This document summarizes Berkeley's argument against the existence of matter. It discusses three key points:
1) Berkeley denies Locke's distinction between primary and secondary qualities, arguing that all perceptible qualities like figure, size, and texture only exist when being perceived and cannot exist without a mind.
2) Matter is not needed as a substratum or support for the qualities we perceive. Qualities are directly perceived and do not require matter to exist.
3) Berkeley's arguments may not refute all theories of matter, as he seems to lump together all affirmations of matter as "materialism." There are differing views on how matter is conceived and what else may exist in addition to matter.
This document summarizes Berkeley's argument against the existence of matter. It discusses three key points:
1) Berkeley denies Locke's distinction between primary and secondary qualities, arguing that all perceptible qualities like figure, size, and texture only exist when being perceived and cannot exist without a mind.
2) Matter is not needed as a substratum or support for the qualities we perceive. Qualities are directly perceived and do not require matter to exist.
3) Berkeley's arguments may not refute all theories of matter, as he seems to lump together all affirmations of matter as "materialism." There are differing views on how matter is conceived and what else may exist in addition to matter.
This document summarizes Berkeley's argument against the existence of matter. It discusses three key points:
1) Berkeley denies Locke's distinction between primary and secondary qualities, arguing that all perceptible qualities like figure, size, and texture only exist when being perceived and cannot exist without a mind.
2) Matter is not needed as a substratum or support for the qualities we perceive. Qualities are directly perceived and do not require matter to exist.
3) Berkeley's arguments may not refute all theories of matter, as he seems to lump together all affirmations of matter as "materialism." There are differing views on how matter is conceived and what else may exist in addition to matter.
This document summarizes Berkeley's argument against the existence of matter. It discusses three key points:
1) Berkeley denies Locke's distinction between primary and secondary qualities, arguing that all perceptible qualities like figure, size, and texture only exist when being perceived and cannot exist without a mind.
2) Matter is not needed as a substratum or support for the qualities we perceive. Qualities are directly perceived and do not require matter to exist.
3) Berkeley's arguments may not refute all theories of matter, as he seems to lump together all affirmations of matter as "materialism." There are differing views on how matter is conceived and what else may exist in addition to matter.
Copyright:
Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9
INTRODUCTiON
Chapter 53: MATTER
THE GREAT IDEAS who assert. its existence postulate it as. stratum .orsupport for the sensible qualities they perceive. The question, therefare, is whether such a substratumis a necessary oran Berkeley does not deny the existence of beings which cannot be. directly sensed. He affirms the existence of the human spirit or mind, of minds other than his own,and the spiritual being of God. These must be inferred to exist in order. to. explain the phenomena of our sensible. experience. and the experience of our own activities in thinking, ing. If, in addition, theexistence of rnatter or:a material substance were necessary to explain the phenomena,. Berkeley would not. obj eet to affinning its existence ;by if it could in no way be directly perceived. His argument therefore involves, first, a denial of Locke's distinction between primary and secondary qualities. Supposing it tobe eral1yagreed that colors, sounds, odors have no actual existence except in the perceiviIig mind, he denies that perceptible figure, size, orma- tion can exist othe:rwise. "It having been shown that none even of these can ,vise than in a Spirit or Mind. which perceives them, it follows that we have no longer any reason to suppose the being of Matter." Matter is not needed as a substratum port for the qualities we perceive. This is the second main point in Berkeley's argument. "Though we give the materialists their external they by theifown confession are never the nearer knowing howour ideas are produced; since they own themselves unable to compre- hend in what Inanner body can act upon spirit, or ho\v it is possible it should imprint any idea in the mind. Hence it is evident that the pro- duction of ideas or sensations in our minds can be no reason why we should suppose Matter or 63 t4AltTERwe came out of the church,"says ...B.oswell in his Life.ofJohnson, "we stood IKing for some time together of Bishop Berke" ,. ingenious sophistry to prove the,. non" of matter, and that everythingin the universe is merely ideaL I observed that though are satisfied his doctrine is not true, itis im.. possible it. I shall never crity With which Johnson answered, stnkIIlg hisfoot with mighty force against a.large stone, tin he rebounded from.it, 'I refute it thus.' "; But Berkeley's argument anticipated Dr. Johnson's style ofrefutation. "I donot argue," hctsa}0s, "against the existence ofany one thing .we can apprehend either by sense or reflex" ion.. That .. the' things I see with my eyes: and touh with my hands do exist,. really.. exist, .1 maKe' not the least The. only thing se existence I deny is that which philosophers call Matter or corporeal substance. And in do.. ing. this there is no damage done to the rest of mankind, who, I dare say, ,vill never miss it." The rest of mankind .does necdto be .in- structed, however, that when they use the BJiord "matter," they speak of nothing. They may from careless habit suppose they are fing to the most obvious something there is in tile world---..the solid, massy, concrete stuff of BJihich .tangible, visible, movable, and moving .tllings,aremade. Of them, Berkeley would ask llowtney know such stuff exists. It is not itself
Wrt, perceive a variety of sllapes, temperatures, textures, sizes, or exten" -but these, Berkeley argues, have their gin beingperceived. Even if certain of these qualities, sometinlCS called "primary," sucb as figure, size, or weight, are supposed. to ang to bodies when they are not actually !Ieing sensed, they are not matter, but only its properties. Matter itself is not sensible. Those O.VEBLEN and LENNEs.lntroduction to [nfinitesi Analysis KLEIN Famous ofElementary GeolnetlY --. Elementary, Mathematics from an Advance Standpoint POINCARE. Science and 1-lypothesis, PART II --. The Value ofScience, PARTI, CH I; PART II --. Science and Method, BK I, CH 2-"3;BK II, CH CASSIRER. Substance and Function, PART I, CH 2- SUP VI E. V. HUNTINGTON. The Continuum, and Other Ty of Serial Order --. The Fundamental Propositions ofAlgebra J. \v. YOUNG. Lectures on Fundamental Conceptso Algebra and Geometry JOURDAIN. The Nature of Mathematics O. VEBLEN and YOUNG. Projective Geometry B. RUSSELL. Principles of Mathematics, CHI --. Philosophical Essays, CH 3 --. Mysticism and Logic, CH 4-5 --. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, CH I N.R. CAMPBELL. What Is Science?, cH6-7 MARITAIN. An Introduction to Philosophy, PART n( --. Theonas, Conversations of a Sage, VI N lCOD. Foundations of Geometry and Induction VVHITEHEAD. A Treatise on Universal Algebra --. An Introduction to .Mathematics --.'. Science and the Modern Wor/d, CH 2 G. N. LEWIS. The Anatomy of Science, ESSAY 1- HILBERT and ACKE.RMAN. Grundziige der theore schen Logik BUCHANAN. Poetry and Mathematics M. R. COHEN. Reason and Nature, BK II, CH I A. E. TAYLOR. Philosophical Studies, CH III GILSON. The Unity ofPhilosophicaI Experience, CH DEWEY. Logic, the Theory of Inquiry, CH 20 CARNAP. Foundations of Logic and Mathematics BELL. The Development of Mathematics G. H. HARDY. A Course of Pure Mathematics --. A Mathematician's Apology KASNER and NEWMAN. Mathematics and the lma ination COURANT and ROBBINS. What Is Mathematics? WEYL. The Philosophy of Mathematics and Natu1j Science 62 SACCHERI. Euclides Vindicatus (Vindication o.fEuch'd) VOLTAIRE. "Geometry," in A Philosophical tionary EULER. Elements ofAlgebra CARNOT. Rijlexions sur lametaphysique du calcul jinitesimaJ GAUSS. Untersuchungen fiber hohere Arithmetik SCHOPENHAUER. The World as Will and Idea, VOL II, SUP, CH 13 DE MORGAN. On the Study and Difficultz'es ofMathe- 1natics COMTE. The Philosophy of Mathematics --. The Positive Philosophy, BK I LOBACHEVSKI. Geometrical Researches on the Theory of Parallels WHEWELL. The Philosophy ofthe Inductive Sciences, VOL I, BK II, CH 11-12, 14 G. PEACOCK. A Treatise on Algebra B. PEIRCE. An Elementary Treatiseon Curves, tions, and Forces W. R. HAMILTON. Lectures on Quaternions RIEMANN. ijber die Hypothesen welche der Geometrie zu Grunde liegen (The Hypotheses of Geometry) BOOLE. A Treatise on Dijferential Equations --. A Treatise on the Calculus ofFinite DiJferences DEDEKIND. Essays on the Theory of Numbers CLIFFORD. Preliminary Sketch of Biquaternions --. On the Canonical Form and Dissection of a Riemann's Surface J EVONS. On Geometrical Reasoning LEWIS CARROLL. Euclid and His' Modern Rivals, GIBBS. Collected Works ' C. S. PEIRCE. Collected Papers, VOL III, par 553-5621, 609-6 45 FREGE. Grundgesetze der Arithmetik BURNSIDE. Theory of Groups of Finite Order CANTOR. Contributions to the Founding ofthe Theory of Transfinite Numbers HILBERT. The Foundations of Geometry PEANO. Arithmetices Principia --. Formulaire de mathematique --. Arithmetica generaIe e algebra elementare BONOLA. Non-Euclidean Geometry E. W. HOBSON. The Theory of Functions of a Real Variable and the Theory of Fourier's Series THE GREAT IDEAS CHAPTER 53: MATTER 64 corporeal substances, since that is acknowl- edged to remain equally inexplicable with or without this supposition." BERKELEY'S ARGUMENTS against matter, which occupy the greater part of his Principles ofHu- man Knowledge, may not have the same force when they are applied against different theories of matter. Berkeley seems to regard his attack on materialism as the refutation of an error at the root of skepticism, atheism, and irreligion. He also thinks rnaterialism creates .difficul ties for the sciences. But are all affirmations of mat- ter to be lumped together as materialism in the same sense? Are Aristotle, Plotinus, Descartes, Spinoza, and Locke materialists in the same sense as Lucretius, Hobbes, and perhaps Marx? Does it make no difference whether bodies are said to be the only real existences, or whether, in addition to bodies, immaterial substances or spiritual beings are also said to exist? Does it make no difference how matter is conceived-whether as a self-subsistent sub- stance in its own right, capable ofexisting apart from any qualities except extension and motion which belong to its very essence, or merely as one factor in the constitution of bodies, the factor of potentiality which, as will be presently explained, has no existence apart from the forms which actualize it? Are skepticism, athe- ism, and irreligion to be associated with all affirmations of matter, in view of the fact that theologians like Augustine and Aquinas seem to think that a sound view of matter supports the truths of religion against the errors of the materialists? There seem to be, in short, three distinct positions to \vhich Berkeley's blanket denial of matter stands opposed. The diametrically op- posite view seems to be the blanket denial of anything except bodies, or of anything which cannot be reduced to a property or function of nlatter. The atomism of Lucretius, discussed in the chapter on ELEMENT, may be taken as representative of this view, though Engels \vould insist that materialism can be dialectical rather than atomistic or mechanical. Between the two extremes, there appear to be two middle positions which are alike insofar as both affirm the immaterial as well as the material. Although they are alike in asserting the existence of spiritual substances, they ma of course, define the nature of these immateri things differently, and differently interpr their relation to the realm of matter. But, theories of matter, their principal differen consists in the way in which they conceive t being of bodies, material substances, or t bodily mode of substance. In the conceptions of Descartes and Lock for example, it is matter which gives actuali to sensible bodies. We have "no other idea notion of matter," Locke writes, "but sam thing wherein those many sensible qualitie which affect our sense, do subsist." The enti substance of sensible bodies consists of matte All their properties derive from the essence nature of matter. But in the conceptions Aristotle and Plotinus, bodies would not exist all if they were composed only of matter, matter is no more than a capacity for being, n something which by itself actually is. Sensib bodies derive their being and all their attribut from the forms which matter assumes wheni potentialities are actualized. Matter totallyd void of form is not the nothing Berkeley calls i but it is so near to nothing that Plotinus says is "more plausibly called a non-being ... a ba aspiration towards substantial existence." These theories of matter or corporeal bei seem to be as contrary to one another as t gether they are contrary to Berkeley's doctrin Yet each of the two middle positions lea toward one of the opposite extremes. The conception of matter seems to be ve much the same in the complete materialism Lucretius and Hobbes and in the view of D cartes, Spinoza, and Locke. In the former, on bodies exist. In the latter, bodies do not co prise the whole of existence, but matter is t whole substance of bodies. The separation body and mind, or matter and spirit, into di tinct substances, or modes of substance, leav matter the same kind of stuff that it is in world which admits of no other reality. Ato ism, furthermore, may be common to bot theories, at least to the extent that it is hel that the complex bodies we perceive are co posed of minute and insensible particles. U like Lucretius, Locke may not insist upon t absolute indivisibility of the particles, or upo the eternity of the uncreated atoms of matte he, like Hobbes and Newton, carries the sion of the familiar. bodies of sense-expe- ce down toparts which cannot be perceived d yet have, in a way, a more ultimate reality an its of rnatter than the complex bodies they (ponstituteo f-Jad we senses acute enough to discern the ute particles of bodies, and the real can" titution on which their sensible qualities de- s d," Locke writes, "I doubt not but that quite different ideas in us; and tnat .which is no\v the yellow color of gold, would then disappear, and instead of it we sno uld see an admirable texture of parts, of a size and figure." the other extreme, Berkeley's complete Cienial of matter has less in common" wi th the 'ViewofAristotle, Plotinus, Augustine, and Aqui- nas than the theory of Descartes, Spinoza, and llliocke has with the materialism of Lucretius and .. Hobbes. They would appear. to be close enough, for one seems to hold that matter is almost non-being and the other that rnatter is simply nothing at all. .But where Berkeley de- nies any role to matter, Aristotle and those who take his view affirm matter to be an indispen- saDIe factor in the constitution of physical tnings. They do not question the reality of bod- iesor their existence apa.rt from mind. On both of these points they are as opposed to Berke- ley as they would be if they were complete materialists. Nevertheless they lean toward :Berkeley rather than toward the other extreme in one respect. Where Berkeley denies the existence ofmatter, they deny its substantiality. 'Where Berkeley says matter has no being, they saY' it has the lowest grade of being-on the 'Very verge of not being! IN SPITE OF ALL the differences noted, the idea matter has a certain constant meaning throughout the tradition of the great books. It is generally associated with the idea of quantity, and especially the basic magnitudes, such as time, space, and mass. Sometimes it is saicl that the essence of matter itself is exten- sioft; sometimes that bodies-not matter itself -have the property of tridimensionality. But in either case that which is or has matter in it necessarily occupies space. The manner of that occupationis also gener- 6S ally agreed upon. Two bodies or t\VO distinct quantities of matter cannot occupy the same place at the same time. A body may not be im- penetrable in the sense of being indivisible, but so long as it remains the whole that it is, it offers resistance to other bodies tending to move into the place it occupies. There is another connection between rnatter and quantity. To those who ask what makes two otherwise identical things two in number........ or what is involved in the merely numerical dif- ference of things alike in every other respect- the usual answer is in terms of matter. Matter is traditionally spoken of as "the principle of in- dividuation." Aquinas, for example, holds that angels, unlike physical substances, cannot differ from one another as do numerically distinct in- dividuals. Because they are immaterial, they can differ only as do species or kinds. "Such things as agree in species," he wri tes, "but differ in number, agree in form, but are distinguished rnaterially. If, therefore, the angels be not com- posed of matter and form, it follows that it is impossible for two angels.to be of one species; just as it would be impossible for there to be several \vhitenesses apart, or several humanities, since whitenesses are not several, except in so far as they are in several substances." The way in which matter is related to in- dividual differences can be exemplified in works ofart. T\vo calls, stamped out of the.same kind of rnatter by the impression of the same die, may differ in no other discernible respect than that they are ttllO of the same kind. Their twoness seems to be somehow related to the fact that each consists ofa distinct quantity of mat.. ter. But it may be asked how two units of mat- ter have the distinction of being t\VO while they differ in no other respect. One answer to this difficult question is that their distinction con- sists in their occupying different places. In the Platonic theory of the origin of many particu- lars all participating in the same form, diversity of place seems to play the role which matter plays for Aristotle and Aquinas. Plato's doctrine of the receptacle, which is discussed in the chapter on FORM, is sometimes interpreted by conceiving the receptacle as space, and sometimes by conceiving it as mat- ter. The receptacle, it is said in the Timaeus, is that which, "while receiving aU things, never TfffiE @REAT IDEAS 67 the atoms, as in Lucretius, and Newton; Of, asin Spinoza,it may he established"by the.,uncrieated and eternal nature ofGod. "By body,,','; Spinoza wri tes, ,"I understand a mode which expressesin a certain and,determinate manner the essenceof God in,:$O far asHe is considered as the thing exte,nded." In the modern,development of the science of mechanics the law of the cOilservationQfmat- terseems to be andther>cxpression,of the. same insight. "We may lay it down as an able. axiom," Lavoisier writes, "that til; all the operations oartal1dnature, po;thing an equal quantity of matter and afterthe experimerr,t." What appears the destruction. gfabody is merely.thetratls- fornlation of its matter into another physical condition, without lossofmass unless.the.t;eis an equivalent gain totaLquantity otmaJter and energy remains cons.tant:throllgh- out all physical; changes. But though change or motion seems to be in- herent in the material \V()rld, of bodies, as well as the frnmutabili ty .of rnatter, seems to be differently conceived according to different The. difference between, the physics of Aristqtle and thephys- of Descartes can be expressed in. tt;rmsof contrary definitions of motion, or '. divergent notions of causality, but of these differ- ences is fully intelligibleflpart from the vari.. ance of these theories from one another orr the nature of matter. When matter isan actual substance, whose es." sence is extension and whose chief local motion, the principles of physics are me" chanical. The laws of mechanics, with space, and mass as their fundamental variables, seem to have a universality adequate for de- scribing all natural phenomena. All. changes in material things are either the local motions of bodies or the result of the local motions oftheir parts. Motions are determined in their magni.. tude and direction by the impressed forcew4ich one body exerts upon another and the resistance of. that other..Motion is itself completely ac" tuaI, as Inatter is; and the only type of cause to which physics need appeal is, the efficient cause,. that is, the push or pull of one body upgll another. Physicists who share this conception ofmat.. GRAFTER 53: MATTER ita tion which belongs; to., everything ".As matter is, said to cause the 'numerical Qf.bodies, so is- it ake sensations' alldjmages . s of the mind"7"""'" that is, of ti1'lgonly particular not genet.. orcl(isses.. Hence such theories' face the f the relation of se.p.sations 'universal intentions of the mind," its or abstract" ideas. ORE 'tRADITIONAL Jl1e<;ining q matter re- tobementioneq./fhe ofphysics hanics are concerlled with changeqrmo- 'heyarenot.concernecl, with ffil.1tabjii ty ral, but with the ofmutability ifested .M(lterial are never conceiveei ,as unmov9-1\)le or able.. qll:estion whether 111atter itself is as. different meaningsfor differenttheories tter.On the. theory (discussed in the er on CHANGE) that matter and form are her principles pf change in changing stances, it is. neither matter nor form but the ancecompositeof matter G,lnd.form \-vhich ges. Those who think that the motions of hysical world are without .beginning and II1G, attribute a similar eternity to matter and ceive it as. imperishahie.. rrhe .theologians wno think that God can annihilate .wha.tever reates,do not hold that matterisindestruct- but they nevertheless attribute. everlast- ing endurance to rnatter in God's plan. Aquinas, tot" example, in his treatise on the end of the world, describes the final conflagration which will purge the material universe but leave its matter in existence under the forms of the ele- ments and the heavenly bodies. "The world will be renewed," he writes, "in such away as to throw off all corruption and remain forever at rest. " I-Ience nothing can be "the subjeFt of tn.atrenewal, unless it be a subject of incorrup- tion," such as "the heavenly bodies, the ele- ments, and man." On other theories of matter the fact thatmo-, tion is regarded as an intrinsic property of bod- i(t$ seen1S to be similarly consistent with the notion that matter itself is immutable or inde- structible. This indestructibility may be con- ceived in terms of the absolute indivisibility of It is supposed that some of the qualities we sense in bodies are actually in them V\T t we sense them or not-such properties as figure, weight, motion. Other sensible qual such as' colors, .odor9; temperatures, or so are supposed to be effects produced by the" tionsof material particles actingon sensi apparatus of animals. This distinction betw "vhat Lockecalls "primary and secondaryq ties"-found also in Lucretius and Descart' is more fully considered in .the chapters QUALITY and SENSE, but here it calls attent to the problemoEhowmatter, devoid of cent sensible .qualities,. causes' these quali ties .' to a For Lucretius the peculiar difficulty oE problem seems to lie in the fact that these tive animal is itself nothing but a material s tern., All its powers and acts are.conceived functions of matter in motion. Hb\\\ then, d moving matter within. the organism gene certain qualities which do not belong tomovi matter outside the organism? For Locke problem raises a difficulty of still another so Secondary qualities, such. as; colors, soun odors, exist only as sensations in the mind. corporeal substances, or bodies, such qualit he writes, "are nothing but the powers th substances have to produce several ideas in by our senses; which ideas are not in the thin themselves, otherwise than as anything is in cause." Though they result from the impact moving particles on.. , the bodily sense-orga they do not belong to the \vorld ofmatter at a but to the realm of spirit. How, then, do t motions of matter cause effects which ex' only in the immaterialdomain of mind? These questions indicate some, of the pr lems of matter as an object, condition, or cau of knowledge. 1'hey also show how the natu of the problem varies with different eonce tions of matter, both in itself and in its relati to mind. There are still other problems whi confront those theories of mind which separa reason or intellect from the sensitive faculty In .such theories the consideration of rna ter's relation to mind goes beyond the questi of the origin of sensations. It takes sensatio and images as. somehow the functions of Iivi matter-the acts of the various sense-orga and the brain. But sensations and images, b cause they are acts of corporeal organs, have th 66 departs. at all. romher .. own nature' and never, in anyway, or at any time, assumes:a form like that ofany enterimtoher." This, accor4.iag to Plotinus, nleans that "its one form. is an invinciBle ;formlessness. " But plotinus, who combines Plato's doctrine of the receptacle and the orms:with Aristotle's theory of.potentiality and actuality, ,holds-'that it ismatter,not space, which is "tho irece:l?:ta(11e and ,nurse of aU says that ".recipient and nurse" is' .abetterdescription of matter than the term "mother," for,that term "is used by those who thinkofa mother as matter to ,the offspring, asa conta.1neronly, giving nothing to them." In his own vle"v,: mat- teris more than space or mere receptivity. He is willing to admit the "parallel with mother- hooel" onlyto the extent that "matter is.sterile, not Jemale .. to full effect, female .in receptivity only, not in pregnancy." TRADITIONALLY, the distinction between uni.. versal and particularisunderstoodas.a distinc- tion between.. the ip.telligible. and '. the'. sensible. This indicatesanother traditional meaning of matteror the material..The realm. ofsensible things is the realmofboclies.Butthe atoms which are the elementary bodies are.also usually called "insensible. particles of matter." This, however, can be interpreted to mean, not that a definite rnaterial' mass or bulk is in itself ab- solutely intangible or imponderable, but. that, because of the lilnitation in our senses, it is perceptible to us. On this interpretation .it would then seem possible to say that allbodily existence is sensible existence. But if we ask about the sensihilityof matter itself, ,rather than of bodies la.rge or small, questions arise \vhichare more difficult. to solve. On one theory of matter,matterdevoid of form is as insensible as it is unintelligible, yet forms which are not material, that is,not in matter, are also insensible but not unintelligi j ble. On the contrary, they are regarded as more perfectly intelligible than embodied forms. I-Io\v, then, does rnatter "vhich is itself insensi- ble cause the forms \vhich it assumes to becolne sensible \vhen they are. rnaterialized ? The theory of matter which does not regard it as a co-principle with form seems to be con- fronted with a different problem of sensibility. THE GREAT IDEAS IN THE TRADITION of Aristotle's physics and metaphysics, especially as developed by Aqui- nas, rnatter and form become basic analytic terms, often having a significance remote from their original meaning in the analysis of change. The conception of prime (or formless) matter as the substratum of substantial change leads to designation of the formed nlatter under!y- 109 accidental change as "second matter." This, i? turn, is called "signate matter" when, con- SIdered as the matter ofan individual substance is viewed as having the limiting hons of individuali ty. "NIatter is t\vofold," Aquinas writes, "con1- RISl'OTLE's DEFINITION of matter as "the pri- mary substratum of each thing, from which it comes to be without qualification, and which persists in the result" not only signifies an ob- ject \vhich the physicist must apprehend ana- logically (i.e., by comparison with substantially formed matter like wood and bronze), but also indicates that matter, by definition, must be in itself both unintelligible and non-existent. What Aristotle calls "the primary substratum" is later called by Plotinus "primal matter," by Augustine "formless matter," and by Aquinas "prime matter." Since they all agree that that which is wi thout form lacks all determination and actuality, they deny that it can have exist- ence by itself or be an object of knowledge, either by sense or reason. Augustine and Aquinas go further. They deny even to God's omnipotence the power of creating matter without form. They speak of matter not as created, but as concreated, that is, united at the very instant of its creation with the forms it must assume in order to exist. God "made formless matter of absolutely nothing, and the form of the world from this formless matter," Augustine writes. Yet I-Ie "created both simultaneously, so that form came upon matter with no space of time intervening." CHAPTER 53: MATTER 69 tlerlyingnature," Aristotle says that it "is an man, and signate or individual; common, such 'eet of scientific knowledge by analogy. For as flesh and bones; and individual, as this flesh the bronze is to the statue, the wood to the and these bones." When the intellect forms so is the matter and the formless before re- concepts of different kinds of physical sub- 'ing form to anything which has form,and stances, it abstracts "from the individual sensi- so also is the underlying nature to substance, ble matter, but not from the common sensible i.e., the actually existing." matter." In defining the nature of man, for example, we abstract, Aquinas says, from "this flesh and these bones,which do not belong to the species as such, but to the individual"; hut we do not abstract from the fact that man, con- sisting of body and soul, is a thing of flesh and bones. To say that man consists of body and soul is to indicate that common matter enters into the definition ofman as a physical substance. But in distinction from definitions of this type, which are proper to physics, mathematical and meta- physical definitions carry the abstraction from matter still further. Tn mathematics, Aquinas declares, the intellect abstracts "not only from individual sensible matter, but also from com- mon sensible matter." In conceiving numbers and figures, the intellect does not, however, ab- stract from matter entirely, but only from in- dividual intelligible matter. The common intel- ligible matter which is represented by "sub- stance as subject to quantity" underlies all mathematical notions. "But some things," Aquinas maintains, "can be abstracted even from common intelligible Inatter, such as being, unity, potency, act and the like, all of which can exist without matter." Such abstraction char- acterizes the concepts of metaphysics. Aquinas thus differentiates the three speculative sci- of physics, mathematics, and metaphys- ICS In terms of three grades of abstraction, each distinguished by the type of rnatter from which the concepts of the science are abstracted. vVith one exception physical matter is not said to be of different kinds when it exists under different forms. The one exception for both Aristotle and Aquinas is the matter of terres- trial and celestial bodies. Basing his inference on the observations avail- able to him, Aristotle holds that the heavenly bodies are eternal-"not subject to increase or diminution, but unaging and unalterable and unmodified." Immutable in every other way, they are, however, subject to local motion. Since they are eternal, both their matter and respects in which the substance is actually terminate), and lacks certain forms which it assume (the respects in which the substanc both indeterminate and potential). As the chapter on indicates, Aristo frequently uses artistic production to affor simple illustration of his theory of matter a form as principles of change. When a man s out to make a bed, he chooses material, such wood, which can be shaped in a certain wa The same wood could have been made into chair or a table. With respect to these vario possible determinations in structure, the w is itself indeterminate and determinable. Before the artist has worked on it prod tively, the wood is in a state of both privati and potentiality with regard to the form of bed, a chair, or a table. The transformati which the artist effects consists in his actuali ing certain potentialities in the material forms or determinations which the rnaterial the moment lacks. When the bed is made, t \vood or matter which is now actually in t form of a bed may still have the potentiali for being remade into a chair or table. The wood, of course, remains actually wo throughout these artificial changes, as it do not when it suffers the natural change of co bustion. This indicates that though the wo may be called Inatter or material by the arti it is not matter, but a substance, a thing co posite of matter and form; for when the wood reduced to ashes by fire, the matter which h the form of wood assumes another form. In the analysis of accidental change, whi artistic production illustrates, it suffices treat a composite substance, like wood or ir or bronze, as the material principle. But in t analysis of substantial change, when matter self changes fronl being one kind of nlatter being another in the coming to be or perishi of composite substances, the material princi must be pure matter-matter totally devoid form. Where a whole substance can be garded as the matter or substratumofacciden change (in quality, quantity, or place) the su stratum of substantial change, which Aristo calls "generation and corruption," must matter in a condition of absolute indeterminac and pure patentiality. Referring to this ultimate substratum as "t REMOVE MATTER entirely from a thing and, according to Aristotle, you renlove its capacity for physical change. Remove form, and you re- move its existence, for nothing can exist with- aut being actual or detenninate in certain re- spects. When a thing changes physically, it loses certain determinate characteristics and acquires others. The determinations it acquires it had previously lacked, yet all the while it must have had a capacity for acquiring them. The thing is "capable both of being and of not being," Aristotle says, "and this capacity," he goes on to say, "is the matter in each." T'he matter of an existing substance is thus con- ceived as that which has certain forms (the ter may not agree, as Descartes and Newton do not, in their mechanical formulations. They mayor may not be atomistsiThey may, like Lucretius, think that local motion is an abso- lutely intrinsic property of the eternal. parti- cles; or, like Descartes and Newton, they may think that God first imparted motion to matter at the \vorld's creation. They may hold that all subsequent motions issue therefrom in a con- tinuous chain of cause and effect. But when matter is the only factor in the constitution of bodies, and one body differs from another only in its quantitative determinations, the conse- quence for physical theory seems to be one or another sort of mechanical formulation. When matter is nothing more than a body's potentiality for change, and when neither what the body is nor how it changes can be explained by reference to its matter alone, physical theory seelns to be constructed in other than mechani- cal terms. Its concepts and principles resemble those of biology. It finds natural tendencies or desires, and ends or final causes, in the motion of inert as well as animate bodies. Central to Aristotle's physics are his theory of the four causes, discussed in the chapter on CAUSE, and his theory of the four types of change, discussed in the chapter on CHANGE. But even more fundamental is his definition of motion as the actualization of that which is potential in a respect in which it is potential. With motion so defined, the principles of phys- ics must include the correlative factors of po- tentiality and actuality which Aristotle con- ceives in terms of matter and form. 68 OUTLINE OF TOPICS 5. Matter in relation to good and evil '6. Criticisms of materialism and its consequences 1'1 and REP 220d-21b;'Q 7,AI, ANS 31a-d; A 2, ANS and REP 3 "Q 14, A 2, REP Id Q IS, A3, REP 18, A 4, REP 2-3 Q47, A I, ANS Q 86, A 3 463b-d; PART I-II, Q 10, A I, REP 2 662d-663d 20 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART Q 52, A I, ANS 15d-18a; PART III, Q 2, A I, ANS and REP 2 710a-711e 28 GILBERT: Loadstone, 13K I, 2sb 35 LOCKE: Human Understanding, BK III, CH X, SECT IS 295a-e 35 BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT II 42 KANT: Pure Reason, 72c-76e esp 186b-d / Judgement, 56sb-d; la. Matter and the analysis of change: prime and secondary matter; privation and form; participation and the receptacle 7 PLATO: Timaeus, 45se-4s8b 8 ARISTOTLE: Physics, BKI, CH BK II, CH I [I93a9-b2I] cn 3 [I94bI6-I9Sa2I] 271a-d; BK II, eH 7-BK III, CH 3 275b-280e; BK IV, CH 2 [209bI-2l0aI3] 288b-289a; CH 4 [2II b S-2I2 a 2] 290e-291a;cH 9 [2I7a20_b26] 297a-e; BK V'I, CH 10 [i40b8- 24Ia26] / Heavens, BK I, CH 33600.- 362a; BK III, CH 2 [30Ib33-302a9] 393b; BK CHAPTER 53:. MATTER REFERENCES 'Fo find the passages cited, use the numbers in heavy type, 'which are the volume arid page numbers of the passages referred to. For e.xample, in 4 HOMER: Iliad, B.K [26S-283] 12d, the number 4 is the number of the volume In the set; the number 12dlndlcates that the sage is in sectiond of page 12. PAGE SECTIONS: \Vhen the text is printed in one column, the letters a and b refer to the upper and lower halves of the page. For example., in53 JAMES : Psychology, 116a-119b, thepassag.e begins in the upper half of page 116 and ends In the lower half of page 119. When the text IS" printed in two columns, the letters a and b refer to the upper and of hand side of the page, the letters eand d to the upper and lower halves of the. nght-hand sloeo( thepage. For example, in 7 PLATO: Symposium, 163b-164e, the passage begins in the lower half of the left-hand side of page 163 and ends in the upper half of the right-hand side of page 164. AUTHOR'S DIVISIONS: One or more of the main divisions of a \vorK (such as PART, BK, CH, SECT) are sometimes included in the reference; line numbers, in braCKets, aregive ll in tain cases; e.g., Iliad, BK 11 [26S-283] 12d. BIBLE REFERENCES: The references are to bOOK, chapter, and verse. When the King James and Douay versions differ in title of bOOKS or in the numbering of chapters or verses, the King James version is cited first and the Douay, indicated by a (D), follows; e.g., OLD MENT: Nehemiah, 7:4S-(D) II Esdras, 7:46. SYMBOLS: The abbreviation "esp" calls the reader's attention to one or more especially relevant parts of a whole reference; "passim" signifies that the topic is tently rather than continuously in the worK or passage cited. For additional infonnation concerning the style of the references, see the Explanation of Reference Style; for general guidance in the use of The Great Ideas, consult thePreface. 1. The conception of matter as a principle of change and as one constituent of the being of changing things: the receptacle or substratum 7 PLATO: Timaeus, 4sse-4s8b 8ARISTOTLE: Physics, BK I, CH 4-9 262a-268d; BKIII, CH 7 286e/ Metaphysics, BK I, CH 6 [987bI9]-CH 7 [988bS] 50sd-s06e; CH 8 [988b22-989b24] s06d-s08a; BK" II, CH 3 [99SaI S-I7] 513d; BK" V, CH 2 [IOI3 a2 4-27] s33b; CH 4 534d-s35e; BK VII, eH 3 ss2a; CH 7-17 ss5a-s66a,c esp CH 7-9 sssa- 5s8a, CH 17 565a-566a,e; BK VIII 566a-s70d; BK XII, CH 10 [I07Sa2S-33] 606a / Soul, BK III, CH S [43oaIO-I4] 662e 12 AURELIUS: Aleditations, BK VII, SECT 23 281h; BK XII, SECT 30 310a-b 16 PTOLEMY: Almagest, BK I, sb 17 PLOTINUS: First Ennead, TR VIII, CH 10, 32a-b / Second Ennead, TR IV-V sOa-60c; TR VII, CH 3 64b-c / Thrd Ennead, TR VI, CH 7-19 110d-119a / Sixth Ennead, TR III, CH 2-8 281e-285d 18 AUGUSTINE: Confessions, BK XlI, par 6 100b-e; par 14 102b 19 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I, Q 3, A 2, ANS and REP 3 lsc-16a; Q 4, A 1, ANS 75 74 difference between celestialandterrestt1al In ter or motion, and as the chapter on 'ASTRa OMYshowTs, by so doing he not only gives-I petus to the Copernican system, but also pa the way for Newton frame laws ofmoti applicable to matter everywhere in theu verse. Because their matter is the same, it possible, Kepler insists, to explain the motion the heavenly bodies by the same principl which account for the motion of bodies 0 earth. THE GREAT IDEAS I. The. conception of matter a principle of change and as oneconstituent of the being of changing things: the receptacle or substratum la. Matter and the analysis of change: prime and secondary n1atter; privation and form; participation and the receptacle lb. Matter in relation to the kinds of change: substantial and accidental change; terrestrial and celestial motion Ic.Matter and the distinction between individual and univ'ersal: signate and com- mon matter; sensible and intelligible matter 2. The conception of matter as extension, as a bodily substance, or as a modeof substance: atoms and compound.bodies 2a. The properties of matter: hypotheses concerning its constitution 2b. The motions of matter or .bodies 2C. Matter -as the support of s.ensible" qualities 2d. The diremption of body and mind, or matter and spirit 3. The existence of matter 3a. Matter as the sole existent: materialism,atomism 3b. Matter as the most imperfect grade of being or reality 3C. Matter as a fiction of the mind 3d. The relation of God to matter: the creation of matter and its motions 4. Matter as an object or condition of knowledge 4a. The knowability of matter: by sense, by reason 4b. The role of matter in the concepts and definitions of the several sciences: the grades of abstraction in physics, mathematics, and metaphysics 4c.,The material conditions of sensation, imagination, and memory 4d. The material conditions of thought: the relation of matter to the existence and acts of the mind 70 their motion must be. different from that of perishable terrestrial ,bodies. "All things that change hayematter," Aristotle writes, "but rnatter ofdifferent sorts; of eternal things those which are not generable but are movable in space have for generation, :however, hut for motion from one place to another." That motion from place to place is, unlike terrestrial niotion, circular; it has the appropriate characteristic .ofendlessness. Kepler challenges .. this .theory. 'of a radical THE GREAT. IDEAS CHAPTER 53: MATTER 72 (1. The conception of matter as a principle of change and as one constituent of the being of changing things: the receptacle or sub- stratum. 1a. Matter and the analysis of change: prime andsecondary matter;priva- tion andform; participation and the recep- tacle.) IV, CH 5 403d-404d I Generation and Corrup- tion 409a-441a,c esp BK I, CH 3 413c-416c I Meteorology, BK IV, CH 12 [389b22-39oa7] 493d- 494a I Metaphysics, BK I, CH 6 [987b30-988a8] 506a; BK II, CH 2 [994al-6] 512b; [994aI9-b8] 512c-d; BK III, CH 4 [999a24-b24] 518a-c; BK v, CH 4 [IOI4b27-IOISaIO] 535a-b; CH 6 [10168, 17-24] 536c-d; BK VI, CH 2 [1026b27-I027aIS] 549a-b; CH 3 [1027bIS-17] 549d; BK VII, CH 7-9 555a-558a; BK VIII, CH I [I042B24-b7] 566b-d; CH 4-6 568d-570d; BK IX, CH 7 574c- 575a; BK XI, CH 9 [106S b 20-3S] 594a-b; BK XII, CH 2-5 598c-601a; CH 10 [107Sa2S_b24] 606a-c 9 ARISTOTLE: Generation ofAnimals, BK I, CH 20 [729aIO]-CH 22 ]73ob33] 269b-271a 12 AURELIUS: Meditations, BK VII, SECT 23 281b 16 KEPLER: Harmonies ofthe World, 1078a-b 17 PLOTINUS: Second Ennead, TR III, CH 18- TR V, CH 5 49c-60c I Third Ennead, TR VI, CH 7-19 110d-119a I Sixth Ennead, TR III, CH 2-8 281c-285d; TR v, CH 8 307d-308c 18 AUGUSTINE: Confessions, BK XII, par 3-6 99d-100c; par 8 101a-b; par 14-16 102b-103a; par 24-26 104c-105b; par 28-"31 105c-107a; par 38-4 I08d-110a; BK XIII, par 48 124a 19 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I, Q 3, A 2, ANS A 8, ANS 19d-20c; Q 4, A I, ANS and REP 2 20d-21b; Q 5, A 3, REP 3 25a-d; Q 7, A 2, REP 3 31d-32c; Q 9, A I, ANS 38c-39c; Q 29, A 2, REP 3-5 163b-164b; Q 45, A 2, REP 2 242d-244a; A 8 249b-250a; Q 46, A I, REP 6 250a-252d; Q 47, A I, ANS 256a- 257b; Q 48, A 3, ANS 261b-262a; Q 66, A I 343d-345c; Q 77, A I, REP 2 399c-401b; Q 84, A 3, REP 2 443d-444d; Q 86, A3 463b-d; Q 92, A 2, REP 2 489d-490c; A 3, REP I 490c- 49lb; A 4, ANS and REP I 491b-d; Q 103, A I, REP 2 528b-529a; Q 104, A I, ANS and REP 1-2 534c-536c; Q 110 564c-568b; Q 117, A 3 598c- 599b; PART I-II, Q 22, A I, REP I 720d- 721c 20 AQUINAS: Surnma Theologica, PART I-II, Q 60, A I 49d-50c; Q85, A 6 182d-184a; PART II-II, Q 24, A II, ANS 498b-499c; PART III SUPPL, Q92, A I, REP 12 1025c-1032b 21 DANTE: Divine Comedy, PARADISE, VII [121- 148] l16b-c; XIII [52-87] 126a-b 28 GILBERT: Loadstone, BK I, 25b 28 HARVEY: On Anirnal Generation, 407c-409b; 412a-415b; 494a-496d esp 494b, 495c-496a 35 LOCKE : Human Understanding, BK III, CH X, SECT 15 295a-c 35 BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT II 415a-b 42 KANT: Pure Reason, 74b-76c; 100d-101b lb. Matter in relation to the kinds of chan substantial and accidental change; te restrial and celestial motion 8 ARISTOTLE: Physics, BK III, CH I [200 b 2 20I a I4] 278b-c;-CH 3 [202 b 22-29] 280c; BK I CH 9 296b-297c es1J [2I7a20_b26] 297a-c; B v, CH 1-2 304a-307b I Heavens, BK I, CH 2 359d-364a; CH 9-12 369a-375d; BK II, Cll [287bIS-2I] 379b; BK IV, CH 3 [3IOb22-31IaI 402b-c; CH 4 [3 I2aJ-22] 403c-d I Generati and Corruption 409a-441a,c esp BK I, cn [320a2-6] 417a I lvfetaphysics, BK CH 7- 555a-558a esp CH 7 [I032aI5-22] 555a-b; B VIII, CH I [I042a24-b7] 566b-d; CH 4 [1044b2] CH 5 [I044 b2 9] 569a-c; BK IX, CH 7 [I049a19 bI] 574d-575a; CH 8 [I050b20-28] 576c-d BK XI, CH II [r067bI]-CH 12 [lo68 b 2S] 596a 597d; BK XII, CH 2-5 598c-601a esp CH 2 [1069 24'-27] 599a I Soul, BK I, Clf 3 [406b26-407 13] 636b-637b 16 PTOLEMY: Alnlagest, BK I, Sa-6a; 8b; lOb-lIb, BK XIII, 429a-b 16 COPERNICUS: Revolutions of the Heavenl Spheres, BK I, 517b-518a; 519b-520a 16 KEPLER: Epitome, BK IV, 888b-890b; 894a; 929b-930b 17 PLOTINUS: Second Ennead, TR I, CH 1-4 35a- 37b; TR IV, CH 6 51d-52a; TR v, CH 6 103b- 104a I Third Ennead, TR VI, CH 8-19 111e- 119a 19 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I, Q 7, A 2, ANS and REP 3 3Id-32c; Q 45, A 2, REP 2 242d-244a; Q 46, A I, REP 1,3,5-6 250a-252d; Q 48, A 3, ANS 261b-262a; Q 55, A 2, ANS 289d-290d; Q6b, 1\ I, ANS 343d-345c; A 2 345d-347b; Q 84, A3, REP I 443d-444d 20 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I-II, Q49, A 4, ANS 5a-6a 28 GILBERT: Loadstone, BK VI, 110b-c lc. Matter and the distinction between individ.- ual and universal: signate and common matter; sensible and intelligible matter 8 ARISTOTLE: Metaphysics, BK I, CH 6 [987bI9- 98saI6] 505d-506b; BK III, CH 3 [998a20_bI3) 517a-b; CH 4 [999a24-IOOoa4] 518a-d; CH 6 [lo03aS-16] 521d-522a,c; BK VII, CH 10-II 558a-561a; CH 15 [lo39b27-3I] 563d; BK VIII, CH 6 [r04sa33-36] 570a-b; BK x, CH I [IOS2 a 28--37] 578d; BK XII, CH 4-5 599d-601a; BK XIII, CH 10 618c-619a,c I Soul, BK II, CH I [412a6-81 642a 12 AURELIUS: Meditations, BK XII, SECT 30 310a-b 17 PLOTINUS: Second Ennead, TR IV, CH 2-5 SOb-SId I Sixth Ennead, TR III, CH 3 282a-c 19 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I, Q 3, A 2, REP 3 15c-16a; A 3, ANS 16a-d; Q 4, A I, REP 3 20d-21b; Q 7, A I, ANS 31a-d; Q 14, A II, ANS 84c-85c; Q 15, A 3, REP 4 93b-94a; Q 29, A I 162a-163b; A 2, REP 3 163b-164b; A 3, REP 4 164c-165c; Q 47, A 2, ANS 257b- 020 258c; Q 50, A 4, ANS 273b-274b; Q 56, A I, REP 2 292a-d; Q 65, A 3, ANS 341c-342b; Q 75, A 4, ANS 381b-382a; A 5, ANS 382a-383b; A 7, ANS 384d-385c; Q 76, A2388c-391a; Q 85, A I, REP 2 451c-453c; Q 115, A I, ANS and REP 1-3 585d-587c; Q 119, A I,ANS 604c-607b 20 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART. III, Q 2, A 2, ANS 711d-712d; A3, REP 3 713a-714c 2 The conception of matter as extension, as a bodily substance, or asa mode of sub- stance: atoms and compound bodies 10 GALEN: Natural Faculties, BK I, CH 12 172d- 173c 12 LUCRETIUS: Nature of Things, BK I [146-448] 2d-6c; [483-634] 7a-8d 1'1 PLOTINUS: Second Ennead, TR IV, CH 7, 52c; CH 12 54c-55b; TR VII, ClI 3 64b-c I Third Ennead, TR I, CH 2, 78d; TR VI, CH 7, lIla; CH 12, 114b-c; CH I6-I9116e-119a 23 HOBBES: Leviathan, PART IV, 271d-272a 28 GALILEO: Two New Sciences, FIRST DAY, 131d- 132a 31 Rules, XIV. 28a-33b I "N!ed!"ta- tions, II 77d-8ld esp 78c-d, 80b-d I ObJectzons and Replies, l14d-115a,c; DEFVII 130c-d; 153c-154b; 231a-232a 31 SPINOZA: Ethics, PART I, PROP 14, COROL 2- PROP IS 360a-361d; PART II, DEF I 373a; PROP 2374a 34 NEWTON: OptiCS,BK lu,S3'7a-b; S4lb 35 LOCKE: Human Understanding, BK en, CH XIII, SECT 11-27 150d-154d passim; ClIXXIII 204a-214b passim; BK III, CH X, SECT IS 295a-c; BK IV, ClI X, SECT 9-19 351b-354c passim 35 BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT 9--17 4l4d-4l6b passim; SECT. 37 419d; SECT .50 422c; SECT 91-96 430d-431d 35 HUME: HU1rlan Understanding, SECT XII, DIV 123506a 42 Pure Reason, 15b-c; esp lOOc-d I Judgement, 580c-d 45 LAVOISIER: Elements of Chemistry, PREF, 3b-4a 45 FARADAY: Researches in. Electricity; 850b,d- 855a,c 53 JAMES : Psychology, 876a-b; 882a-884h 2a.The properties of matter: hypotheses con.. cerning its constitution 8 ARISTOTLE: Heavens, BK III, CH 4 [3()3 a 3:.... b8 ] 394b-d I Generation and Corruption, BK I, CH 2 410d-413c; CH" 8 423b-425d I Metaphysics, BK I, CH 4 [985b3-'19] 503c-d 10 GALEN: Natural Faculties, BK I, CH 12 172d- 173c 12 LUCRETIUS: Nature of Things, BK 1[146-920] 2d-12b; BK 11[333-990] 19b-27c 16 K.EPLER: Epitome, BK IV, 936a-937a 23 HOBBES: Leviathan, PARTIV,271d-272a 28 GILBERT: Loadstone, BKII, 29c-30a 73 28 GALILEO: Two New Sciences, SECOND DAY 178a-196d passim 30 BACON: Novum Organum, BK II, APH 8 140b; APH 25 155a-d; APH 40 170c-173d; APH 48 179d-188b 31 DESCARTES:. Meditations, II, 78c-d; 80b-d I Objections and Replies, DEF VII 130c-d; 154a; 231a-232a 31 SPINOZA: Ethics, PART I, PROP 14, COROL 2- PROP 15 360a-361d; PROP 25, COROL 365b; PART II, DEF I 373a; PROP 2374a 34 NEWTON: Principles, DEF 1 Sa; DEF III Sb; BK II, PROP 40, SCHOL, 246a-b; BK III, RULE III 270b-271a; PROP 6, COROL III-IV 281b; PROP 7 281b-282b; GENERAL SCHOL,371b I Optics, BK II, 479b-485b; BK III,S31a-543b esp 34 HUYGENS: Light, CH III, 566b-569b; CH V, 60lb-603b 35 LOCKE: Human .Understanding, BK II, CHIV 129b-131a; CH VIII, SECT 7'-26 134b-138b passim; CH XIII, SECT 21-27 1S2d-154d;cH XXI, SECT 2-4 178c-179c; SECT 75 200b.. d; CH XXIII, SECT 1-32 204a-212d passim; CH XXXI, SECT 2 239b-d esp 239d; BK III, CHVI, SECT 5, 269b-c; SECT 21 273c-d; CH X, SECT IS 295a-c; BK IV, CH III,SEcr6 313c- 315b 35 BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT 9-18 4l4d4l6c passim; SECT 37 419d;' SECT 47 421t-422a; SECT 85 429c; SECT 91 430d- 43la 42 KANT: Pure Reason, 99a-100d esp 100c-d; 137a-140c; 152a-d 45 LAVOISIER: Elements of Chemistry, PART I, 9a-10c; 12d-13d; 16b-c 45 FOURIER: Theory ofHeat, 169b-170a 45 FARADAY: Researches in Electricity, 273a-276a; 386c-390d; 604c-632d esp 604c-607a,c, 626c- 632d; 819a-c; 850b,d:-85Sa,c 46 HEGEL: Philosophy of History, INTRO, .160c-d 51TOLSTOY: War and Peace, EPILOGUE II, 695c 53 JAMES: Psychology,68a-b 2b. Tile motions of matter or bodies 8 ARISTOTLE: Physics, BKIV,CH 6-9 292c- 297c I Generation and Corruption, BK I, CH 8 423b-425d \. 10 GALEN: Natural Faculties, BK I, CH 12.172d- 173c 12 LUCRETIUS: Nature of Things, BK I [329-397] 5b-6a; [951-1113] 12d-14d; BK II [62-.332] l5d-19b; BK III [177-251 32b-c 19 AQUINAS: Summ.a. Theologica, :BART I,'Q47, A I, ANS 256a-257b; Q 115, A I,' ANsandREP 3,5 585d-587c 23 HOBBES: Leviathan, PART I, 50a-b; PART IV, 268d; 271d-272a 28 GALILEO: Two New Sciences, FIRST DAY, 157b-171b; THIRD DAY-FOURTHDAy197a.. 260a,c THE GREAT IDEAS CHAPTER 53: 'MATTER 74 (2. The conception of matter. as exte,,!sion,' as a bodily substance" or as a mode of substanfe: atoms and compound:bodies. 2b. The mo.. tions of matter or bodies.) 30 BAcoN: Novum Organum, BK I, APH66 114d"'115e; BK II, APH 35-36 162a-168d; APH 40 170e-173d; APH 48 179d-188b 31 DESCARTES: Discourse, PART V 54b-60c / Objections' and Replies, 114d-115a; DEF VII 130e-d; 231a-b 31 SPINOZA: Ethics,PART II, LEMMA 1-7 318e- 380b 34NEWTON:' Principles la-372a / Optics, BK III, 541b 35 LOCKE: Human Understanding, BKII, ClI XXI, SECT 2-4 178e-17ge; CH XXIII, SECT I7209a; SECT'22209d; SECT 28-29 211b.. 212a 38 MONTESQUIEU: Spirit ofLaws,BKI, 1 b 45 LAVOISIER: Elements of Chemistry., PART I, 41b-c 45 FOURIER: The01Y of Heat, 169a-b 51{TOLSTOY: War and Peace, EPILOGUE r695e 53 JAMES: Psychology, 882a; 883a..884b passim 2,0. Matter as the support of sensible 8 ARISTOTLE: Sense and the Sensible, reH 4 [442a3o..:-b24] 680a-e; CH 6 [445P4-446a20] 683h-684c 12 LUCRETIUS : Nature of Things,. BK, II [398-477] 20a-21a; [730-885] 24b-26b; BK IV;[522-721] i51a-53d .. 17 PLOTINUS: Second Ennead,TR IV, ClI 8-13 52e-5Sd/ ThirdEnnead,TR VI, CH6-I9109d- 119a / Fourth Ennead, 'TIt VII, 'ClI 8, 196a-b I SixtffEnnead, TR I, 'CH 29 267c-268b 23 HOBBES: Leviathan, ,PART Ie, .49b-d'; 57a-b; PART III, '172b 30 BACON: NovumOrganum, BK"II,APH 40 170e-173d 31 DESOARTEs:Meditations, II, 78e-d; 80b.:.d / Objections and Replies, DEF VII 130e..d;228c- 22gb; 229d-230e;;231a-b 35 LOCKE: .. !jun1an " SH VIII, SECT 7-26 134h-1381:> passim; clI XXIIi: 204a.. 214b passim, espSECT 1;...,6:204a-2<:>Se, SECT I5208e-d 35 BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT 7-21 ,414b-417a; SECT\ 37 419cl;SECT 49: 422b; SECT 73 427b-e; SECT 76-78 427d428b; SECT 91 430d-431a, 3,,5 HUME: Human' Underftanding, SECT XII, DIV 122-123 505ci:..5Q6a esp DIV 123'506a 42 .KANT: Pure .Reason, ,15b-e; 100e-d 53 i JAMES: Psychology, 185a;331a; S03a 2d. The. direwption of body and mind, or lll,;it- , ter and spirit 1,7 PLOfFINUS: .. First Ennead, TR I . la-fib> 3-71d-4a /Sixth Ennead, TR IV,: cH,r297b-d; CH 4-6 299a-300b 19 AQUINAS: Sunl1na Theologica, A4393a-394e 30 BACON: Advancement ofLearning, 48d-SOb 31 DESCARTES: Discourse, PART IV, 51d.;.S2a Meditations, II 77cJ-81d passim; VI 96b-1 passim I Objections and Replies, DEF VI- 130e; DEF X l30d; PROP IV l33e; 153e-lS' 224d.. 225d; 231a"'232d; 248b 31 SPINOZA: Ethics, PART ,I, PROP 14, COROL 360a; PROP 15, SCHOL 360b-361d; PART PROP 1-7. 373d-375e; PROP 10-13 376e-37 PART III, PROP 2 396e-398b; PART V, PR 451a-452e 35 LOCKE: Hun1an Understanding, BK II, XIII, SECT 16 151d-l52a; CH XXIII, SECT 205a-b; SECT 15;""32 208e-212d passim; XXVII, SECT 27 227d-228a; BK IV, CH' n SECT 28 322a-e; CH x, SECT 9-19 351b-35 passim 35 BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT 18-2 416h-417'a 53 JAMES: Psychology, 84a-93b esp 88a-90a; 95b 98a; 115a-119b esp 118b-119b; 139a-l40 221a-226a esp 221a-222b; 225b-226a 3. The existence of matter 3a. Matter as the sole existent: atomism 7 PLATO: Sophist, 567a-568a 8 ARISTOTLE: Physics,BKII, 269b"e /. Heavens, BK III, CH 4 [303a3-bg 394b.;.d /Generation and Corruption, .BK I, C 2 410d-413e; CH.B 423b-425d /Metaphysic. UK I, ClI 3 f983 b 7]-CH 4 CH 8 [988b23-989b20] 506d-507d; BK VII, C 13 [I039a2-II]\562d; BK XII, eH 10 [175825 I07685J'606a-d 10 GALEN: Natural Faculties, BK I, CH {2l72 173e 12 LUCRETIUS: Nature of Things, 'BK I [146-634
12 AURELIUS: Meditations, BKIX, SECT 39 29Sa BK x, SECT 6 297a-"b 17 PLOTINUS: Second Ennead, TR IV, eH r SOa- eH 7, 52e I Third Ennead, TR I, CH 3 79b- j c Fourth Ennead, TR VII, CH 2-4 192a-193e Six'Nt lnnead, TR 1,CH 25-30 265b-268e ' 18 AUGUSTINE: Confessions" BK v,parI9-2 3'2e-33b; par 25 34b-e; BK: VII,par 1-2 43 44a; par 7 45a-d 19AQ'UINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I" Q 4 A I, 'ANS 256a-257b; Q 50, A 1, ANS 269 270a; Q75, A I, ANS378b..31ge 23 HOBBES: Leviathan, PART Ill, 172b; PART I 269b-272b 30 BACON: NovU1n Organu111, BK II, APH 140b 35 LOCKE: Hutnan Understanding, SECT 8-17 351a..353c passim 53 JAMES:: Psychology, 9$b-98a; [fn I] ; 882a-884b 4a Matter as the. most imperfect grade of be- ing or reahty 7 PLATO: Republic, 423e-424a 2AURELIUS: Medztatzons, BK IX, SECT 36 .294d-295a '1 PLOTINUS: First Ennead,TR' VIII, CH 4-5 28e-2ge; CH 7-8 I Second Ennead, TR IV CH 5 51b-d; CH 15-16 56e-57c; TR v, cIl 5ge-60e /Third Ennead, TR VI, CH 11-14 113a-116a 18AUGUSTINE: Confessions, . UK. XII, ,par 3-8 99d-101b; par 15 102b-e 19 AQUINAS : Summa Theologica,. PART I, Q 3, A 8;ANS and REP 3 19d-20e; Q 4, A I,ANS and REP 2 20d-21b; Q5,AJ, REP 3 25a-d;Q 7, A2, REP 3 31d-32e;' Q 14, A I I, REP 3 84e-85e; Q 15, A 3, REP 3 93b-94a; Q 46, ,A I, REP I 250a-252d; Q 84, A 3, .. REP 2 443d-444d; Q 103, A 1, REP 2 528b-529a; Q 115, AI, REP 4585d-587c 21 DANTE: Divine Comedy, PARADISE, XXIX [13-36] 150b-e 35 LOCKE: Human Understanding, BK .II, CH XXI SECT 2118e; CH XXIII, SECT 28 211b-d 35 Underftanding; .. SECT XII, DIV 123506a 3&. Matter as a fiction of the mind 35 BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT 1-96 413a-431d passim; SECT 133 43ge:440a 35 HUME: Ruman Understanding, SEC1;XII, DIV I23S06a tl2 KANT: Pure Reason, 85d-91d esp 88b-e tl4 BOSWELL: Johnson, 134e-d 3d. The relation of God to matter: the creation of matter and its motions OLD TESTAMENT: Genesis, 1.....2 ApOCRYPHA: . Wisdom of Solomon, OT, Book of WisdQm, 11:18 7 PLATO: Timaeus, 448b-449a; 450b-451b; 458a-b; 466a-b 8 ARISTOTLE: Metaphysics,. l?K XII, CH 6 [I07IbI9-32] 601e; CH 10 [I075bI6-24]606e 12 LUCRETIUS: Nature of Things, BK I [146-158] 2d-3a; BK V [146-194] 63a-e 18 AUGUSTINE: . Confessions, BK VII, pari. 45a- d; BK XI, par 7 90d-91a; BK XII, par 3-9 99d-101e; par 15.... 16 102b-103a; par 24- 105e-107a; par 38-4 108d-110a; BKXIII, par. 45 123a; par 48 124a / City of God, BK XI, .cli 335e 19 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica,PARTI,.Q 8, A4, ANS and REP I 37c-38e; Q IS, A 3, R'EP 3-4 93b-94a; Q 16, A 7, REP 2 99a-d;Q .44, A 2 239b-240a; Q 45, A 2, REP 2242d-244a; A 8 249b-250a; Q 46"A I esp REP I,3,5-6250a- 252d; Q 47, A 'I,;\NS 256a-257b;. Q 65, A 3 341e-342b; Q 66343d-349d;Q 75, A 5, REP 1,4 382a-383b; Q A 3, REP' 2 443d-444d; 'i5 Q 91 484a-488e; Q 92, A 2,REP 2 489d-490e; A 4 491b-d; Q 103, A I, REP 2 528b-529a; Q l0S, AA 1-2 538d-540e; Q, IIO,A2, ANS 565d-566d; Q 117, A 3, ANS and REP 2 598e... 599b . 20 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I-II" Q85, A 6 182d,.184a 21 DANTE: Divine Comedy, PARADlsE,vn[I2I- 148] 116b-e; XIII [52-84J 126a-b; XXIX [IJ...45] 150b-e 22 CHAUCER: Knight'S Tale [2987-3016l209a-b 30 BACON: of Learning, ... .. d 31 DESCARTES : Di,fcourSe,PART v, 54d,.56b 31 SPINOZA: Ethics, PART I, PROP I5360a-361d; PART II, DEF I 373a; PROP 2 374a; PROP 7, SCHOL 375b-e 32 MILTON: Paradise Lost, BKIII [694-735] 150b- 151b esp [708-735] 150b-151b;BK V [468-55] 185b-186a; [577-599J 187b-188a; BK VII [59- 640] 218b-231a esp [70-108] 2l8b-219b,[I92- 386] 221b,.225b 34 NEWTON: Optics, BK III, 541b-543a 35 LOCKE : Human Understanding, BK. II, CH XXI, SECT 2178e;CHXXIII, S.ECT 28 211b-d;BK IV, CH X, SECT 9-19 351b-354e ' 35 BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT 67- 79 426b-428b passim; SECT' 91""-94' 430d- 431c 35 HUME: Human Understanding, SECT XII, DIV 132, 509d [fn I] 46 HEGEL: Philosophy of Histqry, INTRO, 156d- 157b 4. Matter as an object or condition of knowl- edge 4a. The knowability of matter: by sense, by reason 7 PLATO: Phaedo, 228d-22ge / Republic,BK IX, 423e-424a / Timaeus, 456a-458a 8 ARISTOTLE: Physics, BK I, CH 7 [I9Ia8-II] 266d I Metaphysics, BK VII,CH IS [I039b20- I040a8] 563c-564a; BK IX, CH 574d-575a I Soul, BKIII,CH 4 [429bro-43089] 661d-662e 12 LUCRETIUS: Nature of Things,BK I [265-328] 4b-5a; BK II [80-I4I]l6a-d 17 PLOTINUS: First Ennead" TR VIII, . CH 9 31e- 32a I Second Ennead, TR IV, ClI 10 53b-d;CH I254e-55b 18 AUGUSTINE: Confessions,< .BK XII, par 3-6 99d-100e 19 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I, Q 3, A3, ANS 16a-d; Q 14, A II 84e-85e; Q IS, A 3, REP 3-4 93b-94a; Q 50, A I" 269b-2.70a; Q 57, A I 295a-d; Q 66, A I,REP I 343d,.345e; QQ 84-86 440b-464d; Q 87, A I, ANS 465a.. 466e 20 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART III SUPPL, Q92, A I, ANS aAd. REP.I21025e-10321? 30 BACON:. Novum Organum, BK .I, APfI .. 66 114d-11Sc TI-IE GREAT IDEAS CROSS-REFERENCES For: Other considerations of matter as a principle of change, see ART 2b;BEING 7b(S); CHANGE 2a; FORM Id( I)-Id(2); and for the theory of celestial and terrestrial nlatter as distinct in kind, see ASTRONOMY 8a; BEING 7b(3); CHANGE 7C(4); WORLD 6a. The conception of matter as potentiality in relation to formas actuality, and for the theory of physical substances as composite of matter and form, see BEING 7b(2), 7c(3); FORM 2C( 1)- 2c(3); INFINITY 4c; 11AN 3a; MIND 2b; ONE AND MANY 3b(4); SOUL 3c. Considerations relevant to the doctrine that matter is the source of nUlnerical diversity or the principle of individuality in material things, see SAl\tIE AND OTHER Ia; UNIVERSAL AND PARTICULAR 3. 6. Criticisms of materialism and its conse- quences 7 PLATO: Sophist, 567a-568a 8 ARISTOTLE: Soul, BK I, CH 2-5 633a--641d 9 ARISTOTLE: Parts of Animals, BK I, CH I [640b5-64Ia33] 163a-164b 10 GALEN: Natural Faculties, BK I, CH 12 172d- 173c; BK II, CH 3, 185a; CH 6188e-191a 17 PLOTINUS: Third Ennead, TR I, CH 2, 78d; CH 3 79b-e / Fourth Ennead, TR VII, CH 6-8, 194b-197b 19 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I, Q 75, A I, REP I 378b-37ge; Q 84, !A I, ANS 440d- 442a; A 6, ANS 447e-449b 28 HARVEY:On Animal Generation, 355b-d; 495e-496d 35 BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT 21 417a; SECT 35 41ge; SECT 50 422e; SECT 85-88 42ge-430b; SECT 92"':96 431a-d; SECT 102 432d-433a; SECT 133 439c-440a; SECT 141 441a-b 42 KANT: Pure Reason, 126e-d I Judgement, 558b-559d; 579d-580a; 582b-e 51 TOLSTOY: War and Peace, BK III, 140b; 143a-e; BK X, 449b-e; BK XI, 469a-472b; BK XIII, 570d; BK XIV, 589c-590c; 609b; EPILOGUE II, 678a-b; 68ge-690a; 694d-696d S3 JAMES: Psychology, 5a; 8b-9a;84a-119b; 291a-295b; 655b-656a; 745a-b; 823a-825a 54 FREUD: New Introductory Lectures, 882b-884c to 6 CHAPTER 53: MATTER 77 REP 2289d-290d; Q 57, A I, REP 3295a-d; Q 12 AURELIUS: Meditations, BK III, SECT 3 260b; 75, A S 382a-383b; Q 76 385e-399b; Q 77, A BKIX, SECT 36 294d-295a 5 403d-404e; A 8 406b-407a; Q 79, A 3 416a- 17 PLOTINUS: First Ennead, TR VIII 27b-34a esp 417a; QQ 84-88 440b-473a esp Q 84, A 6-Q 8S, ClI 3-S 28a-2ge, elI 7, 30d I Second Ennead, A 3 447e-457a; Q 110, A 2, REP I 565d-566d; TR IV, ClI 16 57b-e / Fifth Ennead, TR IX, CH Q 117, A 3 598e-599b; PART I-II, Q 22,A I 10, 250e / Sixth Ennead, TR VII, CH 27-29 720d-721e 334d-336b 20 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I-II, Q85, 18 AUGUSTINE: Confessions, BK V, par 19-21, A 6 182d-184a; PART III SUPPL, Q 92, AI, 32e-33b; BK VII, par 1-7 par 18-22 j\NS and REP 10 1025e-1032b 49a-50a; BK XIII, par 45 123a I City of God, 23 HOBBES: Leviathan, PART I, 49a-d; 52b-e; BK XI, CH 23 334l:-335e 54b-c; PART II, 162c-; PJ\.RT IV, 262b 19 AQUINAs:Sunlma Theologica, PART I, Q3, A2, 30 BACoN: Novum Organum, BK I, APH 51 111e ANS 15c-16a; Q4, A I, ANS and REP 2 20d-21b; 31 DESCARTES:_ Rules, XII, 18b-20d; XIV-XV PART I-II, Q 17, 8, REP I 692a-e 28a-33d I Discourse, PART IV, 53b; PART VI, 21 DANTE: Divine Comedy, PARADISE, 1[97-142] 61e I Objections and Replies, 215b-e; 229d- 107b-d; XIII [52- 87] 126a-b 230c 41 GIBBON: Decline and Fall, 330a-b 35 LOCKE: Human Understanding, BK II, CH XXVII, SECT 27 227d-228a 42 KANT: Pure Reason, 23a-24a esp 23b; 45d-46a; 48d-49a; 63a; 63d-64a; 6ge- 72c; 81b-83b; 85d-91d; 95a-d; 115b-e; 117b.; 119a; 173b-174a; 187a-e / Fund. Prin. Meta- physic oflvIorals, 281c-282d I Practical Reason, 349b-35Oc esp 350b-e / Judgement, 542b-543c; 570b-572e;604a-b 49 DAR\VIN: Descent oflvIan, 288e-d 50 MARX: Capital, 11b-e 53 JAMES: Psychology, xiiib-xiva; 2b-3b; 8a-67a esp 9a-12b, 15b-17b, 43a-44a, 46a-47a, 51b- 52a, 53a-54a, 66b-67a; 69b-73b; 82b; 84a- 93b esp 84a-85a, 88a-90b, 91a-93a; 116a-119b esp 119b; 151a-153a; 291a-295b; 367a-373a esp 368a-369a, 370b-371a; 455b-456a; 690a-b; 758a-759a; 827b-835a; 856b-858a 54 FREUD: Hysteria, 87a / Interpretation of Dreams, 154d-155a; 367b-e; 382a-e; 384e- 385a / Unconscious, 431e-d I Beyond the Pleasure Principle, 646b-64ge 5. Matter in relation to good and evil 7 PLATO: Phaedo, 224a-226c; 231e-234e / Ti- maeus, 452d-453b; 474b-d I Statesman, 587a- 589c 8 ARISTOTLE: Physics, BK I, CH 9 [I9Ib35-192R24] 267d-268e I Metaphysics, BK I, CH 6 [988a7-I6] 506a-b 12 EPICTETUS: Discourses, BK I, CH 9 114e-116b 4b to 4c. The material conditions of sensation, i agination, and memory 7 PLATO: Meno, 177b-e 8 ARISTOTLE: Soul, BK I, CH I [403 a S'"'""2 632a-b; BK II, CHJ2 [424a25-bI9] 656a-d; III, CH 3 [429 a 4-7] 661b; CH 4 [429 a2 9-- 661c-d I Sleep, CH I [454aI-I2] 696b-e 12 LUCRETIUS: Nature of Things, BK II L398-4 20a-2la; [73-864] 24b-26a; BK IV [26-2 44b-47d; [324-336] 48e; [522--817] 51a-54d 19 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART I, Q A2, ANS 37ge-380e; A 3, ANS and REP 2 380 381b; Q 76, A 5, ANS 394c-396a; Q 78, A ANS 410a-411d; Q 84, A 2, ANS 442b-443 A 6, ANs441e.!449b; A 7, ANS 449b-450 A8, REP 2 450b-451b; Q86, A4, REP 2 463 464d 23 HOBBES: Leviathan, PART I, PART III, 172b-d; PART IV, 262a-b 31 DESCARTES: Rules, XII 18b-25b passilu Meditations, VI 96b-103d passim 31 SPINOZA: Ethics, PART II, PROP 17-18 380 382b 34 NEWTON: Optics, BK III, 518b-519b; 522a 35 LOCKE: 1/uman Understanding, BK II, CH SECT 23 127b; CH VIII, SECT 4 133d; CH SECT 5 142a-b; SECT 10 143e-d; ClI XXI SECT 3 CH XXXIII, SECT 6 249a-b 35 BERKELEY: Human Knotvledge, SECT 18- 416b-417a; SECT 2S 417d-418a; SECT 10 432d-433a 35 HUME: Human Understanding, SECT XII, DI 123506a 45 LAVOISIER: Elements of Chemistry, PART 14a 49 DARWIN: Origin of Species, 85d-87a / Desc o.f Man, 568d-569a 53 JAMES: Psychology, 2b-3a; 13a-19b esp 15 17b, 19a-b; 26b-42a; 49b-50a; 98b-lO passim; 348a-'359a esp 348a, 358a-b; 36 373a esp 368b-369a, 370a-b; e 428b-430a; 453a; 455b-457a; 459a-479a pa sim, esp 460a-464a, 469a; 497a-501b; 520 521a; 758a-759a 54 FREUD: Interpretation of Drea1ns, 351e-35 esp 352a-b / Beyond the Pleasure Prineip 646b-648a esp 646c-d, 647d-648a 4d. The material conditions of thought: t relation of matter to the existence a acts of the mind 8 ARISTOTLE: Soul, BK I, CH 4 [408bI8-3 638e-d; BK III, CH 4-5 661b-662d; CH [43IaI4-bI9] 663d-664b 12 LUCRETIUS: Nature of Things, BK III [94-17 31b-32b; BK IV [722-817] 53d-54d 17 PLOTINUS: Fourth Ennead, TR VII, CH 8, 195 19 AQUINAS: SU1nma Theologica, PART I, Q3, A REP 2 14b-15b; Q 7, A 2, REP 2 31d-32e; Q 1 A 2, REP 1--3 76d-77d; A II, REP I 84c-8 Q 50, A 2, ANS 270a--272a; Q 55, A 2, ANS 4b. The role of matter in the concepts and defi- nitions of the several sciences: the grades of abstraction in physics, mathematics, and metaphysics 7 PLATO: Timaeus, 455e-458b 8 ARISTOTLE: Physics, BK II, CH 2 270a-271a; CH 7-9 275b-278a,e I Meteorology, BK IV, CH 12 493d-494d I lv[etaphysics, BR II, CH 3 [99SaI 5-20] 513d; BK III, CH 3 [99 8a20 - b 14 ] 517a-b; BK VI, CH I [I02S b 28-I026 a 6] 547d-548a; BK VII, CH 10-11 558a-561a; CH IS [I039b20-I04oR8] 563c-564a; CH I7 565a- 566a,e; BK VIII, CH 2-3 566d-568d; CH 6 569d-570d; BK X, CH 8-9 585b-586e; BK XI, CH 7 [I064aI 9-28] 592c; BK XII, CH 9 [ Io 74 b 37-I075a2] 605e; BK XIII, CH. 2 [I077bII]- CH 3 [1078a3I] 609a-d I Soul, BK I, CH 1 [403aI5-bI9] 632b-d; BK III, CH 7 [43 IbI J- I 9] 664b 9 ARISTOTLE: Parts of Animals, BK I, CH I [64IaI4-3I] 163d-164a 16 PTOLEMY: Almagest, 13K I, 5b 19 AQUINAS: Sum1na Theologica, PART I, Q I, A I, REP 2 3b-4a; Q 3, A 3, ANS 16a-d; Q 18, A 4, REP 3 107d-108c; Q 29, A2, REP .3163b-164b; Q 50, A 2, REP I 270a-272a; Q 75, A 4 381b- 382a; Q 85, A I, REP 2 451e-453c 20 AQUINAS: Summa Theologica, PART II-II, Q 9,A2, REP .3 424b-425a 30 BACON: Advancement of Learning, 43d-44e / Novurn Organum, BK I, APH 51111e; APH 66 114d-115e; BK II, APH 8 140b 31 DESCARTES: Rules, XII, 19a-e; XIV 28a-33b / Objections and Replies, .169c-170a 35 BERKELEY: Human Knotvledge, SECT 50 422e; SECT 118-131 436b-43ge (4. Matter as an object or condition of knowledge. 4a. Theknowability of matter: by sense, by reason.) 31 DESCARTES: Meditations, I-II 75a-81d passim; VI 96b-l03d passim I Objections and Replies, 229d-230e 31 SPINOZA: Ethics, PART I, PROP 15, SCHOL 360b- 361d 3S LOCKE: fluman Understanding, BK II, CH VIII, SECT 7-26 134b-138b passim; CH XXIII, SECT 5 205a-b; SECT 15-17 208e-209a; SECT 22-32 209d-212d; BK IV, CH III, SECT 6 313e-315b; SECT 9-17 315e-317e passim; SECT 23-27 320a-322a passim; CH VI, .SECT 14 335d- 336b 3S BERKELEY: Human Knowledge, SECT 16-24 416a-417d; SECT 54 423b 35 HUME: Human Understanding, SECT XII, DIV 123 50Ga 42 KANT: Pure Reason, 186b-d 46 HEGEL: Philosophy of Right, PART I, par 52 25a-e 48 MELVILLE: Moby Dick, 231a 53 JAMES: Psychology, 140b-145a;502a-503b pas- sim 76 II ADDITIONAL READINGS THE GREAT. IDEAS 79 The Nature ofExistence, CH 34 STOUT. Mznd and Matter BROAD. The Mind and Its Place in Nature CH 4 PESCOQS. :,Essai. crJfiquesur l' G. N. LEWIS.' T.he }A.natomy of Science, ESSAY IV B. RUSSELL. Prtnctples of Mathematics, CH S3 --. The ofPhilosophy, CH 2-4 --.. --. The Analyszs of Matter, CHI- 1 4 McDouC: ALL . Modern Materialism and Emergent Evolutton SANTAYANA. Scepticism and Animal Faith, CH 19- 20 --.The Realm of Matter, 10 LENZEN. The Nature of PART IV CH IS' - ... .. , KONINCK. Le probleme de l'indeterminisme CHAPTER 53: MATTER XWELL. Matter and Motion ZE. Metaphysics, BK II, CH S-6 LANCK. Das Prinzip der der Energie . PEIRCE. Collected Papers, )rOL'Vl, par 23 8 - 28 6. SON. The Grammar ofSctence; CRB H. "On the Principle of the Conservation of ergy, " in Popular Scientific Lectures QN. _. ... ANOV. In Deftnse- ofMaterialism ................ Essays in the History of Materialisn1 ERSON. and Reality, CH 4-S, 7- 8 N. Matertaltsm and Empiriocriticism IRER. Substance and Function, sUP IV t. Space-Time-Matter TEHEAD. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of 15 SUAREZ. Disputationes Metaphysicae, v (3), x ( XII (3), XIII-XV, XVI (I), XXVI (2), XXVII, X (4), XXXI (8, 10, 13), xXXIV (S..!6), XXXV (3, XXXVI JOHN OF SAINT THOMAS. Cursus Philosophicus T misticus, Philosophia Naturalis, PART I, QQ 2 9, I I DIGBY. The Nature of Bodies MALEBRANCHE. De la recherche de fa verite,BK (n), CH 8 (2) LEIBNITZ. New Essays Concerning Hun-Jan Una standing, APPENDIX, CH I VOLTAIRE. "Matter," in A Philosophical Diction HOLBACH. The System of Nature J. PRIESTLEY and PRICE. A Free Discussion of Doctrine of Materialism and Philosophical Nee sity SCHOPENHAUER. The World as Will and Idea, v III, SUP, CH 24 BUCHNER. Force and Matter HELMHOLTZ. Popular Lectures onScientiJic Subje VII LANGE. The Flistory of Materialism B. STEWART. The Conservation of Energy Listed below are works not included in Great Books ofthe Western World, but relevant to the idea and topicswitll. which this chapter deals. These works are divided into two groups: 1. Works by authors 'represented in this collection. II. Works by authors not represented in this collection. For the date, place, and other facts concerning the publication of the works cited, consult the Bibliography of Additional Readings which foHows the last chapter of The Great Ideas. For: The conception of matter or extension as a substance, or as H mode of substance, see BEl 7b(4); FORM zd; MAN 3a; MINDZg; SOUL 3c. Atomism as a theory of matter and as a materialistic philosophy of nature; see ELEMENT'S Sh; MIND 2e; and fordiscussions bearing on materialism as a philo.sophyofnature, societ and history, see ELEMENT S; HISTORY 4a(z); MAN 3c; WILL )C. .l\1atter in relation to mind,orbody in relation to soul, see MAN 3a; MIND 2a-ze; SOUL 3e; and for the discussion: qf immaterial substances, spirits, ,or' beings which 'exist apa from matter, seeANGEL 2, 3q;BEING7b(z); ETERNITY 4a; FORza, zd.;GQD4,C; MAN 3a(I MIND za; SOUL 3a-3c. The theological problems of matter, its creation and conservation, see GOD 7a ;WORLD 4 4e( I). The physical properties matter or bodies and the laws of their motion,see ,ASTRONOl 8c(3); MECHANICS 4H, sa-sf(z);;pa-6e; QUANTITY sd-se; SPACE Ia-Id; and for the pro lem of the infinity of matter or of an infinite body, see INFINITY 4a-4b. Matter as an object of knowledge, see KNOWLEDGE sa(2). !\1atter in relation to sensation and to sensible qualities, see ELEMENT se; MECHANICS '1 QUALITY I;. SENSE 3C(3). . Matter in relation to thought,abstract ideas, or, definitions, see DEFINITION 6a; FORM 3 IDEA2g; MEMORY AND IMAGINATION 6C(I); MIND Ia(z); SENSE sa; UNIVERSAL A PARTICULAR 4c. I. AQUINAS. On Being and Essence -.-.-.-. On the Power of God, QA -,.-. De NaturaMateriae et Dimensionibus Inter- /JJ1inalis DESCARTES. The Principles of Philosophy, PART I, 7....-8, 11-12., 62-:-65 ; PART II, 22-23; PART III,2f8- 102; PART/IV, 1-2 7, 31-48 H0 13 BES.. Concerning Body, PART II, CH 8 BERKELEY. Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous KANT. Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science J. S. MILL. An Examination of Sir William Hamil- ton's Philosophy, CH 12-13 . ENGELS. Ludwig Feuerbach and the Outline of Clas- sical Gern1an Philosophy II. EPICURUS. Letter to Herodotus ERIGENA. De Divisione Naturae JUDAH HA-LEVI. Kitab al Khazari CREscAs.Or Adonai, PROPOSITIONS 10-12, 16, 19- 24
A History of Literary Criticism in the Renaissance
With special reference to the influence of Italy in the
formation and development of modern classicism