', i.e. the Logos which is also fire, 'is both
unwilling and willing to be called Zen', a name which means both Zeus, the supreme god, and life; for life and death, Hades god of the
dead and Dionysus god of life, are one and the same (fr. 15). Another important statement of the law of change, a part of fr. 31, may help here: 'The turnings of fire are: first sea, and of the sea half is earth and
half burning.'^ Sea
1
is
is
no such
thing as
Vlastos (AJPy 1955, 366) thinks that Heraclitus's choice of the word dE^coov (ever-living) rather than <5c0dvorrov (deathless) in fr. 30 was motivated by his belief that *the condition of life ever-lasting is not deathlessness but life endlessly renewed by death in a process where youth and age are "the same" (B88)*. If so, this illustrates once more the extreme difficulty of putting
into
2 3
his novel conception of change. P. 480, n. i, below. Half earth and half irpTicrrfjp. This word has aroused
words
much
discussion.
Burnet
calls it
hurricane accompanied
by a fiery water-spout* (EGPy 149), referring to Hdt. vri, 42 and Sen. * Q.N. n, 56 igneus turbo. Kirk considers this absurd*, and doubts whether Heraclitus would have chosen an uncommon phenomenon as a regular means of change between water and fire, or
463
Heraclitus
water.
and contradict the law of flux and struggle. Water is only a momentary stage on the upward and downward path, and, by saying that sea is half earth and half a burning substance, Heraclitus seems to be telling us, in his Delphic manner, that it is being transformed upward and downward at the same time,
rest (stasis)
together'.
In the light of this, fr. 62 may be assumed to refer to this continuous in transformation, a transformation of the physical bodies and of soul
It is
the
most
accurate,
it
runs: 'Immortal mortals, mortal immortals (or 'Immortals are mortal, mortals are immortal'), living the death of the others and dying their
life.'
It
It has,
implying the whole Pythagorean and Orphic doctrine of the soul as an immortal being for which this earthly life is a kind of death and the body a tomb, because it only enjoys full life when discarnate. Men may be described as mortal immortals, gods or daimons temporarily incarcerated in mortal bodies.
times, as
modem
Undoubtedly the language is impressive, especially considering the equivalence of 'immortal' and 'god' in Greek usage, but the question of the nature and fate of the human soul must be considered separately
later.
and stability:
the concept
of measure
of 'measures' in the
We
account of change. The reference in fr. 30 to the measures in which the cosmic fire is kindled and extinguished is amplified by the second quotation made by Clement of Alexandria in the passage cited as fr. 3 1.
He
thinks
it
in
fr.
64.
and thought them worthy of an explanation ('ignition and quenching of clouds') alongside such common phenomena as thunder and lightning (Agtius, ill, 3, 9, DK, A 14). Moreover a man is more likely to be impressed by a rare phenomenon, and regard it as significant, if it happens to support his own views;
Trpncrrfjpes,
On
and, as Diels saw, a waterspout accompanied by lightning (* WindhosemitelektrischerEntladung', and so LSJ) was ideal as ocular demonstration of the link binding fire and water in the process of reciprocal change (Diels, Herakleitos, 24, quot. Reinhardt, Farm. 178, n. i). In any case Heraclitus means that half the sea is reverting to fire,
464
and subsequent destruction by fire; and their inappropriateness to such a conception inclines one still further to reject it.) 'Earth is the word liquefied as sea, and is measured in the same proportion'
its
c
is
logos
as existed before
it
became
earth.'
well explained
retains
by
Vlastos.
throughout all its that logos. In other words, though it changes in appearance it is equivalent throughout in quantity or value, judged by an independent standard, which is that of fire; for all things are an exchange for fire,
as
Any part of earth which becomes water changes a pre-existing logos, it is measured in
(fr.
90).
This
constant in
measure
or
common
measure in
things'. 'Each
TO represents the same amount of fire, which is the common thing uvov in all the different things that compose the series The invariance of
its
measures
is
what accounts
metron in
"steers
all
things, and
fire is
therefore that
which "governs" or
94: 'The sun will not
The
fr.
overstep his measures; otherwise the Erinyes, servants of Justice, will ' find him out.' 'Measures should be taken here in a general sense (c
Kirk, 285) so that to overstep
them means
is set
to deviate in
to follow a
the sky in a measured time, giving out a measured amount of heat. If he were to depart from it in any way (as for example in the myth of Phaethon, when he came too near the earth), die cosmic
is
The emphasis
Kirk,
laid in this
who
or 'warfare') has been disallowed by writes (p. 370) that 'Heraclitus did not deny stability to the
('strife'
natural world;
such a
on the contrary, his main purpose seems to be to assert which according to him underlies all change, and most stability, Reinhardt is right in emnotably change between opposites.
.
text, with <yf\> inserted before WtAccaao, on which see Kirk, 33 1, Vlastos, that the last three words of the 1955, 359, n. 46. Vlastos adopts a suggestion of Cherniss a Vlastos in AJP, 1955, 359-61. fragment are a gloss (#rV. 360, n. 47). 3 For the difficult fr. 120, which Kirk connects with the measures of the sun, see his pp. 289-93.
1
Accepting DK*s
9
AJP
465
Heraclitus
phasizing that there never was anything approaching a Flusslehre in Heraclitus himself.' 1 That the change was always contained within limits, the battle swaying to and fro so that the global balance is always preserved,
is
theless his
to
be to show that
all stability
in the
world is merely apparent, observed with understanding as well as with the senses it proves to be only a resultant of unremitting strife and tension. This is the tenor both of the fragments and of other
since if
testimony, in particular that of Plato, whose remarks consort well with the fragments themselves. Perhaps the strongest evidence of all is the
primacy given to fire. Since it becomes all things, one might ask why one of the others water or earth might not serve equally well as the standard of measurement and the ruling force. Heraclitus, who is
seeking for poetical or religious as much as logical truth, gives a twofold answer. First, as Aristotle said (De An. 40535), fire is the most
which most nearly approaches the incorporeal, is itself in motion and imparts motion to other things. Secondly (a consequence
subtle element,
of first, as Aristotle knew), it is the same as psyche^ the vehicle Heraclitus says the arche is soul, i.e. the exhalation out of which he composes other things. It is the least corporeal of substances and is of the
*
life.
For soul we
may
read
fire.
It
In the identification of soul and fire he was perhaps at his least original. was a popular Greek belief that aither, the substance which filled the
upper heaven above the less pure aer about the earth and of which the celestial bodies were made, was alive and divine; and until the time of
(pp. 270 ff., above), aither and fire Moreover in the fifth century, and clearly distinguished. no doubt earlier, there was a widespread idea that the soul was immortal
Aristotle, or a
very
little
before
him
would
and
1
consisted of an imprisoned spark of aither, rejoin its like. Seeing that aither was believed to
it
which
fill
at
death
all
the upper
regions,
it
this doubtless
of his
a
own
visibly fiery substance of the sun and stars, in his supposition that the 'fire' Heraclitus helped a hot dry vapour. 2 was flame but not system
Reinhardt's view (Hermes, 1942, 18) has been contested by Nestle in ZN, 798, n Aither is divine in Aesch. P.V. 88 and Eur. fr. 839 N. In Eur. fr. 877 it is equated with Zeus. Cf. also other passages adduced by Kirk and Raven, 200, n. i. For the connexion between soul
and
HeL
fr.
466
An
always
it
in
it.
Now
Heraclitus's statement about the river, that it is not the same river the second time you step into it, illustrates the culmination of materialist
belief.
we know that if we stand on its banks tomorrow we shall be looking at entirely different water from that which we see there today. Similarly we commonly regard our bodies as having continuity even though we may be told, and believe, that their material constituents are constantly
changing and will have renewed themselves entirely within a period of seven years. Our justification for this habit of thought is that the form
remains the same: the water or other matter as
were, into the same mould, having the same identity.
as
it
Pythagoras and his school achieved with remarkable suddenness a rational conception of the significance of form, and were much blamed by their successors for
Through
ignoring the material side. For them reality lay in form, for others in matter. Both views have persisted, and whatever may be their respec-
who
tive merits, in anything like a developed scheme of thought only those see reality in form can find any permanence in the world. The
logical
outcome of materialism is the doctrine of uninterrupted flux, as Heraclitus had the intelligence to perceive and the courage to assert; for the matter of things is in fact always changing, and the only permanent thing is form, which can be expressed in the timeless language of mathematical equations. The logical outcome of form-philosophy, on the other hand, is
Platonism or something resembling it: a belief in absolutes, or forms' of things, existing eternally in a region beyond the reach of space or
the nature of the physical world Plato agreed with Heraclitus. He makes the wise Diotima say to Socrates:
time.
*
On
Even during
his identity
the period for which any living being is said to live and retain as a man, for example, is called the same man frorA boyhood
467
Heraclitus
to old age he does not In fact retain the same attributes, although he is called the same person: he is always becoming a new being and undergoing
a process of loss and reparation, which affects his hair, his flesh, his bones, his blood and his whole body. And not only his body, but his soul as well.
No
man's character, habits, opinions, desires, pleasures, pains and fears I remain always the same : new ones come into existence and old ones disappear.
In what way the flux of becoming was for Heraclitus limited or qualified by the existence of a permanent and stable reality is a question that
needs further consideration.
represented Plato's doctrine of immutable forms as having been the outcome of, among other things, *the Heraclitean opinions that all sensible things are continually flowing and
Aristotle, as
we know,
there
is
this,
but unwilling to
accept the impossibility of knowledge, Plato posited a permanent reality outside the physical world. It is usually assumed (a) that these
own
by name as
Plato's informant), and (<5) that although they are explicitly confined to the sensible world, this for Heraclitus constituted the total
sum of reality.
Cratylus carried the consequences of the flux-doctrine to absurd lengths. Nevertheless we have seen evidence in the primacy of War
Strife, in the similes of the bow and lyre and elsewhere, that for Heraclitus the essence of wisdom lay in recognizing unceasing motion, unceasing struggle and effort in the exertion of contrary tensions, as
and
necessary conditions for the continuance of the physical world-order. It seems accurate enough to describe this, with Plato, as a doctrine of the everlasting flux of physical things, and to illustrate it by the simile
of the river into which one cannot step twice. Over against this, however, stands the Logos, whose permanence Heraclitus emphasizes in fr. i by the use of the word is or exists, in
contrast to the changing
to
its
laws. Because of these laws, the order and balance (kosmos) of the world are also constant and everlasting (fr. 30), no of its
internal
components
is
1
is
instants together. It
most acutely
Plato,
W.
Hamilton.
468
Flux and
the
Logos
embarrassed by the curious stage of thought represented by Heraclitus, which at this point is likely to have led him into what from our point of
view
is
an
illogical
and inconsistent
position.
Spiritual
and material
forces are
united as aspects of one and the same entity, although in fact they are becoming so far as to demand complete distinguished Hence the separation. mysterious conception of a 'rational fire', of a
still
Logos, a law of limit, measure or proportion, which takes a physical form. In that aspect, as fire, it would seem to be itself subject to the
all-pervading flux, yet in the eyes of Heraclitus there was a difference. It was in some way a standard by which all things were measured and evaluated (fr. 90, pp. 4<5o, above). In its aspect as Logos, the same
point
is
made by
its
appellation of 'the
common'
(pp. 425
above).
(13)
Although not
all
will agree,
there seems
to the
prevalent religious and philosophical world-picture of his time. In spite of important differences in detail, it may be said that most thinkers of the sixth and fifth centuries shared, in outline, a common
Vlastos thinks that for Heraclitus there is no Trepi^ov, but the whole sum of existence is contained within the cosmos (AJP> 195 5, 366). His reason is that according to the doxographers Heraclitus said that the arcke, or fire, is finite. He cites Arist. Phys. 205 a 14, Theophr. op. SimpL
*
DJL ix, 8.
words K&V
TTSTrgpaa^vov ascribe limitation of the primary substance to Heraclitus himself, though since Theophrastus did so it is probable that Aristotle did also. Theophrastus (who is the source
of Diogenes as well as Simplicius) divided the natural philosophers into two classes, those who believed the arche to be infinite and those who believed it finite, and put Heraclitus in the latter
class. It may seem an easy way out of a difficulty to say that Theophrastus was simply wrong, and I have at other times deprecated such a course. Heraclitus is, however, a rather special case, and that he was misunderstood in antiquity is agreed by all. It is fair to point out that in the
immediate context Diogenes attributes the following statements to Heraclitus as well: (a) fire was the element (oroixeTov) out of which all things were formed by rarefaction and condensation; (f) the cosmos emerged from fire and will be reduced to fire again, and so on alternately for ever, tile way from fire to cosmos being called by Heraclitus war and strife, and the way to ecpyrosis agreement and peace. Vlastos would not accept the truth of either of these statements. Why then should we rely on their author for the finite extent of the arche in Heraclitus? We know that in other respects Theophrastus wrongly assimilated this arche (his word for it, not Heraclitus's) to those of other Presocratic thinkers. He even admits himself that he does not understand it, for it is in this same passage that he makes the rather despairing comment: <ycc<i>6S$ 8* ouSfev fecrBerca. Apart from all this, even if it is true that Heraclitus denied the infinity of fire, it would not necessarily follow that he limited it to this cosmos. I cannot say that my suggestion about Heraclitus's conception of T& TTOV is certain: there is a great deal of uncertainty about this unique and obscure thinker, and Vlastos may be right. But I give what seems to me the most probable hypothesis.
469
Heraclitus
notion of the universe. 1 Heraclitus would accept this scheme just as even an original and rebellious thinker in the Middle Ages would take for
granted the Aristotelian universe with the earth immobile at its centre. There is the cosmic sphere, bounded by the sky, with the earth at its
centre, the fixed stars at the circumference,
planets circling
and the sun, moon and in between. The contents of this cosmos are subject to
which
change and dissolution, being mainly composed of elements or qualities conflict, and prey upon each other. But the cosmos is not the whole of reality. There is also 'that which surrounds*, a quantity of
the untransformed primal substance or arche which for some at least of the Presocratics was infinite or indefinite in extent. This was of a purer,
higher nature than the 'opposites* within the cosmos, which had in * some way been 'separated out* or condensed from it. It was ever5
lasting,
aUve and
of the changes which formed not only surrounded but directed or 'steered*.
Aristotle describes
it
thus (Phys. 203 bio): 'It appears to be the originator of all things, to surround and to direct them And this, it seems, is the divine, for it is immortal and
in fact divine.
indestructible, as
5
was
say.
That
this is
Anaximander and most of the natural philosophers a fair description of the apeiron of Anaximander we
living, sentient character
especially emphasized by Anaximenes. Claiming that it was air, he not only said that this surrounded the universe, but drew an explicit
it and the human soul (fr. 2, p. 131, above), as in did his follower century Diogenes of Apollonia. The Pythagoreans also spoke of the universe taking in breath from the surrounding
parallel
between
the
fifth
existed in purity
it
of the cosmos,
creatures, while inevitably suffering in the process some degree of assimilation to their degraded character. This was the basis of the
It
Pythagorean belief in the kinship of all nature (pp. 200 ff., 278, above). can be seen also in those passages, philosophical or other, which
made oaither,
For a
fuller
1952, 87-104.
470
the
Contemporary World-Picture
say that the soul may become a star (as in Aristophanes, Peace, 832-3), or plunge into the dither, after death; for aer is an impure form ofaitkerfire.
It
portions of the surrounding divine substance sullied contact with the lower elements, an idea exploited a
by
entry into
little later
by
this
philosophical circles makes it probable that it was part of the common background of the philosophers rather than the individual and reasoned
had not emancipated himself from this which was common to the philosophical and general conception
popular religious thought of his time, it is a little easier to make sense of his cosmology and the part played in it by the Logos-fire. In fr. 30, the ever-living fire that is 'kindled in measures and extinguished in
measures'
(i.e.
involved in warfare and the "way up and down*) is 'this world-order of ours' (KOCTHOV
possibility that there exists
something
else
not so designated. This will be the Logos-fire (or ahher) surrounding the cosmos in its purity, inextinguishable and invisible, mind and soul
in their highest form (though not yet conceived as wholly incorporeal). Like the arche of other thinkers it 'steers all things* (fr. 64).* It deter-
of the *ups and downs' within the cosmos and ensure the persistence of the inconclusive battle between its constituent parts, the guarantee of its continued life.
would be not illogical but natural to think of the divine principle as immanent as well as external, the standard or measure of change within the cosmos appearing in
For Heraclitus
as a child of his time
it
to emphasize at physical form as cosmic fire. He would be quite likely one time the all-pervading character of this principle and at another its
1
Perhaps
'all
these things'.
Dr H.
TCI SI), corresponding to the K6<juov T6v5e in fr. 30. 'thunderbolt* the universal (Kpowv6$) in this fragment, Heraclitus By calling guiding principle which was his vehicle, presumably means to 'indicate', in the symbolic language of prophecy that it is both fiery and the supreme divinity; for the thunderbolt was the weapon of the chief
of the gods, who was even identified with it. Kirk (p. 354) quotes a fifth-century inscription from Mantinea A1OI KEPAYNO and later evidence. He notes that in all these identifications the name of Zeus is attached to Kepccuv6$, but to omit it is entirely in keeping with the obliquity of Heraclitus's
Delphic
style.
471
Heraclitus
transcendence.
*
asserted that
The latter may be the purport of fr. wisdom is separate from all things'. 1
108,
where
it is
When
mind
Heraclitus spoke of 'god' or 'the divine', he clearly had in the Logos-fire; but a final brief consideration is wanted of his
Frr. 5, 24 and 53 show that he of Greek polytheism, and such recognized gods in the traditional sense a pluralization is not surprising or difficult to understand. That he had
his
conception of divinity emerges from one or two of his many c rebukes to mankind : Divine tilings for the most part escape recognition
(fr.
own
because of unbelief*
of praying to images, saying that the worshipper 'does not understand what gods and heroes really are*. Divine wisdom and excellence are
contrasted with
114).
human lack of these qualities in frr. 78 and 79. There is all human laws draw their sustenance God does not recognize the distinctions drawn by man
and unjust; to him
all
between
(fr.
just
good and
just
102, p. 442, above). In the light of fr. 67 (p. 444, above) we can go further and say that this is because he comprehends all contraries
was a sense in which the apeiron of Anaximander and the air of Anaximenes also 'were' the opposites, since the opposites were produced from them. The inherent paradox of this conception was made explicit by Heraclitus, though the identity of his Logos-fire with the opposites was much more subtly conceived. In so far as it is explicable, it has been explained earlier: the parallel shows only that this identity is for a Presocratic thinker no hindrance to belief in a primary, living and directive principle which exists both outside and within the cosmos. Zeus is all things and what is beyond them all.'*
in himself. There
'
Justice
he says
is
(fr.
who
fr.
fabricate
and
testify
to
lies.'
Justice
it
See Kirk, 398. Walzer translates *k sapienza*. For T6 cro<p6v as the god or divine principle cf. fr. 32. * For the inconsistency* one may compare Anaxagoras on the point. The divine Mind (vou$), * he insists, is mingled with no thing, but is alone and by itself*, and he gives reasons for this
is
(fr. 12). Nevertheless there is a qualification. *In everything there except Mind; but in some things there is Mind also' (fr. u). a Aesch. fr, 70 ZeOs TOI *r& Trdvrct X&TI TcovS* Orriprtpov.
a portion of everything
472
Religious Beliefs
measure which they chastise. Justice again is equated with the cosmic 1 and of this strife fire is the symbol. If fr. 66 is genuine, its assertion that 'fire will come and judge and convict all things* bears out this identification* As others associated Zeus with Justice,
strife in fr. 80,
so HeracHtus identified
it
fire
that
of Zeus, the
father and king of all' (fr. 53; cf. Plato, be quoted shortly). For those who believe Heraclitus taught ecpyrosisj fr. 66 refers to the final conflagration of the world, but
is
War which
Crat. 4130, to
can equally well apply to individuals. At any rate it is clear that he have said and evil are one' (p. 442, above), although may 'good this did not signify that no kind of behaviour was preferable to any
it
(The equivocal ways in which contraries are one' have been explained on pp. 445 ) The particular sins that call down vengeance are
other.
denying the truth (fr. 28) and exceeding the appointed measure * How, if everything at some time becomes fire*, this same
discriminate between the sinner and the just, judge, which will be faced in the next section.
i.e.
(fr.
94).
fire
can
is
a question
(14) Religion
and
the fate
of the soul
were
the
What attitude did Heraclitus adopt to popular religious cults, and what his beliefs about the soul and its fate after death? The answers to
two questions
first.
these
Clement of Alexandria in
are closely linked, but I start with the evidence for his Protrepticus treats the Greek
mysteries to some heavy sarcasm. They reached their climax at night, by the light of torches. Yes, he says, 'worthy of night-time are the
and of fire, and of the great-hearted (or rather empty-headed) sons of Erechtheus, and the other Hellenes too, whom there awaits, when
rites,
they
*
die,
To whom does
allusion to Heraclitus, fr. 27). Heraclitus of Ephesus direct his prophecies? To night-
wanderers, magi, bacchants, maenads, initiates. It is they whom he threatens with the things after death, to whom he prophesies fire. For
impious
1
is
by
men.* 2
It is rejected by Reinhardt and Kirk (see Kirk, 359-61), but has been defended against them by M. Marcovich feaper to 3rd Internal. Congr. of Class. Stud. 1959, pubL by Univ. of Mrida,
Venezuela). Marcovich, however, adds that *of course the fragment cannot be an argument in favour of the ecpyrosis-interpretation*. a See fr. 14 DK; the full text in Bywater, no. 124.
473
Heraclitus
It is
fire',
doubtful whether, in referring to Heraclitus's prophecies of Clement had anything more to go on than fragments 16 and 66.
For the former he himself is our only authority. It runs: 'How could anyone escape the notice of that which never sets?' In all these quotations
from Heraclitus Clement is doing his best to see a Judaic or Christian meaning. This one he brings into connexion with Isaiah * xxix. 15 Their works are in the dark, and they say, Who seeth us?
:
and
who knoweth
fire,
us?' It
is
the divine
which
vague enough, but probably does refer to always present, as opposed to the sun which,
is
ever since the time of Homer, was regarded as the 'mighty eye' (Soph. 7h 101), Helios who sees and hears everything (//. in, 277). With his
customary pleasure in showing up the stupidity of others, Heraclitus points out that the actions of men after sunset are not carried out under
the eye of Helios.
Some
confirmation of this
is
found in Plato's
Cratylus (4i3B-c), where the reference can hardly be to anyone else. Socrates says that, in his search for justice, someone has told him it is the sun. Someone else, however, pours scorn on this, asking whether
justice disappears
when
And when
ask
his turn calls justice, he says it is fire.' Fr. 66 has been quoted previous page. Its context in Hippolytus is this: 'And he calls
[fire]
want and satiety [fr. 65]. Want is in his view the ordering of the cosmos, and the universal conflagration is satiety, for he says that fire will come and judge and convict everything.' The sentence fire is want and satiety
*
far
the eschatologicaUy-minded Christian bishop. Clement's references to prophecies of fire demanded a slight digression, but at present our concern is to note that according to him
Heraclitus uttered threats against the practitioners of mysteries and of
rites.
Further criticism of established cult occurs in a fragment referred to by several writers of late antiquity, which runs something like this
1
Cf. R.
Mondolfo
It is impossible to be certain that the last sentence, introduced by an explanatory ydp, and saying that initiations are 'impiously carried out* (dvicpoxrrl nuoOvrca), should be attributed to Heraclitus; but the oOv at the beginning of the following sentence suggests that it is, and that only
On
fir.
own argument.
474
Criticisms
(fr. 5):
1
of Popular Cults
it,
"They vainly purify themselves with blood when defiled with man who had stepped into mud were to wash it off with mud. He would be thought mad?z if anyone marked him acting thus/
as if a
Here he expresses disapproval of the general belief that a homicide, stained with blood, could be purged of the pollution of the act by a ritual including animal sacrificed
further criticizes Dionysiac religion, though with an important 'If it were not for qualification. Dionysus that they hold processions
5
and sing hymns to the shameful parts [phalli], it would be a most shameless act; but Hades and Dionysus are the same, in whose honour they go mad and celebrate the bacchic rites/4 This is a hint that the
performed are only reprehensible when the performers do not understand the significance of what they are doing. Here as usual it is
acts
lack of insight that Heraclitus blames. It calls to mind a passage in the Neoplatonist lamblichus: 'Thus I hold that of sacrifices also
two kinds: first, those of men completely purified, such as occur in one instance, as Heraclitus says, or might among an easilycounted few; secondly material, corporeal sacrifices, grounded in mutability, such as befit those who are still in the grip of the body/5
there are
lamblichus
1
is
drawing his
own
distinctions
on
familiar Neoplatonic
Koc6a(povTai 8* fiXXcos atpon uiaivdpevoi MSS. of Aristocritus and Origen; fiXAcos om. Elias and Bywater; fiXXcp conj. H. Frankel; fiXAcos{cc[|Jux> afnan D. S. Robertson (Kirk and Raven, 21 1). M. Marcovich (CP, 1959, 259) defends the traditional text, with a comma after ofycrn. He says: (a) niociv6pvoi is absolute, containing the notion of cclpcrn within it; cf. yfcccrua as t.t.; (f) iiioivduevoi is perfect in sense; cf. De Mori. Sacr. i cut fin. (vi, 364Littr6) &n6vres ie ntpippmv6iie8a oOx obs vuaiv6vivoi and Xen. An. in, 2, 17 ot. . .irp<S06ev oOv futfv TccrT6iivoi vuv d^ecnfjKoaiv. This interpretation has been followed in the translation above. * We know that word-play had significance for Heraclitus, and here it is probably double: (a) a pun on ucrfvecrQoa nicrfvecrOca, (f) a play on the religious and non-religious uses of die former. It meant to be out of one's senses, but to the worshipper of Dionysus it was the desired climax of his religious experience, when the god had entered and taken possession of his soul.
called notiv6iAevos (//. vi, 132). The reference to washing in mud or clay contain another hit at current religious practices, for certain ritual purifications actually did involve smearing the person with clay. See Dem. De Cor. 259, Guthrie, Orph. and Gk. Ret. 212.
may
this
Orestes
by the sacrifice of a pig at Delphi after the killing of Clytemnestra. Apollonius of Tyana
MS.
sTpyacrrai.
alludes to the saying as if it covered animal sacrifice in general. 4 Most scholars accept Schleiermacher's efpyaor* &v for the
Wikmowitz
suspected further corruption, but does not attempt a translation (Gl. d* Hell, n, 209), and the sense can hardly have been other than is normally supposed. For phallic processions in honour of
Dionysus see Hdt. u, 48, Nilsson, Gr. Feste, 263 ff. 5 De Myst* v, 15, 219. 12 Parthey. See Heraclitus,
fr.
69.
475
Heraclitus
lines,
but he evidently knew of a saying of Heraclitus that there was a right and a wrong way of offering worship, and that very few men chose the right way. Elsewhere he hints at a more favourable attitude
to purificatory
"are
Such things then', he writes, 1 introduced for the tendance of the soul in us and to keep within
and other religious
rites.
bounds the evils which birth has caused to grow about it, to set us free and release us from bonds. Hence Heraclitus rightly called them "cures", as tending to cure our troubles and the disasters attendant on
generation.*
The upshot
is
that Heraclitus
was not
hostile to initiations
and
were carried
performance wrong and impious, reducing phallic rites to mere obscenity. Of the esoteric lesson to be learned from them we have
learned this much, that Hades and Dionysus god of life are the same.
the
mysteries, whether Eleusinian or other, taught of life after not the colourless shadow-existence of the Homeric psyche, but death, one in which Ml individuality was retained and rewards and punish-
The
ments were possible. The emphasis on these was especially strong in Orphic and Pythagorean circles (pp. I95ff., above). Whether Heraimmortality of the soul and in posthumous rewards and punishments, or whether such ideas must be excluded as
clitus believed in the
incompatible with the process of flux, is an almost insoluble question on which diametrically opposite views have been held. Soul, it has
been
said, is subject to
at death turns to
water
continuous change into the other elements, and (fr. 36). How then can it have the permanence
still
necessary for the preservation of identity after death, several lives as the Pythagoreans taught?*
less
through
sure that
Whatever
and
its fate,
we may be
they will not be purely rational or without religious overtones. He himself prepares us for this in fr. 45 : 'The limits of soul wouldst thou not discover though thou shouldst travel every road: so deep a logos
1
IVuL
aTcx
40 . 8 Parthey. In so far as TCC ToiccOra has a definite antecedent, it is Td & TO!$ IgpoTs *the things seen and heard in sacred rites*. This view was put most strongly and persuasively by Rohde in Psyche, Eng. tr. 392-4.
I,
1 1,
K<xl <5xoijraiiaTa:
476
has
it/
The Fate of the Soul We are not much helped by fr. 27: When men die
*
there awaits
them what they do not expect or think *, though it certainly suggests survival (and is interpreted by Clement as a threat of punishment)*
in
[i.e.
also
be passed over
if
we
on the grounds that, although they impossible to say what precisely Heraclitus fr. 21: 'What we see when awake is death,
this
an admission that
in reality death ('the body a tomb' as the Pythagoreans said), but the apparent lack of real contrast between the two
clauses,
when contrast is obviously intended, leaves the meaning obscure. Sleep as a cognitive state seems to be condemned as at the end of fr. i, but then one would expect the waking state to be contrasted
it
with
Gods and men honour those slain in war* 24 has also been adduced as evidence for posthumous survival and reward,
as better. Fr.
is
it
thought glorious,
slain respected,
*
by gods
as
undoubtedly is by
of an Orphic* strain in Heraclitus is a further * criticism of customary rites not yet mentioned: Corpses are more fit to be cast out than dung* (fr. 96). In thus dismissing all funerary
in favour
Somewhat
practices and exhibiting the utmost contempt for the body, he might be thought to imply the complementary belief in the eternal value of the soul. The two certainly went together in Orphic and similar religious teaching. In a medieval source he
1
is
quoted
as saying (fr. 4)
treated of A6yo$ fairly exhaustively, I will not add to the many meanings proposed here: 'ground* (Grund, Diels), 'meaning* (Sinn, Kranz), 'cause* (Hicks), 'essence* (E. Weerts), 'measure* (Burnet, Gigon, Kirk). Kirk thinks it refers to the soul as a representative
Having
for
it
portion of the cosmic fire, 'which, compared with the individual, is obviously of vast extent* (KR, 206); but po9uv X6yov lxei would seem a rather recherche" phrase to express simply 'so extensive is it*.
1
3
Fr. 98. Kirk suggests a possible explanation at KR, 211. Of. the xAios dfrotov avryroov of ol dpioroi in fir. 29. Fr. 26 is also best left out
of the discussion.
The text is most uncertain (contrast e.g. Bywater*s version (fr. 77) with DK*s), and however settled leaves the sense highly obscure. The same may be said about fr. 20, in which Clement understood
Heraclitus to be KOKfjcov Tfjv ylvsaiv. Gigon, Unters. ^u H. I2if.
For modern
477
Heraclitus
*If happiness lay in the delights of the body, we should call cattle happy when they find vetch to eat', and this ascetic attitude towards
bodily pleasures (reflected again in fr. 29?) finds a parallel in the same circles. However, these sayings cannot be said to. offer certainty.
One
fragment however
is
much more
positive
(fr.
63) :
They
arise
1 There is vigilant guardians of the living and the dead.' no reason to doubt its genuineness, of which its very unsuitability to
and become
bear the reference Hippolytus gives it (to the Christian doctrine of the resurrection of the body) is itself a guarantee. The words are a plain
allusion to Hesiod's
it is
heroes of the Golden Race after their death became 'good spirits, guardians of mortal men, roaming everywhere over the earth clad in
darkness'. In the light of this, fr. 62, which is in his best oracular style, may also be thought to contain a promise of immortality: 'Immortal mortals, mortal immortals, living the death of others and dying their
life.
V. Macchioro indeed interpreted the fragment in terms of the complete Orphic doctrine of man: the immortal mortals are human
beings who are partly divine and may become wholly so, and 'mortal immortals' refers to Dionysus who though a god was killed by the
Titans. 3
The
reference to the
myth
is
could be a cryptic statement of the Orphic and Pythagorean doctrine of the body as a tomb and the cycle of births. This receives some support
from Sextus Empiricus (Pyrrh. Hyp. in, 230): 'Heraclitus says that both life and death are in both our living and our dying; for when we live our souls are dead and buried in us, but when we die our souls
revive and live/
It is difficult to
is
Sextus's
own
interpretation, and by
1
itself the
omit the
definite subject is expressed. Heraclitus's thought is also brought into close relation with the mysteries by A. Delatte, Les Conceptions de I'enthousiasme, 6-21. As evidence for Orphism in HeraclituSj Macchioro also adduces fr. 52: *Aion (Time?) is a
3
No
Macchioro, Eraclito.
child playing, playing draughts: the kingdom is a child's.' Aion is identified with Dionysus in Christian and Neoplatonic writers, and in the Orphic story the Titans who killed him beguiled
him with playthings (including dorpdyoAoi which Macchioro mistakenly identifies with macro!). But there are no pre-Christian references to Dionysus as Aion, and the interpretation is Altogether hazardous. (Philo seems to have taken Aion to be Chance, playing draughts with human lives. There must surely be an echo of both this fragment and fr. <5o in his De Vita Mos. I, 6, iv, 107. 9 Cohn: TO)(Ti$ y&P <5caToc0UT)T6Tpov oOSfcv fivco xod xdrco T& <5cv0po>ireia irrrreuoCfOT]S.) Of this
fragment I can only say with Gigon that
it is
478
Immortality
instance of the identity of opposites. One may compare fr. 88 : Living and dead are the same, and waking and sleeping and young and old; for these when they have changed are those, and those, changing
*
last clause is
genuine
(p. 445,
no more than
is
reciprocal succession,
as in
fr.
difficult
however, is to explain without invoking the soul's survival after death and
126).
67 (c
fr.
reciprocal,
rebirth into a
new
5
die-hard sceptic might argue that living means only that creatures are formed of what was
life.
it is not so easy to explain away 'old and becomes On the whole therefore this fragment changes young'. favours immortality and palingenesis, though by itself it would perhaps not be conclusive.
The fragments provide no more direct statements on immortality. What follows is inference, and lays no claim to certainty. I start from
the fact that Heraclitus
was more of a religious prophet than a as the tone of his utterances abundantly proves. From rationalist, such a man one should not look for perfect consistency of thought on
the subject of the human soul. It is there if anywhere that he will be influenced by unconscious presuppositions arising from the traditions
of his people, and the position taken here will be that his beliefs about the soul derive from the general world-picture which has been tentatively ascribed to him.
were
was
a living creature.
in the following summary it is necessary to repeat points previously made, this will be done as briefly as possible. To exclude all permanence from his scheme of things is clearly wrong.
Where
and there is emphasis on the related concepts of law and measure. That he did teach a doctrine of flux, and regarded it as one of his prime discoveries, I have mainthe divine'.
eternal,
He believed in
'
The Logos is
tained against
his teaching is
recent interpretation, but to call that the whole of a serious misunderstanding, which in antiquity may have
some
from confusion with his followers. Flux and impermanence were kept within the strict limits of the 'way up and down', and moreover
arisen
He
shared
479
Heraclitus
It is
the substance
and
fire
in our part
The heavenly
pure. Divinity to a Greek mind was synonymous with everlasting life, therefore fire, the substance of divinity, is the principle of everlasting
life.
own
In varying degrees of impurity this life-substance pervades our world and gives life to us and the animals. In its pure form it was
When
(cf. e.g.
is
and mind were breathed in from the less pure form of the same
Clouds, 227-30) said that soul the air, this is consistent, because aer
by
thing, filling the lower atmosphere. (In Heraclitean terms, the fire-soul suffers a certain degree of moistening the time it reaches mortal bodies.) The statement of Sextus that
according to Heraclitus 'we draw in the divine Logos by breathing' belongs to this early scheme of thought, and need not be supposed a
Stoic distortion. In the
coals or
embers which glow when brought near the fire but fade when removed from it. This too may be a genuine Heraclitean reminiscence. Being
in
its
may
purest form aither, a soul, if it has cherished the flame of life, hope to join the heavenly aither at death (see the references on
p. 466, n. 2, above).
These
religious
birth*,
were worked up by the Orphic sectaries and other teachers in Greece into an elaborate doctrine of the 'wheel of
beliefs
arise naturally
but they
become
out of a background of folklore, seen stars in the sky when we die* of the
Heraclitus souls, like everything else,
Now in
way up and down; they are encroached on by the other elements (fr. 36). But their real nature is fiery (hot and dry), and
are subject to the
death
is
'It is
death to
; dry soul is wisest and best'. Death, 1 however, is not complete extinction, for that would contradict the law of unending and reciprocal change, and so we have '. . .but from
souls to
become water
'the
earth
soul'.
is
The
1
striking.
fr.
As
Philo saw,
De
dvotpEoiv dvondgoov,
dAXA
chrocv
480
which had wholly purified itself by the proper and the right kind of life could escape from the wheel and unite
permanently with the divine, so
with
also,
itself
we may
conjecture, did
Heraclitus.
life,
goes the
endless.
way of water and its circulation in the cosmic flux may be The wise soul on the other hand keeps itself dry, cherishes the
fiery element in
it by worshipping the gods in the proper way (that is, with understanding), listens to the Logos and grasps the truth that wisdom is one thing and all opposites subsumed in a higher unity. It
would be
in keeping with all the habits of early Greek thought that such a soul should at the death of the body be assimilated to that Logos,
fire,
and escape from the cosmic cycle of becoming; believe Macrobius, Heraclitus described the soul as
a spark of the substance of the stars' (DK, AI5 scintillam stellaris essentiae). Burnet and others have seen evidence in the fragments of a 'fiery death' as opposed to the death whereby souls become water. It
is
of courage and
virtue as well as vigour, as opposed to those whose souls have been weakened by disease (or, presumably, dissipation; cf. frr. 117, 77).3 Such a view finds perhaps its strongest support not in any actual saying
of Heraclitus but in its consonance with the general picture. The nearest
to confirmation in Heraclitus himself is the
*
gnomic
Greater deaths win greater portions.' This seems a reasonable account. But 'the limits of soul thou wouldst
not discover though thou shouldst travel every road'. Heraclitus himself would certainly scorn the notion that a twentieth-century barbarian
could fathom the depths of its logos, and would doubtless refer us to
1
The
when
it
8*
^jhrrav papuTTEv0os dpyo;Xoio (gold plate from tomb at Thurii, see Guthrie, Orph. andGk. Re!. 173). It adds; *I am a child of earth and starry heaven, but my lineage is heavenly.* 2 In one fragment (115) Heraclitus says that soul has a A6yos locurov ccOcov, a logos which
itself.
3
increases
KR,
frr.
69^(900-01 Kadapcbrepoi
209 f. Direct evidence consists mainly of the metrical imitation of Heraclitus <yvxocl be brought into relation f\ vl voOcrois (136 among the frr. in DK). This can
with
24 and 25.
481
Heraclitus
his
own advice
(fr.
matters*
47).
Some of his
sayings are so
good
as
them
into a
general framework seems not only hazardous but misguided. Such is *A man's die scarcely translatable fr. 119: ?)0o$ ocvSpobirco Sodncov
individuality
daimon The daimon was the personal genius or looked after an individual both in life and after which guardian angel death (for which see especially Plato, Phaedo, 1070); the man with a good daimon would be happy (eu8cciijcov). This superstitious belief 1 Heraclitus reinterprets in a highly enlightened, rational, and ethical way.
is his
.
It is, however, tempting to speculate further. Daimon was a word of more than one use, with a whole world of popular beliefs behind it. Sometimes it was simply a synonym for a god. But as we have seen,
from the time of Hesiod at least the immortal spirits of good men were also daimoneS) and since he gives them the function of 'guardians', it looks as if the daimones who looked after individual men were thought
of in this way. Heraclitus alludes to Hesiod in fr. 63 (p. 478, above), and must have accepted this. Moreover in those religious circles which taught that the soul survived the body, and underwent many incaras a fallen daimon which might rise again form. (This comes out most clearly in Empedocles, proper godlike fr. 115.) There is thus a further depth to this saying. It links up with the belief in transmigration and means: *A man's character is the
nations,
it
to
its
immortal and potentially divine part of him.' This lays a tremendous emphasis on human responsibility and adds to the ethical content of
the sentence.
318 above.)
We are now acquainted with the most important and interesting parts of Heraclitus's message, but may add some details for the sake of completeness. He had some rather strange ideas on astronomy and
1
B. Snell has
some
valuable remarks
on
this
It
seems to be
that idio-
common
and failings, particularly emotional husband for Paris, she is not to blame, for her
Homer and early lyric poetry, outbursts, are the work of the gods.
infatuation
If Helen
man
to act
Celestial
Phenomena
by Diogenes
Laertius
9-1 1):
Exhalations arise from both land and sea, the one sort bright and pure, the other dark. Fire is increased from the bright, and moisture from the others.
The
there are in
nature of the surrounding substance he does not explain, but says that it bowls with the inside turned towards us, in which the bright
exhalations are collected and produce flames which are the heavenly bodies. Brightest and hottest is the flame of the sun; for the other stars are further
less light and heat, whereas the moon, though near the earth, does not move through a pure region. The sun on the other hand is in a brilliant and uncontaminated region and at a suitable 1 distance from us, and therefore gives more heat and light The sun and moon
are eclipsed when the bowls are turned upwards, and the monthly phases of the moon are due to the gradual turning of its bowl.* Day and night,
rain,
like are
brought about by
bright exhalation catching fire in the circle of the sun causes day, whereas the predominance of the contrary one produces night: summer is caused by an increase of heat from the bright one, winter by
The
a preponderance of moisture from the dark. His explanation of the other the same lines. On the other hand he offers no explanation of the nature of the earth, or even of the bowls.
phenomena follows
This account does not seem very percipient, and throws together a surprisingly diverse collection of phenomena under a single general
would be characteristic of Heraclitus to be somewhat impatient of detail, and he may himself have dismissed a number of astronomical and other natural phenomena in a few aphorisms of the sort with which we are familiar. His interest lay, not like that of a
cause.
Yet
it
Milesian physikos in explaining all possible natural phenomena, but solely in using them to support the doctrine of universal reciprocal
change
sun,
(cf.
we
Reinhardt, Farm. 181). Beyond a few remarks about the have nothing but the late compiler's version of his views to
will
goby.
That the sun
already seen
1
we have
were no
(fr.
He
expansion.
'commensurate' and thinks the word is evidence of Peripatetic commensurate* does not fit the context, and the sense required is not xXteiv. Peripatetic. Cf. rather Soph. O.T. 84 f^uirpos yap cb$ 3 v oOT?j; the Literally *to the bowl gradually turning in it*. I confess I cannot understand
translates
*
oeA^vti.
483
Heraclitus
would be night', 1 a fragment whose That is, of interpretation, says Kirk, remains somewhat precarious'. is no there for if a one obscurity course, expects symbolic meaning, about the factual commonplace which it states. With or without the
sun, with
all
it
stars, it is
Though
as
it
stands
probably a straightforward statement. worth making, it may have found its seems it hardly
and place in an account of the comparative brightness of sun, moon stars which went on to offer an explanation, on the lines paraphrased
by Diogenes,
in terms
of
relative distance
of atmosphere. Heraclitus may also have wished to emphasize that day and night are the product of the same cause (the sun) according
as
present or absent, thus emphasizing their essential unity as expressed in fr. 57- but this seems a lot to get out of a very simple
it is
*
sentence.
(fr. 6),
have abandoned philosophy that 'they are much more truly extinguished than the sun of Heraclitus, for they are never rekindled'. Later commentators expand this. The sun passes below
says of those
who
the earth, and is extinguished either because the western regions are cold (Olympiodorus) or because it plunges into the sea (scholiast on the Republic) : when it rises the next morning it is rekindled in the east. 2
of vapour collected in a 'bowl', which ignites when in a fiery * ' and no doubt acquires fuel from further vapours or exhalations region,
It consists
which
its
a belief of Heraclitus that 'the heavenly bodies are nourished exhalation from the earth',3
1
Fr. 99.
Kirk
(i6*ff.) thinks it probable that the words fvacoc TG&V dAAcov dcrrpoov
y
(which occur
in Plut.
omitted
when
Comp. 957A) are an insertion by Plutarch. * For texts see Kirk, 267, and in general cf. his long discussion of this fragment, 264-79. 3 Act. n, 17, 4, DK, 22 A n. It is hardly necessary to go into the troubled question of whether Diogenes was right in attributing to Heraclitus a theory of two exhalations, bright from the sea and dark from the earth, which Kirk (271 ff.) regards as an Aristotelian theory read back into Heraclitus. single-exhalation theory would certainly be adequate for his system, and seems more probable. It would of course be dark and moist, or bright, dry and fiery, according to the law of constant change, partaking in the 'way up and down*. This does not mean that the description of Aetius (rfjs drr6 yffr dvoduiJiidcrgcos) is wrong: it may quite well be general. The sun draws up an exhalation from the earth, whether it comes from sea or land. Kirk seems to go too far in saying (in KR, 204, n.): 'The explanation of night and day (as well as winter and summer) as due to the alternating prevalence of the dark and bright exhala-
484
The Sun
Heraclitus's conception of the sun evidently
owes much
to
Xeno-
phanes's description of it as formed of ignited clouds, or a collection of sparks from the moist exhalation; but since we are told that his sun
travels during the night beneath the earth from its setting-place in the west to its rising-place in the east, he cannot have intended the daily
newness of the sun to be taken in the same radical sense. According to Xenophanes the sun shot off into space in a straight line, and the appearance of a circular course was illusory (p. 393, above). Heraclitus
speaks rather of renewal of the sun than of an entirely new sun, probably with two points in mind: (a) as a heat- and light-giving body it is
new every day, since its flame is quenched at night, (H) like any other flame (and indeed like everything else in the cosmos, which for that reason he characterized as itself a fire), it is constantly being renewed by
the absorption of new matter. Aristotle complains (Meteor. 3 55 a 12) that if the sun were 'nourished' like a flame, as 'some' say, then it
would not only be new every day, as Heraclitus asserts, but always new at every moment. This of course is what Heraclitus did believe.
He did not, however, use the precise language of philosophy but the isolated 'barbed arrows' of prophetic utterance, leaving his hearers to interpret them. For his purpose, *new every day' was an adequate
phrase,
civilized souls
might understand.
the traditional
and poetic idea that at night the sun sailed in a golden bowl round the rim of the world on the encircling stream of Oceanus from west to
east
6 Diehl). Heraclitus has of the sun in its daily simplified things by making the bowl the vehicle of the obviously rid the as thus well, sky getting journey through
(Mimnermus,
fr.
mythical apparatus of chariot and horses; and the extension of the notion of bowls to the moon and stars is an innovation. It looks, however, as
if,
had been
content with a superficial rationalization which (as Kirk has noted) does not even fit the phenomena; for the turning of the bowls which he
tions,
itself consists
knew as well as anyone that day is due to the sun/ Since the sun * of the bright exhalation catching fire', there is no inconsistency in attributing day both to the sun and to the bright exhalation; and whether or not Heraclitus said it, it is at least reasonable that the quenching of the sun's fire, which produces night, should be due to the victory
. .
.is
absurd: Heraclitus
of the dark
485
Heraclitus
invokes to explain eclipses and the phases of the moon would produce and lunar circles, ellipse of light, not the 'bite' out of the solar
leading ultimately to a crescent shape, which in fact appears. (It is * accounted for slightly amplified in Aet. n, 24, 3, DK, A 12 : Eclipses are
an
by
its
and its convex part downwards towards our sight/) As for the composition of the bowls themselves, we know no more than Diogenes and
must take
his
word
for
it
them
further.
The subsequent account of seasonal and meteorological events is too 1 vague to make comment worth while. Nor is it easy to see the significance of the only other pronouncement of Heraclitus about the sun which has come down to us, namely that 'its breadth is the length of
human
foot'
(fr.
3) or alternatively 'it is
The
fragments
by DK,
size that it appears to in the actual included statement, though reads like the second half of a hexameter and may
first
of the
of Heraclitus such as
as
it is, it
we know
might be
By
itself,
supposed to refer only to appearances, as a reinforcement of the thesis that the senses are misleading unless interpreted by the mind. But the
version in Diogenes expressly denies this. It is directly contradictory to the example used by Aristotle in the De Anima (428 b 3) when he
wishes to
we know
recognized to be larger than the inhabited world'. It is hardly possible that Heraclitus believed his statement to be literally true, and its
must remain mysterious.3 The same thing was said later by for however it is the outcome of his peculiar doctrine Epicurus, of the infallibility of sense-perception.
significance
whom
(16) Conclusion
proud
isolation.
The
thoughts in his mind were ahead of his time and language. In his
1
own
It is amplified
by what is
said
TrpTiorfjpes in
Aet. in,
Sfe
3, 9,
DK, A 14,
which, however, is hardly more satisfying. * It occurs in ordinary doxographical form in Theodoret,
280).
3
iv,
22 'HpdKAerros
m>8icaov (Kirk,
f.
486
Conclusion
estimation he was a prophet, bearer of the divine law which the mass of men were incapable of grasping. He could only set it before them in
image and paradox. Practically all his language is metaphorical, and only seldom does he attempt a brief train of argument. What is the use of arguing with the self-satisfied many?
on him has two sides. First, we conceive of the world of our experience as containing objects, possessed of a certain stable and relatively permanent character. This seems to us also
truth that has flashed
The
we commend as good any apparently harmonious arrangement which enables its product to stay quietly as it is, and stigmatize disruptive forces as bad. The truth is far otherwise.
a desirable state of affairs, so that
What we take for stability and rest is the outcome not of any harmonious agreement of parts but of an incessant struggle of opposing forces which has happened to reach an equilibrium of tension. Exertion,
is
*
motion, change are constantly though invisibly going on; strife the condition of existence: there is no rest, only unremitting change.
is
Thunderbolt
all
peace; and
is
at the helm*, War is father and king, War is the true these things are good, for peace as popularly conceived
death.
On the
is
not allowed to
might some day cease. The cosmos has for and will on existed ever go existing, and this could not be guaranteed if there were a possibility of one of the contraries ever gaining a In no can fact exist if its contrary contrary permanent advantage.
should disappear. Pre-eminent in the Heraclitean universe stands the Logos, the divine law of measure and proportion. Everything is always moving up and down the path of change, driven thereto by the attacks of its opposites or its own attacks upon them, but all within
strict limits.
go on unregulated.
The path
is
a circular one,
In the unity of the Logos all opposing forces are contained and transcended. It is the one wise', the god who is day and night, winter
*
and summer, war and peace: personal, then, and intelligent above all else. At the same time, since nothing is yet divorced from matter, this god is of a fiery nature, and in some degree pervades the whole world
like the Zeus-aither
is
a living organism, as
487
Heraclitus
it
remained to Plato, and later to the Stoics. We too have our share in the Logos is common to all, it, we are knit into the cosmic unity; for our own souls are fiery and through the intermediate stage of air we
are in direct contact with the cosmic reason
by
breathing.
Not even
when
we be entirely cut off. We still live, though our bond with 'the common' has become so tenuous, in the absence of senseperception to serve as material for our thought, that we are shut in
asleep can
a private world of illusion. Heraclitus exhorts us not to carry over this shameful condition into our waking hours. We must cultivate the
fiery nature
damp fumes of
may be ready to rejoin the Logos-fire. The road to this body goal is die road of understanding. Whether or not we carry out the
the
it
recognized
rites
of communion
is
immaterial.
Performed without
understanding they are merely disgusting, but if they help us to grasp the unity behind the flux and multiplicity of phenomena they can do
good.
NOTE. No mention has been made in this chapter of any possible connexions of Heraclitus's thought with Persia, in particular with Zoroastrianism. His Logos has sometimes been compared with the Zoroastrian concepts of Ahuna Vairya (as divine Word) and Vohu Mana (as universal Mind), and it has been thought possible to find in Heraclitus (as Plutarch did) the same dualism as in the Persian religion. All this has been omitted because in fact there is no sure evidence of contact or affinities, but only a field for speculation and conjecture. At the same time it is true that Heraclitus was a subject of King Darius and was traditionally believed to have been his friend; that one of his fragments provides the earliest occurrence in Greek literature of the title Magus; and that he accorded a supreme and divine status to fire. Those interested may be referred to the brief and sober summary, with bibliography, of S. Wikander in Elements orientaux dans la religion grecque
ancienne,
579.
APPENDIX
The river-statement (seep. 4^0)
The evidence that Heraclitus said (in whatever exact Greek words), 'You cannot step twice into the same river', is perhaps stronger than
that for the genuineness of any other fragment. There would be no need to rehearse it again, were it not that a few scholars have questioned
488
The River-Statement
it
and uncharacteristic form of words which occurs only in Arius Didymus as quoted by Eusebius (DK, 22 B 12) Upon those who step into the same rivers different and again
* :
different waters flow/ Since the claim that this sentence reproduces the
original words of Heraclitus has received the support of Kirk (whose translation of it I have given), the evidence had better be set forth. But since Kirk's arguments have already been countered Vlastos (AJP,
by
1955, 338-44)5
1 shall
little
more.
I believe
moves on
and nothing
and comparing existing things to the flow of a river he cannot that says you step into the same river twice/
is at rest,
Ayei
irou 'HpotKAerros OTI irdyra xcopei *ai oOSev p^vei, Kai TTOTCCHOU
>ofj
drrsiK&scov TCC
ovra Ayei
ob$ Sis
T6v aOr6v
*
mmxpov OVK
ocv in{3a{r|$.
Metaph. roioa 13 : Cratylus criticized Heraclitus for saying that it is impossible to step into the same river twice: in his opinion you could not do so even once.'
(b) Aristotle,
KparuAo$.
/HpokAeiTcp
rreTinoc
auro$ yap cjbero ou6* anxx. (c) Plutarch, De E, 3926: 'According to Heraclitus it is not possible to step into the same river twice, nor to lay hold twice of any mortal substance in one permanent state/
iariv lufifjvar
TTOTOCHCO yocp
OUK IOTIV
n|3fjvcxi 61$
00 OH- at* 9 I2A: *You cannot step twice into the Heraclitus says, for fresh waters are flowing on/
TroTaiJioI$ yocp 61$ TOI$ ccuToT$
same
rivers, as
OUK
HpdK?^eiTos
Srepa
v/6orra.
thrown everything
?j
Vind. 5590:' Before we know where we are, we shall have into Heraclitus's river, into which he says one does not
its changes moves and alters everything/ T6v 'HpakXetretov arravrra irpdynocra Trora|Ji6v
el$
6v ou
T^
Plutarch quotes Heraclitus frequently, and clearly did not get his quotations from Plato; and he leaves us in no doubt, as he himself was
in
said.
77.31
interchanges
all
things,
Heraclitus
sentence
could not step twice into the same river", comparing becoming to the continuous flow of a river, as having more of not-being than
"You
of being'.
THV OUV6)(fj pOTjV TT}V TTOCVTOC EVCcXAdcrarOUCIOCV, f|V 6 'HpCCKAstTOS T)VlcCTO SlOC TOU 'eis TOV OUTOV TTOTCCJJIOV 6ls nf) ccv l[Ji(3fivai ", TTJ svSsXexel TOU TroxauoO porj TTIV yeveaiv oarsiKOc^cov irAsov TO nf| 6v eyovaav TO^ ovro^ (g) Ibid. 1313 .8: 'The natural philosophers who follow Heraclitus, con.say naturally enough that centrating on the continuous flow of becoming, into the same river/ twice and cannot in flux step you everything is always
.
TO&S 8
irorauov
irepi 'HpccKAerrov
.
d<j>opcDVTas.
Sis
.eixos
9umoA6you$ ai
els
"rrcfcvra pel
OTI
eis
TOV aurov
OUK
ocv 8upaiT]s.
This, it will surely be admitted, is impressive evidence that in the eyes of those most likely to know, whose testimony to the words of Heraclitus
step
we are inclined to accept on other occasions, he said You cannot (or it is impossible to step) into the same river twice'. What is the
it differently? A.D. writer of a first-century
The
fr.
book on Homeric
allegories (also
misquoting and do not step into the same rivers, we are and are not"* (Heracl. Homer. Qu. Horn. 24, fr. 49 a DK: Trora^ois TOIS ocuro!$ in(3aivouev TE xcd OUK 6n|3ccivonev, elusv TS Kal OUK sljisv). With this may be compared Seneca, Ep.
62, proceeds:
unknown),
says:
after seriously
'And again he
"We
step
58, 23:
*As Heraclitus
same
river
we
step
and do not
step twice; for the name of the river remains the same, but the water has flowed past' (hoc est quod ait Heraclitus: in idem flumen bis de-
scendimus et non descendimus. manet enim idem fluminis nomen, aqua * transmissa est). In the first passage some editors suppose that twice*
has fallen out of the MSS. In any case the words TOIS OCUTOIS show that the meaning is the same, for apart from the nonsensical 'we step
(815)
into the
same rivers* (i.e. each of us steps into the same rivers as the same* can only mean the same rivers as we have stepped 'the others), into before. Since our authorities agree that this allegory stood for an
essential
may
it
more than once in slightly different terms. It is certainly tempting to suppose that what Vlastos has called the 'yes-and-no* form is his own
(cf. 'is
is
willing* in
fr.
32, 'wholes
49
The River-Statement
Seneca, a little heavy-footedly, improves on the explanation which may have been Heraclitus's own: one can step elsewhere, given twice into the same river say the Thames or the Cam but in another sense it is not the same, for the water you step into the second
fr.
10).
time was not there before. In this form therefore the saying is essentially the same as in the other, in which it is regularly quoted from Plato
believe to represent
are irrelevant to this discussion, save to discredit the preceding sentence. I agree with Vlastos that, taking the verb in the full existential sense, they express a thoroughly Heraclitean sentiment. They have been thought to
as they
make an abrupt
transition,
and
it is
unscholarly namesake should have thrown together two utterances which did not come together in the philosopher himself. But he had
his reason for
doing
both
illustrate
have no permanent but a flux of and constant renewal. being undergo change Finally there is the form cited by Arius Didymus, which it is
doctrine, that so-called natural entities or substances
advisable to quote in
its full
context
(fr.
12
):
Concerning the soul, Cleanthes, putting the views of Zeno beside other natural philosophers for comparison, says that Zeno calls the soul a sensitive exhalation, like Heraclitus. For he, wishing to make the point that souls
continuously become intelligent by being vaporized, compared them to rivers, putting it like this: upon those who step into the same rivers different
1
Hv
auyxpiaiv TTJV
Ayei
ataOriTtKfjv ocvaOuufaaiv, KoO&rrep Hp<5a<AeiTO$. |3ouA6uevos yap ijjupaviaca OTI cd vyuxod ocvaduuicbusvai voepod del yivovrai, Eixaaev aOra$ TO!$ TroTauoT$ Aycov OUTCOS* mmxuotai rolaiv ocuroiaiv n(3ccfvouoiv erepot xal irspa uSara
<5crro
Whether
doubtful, but as
1
36 shows
being directly attributed to Heraclitus is ('. . .from water comes soul'), it reprein
Or
voepol,
which makes
D. Meewaldt
veotpoi for
491
Heraclitus
sents his belief.
The obvious
difference
between
is
this
others
is
applied specifically to
souls, whereas in the others the reference is to everything alike. The best solution is probably to accept Meewaldt's emendation (n. i on
previous page), in which case we see that the comparison is applied to souls in respect of a characteristic which they share with everything else,
namely that they are continuously being renewed, never substantially the same. The words different and again different waters flow' occur also in slightly shorter form in Plutarch (see above), and perhaps in this form the explanation was added by Heraclitus himself (as possibly
*
also in
88, p. 445, above). As to the statement as a whole, I can only say (against Kirk) that the balance of the evidence is strongly in favour
fr.
of
its
first,
and
correctly,
l\i$air\s or oOK lonv gupfjvon (as Aristotle gives it) must be admitted that none of our ancient sources had the passion for verbal accuracy which possesses the modern scholar. At least Vlastos has shown that the potential form which Plato quotes was perfectly possible for Heraclitus (AJP,
Whether Heraclitus
actually
is
trivial question,
nor can
we decide it.
1955,
492
BIBLIOGRAPHY
The
following
list
with shortened
included which
to mention
titles)
contains full particulars of books or articles mentioned (often in the text or notes. In addition, a selection of titles has been
may be useful for reference although there has not been occasion them in the course of the work.
general
Source-collections (other than those of individual philosophers) precede the list. (On the sources of our knowledge of early Greek philosophy see
pp. xiii-xiv.)
The Greek commentators on Aristotle (most frequently Simplicius and Alexander of Aphrodisias) are referred to in the text by page and line in the appropriate volume of the Berlin Academy's edition (Commentaria in Aristotelem
Graeca, various dates).
COHEN, M. R. and DRABKIN, I. E. A Source-book in Greek Science. New York, 1948 (2nd printing, Cambridge (Mass.), 1958). DE VOGEL, C. J. Greek Philosophy: a collection of texts with notes and explanations.
3 vols., Leiden, 1950-9. DIELS, H. Doxographi Graeci. Berlin, 1879.
DIELS, H. and KRANZ, W. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker (Greek and German). 6th ed., 3 vols., Berlin, 1951-2 (or later editions; the pagination remains the
same).
FREEMAN, K. Ancilla to the Presocratic Philosophers (translation of the texts in Diels-Kranz). Oxford (Blackwell), 1948. KERN, O. Orphicorum Fragmenta. Berlin, 1922. KIRK, G. S. and RAVEN, J. E. The Presocratic Philosophers. Cambridge, 1957
(selected texts with translation and commentary). RITTER, H. and PRELLER, L. Historia Philosophiae Graecae. 9th (selection of texts with Latin notes).
ed.,
Gotha, 1913
ALLAN, D. J. 'The Problem of Cratylus', AJP, 1952, 271-87. BACCOU, R, Histoire de la science grecque de Tholes a Socrate. Paris, 1951. BAILEY, C. The Greek Atomists and Epicurus. Oxford, 1928. BALDRY, H. C. 'Embryological Analogies in Presocratic Cosmogony', CQ, 1932,
BEARE, J. I. Greek Theories of Elementary Cognition. Oxford, 1906. * BECKER, O. Die Lehre vom Gerade und Ungerade im IX. Buch der eukHdischen Elemente', Quellen undStudien %ur Geschichteder Mathematik^ 3 (1936), 533-53. BERGER, H. Geschichte der wissenschaftlichen Erdkunde der Griechen. Leipzig, 1903.
BERTHELOT, M. Les Origines deTalchimie. Paris, 1885, BOEDER, H. 'Der friihgriechische Wortgebrauch von Logos und Aletheia*,
Archiv fur Begriffsgeschichte, 1958, 82-112.
493
Bibliography
BOEHM, Symbolic Pythagoreis, diss. Berlin, 1905. F. lateinische Neuplatonismus und Neupythagoreismus. Leipzig, 1936. Der BOMER, BOOTH, N. B. 'Were Zeno's arguments directed against the Pythagoreans?*,
Phronesis, I9J7, 90-103.
F.
De
BOWRA, C. M. 'Xenophanes fr. 3', CQ, 1941, 119-26. BOWRA, C. M. 'Xenophanes and the Olympian Games*, Problems
Poetry, 1953, 15-37.
in
Greek
la Tetractys',
doctrina e propriis phitosophorum reliquiis exposita. Altona, 1813. tudes de philosophic antique, Paris, 1955. BREHIER, E.
BROAD, C. D. The Mind and its Place in Nature, London, 1925. BRUGMANN, C. *Der griechische viccur6$', Indogermanische Forschungen,
(1903-4), 87-93.
15
BRUNET, P. and MIELI, A. Histoire des sciences, I. Antiquite. Paris, 1935. BURGH, G. B. 'Anaximander the First Metaphysician', Review of Metaphysics,
3 (1949-50), 137-60.
BURCH, G. B. 'The Counter-Earth*, Osiris, 1954, 267-94. BURCKHARDT, G. Heraklit. Zurich, n.d. (after 1922). BURNET, J. Greek Philosophy: Parti, Tholes to Plato (all published). London, 1924. BURNET, J. Early Greek Philosophy. 4th ed., London, 1930. BUSSE, A. *Der Wortsinn von A6yo$ bei Heraklit', Rheinisches Museum, 1926,
203-14.
BYWATER,
J.
'On
Pythagorean*,
BYWATER, J. Heracliti Ephesii Reliquiae. Oxford, 1877. CAMERON, A. The Pythagorean Background to the Theory of Recollection. Menasha
(Wisconsin), 1938.
CAPPARELLI, V. La sapien^a di Pitagora. 2 vols., Padua, 1941 and 1945. CAPPARELLI, V. // contnluto pitagorico alia scien^a. Padua, 1955.
CASELLA, F. 'Hippolyti Refutationes 1.14', Maia, 1957, 322-5. CHAIGNET, E. Pythagore et la philosophie pythagoricienne. Paris, 1873. CHERNISS, H. Aristotle's Criticism of Presocrattc Philosophy. Baltimore, 1935. CHERNISS, H. 'Characteristics and Effects of Presocratic Philosophy \Journ. of the
COOK, R. M.
Hist, of Ideas, 1951, 319-45. * Ionia and Greece in the Eighth and Seventh Centuries
B.C.*,
JHS,
1946, 67-98. CORBATO, C. 'Studi Senofanei*, Annali Triestini, 1952, 179244. CORNFORD, F. M. 'Mysticism and Science in the Pythagorean Tradition', 1922, 137-50, and 1923, i-i2.
CQ,
494
Bibliography
CORNFORD,
1-16.
F.
M. 'Innumerable Worlds
in Presocratic
1934,
F. F. F.
F.
M. Plato* s Cosmology. London, 1937 (repr. 1948). M. Plato and Parmenides. London, 1939 (repr. 1950). M. The Unwritten Philosophy and Other Essays. Cambridge, 1950. M. Principlum Sapientiae: the origins of Greek philosophical thought.
des Anaximandros', Jahrb.
d.
Cambridge, 1952.
DEICHGRABER, K.
DEICHGRABER, K. 'Xenophanes irepi (pOoecos*, Rheinisches Museum, 1938, 1-31. DEICHGRABER, K. *Bemerkungen zu Diogenes' Bericht uber Herakleitos*, Philologus, 93 (1938/9), 12-30.
DEICHGRABER, K. Anaximander von Milet', Hermes, 1940, 10-19. DELATTE, A. Etudes sur la litterature pythagoricienne. Paris, 1915. DELATTE, A. Essai sur la politique pythagoricienne. Liege, 1922. DELATTE, A. La Vie de Pythagore de Diogene Laerce: edition critique avec
intro-
duction et commentaire. Brussels, 1922. DELATTE, A. Les Conceptions de r enthousiasme che% les philosophes presocratiques.
Paris, 1934.
DICKS, D. R. 'Thales', CQ, 1959, 294-309. DIELS, H. *t)ber Anaximanders Kosmos', Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophic,
1897, 228-37. DIELS, H. 'Uber Xenophanes', Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophie, 1897, 530-5. DIELS, H. Herakleitos von Ephesos, griechisch und deutsch. 2nd ed., Berlin, 1909.
DIELS, H. 'Wissenschaft und Technik bei den Hellenen', Neue Jahrbucherfur das
klassische Alter turn, 1914,
117.
1923,65-75. DIES, A. Le Cycle mystique. Paris, 1909. DIRLMEIER, F. 'Der Satz des Anaximandros von Milet*, Rheinisches Museum,
1938, 376-82.
DIRLMEIER, F. 'Nochmals Anaximandros von Milet', Hermes, 1940, 329-31. DODDS, E. R. The Greeks and the Irrational. California Univ. Press, 1951.
'
Geschichte der
DORRIE, H. 'Der Platoniker Eudoros von Alexandria*, Hermes, 1944, 25-39. DREYER, A. History of the Planetary Systems from Thales to Kepler. Cambridge,
1906.
DUCHESNE-GUILLEMIN,
Paris, 1953.
J.
Orma^d et Ahriman:
DUNBABIN, T. DUNBABIN, T.
J.
J.
The Western Greeks. Oxford, 1948. The Greeks and their Eastern Neighbours. Hellenic Society, 1957.
495
Bibliography
Ptolemaios und Porphyries uber die Mustk. Goteborg, 1934. DURING, L. Review of L. A. Stella's EDELSTEIN, Imponan^a di Alcmeone, in AJP, 1942,
I.
371-3.
EVANS, M. G. 'Aristotle, Newton and the Theory of Continuous Magnitude', Journ. of the Hist, of Ideas, 1955, 548-57. FARRINGTON, B. Greek Science. London (Penguin Books), 2 vols., 1944 (repr.
1949)-
FESTUGIERE, A. FESTUGIERE, A.
J. J.
De rAncienne
Copen-
hagen, 1958, 131-78. FIELD, G. C. Plato and his Contemporaries. London, 1930. FRANK, E. Plato und die sogenannten Pythagoreer. Halle, 1923.
FRANKEL, H. 'Xenophanesstudien
Geschichtsquelle', II:
(1=
'X.
als
FRANKEL, H. 'A Thought-pattern in Heraclitus', AJP, 1938, 309-37. FRANKEL, H. D'ichtung und Philosophie des fruhen Griechentums. New York (American Philol. Soc.), 1951. FRANKEL, H. Wege und Formen fruhgriechischen Denkens. 2nd ed., Munich, 1960. FRANKFORT, H. (ed.). Before Philosophy. London (Penguin Books), 1949 and later reprints (originally published as The Intellectual Adventure of Ancient
Man by Chicago University Press, 1946). FREUDENTHAL, J. Uber die Theologie des Xenophanes9 Breslau, 1886. FRITZ, K. VON. Pythagorean Politics in South Italy: an analysis of the sources. New York, 1940. FRITZ, K. VON. 'vous, VOEIV and their derivatives in Homer', CP, 1943, 79-93. FRITZ, K. VON. *voO$, voetv and their derivatives in Pre-Socratic philosophy excluding Anaxagoras', CP, 1945, 223-42 (Part I: from the beginnings to Parmenides) and 1946, 12-34 (Part II: the post-Parmenidean period). FUNG Yu LAN. A short History of Chinese Philosophy. London, 1950. GANSZYNIEC, R. 'Die biologischen Grundlagen der ionischen Philosophic', Archivfur die Geschichte der Naturwissenschaften und der Technik, 1920, 119. GlGON, O. Untersuchungen %u Heraklit. Leipzig, 1935. GIGON, O. Der Ursprung der griechischen Philosophie^ von Hesiod bis Parmenides.
Basel, 1945.
Entretiens,
127^55.
Leipzig,
GOETTLING, C.
W.
Science', Journal of the History of Ideas, 1943, 161-76. GOMPERZ, H. 'Heraclitus of Ephesus*, Philosophical Studies, Boston, 1953.
GOMPERZ, H. "Aacbponros', Hermes, 1932, 155-67. GOMPERZ, H. 'Problems and Methods of early Greek
496
Bibliography
GOMPERZ, T. Greek Thinkers: a
1901-12
(vol.
i
transl. L.
GREGOIRE,
GRIFFITHS,
10-11.
F.
'Heraclite et
history of ancient philosophy. 4 vols., London, vols. 2-4 transl. G. G. Berry). les cultes enthousiastes', Revue neoscolastique de
Magnus,
w C.v
"GUTHRIE,
W.
1952, 87-104.
GUTHRIE, GUTHRIE,
W. K. C. W. K. C.
'Anaximenes and TO KpuorocAXosiSes', CQ, 1956, 40-4. 'Aristotle as a Historian of Philosophy *,JHS, 1957 (i), 35-41.
Greek views on the origins of life and the
early state of man.*T!/!Sihuen y 1957. HACKFORTH, R. Plato's Phaedrus. Cambridge, 1952. HACKFORTH, R. Plato's Phaedo. Cambridge, 1955.
the Ancient Copernicus: a history of Greek 9 Aristarchus together with Aristarchus s treatise on the si^es and
distances of the sun and moon. Oxford, 1913. HEATH, T. L. A History of Greek Mathematics, 2 vols., Oxford, 1921. HEATH, T. L. The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements. 2nd ed., 3 vols., Oxford,
1926.
HEATH, T. L.
HEIDEL,
A
A.
W.
Manual of Greek Mathematics. Oxford, 1931. 'Qualitative Change in Presocratic Philosophy', Archiv fur
CP,
1906, 279-82.
Geschichte der Philosophie, 1906, 33379. HEIDEL, W. A. "The Sivrj in Anaximenes and Anaximander',
W.
W. W.
A. 'The
A.
dxvccpuoi
TAPA,
the Pre-
1909, 5-21.
'irspi 9ucreco$:
among
Socratics', Proceedings
American Academy, 1910, 77-133. A. 'The Antecedents of Greek Corpuscular Theories', Harvard
of the
HEIDEL, W. A. 'On Anaximander', CP, 1912, 212-34. HEIDEL, W. A. 'On Certain Fragments of the Presocratics', Proceedings of American Academy, 48 (1913), 681-734.
HEIDEL, HEIDEL,
the
W. A.
W. W.
Proceedings of the
Known Geographical Treatise', American Academy, 1921, nr. 7. A. 'The Pythagoreans and Greek Mathematics', AJP, 1940, 1-33.
Anaximander's Book the Earliest
A. Hippocratic Medicine:
F.
its spirit
HEIDEL,
and method.
New York,
1941.
HEINIMANN,
HEINZE, R.
Basel, 1945.
New Oxford
History of Music,
497
Bibliography
HOLSCHER, U.
'Der Logos
bei Herakleitos',
Festschrift Reinhardt, Mtinster/
Cologne, 1952, 69-81. HOLSCHER, U. 'Anaximander und die Anfange der Philosophic', Hermes, 1953, 257-77 and 385-417. JAEGER, W. Paideia: the ideals of Greek culture, transl. G. Higher. 3 vols., Oxford,
1939-45 (vol.
JAEGER,
JAEGER,
W. W.
I, 2nd ed.). The Theology of the Early Greek Philosophers. Oxford, 1947. On the Origin and Cycle of the Philosophic Ideal of Life.'
'
First
Eng.
2nd
The Medical Writings ofAnonymus Londinensis. Cambridge, 1947. G. 'Die JUNGE, Spharenharmonie und die pythagorisch-platonische ZaMenlehre',
JONES,
Classica et Medievalia, 1947, 183-94.
W. H. S,
JUNGE, G. 'Von Hippasos bis Philolaos: das Irrationale und die geometrischen
KAHN, C. H.
<5nreipov at Phys. 203 b 4-1 5*, Festschrift Ernst Kapp, Hamburg, 1958, 19-29. KAHN, C. H. Anaximander and the Origins of Greek Cosmogony. New York, 1960. * KAHN, C. H. Religion and Natural Philosophy in Empedocles* Doctrine of the
GrundbegrifFe', Classica et Medievalia, 1958, 41-72. * Anaximander and the Arguments concerning the
Soul*, Archivfur Geschkhte der Philosophie, 1960, 3-35. KARPINSKI, L. C. 'The Sources of Greek Mathematics* (in M. L. d'Ooge's translation of Nicomachus, Introductio Arithmetics, 1926).
KARSTEN, S. Xenophanis Colophonii carminum reliquiae* Amsterdam, 1830. KERFERD, G. B. 'The Date of Anaximenes', Museum Helveticum, 1954, 117-21. KERFERD, G. B. Review of Thesleff 1957 (q.v.) in CR, 1959, 72. KERN, O. De Orphei Pherecydis Epimenidis theogoniis quaestiones criticae. Berlin,
1888.
KERSCHENSTEINER,
KIRK, G.
KIRK, G.
S.
S.
J.
iiber Herakleitos',
Hermes,
'Natural Change in Heraclitus*, Mind, 1951, 3542. Heraclitus: the Cosmic Fragments. Cambridge, 1954.
KIRK, G. S. *Some Problems in Anaximander', CQ, 1955, 21-38. KIRK, G. S. 'Logos, dpnovfri, lutte, dieu et feu dans Heraclite', Revue philosophique,
1957, 289-99. KIRK, G. S. *Men and Opposites in Heraclitus', Museum Helveticum, 1957, 155-63. KIRK, G. S. 'Ecpyrosis in Heraclitus: some comments', Phronesis, 1959, 73-6.
KOSTER, W. J. W. Le Mythe de Platon, de Zarathoustra et des Chaldeens. Leiden, 1951. KRANZ, W. 'Vorsokratisches I und II', Hermes, 1934, 114-19 and 226-8. KRANZ, W. 'Kosmos als philosophischer BegrirTin fruhgriechischer Zeit*, Phitologus, 1938-9, 430-48.
KRANZ,
W.
498
Bibliography
KRANZ, W. KRAUS, W.
'TTocAivTpoTroS dpnovrn', Rheinisches
Museum,
Museum,
KUCHARSKI, P. *Les principes des pythagoriciens et la dyade de Platon*, Archives de Philosophie^ 1959, 175-91 and 385-431. LEVY, A. 'Sul pensiero di Senofane', Athenaeum^ 1927, 1729.
LEVY, I. Recherches sur les sources de la legende de Pythagoras. Paris, 1926. LINFORTH, I. M. The Arts of Orpheus. Berkeley, California, 1941. LOBECK, C. A. Aglaophamus sive de theologiae mysticae Graecorum causis. 2.
Koenigsberg, 1829.
vols.,
LUKAS, F. Die Grundbegriffe in den Kosmogonien aer alten Volker. Leipzig, 1893. LUMPE, A. Die Philosophie des Xenophanes von Kolophon, diss. Munich, 1952. LUTZE, F. Uber das Apeiron Anaximanders : ein Beitrag %u der richtigen Auffassung
desselben als materiellen Prin^ips^ diss. Leipzig, 1878.
MACCHIORO, V. Eraclito: nuovi studi sulF Orfismo. Bari, 1922. McDiARMlD, J. B. 'Theophrastus on the Presocratic Causes', Harvard
Classical Philology
',
Studies in
1953, 1-156.
12.
MACDONALD, C.
MADDALF.NA, A. / Pitagorici: raccolta delle testimonian^e e dei frammenti pervenutkL Ban, 1954. (Italian translation of the texts in DK, with introductory essays and notes.) MARCO VICH, M. 'Note on Heraclitus*, CP, 1959, 259. MARCOVICH, M. 'On Heraclitus fr. 66 DK* (paper to 3rd International Congress of Classical Studies). Merida (Venezuela), 1959. MARCOVICH, M. 'Was Xenophanes in Paros (Greece), Pharos (Dalmatia), or
Pharos (Egypt)?', CP, 1959, 121. MAR6x, K. 'Die Trennung von Himmel und Hungaricae, 1951, 3563*
MARTIN, H. Etudes sur le Timee de Platon. 2 vols., Paris, 1841. MATSON, W. I. Cornford on the Birth of Metaphysics*, Review of Metaphysics
(i954~5)> 443-54MiAUTis, G. Recherches sur
le Pythagorisme. Neuchatel, 1922. in Heraclitus', Proceedings of the 'Ambiguity Congress of Philosophy, vol. xil, Brussels, 1953, 56-60. MINAR, E. L. 'The Logos of Heraclitus', CP, 1939, 323-41.
MERLAN,
P.
XIth
International
Politics in Practice
MONDOLFO, R. See also ZELLER-MONDOLFO. MONDOLFO, R. Problemi del Pensiero Antico. Bologna, 1936. MONDOLFO, R. L*Infinite nel pensiero dei Greet. Florence, 1934; 2nd
edition,
enlarged
under the title L* Infinite nel pensiero delV antichita classica^ 1956. MONDOLFO, R. 'The Evidence of Plato and Aristotle relating to the ekpyrosis in
MORAUX,
Heraclitus', Phronesis, 1958, 75-82. P. Les Listes anciennes des outrages d'Aristote. Louvain, 1951.
J. S.
MORRISON,
499
Bibliography
MORRISON,
NESTLE, NESTLE,
J. S.
101-19.
W. W.
Review of Rathmann
(q.v.} in
Philologische
Wochenschrift, 1934,
407-9.
NEUGEBAUER, O. 'Studien zum antiken Algebra', Quellen und Studien %ur Geschichte der Mathematik, 3 (1936), 2459. NEUGEBAUER, O. The Exact Sciences in Antiquity. Princeton and Oxford, 1951. NILSSON, M. Griechische Feste von religioser Bedeutung, nut Ausschluss der attischen.
Leipzig, 1906.
NILSSON, M. Geschichte der griechischen Religion, vol. I. Munich, 2nd ed., 1955. OLMSTEAD, T. A. A History of the Persian Empire. Chicago, 1948. ONIANS, R. B. The Origins of European Thought. Cambridge, 1951. OSWIECIMSKI, S. Thales: the ancient ideal of a scientist, Charisteria T. Sinko.
Warsaw,
OWEN, G.
PIAGET,
PIAGET,
J. J.
Society, 1957-8,
199222. The Child's Conception of the World. London, 1928. The Child's Conception of Causality. London, 1930.
Physis', Hermes, 1953, 418-38. C. Vocabulaire et structures de pensee archatque chei Heraclite.
Paris,
RAMNOUX,
1959.
RATHMANN, W.
E.
RAVEN, J. Pythagoreans and Eleatics. Cambridge, 1948. REIDEMEISTER, K. Die Arithmetik der Griechen. Leipzig, 1940. REINACH, T. *La musique des spheres', REG, 1900, 432-49.
REINHARDT, K. Parmenides und die
1916.
Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie.
Bonn,
REINHARDT, K. 'Herakleitos* Lehre vom Feuer', Hermes, 1942, 1-27. REYMOND, A. Histoire des sciences exactes et naturelles dans I'antiquite grecque et romaine. Paris, 2nd ed., 1955. RICHARDSON, HILDA. 'The Myth of Er (Plato, Republic, 6i6B)' ? C<2, 1926,
H3-33RIDGEWAY, W. What led Pythagoras to the doctrine that the world was built of numbers?', CR, 1896, 92-5. RIVAUD, A. Tlaton et la politique pythagoricienne', Melanges Gustav Glot^, vol.
*
II.
Paris, 1932.
RIVIER, A.
dans
les
fragments d'Heraclite',
RIVIER, A. *Sur les fragments 34 et 35 de Xenophanes', Revue de Philosophie, 1956, 37-62. ROBIN, L. Greek Thought, transl. M. R. Dobie. London, 1928.
ROHDE,
E.
Rheinisches
*Die Quellen des lamblichus in seiner Biographic des Pythagoras', Museum, 1871, 554-76 and 1872, 23-61.
500
Bibliography
ROHDE,
E. Psyche: The cult of souls and belief in immortality
among
the Greeks,
London, 1925. ROSTAGNI, A. // verbo di Pitagora, Turin, 1924. ROUGIER, L. La Religion astrale des Pythagoriciens. Paris, 1959. (This is a semipopular work. For full references to texts cited the author refers readers to his
earlier work 'L'Origine astronomique de la croyance pythagoricienne en Vimmortalite celeste des ames\ published by the Institut franc.ais d'Archeo-
transl.
W.
B. Hillis.
logie orientale
du
SAFFREY, H. D. *Le
irepl 9iAoao9fcc$
Caire, 1933. This I have not been able to see.) d'Aristote et la theorie platonicienne des idees
SAMBURSKY, S. The Physical World of the Greeks. London, 1956. SANTILLANA, G. DEand PITTS, W. 'Philolaus in Limbo: or, What happened
Pythagoreans? ', /.V, 1951, 112-20. SCHIAPARELLI, G. Scritti sulla storia della astronomia antica.
3 vols.,
to the
Bologna,
1925-7. SELTMAN, C. T. 'The Problem of the First Italiote Coins', Numismatic Chronicle, 6th series, vol. ix (1949), 1-21.
SHERRINGTON, C. Man on his Nature. Cambridge, 1946 (Penguin Books, 1955). SKEMP, J. B. The Theory of Motion in Plato s Later Diologues. Cambridge, 1942.
9
SKEMP,
J.
SMITH, G. Assyrian Discoveries. London, 1875. SNELL, B. 'Die Sprache Heraklits', Hermes, 1926, 353-81. SNELL, B. 'Die Nachrichten liber die Lehre des Thales und die Anfange der
griechischen Philosophic-
und
SNELL, B. The Discovery of the Mind: the Greek origins ofEuropean thought. Oxford
(Blackwell), 1953. (A third ed. in several additional chapters.)
German, published
STEBBING, L. S. A Modern Introduction to Logic, 2nd ed., London, 1933. STELLA, L. A. 'L'Importanza di Alcmeone', Reale Accademia dei Lincei, Ser.
vol. 8, fasc. 4, 1939.
6,
STOCKS,
III.
J.
xxiv
(1915), 207-21.
TANNERY,
'Pseudonymes Antiques',
REG,
Ecphantus, 133-7).
t
TANNERY, P. Pour T histoire de la science hellene. 2nd ed. by A. Dies, Paris, TAYLOR, A. E. 'Two Pythagorean Philosophemes', CR, 1926, 149-51. TAYLOR, A. E. A Commentary on Plato's Timaeus. Oxford, 1928. THEILER, W. Review of Rostagni (q.v.), Gnomon i, 1925, 146-54.
THESLEFF, H. THESLEFF, H.
Period.
1930.
Abo, 1961. THOMPSON, D'ARCY W. A Glossary of Greek Fishes. Oxford, THOMSON, G. Studies in Ancient Greek Society. Vol. 2: The
London, 1955.
501
Bibliography
THOMSON, J. O. A History of Ancient Geography. Cambridge, 1948. 'UEBERWEG-PRAECHTER'. Ueberweg, F. Grundriss der Geschichte der
UNTERSTEINER, M. Senofane,
Philosophie,
ed. K. Praechter, ^thed., Basel, 1953 (photographic reprint of i2th ed., 1923).
commentario. Florence, 1956. VERDAM, H. D. *De carmine simonideo quod interpretarur Plato in Protagora
VERDENIUS,
dialogo', Mnemosyne, 1928, 299-310. W. jl 'Notes on the Presocratics*, Mnemosyne, 1947, 271-89, and
1948, 8-14.
VLASTOS, G.
'Presocratic
1952, 97-123.
VLASTOS, G. 'Isonomia', AJP, 1953, 337-66. VLASTOS, G. Review of J. E. Raven's Pythagoreans and
i953 ? 29-35.
Eleatics in
Gnomon,
VLASTOS, G. 'On Heraclitus', AJP, 1955, 337-68. VLASTOS, G. Review of Kirk's Heraclitus: the Cosmic Fragments, in AJP,
1955, 310-13.
VLASTOS, G.
65-76.
Sapientiae in
Gnomon, 1955,
Voss, O.
De
WACHTLER, J. De Alcmaeone Crotoniata. Leipzig, 1896. WAERDEN, B. L. VAN DER. 'Zenon und die Grundlagenkrise der
griechischen
Mathematik*, Mathematische Annalen, 1941, 141-61. WAERDEN, B. L, VAN DER. 'Die Arithmetik der Pythagoreer', Mathematische
Annalen, 1948
(I:
127-53;
II:
676-700).
WAERDEN, WAERDEN,
B. L.
B. L.
VAN DER. Die Astronomie der Pythagoreer. Amsterdam, 1951. VAN DER. 'Das grosse Jahr und die ewige Wiederkehr', Hermes,
WALZER, R.
Florence, 1939.
JHS,
1955, 114-16.
WASSERSTEIN, A. 'Theaetetus and the Theory of Numbers*, CQ 1958, 165-79. WEBSTER, T. B. L. 'From Primitive to Modern Thought in Ancient Greece', Acta Congressus Madvigiani, vol. 2, Copenhagen, 1958. WEDBERG, A. Plato's Philosophy of Mathematics, Stockholm, 1955. WEHRLI, F. Die Schule des Aristoteles: Texte und Kommentar (Basel), Heft i:
Dikaiarchos, 1944; Heft n: Aristoxenos, 1945 ; Heft vii: Herakleides Pontikos,
1953; Heft vni Eudemos von Rhodes, 1955. WEIZSACKER, C. F. VON. The World-View of Physics, 1952 Grene from 4th German ed., 1949).
:
(transl.
byMarjorie
502
Bibliography
WELLMANN, M. *Eine pythagoreische Urkunde des IV. Jahrhunderts vor Christus',
Hermes, 1919, 225-48.
WHITE, M. 'The Duration of the Samian Tyranny \JHS, 1954, 36-43. WIGHTMAN, W. P. D. The Growth of Scientific Ideas. Edinburgh, 1950.
WIKANDER,
S.
'Heraklit
la religion
grecque ancienne', Colloque de Strasbourg, mai 1958, Paris, 1960, 57-9. WILAMOWITZ, U. VON. 'Hippys von Rhegion*, Hermes, 1884, 442-52.
WOODBURY,
L. 'Simonides on ocpsTif, TAPA, 1953, 135-63die altesten Zeugnisse zur Geschichte des Pythagoras', SitiungsE. *0ber ZELLER, berichte der preussischen Akademie, 1889, 985-96.
ZELLER, E.
'ZELLER-MONDOLFO.' La
lated, edited
work transFilosqfia dei Greet, I. i and I. 2. (Zeller's and enlarged by R. Mondolfo, Florence, 1932 and 1938.) *ZELLER-NESTLE.' E. Zeller, Die Philosophie der Griechen, I. Teil, i. Halfte (yth edited by W. Nestle (Leipzig). ed., 1923) and 2. Halfte (6th ed., 1920), als Staatsmann und Geset^geber. Athens, von Herakleitos A. N. Ephesos ZOUMPOS,
1956.
503
INDEXES
I.
ACHILLES
Isagoge (19), 93 n.
(i, i),
(i<5, 3),
AGATHEMERUS
i
(i),
74
n.
ALCMAEON
fr. (i),
Cho. (515X421,422
Pers. (363), 421
344 and n.
i,
396, 414 n. 3
(2), 351
(3)>348;(4),3 I 3>34<5
4<$6 n. 2; (231),
421;
ALEXANDER POLYHISTOR
ap.
D.L. VHI
(39, 14),
304 n.
(70 Nauck), 472 n. 2; (379), 85 n. 2; (390), 415 n. 3 AE'TIUS I (3> i)> 6 7; (3, 3)> 84, ioo, 108; (3, 4), 119,
fr.
i; (39, 24), 296; (40), 288, 301; (41, i), 215 n. i; (59), 245 n.; (60, 8), 457 n. 2; (67, 3ff.), 92, 975 (75> I 5)> 215 n. i; (462, 16), 259 n. 3 ; (462, 34), 249 n. i ; (5 12, 20), 257 n.; (767), 304 n. 4; (827, 9), 274
131; (3,
(7, 13),
1 9) ?
13;
3255 (7), 89 n - *; (7, !2), 107; (7, 18), 248; (21, i), 339-40
In Meteor. (67,
ap. Simpl.
3), 92,
97
De
and
II
n.; (23, 7), 448 (i, i), 208 n. i; (i, 2), 325; (i, 3), 108,
2), 272; 378; (3> 3)> 325; (4, 3), 456; (6, 5), 267, 272; (7, i), 136 n. 2; (7, 7),
ALEXIS
ap. Athen. (iv, i6iA-D), 187
&
277; (n> 2, 4), 136 n. 2; (13, 7), 9; (*3 I0)> *34; fo> 14), 392; (14, 3), 135 and n. 2; (15, 6), 93; (16, 2 and 3),
284; (9,
i),
n.
De Interpretation
357;
4),
(i<5, 5),
93 andn. i;
(i<5, 6),
137; (17,
Ten
(p.
30 Heiberg),
392 n. 3; (20, i), 93; (20, 3), 392; (20, 12), 284-5; (20, 13), 286; (21, i), 93; (21, 5), 49 bis; (22, i),
484
n. 3; (18, i),
ANAXAGORAS
fr. (7),
420;
(8),
134, 135; (23, i), 135; (24, i), 49; (24, 2),
208 454 n.
n. i;
3,
93; (24, 3), 486; (24, 4), 394; (24, 9), 393;
(25, i), 935 (28, x), 945 (25,
ANAXIMANDER
fr. (i),
M),
*3<5 n. 2;
(29, i), 94; (29, 3), 357; (29, 4), 283; (30, i), 285 ; (30, 8), 394 n. i ; (32, 3), 458 n. 2 (2, n), 392 n. 3; (3, i), 106; (3, 2), 139;
(3, 6),
ANAXIMENES
fr.
(i),
I24f.;
(2),
119,
131,
208 n.
i,
470
392 n. 3;
(3, 9),
464 n-;
391;
(5, 10),
139; (7,
0, 105;
328; (10, 3), 133; (10, 5), 294; (11, 3), 284; (13, 1-2), 284; (13, 1-3), 327; (13,
3),
ANONYMUS LONDINENSIS
n. 2, 278 n. 3
325 ; (i4
i)>
i),
ANTIPHANES
ap. Athen. (iv, i6iA), 187
92
to
409
n.
APULEIUS
-dpologyfyi), 253 Florida (15), 253
(ii32b23), 213 n.; (ii5ob25), 409 n. i; (ii55b4), 438; (117635), 445 n. 2 G.A. (73 a<5)> 9 n 3; (752b22), 348; (762 3 20), 61 G.C. ( 3 33bi8),73n. 2
-
ARATUS
Phaen. (37"9)> 5* 2 on Pkaen. (p. 515, 27 M.), 393
129 n. i; (565 bi), 104; (565 b2 4), 104; (581312), 303 n. 5,348
ARCHILOCHUS
n. i;
(98^23), 33;
ARCHYTAS
fr. (i),
162 n.
2, 226,
336;
(3),
336
n.
(982bi2), 30 n.; (982 bi 8), 41 n. i; (983 b6ff.), 55; (983b7), 82; (983b2o), 40; ( 9 83b3o), 60, 450 n. 2; (98432), 45; (984
35), 120, 123; (98437), 320, 432; (984
ARISTOPHANES
Clouds (227-30), 480; (230), 130; (404-7),
io(5 n. i; (627),
130
n.
i; (1032),
216
213
n., n.,
(98631),
239 n. i, 302; (985 b 32), 229; 220 n.; (98633), 213, 287;
ARISTOPHON
op.
Athen.
(iv,
ARISTOTLE
Anal. Post. (90318), 223 n. Anal. Prior. (41 a 26), 265 n. 2
153; (986331), 345; (986bioff.), 368-9; (986bi4), 380 snd n. 2; (987313), 235; (987315), 240; (987322), 303 n. 3; (987 329), 331; (987332), 450 n. 3; (987bii),
De Anlma
220
n.,
(404320), 350; (404321), 351; (404!? 1 1), 313-14; (40535), 466; (405319), 65; (405321), 132 n. 2; (405325), 462, 466;
(405329), 313; (405330), 350; (405b2), 62 n. i; (405 b 8), 384 n., 385; (4O7b2o), 306; (407b22), 168 n. 3; (4O7b27), 307-8;
264
n. i; (987 b 28),
220
n.,
229; (98935),
i,
202-3;
239;
308; (4o83i8ff.), 313, 314; (40933), 262; (4iob27), 307, 480; (410 bz8), 129 n. 2; (41137), 65; (4i9b33),
(40835),
(100234), 259; (1005 b 23), 460; (1010313), 450 n. 3>489; (io28bi6), 259,
275 n. i; (io28b2i), 249; (io36b8), 234, 256-7; (iO36bi2), 262 3nd n.; (1061
328ff.), 241; (1063322, 35), 451; (1072
n. i;
(27ob2i),
270;
(278b9ff.),
in;
(279
bi2), 282, 380 n. 2, 390; (279bi4), 437; (280311), 455; (29obi2), 220; (290 bi2ff.), 295-6; (29138), 167 n. 2, 296;
(293318), 283; (293320), 154; (293325), 213; (2 9 3bi), 287; (2 9 3bi5), 283; (293
273;
394
294; (298 b 29), 451; (300315), 235; (300 3 1 6), 236; (303 bio), 107
Categoriae (15330), 242 n. 2 Eth. Eud. (i223b22), 433; (1225330), 329 3ndn. 2; (1235325), 447
(352330), 388; 92; (353^7ffO, 39* n. 2; (353 b8), 97 n. 3; (353b9), 101 n. i ; (354328), 138; (355^12), 485; (355325), 97 nn. 3, 4;
(353 b
5),
(352328ff.), 458 n. 4;
506
to
ARIUS DIDYMUS
(642328), 8; (645317), 65
ap. Euseb. op. Stob. n. i
De Part. Animal.
P.E. xv
n. 2; (660 b 28),
Eel n
(i, 17),
ASCLEPIUS In Metaph.
S.
(2),
44
n., 109,
130
i
b2o), 84 n. 2; (203b23), 85 n. i, 114 n. 2; (204b24), 80; (20531-4), 469 n.; (20533), 456; (20732), 85; (207318), 88; (20838), 84; (2i3b22), 200 n. 2,
209, 277; (2i6b24), 319; (218333), 339;
AULUS
GKLT.TUS
BoErmus
Inst. Mus. i CALLIMACHUS
fr.
(2i9b2), 339; (222bi8), 319; (223322), 339; (223328), 338; (223b2i), 339 n. 2; (25 3 b9), 451; (263 b27), 263; (264b27),
351 n. 25(265 b 24), 7
Pol. (125936), 52; (i34obi8), 308; (1340
(10),
224
n. i
CELSUS
vii (7, 3)> 137 n.
i
b26), 335
n.
Rhet. (i398bi4), 153; (i399b6), 371-2; (i407bn), 404, 407-8; (1407^6), 406
n. 2,
(7), 103
(aft), 348
424
n. i
vi (4), 348
vii (2), 303 n. 5 (8), 282 n. 2; (ii),
xvm
458 nn.
2, 3
fragments
(Numbers
refer
to the third
(Teubner) edition of V. Rose. Those thst occur in the transkted selection of Ross (Oxford translation of Aristotle, vol. xii) can be identified by consulting
the tsble given
CHALCIDIUS In Tim. (279), 349 3nd CHRYSIPPUS ap. D.L. vii (143), 202 CICERO
-
n.
n. i
Ac.
i (4,
15), 8
by Ross on
p. 155) (6),
249; (10), 431 n. i; (75), 154 n.; (190205), 215 n. i; (190), 154 n.; (191), 149 n. i, 154 n.; (192), 149 n. i, 150, 154 n.; (i95) 154 n., 188; (201), 200 n. 2, 277,
n (37, 118), 44 n., 122, 377; (39, De Divinatzone I (3, 5), 373; (50, De Finibus n (5, 15), 411 n. 2
v
(29, 87),
i
123), 328
112), 75
254
149 n. 2; (10, 25), 109; (10,
JVLZX
(5, 10),
279 n.; (207), I54n., 215 n. i; (Protr. fr. ii Ross, not in Rose), 168 n. 2 [ARISTOTLE] De AudibiKbus (803 b 40), 227 Magna Moralia (1182311), 209 n. i, 213 n., 239 n.
i,
snd
200
n. 2,
350; (ii, 28), 378; (26, 74), 411 (14, 35), 411
(14, 22),
74
De Mundo
CLAUDIANUS MAMERTUS De Statu Animae II (3), 311; (7), 321 CLEANTHES Hymn to Zeus (2of.), 425 n. 5 CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA
n. 2
Protrepticus (i, 16 Stahlin), 449 n. 2, 473; (i, 49), 321 n. 3; (i, 50), 350; (i, 80), 484 n. i Stromateis (ii, 40), 362; (ii, 41), 49; (ii, 412),
169 n. i; (113), 173 n. 3; (16), 173; (18), 180; (19), 169 n. i, 310 i n. i; (23), (24), 177 n. 3; (43), 151
(ed.
Wehrli)
(i),
(ii,
184),
(90),
322
CRITIAS
(137), 199 n. 2
rr.
op. Ismbl.
V.P.
(25
DK), 401
n. i
507
to
D.L. vin
(84), 323
DEMOCRITUS
fr- (5),
209, 313-14, 3i8, 348; (no, 10), 200, 348 n.; (112, 4), 199; (115), 318 bis, 482; (127), 200 n. i; (129), 161, 165; (132),
6 9 n. 1; (7-9), 32<$, 399 n.; (34), 208 n. i; (53), 423, 424^ (82), 420; (117), 399 and n.
in
n.,
208
DEMOSTHENES
De
ap.
n.
EPICHARMUS
fr.
DERCYT.T.IDES
(2), 244 n. i ; (2, 12), 423; (12), n. i; (20), 199 n. i; (57), 423 n.
DK
426
DlCAEARCHUS
fr.
EPICTETUS
(7-12), 315 n. i; (34), 178
ii (8,
(ed. n. i
WehrH)
10),
202
n. i
EUCLID
ii
DIODORUS
i
(def. 2),
242
n.
400
n.
xin
2.
(13),
269
(v,
DIOGENES OF APOLLONIA
208 n. i; (3), 143; (4, 5), I2 95 (5), 88, 382 n. 2 DIOGENES LAERTIUS i (3), "5; (8), 249 n- 2 ; ( I2)> 204; (isX 45;
fr. (2),
on xin EUDEMUS
(fr.
88), 281
n. 2;
133), 52-3; (fr. 134), 51, 53; (fr. 135), 53 n. 2; (fr. 145), 74, 98; ffr. 186),
281 n. 2
(25), 51; (27), 51; (120), 158 (i), 74, 75, 94 n. 2; (2), 72, 74
n. 4; (3),
EUDORUS
and
n.,
75
44
n.,
247 and
n.
EUDOXUS
ap. Porph. V.P. EURIPIDES
(7),
187
202
n. i
320;
(8),
254; (4), i<>4; (<5), 158; 158, 211 n. i; (12), 190, 224,
242
n. i; (14),
222
n. i; (15), 151 n. i,
155; (20), 190; (24), 184, 244; (24^), 201 n. 3; (25), 276 n. i, 289; (28), 201; (33), 188; (34), 183, i84&y, 185, 188; (36), 157; (40), 179; (4<9, M9 a- 2, I<59 n. i, 178 n. 3, 273; (48), 208 n. i, 294; (54),
HeracL F. (1341 ), 373 Hipp- (952f.), J 95 n. Med. (872), 421 Or. (25), 85 n. 2 Rhes. (924), 166 n. 3; (949), 166 n. 3 Suppl. (2oiff.), 401 n. i; (533f.), 356, 466
n. 2
i,
335;
n. 2, 341 n. i, 343, (82.), 335> (83), 344; (84), 320, 321 n. 2; (85), 327, 330
n. i,
3U
2,
343
408; (3), 409; (3-5),
n. 3; (5), 406 n. 2, 416 l>is; (6), 409 nn. i, 2, 411 n. 2; (7), 411, 486; (8), 455,
408
n. 2; (839), 386 n., 466 n. 2; (877), 466 n. 2; (910), 73 n. 2, 208 n. i; (944), 293 and n. 2; (971), 466 n. 2 EUSEBIUS
and
460, 469 n.; (9), 462; (9-11), 483; (i5)j 406 n. 2; (18), 363, 364, 365, 370; (19), 374 n. 2, 376, 378, 391 ; (20), 362, 365, 395
n. 6; (32), 91 n. 2; (33), 95 n., 138 n. 3;
(38), 155
xv
(20),
489
(i),
75
343
EMPEDOCLES
fr. (2,
7),
399;
5),
i,
384
305; (26,
208 n.
[GALEN]
Hist. Phil. (7), 377 n. i In Hippocr. d& hum. I (i), 54 n.
279; (42), 286; (52), 292; (62), 292; (96), 258, 275 n. 2, 313; (105), 318, 348; (109),
508
to
413; (840), 444, 445, 452 n.; (84^), 445 433; (86), 472; (87), 412, 420;
(88), 445, 452, 479, 492; (89),
Golden Verses
n.
(ed.
WehrH)
D.L. i (12) ( = fr. 87), 204 HERACLITUS {bold figures denote a main entry} fr. (i), 407, 408, 412, 419, 4*4-5, 4^5 *>. 3> 427 and n. 2, 428 n. i, 430, 434, 438, 447,
ap.
164; (44), 164, 168; (88), 164, 204; (89), 164; (11820), 324 n. 2
427 n. 3; 4^0-1, 465, 469; (91), 441 ; (92), 414? (93), 414; (94), 4*5, 472, 473, 483; fe 6)) 4775 (97), 412; (98), 477 and n- 2; (99), 483-4; (100), 453 n - i; ( IOI )>
(9o) 5 432, 457,
452 n.; (102), 413, 442, 445, 472; (103), 352, 427; (104), 412, 451, 454 n. 3; (106), 413 n. i; (107), 415, 425 n., 429, 451, 452 n.; (108), 420, 472; (no), 433, 445; (m), 401, 445; (113), 426 n. i ; (114), 410, 425,
426, 431 n.
n. 2; (116),
427, 428 n.
i,
430;
(3),
486;
(4),
8; (5),
472
lis,
475;
(6), 462,
484;
(7),
477444
440
n. 2; (8), 438; (9), 412, 445; (10), 43 8 n. i, 455, 490-1; (12), 434, 462,
i>
489;
454 n. 2, 472; (115), 481 417 n. 2; (117), 433, 481; J 8), 433; ("9)> 482; (120), 465 n. 3; (121), 409 n. 3; (123), 83 n., 418 n. 3, 441,
i,
(13), 445 n. 2; (14), 473 n. 2; (15), 463, 475; (16), 474; (17), 412, 452 n.; (19), 412, 438; (21), 438, 477; (22), 411; (23),
443 n. 2; (125), 449; (126), 445, 479J (129), 157 and n., 158 n. 2, 417; (136), 481 n. 3
HERACUTUS HOMERICUS
Qu. Horn.
(24),
and
477
n. 3; (26), 433 n. 3,
477
n. 3; (27),
490
10,
208 n.
I,
375 n.
2,
432, 438 n. 2, 454, 455, 459, 464, 468, 471 and n.; (31), 420, 434, 453, 463, 464; (3 2),
463, 472
413
(36),
n. i, 490; (33), 409; (34), 412, n. 2, 426 and n. i, 438; (35), 204, 417;
HERODOTUS
i
433
&,
ter,
2,
421; (74),
5),
420; (95,
i),
422; (116,
412, 416, 417, 426 n. i, 45 1 ; n. i, 465; (42), 412 n. i, 413, 447 n. 3; (43), 409-10; (44), 410; (45), 47<>j (4<5), 43*> 45i; (47), 482; (48),
57, 204, 368,
422; (117, i), 421; (120, 2), 422; (120, 5), 421; (130), 46; (141), 420,
424,* (143, 2),
II (12),
(41), 88,
429 and
446 n. i ; (49), 409; (49 a), 460 n. 3, 490; (5), 4I4, 425, 428 n. i, 434 Ms, 439; (51), 438 nn. i, 2, 439 and n. 3, 460; (52), 478 n. 2; (53), 438 n. 2, 444, 446, 472, 473 J (54), 440-1, 443 n. 2; (55), 429, 452 n.; (56), 412, 414 n. 2, 443 n. 2; (57), 4*3> 442 and n. i, 484; (58), 438 n. 2, 442 and
n- 2; (59), 438 n. 2, 443; (60), 438 n. 2, 443, 478 n. 2; (61), 438 n. 2, 445 and n. 2;
(53)> 37i n. i; (81), 160, 173 n. 4; (109), 33> 35 n. i, 74, 422; (123), 160, 173 n. 4
i"
(99, 2), 422; (119, i), 424; (i25ff.), 346; (131-2), 174 n. 3; (142, 5), 421; (146, 3),
421; (148,
i),
420
iv
2)^420; (14), 159; (25), 294 n. i; (28, 2), 420; (42), 294 n. i; (93-4), 158-9; (95), 148; (138, i)> 421; (151), 4i8
(8,
(62), 464, 478, 490; (63), 478, 482; (64), 382 n. 2, 425 n. 3, 428, 429 and n. i, 432
n.,
464
n., 465,
474 (66), 455 fa, 473 (ft), 444 and n. 2, 445, 455, 472, 479; (68), 476 and n. i; (69), 475 n. 5; (70), 412; (72), 412,
419, 425 n. 3, 426, 452 n.; (73), 427; (74),
Its,
474;
&; (42), 463 n. 3; (50, 2), 398 n.; (93), 421 ; (142), 418; (158, 5), 421 viii (6, 2), 421; (68), 424; (100, i), 420; (100,3), 421; (115), 91 n-3
HESIOD
Erga
(78), 421; (106), 421;
&;
(109^), 400;
430 and n. 2; (76), 453 and n. 2, 462; (77), 433 and n. 4, 481; (78), 398, 413, 472; (79), 413, 472; (80), 438 n. i, 439 n. 3, 447, 473; (81), 417; (83),
416
n. 3; (75),
413 n. i; (126-7), 134; (229), 421; (885), 454 n. 3>* (89), 421
HlERONYMUS OF RHODES
ap.
D.L.
(27), 51, 53
509
to
Hermes
n. 5
(317), 421
i6ff. Festa), 191
IAMBLICHUS
De Loc. in Horn, (vi, 276 L.), 353 De Morb. Sacr. (vi, 364 L.), 475 n. i De Nat. Horn, (vi, 32 L.), 58, 132 n. 2, 384 De Nat. Pueri (vii, 488 L.), 61 n., 91 n. 2 De Vet. Med. (i, 572 L.), 345 and n. i; (i,
620
P.), 244 n. 3; (109, 9), 322 Protrepticus (9), 154 n., 168 n. 2
De
438 319
(vi,
191-2; (85), 188; (87), 191-2; (88), 150 n. I, 219, 268; (94), 151; (104), 341 n. i; (115), 224 n. i; (137), 199 n - 2 ; ( J 48), 273
n. 3;
HlPPOLYTUS
Refutatio
I
(2, 2),
n. 3, 253; (2, 83 ; (<$> a)> 91 n. 4; (6, 3), 98; (6, 4), 90, 93 ;
(6, 5),
248 n. 2, 298; (2, 12), 173 14), 184 n. 2; (<5, i), 44 n.,
i,
(177), 176; (197), 334 n. i; (199), 155 n. 2; (23iff.), 185 n. i; (248), 178 n. 3; (249), 179; (251), I79> I8o > O5*f.)> 180; (257), 320 n., 322; (267), 323, 341 n. i
106 n.
no;
I2I >
"9>
3; 0>
2)> I2 7;
294;
39*; 0>
title
ION OF CHIOS
fr. (i),
392; (14, 4~6\ 387; (15), 200, 324-5, 399 ix (8, i), 405; (9), 439; (10), 432 n., 474;
(10, 8),
406
ISAIAH
xxix (15), 474
HOMER
Iliad i (530), 374; (545), 421 n.
ISOCRATES
Busiris (28), 163; (29), 151
n
III
(485-6), 39 8
(21),
n*
(30),
426
n. i; (277), 474;
JUVENAL
x
n. i
LACTANTIUS
De
LASUS
Opif.
Dei
vni (305), 375 n. i ix (600), 374 n. 3 xi (225), 422 n. xiv (200), 60; (201), 60, 450 450 n. 2
fr. (i
Diehl), 220
LEUCIPPUS
fr. (2),
423
(33), 138 n. 3
n.
n. 2; (246), 60,
D.L. ix LUCIAN
ap.
(i87ff.), 454 n. 3; (393), 420 xvi (150), 129 n. i xvii (547), 393 n. i; (551), 393 n. i xvin (107), 447 n. i ; (309), 439 n. n. 3? (399)> ^o xxi (196), (So, 391
xv
De
Sacrif.
(6\ 129
i i
LUCRETIUS
3,
447
Odyssey
De
Mensibus
(p. 21
(248), 220
(14), 375 n. I (303), 82 n. 2; (469),
i
n. 2, 185 n. i
vin
MACROBIUS
47
n.
i,
311,
xi (100), 418 n.
481
xv
(90),
418 n.
MARCUS AURELIUS
iv (46), 416 n. 3
xix
(246), 99
v
393 n.
i
(27), 202 n. i
MARK,
n. 2; (48off.),
S.
197 n. 2
viii (18),
438
510
to
S.
vin
n. i
(4),
421
(66),
Pyth.
m (61), 199
(54), 421
420
MELISSUS
fr.
(2; 3
337 and
n.
vin
(38), 421
MlMNERMUS
fr.
x
fr.
(ioD.), 485
MNESIMACHUS
op.
DX.
(8, 37),
187
i
PLATO
AlcibiadesI (I
MOSCHUS
fr.
(6 N.), 401 n.
Apology
NlCANDER
Alex. (302), 91 n. 3 Ther. (355; 392)> 9 1 n 3
-
NlCOMACHUS
ii (6 and 7), 261 Harmon. (245 if. Jan), 224
Charmides (1560), 158 Cratylus (386 A), 401 n. 2; (4000), 311; (4010), 450; (402 A), 450, 489; (4028), 450 n. 2; (409 A), 286 n.; (4132), 45 6 5
n. i; (252), 298
Aritkm.
n.
OENOPIDES OF CHIOS
ap. Procl. in Euclid. (283, 9), 242 n. 2
(4I3B-C), 432, 474; (413^), 473 Epinomis (9778), 284 n. 2; (9810), 270; (983 A), 296 n.; (984E-985 A), 271 Epistle vn (3380), 334 n. 2 Gorgias (493 A), 311; ^OTE), 209, 305
OLYMPIODORUS
Laws
De ./4;te
czp.
(7820), 195 n.; (889A), 144; (895E), 351 n. i; (898A), 356; (8996), 65
c),
ONESICRITUS
Strab.
xv
(716), 187
Lysis (2146), 73 n. 2 Meno (76 A), 209; (80 D), 395 n. 5; (81 A,
Orphica
fr. (p.
209
52 Kern), 198 n. (3), 267 n. 2
(3, 1-2), 51
i
I ;
Hymn. 87 OVID
Trot, iv
PARMENIDES
fr. (i,
15), 421; (4, 3-4), 408 n. 2; (5), 427 n. i; (6, 4), 398; (6, 8-10), 408 n. 2; (8, 44), 379 n. 2; (8, 50), 421; (8, 57-8), 408
and n. 3, 311 204-5; (Sis), 312; (810), 312; (8<$B), 309; (880), 310; (96A), 73 n. 2; (968), 349; (996), 294; (1070), 482; (io8E), 100; (109 A HOB), 272 n. i;
(628), 162
n. i; (<53E),
n. 2; (12, 3), 88
PHILISTION
fr.(4
W.),359
(HID), 292; (1138), 202 n. i Phaedrus (2450), 351; (247 A), 293 n. 3 Philebus (248), 207 n.; (280), 429 n. i; (43 A), 460 n. 2
Republic (431
210,
PHILO
De Act. Mund. (21), 480 n. De Opif. Mund. XIII (44), 352 De Vit. Mos. i (6), 478 n. 2
PHILOLAUS
fr-
Protagoras (320 off.), 400 n. 3; (343 A), 50 ff.), 317; (4$>8A), 484; (5000),
423; (525D), (5290), 162 and n.
162,
213;
i,
(5278),
213;
165;
227;
(53iA),
220;
(0, 33o;
(22), 311
(<$),
Sophist
n.,
460;
n. 2;
(242E), 440
8ff.),
278-9 and
n.
PHILOPONUS
De Anima
PINDAR
hth. v (13), 421; (14), 196; (26), 421; (28), 166 n. 3 Nem. IV (31), 423; (44f.), 220
Ol.
ii
vn
(21),
420
to
388, c), 338; (390), 339 and n. i; (390), 282; (40 A), 356; (40B-C), 291 ; (41 c), 349
n. ; (41 E), 291 ; (43 D-E), 354; (45 D), 377 n. i; <47B-c), 210; (50E), 444 n. 2; (520),
i? 2 ; (40, 254; (43)> l88 ; (44), 253; (54), 178 n. 3; (57), 179; (57ff.), 180; (85), 188 Quaest. Horn.
n. 3
'>
(37)
184
n, 2,
ad
ad
(i,
xiv, 200
PLINY
In Ptolem. Harm.
(12, 53), 46; (31), 74; (187),
N.H. n
xvin
44
n.
PRATINAS
fr.
v.(ii2), 29 n. 2
(118), 184
PROCLUS
In Eucl.
Fried!.), 219; (65), 268; (65,
3&),
n.
i
54 n.
PTOLEMY
Harmon.
PLUTARCH
Adv.
Aqu.
Colot.
et
n
n. i
(12),
n.
RUFUS
ap. Oribasius (in, 156), 348
De Am. ProL (4940), 104 De An. Procr.(ioi2D), 26311. i; (ioi2E), 253 De Aud. Poet. (l7E), 395 n. i De Def. Orac. (41 5 F), 457; (4223, D), 322 De E (390 A), 273 n. i; (3926), 489; (3928De Fortuna (980), 484 n. I De Is. et Os. (34), 58 De Prim. Frig. (947F), 124 De Pyth. Orac. (402 F), 54 n. De Ser. Num. Vind. (5590), 489 De Soil. Anim. (9820), 104 De Superst. (ii6c), 427 and n. 3
Qu. Conv. (727D), 103
n.; (727-8),
*
SABINUS
ap. Galen, in Hippocr. de nat. horn, (xv, 25),
384
SENECA
De
Tranq.
xv
II
(2),
409
n. i
i
Quaest. Nat.
(95),
300
iv (4f.), 2 &3 n. 2
367
(49)>
184
n. i;
n. i,
395
i; (127),
(7290), 194 n. 2; (73 EX I02f Qu. Nat. (9I2A), 489; (9120), 450 Qu. Plat. (10030), 269; (10070), 339 Lye. (25), 377 n. i V. Sol (2), 51
397 n. i; (326), 395 n. i ix (127), 200 n. 2, 278 x (280), 260 n. 3; (281), 263 and n. 2; (282),
262; (313), 384
I
[PLUTARCH]
Strom, (n), 90, 98, 102, 133 fa; (iv), 373, 381 (x), 136 n. 2
Pyrrfu
no;
n.,
377
(18), 395 n. i
De
II
Vita Horn.
(4),
443 n. 2
fr.
POLYBIUS
(39, 1-4), 179
SlMONIDES 4 Diehl
(i
and
6),
428 n. 2
PORPHYRY
DeAlst.l
(15), 194; (23), 194; (26), 163, 194
SIMPLICIUS
De Anima
(<58, 10),
II (4),
De
184
(7),
De Antr. Nymph.
V.P.
(<5),
(202,
14),
106,
173 n. 3, 254;
107-8; (386, 22), 215 n. i; (468, 27), 297 n. 3; (471, 4), 93; (471, 5), 298
n. i; (511, 25),
(12), 173 n. 3, 253; (15), 190; (18), 175 n. i; (19), 151, 1 86; (20), 225 n.; (30) 297
512
to
THEOGNIS
and
n. i;
107; (615, 20), 123; (621, 9), 268 n. Cat. (412, 26), 447
(141-2), 398 n.; (254), 421; (415), 418; (417^), 422 Theologumena Arithmeticae
(p. 53
85), 260,
332
n. 3
Phys. (22, 26 ff.), 369 n. 3; (22, 29 f. Diels), 367; (23, 16), 377; (23, 21 ff.), 469 n.; (23, 32), 54 n.; (23, 33), 320, 432; (23, 33-24, 4), 457 and n. i; (24, 4), 458 n. 5; (24, 13),
76; (24, 14), 43 n. 2; (24, 16), 109; (24,
21), 81 n. 2; (24, 26), 43 n. 2, 121; (25, u), 64 n. i; (61), 219 n. 2; (70, 16), 73; (77, 31), 489-90; (149, 32), 120 n.; (150, 20), 89 n. 2; (150, 22), 77; (150, 24), 79 n.; (181, 10), 244; (181, 28), 247 and n.; (455,
20), 243 n. 4; (651, 26), 277; (732, 26), 186 n. 2, 281 n. 2; (1121, 5), 108; (1165,
THEOPHRASTUS
130
D.L. ix
(6),
409
n. i
43-4
n.
ff.),
469 n.; (23, 33), 320, 432; (24, 4), 321 n. 2; (24, 14), 43-4 n.; (24, 26), 44 n.; (24, 31), 127 n.
fr.
89
(p.
189
Wimmer), 228-9
(22, i), 420; (97),
THUCYDIDES
344 n. 2; 420 vi (46, 5), 420 vii (56, 4), 422
1
(i, 3),
420
450 ^
5
(50),
SOLON
fr.
TlMAEUS
fr.
SOPHOCLES
i,
64),
362
Ajax(^\
EL
TIMON
ap.
D.L. ix
(6),
411 n. 2
422
TYRTAEUS
fr. (9, i
O.C. (1163X421
Diehl), 421
O.T.
VARRO
ap. Augustin.
I
C.D. vn
(17),
396 n. 3
VIRGIL
Geor. HI (271
ff.),
n. 3
129 n.
VlTRUVIUS
420
215
n.
i,
i),
WISDOM OF SOLOMON
(18, ic),
xi(2o), 31211. 4
XANTHUS OF LYDIA
ap. Strab.
I
(49),
387
n.
2,
in
i
(i, 172),
412 n. 2;
n.,
(20, 53),
409 n.
XENOPHANES
fr. (i),
STRABO
(p.
7 C.), 44
vi (p. 263
n. 2
C), 176; (280), 334 n. i xiv (632), 409; (638), 217; (642), 411
(),
(17),
(22),
xv SUDA
(716), 187
372 n. i; (18), 376, 399; (21 a), 366; 360, 366; (23), 374, 375 lis and n. i,
376 fa; (24), 374 and n. 2, 375; (25), 373, 374, 382 bis and n. 2; (26), 374, 381, 382; (27), 383, 3 8 5 Ks> (28), 367, 381 n.; (29),
59, 8 Spengel), 263 n. i
THEO SMYRNAEUS
14 Killer), 425 n. i; (22), 244; (50), 228;
(56), 222; (57), 224; (61), 226; (97), 277;
385; (30), 39i; (32), 392; (33), 385, 387; (34), 376 Aw, 395 and n. i, 396, 397 Ks, " 3; (35), 398; (3 6), 397; (37), 399,
4M
XENOPHON
Anal, in
(2, 17),
THEODORETUS
iv (5), 377, 384; (22), 486 n. 2
Mem.
(i,
n), 73
475 n. n. 2
513
II.
GENERAL INDEX
modern scholars denote a main
entry.
Boldfigures
Abaris, 218, 319
in entries referring to
Alcmaeon of Croton, 232 f., 246, 247, 313, 341 ff. treatise on by Aristotle, 233
date, 341-3* 342 n., 344 n. i, 357ff.; relationship to Pythagoreans, 341; writings,
flesh, Pythagorean, Porphyry's work on, 193$. abstract, expression of by adjective and article, ambiguity of, 79, 116, 242 abstraction, attained by Greeks, 37 ; of
medical
number, not recognized by Pythagoreans, 242 Academic School, 22 Academy of Plato, 10 actuality and potentiality in Aristotle, 12 Acusmata (Symbola), Pythagorean, i83ff.,
188
acusmaticiy 191 ff.
interests, 314, 344; empirical approach, 345, 346, 349, 358; his physio-
logy summarized by Theophrastus, 347 account of the senses, 347 f.; brain as central
organ, 348, 349; hearing, 349; sleep, 349;
dis-
between
sensation
and
Adrastus, on Pythagorean musical theory, 228 aer (<5rf|p) : earlier history of word, 126; among
elements, reputedly first in Empedocles, 453; as vapour, 81 ; in Heraclitus, 453 and n. 2; less pure form otaither, 471, 480; in
thought, 348 doctrine of opposites, 232 f., 341; his pairs not enumerated, 247, 345 ; their application to mankind, 345 f.; health depends on
balance of opposites, 313, 346, 436
on the
Anaximander's cosmology, 92; and pneuma, in Anaximenes, 131 and n.; renders invisible but can be seen through,
95 n.
i
soul, 354ff.; in everlasting motion, hence divine, 313, 350; soul-stuff animates the cosmos, 355, with circular motion, 354; motion impeded by crasser material of body, 356; fate after death,
354jff.:
no evidence for
belief in trans-
Aeschylus,
374^
400, 415
i,
164
daimon, 355
Agathemerus, 74 n.
Ahriman (Areimanios), 250 Akuna Vcdrya, 488 Ahura Mazdah, nature of, 2546
Aion, 478 n. 2
air (see also aer), as a
Empedocles, 348, 358, 359; to Anaxagoras, 359; to Plato, 354 [Alexander of Aphrodisias], on Aristotle's account of Pythagorean generation from
relation to
Anaximenes, ii5fT.; as source of life in popular belief, 128 , cf. 480; divine, 130; in Anaximenes, substance both of human
soul and divine universe, 13 if., 201; parallel with human soul in Diogenes of
n. 3, 244;
and
470;
aither,
470, 480; in Parxnenides, 136; substance of the dalmones in Plato, Epinomis, 271-3; in Aristotle, 271; as a 5th
2,
Allman, G.
ocAAoicocris,
J., 46 n. 89 n. 2
514
General index
ambiguity, of oracles, 414
cosmogony: no
detailed
working-out of
88, 89 n.
I,
gonies, 134; basic stuff of cosmos, 279; his arche air, ii5f.; arche alive, immortal and eternal, 128; arche in eternal motion,
300, 357;
Mind
472
n.
i;
127; psyche its source of motion, 128; association of air and life {psyche), 128;
rational motives for choice of air, i^ff.; unconscious and traditional reasons,
I27ff., 130; not retrogressive choice, 116; rarefaction and condensation of air, i2off.,
illumination
Anaximander, 43, 71, 72ff., 120, 279, 294, 337; background, 29; Ionian spirit of historic, 43; date, 72; no mention of before
Aristotle, 72; taste for travel, 75; reputed statue of, 75 and n. 3
460; accounts
by
124; linked with Anaximander' s doctrine of opposites, i24f.; 'offspring' of air the other elements, 122; difficulty
of producing fire from air via earth, 134; gods arisen from air, 130; analogy between cosmic air and human soul, 131,
201, 428 formation of natural world: evidence lacking, 123; earth, shape
Unlimited,
'injustice*
off',
76,
heavenly bodies originate from the earth, i33f.; stars of nature of fire, containing
earthy bodies, 134; fixed in the crystalline, or like fiery leaves, 135; possible distinction of planets and fixed stars, 135; at great distance from the earth, 138; sun
flat like leaf,
compared with Heraclitus, 447, 453; meaning of apeiron, 82, 83 ff.; nature of
both indefinitely large and having no beginning in time, 337f.;
apeiron, 109, 272;
and
the apeiron material, 242; apeiron living divine, 114, 470; equated with the
mixture of Empedocles and Anaxagoras, 77 n. 3; whether in fact a mixture, 87 and n. 2; ultimate prevalence of fire over
water, 101 ; end of the cosmos, 100 and n. 2 cosmology: numerical basis of, 219; astronomical achievements, 74; formation of heavenly bodies, 93 f.; dimensions of celestial objects, 95^; sun, moon and eclipses, 49, 93; shape and position of earth, 98; release from view that earth is supported, 99 ; alleged view that earth is in motion, 99; origin of sea, 92; sea will dry up eventually, 92, 101, 388; 'innumerable worlds', io6ff.; the coreipoi oupovoi
in effect a hemisphere,
in,
350
anthropomorphism, abandoned by Milesians, 44; attacked by Xenophanes, 371 ff. Antiochus, teacher of Cicero, 22
Antiphanes, 187 Antisthenes of Rhodes, Successions, on Heraclitus,
rain, 105
and
origin of
life,
101
ff.
409 n. 2
Anaximenes, 43, 208 n. i, 279; background, 29; date and writings, 115; use of simile,
i38f.; relation to Anaximander, 115; influence on Xenophanes, 391 ; deduction
by
not necessarily "infinite*, 381 and n.; of indistinguishable parts, 85f.; 'having no beginning or end* (Melissus), 337; used of spheres and rings,
85; also temporal aspect, 280; temporal
515
General index
aperon and
calculation as ruling force in nature
spatial
and
senses
not distinguished,
morals, 336
els finreipov
indefinitely', 378,
393
4.
Aphrodite, 27, 70 apokrisis or ekkrists (separation), as a cosmogonic process, 896% 105, 119; of seed in
under Pythagoras's
womb, 91 Apollo, 28, 44; particular patron of Pythagoreans, 203, 205; in Empedocles, 203
n. i ;
constitution, 175 aristocrats, character of in sixth century, 365 Aristophanes, 9, 106 n. i, 130
Aristophon (comic poet), 187 Aristotelian terminology, 56 Aristotle, survival of early ideas in, 2; philo-
by
sophy
of, i2ff.;
on origin of philosophy,
Apollodorus, chrono legist, 46; method of fixing floruit, 4$.; on date of Anaximander, 72 ; of Xenophanes, 3 62 ; of Heraclitus, 408
Apollonia, Milesian colony, 75
30, 31; as historian of philosophy, 41 ft., 56, 82, 120, 2i4f., 237; cautious attitude
Apollonius of Tyana, 169 Pythagorean, 150 &rr6ppTiTO$ A6yos, in Phaedo, 310 Apsu, Babylonian male principle, <5o Aratus, quoted by S. Paul, 24 arche (<5cpx^), early search for, 28 ; term first used by Anaximander, 77; senses of, 57;
&rr6ppT}Tcc (or appTjTa),
on Thales, 546; abundance of surviving work, 25 ; classificatory work, 14; scheme of causation, 63, 236; classification of motion, 382; modernity of outlook, 237; definition of time, 338; on sensation and
thought, 348; Ethics, 13; jProtrepticus, 1 54, 171 ; on Alcmaeon, 341 ; on Archytas,
334 n. i; on Heraclitus, 437, 451; on Philolaus, 329; references to Pythagoras, 1536; on the Pythagoreans, 42, i54f.,
183,200, 214$'., 229 fT.; on Xenophanes, 366-7; relation to Democritus, 12; to
Plato, 12
divinity of, 88, 89 n. i, 128; as reservoir of all that exists, 82 and n. i; cause of
changes in, 63 ; living and sentient ace. to Anaximenes, 128 ff., 470; as conscious directive force, 88; in Milesians, always intermediate between opposites, 457; related to world as soul to body, 316; in
Aristoxenus, 150, 169, 178 n3, 188-9, I 9 I J on conformity with the divine, 199, 210; on Pythagoras's enthusiasm for the study of
Alcmaeon, none, 345; in Anaximander, 76.; in Anaximenes, 115; in Hippasus, 320; in Pythagoreans, the beginning of
number-series, the unit, 244; in
Xeno-
phanes, 378 Archedemus, associate of Archytas, 334 Archelaus, on shape of earth, 294
Archilochus, 415; criticized
Artemis, 44
Asclepius, 436
scientific, 3
of philoso-
by Heraclitus, 412
and n. i, 413, 447 n. 3 Archippus of Tarentum, Pythagorean, 180 Archytas of Tarentum, 147, 162 n. 2, 180, 273, 322, 333fL; date, 334; friendship with Plato, 333; extent of interests, 3356;
public
life, 333 ; possible influence in Plato's Republic, 333; contributions to
Athena, 28 Athens, 7, 8
dr^s, 462 n. i atomism, of Leucippus and Democritus, 5, 6f., 129, 143; of Ecphantus, 3255".; innumerable worlds in, ii3f.
i;
on infinite
260; mechanical applications, 335; theories on sound, 226 ff.; ratios of musical scales
336;
on
the
Decad,
numbers
finite
according to Ecphan-
tus, 326f.
autarkeia, 17
516
General index
autarkes, of the Stoic Sage, 20
ccuroiv, in
Speusippus, 249
Burch, G. B., 96 n. 2
Burnet,
J.
84
166 n.
i,
204, 221,
34,
138 n. 2;
369 n. 2, 481
217!".;
cosmology,
Cadmus, 50 and
n.
i,
Bacchus, properties
of,
372
i
Callimachus, 185 n.
189, 343
i,
96 n.
Cambridge Platonists, 24 Cambyses, 218, 253, 254 Cameron, A., 157 n., i<5i n. i, 164 n. ? 165, 310 n. 2, 311 n. i, 330 n. 2
Campbell, L., 401 n. 2 Capek, M., 282 n. i
Carneades, 22
Casella, F.,
beans,
explanations
i84f.;
rationalized
taboo else-
where, 185
Beare,
J.
n. i
387 n. 4
at,
363
Greek
philosophers,
scheme,
234, 236;
89,
63
Aristotelian,
senses
of,
relation to
moving
cause,
problem
of, 6f.,
Berosus, 94
Berthelot, M., 58 n. 3 Bias of Priene, 412 n. 2
birth,
necessity (Atomists, Empedocles), 143 f.; as 'nature*, mechanical and non-theological, 144;
40
21
celature,
analogous to cosmogony, in Anaximander, 90; in Pythagoreanism, 278 f.; interest in, a feature of primitive thought, 62 n. 2 body as tomb or prison, Pythagorean and Orphic view, 311, 331, 464; whether
174
Celsus, 137
Celts,
Cercops, Pythagorean, 319 Ceyx, wedding of, in Hesiod, 103 chance, and nature, Plato quoted on, 144
change,
continuous
and
imperceptible,
in
471 n.
190
Heraclitus, 451
Boehm,
Boll, F.,
F., 183 n. i,
84
n. 3,
87 n.
2,
97 n.
4,
46
n. i,
48
n. 3, 135
Bomer,
307
Booth, N. B., 265 n. i, 408 n. 2 Bowra, C. M., 363 n., 364 n., 365 brain, as centre of sensation, in Alcmaeon and
Plato, 349
Z3 fChrysippus, of Soli, 19, 20, 21, 202 n. i Chrysogonus, flute-player, 423 n. Cicero, on Epicurus, 19; on Carneades, 22;
2,
278.
See also
on Anaximander, 75
411;
n. 2;
De
Officiis,
22;
circle,
i
i
297 and beginning and end (Alcmaeon), common 35 iff.; beginning and end n. i (Heraclitus), 427 (Parmenides), 427 circular motion, in Aristotle, 13; the only continuous, 35 if.; and psychic functions,
Brugmann,
C., 47 n. 2
356
517
General index
circularity,
connexion with life, 351 ff.; and reason, 35<5; special perfection of, in
Aristotle, 2; and later, 3, 207; of time, 452; or cycle (irepbSos), of the body, 353
68 f.; given in terms of organic Hfe in earHer Greek speculation, 90 ; stages in Presocratics between arche and variety of
nature, i22f., 273; alternate creation dissolution of world, 28 if.
and
cithara,
224
Greek, 15; com15
Alexander,
15
neglected
by
early
Greek
ism,
thinkers, 37
Claudianus Mamertus, on Hippasus, 321; on Philolaus, 311 Cleanthes, 293; on soul in HeracHtus, 434, 491 Clement of Alexandria, 24; on mystery cults,
in ProtreptzcuS) 473
of,
in
and
coagulation (trdyos), of air in Empedocles, 136 cocks, forbidden to epileptics, 190; to Britons, 190; white cocks forbidden to Pytha-^
destructibiHty, 389^ counter-earth, invented by Pythagoreans, 213, 282rT., 288; attributed to Philolaus, 284;
to Hicetas, 328 j
Crates, 93
goreans as sacred to lunar god, 188 Codrus, 409 Cohen, M. R. and Drabkin, I. E., 53 n. 2 coinage (incuse), in Croton and neighbour-
ibid.'
hood, 176 Colophon, birth-place of Xenophanes, 363 comic poets, on Pythagoreans, i63f., 187 common, of Heraclirus's Logos, 425 f.j use of term in HeracHtus, 447 etc.
and the river-statement, 489 creation, and evolution in ancient thought, 142; ex mhilo, foreign to Greek thought,
454 n. 3 creator, in Plato, 143 ; absence
philosophy, 142
Critias, on progress in human culture, 400 Croesus, 32, 115; and Thales, 46; and the
of in early Greek
common
tion, 9
concordance, in Greek music, 223 concordant intervals, see intervals condensation and rarefaction of air, in Anaxi-
oracle,
414
Croton, migration of Pythagoras to, 174; home of Alcmaeon, 341; medical school at, 174
n. 3, 346f.
meaning viscous and transparent', 137; question of, in Anaximenes, 135 f. crystals, geometrical forms of, 226 n. 2, 269
crystalline,
by HeracHtus,
by
197
Cook, R. M., 47
n.
curiosity, source
of philosophy, 30
by
theories of
Cyaxares, 46
118, 125, 172, 221, 242 nn., 244, 249, 250, 264, 265 n. i, 273 n. 2, 301 n. 2, 303,
also transmigration), 2O2f., 354, 478, 480; with HeracHtus, 480, 481 n. i; of
309 n., 315, 323, 344, 381 n., 382 n. 2 corporeaHry (see also matter), emergence of distinct notion of, 326
the seasons, 80, 352; astronomical, and cycHc renewal of die universe, in HeracHtus, 458; of world-renewal and of world creation and destruction, 458 n. 5 cyclic change, in HeracHtus, 433 Cylon, conspiracy and revolt of, i78f., 320 Cynic School, 10, 187
cosmogony, mythical, xi, 28 60, 68, 119, 141 ; creative and evolutionary contrasted,
,
142; design
in, i42f.;
58; in Diodorus,
518
General index
Cyrenaic School, 10 Cyrus, 32, 46, 362, 363
daimon^ daimones, meanings of word, 318, 482; in Hesiod, etc., 3i8f.; as divine attendants of Dionysus, 291 ; as divine element
in
Deucalion, 388 development, human: two conflicting views in classical Greece, 400; viewed as a progress,
SiccKOcrueiv,
dialectical
man, 3i8f.;
47
n. 2,
48 n.
3,
107
n.,
no,
126
408
n. 3
423
n.
Darsow, W., 75
dasmos (Saauos), 29, 454 n. 3 death, in Empedocles, common to body and soul, 314; one element living the death of
another (Heraclitus), 453 ; due to inability to 'join the beginning to the end*
dimension, defined
Dingle, H., 3 Diogenes of Apollonia, 92, 121, 123, 131, 135 n. i, 294; follows Anaximenes on air and
soul, i29f.; restores unity
spirit,
of matter and
terms of form, not matter (Pythagorean), 257 Deichgraber, K., 342 n., 366, 377 n. 2, 379 n. 2, 384 n., 385, 390 n. 2, 407, 462 n. 2 Delatte, A., 151 n. 2, 157 n., 161 n. i, 164 n., 173 n. 3, 183 nn. i and 2, 184 n. 3, 193 n., 200 n. 2, 202 n., 203 n. i, 225 n. i, 335
n. 3, 417 n. i, 478 n. 2 Delian League, 8 Delphic oracle, 414, 417, 418
human soul, 470 Diogenes Laertius, as source, xiv; on Pythagorean Acusmata^ 183; on meeting of Philolaus and Plato, 329; on Alcmaeon,
344 Dionysius II of Syracuse, 334 Dionysus, 27, 478 and n. 2; phallic processions in honour of, 475 n. 4; identified with Hades by Heraclitus, 463, 475, 476 divinity, to Greeks synonymous with everlasting life, 480; conception of TO Qeiov both
Delphic precepts, 183 Demeter, 197, 449 Demetrius of Magnesia, 323 and n. 2; on Philolaus, 330 Demetrius of Phaleron, 16 Democedes, of Croton, court physician to
democratic
Polycrates, 174; his career, 346f. government, in fifth-century Athens, 8
of cosmos, in Ecphantus, 326 of primary entity, 4; in Anaximander, 87 f.; in Anaximenes, 128 of primary substance, in Milesians, 88
divisibility, infinite,
265 n.
n. i
Democritus,
6,
69 n.
i,
89 n.
i,
book on Pythagoras,
155;
soul, 129, 201; on shape of earth, 294; simile of motes in air, 307; atomic system
on
adopted by Epicurus, 18; 'the laughing philosopher*, 409; notion of microcosm in, 208 n. i ; on human ignorance, 399
Dercyllides, on Anaximander, 98 design in nature, in Plato's JLaws, 12, 144; absence of in early Greek philosophy,
century
B.C.,
crystals in
form
of,
Dome,
142 rl.
destructions, of human race
i
by fire,
flood, etc.,
H., 244 n. 4 Drabkin, I. E., see Cohen Dreyer, J. L. E., 93 n., 95 n., 97 n. 2, 98, 136 n. i, 294 n. i Duchesne-Guillemin, J., 254^ Dunbabin, T. J., 50 n. i, 174 n. 4, 175 f., 178
n. i
During, L, 171
n.,
222 and n. 2
519
General index
dyad, indefinite, 202 n., 248, 264 dynamis (8tivcxnis), usage of die term, 325 n. i ; of atoms, fresh conception of Ecphantus,
457; associated with Great Year, 458; question of, in Heraclitus, 45 5 f.
Edelstein, L., 342, 357
effluences,
326
earth,
Empedocles's theory
of,
209
shape of: in Anaximander, 98 ; in Anaximenes, 133; in Pythagoreans, 293 ff. ; evidence of Aristotle on believers in flat earth, 294; sphericity: date of discovery, 2931!., 393 n. 2; first mentioned
in early
in Plato's Phaeclo, 295; position: central, Greek thought, 289; freely sus-
129 Egypt, journeys to by early Greek philosophers, 32, 48, 2175 scientific and tech-
its
rotating
by
328; central
view adopted by
Pythagoreans, 267 ehtatikos (Kor<rnK6$), 231 Elea, foundation of, 362 f.; association with
circling the centre, 282; planetary notion short-lived, 290; called star by Pytha-
name of Xenophanes, 363 by Parmenides, 363; reputedly by Xenophanes, 361, 363 elements, four explicitly distinguished by
Eleatic School, founded
Empedocles,
5,
Xenophanes, 3 83 ff. ; its generative power, 292; as mother of all life, 291, 385 f.; as Hestia (hearth of universe), 293
earthquakes, predicted by Anaximander, 75 and n. 2; storks give warning of, 75 n. 2;
tion,
up by
their opposites, 81; fifth element: history of, 2706; five elements in Chinese
philosophy, 252
elenchtic methods, 9
134,
i,
Echecrates, 169, 273, 310 eclipses, and date of Thales, 46-9; in Anaximander, 96; in Anaximenes, 135; in
Leucippus,
Heraclitus, 483, 486; prediction of, 33; extent of Babylonian prediction, 48; of
maeon, 348 Empedocles, 5, 6, 120, 136, 165, 172, 177, 199, 200 n. i, 267, 294; motive cause in, 88; four elements in, 1221*.; relationship with Pythagoreans, i6o, 208 n. 2, 258; verses
n., 285,
286
See zodiac
3,
and rebirth
of,
389;
created
apparently influenced
supposed work
On
144;
evidence for his views, 324^; cosmology reminiscent of the Timaeus, 326; his cosmos unique, 32<5; declared Pytha-
gorean monads corporeal, 32 y; atomic theory distinct from Democritus's, 326; his atoms limited in number, 325 and n. 2; combination of genesis from numbers,
3i3,
318; Love and Strife in, 305, 437; Apollo in Empedocles, 203 n. 2; theories of
sensation and thought, 348; relation to
physis
Alcmaeon, 348, 358; of unlimited sphere*, 85; kinship of nature, i8<5, 208, 278; preached abstention from beans, 185,
*
Heraclitus, 437; to
in,
82;
speaks
520
General index
Empedocles (cent.) 189; from flesh, 195; believed all things had consciousness, 200; god in Empedo203 n. 2; claimed immortality, 206; kosmos in, 208 n. i; theory of effluences, 209
cles,
i,
125
391
Festugiere, A.
Field,
fifth
165 n.
i,
202
n,,
354, 358 n.
n.
G.
C, 334 n.
3,335
n.
Bacchic
rites,
231, 372
figures, origin
fir,
,
Enuma
Elish,
596
particular associations
Epaminondas, 179
Ephesus, legendary foundation of, 409 EpicharmuSj 244 n. i, 362, 423 n., 426 n.
Epictetus, 21
fire,
i
'nourished*
by
by Pythagoreans
worlds
regarded with religious awe, 288 ; equated with pyramid, 267, 268; related to cither
in Aristotle, 270; in Heraclitus, see Heraclitus; popularly identified with aither,
466-,
92,94 and origin of human life, 102 f.; eating of, 103 n.; sacred fish not to be eaten, 188
abstention
flesh,
269
writings, 195; Pythagorean prohibition on, i87ff.; eating confined to some species,
1 88;
93, 98, 218; his Astronomical History, 74, 334 n. i; on eternal recurrence, 281; on Pythagoreans'
investigations into positions of planets,
95, 298 Eudorus, on pre-Platonic Pythagoreanism, 244 and n. 4, 247, 248 and n. 2 Eudoxus, 187, 253, 290, 393 n. 2
an exception, and transmigration, Empedocles on, 195 and n. flood (see also destructions), connected with
denied,
195;
eating
of,
floruit
on
progress,
400; imitates
Xenophanes, 373 and n. Eurytus, 258, 2738".; meeting with Plato, 329 evolution, as opposed to creation, 142 Examyes, father of Thales: a Carian name,
50
exhalations. See Heraclitus
form and matter in Aristotle, 12; distinction between them, 234; and teleology,
12; purely actual form, in Aristotle, is
God, 12
forms, in Plato,
fossils,
io,
n.
2
i
521
General index
Frankj E., 53 n. x, 150 n. 2, 181 n., 201 n. 2, 2<5 5 n. 2, 324, 330, 332, 335 n. 3 Frankel, H., x, 81 n. i, 363 n. 3, 381 f., 390 n. 2, 393 n. 2, 395 nn., 396 nn. i and 3, 397
Golden Race, heroes of, 400, 478 Gomperz, H., 65, 312 n.
gonimon, of Anaximander, 90, 278 good, according to Pythagoreans: in the table of opposites, 245, 246; in the end, not the beginning, 251; a peace produced by
imposition ofperas on apeiron, 448;
and
nn.,
444
n. 2,
446
good
and bad
445
identified
by
Heraclitus, 442,
385
2,
K. von, 170 n.
171
n.,
180,
goodness,
its
true nature to
be sought (Socit
n. i,
373
n. 3,
426
n. 2,
n. i
rates), 10;
question whether
has a true
252
nature, 10; as
Gorgias, 73 Great Year (Perfect Year), 282 and n. 2, 353; and periodic destructions of mankind,
101, 388; and ecpyrosisy 458 Greek language, later universality
Griffiths, J.
of,
Galen, 137;
Nature, 343; on Xenophanes, 384 galeus, dogfish or shark, 102, 103 and nn.
23 f.
Gwyn,
of,
35 n.
generalization, importance (and dangers) of, 3<S; in Thales, 54; and universals, neces-
yup6s,
meaning
98 f.
i,
Guthrie,
W. K.
C., 39 n.
43 n.
i,
69
n. 3,
102
40
n. i, 132 n. i, 137 n. 2, 182 n. 2, 203 n. i, 206 n., 272 n. i, 282 nn., 285 n. 3, 291 n. i,
generation, logical and chronological, 23 9 f., 456; spontaneous, 59, 102 n. i, 386
genesis, problem of, 38 ; by separation according
3,
466
n. 2,
470
to Anaximander, 76 f. ;
Hackforth, R., 293 n. 3, 311 n. i Hades: equated with Dionysus (Heraclitus), 463, 475, 476; with Areimanios, 249 n. 2
Halley, Edmund, 47 harmonia, harmonie, harmony: account of the word, 220, 2^3; as octave, 223, 288 n., * proportion* 298 n. 2; other senses:
n. 3; in Heraclitus, the reverse
Gigon, O., 29 n.
n. 2,
i,
414 n.
3,
415, 428
n. 2,
444 n. 2, 445 n. 2, 453, 454 n. 2, 459, 477 n. 3, 478 n. 2 Gilbert, O., 105, 106 n. Giordano Bruno, possible influence of
4, 434,
Ecphantus on, 327 gnomon, of sundial, 33, 74; Pythagorean use, 241 ; essential meanings of term, 242 and n. god (see also anthropomorphism; divinity; Heraclitus), concern of gods for human affairs, in early Greek thought, 27; held
responsible
for
Pythagorean, 43 5 f., a precarious equilibrium, 440 (see further under Heraclitus); soul as harmorda (Pythagorean), 307 f.
human
failings,
26
482 n.; neglected by lonians, 30; assimilation to, see divinity; relation of man to God, in Aristotle, 13; all things full of
air a
small portion
299
within us (Diog. Apoll.), 130; spherical in Xenophanes, 376 ff., and identified with the world, 381 ff.; in
Aristotle, 13
Harpagus the Mede, 363 head, the seat of intelligence (Alcmaeon), 348 health, as harmony of physical opposites, in
Alcmaeon, 346; in Western school of
medicine,
Goettling, C.
gold
and
436;
in
Plato's
Symposium,
Magna
522
General index
of intelligence (Empedocles), 348; sensorium (Aristotle), 349 heat: connexion with life, 61, 92, 291, (in
heart, seat
common
Archilochus,
i2i,
Pythagoras, 157, 412, 417, 448; criticized by Parmenides, 408 and n. 2; ignored by later, scientific, philosophers, 419; bor-
Heath, T., 46 n.
i,
n. 2, 138 n. i,
47, 49, 95 n., 97 nn., 135 and 218 n., 265 n. 2, 269 n. i,
rowings by
Stoics, 404;
misunderstood
by
Aristotle to
be
essentially Milesian,
i, 288, 295 n. 2, 297 n. i, 324, 335 n. i See also heaven, separation from earth, 68
300
n. 4,
Ouranos
heavenly bodies, living creatures in Aristotle, 2; divinity of, 350, 357 and n., 480 Hecataeus, 74, 157,408 Heidel, W. A., 57 n. 2, 58 n. i, 67, 72 n. 3, 73 n 2 > 74 f-> 77 nn. i, 3, 4, 80 n., 82 n. i, 97 n. i, 100 n. 2, 118, 161 n. 2, 219 and n. 2,
-
and religious teachers, 403 and n. his obscurity, 403, 410 f.; due to amalgamation of spiritual and material in
his expression, 428, 469; the *Riddler*, 41 1, 443 and n. 2; ancient references to his
man-
kind, 410 ff.; anecdote concerning Socrates, 41 if.; oracular style, 414; picture-
2,
323, 342
n.,
374 n.
2,
language, paradox, parable, 410, 438, 461 ; word-play, 425 n. 5, 475 n. 2; on occasion brilliantly clear, 41 1 and n. 3
philosophical method: prophetic character
Heinimann,
F., 58 n. i
self-
414,
416,
417$".;
conclusions
n.
n. 2
the Logos, 4i9f; its existence affirmed at the outset, 419; independent of the
speaker,
and his school, 163 f.; on Pythagoras philosophia, 204; relation to Hicetas
Heraclitus,
4,
and and
428, 431; includes act of thinking or reflexion, 426 and n, i; has material
425
83 n.
i,
145,
43-9^
embodiment, 428; in
fire,
variety of
modern
interpretations, 403;
subject of ICing Darius, 488; membership of royal clan at Ephesus, 408 ; date and
life,
by human thought
408 ff.; anecdotes and sayings illus* trative of his character, 409 ; the weep-
('steering') principle of the universe, 428; both outside and within the cosmos, 472; is H.*s nearest approach
and governing
ing* philosopher, 409 and n. i ; relation to the prevalent world-picture of his time,
to an arche, 428; the true Logos: 'all things are One*, 425, 444; identified with
469
479
summary
sources, 405 f.
of conception, 434
the senses: H.'s mistrust of, 5; need to be interpreted by the understanding, 415,
429, 451; but primary channels of communication with the Logos, 429 f. (cf.
writings, 406-8; doubt of extent of his own actual words, 403; question whether he wrote a book, 406 f. and n. 2; Aristotle's
evidence for
its
of mankind, 412; for his own people, 409; in particular, for philosophers and poets, 4i2f.; for *much learning', 412, 414;
aristocratic
431); effects of sleep, 427, 430 f.; explanation of sleep, 433 anc^ n - 3 war (strife, tension), the universal creative
pride
and
rejection
of
and ruling force, 446 ff.; common, like the Logos, 447; peace and war identical, 444; Aristotle's account of the doctrine,
43?f-
equality,
409 ; respect for law, 410, 425; on poverty of human knowledge, 413
to
earlier
relation
philosophers,
41 5
harmony: is of opposites, 4353".; simile of bow and lyre, 439 , 45 if., 459; invisible
523
General index
Heraclitus (cont.)
440 f.; a balance of forces in tension, 440; revolt against idea of peaceful and harmonious world, 448; stability of world only apparent, 466; harmony and discord co-existent, 43 6 f.
and
visible,
real
account of his cosmology by D.L., 483 ; world 'the same for all*, 454 and n. 2;
kosmos of world everlasting, though components never the same, 468; substance of
universe single, moving,
finite
(Simplinot in
all
things
identity of,
valued
462; theory of exhalations, 45 2 f.; two kinds of exhalation, 462 n. 2, 483, 484 n. 3 ;
453,
462f.;
and death, 478 f. of, 449 ff., 452, 459 ff.; cyclic character of, 452; and the concept of measure, 464^; fire the measure of change, 465 ; cyclic change of
relation
between
from sea, 462; heavenly bodies nourished by them, 484; psyche an exhalation, 462 sun, 484 ff.; 'one foot wide*, 486; renewed daily, 462, 4846; will not overstep his
stars are exhalations
all
things', 453 n.
3, 5
fire:
elements into each other, 433 the cosmic fire, 454ff., 459; not flame, but hot, dry vapour, 432, 466; world an everlasting fire, 454 ff.; its kindling not
temporal, 459; in one sense the outermost
fire,
433, 466,
cf.
481 ; at death turns to water, 433, 476, 480; nourished by moisture, 43 3 f., 463; described as exhalation, 462; question of immortality, 476 ff.; soul a spirit guardian,
part of the universe, 480; alleged to be H/s arche, 432, 457, 459 f->* his 'first
478,
cf.
482
according to Aristotle, 432; primacy of fire, 456; but not permanent substratum, 461 ; the constant factor in all
cause*
traditional religion and morality: criticism of established cult, 474 f.; of mysteries
transformations, 465 ; all things exchange for, 457; as gold for goods, 461, 465 ; law or measure of change, 461, 466; fire everliving, rational, divine,
and Dionysiac religion, 474f.; of funeral 478; of praying to images, 472; purificatory rites sometimes approved, 476; right and wrong ways of worship,
rites,
both immanent
478
and
external, 432, 459, 462, 469, 471, 474; identified with the Logos, 432, 471; with
with
473 ; 473; Erinyes the servants of justice, 465; just and unjust not distinfire,
472
of fire and soul, 459ff., 463; its opposites, cold and wet, connected with foolishness,
433 other pronouncements
satiety, 455, 474; sea burning', 463 f. and n.; justice, 473,
on
recognized in traditional sense, 472; God, the divine, 444, 472; comprehends all
contraries in himself, 444, 472; our share
fire as
judge or
n., 461,
474
and
n. i,
452
of divine force, got by physical means, 429 summary of H/s scheme of things, 479 f.; general summing up, 486 ff.
Heraclitus, school of, 410
468; essential to being, 449; illustration of the kykeon, 449; its influence on Plato,
and
n. 2, 434, 45 1
of,
poem on murder
215
Hermippus, knowledge of book of Philolaus, 332 n. i Hermodorus, of Ephesus, 409 and n. 3 flpnocrnfros, of man who has sophrosyne, 317
524
General index
Herodotus, 294 n.
160
Hesiod,
xi, 28, 39, 61, 69, 70, 112, 134, i4o, 183, 278, 318, 389, 39<* n. 2, 400, 442, 478;
humanltaSy 23
hylris, 8; Heraclitus's
Cryp6s,
conception
of,
410
meanings
of,
61 f.
hylozoism, 21, 63
castigated
by Xenophanes, 370 f.
Pythagorean, 178
Hestia, 293
fcroipeia,
176;
fcrcapetai,
source for
JroTpoj, 115 n.
327^
Hiero of Syracuse, 362, 364 Hippasus of Metapontum, 192, 268, 320 ff.; no writings, 320; sympathy with conspiracy against Pythagoreans, 320; connexion and confusion with Heraclitus, 32of.; on substance of the universe, 432, 457; his
first
of Pythagoras, 23, i y 5 f. ; Pythagorean Acusmata, 183; Protrepticus, 154, 171; * * treats Pythagoreans* as Pythagoras', 151; method of compilation, 171
[lamblichus], Theologumena Arithrnettcae, Pythagoreans in Egypt, 217 f.
Iberians,
on
principle fire, 320, 432; discoveries in music, 321 f.; his punishment, 149 f.
ignorance,
Hippias, of Elis, 66
remedy sought by
Hippocrates of Chios, 219, 335 Hippocrates of Cos, 8 Hippocratic writings, 8; criticism of philosophers in, 345, 358; On Ancient Medicine,
345;
n. 2
Pythagorean, 159; aspiration of mystic sect in Magna Graecia, 206$ denial of, a
legacy from Homer,. 196; in Heraclitus, 476 f. See also cycle of births, divinity,
Orphics,
On
the
Pythagoreans,
soul,
trans-
migration
imperceptible, invoked to explain the perceptible,
Rome, his Refutations as a source, xiv; on Pythagorean Acusmata, 183; on harmony of spheres, 298; on
Heraclitus, 405 f.
n.; his
78
on
202 n., 248, 264 and Pythagoreanism, 25 if. 'indifference* and position of earth (AnaxiIndia, 187;
mander), 99
individual,
infinite
problem of knowledge of, 41 beyond the cosmos, Archytas on, 336 infinitesimal change, argument of, 451
extension,
infinity,
Hobbes, Thomas, quoted, 31 6Aiis, 6Ax6$, 267 n. 2 Holscher, U., 60 n. 2, 77 n. i, 79 n. 2, 87 n. 2, 138 n. 2, 414 n. 2, 418 n. i
apeirori), isolated
Aristotle,
Homer,
197^; of Orphics, 198; of Pythagoreans to, 149 innumerable worlds, see worlds
attitude
soul in, 196; Homeric religion and the Ionian spirit, 196; a philosophical precursor according to
ic>6f.;
(Empedocles), 348; the head (Alcmaeon), 348; interchangeable with sphere or circuit, in the
Timaeus, 356; in connexion with the
Plato, 450 n. 2; with Hesiod, determined for Greeks the nature of their gods, 370i
Logos
intervals,
(Heraclitus),
426
and
n. i; castigated
by Xenophanes,
301 ; applied
to distances
5*5
General index
Ionia, early seat of philosophy, 3 ; under rule of
Kirk, G. S.,
xii, xiii,
57 n.
2,
82 n.
3,
90
i,
n. 5, 95,
Lydia, 32; Ionian mathematics, 2i8; contrast between Ionian and Italian traditions, see Italian philosophy
Iris,
105
n., I24f.,
i,
I3l,
135 n.
2,
157
n.,
204 n. and n.
208
n. i,
353 n.
n.,
i,
4o6f, 452
and
139, 393
VII passim
irrationals, 149,
Isis, cults of,
klepsydra^ 133
KMnorrcc, origin
n. 2 of term, 393 n. 2
Isocrates,
151, 163, 173 isonomia, in Alcmaeon, 345 and n. 2 Italian philosophy, 196; contrasted
knowledge, human, limitations of recognized by Xenophanes, 398 and n.; emphasis on personal search, 399; contrasted with
with
154
Jaeger,
n. i, 115, 165, n. 2, 343, 365 n., 366 n. i, 384 n.
W., 88
208
379
n. i, 275 and n. i,
true
Jehovah, divine rivals and foes of, 375 Jesus, 413 n. 2, 414 n. 3, 438, 439 Joel, K., 140 n.
Jones,
kosmos
(see also
the term,
no,
W.
H. $.,358
n.
judgment, relative character of, 401 judgments, moral, in Stoicism, 20 Junge, G., 265 n. 2, 295 nn. justice, opposite views of Anaximander and Heraclitus, 447 ; personification of in Heraclitus, 472; equated with a number
used of world first by Pythagoras, 208; construction of in Pythagoreans, 247 ; according to Philolaus, 284 and n, 2; in Heraclitus, 454; element of, link be-
by Pythagoreans,
Kahn, C. H., xiv, 41 n. 3, 44 n., Section in c passim, 123 n. i, 314 n. i, 352 n. 2, 353,
J. W., 253 Kranz, Walther, 39, 47 n. 2, 131 n., 157 n., 158 n. 4, 208 n. i, 300, 327, 406 n. i, 408 n. 2 krasisy in Pythagoreanism, producing har-
W.
374 456
n. 2, n.
375 n.
2,
390
n. i,
453
n. 2,
Kepler, Johannes, 3
Kern, O., 40 n.
Kerschensteiner,
kinesis,
i
J.,
404
n.
scope of term, 382 kings, at Ephesus, 409 kinship, of all nature (see also microcosm-
imposed on philosophers by lann 8 (see also words) Latins, and Pythagoras, 254 Leibniz, possible influence of Ecphantus on,
tions
guage,
of Pythagorean beliefs, 200, 205, 208, 250, 278 ; of all animate nature, in Empedocles, 1 86, 208 ; of all animals to man (Porphyry) ,
195
7 Lenin, 403 n.
J2
General index
Leon (Pythagorean), 344
Leucippus, 6, 91 n. 2, 95 n., 113, 138 n. LeVy, L, 161 n. i, 163 n. 3, 202 n.
life (see also
232
Magus, as
title,
488
n. 2;
instinct
with
map, Babylonian, 99 99 n. 2
of Anaximander, 74,
in
Anaximander,
103;
and
its
origin
within the earth, tfaL; belief in its spontaneous origin, among Egyptians and in
59, 102; as cosmogonic force (Ecphantus), 326; after death, in Eleusinian and other mysteries, 476 (see
Anaximander,
also immortality etc.); the three types of life (Pythagoras), id^f., 21 if.; (Plato), 165
'
Marcovich, M., 387 n. 4, 473 n. i, 475 n. i Marcus Aurelius, 453 marriage, equated with a number by Pythagoreans, 302, 304 Martin, H., 299 Martin, T. H., 49 Mason, S. F., quoted, 36 material and formal, in Aristotle, 233 materialism, leads to belief in flux, 467; term
irrelevant to Milesian philosophy, 64
like:
like to like', 3 ;
known by like,
,
tinguished
from
acusmattci) 191,
217 357,
Greek
seeperas, Pytha-
goreans
line, relation to figures in
mathematics, Egyptian, limitations of, 34 f.; Greek: its debt to Egypt and Babylon, 33,
Pythagoreanism, 257 M., 160 n. Lloyd, G. E. R., 342 n., 358 n. Lobeck, C. A., 151, 372 n. i
Linforth,
Pythagoreans,
by
Thales, 65 f.
for Aristotle,
of
philosophy, 14
logical
Aristotle,
by
and chronological
matter, in early
X6yov 8i56vcn, 38 logos (A6yos), meanings of, 38, 205, 477 n. i; survey of meanings current in fifth century or earlier, 41924; in Heraclitus, 5, 272, 419^".; use of term by Stoics, 21,
426
n. 2; particularly
and
64,
inert,
89; meaning of the term in Aristotle, 12; matter and form, 234, 237,
82,
Love
(see also
Eros) and
Strife,
467; and spirit: relations between them, 6, 88, 143, i44f., 257f., 428, 468; union with mind in Stoicism (Zeno), 19
6
Lucretius, 386;
on
2
Heraclitus, 411
i
Lukas, F., 60
n.
Luynes,
Due
de, 176 n.
Lyceum, 16
lyre, structure of,
1 80
n.,
301;
cosmos compared
Lysis, 179,
to,
298
also
AJcmaeon, Hippocratic
Macchioro, V., 406 n. i, 478 and n. 2 McDiarmid, J., 41 n. 3, 56 n. i, 62, 77 nn. 4, 87 n. 2, 12O n., 121 n. i, 458 n. 5
i, 2,
awareness of fallibility in diagnosis, 344; Western school and health as harmony, 436; quarrel with philosophers, 58, 345,
358 Meewaldt,
J.
Macdonald, C., 35 n. i Magi, good and evil archai of, 249 n. 2; connexion of Pythagoras with, 173 n. 3, 253 f.
magic, sympathetic,
1851".
D., 491 n.
n. i
Megarian School, 10
melancholia,
5;
connexions
Xenopkanes, Gorgias
(treatise),
527
General index
memory, power of
43
lost in sleep (Heraclitus),
inhabitants
of,
285
290;
and
in
n.
3;
called
'counter-earth*,
n. 3,
Xenophanes,
312
n.,
330
by
early
Greek
392; cause of illumination, when discovered, 94 n. 2, 286; white cocks sacred to moon-god, 1885 eclipses of, see
eclipses
n.
Moraux,
n. i
P.,
367
n.
i,
Morrison,
J. S.,
165 n. 2, 173 n.
294 n.
2,
295
229 Metrodorus of Chios, 93 Meyer, E., 46 n. i, 60 n. 2 microcosm macrocosm analogy (see also kinship of all nature), 67, 90, 130, 131 f., 201 ,
208 n. i, 209 f, Mieli, A., 221
Milesian
character, 30;
by Herodotus,
tragedians, Pindar, 196, 205 ; rejected by Pythagoras etc., 206; contrasted with
*
278,
316,
human
culture,
philosophers,
3f.,
29 ff.; practical
curiosity,
its
types
moved by
3o;
by
*
Aristotle, 382; in
Greek philosophy,
acquaintance with Eastern countries, 32; mythical predecessors, 39; scientific outlook, 40, 43, 70, 83; questions asked by, 44; how far a school, 43; summary and
appraisal, 140 ff. Miletus, 121 n. 3; account of, 29; geographical situation, 31; materialistic culture, 30
6,
88
128,
Anaximander), 76, 89, 91, 98; (in Anaximenes), 124, 127; continuous motion of
everything a doctrine
Heraclitus, 410
among followers of
(see also
Milky Way, 94 Milo of Croton, 176, 179, 346 Milton, quoted on opposites, 79
mimesis , mimetes, mimos, meaning
of, 23 of.
distinguished in
Mimnermus, 30
Minar, E. L., 153 n.
n. 2, n. 3
i,
170
n. i
and
n. 2, 173
mullet, abstained
174 n.
2,
179 and
n.,
193
n., 329,
335
Museum,
music
at Alexandria, 16
mind, union of with matter in Zeno's Stoicism, 19; cosmogonic in Anaxagoras etc., 143, 326, 454 n. 3; in Ecphantus, 326 Minoans, 50 n. i Mnesarchus of Samos, father of Pythagoras,
173
Pythagoreans) :
n. 2, 223, 299;
Pythagorean-
ofakosmos, 247 ; music and moral state of the soul (Plato), 317 musical sounds, note on speed and pitch,
226f
mystery-religions (see also Eleusinian
teries),
mys-
433
456
n.,
later
Platonists
and Neo-
pythagoreans, 244
i, 478 n. 2; sarcasm of Clement of Alexandria, 473 myth, value and danger of, 2; Platonic, ibid.; demands particular causes, 40; sudden dissipation of with rise of Milesians, 141 mythology, latent, in early Greek philosophy,
Heraclitus, 425 n.
if.
H00os, 421 n.
moon, in Anaximander, 93
moon-rainbow in
Nabonidus, 46
Naster, P., 176 n.
i
528
General index
natural forces, personal explanation of in early
Roman history,
22
Greek thought, 26
nature. See physis 'nature* and convention, 9
Olmstead, A. T., 31 n.
2, <So
Naucratis, 29
Olympian religion, 196 Olympic games, 363 n. 2 Olympic gathering, illustrating types of
164
the
life,
in
Olympus: name
for uppermost
heaven in
come from
i,
115;
One and
on Pythagoreanism, 156;
n.,
know-
Nestle,
n.
161 n.
i,
313
n.,
324
*
^
5,
399
47 nn.
2 and 4, 48,
opportunity
(Kocip6$),
equated with a
301, 302, 303
number
Nicander, 91 n. 3 Nicolaus of Damascus, on the arche of Xenophanes, 378 Nicomachus of Gerasa, Neopythagorean, 169, 1 80, 244 n. 3; Introduction to Arithmetic
by Pythagoreans,
opposites, 271, 470; evolved directly from arche in Presocratic thought, 122, 273; in
etc.;
can
Alcmaeon); in
Nigidius Figulus, 330 Nile, annual floods of, 59 Nilsson, M. P., 1 83 nn. i and 2, 449 n. Ninon of Croton, 177, 320 Noetus, and Heraclitus, 405 non-perceptible, notion of, 78
475 n. 4
by Milesians, 141
nouns, abstract, relative lateness of, 79 nous, vous, v6os, in Anaxagoras, of primary motive cause, 326; unmixed with matter, 6; in Heraclitus, essential to avoid error
phenomena, grasped of the world (kosmos), 206 ; universal order reproduced in the philosopher, 210 ; see also kosmos
;
term in of perceiving and recognizing identity or significance, 426 n. i number: soul a self-moving number (Xenosenses, 45 1 ; survival of the
Aristotle, 14;
crates), 263 ; numerical order inherent in world, 237. See also Pythagoreans
due to
Orestes, 475 n. 3 organization, and the limit, 207 Orient, extent of influence of, on early Greek philosophers, 3 if.; Greek attitude to,
252; Oriental elements in Pythagoreanism, 25 iff.; later syncretism between Oriental and Greek, 252
originality, in philosophic systems, 17
Nun, primordial
logy, 59
waters, in Egyptian
mytho-
Nyx, 413
n.
occultation of star
by moon,
95 n.
i
Orphics, 182, 203, 272, 331; cosmogony, xi, 39; theogonies, 69; relation to Pytha-
Oceanus, 55,
6o,
with
air
by
the
Pythagoreans, 267; construction attributed to Theaetetus, 268 Oenopides of Chios, 74; quoted on gnomon,
of One , 254; problem 132; rivalry with Homer, 150; general doctrine, 198; doctrine of man and immortality, 464, 478; the
goreans, 150, 198
and
Many
in,
wheel of birth*, 480; rewards and punishments after death, 476; the soul as breath,
129, 201, 307,
242
n.
480
529
General index
Oswiecimski,
$.,
44
n.,
66
n.
Petron, 322f.
PfligersdorfTer, G., 69 n.
i
universe, not merely sky, 380 and n. i Ouranos, 28, 69, 70, 112, 123, 278, 380 n. i, 386 Ovid, 79 Owen, G. E. L., 265 n. i, 408 n. 2
'
Phemius, 415
Pherecydes,
philia,
xi,
29 n.
'
i,
158
Italian
'
TTCcAlVTpOTTOS,
439
n. 3
329 ff.; place and date, 329; standing, 287 n.; question of writings, 330 ff.; fragcontroversy on genuineness, 330 ff.; and regular solids, 267, 269 f.; and
ments,
creation from regular solids, 267, 273 ; as author of a Pythagorean cosmology, 284 f., 286 f.; on the Great Year, 282; Philolaic world-system probably due to Ph. himself, 289; movement of the earth,
Paracelsus, 71
parallax,
how
disposed of
n.,
by Pythagoreans,
122, 136, 172, 294,
light,
on source of moon's
94
ted with Heraclitus's work, 408 and n. 2; his 'Way of Seeming', 136; denied physical
movement and
change,
4-5,
9;
of this denial, 145; denied existence of void, 279; shape of earth according to, 294; contrasted knowledge
influence
words, 204
Pythagoras,
'philosopher*
new
164,
204;
term
to
applied
especially
Pythagoras and followers, 417 philosophy, effect of temperament on, 117; of current thought, 118; wide sense of in early period, x; relation of Greek philo-
sophy
to
modern thought,
i ff.
summary
imposed on
apeiron,
of Greek philosophy, 3ff.; originality of, 3 iff.; European, origin in curiosity, 30; denied, 117; origin of in abandonment of
at,
164
Phoenicians, 50 n.
22;
its
i, 51,
294
n.
dualistic?,
(see
"3
Piaget,
J.,
64
n.
i i
General index
rnXtov, in
Anaximenes, 121
n. 3, 137,
138 n.
W., 330
n.
and
res publica, 23
pollution,
by bloodshed,
201 n.
135; in Plato: relative positions and distances, 298, 301; function of, 339; inde-
pendent movement from west to east (Alcmaeon), 357 and n.; orbits etc. in
Pythagoreanism, 285, 301; non-existent planet invented by Pythagoreans, 213
Plato
(see
5,
Polycrates of Samos, i73f., 346 polydaemonism, in early Greek thought, 26 polymathie, m>Avncc0{Ti, condemned by Heraclitus, 417, etc. polytheism, 26; not rejected
also
forms,
harmonics,
400, 419,
soul),
xiv,
334,
368,
395
n.
5,
435 f.,
153,
436, 437;
relations
on
with
Pythagoreanism,
spheres in, 295
theistic
harmony of the
teleolegical
ii,
,,
301;
and
pra¶tio
evangelica,
as,
Greek
philosophy
and circular motion, 356f.; methexis and mimesis, 229; on motion of planets, 357; political theory, 1 1 ; dilemma of the Meno,
intelligence
on connexion between
viewed
TTptiori'ip,
24
Alcmaeon, 351, 354; Heraclitus, 43 6 f,, of creation, 450, 452 n., 46jf.~ f doctrine
239, 456; Timaeus,
n, 203
n.,
210, 227,
primary (and secondary), senses of, 248 priority, logical and chronological, not properly distinguished by Pythagoreans, 240 progress, in human culture, 400; idea to be
456
Platonic figures, or bodies,
i.e.
regular solids,
268
Platonism,
its
relation
to
earlier
and
later
Xenophanes, 399 f., 401 387 n. i, 400 proof, mathematical, meaning of, 53 and n. 2
Prometheus, myth
of,
attributed first to
of Epicurean,
Plotinus,
first
religious
24; inexpressible
combinations of elements, (Empedocles) 258, (Pythagorean) 275 and n. 2 Protagoras: his account of human origins in Plato's dialogue, 400; autonomy of individual's sensations, 401, 431 psyche, vfi/x^ (see also soul), in Homer, 196, 476; as cause of motion, 65, 67; self-mover, in Anaximander, 128, in Plato etc., 351;
closely identified in general with physical
life,
Plutarch, quotations from Heraclitus, 489 [Plutarch], Epitome, as source, xiii; Stromateis,
as source, xiv
pneuma,
131
irva/ua, in
n.,
31 5
fifth-century
limited, i32f., 272, 278; of the soul as breath, 3075 in Zeno, as material represen-
and 2;
tation of logos, 20
on philosophic,
Pohlenz, M., 82
204, 205
53 1
General index
pyramids,
fire
external
history,
175 ff.;
revolt
against
Pythagoras, 4
life,
Pythagoreans, 178, 329; their emigration to Greek mainland, 179; effect of scattering of societies on continuity of tradition,
1 80
149; date of birth, 173; evidence of connexion with rising mercantile class, 177;
his travels,
Italy,
writings and sayings: no fragments from before time of Philolaus, 155; examples of
173, 217; migration to S. 174; perhaps responsible for Crotoniate incuse coinage, 176$.; gives
4,
Pythagorean Acusmata, i83f.; moral interpretations of these, 184; commentaries preserved and handed down by surPythagorean notebooks ,uTTOtivi<incnra, 201 andn. 3, 266, 289
viving
exiles, i8of.;
>
'
Italians
constitution,
175;
banished
organization: a distinctive society, 167; two types of members, acusmatici and mathematiciy 19 iff.; secrecy, 147, I5off., 167; silence, of novitiate and of school in
general, 151
163;
veneration,
doctrine
and
aims,
i8i;
pre-Platonic
heroization,
canonization,
148;
semi-
alleged writings, accounts of, 1 5 5 ; Mystical Logos* attributed also to Hippasus, 320;
credited with writings in the name of Orpheus, 150, 158; contrasted modern
'
founder,
motives dominant,
i8i;
way
views
of, 1 8 1
between rational and religious sides, 250; these sides not to be treated in isolation, 306; scientific character of much of their
thought, 289; experts in astronomy, harmonics and the science of number, 167 religious preoccupation: religious view of truth, 149; conformity with the divine,
199, 210; the kosmos, living and divine, 200 f., 251; philosophy as basis for religion, 152, 199; mathematics a religious
dence for, 1 68; connected with music, 220 ff.; with commerce, 222; theorem of, 53, 217, 265 ; his musical discovery, 220 ff. ;
anecdotes
the subject, 223 f.; religious teacher as well as philosopher, 148; com-
on
bination in
called the
world
compared
religious
kosmosy 208; his aim to discover kosm&f-in the world, for imitation in the soul, 288;
with
Orphic writings,
150;
taught transmigration of souls, 166; zeal for reforming society in accordance with
his own moral ideas, 175 Pythagoreans and Pythagoreanism, 146 ff.; relation to Oriental thought (India, China,
182; kinship of all nature, i86, 200, etc. under kinship); magical elements,
I53f.; sixth
and
fifth centuries,
157;
sum-
317, 467 and unlimited: the ultimate notions, 207, 242; equated with good and evil, 207, 246; unlimited among sensible things,
mary of early information, i66f.; general account in Aristotle, 2i4f.; his lost book,
42; fourth-century sources exclusive of
Aristotle, i6iff., i66ff.;
most abundant
later sources
241 ; itself a substance (Aristotle), 241 ; void (unlimited) a tenuous form of matter,
280; identifications with breath, void, time, 278, 280, 336, 340; limit imposed
532
General index
Pythagoreans (cont.} both spatially (proportion) and temporally (regular motions of heavenly bodies), 337; mathematical aspect of the unlimited: extension without number or figure, 340; limit and unlimited the elements of numbers, 240; associated with odd and even respectively, 242 f.; explanation of motion, 241
opposites:
table of, 243, 245, 448 n. 3; harmonious blend of, 4485 in what sense
mony,
309, 315; happiness and the numbers of the soul, 164; soul as a harmony, 307 ff.; soul is a harmony, of its own
parts,
numbers
final extinction,
principles, 247 f. Pythagorean mathematics, 2i7ff.; numbers and the cosmos, 21 2 ff.; its numerical explanation a generalization from Pythagoras's own discovery of musical ratios, 221; types of relation, 229; numbers, in
by Aristotle, 266; more physical account, 276; cosmos everlasting, 281; grows from seed, 278 f.; from centre outcized
wards, 281; feeds on air, 281; the unitseed has nature of fire, 281
what
sense
archai,
2735
independent
ing as abstractions, 225; unit, both odd and even, 240; outside the number-series, 244; treatment of Aristotle's account, 246 f.; equated with good, 246; One not
the sole principle, 248, 249; One reverenced as divine, 248; Pythagoreanism dualistic, as distinct from Ionian systems, 249; monistic theory Platonic, 249; the primal One a seed, 278; numbers represented as geometrical patterns, 242 f.,
(planetary earth), 282 ff., probably work of Philolaus himself, 286 ; central fire,
it,
282f. ;
shape and position of earth, 282, 283, 289, 293 ff.; counter-earth, 282, 283; planetary
orbits
and
centric
scheme,
drawn in from
void and breath, 280; a time before time, 338; time as the enclosing sphere, 339 fsubsequent influence: formative influence
259; fluxion theory, 263 f.; elements each assigned a regular solid, 266; numbers physically extended and independent,
etc.,
on
1696*1;
Neoplatonists,
i$5;
early Pythagorean-
213, 280;
numbers
as boundaries, 274f.;
ism obscured by
late accounts,
23
generation
of things
from numbers,
230
evidence
and
objections
of
Aristotle, 229, 233 ff., 236f., 258, 2736; integers as things incompatible with in-
&
numbers,
quantitative, characteristic of
213,
301 ff.;
Aristotle's
strictures
on
Pythagorean number symbolism, 302 f.; disagreement on which numbers, 303 f.;
physical qualities explained
ratio,
modern physical treatment of things, 238; importance of, discovered by Pythagoreans, 238
by numerical
275; world a harmotua y 287; constructed according to a musical scale, 296; harmony of the spheres, 295^
soul: importance of, 195 f.; nature of, 3o6ff.; immortal because akin to divine, 2O2f.,
of musical harmony, 223 and n.; distinguish different bodies, in Pythagoreans, 275 and n. 2, in Empedocles, 258 Rathmann, W., 161 n. i, 165 nn. 2 and 3
533
General index
Raven,
172, 215 n. 2, 216, 233 n. 2, 236 244 n. 3, 248 n. 2, 249, 258 f., 262, 263 n. 2, 264, 269 n. i, 275 n. i, 276 n. i, 280 n. i, 302, 330 n. 2, 408 n. 2 reality, in form and in matter, 467 recurrence, of seasonal changes, 453; see also
J. E.,
i,
Rostovtzeff, M., 15
Russell, Bertrand, 211 n. 2
n.
Sabinus, 132 n.
Sachs, E., 272
SafTrey,
2,
384
repetition
Regenbogen, O., 407 regular solids, and elements, in Pythagoreanism, 267; date of their theoretical construction, 269
H. D., 245 n. Sage. See Seven Sages Sagra river, defeat of Crotoniates
salvation,
at,
174
ways
203
and
n. i
same, sense of, in Heraclitus, 443, 473 Samothrace, and Pythagoras, 254
2,
297 n.
2,
305 n.
diatonic, chromatic
47 and enharmonic,
investigations
i,
370, 381, 387 n. 3, 408 n. 2, 415, 444 n. *, 454 n. 2, 455, 466 n. i, 473 n - *> 483
relativity
and Protagoras's
religious
background to Greek thought, sketch of, i96ff.; religious explanations the most plausible in earlier stages of
thought, 28
eternal
and and
repetition,
and
cyclic,
of
historical
sea,
16
events, 281, 282, 321, 352, 389; a Pythagorean view, 458; in modern thought,
drying up according to Anaximander, 92, 101, 388; encroached on land and vice
versa (Xenophanes),
first
3876^
exhalations
from
(Heraclitus), 462 f.
seasons, cycle of, 80, 352, 452 f. seed, in early philosophy, 278 n. 2; in Pytha-
sole
sleep, ibid.
res
Rhegium, Pythagorean
179
of to thought, in early Greek thought and Aristotle, 348; arises from interaction of wnlikes (Alcmaeon),
&uL;
separation,
distrust of,
394,
Heraclitus
Rohde, E., 40 n.
1 86
i,
161 n.
i,
2,
n. i, 193,
202 n.
153 n.
See cosmogonic process. heaven seven, significance of number, 303 f. Seven Sages, 183; earliest list of in Plato, 50; Thales included in, 47, 49 sex, interest of primitive societies in, 62 n. 2;
as
apokrisis,
Rome,
Ross,
W.
n.,
2,
Sextus
267 n.
2,
272, 354f.
2,
435 n.
534
General index
Sherrington, Sir Charles,
on connexion of
water and
Sibyl, the, 414
life,
71
f.
Sicilian expedition, 8
Silloi,
similarity
ing, 230;
54 n.
Simmias, in Plato's Phaecto, 309, 313 Simplicius, character of his scholarship, 367 singers, status of at symposia, 364
of the four elements* (Dicaearchus), 315; Pythagorean accounts, 321; connexion with motion, especially selfmotion, 263, 35of.; with circular motion
later
n. i
(Plato), 354; in Heraclitus, substantial identity with fire, 433; and exhaled from
cFKiaypa9{a, 274 n.
sleep, theory
430
Smith, G., 48 n. 2
Snell, B.,
moist things, 434; treatment by Plato, 214, 315, 318; by Aristotle, 14 sound, theories of, 226 ff.
n,
374
n. 3,
377
n.,
n. 2,
414
n. 3,
n. 2,
416
n.
n. 3,
sources for Greek philosophy, xii, xiv, 25 space (see also void), in Pythagoreanism, be-
425
n. 5,
452
477
482
i,
418 and
n. 2;
7f.;
later
longs to realm of the unlimited, 257; empty, and Parmenides, 279; and body, not distinguished by early philosophers, 113, 279; treatment of by atomists, 1 13 ,
9,
22
279
Sparta, 8;
with elements by Plato, 267; by Pythagoreans, 266 ff.; date of construction of regular solids, 268 f.
1 66,
Anaximander
at,
75
opposites, 79
Spenser,
Edmund, quoted on
Solon, 51,
204, 388
crafts,
31
and fragments of Philolaus, 202 n., 332; on Pythagorean Numbers^ 260 sphere, constructed from pentagons and
equated with dodecahedron, 268; celestial, constructed by Thales and Anaximander,
74; of different substance from the four bodies (Pythagorean), 272
sphericity, special perfection
meaning
Sophocles, 400
sopkos, 0*096$, Sage,
title
of in Aristotle, 2;
compatible with lack of limit, 85; associated with divinity, 114; of Xenophanes*s
when
dis-
spirit.
and
187, 189; fate after death: belief in sixth fifth centuries, 470 ; in Anaximenes,
of births, immortality); of same substance as stars, 481; becomes a star at death, 350, 471, 480; atomic or material view, 18, 307 n. i,
476 ff.
Anaximander, 95,
;
13 ; in Anaximenes,
body*
3136; immortality of, 10, 201; Pythagorean notion of pre-existence not found in Persian religion, 255; Empedocles on and its transmigration immortality, apotheosis, 314; and its dual nature, 318;
Pythagoreans' thinking, 195; their account of its nature, 203, 3061!.; equated with a
Diogenes of
paramount importance
of,
to
Stella,
43 8 f. L. A., 342
535
General index
Stobaeus (John of Stobi), Physical Extracts,
as source, xiii Stocks, J. L., 98 n.
n.
i
temperament,
ten.
influence
of
in
individual
philosophies, 117
i,
107
n.,
165 n.
i,
204
See decad
and
n. i
77, 460 Stoicism, 10, 17, 19, 132, 202 n. i Stoics, adopt and remould ideas of Heraclitus,
of to paganism, 24
404
storks, foretell earthquakes, 73 n. 2
Strato, 1 6
Strife,
Tethys, 55, 60, 410 n. i tetractys, 225 and n., 277, 288 n., 301, 316 Thales of Miletus, i, 29, 40, 43, 455*. date of, 46 ff.; ancestry, 50; length of life, 50; character in tradition, 50 f.; celestial
sphere of, 74 mythological precursors, 58ff., 68 ff.; as a forerunner of philosophy, 45 question of written works, 54 and n.
statesmanship, trading, engineering, interest in navigation and mensuration, 50; later
stringed instruments, Greek: heptachord and octachord, 299 n. See also lyre
substratum
77
condemned by
Philolaus as contrary
common
belief in its
nourishment by
founder of 'physical' philosophy, according to Aristotle, 40, 45; water as arche, 546%; evidence of Aristotle, 55 f.; earth floats on water, 59; reasons for choice of water,
mythical, 58 ff., rational, 6if.; water and
life:
by Philolaus, 284 f.; by Empedocles, 286; by Xenophanes, 391 f.; in Heraclitus, 434, 483 ff., 486; myth of travel in golden boat, 138, 485; feeds on
moisture, 434; in Anaximander, same size
as earth,
description of
hylozoism, 62 ff., 71 f.; psyche as the cause of motion, 65; animate not disall
things
474
Thebes, Pythagorean centre established at, 179 Themistius, on Anaximander, 72 Theo of Smyrna, quoted on the monad, 244
theocracies, oriental, 32 f.
Theodoret,
xiii
n. 2
theogonies, mythical, xi
i
Tannery,
Tate,
J.,
P.,
46
394 n.
theologi, Aristotle's
307 n. 3 Taylor, A. E., 94 n. 3, 124 n. i, 210, 221, 243 mi-, 265 n. 2, 28l, 316, 324, 338; quoted on Plato's Timaeus, 211 techniques, fundamental in oriental civilizations, 33;
use of term, 40 Theologumena Arithmeticae, on the decad, 260 Theophrastus, 16, 25, 122, 274; as source, xiii; on musical pitch, 228 f.
Oecopla,
theoria,
active
contemplation,
212;
linked
by Pythagoreans with
transmigra-
development
i
of,
as seen
by
Greeks, 400
Teichmuller, G., 138 n.
TSKporfpEodca,
Thomists, 24
344
n.
n.
i,
252,
207
Thomson,
three,
Telys,
demagogue
at Sybaris, 176
2,
193
General index
thunder and lightning, in Anaximander, 106 and n.; in Anaximenes, 139 thunderbolt, in Heraclitus, 428, 471 n.
Ti'amat, 59,60
vegetarianism, see abstention verbal similarity, significance assigned to, 425
n. 5
n. 2
Timaeus,
of Locri,
'On
the World-Soul'
forgery, 156, 332; Timaeus^ of Plato, alleged to be taken from Philolaus, 330
W.
Timaeus,
of Tauromenium,
historian,
on
Vlastos, G., 77 n.
n.,
i,
166 nn.
2.
and
8l n. i, 89 n. 3, 208 n. i,
of, in English and Greek, 33 8 f.; distinguished from mere succession, 338; to Greeks unimaginable without ordered and recurrent motions, 280,
408 n. 2, 416, 429, 433 n. 3, 439 nn. i and 3, 447 n. 4, 454 n. 2, 458 and n. 5, 463
n. i, 465, 465 n. i,
Vohu Mana,
of, 352, 452; relation to cosmological order, 338; Pythagorean conception of, 280; in Plato, to be identified with planetary motions, 339, time
339; circularity
void, identified with air (Alcmaeon), 349, 358; * drawn in* by the cosmos (Pythagorean),
Un-
before time began, not absurd, 338; time and the unlimited, 336f Timon of Phlius, 366, 411
Titans, 141
toys, mechanical, invented by Archytas, 335 traditional conceptions behind philosophies,
numbers, 280; existence of denied by Parmenides and reasserted by atomists, 7. See also
space
volcanoes, 292
vortex, universal, stars carried passively
round
by, 357
118
transmigration of souls (see also cycle of births), 159, 165, 190, 354; a Greek doctrine, not
342
n., 343,
Egyptian, 160; taught by Pythagoras himself, i86, 3065 excluded in Aristotle, 14 Tpoirai, whether of solstices or revolutions, 97
truth, speaking, in relation to
Waerden, B. L. van
265 nn., 282 n.
2,
der,
n., 228,
i,
Pythagoras and
Persians, 254
turbans, 138
357 n. Walzer, R., 454 nn., 472 n. i Wasserstein, A., 265 n. 2 water, importance of in Egyptian and Mesopo328, 335 n.
i,
number (Pythagoreans), 240, 244; both odd and even, z&V.; primacy of; asserted by late writers on Pythagoreanism, 244; Cornford's theory on this, 244, 247, 25 of.; in
Pythagorean cosmogony, appears as a spsrma, 246; divinity of, (Xenophanes) 380 and n. i, (Pythagoreans) 248
way
tamian river-cultures, 58f.; relation to life and modern thought, 71 ; associated with foolishness, in Heraclitus, 433. See also Thales of life, religious, 4; the object of Pythain ancient
ibid.
unity, primal, in Milesians, 4, 70; search for unity a universal phenomenon, 70; non-
2,
170 n.
i,
173 n. 3,
Wellmann, M., 202 n., 324, 342 wheel of birth, see cycle
n.,
411
n.
Pythagoreans
Untersteiner, M., 367 n. 2 Ure, P. N., 174 n. i
Socrates's
values,
defence
of absolute, 9;
in,
unlike Ionian
White, M., 176 n. i, 177 n. i Whitehead, A. N., 56 n. i Wightman, W. P. D., quoted, 33, 68, 70 f., 72, 102, 238 Wilamowitz, U. von, 131 n., 202 n., 204 n. i, 267 n. 2, 309 n., 311 n. 3, 323, 332 n. 3, 475 n. 4
537
General index
Wilson,
J.
A., 102 n.
monotheist or polytheist, 361, 375 , no hierarchy of gods, 373; self-sufficiency of deity implied, 373; God not like man either in shape or in mind, 398; God has a body, 376; of spherical shape, 376, 378,
81 n.
i,
428 n. 2
N.D.
379;- and finite, 378; said in Cicero's to be infinitum; God identical with
ff.;
has no
is
one,
375; single, whole, unmoving, 374; difficulties of immobile God, 381 ; though
essentially one, yet manifested in
menes, 137; as god (Xenophanes), 38off.; according to all natural philosophers, had a beginning in time (Aristotle), 390; always existed (Xenophanes), ibid. world-soul, in the Timaeus, 316 worlds, 'innumerable', 390; question of in
many
forms, 376
Anaximander
oOpocvot),
ccrreipoi
K6crnoi
or
1136;
cosmology: material and non-material, finite and infinite, not distinguished, 369 and n. 2; earth alleged to be taken as his arche, 384; the cosmos not infinite, 377 ; ungenerated, 380, 382, 386; nature of the cosmos summarized, 382f. astronomy and meteorology, 3 90 ff.; how far dependent on Anaximander and Anaximenes,
391;
Xanthus of Lydia, on
fossils, 387 n. 2 Xenocrates, 222, 260, 264 f., 270 , 291 n. called soul a self-moving number, 263
no astronomy
in
extant
i;
Xenophanes, 4, 5 8 n. 2, 360 ff. ; tradition, 366 ff. ; date and life, 362!!". connexion with Elea and Eleatic school, 363 f., 368, 370; relationship with Parmenides, 369, 379 writings, 3<$5; poetical claims, 364; verseforms, 365 ; epics, 365 ; reported
nature*,
366;
imitated
work on by Timon of
importance of the sea, 391; observation of fossils, 373, 387 and n. 2; alternation of wet and dry ages, 3876^; origin of life
from the
personal
earth,
385^
367
opinions upon: of Heraclitus, 368, 408; of Aristotle, 366, 369; of Theophrastus, 67;
399;
;
limitations
of
knowledge and opinion (seeming), 395 and n. 5, 399; no evidence of corresponding realms of
of opinion with divine certainty, 396 and n. 3, 397; distrust of senses, 394, 397f.; relative character
existence, 397; contrast
Homer and
386 f.;
Hesiod, 370
common
370; protests against impiety towards gods, 371 f.; satire on Pythagoras, 157; opposition also to Thales and Epimenides, 370; denial of validity of divinations or prophecy, 373; unity, interpreted in stricter sense than by Milesians,
368, 380, 383, 402 constructive theology,
Yin-Yang, 252
Zalmoxis, I48; and Pythagoras, I58f. Zancle (Messana), stay of Xenophanes at, 363
Zaratas (Zoroaster), 253
Zeller,E. (selected references), 107 n., 134 n.
i,
373 fT.;
361
;
question
i,
410 n. 2,
whether
theologian,
whether
538
General index
Zen, as both Zeus and
life
(Heraclitus), 463
zodiac,
discovery
of obliquity
of,
74,
97
Zeno of Citium, Stoic, 19, 491 Zeno of Elea, 204, 262, 264, 265 and
Zephyr-eggs, 129
zero,
n. i
n*
3COTJ,
distinguished from ^A/X^, 202 Zoroaster (Zoroastres), 173 n. 3, 184 n., 250,
unknown
to Greeks, 240
Zeus, 27, 126, 129, 141, 196, 284, 287, 290, 374,
386, 429, 472 n. 2, 473; equated with
253 Zoroastrianism and Pythagoreanism, resemblances and differences, 254; and Hera.
Oromasdes, 249
n. 2
clitus,
488
C2
118613