A.B.cook - The Metaphysical Basis of Plato's Ethics, 1895
A.B.cook - The Metaphysical Basis of Plato's Ethics, 1895
A.B.cook - The Metaphysical Basis of Plato's Ethics, 1895
TORONTO, ONTARIO
THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
PLATO S ETHICS
THE
METAPHYSICAL BASIS
OF
PLATO S ETHICS
BY
MILTON
V
B
392
CAMBRIDGE
ALEXANDRA STREET
CONTENTS
PAGE
PREFACE . ix
i. The Parmenides I
3. Aristotle s Psychology . . . . .
.23
PART II. HIGHER AND LOWER MENTALITY . .
54
i.
Purpose and Necessity 55
3. Theology 85
morality.
Plato conceived the universe to be a VOTYTOV ,wov
f<y
j, sa y that of Man. Man being one of the sub
ordinate fwa expresses one aspect, viz. the humanity,
of the supreme %wov. He is endowed with four
mentioned.
esoteric meaning,
space."
activity reality,"
I. The Parmenides.
In Farm. 132 B the Platonic Sokrates, wishing
seq.
to. secure the of the Idea against the criticism
unity
THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
(i)
That a voi^a must have a content, an ov n ;
previously refuted.
(ii)
That if on the one hand each Idea is a voi^a,
and on the other hand particulars are related to Ideas
by participation
then particulars as aggre
(/Ae 0efi<?),
1
I understand vo-fj/mara ovra, avorjra elvai (Parm. 132 c) as spoken
of particulars ; for, if a thing e/c vori^o- ruv eVrtV, it is to borrow a
phrase of Aristotle s ffvvOea-is ris i)5tj vorjfjLaTwv tio-irep ev t>vr<av,
and
may justly be described as Another logically correct
itself a v6rj/j.a.
are some Ideal j/oTj/uara which are not contained in minds." But this
seems to me inadmissible on two grammatical grounds (i) It involves :
juei/ . . .
vof]T(f Kal /j.ovoei5e? Kal o.Sia\vrcf . . . T 8e . . .
avo^Tcp KCL\
To
put the dilemma in other words. If we choose
the horn (a), we assume that voijfj,ara (i.e.
first
par
ticulars, regarded as aggregates of Ideas) must in
J
is shown
difficulty by Sokrates answer A\\ ovSe
rovroj (frdvai, e^a \6yov. Again, it is noteworthy that
in Parmenides first retort the same postulate was
oiicria Kal vovs avSr^ros ical \6yos and not always then
Uppriros), (e.g.
[Alex.] in Arist. Met. ed. Hayduck p. 670, 27 rfc yhp vof\T\]v Kal Be iav
iro\\ol /A^ flvai a.i/oT)Tcas aire<f>-f>vavTo).
In view of these objections I
have followed a simpler syntax, and given to av6tiros a
meaning that
"
Stephanus calls
30 B, where, as in Gorg. 514 c, av6rjros is opposed to vovv
THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
2
e.g. Horn. Od. 215, Hes. Op. 129, Theog. 656, Empedocl. ed.
Karsten vv. 313, 316, 317.
OF PLATO S ETHICS.
thinking ;
it may also be fair to presume that B or
.Z? s mind has a similar faculty for thought; but is it
3
The English language tolerates the following sen
elasticity of the
tence :
passing thought be the directly verifiable existent,
"
If the
which no school has hitherto doubted it to be, then that thought is itself
the thinker, and psychology need not look beyond" (W. James, The
thought of."
still, We may however, raise the ques
tionwhether voTjpa means (a) the object thought of,
as it is
independently of the thinking subject, or
(b) the object thought of, as represented by the
be" is appre-
5
Tao>a Siavoias \OJIKOV faov a definition elsewhere
used to elucidate the Stoic term \efcr6v, which also
was the mental representation of TO d^^aivo^vov.
This distinction between (a) TO voovpevov and (b) TO
voovpevov y voovpevov would be important enough if
we were dealing with objects sensibly perceived. But
in the case of the Platonic Ideas it does not trouble
us, because as Proklos, ibid. 140, puts it o ^Wpcm;?
Q
v vor)iLacn Tidlv ovcn&crdai ras t Sea? v7re\a/3v. The
Idea and Mind s thought of the Idea are one. The
former has no existence apart from the latter. We
have mounted to a where the word ^avraa-^a^
level
5
Cp. Alex, de anini. ed. Bruns p. 85, 20 tyylvvrtu 5e TJ
efts T<
vif r^v apxV faro. airb TTJS irepl ra ot
/j.(Ta.&a<Tti>
6 *V
Cp. Alex, in Arist. Met. ed. Hayduck p. 92, 19, 22,
t Se ats T\ inr6<na.<Tis and rb fivai OLVTUV cV T$ voeiffQai.
THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
deliberately admitted :
7
Note that, when Sokrates answers in the affirmative the question,
Oi>x
fv6s Tii/os, & 7rl iraviv ^/celVo rb v6r)/j.a tirbv voe?, /j.iav Tiva oixroiv
8
In Phaedrus 247 C, D, soul is described as an ovrws . . ov<ria .
fj.6vtf 6tar^ v$. Of this intelligible entity it is said Ka6opa pey avr^v :
irp6cre<rTiv
. . . oAAo r^v eV T$ 6 Iffnv ttv tivrus firio-T^fjL rjv olffav Kal
r&\\a wo-avTws TO. ovra ovrtas Qfa<ra.^4vt] K.T.A.. Mutatis mutandis this
passage is applicable to the Idea as it is portrayed in the Parmenides.
io THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
The 9
general sense of the last clause is can think "
We
only of what exists and the argument
;
shows
"
that,
if we can think of nothing but TO 6V, TO fj,rj ov will be
TrecfraTiafjLei
evpijaeis TO voelv.
9
Literally, the words may be rendered "The same thing exists
seq. Plato puts into the mouth of the Eleate the two
10
It matters little whether we follow Simplicius (in Phys. A, ed.
object,"
or adopt Mr. Burnet s version (Early Gr. Philos. p. 186) : "
It
is the same
thing that can be thought and for the sake of which the
thought exists." In the former case we identify the subject with the
object ofv6i]ffis, in the the latter the object with the subject. Whichever
rendering we choose, the argument will be the same, viz. x = =
z, and_y z,
therefore x =y.
11
I do not mean
to imply that Parmenides himself expressly drew
this inference, or spoke of rb %v as a vovs. We have no better authority
for such an assertion than Plotinus Enn. v. i. 8, and Simplicius in Phys.
A. ed. Diels p. 143, i8ff. Moreover, there is the negative evidence
of Plato, who, in Soph. 244 B, c, states that the Eleatics called their
principle by the two names ev and &v, but makes no mention of vovs
as a recognised appellation. My point is merely that the historical
Parmenides identification of voov^evov and voovv paved the way for the
Platonic Parmenides postulate of vo-fiftara voovvra.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 13
rovca . . .
<70(f)la
teal vovs \eyofj,evrj SiKaiorar av.
Laws 897 C rj gvfjiTrao-a ovpavov 6809 apa Kal (f>opa
7repi<f)opa
Kal \o^La-^iol^ Ofjioiav <f>v(Ti,
Ibid. A. 9. 1075 a
ov% erepov ovv
3 6Wo<? rov voov-
jjLevov
/cal rov vov, ova /JLTJ vXrjv e^et, TO avro-
earau KOI f) voxels TO) voovpevu) /juia.
Porph. /
Categ. ed. Busse p. 91, 14 Xe7a>
6Vt
ev <$9
elvai TO irdv, Kal TOVTWV TKjjLrjpia
/caXto<? re /cal ev.
12
Cp. Theaet. 183 E riop^evi Sr/y 5e p.oi Qaiverai, rb TOV
al5o"i6sre /j.01 ?yat o/ta Seivds re ... KOI pot ft ados <f>dvr)
n
ytvvcuov, Soph. 237 A rbv TOV iraTpbs Hapnevtiov \6yov
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 17
(i)
As the subject and object of vorja-^ it is
(ii)
As the subject and object of yvwcns it
la
Arist. Topica Z. IO. 148 a 2O a-rraOf is yap Kal aitivriTOi $oicov<nv at
namely :
(ii)
with Kivrja-is, in which case we have far; and
\eyeiv.
own doctrine :
Psych. A. 4. 14. 408 b 29 6 8e vovs fooos Qei6rep6v Kal n
O7ro06s f<rnv, ibid. F. 5. i. 430 a 17 Kal OVTOS 6 vovs (the vovs iroiyTiKts)
Xopio-rbs Kal afj.iy^s Kal airad-f)s, rrj ovffia &v evepyeia, Met. A. 7. 1073 a
1 1 which predicates airaOes Kal ava\\oiwrov of the ovffia . . . aiSios Kal
aKlvrjTos Kal Kexpto7i"? T^"
ala-Bijruv. Hermes (quoted by Stob.
Ed. I. Ixi. i, ed. Wachsmuth i.
p. 275, 17) has 6 vovs a-rraO-fis.
14
This explains why the definition of ovrus $>v
given in Soph. 247 E,
248 c was regarded as provisional and not final. Whatever possesses
20 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
Phileb. 30 D OVK.OVV eV . . .
rfj TOV Jto? e/aet? </>
ecrOcu $t>a
TTJV rr}<?
alrias
the
qua subject and object of yvuxris. But qua subject and object of v6r](rts
this same ova-la was admitted to be ccTroflfc. Consequently, unless
Svvafjus can be taken to denote the power of passing from the first
or
static into the second or kinetic condition, we must substitute the
15
For Plato s conviction that vovs must be attached to tyvx^ see the
following passages :Phileb. 300 /J.TIV Kal vovs avev ^VXTJS OVK &v
(ro<pia
7TOT6 yfvo urdrjv, Farm. 132 B /u^ TUV ci Swi/ fKa<rrov 77 TOVTWV voT]/j.a, Kal
16
See Soph. 249 B uyuau ei 6 ovv, & eo/Trjre, aKiv^rwv T ovruv
vovv wSfvl ire pi wo eris flvai ^Sa/jiov, the counterpart of 249 C Tt 5 ;
&vtv rovrtDV (sc. rov Kara ravra K.T.A.) vovv xaQopas ovra ^ yev6/j.fvov
if Kal btrovovv ;
24 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
Trpwrovpyol Kivr](7^i^
%vy<yvels f) ra? Sevrep-
ovpyovs av TrapdXafjiftdvovcrai Kivr)Gi<$
ayovo-i, irdvra et? av^cnv Kal <j>6iaiv
fcal
Kal <rvy/cpi(Tiv.
several parts.
Aristotle s thesis is (Psych. A. 2. 6. 404^ 8) that
those thinkers, who find the main characteristic of
in TO yivcoo-Keiv Kal TO al<r9dve<r6ai, identify
witn their dp^ or ap^at. Empedokles, for
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 25
(i)
In the Timaeus Plato makes both 77 ^nJ\r] and
TCL TTpdyfjiara out of the same elements (sc. ravrbv and
Sofa, cucr0rj<n<i),
which correlate with four eiSrj TOW
<aov
e| avrys TT}S TOV tvbs iSeas Kal TOV irpuTov p-^Kovs Kal irXaTovs Kal
fidQovs, TO. 5 a\\a op,oioTp6Tr<as.
ert 8e Kal a\\ws, vovv n\v TO 4V,
/jLfV v$, TO. 8 ^7r/(TT7)fi77, TO. Sc 86i;T), TO. 8 alo~0-f)fffi ftSr; 8 of api6fj.ol
OVTOl T&V
26 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
(b) ra TT
pay par a (i.e. things in general, the object
of knowledge) are formed IK. rwv dp^Mv.
18
Cp. Simplic. in Arisl. Psych, ed. Hayduck p. 29, II
roivvv (is TOS a.px-s ra re yixaara TTOJ/TO, rovrfffri TO 6Vro, /cai ras
TOVTUV 8vvd.iJ.fiS
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 27
dpxn v &>?
(rroi^elov KalTovdpiO^oveKTOV 1/69.
19
Stob. Ed. i. x. i6b, ed. Wachsmuth i.
p. 128, 14 has ol ^v olv
rjyovvrai
28 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
20
Foreshadowed in dialogues earlier than the Timaeus, e.g. Soph.
249 B TO Kara ravra /cal U<TO.VTWS /cal irepi rb avr6 K.r.K. Farm. 1580
TV fTfpav Qixriv TOV effiovs (= Tim. 35 A TV Qarepov fyvffiv).
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 31
21
I fail to see any such justification for the term as Mr. Wallace
(ed. Arist. Psych, p. 205) finds in Tim. 308 ovrtas ovv 5^ Kara \6yov
SeT \eyeiv r6v5f rbv K6<r/J.ov oaov ^fj^v^ov evvovv re rrj
Sta TOV Qeov yeveffdai trpovoiav. The cosmos can only be
described as a uov in so far as its intelligibility implies the evolution
of eTrto-T^Tci, So^acrrd, ajVflTjra and this is just what Simplicius would
exclude ;
for these he finds in T& &\\a.
32 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
satis olent."
22
Themistius explanation is T& ^tv olv avro&ov, row cert rbv
KOfffJLOV TOV VOTIT^V, ^K TU>V
TTp(t>TUV
tlTo lOW apX&V, TO. M /uLfpOUS fK
TUV vQei/jifvui &ffirep yap rck a(V0i}rck *x ei VP^ &\\T)\a. OUTW xal ras
IS fas avrwv irpbs oAA^jAas *x flv ( e d. Spengel p. 21).
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 33
Ita et Plato,
similibus cognoscerentur, eosdem numeros
avTo^ooov fecit, eosdem menti indidit. Sic
23 ed. 1877, P- l8 7-
Arist. deanima,
24 88.
Ibid. p. 1
34 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
"
universal Subject :
avTo nev TO ffiov e f ai/r?}<? T?}? TOV ^05 ZSea? KOI TOV
23
That is, the supreme Nous in its passage into cosmic existence, as
opposed to that cosmic existence which originates from the evolution of
the supreme NoOs.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 35
the
"
26
Plato, according to Mr. Archer-Hind s rendering, uses auri rb
&ov of the individual animal in Tim. 89 B : but the passage, as we
shall see, may be taken differently.
36 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
as the absolute
"
/zepou? et Set wa
of Tim. 30 C), and ra a\\a as tlie "
TI
ra a\\a rra palely para, olov TO avroicaXov, TO avrodv-
^pt7T09, Kal eVt TWV \onra)v o/^o/co?)
and strongly
supported by the variant readings 8 aXXa? T<?
lowing :
ev ical Kara ye
third also.
But before passing to the last consideration we
must enquire further concerning the nature of the
four stages that have hitherto been mentioned without
comment. Aristotle alludes to them again in Met. M.
2. 1077*2 24 e-ri al 76i>e<76t? Trpwrov JJLW jap
&r)\ovcrw.
eVt fjLrjKos yiyverai, etra 7rl
TrXarov, re\vraiov 8 et?
Laws 894 A
rj
Trdvrcov ryeveaw, fjViK av ri 7ra#o? 77 ;
29
[Alexander] in Arist. Met. M. 2. 1077^ 14 ed. Hayduck p. 731,
things ;
for on the one hand the Numbers were
known as the absolute Ideas and first principles,
and they are constructed out of their elements (sc.
1.2.3.4.) while on the other hand things are appre
;
class
"
or "
group
"
is supported
by the fact that the article, prefixed to the same word
when used above in its technical sense (ra et 8?; aura),
is here absent. The argument, I take it, may be set
out as follows :
31
Simplic. in Arist. Psych, ed. Hayduck p. 29, 12 Hijpovir
5e rd re
&vra ov Kara TrActros, a\\a Kara )8a0os, fts re ra vorjra /cat eTriar^ra Kal
So|ao-To Kal alvQyra, Kal 6/jLoius ras yvaxreis fis vovv Kal eirKrr^/j. rjv Kal
at<rQt](nv.
44 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
The
recognition of the planes of consciousness
symbolised by these numbers I. 2. 3. 4. throws light
where light is much needed upon the use of the
technical term Be/cds. Aristotle more than once affirms
that certain Idealists continued their Ideal Numbers
Ibid. M. 8. 1
084*? 12 el Be
7ro(7ov
; TOVTO yap Bel \eyecr0ai, ov fiovov cm,
d\\a KOI BIOTI. u\\a IJLTJV el fjue^pi rijs Be/cdBo?
6 dpiOfJios,
wcTTrep rives (f)acrii>, irpwrov /j,ev ra)(v
ra eiBrj olov el GCTTLV r) rpias avrodv-
,
r/9 carat, dpiO^o^ avrolrrrros ; avrb yap
Kacrros diQos ^ei Be/cdBos.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 45
1*>V)
6(7TL 7T\eloV, Yj
TO, flVplCL.
apiO/j.ol fjitv otiv 8icb rovro SeKaSiKol 8e 5tck TIJV r\fi6r-rira T<av
these four stages produce the decad, which the Pythagoreans named
Tlavrf\eia (Stob. Ed. I. ed. Wachsmuth i.
p. 22, 5).
32
For the ensuing description cp. Simplic. in Arist. Psych, ed.
Hayduck p. 29, 2 0^70^ 5e els ras etSrjrt/cas apxas Kal ras tyvxixas
48 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
rraffas yyucreis, T^V n\v voepav &s naff evuxriv a/AepHTTov orvvaipov/j.fvr)v
TOV airfov ets Tb aiTiaTbv Trpoayo/JLevrjv, &s 5e KOI 5ia Tb airwaves Kal del
8ja T&V avTcov 68evov ets T^V SvdSa, T^V 5e 86av fls r))V rpidSa Sia rb T^JV
^vya/jLtv avrijs yur/ eVi rb avrb aet, aAAa Tore fiej/ M rb d\7j0es Tore 5e
cirl rb tyevSos K\iveiv, fls Se rrjv rcrpaSa r}]V ouaQ^aiv 5td rb (rcafJ-dTuv
flva.1 avTik-rjirriK^v. Themist. in Arist. Psych, ed. Spengel p. 21, 17
e^e/i e TTJS TOV cvbs tSe as avr-fjv (sc. r^v tyvxyv) 8t/>(^OVTO,
5e eVc rys vpuTijs Svdtios
fTTi<rri]fji-riv
tubs yap ev Kal TJ a<p ^
yap TWV irpordcrfcav fTrl rb <rv/j.Trepaff/J.a, rfyv 8J|ov 5e e /c
airb
T^S irpurtfjs rpidSos, ttffos ^v Kal TOV eVnre Sou api6fj.6s TTJS yap 8^775 IjSt]
Kal rb oA7j0es Kal rb i^evSos IK rwv irpordaewv, atffOrjffiv 5e aTrb rrjs
We
are now in a position to combine the results of
all three clauses and to indicate the advance made
by
the passage as a whole.
From the critique of the Platonic Parmenides,
fittingly supplemented by that of the Eleatic stranger,
33
M. 2. 1077 a 29, Psych. A. 4. 17. 409 a 5. It is,
Met.
however,
to be observed that in 407 a
29 Aristotle has himself been guilty of much
the same conception as that which he ridicules: al 5
Kal airoSfi^eis
OLTT
apx^s, Kal fgoiKrl irus re\os, T^tv <rv\\oyKT(jLbv t) rb o-vfjurepa(Tfj.a- et 5f
fj.fl TTfpaTovvTai, a\\ OVK avaKci/jnrTovfri ye ird.\iv ^TT apx f}
4
50 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
NoO? ;
in the case of the series of ovcriai., vorjais was
otiv Uvday6peioi Kal Tl\dTwv ovffiav avr-fjv (sc. r^v tyvxyv) <t>d<riv.
-PI
I? I
152
o
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 53
and ({3)
the mutable becoming of the same in space of
one, two, and three dimensions. Its objects of cogni
36
Proklos in Tim. 3 19 A.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 55
afresh the
to secure due perspective by emphasising
shall, therefore,
in the
salient points of view. I
present chapter
endeavour to illustrate from the
the contrast thus formulated
Platonic dialogues
and of Mind,
between the subjective aspects
objective
successive illustration, while
in the hope that each
in the use of
exhibiting Plato s technical consistency
the
non-technical terms, may bring into clearer light
moral significance of his design.
Sta vov
Timaeus 47 E discriminates (a) ra
Hiovpwt** from W
dvdvtcr)* wvfava,
and^
declares that the universe is the combined product
CSe rov Koa^ov ytveaK
of both :
pepiwtvri 7P V
vov o-vardaetoS eyevvrjOr].
ef avdyrcris re teal
we learnt from
Now (a) the creations of vow, as
of subordinate
the Parmenides, comprise a series
in a single
Minds called the Ideas, which are unified
as their basis and ground
supreme Mind conceived
& 1
are the
work. Again, (b) rd dvdyic^ y^vo^va
the necessary passage of
results brought about by
of -being" into
the said Minds from the higher mode
this lapse, this
lower mode of becoming" and
"
the ;
56 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
objective
"
37
Mr. Archer-Hind seems to me ill-advised in stating (ed. Tim.
p. 167 n.) that "Plato calls avdyKij the KKa.vuy.evT) alria, because,
though working strictly in obedience to a certain law, it is for the most
part as inscrutable to us as if it acted from
arbitrary caprice." The
term surely denotes nothing more than deviation.,
TT\av<a^.fv^ and is the
equivalent of 6a.Tpov as opposed to Ta.vr6v.
38
For &ov\rj<Tis ) ( avayKT] cp. Crat. 420 D where rb Kara TV
&ov\i]<Ttv yiyvo^evov is
opposed to rb avayKaTov Kal avrirvirov, irapa
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 57
TO irav roSe
(6 fwtora?) irdv-ra on, ^aKicrra
6{3ov\r)0r) TrapaTrXrjcria eavra>.
TCIVTTJV
t
ea>? KCLI Koo-fjiov
fjid\ta-r av rt? dp%f)
1
(29 E 3 A).
59
Laws 8l8 A foiKfv 6 rbv debit irpurov Trapoifj.ia(ra.p.fvos (cp. ibid.
741 A, Protag. 345 D) els ravra airo/3\f\l/as flirew ws ovSe 6ebs avdyKrj /j.-f)
wore pax&ptvos, ovai dftai ye, oT/iOi, rwv avayKtav eiffiv, K.T.\.
(f>avp
a-vfJifieTpa
elvai. Tore yap ovre TOVTWV ocrov f^rj
H3 A).
from
(/3)
ev(not ev ov, but ev conceived apart
is an undivided unity. The possession of owria,
ovaia)
however, forces ei; into combination with TO eVepoi/,
are not ev. On the other hand ra\\a f^ere^et, Try rov
e^o? in virtue of possessing fjiopia, which are /jiopia rov
o\ov re /cal
40
Heindorf, Bekker, Schleiermacher, and the Zurich edd. wrongly
bracket the word ov : it is just this possession of which renders ov<ria
(/3)
Both the oXov and each popiov may be said
IJLere^eiv TOV ez/6?, and therefore to be erepa rov evos.
And 77 erepa <f>vais
TOV fl Sou? will ever be aireipov
Tr\r)9ei. (I57E 1580).
(7) Lastly, ra a\\a rov e^o?, when combined with
TO eV, give rise to a third class of existences, viz. ra
41
The Journal of Philology, xi, 318.
62 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
43
Oeia fiovXrjais, and is rightly opposed to the sub
42
Stob. Ed. I. xii. I a, ed. Wachsmuth i.
p. 134, Qff.
43
Unless, indeed, we hold that Plato like Aristotle recognised a
hypothetical avdyK-rj. The latter author sometimes (e.g. Psych. B. 8. 10.
420 b 19 seq.) distinguishes avayKaiov from eVe/ca rov c5, but elsewhere
(e.g. de part. an. A. I. 642 a 32 TJ 8 avayKi] brl tnifudvtt 6n el /xe</
^Kftvo fffrat rb ov eVe/co. ravra avdyKT) etrrlv %x*u , ore 8e /c.r.A.) admits
a necessity of a conditional or hypothetical sort. In the second sense
Plato s Ideal series would be itself avayicaiov.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 63
14
Frag. Trag. adesp. 421 N. cp. Eur. Alk. 965
xpfiffffov ouSej/ avdyKas
-nlpov.
64 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
r)
8e 6e\7](7i^ OVK dXoyos rjv, ov&e TOV etV?), ovB &>?
45 The
correspondence in point of diction with Cratylus 403 c is
remarkable: Aeer^ubs (acp orcfovf, Sxrre jj.4vsiv dirovovv, TrSrepos
, OLvdyKt] f) eiridv/nia; HoAu Siatpepei,
46
Enn. vi. viii. 18.
47
Cp. Tim. 32 C &\VTOV i/iro rov &\\ov irX^v inrb TOV vv8r]<rai>Tos
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 65
prerequisite vorjaw.
Turning next from ra &a vov SeS^toupv^/oteW to
TO, St dvdy/cTjs ^v^vo^va (Tim. 47 E), we find that
Plato regards the degradation whereby Mind lapses
from the mode of Identity into that of Diversity as
a necessary transition, taking place perforce. The
Creator in Tim. 35 A combines the psychic ingre
dients rrjv Qarepov (frixnv Sva-fjiiKTOV ovaav et? ravrov
5
66 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
\avv6/j,evov K.T.\.
Ibid. 68 B &v (Jbrjre TIVCL dvdyKrjv pyre TOV elfcora
\6<yov
K.T.\.
OGTOVV /c.r.\.
K.T.\.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 67
6da v
rdgis, dvdyicr) Trpovoia
avTo
by adhering strictly to the statement that every
&ov unites in itself ravrbv the mode of pure thought
with ddrepov the mode of knowledge, opinion, sensa
tion. It seems, however, desirable to justify this
the matter somewhat more
procedure by probing
not unnatural tendency
deeply, in view of a certain
to confuse the issues of this terminology with the
ev iro\\d.
implications of the antithesis
KCL\
49
Stob. Ed. I. xlL I. ed. Wachsmuth i.
p. 277, 15.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 69
KOL vvv.
Our business then is not with the broad logical sense
of these words, but rather with their narrower meta
50
Vid. e.g. Tim. 520.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 71
Tim. 5 2 A 6(j,o\o<yr}reov
ev fjuev elvai rb Kara ravra
>,
dyevrjrov Kal dvwXeOpoVj ovre et? eavrb
aXXo a\\oOev ovre avrb et? aXXo
TTOL iov, doparov Be Kal a XXcu? dvala-Qrjrov, rovro
(Tim. 48 E).
49 A).
In short, the terms ravrbv and Odrepov in their
discriminate
primary ontological significance serve to
the dvrio-roi xa of Tim. 27 D 29 D :
7 e v e a- 9 the province of
ovo-ia, the province of
1
7T/0-Tt9. 29 C.
290.
TO 6i>
aet, <yeve<riv
Be ov/c TO yiyvojAevov fiev del, bv Be
ovBeirore (27 D)
(27 D)
TO Kara ravra e^pv (28 A) TO 76701/69 (28 B)
(29 A)
TO dtSiov (29 A) TO 7670^69 (29 A)
72 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
Be ovSeTrore ov
(28 A)
TO \6<yft>
Ka acr-
e?(29B) I
Oarepov <f>vais
is clear from its employment in
Arist. Met. B. 4. 1001 & 23, N. I. 1087 4ff.,
1088 # 15, 2. 1088 32, 1089 6ff., 5. 1092 a
29)-
e ecrTdvai, JJLTJ
ecrro? Be KiveiaOat, ; OUTW?.
51
These passages probably refer to Plato notwithstanding Philop.
in Arist. Phys. ed. Vitelli p. 352, 20 c\eyov 8e ot TIv8ay6pioi r^v
/cat avi(r6T7)ra Kal rb fiv. ^
52
Arist. Psych. P. io. 8. 433 b 24 is parallel only in appearance.
74 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
14 77
8 erepa fjuolpa TT}? evavriwaeco^
1091 b 25 10920 5.
ora (f>V(7i,
TroXXou? elvau ira\iv TO 1/5 e/^e /cal
(j3)
the one particular with its many parts :
Parrn. 1
29 C el 8 e/z-e ev rt? a7roSe/a ovra teal
,
rl Oav/jLacrTov, \eywv, brav fjuev fiovXrjTai,
a a7ro<f)ati>iV)
ft)? erepa fiev ra eVl Sefta
fiov <TTLV,
erepa Se ra eV api<rrepd
K.T.\.
^>a^
TO ev firj
ev aXXa TroXXa fjiopia.
/JLCU (cp. 1290 ou T& e?/ Tro\\a ov5f TO TToAAo eV), where e^ and iro\\a
represent ///^ /^/j ^/" Unity and Multiplicity.
76 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
54
In point of fact I cannot find a satisfactory example of
particulars, nor even of ec
=
the supreme Idea, in the earlier dialogues.
The nearest approach to the former seems to be Rep. 445 C \v pfv eJvai
elSos TTJS operas, fadpa 5e rrjs Kaic ias. The latter is of course deducible
from the use of the singular number.
78 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
55
32) and Z. 1 6. 1040$ 29,
are directed against certain Idealists probably
followers of Xenokrates o vc06p6s bQ who despite the
particulars
988 # 2, etc.) may be due to the same inaccuracy
which caused the retention of the term ^e0ei? in the
place of the more exact /u/^o-t? (Met. A. 6. 987 b 10,
M. 4. 1079 # 2 5> Phys. A. 2. 209 b 35).
On the other hand Aristotle commonly identifies
the Platonic aireipov with the material cause, and
55
The list in the Index Arist. 618 a 25 is incomplete.
56
Diog. Laert. iv. 2. 6.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 79
and are referring to the fact that the Ideas are a series
M. 7. 1081^ 35 ff.)
8o THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
ryevrj&ecrdov.
In the second place the erepoTrjs of TO ev is not to
f<wa.
In drawing
a comparison between the in
telligible and sensible universe he declares that the
partial Animals embraced by the entire Animal
answer to the particular specimens contained in a
visible cosmos : Tim. 30 C ra yap Brj VOTJTO, wa Trdvra
6
82 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
59
To the same effect Arius Didymus in Stob. Ed. I. xii. 2a. ed.
Wachsmuth i.
p. 136, 10.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 83
GO
^efc
TO deov ie elvai TOP 7rL/jL6\ovfjL6vov
KOI rjfjLas etceivov KTijfjiara elvai.
The moral
bearings of this question call for further
consideration for the present I proceed, noting merely
:
in lieu "soul
60
Cp. Phaedr. 246 E Zeus HiaKoffptav irdvra ical
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 85
III. Theology.
61
Plato and The Older Academy, p. 494.
86 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
of Tim. 37 c
ft)? 8e Kivrjdev avrb Kal {fav evolve TWV ai&lcov
76701/0? aya\iJ>a
o yevvrfaas
63
Stob. Ed. I. x. i6a ed. Wachsmuth i.
p. 127, 20. Ed. I. i. 29
rb p.ova$iK6v, rb
(Aetios) ibid. p. 37, 4 U\drwv Se rb Hv, rb /toi/o</)ues,
forces &v, Ta.yaQ6v. Udvra tie TO, rotavra ruv ovofjuirtav els rbv vovv
<nreu5t. Nous olv 6 eedr. Cp. Ed. I. vi. la (Menander) ibid. p. 83,
64
irpura. SiaKCKpifjieva rrjs afjLfpiffTQv fvctxrews, as Simplicius in Arist.
Psych, ed. Hayduck p. 28, 22 calls them.
65
Ed. Ttmaeusp. nSn.
66
Cp. Polit. 272 E of /corei rovs roirovs crvvdpxovres r$
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 89
eiroi^ae.
542 a
67
Tim. 3 1 A, cp. Bonitz Ind. Arist. p. 8.
68 &v 5e ov.
Cp. Farm. 1640 07*01 eowrat, cTs CKOO-TOS <pa.iv6nevos,
and in Tim. 68 E
ravra Br]...6 TOV Ka\\i(TTov re /cal apiarov
o? ev rot? <yi<yvo/jU6vots
r
jrape\diJi(3aveV) fjvifca TOV
;
implies unique
that the object is perceived not in its shifting phase of
tcivrja-i? but in its permanent condition of o-rdat^ that
is, not as a particular but as an Idea. Hence in every
case particularity connotes numerical indefinity. The
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 91
69
Compare Cicero s description of Xenokrates theology: "Decs
enim octo esse dicit ; quinque eos qui in stellis vagis nominantur, unum
qui ex omnibus sideribus quae infixa caelo sunt ex dispersis quasi membris
simplex sitputandus Deus, septimumsolem adiungit, octavamque lunam."
70
Cp. the fragment from Porphyry irepl a.ya.\na.T<av cited by Stob.
Ed. I. 25 ed. Wachsmuth i. p. 31, 8
i. Zevs ovv 6 iras /c<fo>tos, faov IK
(t>(i>v Kal debs CK dfuv. Zevs Se Kal <
<5 Qe6s > ,
Ka6b vovs a<p
ov
, tin $
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 93
71
Cp. Laws 950 D T^\iov...Kal rovs &\\ovs fleous, 828 C ruv
8<rovs o5 Ocovs ovpaviovs tirovonaffreov, Crat. 397 C Qatvovrai fj.oi ol
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 95
irpuroi ra>v
o.vty&K<av
rav ircpl T^V E\\dSa rovrovs i*6vovs robs Ocovs
, ov<rirfp
vvv iro\\ol
affrpa Kal
96 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
72
produced: et Sore? 8e avr6...deo^...^vve(7Trj(7 . In
much the same way o oyfjLiovpyb? of Tim. 28 A, 29 A,
etc. is pluralised into ol Bq/juavpyol of 75 B, 6 ^vviaras of
29 E into ol fucr<JT7;cra^T69 of /I D.
73
d6dvaroi pev ov/c ecrre ouS aXvroi TO TrdfjLirav, ov
TL i*,ev Sr) \v0ijo-e00e ye ovSe rev^eade Oavdrov
72 The converse
change from singular to plural occurs in Farm.
1340 QVKOVV ei irapa r$ 6e$ avrt) e<rrlv
rj aKpifieffTdrr) eiriffTrnj.r], ovr
&v 77 SeffiroTeia f) ^Ksiixav VJ/JLWV irore kv Seo TrJo e/ej , OUT &v rj firiffT^/jLT)
*X OV T To-VTa ev O.VT$ dvtjTa aQa.va.rd re, and in Tim. 92 C Qvt]Ta, yap /col
"
7*
eTrio-Kevaarrjv rrapa rov Srj/j,iovpyov.
These passages confirm us in the belief that the
existence of the starry gods as a plurality is
merely
subjective and phenomenal.
In brief, the Bed 6e&v are related to the
supreme
0eo9 as particulars to their corresponding Idea. Aetios
account of that relation in Eel. I. xii. i a ed. Wachs-
muth i.
p. 134, 9
loea early ovcria a(ra)jj,aro<*
. . .
rrarpos e7re%ov(7a
TO?? aiV0?7Tot? Tfifyv
is
apparently founded on, and certainly justified by,
Tim. SOD where the Idea is compared to a rrarrjp,
the particular to an eicyovov. Now in 42 E the Oeol
flew with reference to the supreme #eo? are called ol
TratSe? rov rrarpo^. Similarly in 37 C the latter is
75
6 yevvrjo-as Trarrfp, and in 69 C the former are ra
7Q
eavrov <yevvr)fjiara.
This coincidence of nomenclature,
by establishing the proportion As particulars their :
75
Cp. Polit. 273 B.
70
Soph. 266 B has 0eoD yew-fi/taTa of particular men etc.
77
Chalcidius in Tim. 41 A ed. Wrobel p. 200 well remarks: "Illi
7
98 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
says :
"
attendant passions :
78
It may be remarked that the office which Rep. 41 5 A (a\\ 6 8ebs
TrAaTTOJf, ftffoi /J.v V/J.UV iKavol ^pxetr, xp va"bv eV rf) yevecrei vve/j.i}-ev,
cp. Arist. Pol. B. 5. 1264 12 6 irapa rov 6eov xp v <*6s) assigns to the
in the Timaeus assigned to the 6eol Qeuv.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 99
Trepl
ra aca^ara <yiy vo^evrj pepicrTr) (Tim. 35 A),
signalised.
On the one hand, it must be observed that this
81
Cp. Tim. 6QC TOJJ/ fjifv Be i<av avrbs yiyvercu
102 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
ep ycov.
Soph. 265 C &5a orj TTavra dvrira real
d\\ov TWOS r)
6 eov SrjfjLiovpyovvTos
83
Plato and The Older Academy p. 390, n. 8.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 103
OVK dp 1
83
Met. A. 6. 987 b 10.
io4 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
84
Compare the use of tai<pvris
in Symp. 2IOE
rt Oav/jLaarbv r\\v tyvaiv na\6v K.T.A., Gorg. 523 E avrfj rfj
r^v xJ/vxV 9*povrra f^al^vris a.TroQa.v6vTos e/coo-rou. The former passage
conceives the individual mind confronting that which is avrb naff avrb
jucfl O.VTOV /j.ovoei5es del
the latter represents the disembodied soul of
ftv,
ing diagram :
eltccov
TrapdSeiyfjLa
Oed? Oeoi 0cu!v
85
With the Platonic derivation from Sa-fi/J-uv in Crat. 398 B L. and S.
compare Archil. 3, 4 TCIUTTJS yap Kfivoi 8ai/j.ovcs flffl fj-dx^s.
io6 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
of individuals.
If it be asked In what relation does this hierarchy
stand to the evil World-soul of the Laws ? I should
reply that, since vow is del 0eo? (Laws 897 B), Necessity
or the force which produces the degeneration of
86
Tim. 41 c, 69 D, 720.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 107
Mind,
Laws 897 B ^rv^rj...dvoia vyyevo{jiei>r}
TrdvTO, av
rdvavrta TOVTOL^ aTrepyd^erat,.
Theaet, I/6E Trapa^e^yfjidrcDv, o>
(f>i\6,
eV TO> own
eaT(i)T(tiv, rov pev Oelov evBaifjioveardrov, rov 8e
ddeov dOXtwrdrov
or in that of the subordinate minds,
Tim. 86 B voaov ^ev Brj ^u^? avoiav
Rep. 58QE el Se TO eavrov fetor arov VTTO
rdra) re teal ^napwrdrw &ov\ovrai,...ovK apa
67 8c6s.
Cp. Tim. 53 B 6Tav airy rii/bs
io8 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
/jLTa7re<f)patcev.
And if we allow for Xenokrates*
identification of the Ideas with Mathematical num
bers the statement may be accepted as in the main
correct. At least all
the gods of the Platonic theocracy
in elemental forms.
38
Stob. Ed. i. i.
29 b ed. Wachsmuth i.
p. 37, 2.
89
Arist. Top. .6. 112 a 37.
90
Clemens Strom. V. xiii. 87 KaQ6\ov yovv rV v*pl TOV Qelov Zvvoiav
EevoKpciTTjs.. OVK aTTf\irici Kal eV rots a\6yois fyois (quoted by Zeller
op. at. p. 592.)-
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 109
for good and the power that makes for evil reappears
91
perhaps in Xenokrates broad contrast between Zeu?
UTraro? and Zevs vearos. But the further recognition
28 6 fj,ev
ovv rov vovv Ke\eva)v apxew So/eel Ke\eveiv
2. 1007
91
Clemens Strom. V. xiv. 116, Plut. Plat. Qu. ix. I, p.
pupil :
76/909.
It might be shown that the theology of the neo-
Platonists in some measure revived the usage of the
(ft)
The voepal Swa/xet?, z>. the Platonic Ideas,
which consist the supreme IVoi)? and, as
in
94
sharing its animation, are termed 0eot .
95
(7)
The 6pa)jj,evoi 6eol ,
i.e. the stars.
96
(8) The of particular men.
SatfjLoves and the 6eol
reflection.
94
Enn. V. i.
4, cp. ibid. II. ix. 8 TTUS OVK &v ris &ja\fj.a fi/apyes
Ka\bv rwv VOIJTUV Ofwv ftiroi; ibid. V. i. 7 irav p.ev rb T&V
K<i\\os t ircd/ras 8e Oeovs voyrots. lamblichus too calls the Ideas
vofpoi (v. /. votjToi) Qeoi ap. Prokl. in Tim. 94 C.
95
Enn. V. i. 4, cp. ibid. V. i. 2 errrt Se Kal faios 0eJs, 6ri e^vxos t
rbi>
Sai/Jiova Kal ov rou v<pei/j.cvov yevovs rbv <rvv6vra
( Vit. Plot. IO).
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 113
PART III.
jective world
as its copy. And this language
applies not only to particulars themselves which,
u4 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
Xepaalov riraprov
but also to the conditions of particular existence. For
Time, according to Plato, is an image of Eternity, and
Space a simulacrum of Ideal Otherness.
The former fact is stated in so many words :
"
209^33
TlXdrcovi /jLV70i Xeicreov . . . Sia rl ov/c ev TOTTCO ra
iSr) KCU ol apiduoi, elirep TO /AeOeKTi/cbv 6 TOTTO?,
176 70V /J,<yd\OV
KCU 7OV fJLlKpOV 6Wo? 70V
fJLedeK7t,KOV 617 T7J? uX???, to<77Te/3
V Tft)
TifJbO,i(i>
yeypafav
will be met by the answer that the term TOTTO? is not
rightly used till Ideal alterity has passed into indi
vidual extension.
It was this doctrine that particulars and the
modes of particular existence bear to ideas and the
modes of Ideal existence the relation of an ei/ccov to
97
Mr. Archer-Hind (ed. Tim. p. 171) paraphrases: "For true
reason declares that, while the type is one, and the image another, they
must be apart ; for they cannot exist one in the other and so be one and
two at once." But surely rb fj.ev and rb Se are both forus ovra, i.e.
K.T.A.. . .
,T<f
possible.
f
Starting from this point of contact between
Meta
attempt to show how the
physics and Morals,
I shall
98
Cp. Stob. Ed. i. Ixi. I (Hermes) ed. Wachsmuth i.
p. 275, 16
& vovs fv Ttf 6*$, 6 \oyiv/j.b? ev T$ avOp<air(f.
Aristotle after describing
99
It does indeed use the phrase vovv ex**" (68 B), vovv ex*" (89 B ) =
"sensible, reasonable," and the compounds Ivvosiv (870), ttaravo^lv
(90 D) etc. But to avoid them would have been mere pedantry.
ii8 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
register, <w
100
This strange expression seems chosen to escape the direct attri
bution of vovs to a particular. Similarly in 51 D, where Plato calls the
Ideas a*/o/<r07jTo rj/j.uv efty, voov^va. n6vov, the position of the
u<
pronoun is instructive.
101
Simplicius (in Arist. Psych, ed. Hayduck p. 317, 11) states that
plants %x ftv Al/J/ TWO. alffdrjffi^, a.fj,v8poTpav 5e t) KOTO TO &\\ws cD/To,
xal &s UXdrtav olov Ka6cv8ov(rav atffBtiffiv. Similarly Empedokles
f<j)Tj
(according to Sextus Math. viii. 286) TrdVro j}iov \oyiica rvyx&veiv, Kal
ov ua pAvov a\\a Kal Qvrd, prjrus ypaQuv irdura yap IffQi <f>p6vr)<riv
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 119
sine divinitatis
adminiculo ipsa per se anima nihil valeat spectare
103
Cp. Tim. 68 D 0ebs pev TO vo\\a fls ev tvytcepawvyai Kal Trd\ti>
e{ cvbs fls TTO\\O. Sia\vetv iitavus ftriffrdfievos apa Kal SUJ/OT^S, avQpta-
iruv Se ouSels ovStTfpa TOVTWV iKavbs o&Tf Herri vvv O&T ciffavBis TTOT*
(<rrai.
103
In Plat. Tim. 41 E, ed. Wrobel p. 202.
THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
104
See the admirable remarks of Mr. Archer-Hind ed. Timaeus
pp.
48-49.
105
Plat. Epist. d. 3 10 A.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 123
kind
vOpwTrovs 6<n?, o>?
76 Ka-ra<f>aiv6Tcu
(f>avordr(f)
TLVL Trvpi teal ol fiev TraXaioi,
and learnt from his lips rrjv rov iravros fyvcriv (Tim.
41 E). This they were enabled to do, because the
souls of men conceived as not yet associated with
their bodies do not differ from the Idea of Man, under
whose intuition all noetic existence would naturally
106
fall. The doctrine of Anamnesis is in fact the safe
)
CK 7ro\\(H)v lov aladrjcrewv et? ev
106
Diog. Laert. iii.
38 iSmfrara /j.ev aofyiav vyc irai (sc. Plato) eivai
ruv vot\T<i)V xal uvrus &VTUV 4iri(rTr)/jLir)v, ^v <pT)(n irepl
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 125
fc6<r(jLi6$
re Kal Oelos et? TO Svvarbv dv@pa)7rq)
yiyverat.
KOLdOaL ?rpo<?
rbv Oebv /SXeTret^, /cal
Theaet. 1
76 A, B Sto teal ireipacrdai %pr) evdevbe e/celae
Be
favyeiv o TI Td%t,<7Ta. <f>vyrj
Kara TO Bvvarov.
126 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
TrapaTrXtfcria eavrw.
Laws 716 C rbv ovv rc3 TOIOVTM (sc. Oew) TrpocrfaXf}
yevrjo-opevov et? ^vvafjuv o TI fidXicrTa teal avrbv
TOIOVTOV dvayxalov yiyveo-Oai.
But with the modification of the earlier metaphysic it
became possible to employ more precise definition.
I have said that in Plato s maturer view the individual
man and body soul being the active,
consists of soul
107
These last words are noteworthy. Had the bonum been defined
as approximation to any single Idea, it might have been inapplicable to
128 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
(90 C)
recognising just that apportioned activity which is
the mark of genuine justice. 108 Nor do we lose sight
of the fjLiKTos jSlos advocated in the Pkilebtis, for with
this conception of the rational object is closely linked
Theaet. 76 E 7rapa&i,yiJ,dT(ov
1 ev T&J OVTI e<7TO)TCt)^, . . .
the particulars of that Idea in their future life, because such particulars
efot.
For in truth the o-vvayvpfAos
(frpovrfaews, the conversion
of opinion into knowledge, is pvpia) ?rpo? evScupoviav
&i,a(f>epa)v (Politic. 272 c). Even on the perceptive
plane conformity to nature s design is attended by
pleasure. Thus of sensation in general we read :
110
The number 6fuv must balance that of the rpla Qv-nra.
of the fleol
9
THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
67 A TO
1
ev . . .
(Buifypevov ... TO 8e ... tra\iv 77 ir
conformity.
vorjrbv cognised by
cooi> is a VOTJTOV oW on the plane
of sensation, and the result must be a localisation of
the former by the latter in the vTroSo^rj.
111
Tim. 51 B.
132
THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
cosmic body. A
being endowed with superhuman-
will be apprehended not as a man
say, stellar thought
limits of each several
but as a star. Again, within the
of personal shape will be referred
species differences
allowance being
to differences of personal attainment,
tendencies soon to be
made certain
for retarding
noticed.
That in Plato view physical was thus dependent
s
from
upon psychical development may be gathered
Aristotle s criticism in Psych. A. 3. 22-23, 407 ^ *S- 2 4
TV^pixnv. ol 8e /JLOVOV
7n^ei,povfjL6V \e<yeiv,
oi>To>9
e^^av^aro KOL o
<yap
rov (Biov Secr/Aol T^? ^^7)9 TO) o-(t)fj,art
rigid science :
la"xypav fjn~
5.
and a"
starved, or if a be starved and a! fully developed,
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 137
%vvafjL<j)6Tepov,
o>oi> o KaXovpev.
avev 0"a>/*flT09
Mvelv fJLr)T (Tw/jba avev
"va
afAVvo/Jieva) rylyvrjo-Oov la-oppoirco KOI
fjs,
vyirj.
Phaed. 67 D TO /ieXeT??/x<x
avro rovro ecm
KOL
of the Beol u2
6ea)i> .
Consequently the best imitation
of that circularity which symbolises 113 pure thought
will be the spherical shapes and revolving orbits of
. .
Kivr)<rew
Be &vo Trpoarj^frev e/cdcrTq), rrjv
. . .
7rpL<f)6p rj
Se rjv KOL avra KOI fj Tropeia
&v Sta TO Tot? yoveva-w ofioia elvai.
ev rMV irdvTwv
112
They are repeatedly said to follow the example of the supreme
s, c.g. Tim. 410, 42 E, 69 C.
113
Tim. 34 A, Laws 898 A.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 139
11 *
a/jLd (TTpoyyvXa /cal TT poorer) SiypeiTo (r^fiara (73 D).
This difference marked by two curious
in dignity is
Ta Se evaifjia . . .
TrepLeC^rj^^eva axnrep VTT* ovpavov
e/cdarov TOV feoou, rrjv TOV
i
<f>opdv.
114
For irp6iJ.r}Kfs as a deterioration of o-^atpoetSes cp. Tim. 91 E
is re Kal iravroias
apyias iKavrwv al TrepupopaL
140 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
115
This is not so puerile a notion as it seems at first sight to be.
"
We can as yet hardly say what are even the local boundaries that
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 141
divide the organism from its environment. When does the air in our
of the body ?
116
By a /eupros is meant a basket of wicker work with a wide mouth
but a comparatively narrow neck, used for catching fish see the illus :
trations in Rich Diet. Ant. s.v. nassa, Daremberg & Saglio Diet. Ant.
s.v. Prof. Cook Wilson in his polemic on the Timaeus
colum.
p. adopts M. Th. H. Martin s view that the
78 seq.
mouth of the trap
must have the ends of the reeds pointing inwards. But he himself
admits that "there is nothing about such a hindrance in Plato," and it
seems more probable that Kvpros here denotes that form of fish-trap
which was closed a lid ; for we should thus obtain a parallel between
by
the lid and the closing of mouth and nostrils. Oppian Hal. iii. 341370
gives a full account of this Kvpros
with a lid : when
the trap is full, the
fisherman claps to the lid and lifts the whole out of the water WHO.
r6r avfy Kvproio irepl ffr6(ia
ykp iro\\oi re Kal cfanrees reAeflaxn, | 5$J
KV<t)ffffovra.s
avfipvffev.
142 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
body et? TJ]V IK T/}? KoiKias crrl ra? (f)\efta<; vSpelav. The
process may readily be followed by the help of the
appended illustration. It comprises two movements,
(a) eKTrvor) and (b) avairvor). (a) Expiration. We
start with our eyicvpna full of air (fig. i). This air,
Kal T<z9
pivas into the eyKvpTia, and we reach our
original position once more.
This arrargement of air and fire in concentric
layers recalls the elemental \r)%ei 9 of Tim. 5 3 A, 63 B
seqq., and the oscillation of the whole is described in
terms which tally with the alcopa of Phaed. 1 1 1 E :
Koi\ia<s Trj
PIG.l. FIG 2
To fa.ce page
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 143
airoreketadai, TTCLV.
Tim. 30 A Xo7tcTtt//,ei>o<?
ovv evpia/cev ere TWV Kara
fyvcLv oparwv ovbev dvoTjrov rov vovv eftovros
6\ov o\ov rcdXXiov eaeo-Oai irore epyov.
In a word, Plato looks upon beauty as the visible
manifestation of that goodness which is the essential
attribute of mental activity :
590 B avrl
(5880).
e6yovs re Kal
117
Cp. also the |u^<f>irros 8vvafj.i$ viroirrepov
of Phaedrus 246 A.
10
146 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
tye<yeo~dai,
em avierai ev TOJ TOLOVTM TO Sewbv
TO fjieya eiceivo /cal 7ro\ueiSe9 dpe/jufjua Trepa TOV
with Tim. 91 B
opevov a\\o a\\o6ev ovre avrb et? aXXo TTOL lov (Tim.
"
119
Stobaeus Ed. I. xlix. 60 (Porphurios) ed. Wachsmuth i. p. 445,
23 observes that, according to Plato, the soul eV TOIS \eyofj.fvai
(T^fi Kal fj.eTaK6(Tfj.Tfj<riv
els e repo
T& TTp6(T<pOpOV
Kttl OlKe lC
148 THE METAPHYSICAL BASIS
121
Cp. Stob. Ed. i. xlix. 6 (Hermes) ed. Wachsmuth i.
p. 324, 5
Toivvv ttfrlv euStos J/OIJTIK)] ouata . . .
a7raAAa*yr<ra 5e TOV QVITIKOV
Bov/jLevr)<;
ev TOVTW &ia$ov/j,vo
TO 9VT]TOV 761/09.
Thus 8 1 C declares that, when the triangles of the
spinal chord are loosed, fyOivei TTCLV %wov: and 81 D
adds that, when the same triangles give way alto
122
Cp. ibid. 73 C a"irepfj.a
. . .
&povpai>, 846 TWV fri^iav, 86 C SevSpov.
OF PLATO S ETHICS. 151
PJiaedo 1 1
5 D ovKen vfuv Trapa/jLevw, aXA, ot^fjcro/uat
aiTLCov et9 fMaicdpayv 8/7 Tivas ev^ai^ovla^.
TOTTfOV.
the "house
"
and "
124
Alexis Olympiad, frag. com. ed. Meineke iii. 455 <ru>/j.a
j.v
ov ffoX^ TlXaruvos ;
152 METAPHYSICAL BASIS OF PLATO S ETHICS.
epyov
TO fj^ev apeivov yiyvofjievov r}6o<$ els
ico
TOTTOVj ^elpov Se et? TOV ^eipova^ Kara TO
TTpeTTOV CLVTMV Ka<TTOV
-
so that particular life is justly said to depend on the
supreme %wov :
1
Tim. 89 B tear avro TO ^wov el/juap/juevov ef
P- 709. 33
P- 721, 31
p. l6
73 J
Alexis Olympiad, frag. com.
ed. Meineke iii. 455
Archilochus 3. 4
Archytas in frag. phil. Gr.
ed. Mullach i. 565
Arist. de an. gen. B. 3. 736
27
decaelo B. 12. 292* 32
demundo 2. 391 b 14 19 no
de part. an. A. I. 6420
32
*
5. 645 4
- A. 10. 6860 28
Eth.Eud.H. 12. 1245*
16
14. 12480 27
Eth.Nic. Z. 7. 1141034
- H. 14. 1153* 3 2
K. 7. 11770 16
frag. 46. 14830 27
- 184. 15100 4
184. 15100 14
187. 1511043
apud Philoponum
Met. A. 6. 987 b 10
6. 987* 10
6. 987* 10
6. 988 2
154 INDEX LOCORUM.
INDEX LOCORUM. 155
I
56 INDEX LOCORUM.
INDEX LOCORUM. 157
158 INDEX LOCORUM.
INDEX LOCORUM. 159
i6o INDEX LOCORUM.
NOV 1 9 1980
CT 7 195,
flTT
S 5
Cf> *
10
CvJ