This article discusses the legacy and limitations of New Criticism as the dominant approach to literary criticism since World War II. While New Criticism's emphasis on close reading and the autonomy of the literary text was beneficial for teaching literature, it ultimately led criticism to focus almost exclusively on interpretation of individual works. The author argues that interpretation is just one task of criticism among many, and that we need other approaches like histories of literature as an institution and analyses of literature's social and psychological roles to further our understanding of literature as a whole.
This article discusses the legacy and limitations of New Criticism as the dominant approach to literary criticism since World War II. While New Criticism's emphasis on close reading and the autonomy of the literary text was beneficial for teaching literature, it ultimately led criticism to focus almost exclusively on interpretation of individual works. The author argues that interpretation is just one task of criticism among many, and that we need other approaches like histories of literature as an institution and analyses of literature's social and psychological roles to further our understanding of literature as a whole.
This article discusses the legacy and limitations of New Criticism as the dominant approach to literary criticism since World War II. While New Criticism's emphasis on close reading and the autonomy of the literary text was beneficial for teaching literature, it ultimately led criticism to focus almost exclusively on interpretation of individual works. The author argues that interpretation is just one task of criticism among many, and that we need other approaches like histories of literature as an institution and analyses of literature's social and psychological roles to further our understanding of literature as a whole.
This article discusses the legacy and limitations of New Criticism as the dominant approach to literary criticism since World War II. While New Criticism's emphasis on close reading and the autonomy of the literary text was beneficial for teaching literature, it ultimately led criticism to focus almost exclusively on interpretation of individual works. The author argues that interpretation is just one task of criticism among many, and that we need other approaches like histories of literature as an institution and analyses of literature's social and psychological roles to further our understanding of literature as a whole.
Copyright:
Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 14
At a glance
Powered by AI
The passage discusses the legacy and influence of the New Criticism on literary education and criticism in the post-World War II era.
The New Criticism came to occupy a dominant position in universities and influenced how literature was taught and written about, focusing on close reading of texts. However, it is now being challenged by newer forms of criticism that consider historical and social contexts.
It gave literary education a new focus on the experience of reading texts itself rather than just accumulating information. It allowed even beginning students to engage closely with texts.
University of Oregon
Beond Inlevpvelalion TIe Fvospecls oJ Conlenpovav Cvilicisn
AulIov|s) JonalIan CuIIev Souvce Conpavalive Lilevaluve, VoI. 28, No. 3, Conlenpovav Cvilicisn TIeov and Fvaclice |Sunnev, 1976), pp. 244-256 FuIIisIed I Duke University Press on IeIaIJ oJ lIe University of Oregon SlaIIe UBL http://www.jstor.org/stable/1769220 . Accessed 19/08/2013 1703 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . University of Oregon and Duke University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Comparative Literature. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions JONATHAN CULLER Beyond Interpretation: The Prospects of Contemporary Criticism IN THE YEARS since World War II, the New Criticism has been challenged, even vilified, but it has seldom been effectively ignored. The inability if not reluctance of its opponents simply to evade its legacy testifies to the dominant position it has come to occupy in American and British universities. Despite the many attacks on it, despite the lack of an organized and systematic defense, it seems not unfair to speak of the hegemony of New Criticism in this period and of the determining influence it has exercised on our ways of writing about and teaching literature. In a sense, whatever critical affiliations we may proclaim, we are all New Critics now, in that it would require a strenuous consciousness of effort to escape notions of the autonomy of the literary work, the importance of demonstrating its unity, and the requirement of "close reading." In many ways the influence of the New Criticism has been beneficent, especially on the teaching of literature. Those old enough to have ex- perienced the rite de passage, the gradual emergence from an earlier mode of literary study, speak of the sense of release, the new excitement breathed into literary education by the assumption that even the mean- est student who lacked the scholarly information of his betters, could make valid comments on the language and structure of the text. No longer was discussion and evaluation of a work something which had to wait upon acquisition of a respectable store of literary, historical, and biographical information. No longer was the right to comment some- thing earned by months in a library. Even the beginning student of literature was now confronted with poems, asked to read them closely, 244 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions PROSPECTS OF CRITICISM and required to discuss and evaluate their use of language and their thematic organization. To make the experience of the text itself central to literary education and to relegate the accumulation of information about the text to an ancillary status was a move which gave the study of literature a new focus and justification, as well as promoting a more precise and relevant understanding of literary works. But what is good for literary education is not necessarily good for the study of literature in general, and those very aspects of the New Criticism which ensured its success in schools and universities deter- mined its eventual limitations as a program for literary criticism. Commitment to the autonomy of the literary text, a fundamental article of faith with beneficial consequences for the teaching of literature, led to a commitment to interpretation as the proper activity of criticism. If the work is an autonomous whole, then it can and should be studied in and for itself, without reference to possible external contexts, whether biographical, historical, psychoanalytic, or sociological. Distinguishing what was external from what was internal, rejecting historical and causal explanation in favor of internal analysis, the New Criticism left the reader and critic with only one recourse. They must interpret the poem; they must show how its various parts contribute to a thematic unity, for it is this thematic unity which justifies the work's status as autonomous artifact. When a poem is read in and for itself critics must fall back upon the one constant of their situation: there is a poem being read by a human being. Whatever else is external to the poem, the fact that it addresses a human being means that what it says about human life is internal to it. The critic's task is to show how the interaction of the poem's parts produces a complex and ontologically privileged state- ment about human experience. Though they may occasionally attempt to disguise the fact, the basic concepts of the New Critics and their followers derive from this particular thematic and interpretive orientation. The poem is not simply a series of sentences; it is spoken by a persona, who expresses an attitude to be defined, speaking in a particular tone which puts the attitude in one of various possible modes or degrees of commitment. Since the poem is an autonomous whole its value must lie within it, in the richness and complexity of the attitude, in the variety of the alterna- tive values or judgments it puts into the balance and relates to one another. Hence one finds in poems ambivalence, ambiguity, tension, irony, paradox. These are all thematic operators, which permit one to translate formal features of the language into meanings, so that the poem may be unified as a complex thematic structure which expresses an attitude toward the world. And in place of a theory of reading which would specify how order was to be achieved, the New Criticism 245 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions COMPARATIVE LITERATURE deployed a common humanism or, as R. S. Crane calls it, a "set of reduction terms" toward which analysis of ambivalence, tension, irony, and paradox was to move: "life and death, good and evil, love and hate, harmony and strife, order and disorder, eternity and time, reality and appearance, truth and falsity . . . emotion and reason, simplicity and complexity, nature and art."' A repertoire of contrasting attitudes and values relevant to the human situation served as a kind of target lan- guage in the process of thematic translation. To analyze a poem was to show how all its parts contributed to a complex statement about human problems. In short, it would be possible to demonstrate that, given its premises, the New Criticism was necessarily an interpretive criticism. But in fact it is scarcely necessary to make out such a case, for the most impor- tant and insidious legacy of the New Criticism is the widespread and unquestioning acceptance of the notion that the critic's job is to interpret literary works. Indeed, fulfillment of the interpretive task has come to be the touchstone by which other kinds of critical writing are judged, and reviewers inevitably ask of any work of literary theory, linguistic analysis, or historical scholarship, whether it actually assists us in our understanding of particular works. In this critical climate it is therefore important, if only as a means of loosening the grip which interpretation has on critical consciousness, to take up a tendentious position and to maintain that, while the experience of literature may be an experience of interpreting works, in fact the interpretation of individual works is only tangentially related to the understanding of literature. To engage in the study of literature is not to produce yet another interpretation of King Lear but to advance one's understanding of the conventions and operations of an institution, a mode of discourse. Indeed, there are many tasks that confront criticism, many things that we need if we are to advance our understanding of literature, but if there is one thing we do not need it is more interpretations of literary works. It is not at all difficult to list in a general way critical projects which would be of compelling interest if carried through to some measure of completion; and such a list is in itself the best illustration of the potential fecundity of other ways of writing about literature. We have no convincing account of the role or function of literature in society or social consciousness. We have only fragmentary or anecdotal histories of literature as an institution: we need a fuller exploration of its hisorical relation to the other forms of discourse through which the world is organized and human activities are given meaning. We need a more sophisticated and apposite account of the role of literature in the psy- 1 The Languages of Criticism and the Structure of Poetry (Toronto, 1953), pp. 123-24. 246 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions PROSPECTS OF CRITICISM chological economies of both writers and readers; and in particular we ought to understand much more than we do about the effects of fictional discourse. As Frank Kermode emphasized in his seminal work, The Sense of an Ending, criticism has made almost no progress toward a comprehensive theory of fictions, and we still operate with rudimentary notions of "dramatic illusion" and "identification" whose crudity proclaims their unacceptability. What is the status and what is the role of fictions, or, to pose the same kind of problem in another way, what are the relations (the historical, the psychic, the social relationships) between the real and the fictive ? What are the ways of moving between life and art? What operations or figures articulate this movement? Have we in fact progressed beyond Freud's simple distinction between the figures of condensation and displacement? Finally, or perhaps in sum, we need a typology of discourse and a theory of the relations (both mimetic and nonmimetic) between literature and the other modes of discourse which make up the text of intersubjective experience. The fact that we are so far from possessing these things in what is, after all, an age of criticism-an age where unparalleled industry and intelligence have been invested in writing about literature-is in part due to the preeminent role accorded to interpretation. Indeed, one of the best ways of talking about the failures of contemporary criticism is to look at the fate which has befallen three very intelligent and promis- ing attempts to break away from the legacy of the New Criticism. In each case the failure to combat the notion of interpretation itself, or rather the conscious or unconscious persistence of the notion that a critical approach must justify itself by its interpretive results, has emasculated a highly promising mode of investigation. My first case, and in many ways the most significant, is that of Northrop Frye's Anatomy of Criticism. Frye's polemical introduction is, of course, a powerful indictment of contemporary criticism and an argument for a systematic poetics: criticism is in a state of "naive induction," trying to study individual works of literature without a proper conceptual framework. It must recognize that literature is not a simple aggregate of discrete works but a conceptual space which can be coherently organized; and it must, if it is to become a discipline, make a "leap to a new ground from which it can discover what the organizing or containing forms of its conceptual framework are."2 Working on this new ground involves assuming the possibility of "a coherent and com- prehensive theory of literature, logically and scientifically organized, some of which the student unconsciously learns as he goes on, but the main principles of which are as yet unknown to us."3 2 natomy of Criticism (New York, 1965), p. 16. 3 Ibid., p. 11. 247 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions COMPARATIVE LITERATURE This is certainly a direct attack on the atomism of the New Criticism and the assumption that one should approach each individual work with as few preconceptions as possible in order to experience directly the words on the page, but Frye does not realize the importance of attacking interpretation itself. He hovers on the edge of the problem, characterizing as "one of the many slovenly illiteracies that the absence of systematic criticism has allowed to grow up" the notion that "the critic should confine himself to 'getting out' of a poem exactly what the poet may vaguely be asumed to have been aware of 'putting in' "; but the function of this argument in his overall enterprise is anything but clear. It is wrongly assumed, he continues, that the critic needs no conceptual framework and that his job is simply "to take a poem into which a poet has diligently stuffed a specific number of beauties or effects, and complacently to extract them one by one, like his prototype Little Jack Horner."4 One might conceivably take this sentence as a general attack on interpretation, especially interpretation of a complacent and funda- mentally tautological kind, but in fact, as the earlier sentence makes clear, Frye's real target is interpretation of an intentionalist kind. Join- ing the New Critics in rejecting criticism which is guilty of the inten- tional fallacy, Frye has picked the wrong enemy and opened the door to a trivialization of his enterprise. The systematic poetics for which he calls and to which he makes a substantial contribution can thus be seen as a simple prelude to interpretation. Approaching the text with a conceptual framework, which consists of the theories of Modes, Symbols, Myths, and Genres as outlined in the Anatomy, the critic can interpret the work-not by pulling out what the poet was aware of putting in but by extracting the elements of the various modes, genres, symbols, and myths which were put in with or without the author's explicit knowledge. In this case, interpretation would still be the test of a critical method, and the value of Frye's approach would be that it enabled one to perceive meanings which hitherto had been obscure. Certainly this is not the justification Frye would wish to give his project. His repeated assertions that criticism must seek a comprehen- sive view of what it is doing, that it must try to attain an understanding of the fundamental principles which make it a discipline and mode of knowledge, show that he has other goals in mind. But his failure to question interpretation as a goal creates a fundamental ambiguity about the status of his categories and schemas. In identifying Spring, Summer, Autumn, and Winter as the four mythic categories, what exactly is Frye claiming? He might be suggesting that these categories form a 4 Ibid., pp. 17-18. 248 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions PROSPECTS OF CRITICISM general conceptual map which we have assimilated through our experi- ence of literature and which helps to explain the fact that we interpret literature as we do. In other words, he might be claiming that in order to account for the meanings and effects of literary works one must bring to light these fundamental distinctions which are constantly at work in our reading of literature. Alternatively, he might be claiming that he has discovered categories of experience basic to the human psyche and that in order to discover the true or deepest meaning of literary works we must apply to them these categories, as hermeneutic devices. Though the difference between these alternatives may seem slight, it is in fact crucial to the project of a poetics. In the second case one is claiming to have discovered distinctions which serve as a method of interpretation: which enable one to produce new and better readings of literary works. In the first case one is not offering a method of interpre- tation but is claiming to have made some progress toward explaining why we interpret literary works as we do. In terms of the polemical introduction and the suggestion that we should try to make explicit the implicit theory of literature which students unconsciously acquire in their literary education, the first interpretation would certainly be preferable; but in terms of the traditional tasks and preoccupations of criticism, which Frye has not had the self-consciousness to reject, the second interpretation is more likely to prevail. In fact, this is exactly what has happened. Though it began as a plea for a systematic poetics, Frye's work has done less to promote work in poetics than to stimulate a mode of interpretation which has come to be known as "myth-criticism" or archetypal criticism. The assumption that the critic's task is to interpret individual works remains unchanged, only now, on the theory that the deepest meanings of a work are to be sought in the archetypal symbols or patterns which it deploys, Frye's categories are used as a set of labeling devices. Frye failed to recognize that the enemy of poetics is not just atomism but the interpretive project to which atomism ministers, and this led not only to deflection of systematic energy but to the promotion of a rather anodyne mode of interpretation. Labeling the archetypal elements of literary works does not get one very far, especially since it is possible to argue that these archetypes are designed to help explain why it is that we interpret works in the way we do. Generally, one can only deplore the foundering of an exciting enterprise. Frye complained that poetics had advanced very little since Aristotle; we can now complain that, in America at least, poetics has advanced very little since the A4natomy of Criticism. The second example of a potentially revolutionary movement which has not succeeded in freeing itself from the shackles of interpretation 249 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions COMPARATIVE LITERATURE is psychoanalytic criticism. Although, as I have already suggested, there are many central problems concerning the status and effects of fictions which might be elucidated by a psychological or psychoanalytic approach, the best criticism of this kind seems, almost unconsciously, to have adopted interpretation as its goal, as if a psychological approach to literature could only prove itself by demonstrating its superiority as an interpretive method. Frederick Crews's The Sins of the Fathers: Hawthorne's Psychological Themes certainly demonstrates the ap- propriateness of a psychoanalytic method for making sense of many powerful and puzzling elements in Hawthorne's work. Oddities of plot, character, and fantasy become more interesting and their force is made more intelligible when they are analyzed as representations of the con- sequences of unresolved Oedipal conflicts: the works "rest on fantasy, but on the shared fantasy of mankind, and this makes for a more pene- trating fiction than would any illusionistic slice of life."5 It would be unjust to criticize The Sins of the Fathers for being an interpretive study, since in so being it demonstrates the efficacy of the psychoanalytic approach to the dominant task of criticism. But it is sad that the most accomplished work of psychoanalytic criticism should address itself to this task, for there is always the danger that psycho- analytic criticism will define itself in these terms: as a method of inter- pretation for texts which contain special oddities or discontinuities of character and event. This would indeed be to surrender to the demands of interpretation. My third case is the "affective stylistics" of Stanley Fish, which begins with a determined attempt to break away from the assumptions and procedures of the New Criticism but which, again, fails to identify interpretation as the real enemy and so nullifies the theoretical insights on which it was originally based. Fish starts by rejecting the notion that the work may be treated as an object complete in itself and suggests that the "affective fallacy" is not in fact a fallacy. Wimsatt and Beards- ley had argued that one must not confuse the poem and its results ("what it is and what it does") and maintained that if one concentrates on the psychological effects or experience of a poem, "the poem itself, as an object of specifically critical judgment, tends to disappear."6 Fish replies that "the objectivity of the text is an illusion, and moreover, a dangerous illusion ... A line of print or a page of a book is so obviously there that it seems to be the sole repository of whatever value and meaning we associate with it."7 But in fact the text acquires meaning only in the activity of reading. Spatial metaphors which make the text 5 The Sins of the Fathers (New York, 1966), p. 263. 6 W. K. Wimsatt, The Verbal Icon (Lexington, Ky., 1954), p. 21. 7 Stanley Fish, Self-Consuming Artifacts (Berkeley, 1972), p. 400. 250 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions PROSPECTS OF CRITICISM the container of a meaning falsify the situation, which is always one of a temporal and sequential experience. The meaning of a word or other element of a text is what it does in the work, and to specify what it does is to show how it is received, organized, and generally processed by the reader as he moves from left to right and from line to line of a text. The meaning of a work is not something it contains, in spatial fashion, but the experience which results from the linear and temporal process- ing of its components. One must analyze an event rather than an object if one would discuss the meaning and value of a text, and this involves "an analysis of the developing responses of the reader in relation to the words as they succeed one another in time."8 This is a fruitful reorientation, and one should be clear about the various things it does. First of all, by stressing the importance of analyzing an act rather than an object, Fish's approach is, as he says, "from the very beginning organizing itself in terms of what is sig- nificant,"9 whereas if one tries to treat the text as an autonomous object and describe its properties one has no particular way of distinguishing between significant properties and insignificant ones. One can continue, almost ad infinitum, counting elements, noting their distribution, and generally producing facts about the text as object which have little relevance to what we would be willing to recognize as the meaning and value of the text. If one begins by analyzing interpretive acts, on the other hand, the significant properties of the text are those which have provoked or are deployed in the interpretive experience. But secondly, and this is perhaps a more significant point, in rejecting the notion of work as object Fish prepares to accord literary theory its true role. If a work were an autonomous entity which contained its own meaning, then literary theory would consist only of ex post facto generalizations about the properties of such entities. It would be very much an ancillary activity, with no necessary place in the study of literature. (Indeed, for the New Critics literary theory was largely a negative activity: designed to rule out of court, by labeling as fallacies, approaches which might prevent an innocent and direct contact with "the words on the page.") If, however, one claims that the qualities of literary works can only be studied by analyzing the reader's response, then the task of literary theory becomes central: it must account for responses by analyzing the norms, conventions, and mental operations which make these responses and interpretations possible. If a given sentence can have different meanings in a novel and in a lyric poem, it 8 Ibid., pp. 387-88. 9 Fish, "What Is Stylistics and Why Are They Saying Such Terrible Things About It?," in Approaches to Poetics, ed. Seymour Chatman (New York, 1973), p. 149. 251 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions COMPARATIVE LITERATURE is because the conventions of verse and prose lead one to respond to it differently, and to explain the meaning or response is to set out the conventions on which it is based. Or again, if a work can be read either as literature or as history, biography, and so forth, the differences in meaning and response are to be explained in terms of conventions and expectations which produce them. If the meaning of each text were inherent to it, then there would be little need for a general theory, except to point out this fact and to list some possible heuristic strategies which might, on occasion, help readers to discover this inherent meaning. But if the meaning of a work lies in the function of its elements in a sequential interpretive experience, then the task of literary theory is to explicate the notion of the "reader" in and through whom the combination and sequential interaction of ele- ments takes place. What is it to be a skilled or informed reader of literature? We presume to test students' progress towards this goal, but we have few explicit ideas of what they are supposed to learn, and have made scant progress towards setting out the conventions, norms, and operations which they are supposed to master if they are to become "readers." Fish's focus on response places this question in the fore- ground of literary study. Understanding literature is not a matter of understanding literary texts but of studying the activity of interpreta- tion so as to make explicit the vast sum of tacit knowledge which enables works to have meaning and which we may label "literary competence." The task of the critic, as it seems to emerge from Fish's enterprise, would be to describe the procedures and conventions of reading so as to offer a comprehensive theory of the way in which we go about making sense of texts. But, sadly, this is a step which Fish himself does not take; nor does he seem even to recognize that this is an impli- cation of his theoretical reorientation, so blinded is he by the notion that the critic's job is to interpret. He raises the question of a general theory of reading only once, and then to beg it: the informed reader, he says, is assumed to be "sufficiently experienced as a reader to have internalized the properties of literary discourse, including everything from the most local of devices (figures of speech, etc.) to whole genres."10 To insist that meaning and value lie not in the text itself but in the activity of reading, and then to turn around and tell us that we need not inquire what this activity involves, is a scandalous derelic- tion of duty. And the fault seems to lie with interpretive commitment. Fish wants to illustrate his claim that meaning and value are better conceived as temporal experiences than as spatial configurations or structures and that literature is thus "didactic in a special sense; it does 10 Fish, Self-Consuming Artifacts, p. 406. For further discussion of what this involves, see Jonathan Culler, Structuralist Poetics (Ithaca, 1975). 252 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions PROSPECTS OF CRITICISM not preach the truth but asks its readers to discover the truth for themselves."'1 He sees his task as that of showing us what truths are discovered by the experience of reading particular works. And so in Self-Consuming Artifacts: The Experience of Seventeenth-Century Literature he leads us through a series of works, showing how, in each case, propositions, categories, and distinctions are proposed as if they were going to be developed and made essential but then are questioned, undermined, and generally displaced by what follows. The works them- selves thus become "self-consuming artifacts" and the value which remains is that of the experience of reading. To define this value in each case, to show what results from the interaction of the parts, is of course to retreat to the traditional tasks of thematic interpretation. Commitment to interpretive criticism is particularly ironic in Fish's case since, as he repeatedly tells us, this is simply a matter of describing his experience of reading. His theory has radically reduced the space of interpretive play and worked the analyst into a tight corner. To claim simultaneously that one is simply describing the experience of readers and that one is producing new and striking interpretations is indeed a difficult act, and Fish's energies are devoted to maintaining this stance in difficult conditions. How long he can maintain it is, of course, another question: there is clearly not much future in the enterprise of offering ever more interpretations by recounting the reader's experience of texts. The future lies, on the contrary, in the theoretical enterprise which Fish sketches and then flees.12 These three cases, though very different in the content of their proposals and results, suggest in their formal and strategic convergence a gloomy prognostic: the principle of interpretation is so strong an unexamined postulate of American criticism that it subsumes and neutralizes even the most forceful and intelligent acts of revolt. "La musique savante manque a notre desir." The desire to find new ways of writing about literature has been frustrated for want of knowledge- able accompaniment. But there are now signs that the increasing influence of European criticism will prevent other possibilities, now being bruited about, from slipping back into an interpretive mode: a theoretical sophistication will prevent them from falling prey to un- examined assumptions. Briefly put, the lesson of contemporary European criticism, in its most vital moments, is this: that the New Criticism's dream of a fresh and unprejudiced approach to each autonomous artifact is not only impossible but fundamentally misconceived, even as an ideal. To read 11 Ibid., p. 1. 12 For further discussion, see Jonathan Culler, "Stanley Fish and the Righting of the Reader," Diacritics, 5:1 (1975). 253 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions COMPARATIVE LITERATURE a work as literature is inevitably and necessarily to read it in relation to other texts, past and present. And even if literary genres and the concept of literature itself be bracketed, to read is still to engage in an intertextual encounter. Reading is never a natural and innocent activity. The condition of the reader is to come after, to be constituted as reader by the repertoire of other texts, both literary and nonliterary, which are always already in place and waiting to be displaced by a critical reading. When the individual subject reads he becomes an intersub- jectivity: the track or furrow left by an experience of texts of all kinds, of a range of organizing discourses. As Roland Barthes writes: The 'I' which approaches the text is itself already a plurality of other texts, of infinite or, more precisely, lost codes (whose origins are lost) . . . Subjectivity is generally thought of as a plenitude with which I encumber the text, but in fact this faked plenitude is only the wash or wake of all the codes which make up the 'I,' so that finally my subjectivity has the generality of stereotypes.13 Given the intertextual nature of reading and readers, the literary work participates in a variety of systems, plays among a series of languages: the languages of various literary genres (systems of con- vention and expectation), the logics of story and teleologies of emplot- ment, the language of desire with its strategies of displacement and condensation, the various modes of discourse which make up a culture (the formal and informal ways of assigning meaning to things), and the various literary forms or languages which at a given moment can be codified as tradition. Situated among other texts which it cites, parodies, refuses, and transforms, the work is made possible or con- stituted by these various discursive systems or languages among which it plays. It is a tenuous intertextual construct, and the critical task is to disperse it, to move through it toward an understanding of the systems and semiotic processes which make it possible. Criticism which accords with this way of thinking can take many guises. In addition to the kind of formal and systematic poetics en- visaged by Frye and now being developed especially in France, one might cite Fredric Jameson's attempt, particularly in Marxism and Form, to work toward a dialectical criticism which would attempt not so much to resolve difficulties and offer interpretations as to take the resistance of a work as the object of attention and to define the nature of a work's opacity or otherness by moving outwards towards other examples of opacity and the historical ground of this type of opacity. "Thus our thought no longer takes official problems at face value but walks behind the screen to assess the very origin of the subject-object 3 S/Z (Paris, 1970), pp. 16-17. 254 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions PROSPECTS OF CRITICISM relationship in the first place."'4 The product or result of dialectical criticism is not an interpretation of the work itself but a broader his- torical account of why interpretation should be necessary and what the need for interpretations of various kinds signifies. Jameson's enterprise would lead, among other things, to a "dialectical rhetoric, in which the various mental operations are understood not absolutely, but as moments and figures, tropes, syntactical paradigms, of our relationship to the real itself, as, altering irrevocably in time, it nonetheless obeys a logic that like the logic of a language can never be fully distinguished from its object."15 A Marxist criticism conceived in this spirit would demonstrate that the relationship between a literary work and a social and historical reality is one not of reflected content but of a play of forms. Social reality is composed of paradigms of orga- nization, figures of our relationship to the real, and the interplay between a literary work and its historical ground lies in the way that the work's form and formal devices assimilate, transform, or supplement a culture's ways of producing meaning. Jameson's work may be seen as part of the larger, liberating project of reinventing literary history, which is perhaps most easily and perti- nently observed in the pages of New Literary History.16 Once one rejects the view that the critic's task is to interpret autonomous and atemporal monuments, one is led to produce a theory of literature as a conceptual space, and since even a minimal degree of self-consciousness would make one aware that the way in which one does this is necessarily historical (caught up in a historical process), one's project becomes that of literary history, broadly conceived. One's relationship to past works, and to present works also, is a historical relationship, and the concepts one uses to formulate and to analyze these relationships are themselves historical constructs. But history, especially in the realm of literature, is not something given: not a chronological series to which one can appeal, as if this would ground one's enterprise. History is what one must construct in order to be able to talk about literature and to give oneself a place to stand in relation to it. This is no doubt why, after several decades when literary history was abandoned to positivistic scholarship, it has once again become the principal terrain of creative and agile criticism. This observation is perhaps less a claim to be substantiated than a prediction about the sources of energy in American criticism in the coming years; but one might note, as an exemplary case, the way in 14 Marxism and Form (Princeton, 1971), p. 341. 15 Ibid., p. 374. 16 In addition to other works mentioned below, see Nez Directions in Literary Histctry, ed Ralph Cohen (Baltimore, 1974). 255 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions COMPARATIVE LITERATURE which the Yale "Formalists" have been succeeded, as the cutting edge of criticism, by those whom one might baptize the "Yale Deformalists": Geoffrey Hartman, Harold Bloom, Paul de Man. Drawing sus- tenance from a historically conceived romantic poetry rather than an ahistorical metaphysical or Augustan verse, invoking as the stimulus of repeated quest and failure the impossible calling of high romanticism, they treat literature and the reading of literature as a perpetual historical error and deformation. "History," writes Geoffrey Hartman, "is the wake of a mobile mind falling in and out of love with the things it detaches by its attachment."'7 This becomes the temporal scheme of Harold Bloom's The Anxiety of Influence: each poet must slay the father, must slay his predecessors through revisionary misreadings, so as to create a historical space in which poetry, as manifested anew in him, can take place. The hidden order of historical continuity is based on a negative and dialectical principal, of poetic misprision, which also figures the relationship between reader and text: in the historical econ- omy of literature the reader, like the new poet, is the latecomer who must misconstrue the text so as to leave a space in which he can write it himself; he must create an absence through his own reading so that he may, in his own name but also in the name of the Father, invoke and imagine what is absent. That the greatest insights result from this process of necessary misreading is the claim of another subtle theorist of deformation, Paul de Man, for whom interpretation is always in fact literary history: an error which assumes a historical categorization and conceals its own historical status.18 Criticism of this kind may not seem to make interpretation the enemy and to take arms against it, but that is only because it recognizes the suasive efficacy of subtler evasive strategies. Concerned with ways of opening and dispersing the text, of questioning the schema of interpre- tation, it has come happily to describe interpretation as error. If in- terpretation is always necessary error, then we shall become concerned with finding out why; and if we study the conditions of interpretive error we become involved in a historical and theoretical enterprise which probes those wider and more interesting questions about the ways of literature and of reading which have been repressed or displaced during the reign of interpretation. Brasenose College, Oxford University 17 "History-Writing as Answerable Style," in New Directions in Literary History, p. 100. See also his Beyond Formalism (New Haven, 1970). 8 Blindness and Insight (New York, 1971), p. 165. 256 This content downloaded from 140.233.2.215 on Mon, 19 Aug 2013 17:03:07 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions