Attention and Effort. (1973)
Attention and Effort. (1973)
Attention and Effort. (1973)
and Effort
DANIEL KAHNEMAN
The Hebrew University of Jerusalem
PRENTICE-HALL, INC.,
To
Irah, Michael and Lenore
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2
London
Sydney
CANADA, LTD., Toronto
INDIA PRIVATE LIMITED, New Delhi
JAPAN, INC., Tokyo
Contents
ix
PREFACE
13
26
28
33;
vi
CONTENTS
50
4 LOOKING
Spontaneous Looking, 52; The Acquisition of Visual Information,
Eye Movements and the Spatial Orientation of Thought, 60;
Review, 64
56;
66
70;
ATTENTION TO ATTRIBUTES
98
112
135
136
156
Contents
vii
178
REFERENCES
203
NAME INDEX
238
SUBJECT INDEX
242
Preface
There are several distinct subcultures among students of attention: investigators whose background is in studies of audition, others who think
in terms of visual perception, others who are primarily interested in
speeded performance, and some who study physiological arousal and
its multiple psychological determinants. Each of these subcultures has
tended to evolve its own language, and its particular conventions concerning the choice of experimental manipulations arid of dependent variables. Each has also developed its own biases. I have attempted in this
book to incorporate findings and ideas from these disparate sources into
a coherent formulation of attention.
The book is intended for graduate students and for advanced undergraduates studying the role of attention in perception and in performance. It consists primarily of a review of the research areas that are
commonly grouped under the label 'attention.' While the book presents
a particular interpretation of this research, I hope it may be useful to
students and to teachers who do not share this interpretation.
As will be evident to the reader, I have learned much of what I
know about attention from Donald Broadbent and Anne Treisman. It
will also be obvious that I find Ulric Neisser's approach to perception
and to cognition very congenial. A less obvious but equally important
ix
PREFACE
intellectual debt is to the late David Rapaport. While serving as his research assistant for one summer many years ago, I was introduced to
the psychoanalytic view 'of attention as energy. Many years later, having
become (as I thought) a rather tough-minded experimental psychologist,
I was surprised to discover that my understanding of attention bears
the permanent imprint of that encounter.
This text owes its existence to Jacques Mehler, who suggested
several years ago that I write a chapter on attention, and who patiently
prodded me through these years, while a misshapen chapter finally
evolved into a book. The conception of the book was influenced by my
students and collaborators, Daniel Gopher and Anat Ninio, who insistently demanded a clarification of my own views, and who also contributed to that clarification. Frequent discussions and friendly disagreements with Michael Posner and Steven Keele during the year that I
spent in Oregon inspired much of the material in the present version. I
have benefited from their scholarship as well as from their intellectual
generosity. The text also bears the marks of comments by my wife Irah,
by Ulric Neisser, Paul Obrist, Anne Treisman, Barbara and Amos
Tversky.
So~e of the ideas in this book were shaped by the results of experiments carried out in my laboratory at the Hebrew University. I
learned much from the students who conducted several of these studies:
Uri Avner, Avishai Henik, Ditza Kafry, Nurit Lass, Rina Levy and
Eythan Weg. Several able assistants participated in the project: Absalom
Bauman, David Bigeliter, Itamar Gatti, Ruth Kimchi, Noa Klein and
David Shinar. Yitzchak Hadani provided the technical expertise that
made the experiments possible.
In the preparation of the book I had valuable bibliographical help
from Bernard Goitein and Ilan Shapiro, and help that went well beyond
the standard secretarial duties from Tamar Ziv, Nira Rebaisen and
Leila Berner at the Hebrew University, from Meredith Woodward and
Karon Johnson at the Oregon Research Institute.
The book was completed during a sabbatical year spent at the
Oregon Research Institute and it is indeed a pleasure to acknowledge
the marvelous hospitality and the intellectual stimulation of my colleagues in that institution.
Finally, it is a pleasant duty to admit that this work could not have
been completed withollt financial support from various sources: The
Center for the Study of Disadvantaged Children and the Central Research Authority at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem, and Grant
No.5 SOl RR 05612 to the Oregon Research Institute.
D.K.
Jerusalem, 1973
7
Basic Issues in
the Study of Attention
theories about it, kept alive the concern with specific aspects of attention
such as the preparatory set and the span of ap-prehension. The term
"attention" was effectively banished from the vocabulary of scientific
psychology: the dominant theorists of the day found it useless, and the
empirically inclined functionalists were more concerned with the trees
than with the forest. -Thus, in 1953 Osgood published an important text
which covered the entire field of experimental psychology and mentioned
"attention" only once, in the discussion of a particular theory of discrimination learning.
By the end of the 1950s, the situation had altered radically, and
the newly legitimized concept of attention was a central topic in an
emergent cognitive psychology. The new Zeitgeist ascribed more spontaneity and autonomy to the organism than had the classical doctrines
of behaviorism, Gestalt theory, and psychoanalysis. Spontaneity and autonomy imply some degree of local unpredictability. Indeed, the main
function of the term "attention" in post-behavioristic psychology is to
provide a label for some of the internal mechanisms that determine the
significance of stimuli and thereby make it impossible to predict behavior
by stimulus considerations alone.
There is more to attention than mere selection. In everyday language, the term "attention" also refers to an aspect of amount and
intensity. The dictionary tells us that to attend is to apply oneselfpresumably to some task or activity. Selection is implied, because there
are always alternative activities in which one could engage, but any
schoolboy knows that applying oneself is a matter of degree. Lulled into
a pleasant state of drowsiness by his teacher's voice, the schoolboy does
not merely fail to pay attention to what the teacher says; he has less
attention to pay. A -schoolboy who reads a detective story while his
teacher speaks is guilty of improper selection. On the other hand, the
drowsy schoolboy merely suffers from, or perhaps enjoys, a generally
low level of attention.
A comprehensive treatment of the intensive aspect of attention was
offered by Berlyne (1960). He suggested that the intensity of attention
is related to the level 'of arousal, that arousal can be measured with the
aid of electrophysiological techniqlIes, and that it is largely controlled by
the properties of the stimuli to which the organism is exposed. Berlyne
(1951, 1960, 1970) also pioneered in the study of collative properties,
sllch as novelty, complexity, and incongrllity, which cause some stimuli
to be more arousing than others. He observed that the more arousing
stimuli generally tend to capture the control of behavior in situations of
response conflict.
Berlyne was mainly concerned with i.nvolllntary attention. The collative properties that he studied control an involuntary selective process
and they elicit an involuntary surge of arousal. A cognitive psychology,
however, is not congenial to studies of involuntary behavior. Perhaps as
a result, the line of investigation which Berlyne opened has not been
followed very actively,. In contrast, the study of voluntary selective atten-
There has been one major attempt to solve this problem by using
the terms and measures of a branch of applied mathematics called the
theory of information (Attneave, 1959; Garner, 1962). This theory provides a measure of the complexity and unpredictability of both stimuli
and responses, the "bit" of information. In the context of the theory, man
is viewed as a communication channel that transmits information. The
capacity of such a channel is given in bits/ second, reHecting the rate at
which information is transmitted through it. Channel capacity has been
measured in human activities such as reading, driving a car, or playing
the piano, as well as in the operation of systems such as telephone links
or television sets. Unfortunately, estimates of human channel capacity
in different tasks, or at different stages of practice, have been too inconsistent to be useful. Indeed, the variables of stimulus discriminability
and stimulus-response compatibility are ij10re powerful determinants of
the speed and quality of performance than are the variables suggested
by the information analysis (Fitts & Posner, 1967). As cognitive psychology abandoned the measures of information theory, it was left without
a meaningful common unit to compare different tasks, and without a
valid approach to the measurement of human capacity. Physiological
measures of effort could contribute to fill these gaps.
with only a narrow beam of clear and sharp vision, and he is therefore
dependent on sequential scanning for a comprehensive look around him.
He is also equipped with a single tongue and must therefore arrange his
verbal responses in sequence. Attention theorists are concerned with the
possibility that there are similarly limited stages in the central nervous
system, which would make man unable to think, remember, perceive, or
decide more than one thing at a time.
As Chapters 7 and 8 will show, the modern study of attention has
been dominated by theories which assume a bottleneck stage somewhere
in the system, but the locus of the bottleneck has been controversial. To
introduce this issue, Figure 1-1 presents a crude outline of two models
of selective attention, in which the bottleneck is located at different
stages.
( A )
Stimulus
Stimulus
......
,,-
SENSORY
REGISTRATION
. . . AND STORAGE
.,'-
PERCEPTUAL
ANALYSrS
'"""
RESPONSE
SELECTION
~7
( B)
Stimulus
Stimulus
.....
1
-?
"
......
......
SENSORY
REGISTRATION
AND STORAGE
'"
7'
;'
......
PERCEPTUAL
ANALYSIS
RESPONSE
SELECTION
"
FIGURE I-I
Two models of selective attention.
rent stimtIli are extracted in parallel and without interference. The bottleneck that imposes sequential processing is only encountered later: it
prevents the initiation of more than one response at a time, and selects
the response that best fits the requirements of the situation.
As an example of the questions to which the two models provide
different answers, consider a person at a eocktail party who actively participates in one of the many loud conversations that take place in the
room. Assun1ing that the sensory messages that correspond to several of
these conversations reach the central nervous system of the listener, we
may ask: at what point is the attended conversation favored over the
others? To what stages of perceptual analysis do the unattended messages penetrate? According to filter theory (model A) the unattended
messages are never decoded in perceptual analysis. In effect they are not
"heard.~' According to model B, all the conversations are heard, but only
one is responded to. The interested student who ponders Figure 1-1 will
probably be able to invent several of the experiments which have been
designed to a~swer such questions, and which will be discussed in some
detail in Chapters 7 and 8.
The evidence of these studies indicates that selective attention to
inputs affects perceptual analysis. This is contrary to model B. However,
man is also capable of dividing his attention between concurrent messages. This is contrary to model A. Thus, one of the main conclusions
of research on attention is that man's cognitive operations are far more
flexible than either of these bottleneck theories would suggest.
While the allocation of attention is flexible and highly responsive
to the intentions of the moment, there are pre-attentive mechanisms that
operate autonomously, outside voluntary control (Neisser, 1967). These
provide a preliminary organization to perception by a process of grouping and segmentation. The objects of perception are defined at that
stage, and subsequent processes of selective attention operate on these
objects. The general rule is that it is easy to focus attention exclusively
on a single object and difficult to divide attention amollg several objects.
Conversely, it is easy to notice several aspects or attributes of an object,
but it is difficult or impossible to prevent the perceptual analysis of
irrelevant attributes. Thus, we seem tInable to see the shape of an
object without seeing its color as well.
lOA TTENTION
AND EFFORT
MISCELLANEOUS
DETERMINANTS
MISCELLANEOUS
.......~ MANIFESTATIONS
OF AROUSAL
AROUSAL
rlJvv'L
ENDURING
DISPOSITIONS
!AVAILABLE;
:CAPACITY:
I
MOMENTARY
INTENTIONS
POSSIBLE ACTIVITIES
RESPONSES
FIGURE 1-2
A capacity model for attention.
11
The two central elements of the model are the allocation policy
and the evaluation of demands on the limited capacity. The evaluation
of demands is the governor system that causes capacity (or effort) to be
supplied, as needed by the activities that the allocation policy has selected. The policy itself is controlled by four factors: (1) Enduring dispositions which reflect the rules of involuntary attention (e.g., allocate
capacity to any novel signal; to any object in sudden motion; to any
conversation in which one's name is mentioned); (2) Momentary intentions (e.g., listen to the voice on the right earphone; look for a redheaded
man with a scar); (3) The evaluation of demands: there appears to be
a rule that when two activities demand more capacity than is available,
one is completed (see Chap. 8); (4) Effects of arousal: systematic
changes of allocation policy in high arousal will be discussed in Chapter 3.
The capacity model of Figllre 1-2 is intended to complement rather
than supersede models of the structure of information-processing such
as those illustrated in Figure 1-1. The two figures, in fact, belong to different types: the models of Figure 1-1 are schematic flow-charts that
describe the sequence of operations that are applied to a set of simultaneous stimuli. In contrast, Figure 1-2 is a control diagram that describes
the relations of influence and control between components of a system.
For example, Figure 1-2 implies that a state of overload in which the
demands of ongoing activities exceed available capacity will induce a
compensatory increase of both arousal and capacity.
The present chapter has illustrated two types of attention theories,
which respectively emphasize the structural limitations of the mental
system and its capacity limitations. Both types of theory predict that
concurrent activities are likely to be mutually interfering, but they
ascribe the interference to different causes. In a structural model, interference occurs when the same mechanism is required to carry out two
incompatible operations at the same time. In a capacity model, interference occurs when the demands of two activities exceed available capacity. Thus, a structural model implies that interference between tasks
is specific, and depends on the degree to which the tasks call for the
same mechanisms. In a capacity model, interference is nonspecific, and
it depends only on the demands of both tasks. As Chapters 8 and 10 will
show, both types of interference occur. Studies of selective and divided
attention indicate that the deployment of attention is more flexible than
is expected under the assumption of a structural bottleneck, but it is
more constrained than is expected under the assumption of free allocation of capacity. A comprehensive treatment of attention must therefore
incorporate considerations of both structure and capacity.
12
The major themes of this book have been outlined in the present
chapter. The n10st important of these themes is an attempt to integrate
the intensive and selective aspects of attention. The intensive aspect of
attention is identified with effort, and selective attention is viewed as the
selective allocation of effort to some mental activities in preference to
others. Because of the connection between effort and arousal, physiological measures of arousal can be used to measure the exertion of effort.
Some types of information-processing activities can be triggered solely
by an input of information. Others require an additional input of attention or effort. Because the total quantity of effort which can be
exerted at anyone time is limited, concurrent activities which require
attention tend to interfere with one another"
A contrast was drawn between a structural model, in which cognitive activity is limited by a bottleneck, or station at which parallel processing is impossible (see Fig. 1-1), and a capacity model in which the
limited capacity determines which activities can be carried out together
(see Fig. 1-2). Neither model is adequate alone, but each captures some
important aspects of cognitive activity.
'
These major concepts should serve as background for the study of
subsequent chapters, which review some central areas of research in attention. Chapters 2 and 3 discllss some intensive aspects of attention and
elaborate the capacity model of attention and mental effort. Chapter 4 is
devoted to looking behavior. Some variants of selective attention are discussed in Chapter 5, which presents a model of the role of attention in
perception. A brief review of attention to attributes in Chapter 6 is followed by a more thorough review of focused and divided attention with
simultaneous inputs (Chaps. 7 and 8). The division of attention between
simultaneous or immediately successive speeded responses is discussed
in Chapter 9. Chapter 10 returns to the concept of effort and its measurement by task interference.
The interested student will find additional relevant material in
several recent texts (Broadbent, 1971; Keele, 1973; Moray, 19'69a, 1969b;
Norman, 1969a). A vast amount of research relevant to attention is conveniently available in special volumes of the journal Acta Psychologica,
published in 1967, 1969, and 1970. Kornblum (1972) has edited an additional volume in this series. For a humbling look at what was known
about attention at the turn of the century, a text by Pillsbury (1908)
should be consulted. Woodworth (1938) also reviews much research
which remains relevant and illteresting, although it is rarely cited in recent work.
2
Toward a Theory
of Mental Effort
This chapter elaborates the capacity model that was introduced in Figure 1-2. The first section is concerned with the control of effort by the
feedback loop leading from the Evaluation of Demands on Capacity to
the Arousal-Capacity system. The second section summarizes the evidence that arousal varies with momentary changes in the load' imposed
by mental' activity. Some determinants of the effort requirements of
various activities are discussed in the final section.
The capacity model shown in Figure 1-2 assumed that the capacity
which can be allocated to various activities is limited. It also assumed
that the limit varies with the level of arousal: more capacity is available
when arousal is moderately high than when arousal is low. Finally, it
assumed that momentary capacity, attention, or effort (the three terms are
interchangeable in this context) is controlled by feedback from the execution of ongoing activities: a rise in the demands of these activities
causes an increase in the level of arousal, effort, and attention.
13
14
The key observations suggesting this model will be discussed in detail in the next section, where it will be shown that physiological arollsal
varies second by second when a subject is engaged in a task, and that
these variations correspond to momentary changes in the demands imposed by the task. Thus, aro,usal and effort are usually not determined
prior to the action: they vary continuously, depending on the load which
is imposed by what one does at any instant of time.
A crude physical analogy may help clarify these ideas. When you
push a slice 0. bread into the toaster, this increases the load on the general electric supply. Witholtt a countervailing change, the new, load
would cause the voltage supplied to all users to drop. However, the
generator that supplies the current is equipped with a governor system
which immediately causes more fuel to be burned to restore the constant
voltage. In this manner, the total power that the generator supplies
varies continuously as a function of the load which is imposed by the
momentary choices of the consumers of electricity.
The analogy can be pursued further. Note that, as a user of electric
power, you rarely control the amount of power that you require in a continuous or graded fashion. All you decide is that a certain aim is to be
achieved, whether it be toasting a bun or illuminating a room. How
much power is drawn depends on the structure of the elements that you
switch on. As a first approximation, the same rule applies to mental work
as well. In general, we merely decide what aims we wish to achieve. The
activities in which we then engage determine the effort that we exert.
An important observation in studies of physiological arousal and
performance is that arousal varies with the difficulty, of different tasks, as
measured by error rate. This apparently reasonable finding is actually
quite puzzling. At an intermediate level of difficulty, the subject makes
a significant number of errors. Yet he does not work as hard as he can,
since he exerts greater effort when difficulty is further increased. Why,
then, does the subject not work harder at the initial level of difficulty,
and avoid all errors?
The answer appears to be that the subject simply cannot try as
hard in a relatively easy task as he does when the task becomes more demanding. The reader may wish to confirm this by an armchair experiment. First, try to mentally multiply 83 by 27. Having completed this
task, imagine that you are going to be given four numbers, and that
your life depends on your ability to retain them for ten seconds. The
numbers are seven, two, five, nine. Having completed the second task,
it may appear believable that) even to save one's life, one cannot work as
hard in retaining four digits as one must work to complete a mental
multiplication of two-digit numbers.
In an attempt to study this question experimentally, subjects were
15
'y/
/
Total capacity / /
o&. "
,,"
,'-
~r~---
..".",.""""/
/
/
~
Capacity supplied
to pri mary task
Capac ity demanded by pri mary task
FIGURE 2-1
Supply of effort as a function of demands of a primary task.
16
17
his disposal, he would surely use it to reduce his error-rate. This view assumes that effort is maximal whenever a well-motivated subject engages
in a task in which he makes some errors, regardless of how difficult the
task is. In fact, tasks at different levels of complexity elicit different degrees of arousal and demand different amounts of attention and effort.
The present section has elaborated the connection between two elements of the capacity model that was introduced in Figure 1-2: the
Evaluation of Demands on Capacity and the Arousal-Capacity system.
The main assumption of the model is that the mobilization of effort in a
task is controlled by the demands of the task, rather than by the performer's intentions. In addition, the system response is assumed to be insufficient, with an increasing gap between demand and supply when
overload is approached. Finally, it is assumed that the spare capacity
which is devoted to continuous activities of perceptual monitoring decreases with increasing involvement in a primary task.
18
MISCELLANEOUS SOURCES
OF AROUSAL:
anxi ety f fear/anger f
sexual excitement,
muscular strain, effects of
drugs, intense stimulation, etc.
AROUSAL
r-Lrvv--L
I
:AVAILABLE:
!CAPACITY:
MISCELLANEOUS
.......... MANIFESTATIONS OF AROUSAL:
pupillary dilation,
inc reased sk in
conductance, fast
pulse etc.
ALLOCATION
POLICY
/ / \
...----'//
~---
D11~~ ~~_~D
POSSIBLE ACTIVITIES
RESPONSES
FIGURE 2-2
Effort and other determinants of arousal.
specific measures of effort have had little application, and two standard
measures of sympathetic activity remain the most useful autonomic indications of effort: dilation of the pupil is the best single index and an
increase of skin conductance provides a related, but less satisfactory
measure (Colman & Paivio, 1969; Kahneman, Tursky, Shapiro & Crider,
1969). A third measure of sympathetic dominance, increased heart rate,
cannot be used as a measure of effort, for reasons that will be described
in Chapter 3.
A useful physiological measure of mental effort must be sensitive
to both between-tasks and within-task variations. That is, it should order
tasks by their difficulty, since more difficult tasks usually demand greater
effort. It should also reflect transient variations of the subject's effort during the performance of a particular task. A perfect measure of mental
effort would also reflect between-subject differences, i.e., differences in
the amount of effort that different people invest in a given task. There is
19
little evidence concerning the third point (Kahneman & Peavler, 1969;
Peavler, 1969), but measurements of pupil diameter appear to meet the
first two requirements, and they provide a sensitive indication of both
between-tasks and within-task variations of effort (see Goldwater, 1972,
for a comprehensive review).
The claim that pupillary dilations indicate mental effort was made
by Hess and Polt (1964; Hess, 1965), who observed a striking correspondence between the difficulty of mental arithmetic problems and the
n1agnitllde of the dilation during the solution period. The correspondence between cognitive load and pupillary dilation was later confirmed
in many contexts: arithmetic (Bradshaw, 1968b; Payne, Perry & Harasymin, 1968); short-term memory tasks of varying load (Kahneman &
Beatty, 1966); pitch discriminations of varying difficulties (Kahneman &
Beatty, 1967); standard tests of "concentration" (Bradshaw, 1968a); sentence comprehension (Wright & Kahneman, 1971); paired-associate learning (Colman & Paivio, 1970; Kahneman & Peavler, 1969); imagery tasks
with abstract and with concrete words (Paivio & Simpson, 1966, 1968;
Simpson & Paivio, 1968), and the emission of a freely selected motor response instead of an instructed response (Simpson & Hale, 1969). In all
these situations, the amount of dilation increases with task demand or
difficulty. The relation between attention and pupillary dilation is maintained even in the absence of specific task instructions: Libby, Lacey,
and Lacey (1973) observed dilations of the pupil when the subject
merely looked at pictures. The largest dilations occurred while looking at
"interesting" and "attention-getting" pictures (see Fig. 3-1 on p. 30).
Pratt (1970) also observed that the pupillary dilation varied with the
unpredictability of random shapes to which subjects were exposed. Evidently, complex and interesting pictures, like difficult tasks, attract attention and demand a relatively large investment of effort.
The second test of an adequate measure of effort is within-task
sensitivity. Several studies have confirmed the suggestion (Hess, 1965)
that the size of the pupil at any time during performance reflects the
subject's momentary involvement in the task. Indeed, the fidelity of the
pupil response permits a second-by-second analysis of task-load and
effort. Kahneman and Beatty (1966), for example, showed that the presentation of each successive digit in a short-term memory task is accompanied by a dilation of the pupil. The increase in pupil diameter
corresponds to the increasing rate of rehearsal which is imposed by the
presentation of the additional digit. This pattern of rehearsal can be
altered by presenting the items in several groups, separated by pauses.
Then, a brief dilation of the pupil occurs after the presentation of each
group, corresponding to the spurt of rehearsal during each pause (Kahne-'
man, Onuska & Wolman, 1968). Finally, when a subject is informed that
20
he need no longer retain the digits he has heard, his pupil briefly dilates,
then constricts, as he ceases to rehearse (Johnson, 1971).
The pupillary dilation is a relatively fast response, and major dilations can occur within one second after the presentation of a demanding
stimulus. Thus, Beatty and Kahneman (1966) showed that the pupil
dilates about 10 percent of base diameter during the first second following the presentation of a familiar name, when the subject must respond
by the appropriate telephone number. Similarly, in a pitch discrimination task, the diameter of the pupil reaches a maximum within one second of the presentation of the critical tone; the size of the pupil at that
time faithfully reflects the difficulty of the discrimination (Kahneman &
Beatty, 1967). When subjects are required to produce an image that corresponds to a particular word, pupil diameter reaches its maximal value
faster with concrete than with abstract words (Colman & Paivio, 1969;
Paivio & Simpson, 1968; Simpson, Molloy, Hale & Climan, 1968). A plausible explanation of this finding is that the visual image is produced
sooner for concrete than for abstract words.
To further test the validity of the pupillary measure of effort, a
behavioral measure of spare capacity was introduced. Subjects were
required to perform two tasks simultaneously. The primary task involved
the transformation of a digit string: the subject heard a series of four
digits (e.g., 3916) at a rate of one digiti second, and he was instructed to
pause for a second, then to respond with a transform of that series
(4027), adding 1 to each digit of the original set. In addition, the subjects
performed a secondary task. In one experiment (Kahneman, Beatty &
Pollack, '1967), a series of letters was flashed in quick succession, and
the subjects monitored the display for the occurrence of a "K." In
another experiment (Kahneman, 1970), the subjects were briefly shown a
single letter, which was to be reported after the completion of the digittransformation task. The payoff structure in these experiments was designed to ensure priority for the digit-transformation task: the subject
was paid for the visual task only if he had performed the transformation
task adequately.
Figure 2-3 shows the results of these studies. It includes four
curves: (1) a typical pupillary response to the digit-transformation task;
(2) the average percentage of missed K's as a function of the time of
their presentation; (3) the average percentage of incorrectly reported
letters as a function of the time of their presentation; and (4) the average
percentage of failures in the digit-transformation task, as a function of
the time of presentation of the visual letter.
The most important feature of Figure 2-3 is that ~he pupillary response and two different behavioral measures of spare capacity show
similar trends, although the pupil appears to lag slightly. As a first ap-
Detection of 'K I
Letter
...---.. identification
. - -... Digit task
70
0.7
60
. 0.6
50
0.5
,
en
(l)
L.
.~
:::>
.....
c
(l)
u
L.
(l)
0-
\,
40
0.4
\,
\
30
z
a
'"0
>-..
a'-
0.3 .0..
::>
a..
\
\
20
.",.
........
0.2
'-...... 'e
0.1
10
Report
o
Time (Sec)
FIGURE 2-3
Two measures of perceptual deficit and the pupillary response to a digittransformation task. Also shown, the probability. of success in the transformation task as a function of the time of occurrence of the visual target. (Sources:
Kahneman, Beatty & Pollack, 1967; Kahneman, Tursky, Shapiro & Crider,
1969; Kahneman, 1970, with permission).
21
22
23
4.70
Say Add 1
Think Add 1
4. 50
E
E
c
-0
Think Add 0
4.30
s-
Q)
Q)
E
c
-0
4.10-
.0.
:>
0..
3.90
1 2
10
12
14
16
18
20
22
24
26
Ti me (seconds)
FIGURE 2-4
Pupillary responses to two tasks under instructions to say response twice
(say), or to think response and then say it, (think). (From Kahneman, Peavler
& Onuska, 1968, with permission.)
24
25
26
larly large pupillary dilations when the subject was also asked to indicate the instant at which he achieved the image. Since the occurrence of
an overt response is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for
large pupillary dilations, it seems likely that the instruction to report the
achievement of an image induced time-pressure, and thereby increased
effort.
The most important type of time-pressure is that which is inherent
in the structure of the task. Thus, severe time-pressure necessarily arises
in any task which imposes a significant load on short-term memory, because the subject's rate of activity must be paced by the rate of decay of
the stored elements. In mental arithmetic, for instance, one must keep
track of the initial problem, of partial results already obtained, and of
the next step. Stopping or slowing even for an instant usually forces one
to return to the beginning and start again. In tests of short-term recall,
the increasing number of items that must be rehearsed causes a rapid
buildup of time-pressure, which is also reflected in autonomic measures
of arousal. Time is also critical in a pitch-discrimination task with brief
tones, where rapidly decaying traces must be quickly evaluated. In all
these tasks, large pupillary dilations occur.
Some problems are difficult because the elements that are essential
to the solution are relatively inaccessible to retrieval from memory.
Other prob,lems are difficult because they impose severe time-pressure.
The indications are that effort is less closely related to the dimension of
accessibility than to the dimension of time-pressure. During paired-associate learning, for example, the pupillary response at recall decreases
quite slowly with increasing familiarity (Kahneman & Beatty, unpublished observations). Bradshaw (1968b) has reported that the size of
pupillary dilations does not vary with the difficulty of word-construction
problems, although. it varies consistently with the difficulty of arithmetic
problems. The difference could be due to the differing roles of storage
and rehearsal in the two tasks. The more difficult arithmetic problems require more storage and rehearsal than do easier problems, and therefore impose more time-pressure. In contrast, a word problem is difficult
only because correct answers are few and inaccessible; it imposes neither
more load on storage nor more time-pressure than an easy problem, and
it does not elicit greater effort.
REVIEW
27
allocation of effort for each task. The investment of less than this stan'effort causes a deterioration of performance, but in most tasks it is
impossible to completely eliminate errors by a voluntary increase of
ort beyond the standard. As a result, the voluntary control of effort is
limited in scope. It was assumed that the increased allocation of effort
difficult tasks-does not suffice to maintain performance at a constant
and that the spare capacity that remains available for perceptual
monitoring decreases with increasing involvement in a primary task.
Evidence was presented that transient variations of arousal during
performance of a mental task correspond to transient changes in the
demands of the task and to temporary decrements in behavioral measures of spare capacity. However, the measurement of effort by physiological indications of arousal such as the pupillary dilation is complicated
the fact that the manifestations of arousal are not specific to effort.
Finally, the concept of momentary effort was distinguished from
the probability of failure in a task and from the total amount of work
required by that task. Much mental activity appears to occur without
the exertion of substantial effort. Time-pressure is a particularly important determinant of momentary effort. Tasks that impose a heavy load
on short-term memory necessarily impose: severe time-pressure.
3
Arousal and Attention
.......
....
II II
Attention
5. 1
- - - - - -.-- - - - --e Lo w
. - - - . - - - . Med
5.0
High
~
~
u.J
Iu.J
4.9
<{
0
....J
a:
=>
CL
4.8
4.7
PUPIL DIAMETER
75
74
..
- I
..., \.
'\
"
., '.'.....
73
,, ,
\.
\
\
u.J
'~-.\ ......
~\
~-.
,
.i
~,J
'e
f~
<{
UJ
:c
72
HEART RATE
71
10
15
FIGURE 3-1
Cardiac and pupillary responses to pictorial stimuli at three attention
values (adapted from Libby, Lacey & Lacey, 1973, with permission).
30
Directional fractionation occurs when the subject is merely exto information, but it is replaced by the common arousal pattern
the subject starts to manipulate the information in a task. Thus,
Schwartz, and Crider (1970) asked subjects to listen to a string
four digits and to subsequently report a transform of this list (Add 1).
... ,..~_.,..,. the subject was listening to the digits, there was a marked cardiac
deceleration accompanied by a rise in skin conductance. Later, the heart
accelerated as the subject prepared and rehearsed his response.
Lacey (1967) proposed that generalized sympathetic dominance occurs when the individual resists stimulation, either because it is aversive
continuous pain) or because it is distracting (e.g., stimulation that
interrupts problem-solving activity). He suggested that directional fractionation with cardiac deceleration occurs in states of attentive acceptance of external stimulation, and that heart rate plays a causal role
a feedback loop which controls attention.
While the existence of directional fractionation is not in doubt,
Lacey's original interpretation of acceleration as a correlate of stimulusrejection was probably incorrect. In the data of Libby, Lacey, and Lacey
(1973), for example, the largest cardiac decelerations were observed for
the most unpleasant stimuli. The evidence supports an alternative formulation, that momentary heart rate reflects the current degree of motor
tension or mobilization for action.
Directional fractionation and cardiac deceleration reliably occur
under conditions of "waiting for something to happen." The two waiting
situations that have been investigated most thoroughly are: (1) the foreperiod between an alerting signal and the stimulus in a reaction-time
experiment (Chase, Graham & Graham, 196'8; Connor & Lang, 1969;
Coquery & Lacey, 1966; Lacey & Lacey, 1964, 1966; Obrist, Webb &
Sutterer, 1969; Obrist, Webb, Sutterer & Howard, 1970b; Webb & Obrist,
1970); and (2) the interval between a neutral conditioned stimulus (CS)
and an aversive unconditioned stimulus (DeS) in a classical conditioning paradigm (Deane, 1961; Hastings & Obrist, 1967; Jenks & Deane,
1963; Notterman, Schoenfeld & Bersh, 195,2; Obrist, 1968; Obrist, Wood
& Perez-Reyes, 1965; Wilson, 1964).
The waiting paradigm has been studied carefully by Obrist, who
found that cardiac deceleration is typically accompanied by a marked
reduction of irrelevant movement, and by the steady fixation of an unblinking eye (Obrist, Webb & Sutterer, 1969; Webb & Obrist, 1970). This
pattern is adaptive: any subject in a reaction-time experiment soon discovers that a high level of motor tension during the foreperiod yields a
slow RT. A relatively relaxed posture, in which ongoing 'activity is inhibited, tends to be optimal. Indeed, Obrist, Webb, Sutterer, and
Howard (1~70b) confirmed the correlation between inhibition of irrele-
32
vant activity and the sllbseqllent RT. They also found that the correlation is maintained even when the cardiac deceleration is. prevented by
atropine, a result which provides decisive evidence against Lacey's suggestion that cardiac deceleration plays a callsal role in the control of
attentional patterns. Rather, the decrease in heart rate is simply a manifestation of a general inhibitio11 pattern. A detailed discussion of the
physiological n1echa11isms controlling the cardiac response has been offered by Gbrist, Webb, Sutterer, and Howard (1970a). Fllrther evidence
for Gbrist's analysis was offered by Cohen and Johnson (1971), who observed highly significant correlatio11s between heart rate and electro-
myographic measures of muscle tension, both within each subject's data
(over successive measurements) and between subjects: the most relaxed
sllbjects had the slowest pulse.
The inhibition of movement during the RT foreperiod has correlates in the measurable activity of the brain. The alerting stimulus of the
RT paradigm is normally followed by a very consistent change in the
EEG, known as the CNV, or continge11t .negative variation (Walter,
Cooper, Aldridge, McCalltlm & Winter, 1964). The CNV, sometimes
called the expectancy wave, is a sllstained change of baseline potential
which is contingent upon the expectation of a subsequent significant
stimulus (Cohen, 1969; Tecce, 1972). The occurrence of a CNV tends to
be associated with a slow heart rate during the foreperiod, and with a
fast RT (Connor & Lang, 1969; Hillyard, 1969).
Elliott (1969) observed directional fractionation in a new and rather
llnexpected situation, and he proposed an interpretation of the cardiac
response which was quite similar to Obrist's view. He studied autonomic
respo11ses i11 the conflict situation induced by the Stroop test, in which
the sllbject lTIUst read the colors in which color names are printed and
refrain from reading the ,vords themselves (see p.109). In this conflict
situation the sllbject may be noticed "reading . . . with almost emphatically deliberate pace, holding himself back from a speed that
might produce c011fusion and error [Elliott, 1969, p. 218]." This inhibitory
pattern is accompanied by a slowing of the heart. Elliott concluded that
cardiac deceleration is associated with the inhibition of responses, and
that cardiac acceleration accompanies the instigation, anticipation, and
initiatio11 of responses. In a fllrther test of this hypothesis, Elliott, Bankart,
and Light (1970) measured heart rate and palmar conductance for the
three conditions of the Stroop test (word, color, and word-color interference) and found that heart rate fell as the difficulty of the test condition increased, while palmar condllctance rose.
111 c011clusion, consideration of the cardiac response and of the nattlre of the task situation pern1its two, and perhaps three states of high
arollsal to be distingllished:
(1)
(2)
(3)
The evidence of this section disproves the early idea that arousal
can be identified with sympathetic dominance. Subtypes of arousal fl1USt
be distinguished. However, the suggestion that the concept of arousal
should be abandoned appears too extreme. A concept of arousal is
needed to differentiate the state of the subject in a task situation from
his state at rest. While solving a problem, looking at a picture, or reading
a Stroop card, the subject is more active and alert, in short more aroused,
than he is at rest. Arousal can be measured, since there are at least two
indices of autonomic activity, skin conductance and pupil size, which
appear to-increase monotonically with attention in all task situations.
34
complexity (Yerkes & Dodson, 1908). These relations are schematically illustrated in Figure 3-2.
High
A simple task
Q)
o
E
so
"+-
A complex
task
s-
Q)
0..
"+-
....>-.
o
~
Low
High
Low
Arousal level
FIGURE 3-2
The Yerkes-Dodson law.
36
MISCELLANEOUS
DETERMI NANTS
AROUSAL
high arousal
disrupts allocation
rl.rvvL
when evaluation
is incorrect
a ro usa I fa i Is to
rise sufficientl y
for good
performance
:AVAILABLE:
i CAPACITY:
I
I
I
MOMENTARY
INTENTIONS
EVALUATION
OF DEMANDS
ON CAPACITY
""",.....------ .......... ,
1/
(
\
,
"
low motivation
"\
or low arousal may
\
prevent adoption
)
of task set
/
--- - -
- ----
",,------- ........
ONGOING ACTIVITIES
/
/'
",.,
RESPONSES
\
\
"-
fatigue
\
and low arousal
\
may interfere with }
the evaluation
/
of performance /
'.........
..........
---."", ,,//
FIGURE 3-3
Effects of high and low arousal on attention and performance.
(Malmo, 1965; Malmo & Surwillo, 1960). Fatigue and sleep deprivation
apparently increase the difficulty of continuous performance, and the
motivated subject compensates for the added difficulty by increasing his
effort.
In general, then, if an initially drowsy person is given a task, he
will wake up and perform. In the terms of an effort model, it may be
more accurate to say that the person will perform and wa~e up, since
it is the demand of the performance that causes the increase of arousal
and of capacity. The occasional failures of this feedback system are best
explained by motivational factors (Broadbent, 1971). The fatigued or
sleepy subject may (1) fail to adopt a task set; or (2) fail to evaluate the
quality of his own performance. Figure 3-3 indicates that, if failures in
a task are not detected, the system will reach equilibrium at low levels
of both arousal and performance. A motivational interpretation explains
both the dramatic effect of knowledge of results (KR) on the performance of sleep-depriv,ed subjects (Wilkinson, 1961, 1963), and the original
Yerkes-Dodson discovery that the speed of discrimination learning depends on the intensity of the stress that motivates learning.
The detrimental effects of over-arousal must be explained in other
terms, however. The allocation of capacity appears to change systematically when arousal is high, and this change causes a decrement in the
performance of certain tasks. The next section reviews the evidence for
this conclusion.
Easterbrook (1959) presented a theory which was intended to explain both the decrement of task performance with increasing arousal,
and the observation that this decrement occurs sooner in complex tasks
than in simple ones. He proposed that an increase of arousal causes a
restriction of the range of cues that the organism uses in the guidance of
action.
This hypothesis explains the Yerkes-Dodson law as follows: consider a task which requires the simultaneous processing of a certain number of cues. When arousal is low, selectivity is also low, and irrelevant
cues are accepted uncritically. When arousal increases, selectivity increases also, and performance improves because irrelevant cues are more
likely to be rejected. With further increases of arousal, however, the
continuing restriction of the range of usable cues eventually causes relevant cues to be ignored, and performance deteriorates again, in accordance with the Yerkes-Dodson law. With the additional assumption that
the range of necessary cues is narrower for simple than for complex tasks,
this argument implies that the optimal level of arousal should be relatively high in simple tasks. It also implies~ that chronically over-aroused
individuals should perform poorly in complex tasks and relatively better
in simple tasks. There is considerable evidence that both conclusions are
valid.
Easterbrook marshalled much research support for the narrowing
of attention under high arousal. For example, he cited an experiment by
Bahrick, Fitts, and Rankin (1952) in which subjects were engaged in two
tasks: continuous tracking of a target, and monitoring the occurrence of
occasional signals in the visual periphery. When the incentive pay for
both tasks was increased, performance of the central task improved, and
performance of the peripheral task deteriorated. Similar findings were
also described by Bursill (1958), who manipulated arousal by making his
subjects work under conditions of extreme heat and humidity. The balance of attention to central and peripheral tasks was altered in conditions of high arousal.
38
creased until he could do so. The task was performed both in quiet and
tillder intellse continllous noise. The noise had a slight beneficial effect
on the detection of the heavily printed word. Of course, when that word
was at threshold, the Inore finely printed word paired with it was hardly
visible. When the subject was required to identify the less visible word,
however, the word in heavy print must have been clear and obvious. The
"pull" of that stimulus was apparently harder to resist in noise than in
quiet, because the identification of the faint word was significantly impaired by the presence of noise.
Another experiment reported by Broadbent (1971, p. 430) also suggests that the ability to select relevant stimuli is impaired by arousal.
Subjects were briefly shown an array of red and white digits and were
asked to report as many digits of one specified color as they could. Performance in this selective task deteriorated under loud noise. In contrast, noise was associated with a slight performance improvement when
subjects were told to write as many digits as pOSSible, regardless of color.
In contrast to the impairment of effective selection in Broadbent's
experiments, there are situations in which selective attention to relevant
stimuli appears to improve under noise stress. One of these situations is the
rod and frame test, in which a subject in a darkened room is to adjust a
faintly luminous rod to the vertical. The rod is enclosed within a tilted
luminous frame which suggests a false orientation. To determine the true
vertical, the subject must ignore this visual cue and rely on kinesthetic
sensations. Performance in this task improves in the presence of loud
background noise (Oltman, 1964).
Another task in. which performance improves in noise is the .Stroop
test, which will be discussed in more detail in C~apter 6. In the most
difficult condition of this test, subjects are shown a card in which names
of colors are printed in inks of different colors. They are required to report the color of the ink in which each word is printed, suppressing the
tendency to read the word itself. Performance in this condition improves
in loud noise (Agn.ew & Agllew, 1963; C'allaway & Stone, 196;0; Houston,
1969; Houston & Jones, 1967). What improves in noise is specifically the
ability to control interference. Thus, there is no interference when subjects merely name the colors of neutral symbols, and performance in this
easier condition is actually worse in noise than in quiet (Houston, 1969;
Houston & Jones, 1967).
Although these results appear to support Easterbrook's hypothesis
that high arousal enhances selectivity, Houston and Jones (1967) found
reasons to doubt this interpretation. Noting that drug stimulants and
noise do not produce identical effects on the Stroop test (Callaway &
Stone, 1960; Quarton & Talland, 1962), they suggested that it is the struggle to inhibit irrelevant responses to the noise which enhances the sub-
40
42
& Mandell, 1965; Berlyne, Borsa, Hamacher & Koenig, 1966; Berlyne &
Carey, 1968). Thus, short-term memory appears to be impaired by high
arousal (Easterbrook, 1959), while long-term memory improves. Further
evidence for the dependence of short-term memory on arousal was obtained in studies of the diurnal rhythm. Physiological arousal level is
known to increase gradually during the day (Kleitman, 1963), and performance in most tasks shows a corresponding improvement. Immediate
memory, however, shows a significant decrease between morning and
afternoon (Baddeley, Hatter, Scott & Snashall, 1970; Blake, 1967). The
interpretation of these results has usually been in terms of a direct effect
of arousal level on the consolidation of memory traces. An alternative hypothesis is that subjects engage in more active rehearsal when highly
aroused, and that the effects of such rehearsal are beneficial for longterm retention and detrimental for short-term recall.
In summary, the evidence reviewed in these sections suggests that
a state of high arousal is associated with the following effects: (1) narrowing of attention; (2) increased lability of attention; (3) difficulties in
controlling attention by fine discriminations; and (4) systematic changes
of strategy in various tasks. On the other hand, a state of extremely low
arousal may cause: (1) a failure to adopt a task set; (2) a failure in the
evaluation of one's performance, resulting in an insufficient adjustment
of the investment of capacity to the demands of the task (see Fig. 3-3).
(GSR) and the dilation of the pupil. However, Sokolov has distinguished
the orientation reaction to novel stimuli from the defensive reaction to
aversive and painful stimuli. The arousal pattern is commonly identified
with the defensive reaction. The most important difference between
orientation and defense is that the OR is characterized by vasoconstriction
in the limbs and vasodilation in the head, while the defensive reaction includes generalized vasoconstriction. Sokolov considered this dissociation of the vascular response so important that he tended to use it
as an operational definition of the OCCllrrence of an orientation reaction.
This usage h~s not generally been adopted in the West, where several
experimenters have confirmed that peripheral vasoconstriction follows
novel stimuli (e.g., Unger, 1964; Zimny & Miller, 1966), while others have
failed (Cohen & Johnson, 1971; Keefe & Johnson, 1970; Raskin, Kotses &
Bever, 1969a, b). Western investigators tend to use the GSR (e.g., Germana, 1968; Maltzman & Raskin, 1965) or a transient desynchronization
of the EEG (Berlyne & Borsa, 1968) as measures of the OR. Unfortunately, these measures do not distinguish the specific OR pattern from
related states, such as emotional arousal and mental effort.
The OR precedes and dominates other responses to the same stimulus (Sokolov, 1963; Zimny & Kienstra, 1967; Zimny & Miller, 1966). This
is shown most dramatically by the reaction to sudden immersion of the
hand in hot water. Although the adaptive reaction to this stimulus is a
peripheral vasodilation which facilitates heat loss, the initial response to
immersion in hot water is a typical OR, complete with peripheral vasoconstriction. Only after a few seconds does the adaptive response predominate. The OR similarly dominates early responses to aversive stimuli,
such as electric shock, which later elicit the defensive pattern of
vasoconstriction in both head and limbs. After a few repetitions the OR
diminishes in both extent and duration, until it eventually vanishes completely and only those adaptive or defensive reactions remain that are
appropriate to the stimulus.
Habituation with repetition is the most important characteristic of
the OR. For example, when a subject is instructed to "listen to tones,"
the first and perhaps the second tones elicit very substantial GSR's, but
a low steady state is reached with a few presentations (Uno & Grings,
1965). The habituation of the OR does not imply that the stimulus is no
longer registered or analyzed. Rather, the subject has learned to expect
the stimulus, and the OR is only released when the characteristics of
the stimulus violate expectations. Sokolov (1969) has provided a compelling demonstration of this expectation effect: when a single flash of
light is omitted from a regular series, a major OR occurs soon after the
time at which the omitted light was due. Similar results have been described by Badia and Defran (19'70), among others.
44
Processing of
Information - -...
novel
stimulus
Improved
perceptual
analysis
FIGURE 3-4
Recursiveness in the processing of a novel stimulus.
"
II:1..1.,&,--
46
lations among its various manifestations are not very high. It is better
viewed as a set of independently controlled changes, which usually
OCCllr together becallse they are often adaptive on the satre occasions.
Figure 3-5 presents such a view of the OR.
MISCELLANEOUS
DETERMI NANTS
MISCELLANEOUS
........---. MANIFESTATIONS
OF AROUSAL
AROUSAL
,I
~
ENDURING
DISPOSITIONS
1 ) Enhance processing
of novel stimulus
2) Inhibit ongoing
activi ty
3) Orient and prepare
lAVAILABLE:
: CAPACITY:I
I
4) Increase arousal
to meet current
or anticipated
demands
ALLOCATION
POLICY
/ I \
r-----/ /
//
~--_
D1J~~
"-
~=D
POSSIBLE ACTIVITIES
EVALUATION
OF DEMANDS
ON
CAPACITY
RESPONSES
FIGURE 3-5
Components of the orientation reaction.
48
REVIEW
4
Looking
Looking 51
high speed. The other type of eye movement is pursuit, a smooth motion
which occurs only when the eye fixates a moving object. Smooth motions
of the eye do not occur in the absence of a moving object in the field,
and the eye cannot be moved slowly from one locus to another, except
in pursuit.
Looking is obviously under voluntary control, because one can decide where to fixate, but conscious and deliberate control of fixation is
actually infrequent. As with other highly skilled components of voluntary performance, such as walking or the maintenance of balance, looking is controlled by a general intention, and consciousness plays a minor
role in the execution of the intended sequence of fixations. The processes
that determine the locus of individual fixations are psychologically silent,
and their feedback is so poor that people do not usually know precisely
where they are looking.
The precise measurement of eye movements and eye position by
photography or electrophysiological measures is a laborious procedure
which requires sophisticated equipment. However, because people are
unaware of the precise locus of their fixation at any time, a simple alternative technique can be used to provide crude estim-ates of fixation
tendencies. Kaufman and Richards (1969) have recently reintroduced
this technique, which was known in the nineteenth century. The equipment consists of a slide or movie projector, fitted with a blue filter and
with a polarizing filter which can be made to rotate at slow speed. A
non-depolarizing projection screen is also required. The observer sees
whatever image is projected on the. screen. In addition, he sees a small
fuzzy line whirling on the screen whenever the polarizing filter rotates.
The line is actually the shadow cast on the observer's fovea by crystalline structures in his eye (called the Haidinger brush). This shadow is
normally invisible because it is stabilized on the retina, but the rotation
of the polarizing filter causes the shadow to disappear and reappear
intermittently, and this makes it visible to the observer. Naive observers,
however, are invariably convinced that the whirling shape on the screen
has been projected by the experimenter, and they can be asked occasionally to indicate the position of the shadow on a map, thus providing a
record of where they are looking at the time. Kaufman and Richards
(196-9) have documented the fact that subjects are often ignorant of the
true locus of their fixation. Moreover, they can be exposed to the Haidinger brush repeatedly before discovering its relationship to their eye.
Looking behavior is never random. When one's activities require
the intake of visual information, the movements of the eye adjust to that
function. In the absence of a specific task set, the control of fixation is
handled by enduring dispositions and standard routines of "spontaneous
looking." These routines, many of which are probably innate, tend to
52
SPONTANEOUS LOOKING
In the absence of a specific instruction to search for visual information, spontaneous looking is controlled by enduring dispositions that determine which parts of the field of view should attract and hold the gaze.
Berlyne (1960, 1966) has distinguished two classes of stimuli that attract
spontaneous attention: physical properties, such as the presence of many
contours, and collative properties, such as novelty, complexity, or significance.
The distinction between physical and collative properties is not
sharp, however, because collative properties, in their most elementary
form, can be reduced to physical properties. Novelty and complexity are
important collative properties that control spontaneous attention in the
adult. The inf.ant is already very responsive to the most elementary level
of complexity-an isolated figure in a blank field-and to the most elementary level of novelty-movement (Gesell & Ilg, 1949). Human infants
who are given a choice of two patterns in their visual field (Fantz, 1958)
show an immediate preference for relatively complex stimuli: patterned
stimuli are preferred to homogeneous gray patches (Fantz, 1965a; .Hershenson, Munsinger & Kessen, 1965), and within the first few months
there is a gradual development of preferences for complex random arrays
over simpler displays (Fantz, 1967), for radial over linear patterns, and
for solid over two-dimensional figures (Fantz, 1965b).
Some of the collative factors that attract the spontaneous attention
of human adults have similar effects on the behavior of lower animals.
The effect of novelty on viewing time, for example, is not restricted to
humans: Berkson (1965) has shown a very rapid decrease of viewing
time with repeated exposures in infant chimpanzees. Complexity also
Looking 53
54
flict situation (Berlyne, 1966). The next chapter will show that related
factors also determine which area in the visual field spontaneously
emerges as figure over the background (see Fig. 5-3 on p. 77).
A stimulus which is novel, complex, or incongruous certainly demands greater processing effort than a stimulus distinguished by none
of these properties. Thus, a basic rule of the allocation policy appears
to be that perceptual activities which demand much capacity are favored
over less demanding activities. This rule already controls the looking behavior of infants, and it remains valid in adults.
Although pleasure-seeking is often seen as a basic principle of
behavior, spontaneous looking does not seem to conform to this principle. The best evidence has been obtained in the free-viewing paradigm,
in which subjects are given control of the time they spend viewing a
series of abstract pictures. The behavior of subjects who are given no
specific instructions tends to be similar to the behavior of subjects instructed to linger on "interesting" stimuli, and quite different from that
of subjects who follow a "pleasingness" set. Three-sided shapes, for instance, are judged more pleasant than nine-sided shapes, but they are
looked at less, in the absence of special instructions (Brown & Farha,
1966). Berlyne and Lawrence (1964) and Day (1966) also found a negative correlation between free viewing time and verbal preference for
irregularity of shape. Observations of this kind suggest that the enduring
dispositions which control spontaneous attention reflect epistemic motivation, the need to perceive clearly and to reduce uncertainty.(Berlyne,
1960, 1965; Durham, Nunnally & Lemond, 1971; Nunnally, Faw & Bashford, 1969; Woodworth,1958).
It must be mentioned, however, that spontaneous looking is not
always controlled by epistemic motivation. The widespread use of female
beauty in advertising does not appeal to collative variables. More generally, the needs and values of individuals determine what they find interesting, and what they prefer to look at. Extroverts, for example, prefer
to look at a picture of a party than at a picture of a lone man reading
a book (Bakan & Leckart, 1966). And a subject whose Rorschach responses classify as a "repressor" may studiously avoid a bare-breasted
woman in a picture, concentrating instead on a man reading a newspaper (Luborsky, Blinder & Schimek, 1965).
Yarbus (1967) has studied patterns of fixations during prolonged
observation of pictures. Figure 4-1 presents two of his pictures and typical records of fixation sequences. A striking feature of these records is
their repetitive nature: in the left panel, fixations repeatedly travel back
and forth between the girl's eyes, and in the right panel they repeatedly
climb the trees. The right panel also illustr'1tes the roles of both phYSical
and collative properties in. the control of spontaneous looking: the selec-
Looking
55
FIGURE 4-1
Records of eye movements during the continuous observation of two pictures (from
Eye Movements & Vision by A. L. Yarbus, with permission).
tion of the trees that are often fixated is controlled by the physical
property of brightness contrast, but the large numbers of fixations on
the human figure must be attributed to collative factors.
56
Looking
57
58
because the deliberate control of search required more time and effort
than it could save.
A particularly interesting type of looking decision controls fixations in a monitoring task with multiple targets. Thus, an airline pilot
faces more dials than he can see at a glance, and he must distribute his
looking to maximize the probability that any significant event will be detected soon after it occurs. The probability that a dial contains new information is a function of at least two factors: the overall rate at which
information is conveyed on that dial, and the elapsed time since the
last look at it. Senders (1965) has used the mathematics of information
theory to derive an optimal policy that determines the sequential allocation of looks among dials. He found that trained observers closely approximate optimal looking behavior. Evidently, the system which allocates
looks is able to consider the changing probabilities that each of many
dials will merit a look.
Senders (personal communication) has di~cussed the example of an
adult reading a newspaper beside a swimming pool, while a baby is randomly cra'Yling about in the area. At what intervals will the adult look
up to check the baby's positiol1? The interval will depend on where the
baby was when last seen, al1d on its direction and rate of progress at
the time. It will also depend on the depth of the pool, and on whether
or not it is filled with water.
The duration of fixations appears to be less responsive to momentary
fluctuations of attention than is their location. Although it is possible for
an observer to maintain steady fixation for several seconds, the rate of
fixations is normally much faster, and the fixations are usually rhythmic.
Thus, a conclusion of the study of reading is that the difficulty of reading
material has a greater effect on the number of fixations per line than
on the duration of individllal fixations, which averages 200-225 milli~
seconds (Morton, 1964; Tinker, 1947, 1958). In the observation of pictllres, the common duration of fixation is 300-350 milliseconds (Mackworth
& Bruner, 1970; Yarbus, 1967). Rhythmic motion occurs during uninstructed observation (see Figs. 4-1 and 4-2). Of course, ocular motion is
l1ecessary to prevent loss of vision from retinal stabilization (Riggs, Ratliff, Cornsweet & Cornsweet, 1953), but the spontaneous rate appears to
be considerably faster than is necessary to avoid fading.
Under some cOl1ditions, however, the duration of an individual
fixation may correspond to the attention that the object of fixation reqllires. An interesting pattern of results was reported in a series of studies
by COllld. In the initial experiment, subjects scanned a display of numerals for occurrences of a target numeral (Could & Schaffer, 1965).
Although targets were fixated more often than non-targets, the duration
of fixations on targets and on non-targets was the same. Different results
Looking 59
60
chapter, is another illustration of an attentional effect that is not controlled by fixation, althollgh we usually fixate the figure rather than the
background.
It will be useful to summarize the information presented in this
section and the preceding one, concerning the factors which control
looking.
When fixation is governed by a visual task, the locus of fixation is
determined by an assessment of the probabilities that relevant information will be acquired, and that the acquired information will be useful.
Many factors can contribute to the assessment of these probabilities:
, known base rates for a particular area, and the elapsed time since the
area was scanned (Senders, 1965); the detection of some features of a
possible target, such as its color (Williams, 1966); a preliminary identification of a target (Gould, 1965; Sanders, 196;3); and general knowledge
about the strllcture of the situation (Yarbus, 1967).
When fixation is not controlled by a specific task set, it reverts to
the control of enduring dispositions. Looking and attention are then
spontaneous rather than deliberate. Two sets of enduring dispositions
may be distinguished: innate routines which are triggered by specific
physical features, and more elaborate responses which are mostly triggered by the mismatch between a stimulation and a neuronal model of
expectations, i.e., by collative features.
The more elementary dispositions are usually overridden by a task
set. However, a sudden change of the visual scene will usually elicit
both an orientation reaction and a fixation toward the locus of change,
even when one is engaged in a task. Thus, enduring dispositions and
task set can override one another.
Looking
61
brush technique (Kaufman & Richards, 1969; see p. 51) was used to
detect fixation tendencies. The eye quite regularly fixated the task-related
object, although. that object could provide no useful information. The
hierarchy of the processes that control looking was clearly evident. When
a single object was shown in the field, subjects almost invariably looked
at it, regardless of whether it was relevant or not. When more than one
object was shown, the relevant object was fixated. Finally, when the
subject was questioned about a picture that was no longer present, he
usually fixated that area of the blank screen where the relevant information had been shown.
Are these orientations helpful to performance of the task? In an
attempt to find out, Kahneman and Lass compared subjects' performance
when a relevant object was shown, when an irrelevant object was shown,
and when the screen was blank. No significant effects were found. For
example, subjects produced as many words with a specified letter in the
third position when that letter was shown on the screen and when an
irrelevant letter was projected. The irrelevant letter was fixated, but it
did not interfere. In this study, at least, the preference for fixation on
the relevant letter appeared to serve no purpose. In general, however,
the correspondence of orientation to thought is adaptive, because it ensures that relevant information will be quickly acquired.
An impressive demonstration. of the association between eye movements and internal processing was provided by Bryden (1961) and by
Crovitz and Daves (1962), who showed that the locus of greatest accuracy
in tachistoscopic recognition is related to the direction of eye movements
following the stimulus exposure: for example, when the eye moves to the
right, the far right figures are likely to be reported accurately. This is
true although the eye movement occurs after the exposure and cannot
affect sensory registration in any way.
A series of studies of eye movements during paired-associate learning provides further evidence of the correspondence between the locus of
fixation and the focus of internal processing. The studies also provide a
demonstration of the use of eye movements to test theories about internal
events. A prevalent theory of paired-associate learning suggests that its
first phase is response consolidation (Underwood, Runquist & Schultz,
1959; Underwood & Schultz, 1960). Correspondingly, during early phases
of learning, the eye typically fixates the stimulus, then the response (S-R),
and it lingers on the response item (McCormack & Haltrecht, 1966; McCormack, Haltrecht & Hannah, 1966, 1967). The tendency to fixate the
response item is further enhanced when that item is low in meaningfulness
(McCormack & Hannah, 1967; McCormack & Moore, 1969). The second
stage of paired-associate learning has been identified as a phase of stimulus-response association. In that stage, the typical sequence of fixations
62
is S-R-S, and the eye spends more time fixating the stimulus than the
response. The patterns of fixatioll observed in these ,experiments certainly represent processing effort rather than information intake, because
the exposure time (typically two seconds) is more than sufficient to
acquire two visual nonsense syllables.
There has been much interest in the eye movements of chess players.
De Groot (1966) and Jongman (1968) described the fixation patterns of
master players, who were allowed to study a complex chess situation for
five seconds in order to later reproduce it from memory. Many of the
players immediately perceived the best possible moves for both opponents. Indeed, the master's eye quickly finds the area of main tension
of the game, and the first fixation after the presentation of the display is
already highly selective. Generally, however, the correspondence between the verbalizations of a chess player and his recorded looking behavior is far from perfect, and the master player often fails to fixate a
piece about which he is much concerned. In the initial study of a position, possible sequences of moves are clearly perceived, but rarely mirrored by eye movements. When a player is allowed a longer period to
study the board, the correspondence between fixations and the moves
considered apparently improves after the first 10 or 15 seconds (Simon &
Barenfeld, 1969; Tikhomirov & Poznyanskaya, 1966). In general, these
investigations suggest that the movements of the "mind's eye" are correlated with those of the physical eye, but also that the correlation is
optional rather than obligatory.
Another observation which demonstrates the optional nature of
the correspondence between eye and thought was obtained by Kaplan
alld Schoenfeld (1966). They showed subjects five-letter anagram problems which could all be solved by the same transposition of the order
of the five letters. Those subjects who discovered the rule usually announced their response after fixating each of the letters exactly once, in
the order of their position in the solution. But other subjects were able
to solve the anagrams withollt discovering the rllle, and their sequence
of fixations did not correspond to the solution.
Gopher (1971) studied the patterns of eye movements accompanying different tasks of auditory attention. The auditory messages were
presented by earphones in his experiments, and eye movements could
serve no function of sensory acquisition. Neve~theless, highly consistent
patterns were observed. Eye movements were markedly inhibited when
sllbjects listened to a monallral message (i.e., a message presented to a
single ear), or when they were exposed to dichotic messages (i.e., different messages to the two ears) and were told to focus attention on one
and ignore the other. When focusing attention, subjects almost always
make a large saccade at the beginning of the message, invariably in the
Looking
63
direction of the relevant ear and they maintain their fixation in that
direction during the entire message. Dividing attention elicits a different
pattern of eye movements. Gopher studied a task in which the subject is
instructed to listen to both messages and to repeat target words that can
be presented to either ear. When the target words are distinguished by
a physical property (e.g., a word spoken by a male voice inserted in a
message spoken by a female voice), subjects primarily fixate ahead, although they make an eye movement whenever a critical word is heard.
When the critical word is defined by a semantic property (e.g., an animal
name) the rate of eye movements doubles, and rhythmic alternations of
small saccades become very freqllent.
Gopher (1971) found that deliberate fixation to right or left can
alter performance in a task of divided auditory attention. His subjects
were asked to monitor dichotic messages for the occurrence of semantically defined target words. Occasionally, two target words were presented simultaneously. As will be shown in Chapter 8, subjects often
detect only one member of such a simultaneous pair, and right-handed
subjects most often respond only to the word presented to their right
ear. This pattern was even more pronounced when subjects were instructed to fixate 20 degrees to the right of center. When they were
instructed to fixate left of center, the imbalance between the ears vanished. The result could reflect either a shift in the spatial focus of attention or a temporary alteration of the normal pattern of cerebral dominance (Kinsbourne, 1970, 1972).
The relation between auditory attention and the direction of the
gaze is an important source of cues in situations of social interaction
(Argyle & Dean, 1965; Exline, 1963, 1971; Kendon, 1967; Strongman,
1970). People are extremely sensitive to eye-to-eye contact and show unusually high acuity in judging whether someone else is gazing directly
at them (Gibson & Pick, 1963). The listener in a conversation tends to
gaze directly at the speaker, and this gaze, which conveys continued
interest, provides support for the speaker. The listener normally averts
his gaze when he prepares to speak, probably indicating that he is turning attention to the preparation of his own message. The listener's averted
gaze is often accepted as a tacit instruction for the speaker to fall silent.
The direction of the gaze aversion which accompanies the onset
of active thought is highly consistent for different individuals and for
different classes of problems. About half the population initially look
to the right when they begin to think about a verbal problem, and the
other half look to the left (Day, 1964, 1967a, b). Kinsbourne (1972) noted
that movements to the left are relatively more frequent when subjects
solve spatial problems than when they solve verbal problems, and he
also,showed Significant differences between right-handed and left-handed
,/
64
subjects. Both observations suggest that the lateral movement may itldicate a temporary preponderance of activity in one or the other hemisphere of the brain. Other investigators have studied various correlates
of the preferred direction of the lateral eye movement. Thus, Bakan
(1971) reported that left-movers are more hypnotizable (the correlation
was 0.44), and he confirmed Day's observation that the EEG of leftmovers has a prominent alpha component. Bakan and Shotland (1969)
also showed that right-movers read significantly faster than left-movers
and are less prone to interference on the Stroop test. Perhaps most surprising, a significant negative correlation was fOtlnd between the eye
movement tendencies of spouses (Day, 1967a); right-movers tend to
marry left-movers!
Turning inward to think is also associated with a dramatic increase
in the rate of eye movements (Lorens & Darrow, 1962), which contrasts
with the inhibition of eye movements during attentive listening (Gopher,
1971). Antrobus, Antrobus, and Singer (1964) noted that both active
thinking and deliberate attempts to suppress a conscious wish or fantasy are associated with a very high saccadic rate. Relaxed, passive, or
wish-fulfilling thought leads to reduced motility. The frequency of blinks
follows similar rules. These results suggest that changes of fixation and
blinks punctuate changes of mental content, a conclusion which is also
consistent with the observation th3:t LSD causes a very high saccadic
rate (Kohn & Bryden, 1965). It is notable that mental work increases
ocular motility even in congenitally blind subjects (Amadeo & Gomez,
1966).
In summary, the involvement of eye movements in mental processes
attests to the linkage between the eye and the focus of attention. Thoughts
often "move" over a representation of space, and the position of the eyes
tends to reflect the current direction of attention. Eye position also
serves to label the direction of sensory attention, even in the absence of
visual input, and this pattern of selective orientation may affect the
allocation of auditory attention. Finally, the rate of eye movements often
corresponds to the rate of thinking, even in the absence of any spatial
component.
REVIEW
Looking
65
5
Attention and Perception
The preceding chapter was concerned with overt orientations that reflect the allocation of attention. We now turn to the study of central
mechanisms of selection and allocation. The present treatment identifies
the allocation of attention to perceived objects with the figural process,
which selects certain areas of the field as figure and relegates others to
the background.
The first section outlines a model of some stages of perceptual
analysis, and the second introduces a taxonomy of attention tasks. The
remainder of the chapter is concerned with the explication of the processes of unit formation, figural emphasis, recognition, and perceptual
interpretation, and with the relation of these processes to selective
attention.
SENSORY
REGISTRATION
AND STORAGE
ALLOCATION
POLICY
(Attention and effort)
Perceptual
Readiness
UNIT FORMATION
Preliminary
segregation of
perceived objects
FIGURAL EMPHASIS
Attention is allocated
to objects
ACTIVATION OF
RECOGNI TION UNITS
Possible
interpretations
for some objects
SELECTION OF
INTERPRETATIONS
Perceptual
in te rp re ta t ions
are se Iec ted
RESPONSE SELECTION
FIGURE 5-1
Schematic model for perception and attention.
68
70
(2)
Selection of inputs. The relevant and irrelevant stimuli are discriminated by an obvious physical characteristic, allowing the
subject to adopt a stimulus set. Broadbent (1958, 1971) calls this
type of early selection filtering. An auditory example of inputselection task could be: "Listen to the message that comes from
the left; ignore other messages." According to the model introduced in the preceding section, the selection of inputs is mediated
by the allocation of attention to the relevant inputs at the stage of
figural emphasis
Selection of targets. Here the subject is instructed to search for a
designated target. The distinction between selection of inputs and
selection of targets is' that the relevant items are rare and relatively
71
diffi~ult to find in the latter task. However, the mechanism of selection appears to be similar in the two cases.
(3)
(4)
TABLE
5-1
Stimulus
Task
Labels
72
questions eventually refer to the same object, the word-five-that-isprinted-at-the-bottom, but the sequence of operations that lead to this
object are different in the two tasks.
The reader will probably agree that it is easier"to find the word at
the bottom and read it than to find the "five" and report its location. The
sequence of operations on attributes is important because the attributes
which allow the most effective control of figural emphasis are not the
same as the attributes to which responses are most easily attached. The
example illustrates the general rule that it is easy to direct attention by
the attribute of location, and easy to control the final response by the
attribute of shape. It is also easy to control visual attention by the
attribute of color (Uleman & Reeves, 1971; von Wright, 1970; Williams,
1966).
UNIT FORMATION
(- A )
( B)
,-:"1-') )'
r( "
) .,})
.,') J
~ <.
l :J ) ) ~ \ ) "-(.
Jl1~()
\., (
(C )
( D)
TTTTTTTO
TTTTTTTT
TT
TTOOOO
TTTTTOOO
TTTTTTOO
( E)
T T TTL
TTTTTLLL
TTTTTTLL
T T
T T
T TTL
T T
T T T
T T T
(G)
FIGURE
5-2
Determinants of grouping.
73
74
75
76
FIGURAL EMPHASIS
( B)
( A)
~
r~
) (J
>'
\ - ,,)
r ,""\ I
' . ) J'\
) ) . . ~ ) "'l
f
J
J
'-
'J
( D)
(C )
( E)
A
A
A
A
A
( F)
A
A
xxx XXX XX
A
A
XXOXXXXX
XXXXXXXX
A A A A A A A A A
A A A A A A A
A A
A
A
A
A A
A
A
( G )
ABCDEFGJ
KLPQRIUV
YABCDEFG
FIGURE 5-3
Determinants of figural emphasis.
77
78
(2)
(3)
79
Collative factors are illustrated in panels F and G;, where the odd
element tends to "stand out," as does the CAPITALIZED word in
this sentence. There may be an impression of three-dimensionality,
although not as pronounced as in panels A-D.
The effect of intentions is easily observed by deliberately selecting an element in any of the panels, e.g., a particular letter in
panel G. One may choose a larger unit, but at a certain cost in the
experience of attensity. It is this feature of the experience of attention which suggests the frequently used metaphors of "a beam
of light of varied width" (Hernandez-Peon, 1964) or "a lens of
variable power" (Eriksen & Rohrbaugh, 19-70; Eriksen & Hoffman,
1972).
80
occurring relatively sooner than the other. Consequently, the two appear
to be simultaneous when the attended stimulus is actually shown later
than the other (see p. 137).
81
SENSORY
REGISTRATION
00
t..o
ENDURING
DISPOSITIONS:
( 1 ) Standard rules:
moving objects, warm
colors, etc.
( 2 ) Collative variables,
,.,---.........
//
"\
Rules of grouping: \
similarity,
proximity, etc.
""
UNIT FORMATION
/"_
FIGURAL EMPHASIS
I/
(
\
MOMENTARY
INTENTIONS
(e. g., search for
blue objects, listen
to man on the right,
etc. )
/'
Tentative
\
'\
recognition of \
signi ficant obj ect.
\
Violation of
/
expectations
\
""'------"'"
,/
FIGURE 5-4
Attention, grouping, and figural selection.
ACTIVATION OF
RECOGNITION UNITS
I.'
I.'
..
-........,
Effects of
coding
availability
"
/
--'"
"
\
84
direct attention to the target. By that time the display has been removed,
and attentioll must be directed toward a fading representation. The frequency of adjacency errors indicates that spatial confusions are likely to
occur in that case. These difficulties in "addressing" a target are increased
both by crowding the items and by presenting a large number of items.
Differences in reaction time as a function of addressing difficulties can
be found even with clearly visible stimuli (Eriksen & Hoffman, 1972).
A particularly impressive observation was reported by Snyder (1972),
who found adjacency errors even when the relevant target called attention to itself. Subjects were briefly shown a display of 12 different letters.
One of these differed from the others, in color, in orientation, or by
being fragmented. The subjects were required to report the odd letter.
In many cases they erred and reported one of the letters adjacent to the
target. This result provides strong evidence for recursiveness in the control of attention.
The examples that have been discussed so far were all visual, but
the concepts of grouping and figural selection apply to other modalities
as well. There is a clear experience of grouping in audition, both in
space and over time. There is also an experience of figure-ground organization: as we listen to a concerto, the soloist often provides the figure,
and we can also deliberately choose to attend to one group of instruments when the orchestra is playing.
The main conclusions of the preceding discussion of unit formation
and figural emphasis are illustrated in Figure 5-4. The figure suggests
that the process of figural emphasis should be viewed as the allocation
of effort, capacity, or attention to the perceptual elaboration of some perceptual units in preference to others. The allocation policy is governed
by enduring dispositions and by momentary intentions. As was the case
in the control of eye movements, the enduring dispositions that control
figural selection are of two types: standard rules that allocate attention
whell certain physical characteristics are detected, and collative features
such as novelty or significance. The standard rules can be applied before
the stimulus information makes contact with recognition units. Collative
variables, on the other hand, can only affect figural selection through a
recursive path.
The analysis of figural emphasis as a special instance of allocation
of attention implies that perceptual processing draws on the limited
capacity system that was discussed in Chapters 2 and 3. This conclusion
is supported by the frequent observations of perceptual deterioration in
a crowded and -complex field (Eriksen & Lappin, 1967; Eriksen & Rohrbaugh, 1970; Keeley, 1969; Mackworth, 1965; Rummelhart, 1970). In an
important study, Sperling et ale (1971) showed that information is extract~d
at approximately the same overall rate from arrays of varying complexity,
85
86
evidence that the visual code and the name code for letters are in fact
produced in parallel, although the production of the name code is
slower. In the terms of the present chapter, this means that the visual
letter "a" simultaneously activates at least two recognition units: a unit
that is specific to the lower-case "a," and a unit for which both the
lower-case and the capital forms are appropriate stimuli.
The conclusion that two physically distinct'stimuli such as "a" and
"A" can make contact with a common recognition unit without the mediation of prior recognitions is of fundamental importance, because it contradicts a common view of perception as consisting of the sequential
production of increasingly abstract codes for a stimulus.
From the conclusion that "a" and "A" activate a common recognition unit, there is .but a small step to the idea that all numerals may activate a recognition unit, and all letters another. Evidence from both reaction time (Posner, 1970) and visual search (Brand, 1971) indicates that
this is the case. In contrast, there seems to be no common recognition
unit for vowels (Posner & Mitchell, 1967), and the identification of a
letter as a vowel or consonant therefore requires the elicitation of the
name code for that letter. As Posner (1970) pointed out, the availability
of an immediate code common to all letters or all digits, and the absence
of such a code for vowels, reflects the manner in which these materials
are learned. With. very prolonged practice, a common recognition unit
can apparently be formed even for totally arbitrary collections (Rabbitt,
1967).
The very slow process in which recognition units evolve has been
described in an important text by Gibson (1969). In a recent treatment
of attention, Broadbent (1971) spoke of a slow process of categorizing,
by which different stimulus configurations which are associated with the
same response (e.g., the letter "a" in different handwritings) eventually
come to elicit the same category state (here called perceptual interpretation). This type of perceptual learning results in a recognition system
which is both highly refined and well adapted' to the requirements of the
environment.
88
suffice to identify a less familiar event. Bruner (1957) has offered a classic
treatment of this perceptual readiness. He described the main manifestations of readiness by the example of a man who is peculiarly ready to
see apples: "The apples will be more easily and swiftly recognized, a
wider range of things will be identified or misidentified as apples, and in
consequence the correct or best fitting identity of these other inputs will
be masked [Bruner, 1957, p. 130]." The main determinants of the perceptual readiness for a particular stimulus are the past frequency of its
occurrence, its probability of occurrence in the momentary context, and
its present significance to the individual.
Recent treatments of perceptual readiness have increasingly used
the tools and concepts of signal-detection theory. Some of the same concepts have also become central to theoretical treatments of attention'
(Broadbent, 1971; Norman, 1968; Treisman & Geffen" 1967). It will therefore be useful to briefly introduce some essential terms of signal-detection theory (for a more detailed, highly readable treatment, see Coombs,
Dawes & Tversky, 1971).
Signal detection theory was originally developed to account for
studies of detection and discrimination with a yes-no response (Green &
Swets, 1966; Tanner & Swets, 1954), in the general paradigm illustrated in
Table 5-2. In this paradigm the experimenter presents the target .stimulus
on some trials but not on others, and the observer indicates on each
trial whether he believes the target was present or absent. The four
entries in Table 5-2 represent the possible outcomes of such a trial.
The most obvious observation in this situation is the variability of
the subject's behavior on repeated occurrences of the same condition.
He sometimes says "Yes" and sometimes says "No" both when the stimulus
has occurred and when it has not. Signal detection theory explains this
unreliability by assuming the existence of internal noise, which causes
the value of a hypothetical sensory magnit~de to vary randomly over
time, even in the absence of a signal. When a signal is shown, the sensory magnitude increases by a certain amount, depending on the intensity of the Signal. If the signal is weak, it is possible that the sensory
magnitude produced by the combination of signal and noise is less than
TABLE 5-2
The basic structure of the signal-detection paradigm.
Response
Present
No
Miss
Yes
Hit
Correct
Rejection
False
Alarm
Stimulus
Absent
values that occasionally occur by noise alone. The subject, of course, cannot know whether the sensory magnitude that he experiences on a given
trial is due to noise /alone or to a combination of noise and signal. What
he does know is that higher values of sensory magnitude are more likely
to occur when the signal was presented than when it was not. Under
these circumstances, a rational observer will adopt a criterion, i.e., determine in advance a critical value of sensory magnitude. On any trial he
will say "Yes" if the sensory magnitude exceeds that criterion, and "No"
otherwise. The vallIe of the criterion is often labeled by the Greek letter
Beta.
Figure 5-5 illustrates these concepts by two elementary examples.
In both panels A and B, the distribution at the left represents the probability that a value of sensory magnitude will arise from the internal
noise of the system. The distribution of noise is assumed to be normal,
and it has been standardized so that its mean is zero and its standard deviation is one. The two panels also present the hypothetical distributions
of sensory magnitude for trials on which the signal is shown. The
illustrations refer to the simplest possible situation, where the variance
of the distribution is not affected by the introduction of a signal. The
same considerations apply to the more realistic models, which assume
that the signal causes both a shift of the distribution to the right and an
increased variance. The signal in panel A is weak, and it causes the distribution of values to shift by only half a standard deviation, relative
to the noise distribution. The distance between the two distributions,
in standard units, is the sensitivity parameter of the theory. Sensitivity is commonly denoted by the symbol d'; in panel A, d' == 0.5. In
both panels A and B, two values of the criterion are indicated, at values
of 0.0 and 2.0 on the scale of sensory magnitude. A subject who adopts a
criterion of 0.0 will say "Yes" if the value of sensory magnitude exceeds
the mean of the noise distribution. A Beta of 2.0 signifies that the ob..
. server says "Yes" only if sensory magnitude is higher than the mean of
the noise distribution by two staIldarddeviations or more.
The four panels of Table 5-3 present the expected performance of an
observer in the four situations illtIstrated in Figure 5-5 (d' == 0.5 and
TABLE 5-3
Distribution of responses in four signal-detection problems.
Beta == 0.0
d' == 0.5
Beta == 2.0
d'== 1.5
Beta == 0.0
d' == 1.5
Beta == 2.0
"Response
No
Yes
No
Yes
No
Yes
No
Yes
Present
,Absent
.308
.500
.692
.500
.933
.976
.067
.024
.067
.500
.933
.500
.692
.976
.308
.024
d'- 0.5
. Stimulus
Beta = 0.0
( A)
No
Yes
+-- --+
Yes
~
-2.0
-1.5 -1.0
-0.5
0.5
1.0
1.5
2.0
'---y--J
d'
Sensory magn itude
( B)
Beta = 0.0
No
Beta = 2.0
No
Yes
+--
Yes
+-
-2.0 -1.5
-1.0 -0.5
0.5
1.0
1.5
2.0
d'
Sensory magnitude
FIGURE 5-5
Constructions from signal-detection theory.
d' ==.1.5; Beta == 0.0 and Beta == 2.0). Note that performance in. the
absence of a stimulus depends only on the criterion, while performance
when the stimulus is present depends on both the criterion (Beta) and
the discriminability of the signal (d').
In a real experiment, of course, the data are obtained in the form
illustrated by Table 5-3, and the structure illustrated in Figure 5-5 is inferred from these data. Given the four entries in a table of experimental
results, d' and Beta can be calculated, by using the assumptions of. the
90
91
The distinction between sensitivity and criterion suggests an elegant approach to the fascinating and intractable question of perception
vs. 'response. It is tempting to identify d' as a measure of perceptual
efficiency arid Beta as a measure of response readiness. Indeed, the ease
with which Beta can be altered in the detection paradigm appears to
support such an identification. In the context of recognition, however, a
low value of Beta for a particular recognition response has gentline
effects on perception, as shown in the following ~xample.
Consider the picture of the room in panel A of Figure 5-6. All ob. servers see it as a normal rectangular room, but in fact it is not, as shown
92
FIGURE 5-6
Interior and exterior views of a distorted room (Ittelson, 1952, with
permission).
by the exterior view of panel B. The distorted room was carefully constructed so that when it is viewed or photographed from a particular
spot, the image that it casts on the retina, or on the photographic plate,
is identical to the image cast by a rectangular room (Ittelson & Kil-
94
sion is that subjects' incorrect responses in the word-recognition task include large numbers of frequent words (Broadbent, 1967; Brown &
Rubenstein, 1961; Pollack, Rubenstein & Decker, 1960)~ In the absence of
stimulus information the subject is more likely to guess that a highfrequency word has been presented, which is clear evidence for a criterion bias. For a more detailed discussion of this conclusion, see Catlin
(1969) and M. Treisman (1971).
Perceptual readiness probably mediates the context effects that play
a crucial role in our ability to recognize events on the basis of impovern
ished and degraded cues. Thus, the recognition unit for "your is almost
certainly activated to some degree whenever we are exposed to the word
"year." Nevertheless, mistakes of interpretation will be rare because of
the probable presence of contextual cues which increase the readiness
to recognize one of these words ("please give me y-r coat") or the other
("he will graduate next y-r").
In Figure 5-7, the concepts of signal-detection theory are related
to the information-processing sequence which is the topic of this chapter.
The figure suggests that the sensitivity (d') and the criterion (Beta) for
any response are each affected by events at several stages of the
sequence.
Sensitivity (d') is affected by the quality of the information that is
delivered to the recognition units. Sensitivity is high if the initial signal
was loud and clear. There'is also evidence to suggest that sensitivity is
high for an object to which we pay attention, and which has been selected at the earlier stage of figural emphasis (Broadbent & Gregory,
1963; Kahneman, Beatty & Pollack, 1967; Moray & O'Brien, 1967; Treisman & Geffen, '1967). In addition, sensitivity is affected by the availability
of recognition units: if an American and a Chinese adult are compared in their ability to discriminate Chinese characters, the outcome
will surely be a vast superiority of d' favoring the person who has had
lifelong experience with these characters.
The criterion level (Beta) is determined by events at two different
stages of the sequence. A state of perceptual readiness affects the selection of interpretations, in the manner illustrated by the example of the
distorted room. In addition, a criterion bias' may operate at the subsequent stage of response selection. A subject in a tachistoscopic experiment, having tentatively identified a briefly exposed word as WHORE
may nevertheless opt for WHOLE as a s~fer response, lest his mind be
thought dirty.
It is assumed in Figure 5-7 that the response system is itself noisefree. Both d' and Beta will be altered if there is unreliability in the
selection or execution of responses. Imagine,' for example, that the observer indicates a yes-no response by 'pressing one of two keys, which
Quality of
Sensory Signal
SENSORY
REGISTRATION
increases d '
UNIT FORMATION
'V
Allocation
of Attention
increases d '
\/
\V
'li
FIGURAL EMPHASIS
I
I
\{J
\1/
Availability
of
Recognition
Units
\ It
ACTIVATION OF
RECOGNITION UNITS
increases d '
\ II
, I
1.,
\11
W
Perceptual
Readiness
SELECTION OF
INTERPRETATIONS
lowers Beta
I I
I I
I I
I I
Response
Readiness
lowers Beta
SELECTION OF
RESPONSES
FIGURE 5-7
Determinants of sensitivity and criterion level.
95
96
..
are so close together that he presses the wrong key on a significant number of trials. Such response noise invariably lowers d', and usually alters
Beta as well. It is probably safe to ignore the effects of response noise
in most psychophysical experiments. When signal-detection methods are
applied to studies of attention, however, the possible occurrence of careless responses should not be neglected.
Two of the five processes mentioned in Figure 5-7 are neither new
nor controversial: the quality of sensory registration surely affects d'
while response readiness is reflected in the value of Beta. The three
remaining processes . deserve a final 'comment.
The model of Figure 5-7 assumes that the allocation of attention to
an object enchances the sensitivity of the system (d') in dealing with that
object. This view is similar to the treatment of focal attention by Neisser
(1967). Other authors have adopted the position that the withdrawal of
attention from a stimulus causes a lowering of sensitivity, equivalent to
an attenuation of the input (Broadb'ent, 1971; Broadbent & Gregory,
1963; Treisman, 1960; Treisman & Geffen, 1967). But Norman (1968) has
proposed that all effects of selective attention can be explained by rapid
alterations of criterion biases. We shall be concerned with this issue in
Chapters 7 and 8.
The idea that the availability of recognition units is an important
determinant of sensitivity was emphasized by Broadbent (1971). In the
absence of appropriate recognition units, the selection of an appropriate
interpretation becomes impossible.
Broadbent's term for perceptual readiness is pigeonholing,which
he defines as "the process by which the nervous system adjusts so as to
allocate larger or smaller numbers of states of evidence to each category
state [p. xi]." In his terms, for example, the category state "rectangular
room" is a pigeonhole to which states of evidence (corresponding to
stimulus events, except for the effects of "noise" in the nervous system)
are very liberally assigned. Pigeonholing is reflected in the setting of the
criterion for a particular recognition. Pigeonholing, or perceptual readiness can affect the experience of perception. By suitable analyses, however, it is possible to distinguish between perceptual changes which
represent a shift of criteria and other perceptual changes which represent alterations of the sensitivity of perceptual analysis.
REVIEW
6
Attention to Attributes
DISCRIMINATION LEARNING
The relation between attention and discrimination learning, origi11ally stated by Lashley (1942; Lashley & Wade, 1946), was rediscovered
and enthusiastically studied in the 1960s (e.g., Fellows, 1968; Lovejoy,
1968; Sutherland & Mackintosh, 1971; Trabasso & Bower, 1968). In a
typical discrimination problem the human or animal subject is faced
with stimuli that differ in many attributes, such as shape, color, size, and
number. The subject must learn to respond to a particular class of stimuli, defined by a simple rule which he must discover, e.g., "all large ob~)
98
Attention to Attributes
99
100
100
Color-form obiect
Learners, MA 2-4
N = 21
Learners, MA 4-6
N = 20
90
80
(1)
Nonlearners, MA 2-4
(N = 19)
70
-c
0
.....
0
60
(1)
s..
s..
.....
50
Chance
(1)
0
s..
(1)
a..
40
(1)
30
20
10
20
40
60
80
100
120
140
160
180
200
220
240
Trials ( T )
FIGURE 6-1
Effects of intelligence on discrimination learning are shown in the average
performance of four groups classified by mental age and achievement. From
Handbook of Mental Deficiency, edited by N. R. Ellis. Copyright 1963 by
McGraw-Hill, Inc. Used with permission of McGraw-Hill Book Co.
man & House, 1963) incorporate a two-stage notion.. These models have
much in common, although they differ in important details, such as the
number of dimensions that can be attended on each trial, and the precise
effects of nonreinforcement on attention and on the overt response. All
attention models can account for either continuity or discontinuity in
learning. Continuous learning is typically observed when the relevant
dimension is very obviolls, so that the subject may be in stage (b) from
the very first trial. On the other hand, sharply discontinuous learning is
predicted if the relevant dimension is obscure or if the learner is very
slow (see Fig. 6-1). Formal theories of discrimination learning are concerned with the details of several effects that Sutherland (1964) related
to his two-stage model: the transfer of discrimination training along a
dimension (Sutherland, Mackintosh & Mackintosh, 1965); the reversal
shift effect (Kendler & Kendler, 1962, 1970a, 1970b); and the overtraining
Attention to Attributes
101
reversal effect (Lovejoy, 1966, 1968; Mackintosh, 1964, 1965; Wolford &
Bower, 1969).
Allattentional theories of discrimination learning assume that the
various attributes of objects are not equally attended. In the simplest
version of such a theory, only one dimension is attended when the discrimination is learned. For example, a pigeon may be selectively reinforced for pecking at a green circle, rather than at a red triangle (Jones,
1954). Shape and color are both relevant to this discrimination, and it is
of interest to discover what the animal learned. Does it now peck at circles, or at green objects, or at both? The answer is obtained by studying
transfer to a situation in which one of the relevant cues is kept constant
while the other is varied. There is general agreement that individual subjects in animal experiments typically learn only one of the relevant cues
and respond well to that cue and poorly to all others. The selected cue,
however, may be different for different subjects or classes of subjects
(Jones, 1954; Reynolds, 1961; Sutherland & Holgate, 1966; Sutherland &
Mackintosh, 1964).
The dominance of a single cue in a complex of relevant cues is not
restricted to lower animals. Trabasso and Bower (1968) illustrated various manifestations of cue dominance in a series of experiments with
student subjects. Thus, subjects who have solved the problem on one
cue often fail to notice any change when an initially irrelevant cue is
made relevant (and redundallt) in a later stage of the experiment. The
results of transfer tests are usually consistent with.a dominance hypothesis, although some subjects do solve discrimination problems on several
cues. Trabasso and Bower (1968) found no consistent differences in
learning rate between those subjects who solved a problem by two cues,
and those who solved it by only one.
Some factors that make a particlllar cue more salient than others
have been identified. Discriminability is such a factor. For example, if
ellipses are presented which vary greatly in overall size and only slightly
in eccentricity, alld both size ,and shape are relevant, then size rather
than shape will' dominate behavior in a concept-identification task
(Archer, 1962; Imai & Garner, 1965; Trabasso, 1963). The corresponding
effect in animal learning is called overshadowing (Mackintosh, 1971).
Prior learning is also important. A dimension that has been successfully attended in one discrimination problem tends to dominate performance in subsequent discrimination learning (Lawrence, 1949, 1950). On
the other,hand, there is evidence that prior experience in which a cue is
irrelevant significantly retards learning when that cue is eventually made
relevant (Goodwin & Lawrence, 1955; Levine, 1962; Lovejoy, 1968;
Mackintosh, 1964; Trabasso & Bower, 1968).
In addition, there are consistent individual differences (Shepard,
102
Attention to Attributes
~
103
of first graders with the cues relevant to reading may have generalized
effects on the perception of objects and on the ease with which they can
be discriminated from one another. The slow process by which recognition units develop has been labeled categorizing (Broadbent, 1971).
SELECfIVE REPORT OF ATTRIBUTES
(2)
(3)
According to the perceptual tuning hypothesis, the selected dimension "stands out" in perception at the time of presentation.
According to the response hypothesis, the attended attribute suffers less forgetting, because it is rehearsed more effectively and is
reported first (Lawrence & La Berge, 1956).
According to the encoding hypothesis, the attended and unattended attributes are treated differentially only at the point of
transition from sensory memory to the verbally encoded representation of the stimulus (Haber, 1964a, b; 1966; Harris & Haber,
1963). The attended attribute is likely to be encoded first, thus
gaining the advantage of primacy in recall.
104
SPEEDED
CLASSIFICATION
106
the red objects may be small circles printed near the top right corner of ,
the card, while all the blue objects are large triangles printed near the
bottom left corner). Alternatively, the other attributes may be orthogonal
to the relevant dimension (e.g., the red objects that are to be sorted together may vary in shape, size, vertical and horizontal position).
The basic design can be modified in a variety of ways (Posner,
1964). The most elementary version, in which a single attribute is relevant, is called a gating task. The term "filtering" has sometimes been
used in this context. In this book, however, filtering refers to the selectionof inputs .which share a particular attribute (e.g., all words printed
in red ink in a page of text), but call for distinct responses (e.g., reading
each word). In the gating variant of speeded classification, on the other
hand, the sa;me response is made to all the stimuli that share the criterial
attribute.
The condensation task is a more complex variant of speeded classification. Here the stimuli requiring a single response are defined either by
a disjunctive rule applicable to one dimension (e.g., red or blue stimuli
vs. green or yellow), or by a rule involving several dimensions (e.g., red
squares or blue circles vs. red circles or blue squares). Keele (1970) observed that the second variant of condensation is far more difficult than
the first. Accordingly, Gottwald and Garner (1972) referred to the easier
variant as grouping, and retained the term condensation for the harder
task. The dependent variable in speeded-classification tasks is the speed
achieved in sorting cards. Alternatively, the cards may be successively
presented in the tachistoscope, and the subject may be required to indicate his response by pressing an appropriate key as quickly as possible.
A vast amount of research has been devoted to the questions of
whether the attributes of a stimulus are interrogated sequentially or in
parallel, and of whether this interrogation is exhaustive or self-terminating. The results of this research are confusing and contradictory (e.g.,
Biederman, 1972; Biederman & Checkosky, 1970; Garner, 1970; Rabbitt,
1971; Smith, 1968). This outcome should not be surprising. Some of the
complex tasks that have been studied certainly involve covert verbal encoding of the various stimulus attributes prior to the selection of a response. In such tasks the processing of the relevant dimensions will
appear to be serial, because the encoding is serial. Furthermore, verbal
encoding is relatively flexible. The order of encoding can be altered, as
was shown in the preceding section, and the subject may be able to
terminate the encoding as soon as he accumulates sufficient information
(e.g., Biederman, 1972). In other situations the subject's task is simpler,
and he soon learns to dispense with verbal encoding. In those situations,
analyses of multi-attribtlte discrimination problems provide evidence of
parallel processing (e.g., Biederman & Checkosky, 1970; Hawkins, 1969).
Furthermore, the disappearance of verbal encoding is certainly gradual,
f
108
control sitllations in which the irrelevant dimension was not varied. This
finding was obtained with the hue and brightness (chroma and value)
of a color chip and with the horizontal and vertical position of a dot.
Conversely, interference was observed when the irrelevant dimension in
an integral pair was randomly varied. There was neither facilitation nor
interference when the dimensions were assigned to distinct objects, except in th~ rather trivial case where the subject found it more convenient
to concentrate on the "irrelevant" object, which provided a better clue
than the relevant one (Felfoldy & Garner, 1971).
Garner (1970) related the effects of integrality in speeded classifications to some observations obtained in the scaling of similarity. Thus,
Shepard (1964) had subjects judge the similarity of circles, each containing a single radius; the size of the circle and the orientation of the radius
were varied. These two dimensions are not integral, because they refer
to separable objects. As might be expected, subjects encounter severe
difficulties in evaluating the similarity of such compound stimuli (Eisler
& Knoppel, 1970). Which two objects are more similar: two circles of the
same size with different radii? or two circles of different sizes with identically oriented radii? Shepard (1964) noted that some subjects' judgments
were more affected by circle size, while others were more affected by the
orientation of the line, and he attributed these differences to attep.tion.
More important, he concluded that the pattern of similarity judgtnents
was intermediate between the pattern predicted by a "city-block" tnodel
(in which the "distance~' between stimuli corresponds to the sum ,of distances on two dimensions) and a pattern predicted by a Euclidean model
(in which distance is measured along the shortest path between two
points). Hyman and Well (1968). performed a similar experiment with
decidedly nonintegral attributes: the hue of one color chip and the
brightness of another. Their similarity judgment~ confolined to a cityblock model. Garner and Felfoldy (1970) used the stitI?uli of these two
experiments in their study of speeded classification, al1d they found no
interference between nonintegral dimensions. Thus, Garner (1970)
concluded that integral dimensions have three characteristics:
(1)
(2)
(3)
The last characteristic is not always found. Subjects can sometimes use
the redundancy of integral dimensions when it is available, but also
avoid interference when there is no redundancy (Felfoldy & Garner,
1971; Garner, 1970). However, the rules of integrality provide a useful
Attention to Attributes
109
110
REVIEW
7
Focused AttentionFindings and Theories
Debate about the nature of selective attention has centered on tasks that
require the subject to select inputs, or filter informatron. The classic
example of input selection is the situation that Cherry (1957, p. 278)
described as the cocktail-party problem: a guest at a cocktail party usually listens to one conversation and ignores all others, regardless of how
loud they may be. In general, a person is ,said to select inputs when he
focuses attention exclusively on stimuli that originate from a particular
source or share some other characteristic feature.
Experimental studies of input selection have. typically used auditory stimuli. Broadbent (1958) defended the choice of the auditory
modality for the study of attention on the grounds th~t auditory attention can be studied without the encumbrance of the orientation movements which dominate visual attention. When a medley of auditory
messages is fed through headphones, the listener must rely on central
selective mechanisms to isolate the relevant message and ignore the
others, whereas the selection of relevant visual stimuli is usually carried
out by eye movements. To obtain a pure measure of central processes
of visual selection, the experimenter is therefore compelled to present
brief stimuli which are removed before eye movements can occur. This
112
113
Man's notable ability tores_ist distraction is a manifestation of selective attention. The success with which distraction can be resisted was
documented in a series of early studies reviewed by Woodworth (1938).
On the average, measures of intellectllal functions were barely impaired
by intense irrelevant stimulation. However, distraction is resisted ata
cost: motor tension and autonomic manifestations of arousal are higher
than normal. Thus, one is much more likely to break one's pencil while
Writing an examination in a noisy room than when the room is quiet. One
is rarely justified, however, in attributing failure in a test to the presence
of distracting !conditions.
In the early studies of distraction, the subject's attention was focused on his mental activities, but modern studies of selection typically
deal with the ability to select a relevant input in the presence of others.
Many studies have used the shadowing task, in which the listener follows
a message by repeating every word, and attempts to ignore other messages to which he is simultaneollsly exposed. Cherry (1953; Cherry &
Taylor, 1954) established that the presence of a distracting message
barely impairs shadowing performance when the rejected and attended
messages are distinguished by an obvious physical characteristic, such as
spatial origin. In some of these experiments Cherry used the method of
dichotic presentation, in which two messages are presented by earphones
to different ears. He observed that subjects are always aware of the
presence of the rejected message on the unattended ear, but know
114
115
a list of letters for occasional digits is not seriously impaired by the presentation of an irrelevant message to the other ear (Moray & O'Brien,
1967; Underwood & Moray, 1972). Similarly, a subject instructed to press
a key as soon as he hears an animal name in a recorded message responds as fast in the presence of an irrelevant message as when that
message is absent (Ninio & Kahneman, 1973).
The main difference between shadowing and monitoring is that
the former task requires continuous overt responses, while the latter does
not. Several experiments in my laboratory have investigated a recognition
task that requires no immediate response (Henik, 1972; Kahneman, 1970;
Levy, 1971). Two messages, each consisting of 31 unrelated words, are
presented dichotically and the subject subsequently attempts to recognize some of the words that were presented to the right ear. The recognition choices also include an equal number (eight) of words presented
to the left ear, and of words that were not presented at all. The critical feature of the design is that the subject is penalized for recognizing words
that were presented to his left ear.
Three experiments using a fast rate of presentation (two words/ sec
in each ear) compared recognition in focused attention and in a control
condition where the relevant message was presented alone. The presentation of an irrelevant message caused a decrement in the recognition of .
relevant items (from 61 percent to 54 percent). The percentage of false
recognitions of unpresented words was 32 percent in both conditions,
and 37 percent of the left-ear words were judged to be familiar. Thus,
selectivity was high, though far from perfect. Selectivity was only slightly
poorer ata slower rate of presentation (one word pair/ 1.5 sec). Finally,
subjects were able to prevent a high rate of intrusions even when the
words were presented to the two ears in alternation at the comfortable
rate of one word every .75 seconds. The results show that a listener
could usually refrain from paying attention to the irrelevant items, even
when no relevant word was presented at the same time. However, intrusions of left-ear items were more frequent in an experiment (Henik,
1972) where only a few such words were presented. It appears that the
continuity of the irrelevant message is important in permitting that
message to be ignored.
There is no doubt that selective attention was less effective in our
recognition. experiments than in studies of shadowing. In one of these
studies subjects who shadowed a message on one ear later failed to
recognize a phrase that had been repeatedly presented to the other ear
(Moray, 1959). This result was obtained although the subjects were not
specifically enjoined not to listen to the irrelevant ear. In our studies sub~
jects were penalized for listening to the left ear but they nevertheless did
so occasionally. The difference is due in part to the shadower's own voice,
116
117
118
just as filter theory would predict. Contrary to filter theory, however, the
rejected message is apparently analyzed as speech: subjects realize the
identity of messages even when they are spoken in different voices; and
bilingual listeners often recognize the identity of a message and its translation. Neither result should occur if the rejected message is not analyzed
as speech. At the very least, these findings show that some verbal analysis of the rejected message sometimes occurs.
There is additional support for this conclusion. Lewis (1970) recorded latencies for shadowing unrelated words and found that the shadowing latency for a word is significantly increased by simultaneously
presenting its synonym to the other ear. Evidently both words must be
recognized for this effect to occur. However, Treisman (unpublished)
observed that this synonym effect occurs only at the beginning of the
message. Selectivity improves within a few seconds and the content
of the irrelevant message no longer affects shadowing latency. An intriguing result was reported by Corteen and Wood (1972). They first
associated an electric shock to the presentation of city names in a word
list. Later, city names which were included in the rejected message in a
dichotic shadowing task often elicited a galvanic skin response, although
they were never consciously identified and did not interfere with the
shadowing performance.
Selectivity with auditory stimuli appears to be generally poor when
the messages are brief. Thus, Brown (1970) instructed subjects to attend
to one ear and then presented a single dichotic pair of words. Precuing
the relevant ear did not improve the subject's ability to recognize a word
presented on that ear. With somewhat longer messages, however, such
precuing is very helpful (Broadbent, 1952; Spieth, Curtis & Webster,
1954). These results indicate that focusing attention takes time.
Greenwald (19'70a, b) described another instance of a failure to
filter a very brief message. He simultaneously presented a visual and an
auditory digit and recorded subjects' reaction times for reading the visual digit. The subjects were unable to reject the irrelevant auditory digit;
their RT was slower when this digit was not the same as the visual digit.
Greenwald also reported an important interaction between the modality
of the interfering stimulus and the modality of the response: interference
from the auditory item was more severe when the subject had to say the
visual digit than when he wrote it (Greenwald, 1970a,.1970c).
In response to the suggestion that the failures of selection in his
experiment were due to the brevity of the messages, Greenwald (1970b)
showed that a spoken digit delays RT to a relevant visual digit even
with successive stimuli presented at the rapid rate of one item/ second.
However, this serial RT task cannot be considered a truly continuous
119
120
Broadbent's filter theory is the natllral starting point for any discussion of modern theories of attention. Some of the main features of
this theory have already been noted, as well as some of the evidence
that shows it to be inadequate. Briefly, Broadbent assumed a sequence
of three elements: a short-term store (S-system), -a selective filter, and a
limited capacity challnel (P"7system). Concurrent stimuli enter into the
S-system in parallel, and they are analyzed there for physical features,
such as location or tonal quality. There is no definite limit on the capacity of the S-system. The selective filter allows those ~timuli that arrive
on a designated "channel" into the P-system. A channel is defined by any
physical characteristic for which the filter can be set. Thus, location or
pitch could both define a channel in audition. Color or size could define
a channel in vision.
More elaborate perceptual analyses are carried out in the P-system.
This system deals serially with accepted stimuli,. and the time spent on
each stimulus depends on the amount of information that the stimulus
conveys. When the P~system has cleared, the filter allows a new stimulus
to enter. Thus, when two stimuli are presented simultaneously, .they can
be handled successively, but only if the processing of the first is completed before the record of the other in the S-system has decayed. This
feature of Broadbent's theory explains the common experience of the
"double take," in which one returns to a stimulus that was ignored or not
fully processed at the instant of its presentation. Such is the experience
of the husband, deeply engrossed in his paper, who first exclaims,
"What?" and then, without waiting for an answer, goes on to say, "No,
I'm not hungry," as he retrieves his wife's query from an -echoic memory.
Filter theory interprets focused attention as setting the filter -to
select a certain class of stimuli' and to reject all others. Irrelevant messages are simply allowed to decay in the S-systemwithout undergoing
more advanced processing in the P-system. Therefore, attention is most
effectively focused by a stimulus set, in which the relevant stimuli are
distinguished by one of the simple operations that the filter can perform, e.g., discriminations of location, pitch, and speech-like quality' in
sounds. Selection is difficult or impossible in the absence of a clear physical distinction between relevant and irrelevant stimuli. Filter theory is
supported by the finding that subjects cannot focus attention solely on
digits when a mixed array of digits and letters is briefly presented (Sperling, 1960). Similarly, bilingual subjects cannot separate a message in
English from a simultaneous message in French if the two messages are
121
spoken in the same voice and originate at the same location (Treisman,
1964a). Selection by semantic class, or by language, requires the .subject
to adopt a response set (Broadbent, 1970, 1971), because the relevant
items are defined by a common set of responses rather than by a common stimulus feature. Although Broadbent's (1970) elaboration of his
original theory acknowledged that selection by response set is sometimes
possible, he presented evidence that response set is generally much less
effective than stimulus set.
Filter theory implies that attention cannot be divided, because the
P-system performs no' parallel processi;ng of discrete stimuli. According.
to the theory, the apparent division of attention in the performance of
concurrent activities is mediated by alternation between channels or
between acts, and the rate of alternation is slow. Broadbent (1958) assumed that the minimum dwell-time of the filter is about 300-500 milliseconds. The processing of simultaneous complex messages fails when
the processing of the first message which enters the P-system is so prolonged that the traces of the other message decay in the S-system before
they can be retrieved.
As initially stated, filter theory was wrong. It will be shown in
Chapter 8 that parallel processing of simultaneous stimuli does occur in
divided attention. Furthermore, the evidence of the preceding section
demonstrates that the content of an irrelevant message is identified, at
least dimly and at least some of the. time, even when the subject attempts to ignore it. Finally, the idea of a slow-moving filter that selects
one stimulus at a time is not viable. Thus, virtually all the predictions of
filter theory about what people cannot do have been disproved. However, filter theory provides a useful approximation to what people usually do. In addition, it has the unique distinction among attention
theories of being sufficiently precise to be definitely disproved.
Many of the terms and concepts of filter theory have been widely
applied. In particular, the image of filtering as an operation that opens
one channel and closes others has been very influential. This image,
however, was derived from the study of auditory attention and of the
dichotic case in particular. It is not easily applied to visual attention. For
example,. what defines the channel selected when one reads a book?
The analysis of attention presented in Chapter 5 proposes the concept
of perceptual unjt,or group, as an alternative to the concept of channel.
Another influential idea of filter theory was the concept of a preperceptual memory (the S-system). The temporary storage of unanalyzed
sensory information has acquired many names from numerous investigators. Sperling (1960) spoke of a visual image, which he later (Sperling,
1963) renamed Visual Information Storage (VIS), and to which he added
an Auditory Information Storage (AIS) (Sperling, 1967). Crowder and
122
123
that attended and unattended stimuli are treated differentially from a very
early stage of perceptual analysis. This differential treatment causes a reduction of sensitivity (d') for unattended stimuli. In general, unattended
items do not activate the corresponding dictionary units, ~xcept when the
threshold of one of these units is exceptionally low.
Treisman (1969) later presented a more inclusive treatment of the
entire field of selective attention. Two observations were basic to that
theory: (1) people can easily focus attention on one input (e.g., the voice
on the right), while the.y have great difficulty in dividing attention between two inputs; and (2) people can easily divide their attention between the various aspects or attributes of a particular input (La Berge &
Winokur, 1965; Lappin, 1967), but they encounter great difficulty in focusing on one aspect of a stimulus and ignoring the others (Stroop, 1935;
Treisman & Fearnley, 1969).
As was mentioned in the preceding chapter, Treisman (1969) proposed that a single input can be processed by several analyzers in parallel,
while the processing of two inputs by the same analyzer is necessarily serial. In a major departure from filter theory, she concluded that
divided attention and parallel processing are possible for two simultaneous inputs, but only if they do not reach the same analyzers. Serial
processing is mandatory, however, whenever a single analyzer must
operate on two inputs.
The main implication of this new theoretical idea concerns divided
attention: unlike filter theory, Treisman's analyzer theory permits parallel processing, e.g., of information presented to different modalities. This
issue will be considered in detail in the next chapter.
Treisman (1969) retained the filter-attenuation approach to focused
attention. She used the concept of analyzer only to explain why any major physical change in the characteristics of a rejected message is invariably recognized (Lawson, 1966; Treisman & Riley, 1969). Such a stimulus
is easily detected because it reaches analyzers that are not occupied by
the relevant message.
124
125
this information causes the pertinence of the unit to increase. With this
assumption of recursiveness, Norman's theory explained why stimulus set
need . not be substantially more difficult than response set. It still failed
to explain, however, why stimulus set is actually easier.
Norman (1968, p. 528) emphasized the contrast between his view
and Treisman'sfilter-attenuation theory. Both theories account for the
effects of context and word significance in selection by criterion bias.
However, Norman also explains filtering as a criterion effect, whereas
Treisman implies that discriminability (d') is reduced for items rejected
by the filter.
An experiment by Mor(ly and O'Brien (1967) appears to provide a
test of ~orman's predictions. Subjects were exposed to a dichotic message consisting of letters and digits; they were to attend only to the- right
ear, and to press a key with the right hand whenever they heard a letter
on that ear. Although instructed to ignore the message on the left ear,
they were to tap a key with the left hand whenever they happened to
hear a letter on that ear. The signal-detection analysis of the results was
not entirely conclusive, because of the very low false alarm rate, but it
suggested that the criterion for left-hand responses was lower than the
criterion, for right-hand responses. That is, the number of false alarms on
the irrelevant channel was greater than Norman's theory wouldperdict.
In addition, d' was much lower on that channel. Other experiments (e.g.,
Broadbent & Gregory, 1963; Kahneman, Beatty & Pollack, 1967) have
also supported the conclusion that selective attention affects discriminability, contrary to the position of Deutsch and Deutsch and Norman.
One could perhaps attempt to dismiss these results by invoking a
distinction between two types of criterion effects, which operate respectively on recognition and on the overt response. In the experiment by
Moray and O'Brien, for example, the criterion for recognizing irrelevant
words on the left ear could be high (low pertinence), while the criterion
for making responses with the left hand could be low (careless responses). This distinction has some intuitive appeal. If it is accepted,
however, the claim that pertinence affects the criterion is robbed of any
operational consequences.
126
127
128
which could avoid this difficulty. He described perception as the confirmation of a changing set of expectations, concerning future phonemes
when one listens to speech, or the foveal image that would be produced
by possible movements of the eye when one looks at a picture. He also
assumed that the perceiver normally stores in memory only sets of expectations that have been confirmed. Stimuli that are not matched to
prior expectations are very rapidly forgotten, unless they are exceptionally salient. An intention to focus attention on one message causes detailed expectations to be produced for that message alone. Irrelevant
messages are not expected in detail, and are forgotten almost as soon as
they are heard. The production of expectations, of course, is very similar
to Neisser's active synthesis.
Hochberg's approach is similar to Neisser's, but he implies a separation of detailed perceptual analysis from awareness. Detailed perception depends on the generation of confirmed expectations, but awareness
of what one perceives also depends on whether the results of perceptual
analysis are stored inrpemory. If a stimulus is anticipated, but immediately forgotten, there will be no awareness although perception may be
detailed. Thus, Hochberg would probably describe driving as a case of
detailed anticipation with immediate forgetting. This description appears
more appropriate than a statement that driving is controlled by' crude
and global mechanisms, as implied by Neisser's theory. Another heuristic
advantage of Hochberg's formulation over Neisser's is that the concept
of expectation is more readily translated into the language of signal-detection theory than analysis-by-synthesis. However, Treisman (personal
communication) has observed that detailed expectations cannot be quite
as important as Hochberg's treatment would suggest. Thus, it is possible
to shadow a message even if it consists of unrelated words, precluding
the formation of expectations.
It may be noted that Freud's analysis of attention in the famous
seventh chapter of The Interpretation of D'reams was somewhat similar
to Hochberg's proposal. Freud discussed the attachment of attentioncathexis to objects of perception or to objects of thought, and the hypercathexis that allows them into consciousness. Freud adopted a positive
view of focused attention, in which selective attention is the active
elaboration of chosen ideas, rather than the inhibition of others (Freud,
1900; Rapaport, 1967; Schwartz & Schiller, 1967,1970).
An important notion in Freud's view was that the total quantity of
attention cathexis available at anyone time is limited, and that the
amount of attention demanded by an object of thought or perception
depends on how it is elaborated in cognitive activity. This view implies
that the limitation on what man can perceive depends on how he perceives, and on what he does" with his percepts. Freud's theory of attention was an effort theory.
129
THEORETICAL SYNTHESIS
Unit Formation
The array of stimulation is sorted into integral units, which maintain their identity through subsequent stages of perceptual analysis. Subsequent operations are applied to these units: units are allocated capacity
at the stage of figural emphasis, and units or features of units activate the recognition stage. An operation at one of these later stages can
fail because the earlier grouping stage did not isolate the relevant unit.
The suffix effect, which will be discussed below, is an example of a
failure of selection due to grouping.
The idea of an initial grouping stage is adopted from Neisser's notion of pre-attentive mechanisms. It applies both to vision and audition.
For example, letters printed in red may form a natural group within a
larger array of letters printed in black. Similarly, a phrase spoken by a
particular voice and originating in a particular location constitutes a natural auditory unit in the cocktail-party situation. In both vision and
audition location in space is the primary determinant of unit formation:
sounds that originate in a particular location tend to be grouped, as do
clustered visual objects.
According to this analysis, attention is focused by selecting among
available perceptual units (objects or events) those units to which most
capacity should be allocated. By measuring grouping, we may be able to
predict the outcome of selective attention (Beck & Ambler, 1972; von
Wright, 1968, 1970; Williams, 1966). Furthermore, a careful study of the
laws of unit formation is needed to overcome a serious weakness of filter
theory: its failure to explain why certain physical features of stimuli are
effective in defining "channels," while others are not.
Figural Emphasis
Capacity is allocated in graded fashion to various groups. The
frequent demonstrations that selective atteation usually results in attenuation rather than in total blocking suggest that figural selection is not allor-none. Parallel processing of different units is possible, but perception
draws ona common pool of capacity, and the ability to carry out detailed
analyses of several units is limited.
130
Broadbent's theory assigns the functions of both grouping and selection to the filter. However, it appears essential to separate these functions, since they follow different rules. A major difference is the degree
of voluntary control over the two stages: with rare exceptions, unit formation is largely controlled by involuntary and psychologically silent
processes, while the allocation of capacity is immediately responsive to
momentary intentions.
Although the allocation of capacity is generally effective, it is not perfect. Some capacity is allocated to the processing of irrelevant stimuli,
and the processing of a selected stimulus is rarely as effective in the
presence of other stimulation as when the same stimulus is shown alone.
131
132
GROUPS OR CHANNELS
133
S-system, the observation that the suffix effect can be prevented .led to
the conclusion that PAS is located after the filter (Morton, 1970a, b).
The stimulus prefix effect was addressed by Neisser in very different terms (Neisser, Hoenig & Goldstein, 1969). In the context of a theory
of analysis-by-synthesis, the rhythm of the presentation was assumed
to dominate the perceived organization of the digit list: "The stimulus
string consists of eight digits and is heard as such; all eight take up space
in the resulting construction-even if one was redundant-because they
were heard as a single utterance [Neisser, Hoenig & Goldstein, 1969, p.
425]." It follows that the prefix effect should be eliminated by altering the
perceived structure of the string. This was successfully achieved by presenting the prefix in a different voice than the list. Moreover, there was
no disruptive effect when the prefix consisted of the sequence "zero,
zero, zero." This prefix constitutes a group, which can be easily segregated from the relevant material.
This study illustrates the superiority of a formulation of selective
attention as an operation on perceptual units rather than on channels.
It is surely unreasonable to assume that the triad "zero, zero, zero" defines a channel, whereas a single "zero" does not. The triad, however,
provides an adequate group.
The theory of attention that was summarized in the preceding section explains the results of this study by the operation of a pre-attentive
process of unit formation: interference occurs only within a perceptual
unit, and it can be prevented if the potentially interfering material is included within a unit of its own. This interpretation applies to the suffix
effect investigated by Crowder and Morton, as wel~ as to the prefix effect
studied by Neisser et ale Furthermore, the same rule is expected to apply
in vision as well as in audition. In contrast, the Crowder-Morton hypothesis explains only auditory suffix. effects, in terms of interference
with a precategorical acoustic storage.
To test this conception, Ulric Neisser and I tried to obtain a visual
equivalent of the suffix effect, and also to reduce that effect by a manipulation of grouping structure.
Subjects (N == 64) were shown a clearly legible array of six relevallt digits for half a second, and they immediately wrote the digits they
could recall. A visual "suffix" was shown on most trials, next to the far
right item. The 'digit "zero" appeared only asa suffix, and the subjects
were given advance exposure to all the suffixes that were used. Figure
7-1 shows several of the displays and indicates the number of errors that
were made in the fifth and sixth positions for each of these displays. As
in the case of the auditory suffix, the detrimental effect of the visual suffix
was most pronounced in the two positions closest to the interfering item.
Figure 7-1 shows that interference is pronounced when the suffix
134
Percent errors
Percent errors
Positions
Positions
54
57
45
49
43
42
(B)
( A)
976543
41
38
( D)
(C )
1375260
53
69
( E)
857146
000
000
726439000
000
000
418359
( F)
48
47
842915.
FIGURE 7-1
Effects of different visual suffixes.
is embedded within the perceptual group of relevant material. Interference can be prevented or reduced by removing the suffix from the relevant group, as in E, or by embedding it into another group, as in D.
This experiment has been discussed in detail because it provides a
suggestive prototype of focused attention tasks. As in other attention
tasks, the subject is instructed to respond to some stimuli and ignore
others. Whether he can do so depends on a grouping process which
precedes and constrains the allocation of attention. Attention operates
by emphasis rather than by filtering: the suffix is always "seen," but it is
seen as background rather than as figure.
The results of Figure 7-1 demonstrate the futility of attempts to
explain all effects of attention by a bias on the control of responses. The
pertinence of all suffixes was surely very low, yet some caused interference while others did not.
It is also difficult to analyze this visual example of focused attention in terms of a filter that selects among channels. The difficulty illustrates the prevalence of auditory concepts in modern discussions of
135
8
Attention Divided Among Inputs
137
sis (Norman & Rummelhart, 1970) and memory (Lindsay & Norman,
1969).
Neisser (1967) assumed parallel processing at the pre-attentive
level, but he treated focal attention as unitary. Furthermore, the idea
that speech is analyzed by synthesis appears to imply that only one verbal input can be synthesized at a time.
Treisman's (1960) attenuation concept implied that some parallel
processing of concurrent inputs occurs even when attention is deliberately focused on one. input. Later she argued that parallel processing of
simultaneous stimuli is possible in different analyzers, while serial
processing is necessary within \a single analyzer (Treisman, 1969).
The discussions of figural emphasis and of effort in previous chapters suggests that parallel processing of simultaneous inputs is possible.
However, para1lel processes that impose heavy demands on the limited
capacity are likely to interfere with one another.
We will first examine some experiments in which the processing of
simultaneous stimuli was either seriously impaired or obviously serial,
then turn to other experiments in which processing was demonstrably
parallel. Effects of effort and modality are discussed in the final sections.
138
essing at some stage of analysis or decision. The results and the models,
however, vary widely (see Sternberg & Knoll, 1972, for a detailed review).
Prior entry was originally investigated because the demands on the
nineteenth-century astronomer appeared to exceed his capacity. The
modern investigations of the problem were prompted by the difficulties
of 'another overloaded functionary: the air-traffic controller (Broadpent,
1952, 1954a; Mowbray, 1953, 1954; Poulton, 1953; Spieth, Curtis, & Webster, 1954; Webster & Solomon, 1955). The common finding in these
studies was that listeners either completely fail to deal with simultaneous
messages or at best handle them successively.
Broad"bent (1954a) inve!1ted an experimental task which he used to
demonstrate the successive handling of simultaneous stimuli. The subject
in the split-span experiment is presented with two lists of digits simultaneously and reports what he recalls from the presentation. In a dichotic presentation, for example, he may receive the sequence 7-2-8 to one
. ear, and 9-4-5 to the' other. In other variants of the split-span design,
auditory items may be presented simultaneously on two external speakers, or an auditory item may be paired with a visual item (Broadbent
& Gregory,1961, 1965; Madsen, Rollins & Senf, 1970). When the presentation rate is faster than about one pair/second, these designs produce
the same result: subjects' reports tend to group all items that have arrived on one channel (defined by ear, location, voice, or modality), followed by the items from the other channel. Subjects who are required to
report the items in pairs (e.g., 79-42-85 in the example above) make more
errors than when they are allowed to report channel-by-channel. Order
information, in particular, is often lost in pair-wise recall (Bryden, 1962,
1964; Moray & Barnett, 1965). The difficulty of pair-wise recall decreases
markedly with prolonged practice (Moray & Jordan, 1966), but the task
always remains difficult.
The split-span experiment has produced three main findings. (1)
The task can be performed. Although subjects' performance with such
short lists is impaired, it is often adequate. (2) Successive, not simultaneous items tend to be grouped in recall. (3) In particular, items presented
on the same channel or in the same modality tend. to be grouped. These
findings suggested to Broadbent the image of a filter which selects a
channel, stays on that channel until the termination of its message, and
then switches to accept the second message, which was stored meanwhile in the S-system.
An alternative interpretation is that the preferred order of report
is determined by .perceptual grouping. If items are perceptually grouped
by source or modality, the most advantageous order of report will be
compatible with this spontaneous organization. The tendency to group
successive rather than simultaneous items also represents a law of group-
139
ing. Savin (1967) presented subjects with two successive pairs of digits,
all four digits spoken in the same voice and, originating at the same
place. His subjects almost invariably grouped successive rather than
simultaneous items in their reports. Thus, the normal mode of organization for auditory stimuli is sequential. Although this was not its original
purpose, the split-span experiment has provided valuable information
concerning, Gestalt-like rules in auditory perception.
The tendency to report items by channel can be overcome by other
grouping 'factors. This was first shown by Gray and Wedderburn (1960).
They presented the three syllables of a word (e.g., extirpate) or the three
words of a brief phrase (e.g., mice eat cheese) in alternation to the two
ears (e.g., right-Ieft-right), and simultaneously alternated a list of three
digits (left-right-Ieft). They found that subjects' reports followed content
rather than ear of arrival. Similar results have been obtained in many
other experiments (e.g., Bartz, Satz & Fennell, 1967; Broadbent & Gregory, 1964; Yntema & Trask, 1963). This effect of content is limited to
dichotic presentation; when the series are presented on different modalities, report by content almost never occurs (Madsen, Rollins & Senf,
1970).
The content effect in the split-span design is probably related to
the finding that subjects who are instructed to shadow b'y ear are nevertheless affected by the continuity of content (Treisman, 1960). It has already been mentioned that semantic factors can affect perceptual organization. In addition, groupillg by content in the split-span design also
facilitates retrieval. Subjects who attempt to report by channel must
produce awkward sequences such as mice-three-cheese, six-eat-two, and
organization by content could be imposed at retrieval to avoid such sequences (Broadbent & Gregory, 1964; Sanders & Schroots, 1968).
The question of how attention affects storage in the split-span
design has been studied by Bryden (1971). His subjects were to actively
rehearse one series (called A, for attended) and to ignore the other (U,
for unattended). They were also to report both series in a specified order, with either the attended or the unattended series first (i.e., the
orders were UA or AU). The striking result was the difference in the
shape of the serial position curves for the A and U groups. As may be
seen in Figure 8-1, the serial position curve -is Hat for the A group, but
there is a pronounced recency effect with U items. Significantly, this
result occurs regardless of the order of report.
Another interesting feattlre of Figure 8-1 is that the order of report
(AU or VA) has less effect on the U-message than on the A-message.
The A-message is more susceptible to output interference, the disruption
of memory which is caused by the activity of recall. This finding is consistent with the idea that the U -message is stored as an acoustic rather
140
220
210
200
190
0
...qN
180
c 170
E
....0 160
Q)
''-
0
'Q)
...0
E
:::>
150
140
130
120
110
A-U order
100
OT
Attended
Unattended
FIGURE8l
Recall as a function of attention and order of report (Bryden, 1971, with permission).
141
there is no evidence that subjects must respond in this manner, nor that
they cannot perceive simultaneous items in parallel.
F AlLURES
OF DIVIDED ATTENTION
142
143
than the precise temporal relations between the onsets of the targets
(Avner, 1972).
144
to target items on one ear and only one task in response to critical items
on the other ear. This difference could be reflected in the importance attached to critical items on the two ears, with a consequent bias in favor
of the slladowed message.
To overcome this criticism, Treismanand Riley (1969) required
subjects to shadow one of two dichotic lists of computer-synchronized
digits and to detect occasional letters on either ear. The ingenious feature of the design. was the response that the subject w.as to make to a
target item on either ear: he was to immediately stop shadowing. Thus,
the response to a critical item was the same, regardless of the ear on
which is was heard. The subjects detected "76 percent of letters on the attended ear, and 33 percent on the other. The large bias in favor of the
shadowed message' provides strong evidence against the Deutsch and
Deutsch theory (1963, 1967). However, it should be noted that selectivity
was less impressive than in the Treisman alld Geffen study. This result
would be expected by a theory which emphasizes grouping effects. The
use of computer-synchronized digits eliminates most factors essential to
the formation of effective perceptual groups, and thereby hampers
selection.
In other conditions of the same experiment, Treisman and Riley
(1969) observed that critical letters which differ in voice from the background digits are always detected on the unattended channel. This effect
of voice quality relates' to Lawson's (1966)' finding that listeners easily detect a tone on the rejected ear. 'As was noted in the preceding chapter,
such results are consistent with filter theory, which assumes that all stimuli are tested on obvious physical characteristics.
Treisman's experiments demonstrate that attention cannot be divided between .concurrent stimuli if the listener is' biased toward one
channel by the instruction to shadow one of the 'messages. The bias
favoring the shadowed message overcomes the effects of the relevance of
designated targets, such as the letters in the Treisman.. Riley study. Another demonstration of attentional bias was offered by Weg (1'971) in
my laboratory. Subjects listened to dichotic messages, each ten words
long, presented at a rate of two pairs/ second. The recognition of rightear words was tested, as in the focused attention experiments described
in the preceding chapter. In addition, subjects were required to note the
occurrence in the left-ear message of one or two target items, which they
were asked to recall immediately after the presentation of the message.
Three types of target items were used: (1) words belonging to a content
category, such as animal names; (2) digits; (3) isolated digits in a male
voice inserted in a message spoken by a female. 'Subjects were paid a
substantial bonus for successful recall of critical left-ear words and were
paid at a lower rate for recognizing right-ear items. They were penalized
for mistaking left-ear words as familiar in the recognition test.
145
146
If it is not(2)
(3)
147
ferent relevant aspects of the same stimulus. Subjects in these experiments made absolute judgments of various attributes of simultaneous
visual and auditory stimuli. Their performance was evaluated by a measure of information transmission, which reflected their consistency, in
assigning distinct labels to different stimuli. Subjects transmitted almost
as much information on each dimension when they judged both stimuli
together as they did when the judgments were made one at a time.
Manipulations of stimulus duration had no effect, suggesting that the two
discriminations were indeed performed in parallel. Thus, attention was
effectively divided between the two tasks (Lindsay, Cuddy & Tulving,
1965; Tulving & Lindsay, 1967), at least when the stimuli to be judged
were easily discriminable from one another. Very different results were
obtained when discriminability was reduced, and these additional findings will be discussed in the next section.
Evidence of parallel processing was oqtained by the present author
and his students (Levy, 1971) in studies of recognition memory following
dichotic presentation of word lists. The experimental situation has already been mentioned in' the discussion of focused attention. In the divided attention condition, the subject~ were 'exposed to dichotic lists of
31 words each, and they subsequently attempted to distinguish words
that had been presented from unpresented distractors. The recognition
list always, included several pairs of items that had been presented
simultaneously to the two ears. Filter theory entails a strongly negative
relation between the recognition of simultaneous words: if an item on
one ear is recognized, then attention must have been directed to that ear
at the time of presentation, and therefore away from the other ear. Thus,
the probability of recognizing two simultaneous, items should be substantially lower than the product of their separate probabilities of recognition.
Several experiments, conducted at various presentation 'rates on a
total of 260 subjects, failed to confirm the, prediction from filter theory.
The interaction between simultaneous items predicted by this theory
simply did not occur. A typical subject in these experiments recognized
about 51 percent of right-ear items and 48 percent of left-ear items
(equivalent to about 30 percent recognition after correction for chance
success), and these values were unaffected' by the recognition of the
corresponding item on the other ear. In contrast to this independence between simultaneous items, there was' a slight but highly consistent negative relation between successive items.
The results indicated that man can listen to both ears at once and
store some part of what he hears, although recognition performance is
far poorer than when he listens to only one ear. The subjects faced with
the overwhelming task of listening to two messages at once quickly real-
148
ized the futility of any active strategy and usually reported adopting a
passive, receptive attitude. With this attitude, there were no indications
of interference between simultaneous items, but performance on all items
was quite poor.
149
150
AROUSAL
/.--
..........
/ increased "
/
arousal
\
(
reduces
\
\
spare
J
',capacity /
1----.
rlrvv-L
I
:AVAILABLE:
: CAPACITY i
/----....,
-T/
II \
.....-.--.'/ /
\:---
"-
TENTATIVE
RECOGNITION
OF TARGET
..-----,
/'"
/
causes
\
'I increase ,
~----....I of demands .....- - - - - - - - - - - \\ on capac I ty /
"
'---...".,.-/
-....-.,
/ / surge of "
arousa I to "
/........---,
\
meet
/
,
\
increased ;1
may cause \ , demand /
I interruption \ ,____ ""
\
of other
J
\
activities I
""""'-_/
/ / directs '
I attention to \
\further activities,
\
related
/
" to target / /
Mt SC ELlANEOUS
MANIFESTATIONS
OF AROUSAL
FIGURE 8-2
Effects of the tentative recognition of a target stimulus.
151
152
task). The probability (corrected for chance success) that a word would
be recognized increased from 40 percent to 50 percent, depending on
whether the word with which it was paired was or was not recognized.
The negative correlation in recognition, while consistent, was much less
pronounced than in recall. This finding is consonant with the view that
the negative correlation between concurrent activities is a function of
effort.
Another observation concerned the recognition of a non-target
word that had been presented simultaneously with a target. The recognition of those words was very severely impaired in the voice group, but
there was little or no impairment in the content group. A similar result
was obtained by Weg (1971). As may be recalled, Weg instructed subjects to listen to all words on the right ear for a recognition test, and to
detect and later recall critical items occasionally presented on the left
ear (see p. 143). The recognition of the right-ear word presented simultaneously with a left-ear target was more severely depressed when the
target was a digit in a male voice (the rest of the message was in a
female voice), than when the target was a digit or an animal name
spoken in the same voice as the rest of the message.
The difference between the interfering effects of voice and content
targets can be interpreted by noting that a voice target may be "recognized" as a target at an earlier stage of analysis than a content target.
Consequently, the narrowing of attention indicated in Figure 8-2 will be
more' detrimental to the item paired with a voice target,because attention will be withdrawn from it sooner. .
In' summary, the findings reviewed thus far indicate that parallel
processing of simultaneous inputs is pOSSible, contrary to 'filter theory.
There seems to be no single-channel bottleneck in the perceptual system,
. but attention tends to be more nearly unitary at high levels of effort than
when little effort is exerted.
Attention Divided
Amo~g
Inputs
153
154
REVIEW
This chapter began with the question of wheth~r simultaneous inputs are 'processed in parallel or in sequence. The conclusion is that
both modes of processing occur, depending on the task and on the cir-
155
9
Speeded Responses
to Simultaneous
and to
Immediately Successive Signals
Measures of reaction time have been used extensively in attempts to
study man's ability to divide his attention between two response tasks
which overlap in time. The' first section of this chapter discusses the
issue of response integrality:. when are two physically distinct responses
properly viewed as components o~ a single molar response? Subsequent
sections deal with results obtained with quickly successive signals. Additional studies in which reaction time is used to measure the division of
attention are described in Chapter 10.
How does man produce multiple responses to mul~iple simultaneous or immediately successive signals? A vast number of studies have
been devoted to this question, in an attempt to clarify the interactions
between concurrent processes of perception, decision, and response. A
preliminary question that must be answered, however, concerns the very
definition of multiple signals and multiple responses. The discussion of
integrality in Chapter 6, and of grouping processes in Chapters 5 and 7,
156
157
158
159
fv4tcnual information:
0 bits
1 bit
2 bits
700
600
u
eu
en
E
eu
E
.... 500
c
.2
....
u
eu
L-
'0
...0
400
L-
eu
>
0
300
200 '-----'-
__'__
...a..-.
2
Verbal information (Bits)
FIGURE 9-1
Verbal RT as a function of information in verbal response, for three
levels of information in manual response (from Schvaneveldt, 1969,
with permission).
160
700
0
0
600
,.......
Cl)
en
Cl)
....
500
c:
2
....
~
400
300
...
cCl)
...
...
o
FIGURE 9-2
Manual RT (filled symbols). and verbal RT (unfilled symbols) as a function of
total information. Symbols identify the information in the manual respon,se: 0
bits (triangles); 1 bit (squares); 2 bits (circles).
161
firmed, there is a trend in Figure 9-2 that this hypothesis does not predict: the IRI between the two responses tends to increase with the
complexity of the task. It appears that the organization of the compound
response becomes looser at a high level of complexity. Why this occurs is
not clear. Certainly, however, the implication of this result is that there
is less overlap between the processes leading to the two responses when
the situation is complex than when it is simple. This conclusion is diametrically opposite to the conclusion that Schvaneveldt drew from consideration of the data of Figure 9-1.
The preceding discussion shows that the question of whether two
distinct responses constitute two tasks or one, cannot be dismissed as a
matter of definition. It is an empirical question. Integrality of responses
has observable consequences, and response units must be discovered,
not defined. In Schvaneveldt's study, there were two indications that
response . grouping or integration occurred. First, the latency of the
manual response, which was always the first to occur, depended equally
on the information conveyed by both the position and the identity of the
numeral. Second, the IRI between the two responses was relatively short
and varied only within narrow limits. However, the fact that IRI did
vary systematically with the overall complexity of the task suggests that
response integration may be a matter of degree.
Phenomena of grouping and organization are as important in, the
context of response as they are in the context of perception. Re~ponse
grouping and integration extend over both space and time: complex
coordinated acts such as shifting gears in an automobile involve different
limbs and a relatively prolonged sequence of subordinate activities. As is
also true of perceptual organization, response organization is hierarchical, and response units are integrated in groups of increasing size. It is
often. easy to discover the size of the dominant unit of organization.
Speak aloud, for example, and try to obey the instruction "say everything twice." What did you discover? What was the size of the units
that you chose to repeat? Almost invariably the repeated unit consists
of more than one word, though the words are clearly present as distinct
subordinate units. The effect is not restricted to verbal response. Set
yourself to make free-form movements with both hands. Now try to "do
everything twice." The analogy of the motor experience to the verbal
will be clearly evident.
The isolation of valid response units is an essential prerequisite
to the study of divided attention in motor performance. It is only meaningful to speak of attention as divided among isolable processes, but
these isolable processes must first be discovered (Posner, Lewis & Conrad, 1972). The discussion of perceptual attention in earlier chapters led
162
.AND TIlE
163
between the two signals was the only effective variable; the magnitude
of the second signal did not seenl to matter. This result led C'raik to
describe the intermittence of corrective processes by the term "psychological refractory period" (PRP) which had been introduced earlier
(Telford, 1931). Craik suggested that man behaves as a,rl intermittent
servomechanism; the main characteristic of such a mechanism is that
the corrections it makes when performing a continuous action are discrete, and limited in rate. Information that arrives during the refractory
period which follows each correction is acted upon only at the next
instant of sampling.
Subsequent investigations of refractoriness have largely abandoned
the tracking task in favor of the simpler situation in which the subject
reacts to two rapidly, successive stimuli, Sl and S2. The sequence of
events in a typical trial is shown in Figure 9-3. The question that is
raised in such experiments is whether the subject can prepare the response (R2) ,to the second stimulus (S2) while engaged in preparing or
executing the response (R1 ) to the first stimulus (Sl).
The data of a reaction-time experiment in the refractoriness paradigm are usually plotted as in Figure 9-4, in which RT2 is pl9tted as a
function of the interval (lSI) between Sl and S2. Figure 9-4 presents
theoretical functions for the dependence of RT 2 on lSI, which are derived from the single-channel hypothesis, as formul~ted by Welford
(1952, 1959', 1967) and by D'avis (1957). This hypothesis is an application
of Craik's original view to the reaction-time situation. The mainassumption of single-channel theory is that the response-selection stage of information-processing is a bottleneck, or single channel, which can select
responses only one at a time. The one exception that Welford admitted
RT 2
(,----------')...'--------.....1
RT 1
r".-------A"------I----.....'
S1
S2
Jl~
\.
R1
R2
n------n-----_--rL
l'-
-y---- _ _.........)
I RI
'S I
T i m e - - -.....
)
FIGURE 9-3
The sequence of events in a typical trial of a refractoriness study: 8 1 and 8 2 are
successive stimuli; R1 and R2 are the corr~spondingresponses.
164
,
""
""
""
"
"
( B)
",
""
""
""
""-
"""-
""---------.----a.------.
" . . .- ------
Control RT 2
RT 1
---'A""---------.-.\_ ~
I,--
Time--..
)
FIGURE
Feedback
delay
9-4
Reaction time of second response (RT 2) plotted as a function of interstimulus interval (lSI). Two predictions from single-channel theory are
shown: (A) prediction on the assumption that the processing of 8 2 begins
with the execution of Rt ; (B) prediction on the assumption of a further
delay for processing feedback.
165
166
( B)
o
c:
c
Q)
Feedback delay
Q)
(A)
o
a.
U)
Q)
'I
'-
....c
Q)
Control RT 2
Q)
RT 1
t.=
r
Time
Feedback
delay
Inter-stimulus interval
FIGURE 9-5
Inter-response interval as a function of inter-stimulus interval. 'J;he
predictions from single-channel theory correspond to the functions
labeled (A) and (B) in Figure 9-4.
+ lSI -
( A)
3 bits
2 bits
1 bit
167
700
400
--0-- Control RT
2
--0-- Control RT
400
B)
o
u
Q)
300
200
50
150
300
500
FIGURE 9-6
Data from Smith (Acta Psychologica, 30, 1969). RT 2 and IRI are shown
as a function of lSI. The parameter is the information of R1
As plotted in Figure 9-6, panel B, the data are seen to violate drastically
the predi~tions of single-channel theory, since the horizontal segment predicted by that theory is missing in all cases. The discrepancy between
the impressions that are gained from observing the two panels of Figure
9-6 is due to a simple fact of sensory discrimination: we are much
168
more sensitive to deviations of a line from the horizontal than to deviations from a slope of minus one!
The results of Figure 9-6 are incompatible with single-channel
theory for two reasons: (1) because they indicate that IRI can be shorter
than the control value of RT 2, so that some processing must be parallel;
(2) because the slope of the functions that relate IRI to lSI is always
positive, again indicating parallel processing. These. deviations from
single-channel predictions are much too large to be explained by random
fluctuations of RT1
The slope of the function that relates IRI to lSI in Figure 9-6, panel
B, is a meaningful parameter: it represents the amount by which IRI may
be shortened (in msec) if the presentation of S2 is advanced by one millisecond. Both single-channel theory and a grouping hypothesis entail a
slope of zero for" the range of short lSI's. On the other hand, the hypothesis that the processes leading to the two responses are completely independent entails that the slope of the function should be unity. The result
shown in Figure 9-6B is typical: the slope of the IRI function is positive
throughout, and the function is pOSitively accelerated. This result is incompatible with the three hypotheses that have been introduced in this
discussion: single-channel theory, and the grouping and independence
models. The results imply that some attention is devoted to the processing of S2-R2 as soon as S2 is presented. Furthermore, the amount of
attention devoted to S2 increases steadily during the latency of R 1
These results are typical of a large number of studies of refractpriness
(e.g., Bertelson, 1967; Broadbent & Gregory, 1967, exp. 1; Nickerson,
1967; Sanders & Keuss, 1969).
It may be noted in Figure 9-6 that the slope of the IRI function
varies inversely with the complexity of R1 :IRI increases more slowly
with lSI when R 1 is complex than when it is simple. Since the slope of
the IRI function reflects the rate at which S2 is processed, this finding
appears to support an effort theory, which entails a reduced sharing of
capacity when one of the two competing activities is highly demanding.
However, a more fundamental observation is that the shortest IRI is
almost the same at the three levels of complexity. This result suggests a
modified concept of refractoriness, i.e., that there is a minimal interval
that separates successive responses when these responses are not grouped.
If such a minimal IRI is a basic feature of the system, the divergence of
the curves follows necessarily, as the following argument shows. At a low
value of lSI, both RT1 and RT 2 are affected by a change in the complexity of R 1 , but IRI is the same for different levels of complexity. At a high
value of lSI, on the other hand, only RT 1 is affected by the complexity of
R 1 and IRI is consequently longer when R 1 is Simple then when it is
169
complex. Between the two values of lSI, therefore, the slope of the IRI
function must be generally steeper for the simpler R 1 Since this result
follows necessarily from ,the assumption of a common minimal value of
IRI, the temptation to interpret the differences between the slopes of the
curves must be firmly resisted.
There is additional evidence for the notion of a minimal IRI between ungrouped responses. Karlin and Kestenbaum (1968) carried out
an experiment very similar to that of Smith (1969). They studied five
different combinations of RT tasks. In the notation introduced earlier,
the tasks were: i-2; 2-2; 5-2; 1-1; 2-1. The minimal values of IRI
were almost the same for' all conditions: they varied only from 220
milliseconds (for the 1-2 condition) to 244 milliseconds (for the 2-1
condition). The data were generally very similar to those shown in Figure 9-6: the slope of the IRI function was positive in all conditions and
at all values of lSI, and the curves diverged systematically as a function
of R 1 complexity. The complexity of R2 , on the other hand, had very little
effect on the IRI functions.
Keele (1973) has emphasized the importance of these observations
by Karlin and Kestenbaum, and he made them the cornerstone of a general view of attention. Although he did not analyze the data in terms of
IRI, it is probably easiest to present his approach in such terms. 'In his
view, the finding that the minimal IRI does not vary greatly with the
complexity of responses indicates that the processes leading to the two
responses interact only at the stage of response initiation, while earlier
operations occur in parallel and without interference. Thus, Keele separated the stages of information-processing into two sets: (1) perceptual
analysis and memory retrieval (including response selection); (2) initiation and execution of responses. He suggested that the earlier operations
occur in parallel and without interference because they require no attention. Only response-related operations, such as rehearsal or the initiation of overt responses, demand attention and are mutually interfering.
The constancy of the minimal IRI with variations of response complexity
is COllsistent with this hypothesiS of a conflict at the stage of response
initiation.
Keele's position that the processes of perception and retrieval do
not depend on attention is similar to the views of Deutsch and Deutsch
(1963) and Norman (196'8), which were found inadequate in preceding
chapters. However, the finding which Keele emphasizes, i.e., the near
constancy of minimal IRI over experimental conditions, does appear to
be of fundamental importance. Perhaps this was the kernel of truth in
the original hypothesis of psychological refractoriness. If the minimal IRI
is independent of response complexity, the single channel cannot be 10-
170
171
700
600
~
Q)
500
E
..........
c
c:
~
c
400
<J)
V)
c
o
a.
V)
300
'-
....c
Q)
200
Controt
100
100
200
300
400
500
FIGURE 9-7
Data from Broadbent and Gregory (1967), with permission of The Royal Society.
with the stimuli: the subject pressed the key located under each light
that was Hashed. In the other condition (solid line), the S-R relations
were incompatible in both R1 and R2 because the subject was required to
press the key under the light that was not Hashed in each pair.
The results in the two conditions are markedly different. When
the two reactions are compatible, there is considerable parallel processing, as indicated by low values of IRI and by the fact that the slope of
the IRI function is consistently positive. When the reactions are incompatible, in contrast, there is no evidence of any sharing of capacity during the first 250 milliseconds of exposure. In addition, the processing of
the second reaction is relatively ineffective even after R1 is completed,
as indicated by the fact that the IRI function is of less than unit slope.
The shortest IRI in that condition is substantially longer than the con-
172
trol value of RT2, indicating a prolonged disruption of th~ second reaction by the occurrence of the first.
These results are not consistent with the theory proposed by Keele
(1973). If the processes that precede response initiation require no attention and occur in parallel, there is no special reason for a variation of
stimulus-resp'onse compatibility to affect the IRI function. The locus of
difficulty in an incompatible situation is in the stages of retrieval and
selection of the appropriate response, which Keele assumed to be
non-attentive. At the stages of initiation and execution, compatibility
should have no further effects. Thus, Keele's theory lacks a mechanism
that would explain the effect of compatibility on the minimal value of
IRI and on the slope of the'function.
The qualitative difference between the two IRI functions of Figure
9-7 suggests a far-reaching conclusion: perhaps no model can be correct
which assumes that the processing of 8 1 and 52 is necessarily parallel,
nor can a model be correct which assumes that processing of such stimuli is necessarily serial. Models that assume a consistent mode of operation under all conditions may be termed "hardware" models. They
attempt to explain the results in terms of the structure of the machine.
However, the machine seems to be able to organize its operation in different ways. Thus the device with which we are concerned is capable of
purely serial processing on some occasions, and of parallel processing on
others. The behavior of such a device in any situation is, perhaps better
explained by reference to the program which governs its opera~on than
by assuming that its function necessarily mirrors its st:fucture. This is
not to deny that structural limitations exist, but merely to state the obvious point that the observation that a system behaves in a certain mannerdoes not' imply 'that the system must behave in that manner. When
the operation of the system is shown to be qualitatively different in different conditions, its behavior in anyone condition is best explained in
terms of software, program, or strategy. The use of the concept of allocation policy in the present work is intended to suggest such an approach to attention. In Chapters 7 and 8, it was shown that man can both
focus, and divide his attention, within certain limitations that depend on
the task and on the circumstances. It should not be surprising to observe
a similar flexibility in the allocation of capacity in the context of successive speeded responses.
A study in the refractoriness paradigm carried out in my laboratory (Kafry, 1971) led to the fortuitous discovery of another case in
which a slight modification of experimental conditions causes a qualitative alteration in the allocation of capacity. Kafry investigated refractoriness in the R5I case, i.e., the experimental situation in which 52 is always
presented some time after the occurrence of R1 (Rabbitt, 1969; Triggs,
173
1968). She was looking for possible refractoriness effects following a response (Davis, 1957; Welford, 1959).
In all the experiments in her study, R2 was a compatible threechoice response to one of three lights, executed with the right hand. In
the two conditions shown in Figure 9-8, the subject's first task (R1 ) was
to stop a digital millisecond counter as close as possible to a specified
value (600 or 1200 msec in these data). The counter started at zero on
each trial, and the subject stopped it by depressing a key with his
left hand. The key-press caused 8 2 to appear, either immediately
(RSI = 0) or after a variable delay. Figure 9-8 includes data for two
groups of subjects who differ markedly, on the average, in psychomotor
.
skills: 20 untIergraduates and 20 Hight cadets.
The results for both groups were very similar: the "600" condition
caused total refractoriness for about 200 milliseconds following the
900
-...
... ...
Q)
0---0
E 800
......,
o
c:
CI>
en
c:
8.en
700
~
I
'CI>
....
.E
600
500
100
200 .
300
400
FIGURE 9-8
Data from Kafry (1971), with permission. Filled circles: data of 20 students.
Unfilled circles: data of 20 flight cadets.
174
175
finding of major delays ofR2 in the RSI design (Kafry, 1971; Rabbitt,
1969), since there are no conflicting tendencies when S2 is presented
after the completion of R1. The simplest explanation of these delays is
that the preparation for a subsequent stimulus and a subsequent response demands effort. Under some conditions (see, e.g., Fig. 9-8), this
preparation is precluded during the processing of another response.
Response-conflict theory and the limited capacity hypothesis both
suggest that R1 should be somewhat slower in the double-task situation than when it performed alone. Results. confirm this expectation.
Many studies have reported the consistent finding that the reaction to
the first stimulus is slower in the double-task paradigm than when a
single stimulus is presented (Bertelson, 1967; Broadbent & Gregory, 1967;
Gottsdanker, 1969; Gottsdanker, Broadbent & Van Sant, 1963; Herman &
Kantowitz, 1970; Nickerson, 1967; Smith, 1967c; Triggs, 1968). The delay
is usually quite small (around 30 msec). The delay of R1 has been foun'd
to vary inversely with lSI in some experiments: when S2 followed 8 1 in
quick succession, RT1 was slow (Herman & McCauley, 1969). The delay
of R1 also increases with the complexity of the processing that S2 and R2
require (Karlin & Kestenbaum, 1968). The competition between the
processes leading to the two responses is further connrmed by the observation that the speed of R1 and R2 can be manipulated by instructions: as one of these responses is made faster, the other correspondingly
slows (Triggs, 1968). Herman and Kantowitz (1970) have reviewed these
effects in detail.
An important observation that must be considered in explaining refractoriness is that a stimulus which does not require a response can
nevertheless delay the resp(onse to another stimulus. Thus, a large number of studies have s'hown that the.interpolation of an irrelevant stimulus
82 after S1 causes H1 to be delayed (Davis, 1959', 1962; Elithorn, 100'1;
Fraisse, 1957; Kay & Weiss, 1961; Nickerson, 1967; Rubinstein & Rutschman, 1967; Sinith, 1967a). The delay is small (usually 40-60 msec), and
its interpretation is controversial (Bertelson & Tisseyre, 1969; Davis, 1959;
Herman, 196~). A larger delay has been observed where a stimulus 8 1
inhibited a response. When S2 was presented shortly after such an inhibitory stimulus, RT2 was longer than normal (Sanders & Keuss, 1969). These
results are consistent with a theory of limited and shared capacity, but
they are. also easy to explain within a response-conflict theory.
Bernstein (1970; Bernstein, Clark & Edelstein, 1969a, b) has reported the ihterestingfinding that visual .RT can be facilitated by
presenting a loud auditory stimulus some time after the relevant vishal
stimullls. A plausible explanation of this effect is that the tone increases arousal and therefore 'facilitates ongoing processes. When the second
176
REVIEW
177
10
Attention and
Task Interference
CAPACITY INTERFERENCE
179
J80
tion that the subject was asked to perform on material stored in memory (e.g., mentally arrange five words in alphabetical order). Finally,
the activity of verbal recall of stored material caused severe interference
with tracking. This reslllt is consistent with physiological measures of
effort, as well as with other studies of divided attention (Kahneman &
Peavler, 1969; Kahneman & Wright, 1971; Trumbo & Noble, 1970).
In a related study, Shulman and Greenberg (1971) observed that
the probability that a subject would recognize an item in a tachistoscopic
exposure was inversely related to the length of a list,that he was silently
rehearsing at the time. However, the relation between perc~ptual deficit
and memory load appeared to break down when the amount of material
exceeded memory span. This interesting, result confirms the suggestion
that effort no longer increases when a task becomes impossibly difficult.
The same authors also found that reaction time in deciding which of two
lines' is longer is delayed by concurrent rehearsal (Shulman & Greenberg,
1971; Shulman, Greenberg & Martin,1971).
The interaction of learning activity with other tasks may follow
different rules in motor le.arning, which does not involve rehearsal.
Eysenck and Thompson. (1966) reached the surprising conclusion that
concurrent activity disrupts the performanc~, but not the learning, of a
motor skill. Subjects pressed a foot pedal in response to auditory signals
while learning to track on the pursuit rotor. The rate of foot responses
imposed by the auditory signals was varied. The tracking performance
deteriorated as the rate of this interfering response was increased, but
the difference between groups exposed to different levels of distraction
vanished as soon as the distraction was removed. Fo~lowing a rest period,
all groups showed a large reminiscence effect and' precisely identical
tracking ability. Eysenck and Thompson (1966) co,ncluded that attention
is not involved in the acquisition of skill during massed practice. This
provocative conclusion. demands further study.
A study by Keele (1967) provides strong evidence for a hypothesis
of limited capacity. Keele instructed his subjects to turn off a series of
lights; he controlled the difficulty of that task by the compatibility of
the stimulus-response arrangements. In addition, the subjects were asked
to count backward, by one, three, or seven. Measurements of the speed
of both responses indicated some gain from performing the tasks together, when both were easy. The total time required to perform a certain number of responses of both kinds was less when two easy tasks
were combined than when they were performed successively. When the
tasks were both difficult, on the other hand, the attempt to combine or
interweave them resulted in a marked loss of efficiency. As predicted by a
capacity model, the quality of performance on each task decreased regularly with the difficulty of the other.
181
182
DECISION BO'TTLENECK
OR COMPETITION FOR EFFORT
Control. No task.
Free response. Pressing one of five buttons, freely chosen, once
184
(c)
(d)
(e)
every three seconds. This task involves only stages 3 and 4, i.e., the
selection and execution of a response.
Learning the stochastic rules governing a sequence of lights, shown
at the rate of one every three seconds. This task involves only
stages 1 and 2.
"Shadowing" the series of lights, without learning instructions.
Shadowing was done. by pressing the button spatially corresponding
to each light that came on. This task was assumed to involve stages
1,2, and 4.
Anticipating each of the lights by pressing the appropriate button.
This task was assumed to involve all stages.
185
The reinterpretation of the experiment of Trumbo and Noble relies on speculations about what pupillary measurements would have
shown, if collected. This type of reasoning is hardly conclusive. However,
there exist experimental results that directly confirm the continuous covariation of a measure of interference with physiological indications of
effort and arousal (Kahneman, 1970; Kahneman, Beatty & Pollack, 1967).
These results were discussed in an earlier chapter (see Fig. 2-3 on page
21). The subjects in a. series of experiments performed a demanding
digit transformation as their primary task, and as a subsidiary task they
monitored a visual display for a significant signal. Two of the curves in
Figure 2-3 illustrate the time-course of the perceptual deficit that occurred during the transformation task, while a third curve traces concurrent changes of pupil size. Control experiments in which an artificial
pupil was used showed that the dilations of the pupil were not the cause
of the visual deficit. The observation of a close correspondence between
behavioral and physiological measures provides strong support for an
effort theory. Another important observation in Figure 2-3 is that the
perceptual deficit was severe during the pause between the presentation
of the .digits and the subject's response. Thus, the interference with perception was due neither to the presence of concurrent stimuli nor to the
occurrence of concurrent responses.
The present argument suggests a reformulation of single-channel
theory. This theory assumed that the stage of response selection is a
bottleneck, which can only deal with one response at a time. Instead, it
appears plausible to assume that the selection of a response is often highly
demanding of attention and effort. As ;a result, activities that demand
response selection will tend to interfere with other activities. Response
selection, however, is neither a necessary condition for the occurrence
of interference, nor a sufficient condition for the total refractoriness postulated by single-channel theory.
The observation of a perceptual deficit that accompanies the transformation of a series of digits illustrates the use of a probe signal to
measure- variations of spare capacity during the performance of a primary task. To obtain such a measure, the probe must be introduced at an
llnpredictable time. According to the theory of effort outlined in Chapter
2, the accuracy and the speed of the response to an unpredictable probe
reflect the spare capacity that is allocated to perceptual monitoring at
the instant of presentation. The theory assumes that spare capacity de-
186
of
187
188
A subsequent study (Posner & Klein, 1972) provided additional evidence forthe validity of probeRT as a measure of task load. Enormous
delays were observed when the subject was instructed to apply a transfo~mation to the first letter and to match the second letter to the output
of the transformation. The subject was to make a positive response if the
second letter occurred in the alphabet three positions after the first (e.g.,
the response was positive if the first letter was M and the second was P).
This task certainly keeps the subjects very busy during the brief interval
between the first and the second letter. Accordingly, they tend to delay
responding to the probe until the completion of the matching task.
This brief discussion of the perceptual-deficit and probe-RT
methods echoes the conclusions reached earlier in the discussion of
measures of continuous load. The object of all these methods is to measure the attentional demands . of primary tasks, but the results of any
single method must be interpreted with caution, because of the everpresent possibility that the observed interference is due to structural
factors rather than to limitations of capacity. The methodological moral
is clear: effort or load should always be measured by at least two independent methods, so chosen that they are unlikely to cause structural
interference in the same way. For example, a perceptual subsidiary task
minimizes overt responses, but it usually involves some load on shortterm memory; aprobe-RT task causes response conflict, but imposes no
load on memory. The two methods appear to be complementary. Alternatively, either of these methods could be used in conjunction with
physiological measures of effort and arousal (see Chap. 2). The time-lags
involved in autonomic responses, however, make them inadequate for
the study of the microstructure of effort demands. For that purpose, the
only alternative to convergent behavioral measures may be a combination of a behavioral method with measurements of evoked cortical responses (e.g., Posner, Klein, Summers & Buggie, 1973; Posner & Warren,
1972).
189
190
tionale for the use of visually masked stimuli as probes in the measurement of spare capacity. Studies of the duration and locus of fixations
indicate that attention can be quickly directed to a potentially significant stimulus that is not immediately identified. The fixation on a
significant stimulus can also be extended-a" decision that is certainly
made within 150-200 milliseconds of the initial fixation. If the potential
target was first viewed in the visual periphery, a tentative detection can
control the choice of the next fixation (Gould & Schaffer, 1965). In these
examples, an activity of perceptual analysis demands 2 attention. However, a delayed allocation of attention cannot affect perception if .the
stimulus is immediately removed and its trace destroyed by a subsequent mask. In this manner, the use of masked stimuli provides a pure
measure of the attention that was allocated to visual perception at the
instant of presentation.
192
193
often grouped under the collective label of set. .The present treatment
has distinguished several classes of preparatory adjustments.
A state of perceptual readiness for a particular perceptual interpretation'increases the likelihood that this interpretation will be adopted,
both when sensory informatio'n is appropriate to. it, and when the match
between the features of this information and the critical features of the
relevant recognition unit is less than perfect. Perceptual readiness is
mediated by a criterion bias favoring some interpretations over others.
A state of readiness for a particular interpretation implies that the
achievement of this interpretation demands 1 less information input, and
less attention, than does the achievement of other interpretations. Thus,
a stimulus for which one is ready is likely to be identified even when it is
presented on an unattended channel, or at a low level of intensity or
clarity.
A state of response readiness similarly lowers the criterion for the
elicitation of a particular response, or class of responses. It is reasonable
to assume that a response for which one is ready demandst less effort
than does a response for which one is not prepared.
Perceptual and response readiness may be viewed as altered states
of the specific units which are activated in the processes of perceptual
interpretation and response selection. In contrast, selective set is a characteristic of the allocation policy that controls figural emphasis and other
manifestations of selective attention. Here, a selected stimulus demands 2
attention: more attention or effort is allocated to it than to the processing
of other stimuli. Two variants of selective set have been distinguished,
of which one is mediated by the immediate allocation of attention to
stimuli isolated at an early stage of analysis, while the other involves
'
recognition units and a .recursive path of attention control.
The primary mechanism of selective attentionma)7 be identified
with Broadbent's filter. Perceptual emphasis is allocated to stimuli that
possess a particular attribute, e.g., sounds that originate in a particular
place or words printed in a particular color. A search set could affect
processing by the same mechanism, and it is conceivable that a target
for which one is set' can attract attention prior to the activation of the
recognition system, if the target is identified by obvious physical characteristics. A selected stimulus attracts more attention than do other
stimuli. Thus, a stimulus for which one is prepared will "jump" from
the background (e.g., Eriksen & Collills, 1969a; Neisser, 1967). An attended stimulus will also have prior entry, i.e., it will appear to have
occurred sooner than a physically simultaneous unattended stimulus
(Sternberg, Knoll & Gates, 1971). The reaction to a stimulus that matches
expectation is speeded (Egeth & Blecker, 1971). Indeed, some compo-
194
nents of the evoked cortical response occur sooner when the stimulus
matches expectations than when it does not (Posner, Klein, Summers &
Buggie, 1973). The effects of selective attention on the sensitivity parameter of signal detection can be mediated by this type of selective set.
Secondary selective attention is controlled either by a tentative
recognition of a significant stimulus, or by a failure to obtain an adequate
perceptual interpretation for an event which violates the neuronal model
of expectations. Such stimuli demand2 attention, which is allocated to
them via the recursive path of attention control. This mechanism is involved in some search tasks (e.g., monitoring a list for names of animals).
The tentative detection of the selected stimulus probably causes a surge
of eff~rt, as well as a redirection of attention to the detected target.
The various mechanisms of set are not mutually exclusive, and
more than, one mechanism may be engaged in any task. Thus, a set to
search for animal names may increase the perceptual readiness for these
names; it may also sensitize the process of secondary selective attention,
so that a tentative recognition of a target item will cause especially detailed analysis of that item. Preparatory adjustments appear to be
highly flexible.
Other aspects of preparatory set are the elicitation of anticipatory
arousal, and of a specific posture of orientation. The warning signals
commonly used in 'studies of reaction time and of the perception of brief
stimuli, serve both these functions :of orientation and arousal. To be fully
effective, such a warning signal must be delivered about 500 milliseconds before the relevant stimulus. Achieving a state of optimal readiness .takes time. Studies of the foreperiod effect also indicate that o,ptimal
readiness cannot be maintained very.long. Responses to. stimuli that follow the warning signal bya second or more tend to be slower than .when
the foreperiod is half a second. This failure to maintain readiness is consistent with the hypothesis that arousal is largely controlled by the feedback of ongoing activity. In the absence of such feedback, arousal diminishes.
The alerting function of warning signals has been studied in detail
by Posner (Posner & Boies, 1971; Posner, Klein, Summers & Buggie,
1973). ffe concluded that the presentation of the initial letter in the
letter-matching task can facilitate performance both. by increasing alertness and .by increasing the specific readiness for the repetition of that
letter. The two facilitative effects summate without interacting. This
finding suggested the hypothesis that the encoding process whichmediates the specific readiness for a letter is equally effective at various levels
of arousal. An additional discovery concerned the nature of the foreperiod effect: Posner was able to show that the U-shaped function which
relates RT to the duration of the foreperiod is associated with a
195
196
STRUCTURAL IN'I'ERFERENCE
The introduction to this chapter distinguished two types of interference between tasks: capacity interference, which arises as a function
of the attentional demands of competing activities; and structural interference, which occurs because the activities occupy the same mechanisms of perception or response. Structural interference in perception
was illustrated in Chapter 8, where it was shown that concurrent monitoring tasks in one modality tend to be more difficult than concurrent
monitoring in different modalities (Treisman & Davies, 1972). This study
illustrates the gen'eral method by which structural interactions can be
demonstrated. Tasks A and B are equated by difficulty or by a physiological measure of effort, when performed singly. If the combination of
task A with a new task C is more demanding or difficult than the combination of tasks B andC, this result prOvides evidence for interference between A and C beyond what can be explained in terms of attention or
capacity. The alternative interpretation, that tasks Band C are mutually
facilitating, also assumes a structural interaction.
Structural interference appears to have been a confounding factor
in several of the studies that attempted to measure capacity interference.
Thus,Brown (1966) noted that the subsidiary tasks of interval production
and, random-number generation are affected differently by primary activities that involve a high rate of overt responses or a high rate of mental
activity. Similarly, there are indications that probe~RT measures are
especially sensitive to the motor component of the primary activity. The
general rule appears to be that similar activities' tend to be mutually
interfering, unless they 'can be integrated.
Structural interference can also arise within a single task, through
an interaction between the modality of the response and the modality of
the input that controls the response. Brooks (1968) has: offered an elegant
197
demonstration of this effect. In one of his experiments, he briefly presented a line diagram (e.g., Fig. lO-lA), and later required subjects to
begin at the star and categorize successive corners by saying "yes" if the
corner is on the extreme top or bottom and "no" otherwise. The correct
sequence of answers in this example is "yes,yes,yes,no,no,no,no,no,no,yes."
Three modes of response were compared: calling out the words "yes"
, or "no" for each corner; pointing to the appropriate word in columns of
"yes" and "no" (Fig. 10-lB); tapping with the left hand for "yes," and
with the right hand for "no." The first response was purely vocal, while
the second required visual monitoring. Subjects had much more difficulty
with pointing than with the other modes of. report. In another condition,
the subjects heard a sentence (e.g., "A bird in the hand is not in the
busll") and were asked to recall the sentence 'and to categorize each
word as a noun ("yes") or any other part of speech ("no"). The same
thre~ modes of response were used, but now the vocal response was by
far the most difficult. Brooks (1968, p. 354) remarked: "The subjects
reported that they 'could say the sentence to themselves' while tapping
or pointing, but not while saying 'yes' or 'no.' The diagrams could be
'pictured' while the subjects were tapping or saying 'yes' or 'no,' but not
while they were trying to point."
Brooks (1967, 1970) also showed that reading and visualization are
mutually interfering. Subjects were given a verbal description of a spatial
arrangement, and were asked to imagine and describe a rotation of that
198
199
200
The difference between the left-hand and the right-hand sides of this inequality is a measure of structural interference. If the two performance
units are incompatible or otherwise mutually antagonistic, the effort required to perform both together will be greate~i than the sum of the
effort required to perform them separately. In addition, the total effort
required to perform two acts together can be greaterthan the sum of separate demands, if the organization of joint performance itself demands
attention (Lindsay, Taylor & Forbes, 19'68; Moray, 1967; Taylor, Lindsay
& Forbes, 1967).
The assumptions stated so far entail the prediction of some interference for all cases in which non-redundant tasks are performed together,even in the absence of structural interference. The basic assumption of the model is that the supply of effort is a negatively accelerated
function of demand. Since the joint demands of two performance units
are greater than the demands of either, the total deficit must be larger
in joint performance than when the tasks are executed in isolation. Thus,
Total Deficit ~ Sum of Separate Deficits.
201
(2)
(3)
(4)
REVIEW
202
References
J.
S., ANTROBUS,
J.
J.
204
References
205
206
References
207
BLAKE, R. R., and Fox, R. (1969) Visual form recognition threshold and the
psychological refractory period. Perception and Psychophysics, 5, 46-48.
BOGGs, D. H., and SIMON, J. R. (1968) Differential effect of noise on tasks of
varying complexity. Journal of Applied Psychology, 52, 148-153.
BORGER, R. (1963) The refractory period and serial choice-reactions. Quarterly
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 15, 1-12.
BORING, E. G. (1950) A history 'of experimental psychology (2nd ed.). New
York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
BRADSHAW, J. L. (1968a) Load and pupillary changes in continuous processing
tasks. British Journal of Psychology, 59, 265-271.
- - . (1968b) Pupil size and problem solving. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 20,116-122.
BRAND, J. (1971) Classification without identification in visual search. Quarterly
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 23, 178-186.
BROADBENT, D. E. (1952) Listening to one of two synchronous messages. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 44, 51-55.
- - - . (1954a) The role of auditory localization in attention and memory
span. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 47, 191-196.
- - - . (1954b) Som~ effects ,of noise on ,visual performance.. Quarterly Journal
of Experimental Psychology, 6, 1-5.
- - - . (1956) Listening between and during practiced auditory distraction.
British Journal of Psychology, 47, 51-60.
- - - . (1957a) A mechanical model for human attention and immediate memory. Psychological Review, 64j 205-215.
- - - . (1957b) Effects of noise on 'behavior. In Handbook of noise control,
ed. C. M. Harris. New York: McGraw-HilI. Pp. 1-33.
- - - . (1958) Perception and communication. London: Pergamon Press Ltd.
(1963) Possibilities and difficulties in the concept of arousal. In Vigilance: A ~ymposium, eds. D. N. Buckner and J. J. McGrath. New York:
McGraw-Hill. Pp. 184-198.
(1967) Word-frequency effect and response bias. Psychological Review, 74, 1-15.
(1970), Stimulus set and response set: Two kinds of selective attention. In Attention: Contemporary theories and analysis, ed. D. I. Mostofsky. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts. Pp. 51-60.
. (1971) Decision and stress. London: Academic Press.
, and GREGORY, M. (1961) On the recall of stimuli presented alternately
to two sense organs. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 13,
103-109.
, and GREGORY,M. (1963) Division of attention and the decision theory
of signal detection. Proceedings of the Royal Society, B, 158, 222-231.
-----, and GREGORY, M. (1964) Stimulus set and response set: The alterna. tionof attention. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 16, 309317.
208
References
209
BRYDEN, M. P. (1961) The role of post-exposuraI eye movements in tachistoscopic perception. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 15, 220~225.
- - - . (1962) Order of report in dichotic listening. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 16, 291-299.
- - - . (1964) The manipulation of strategies of report in dichotic listening.
Canadian Journal of Psychology, 18, 126-138~
- - - . (1971) Attentional strategies and short-term memory iIi dichotic listening. Cognitive Psychology, 2, 99-116.
BURSILL, A. E. (1958) The restriction of peripheral vision during exposure to
hot and humid conditions. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology,
10, 113-129.
CALLAWAY, E. (1959) The influence of amobarbital (amylobarbitone) and
methamphetamine on the focus of attention. Journal of Mental Science,
105, 382-392.
- - - , and STONE, G. (1960) Re-evaluating the focus of attention. In Drugs
and behavior, eds. L. Uhr and J. G. Miller. New York: John Wiley. Pp.
393-398.
- - - , and THOMPSON, S. V. (1953) Sympathetic activity and perception:
An approach to the relationships between autonomic activity and personality. Psychosomatic Medicine, 15, 443-455.
CAMPOS, J. J., and JOHNSON, H. J. (1966) The effects of verbalization instructions and visual attention on heart rate and skin conductance. Psychophysiology, 2, 305-310.
- - - , and JOHNSON, H. J. (1967) Affect, verbalization, and directional fractionation of autonomic responses. Psychophysiology, 3, 285-290.
CARVER, R. P. (1971) Pupil dilation and its relationship to information processing during reading and listening. Journal of Applied Psychology, 55,
126-134.
CATLIN, J. (1969) On the word-frequency effect. Psychological Review, 76,
504-506.
CAVANAGH, J. P., and CHASE, W. G. (1971) The equivalence of target and nontarget processing in visual search. Perception and Psychophysics, 9, 493495.
CHASE, W. G., GRAHAM, F. K., and GRAHAM, D. T. (1968) Components of HR
response in anticipation of reaction time and exercise tasks. Journal of
Experimenta.l Psychology,. 76, 642-648.
CHERRY, E. C. (1953) Some experiments on the recognition of speech, with
one and two ears. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 25, 975979.
. (1957) On human communication: A review, a survey, and a criticism.
Cambridge: Technology Press, MIT; New York: John Wiley.
, and TAYLOR, W. K. (1954) Some further experiments upon the recognition of speech with one and two ears. Journal of the Acoustical Society
of America, 26, 554-559.
210
COHEN, J. (1969) Very slow brain potentials relating to expectancy: The CNV.
In Average evoked potentials: Methods, results, and evaluations, eds. E.
Donchin and D. B. Lindsley. NASA, SP-191, Washington, D.C. Pp.
143-198.
.
COHEN, M. J., and JOHNSON, H. J. (1971) Relationship between heart rate and
muscular activity within a classical conditioning paradigm. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 90, 222-226.
COLAVITA, F. B. (1971) Interspecies differences in sensory dominance. Paper
presented at the Twelfth Annual Meeting of the Psychonomic Society,
St. Louis, Missouri, November.
COLMAN, F. D., and PAIVIO, A. (1969) Pupillary response and galvanic skin
response during an imagery task. Psychonomic Science, 16, 296-297.
- - - , and PAIVIO, A.(1970) Pupillary dilation and mediation process during
paired-associate learning. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 24, 261-270.
CONNOR, W. H., and LANG, P. J. (1969) Cortical slow-wave and cardiac-rate
responses in stimulus orientation and RT conditions. Journal of Exp~ri
mental Psychology, 82, 310-320.
COOMBS, C. H., DAWES, R. M., and TVERSKY, A. (1970) Mathematical psychology: An elementary introduction. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: PrenticeHall.
COQUERY, J.M., and LACEY, J. I. (1966) The effects of foreperiod duration on
the components of the cardiac response during the foreperiod of a
reaction-time experiment. Paper presented at the Meeting of the Society
for Psychophysiological Research, Denver, October.
CORBALLIS, M. C., and; LUTHE, L. (1971) Two-channel visual memory. Perception and Psychophysics, 9, 361-367.
CORCORAN, D. W. J. (1965) Personality and the inverted-U relation. British
Journal of Psychology, 56, 267-273.
CORNSWEET, D. J. (1969) Use of 'Cues in the visual periphery under conditions
of arousal. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 80, 14-18.
CORTEEN, R. S. (1969) Skin conductance changes and word recall. British
Journal of Psychology, 60, 81-84.
- - - , and WOOD, B. (1972) Autonomic responses to shock-associated words
in an unattended channel. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 94,
308-313.
CRAFT, J. L., and SIMON, J. R. (1970) Processing symbolic information from a
visual display: Interference from an irrelevant directional cue. Journal of
Experimental Psychology, 83, 415-420.
CRAIK, K. J. W. (1947) Theory of the human operator in control system~ I.
The operator as an engineering system. British Journal of Psychology, 38,
56-61.
------. (1948) Theory of the human operator in control systems II. Man as an
element ina control system. British Journal of Psychology, 38, 142-148.
CREAMER, L. R. (1963) Event uncertainty, psychological refractory period, and
human data processing. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 66, 187194.
References
211
CROVITZ, H. F., and DAVES, W. (1962) Tendencies to eye movement and perceptual accuracy. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 63, 495-498.
CROWDER, R.G. (1967) Prefix effects in immediate memory. Canadian Journal
of Psychology, 21, 450-461.
- - - . (1969) Phonic interference and the prefix effect. Journal of Verbal
Learning and Verbal Behavior, 8, 302-321.
- - - . (1971) Waiting for the stimulus suffix: Decay, delay, rhythm, and
readout in immediate memory. Quarterly Journal of Exp'erimental Psychology, 23, 324-340.
- - - , and MORTON, J. (1969) Precategorical acoustic storage (PAS). Perception and Psychophysics, 5, 365-373.
DALLETT, K. M. (1964) Effects of a supplementary prefix on recall. Journal
of Experimental Psychology, 67, 296--298.
DAVIES, D. R. (1968) Physiological and psychological effects of exposure to
high intensity noise. Applied Acoustics, 1, 215-233.
- - - , and HOCKEY, G. R. J. (1966) The effects of ,~oise and doubling the
'signal frequency on individual differences, in visual vigilance performance. British Journal of Psychology, ,57, 381-389.
- - - , and TAYLOR, A. (1969) Varied auditory stimulation, temperament
differences and vigilance performance. British Journal of Psychology, 60,
453-457.
DAVIS, R. (1957) The human operator as a single channel information system.
Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 9, 119-129. '
- - - . (1959) The role of "attention" in the psychological refractory period.
Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 11, 211-220.
- - - . (1962) Choice reaction times and the theory of intermitt~ncyin human
performance. Quarterly Journal of Experimental' Psychology, 14, 157166.
DAVIS, R. C. (1957) Response patterns. Transactions of the New York Academy
of Sciences, series 2, 19, 731-737.
DAY, H. (1965) Exploratory behavior as a function of individual differences
and level o~ arousal. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Toronto.
- - - . (1966) Looking time as a function of stimulus variables and individual
differences. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 22, 423-428.
DAY, M.E. (1964) An eye movement phenomenon relating to attention,
thought and anxiety. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 19, 443-446.
- - - . (1967a) An eye-movement indicator of type and level of anxiety:
Some clin'ical observations. Journal of Clinical Psy'chology, 23, 438-441.
- - - . (1967b) An eye movement indicator of individual differences in the
phYSiological organization of attentional processes and anxiety. Journal
of Psychology, 66, 51-62.'
DEANE~ G. E. (1961) Human heart rate responses during experimentally induced anxiety. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 61, 489-493.
DE GROOT, A. D. (1966) Perception and memory versus thought: Some old
ideas and recent findings. In Problem solVing: Research, method, and
theory, ed. B. Kleinmuntz. New York: John Wiley.
212
DEUTSCH, J. A., and DEUTSCH, D. (1963) Attention: Some theoretical considerations. Psychological Review, 70, 80-90.
- - - , and DEUTSCH, D. (1967) Comments on "Selective attention: Perception or response?" Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 19,
362-363.
DILLON, R. F., and REID, L. S. (1969) Short-term memory as a function of information processing during the retention interval. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 81, 261-269.
DIMOND, S. (1970) Reaction times and response competition between the
right and left hands. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 22,
513-520.
DUFFY, E. (1957) The psychological significance of the concept of "arousal"
or "activation." Psychological Review, :64, 265-275.
DURHAM, R. L., NUNNALLY,J. C., and LEMOND, L. C. (1971) The effects of
levels of information conflict on visual selection. Perception and Psychophysics, 10, 93-96.
EASON, R. G. (1963) Relation between effort, tension level, skill, and performance efficiency in a perceptual-motor task. Perceptual and Motor
Skills, 16, 297-317.
EASTERBROOK, J. A. (1959) The effect of emotion on cue utilization and the
organization of behavior. Psychological Review, 66, 183-201.
ECETH, H. E. (1967) Selective attention. Psychological Bulletin, 67, 41-57.
- - - , BLECKER, D. L., and KAMLET, A. S. (1969) Verbal interference in a
perceptual comparison task. Perception and Psychophysics, 6, 355-356.
- - - , and PACHELLA, R. (1969) Multidimensional stimulus identification.
Perception and Psychophysics, 5, 341-346.
EISLER, H., and KNOPPEL, J. K. (1970) Relative attention in judgments of
heterogeneous similarity. Perception and Psychophysics, 8, 420-426.
ELITHORN, A. (1961) Central intermittency: Some further observations. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 13, 240-247.
- - - , and LAWRENCE, C. (1955) Central inhibition: Some refractory observations. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 7, 116-127.
ELLIOTT, R. (1969) Tonic he~rt rate: Experiments on the effects of collative
variables lead to a hypothesis about its motivational significance. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology, 12, 211-228.
- - - , BANKART, B., and LIGHT, R. (1970) Differences in the motivational
significance of heart rate and palmar conductance: Two tests of a hypoth.esis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 14,166-172.
ELLIS, S. H. ~nd CHASE, W. G. (1971) Parallel processing in item recognition.
Perception and Psychophysics, 10, 379-384.
ELLS, J. (1969) Attention requirements of movement control. Unpublished
Ph. D. dissertation, University of Oregon.
EpSTEIN, W., and ROCK, I. (1960) Perceptual set as an artifact of recency.
American Journal of Psychology, 73, 214-228.
References 213
ERIKSEN, C. W., and COLLINS, J. F. (1969a) Visual perception rate under two
conditions of search. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 80, 489-492.
- - - , and COLLINS, J. F. (1969b) Temporal course of selective attention.
Journal of Experimental Psychology, 80, 254-261.
- - - , and HOFFMAN, J. E. (1972) Some characteristics of selective attention
in visual perception determined by vocal reaction time. Perception and
Psychophysics, 11, 169-171.
- - - , and LAPPIN, J. S. (1967) Selective attention and very short-term recognitionmemory for nonsense forms. Journal of Experimental Psychology,
73, 358-364.
- - - , and ROHRBAUGH, J. W. (1970) Some factors determining efficiency of
selective attention. American Journal of Psychology, 83, 330-342.
EXLINE, R. V. (1963) Exploration in the process of person perception: Visual
interaction in response to competition, sex and need for affiliation. Journal
of Personality, 31, 1-20.
- - - . (1971) Visual interaction: The glances of power and preference. In
Nebraska symposium on motivation, ed. J. K. Cole. Lincoln: University
of Nebraska Press. Pp. 163-206.
E.YSENCK, H. J. (1967) The biological basis of personality. Sp.ringfield, Ill.:
Charles C. Thomas.
- - - , and THOMPSON, W. (1966) The effects of distraction on pursuit rotor
learning, performance and reminiscence. British Journal of Psychology,
57, 99-106.
FANTZ,R. L. (1958) Pattern vision in young infants. Psychological Record,
8,43-47.
- - - . (1965a) Visual perception from birth as shown by pattern selectivity.
Annals of the New York' Academy of Sciences, 1'18, 793-814.
- - - . (1965b) The ontogeny of perception. In Behavior of non-human
primates, eds. A. M. Schrier, H. F. Harlow, and F. Stolhitz. New York:
Academic Press. Pp. 365-463.
- - - . (1967) Visual perception and experience in early infancy: A look at
the hidden side of behavior development. In Early behavior: Comparative and developmental approaches, eds. H. W. Stevenson, E. H. Hess,
and H. L. Rheingold. New York: John Wiley.
FEHRER, E., and RAAB, D. (1962) Reaction time to stimuli masked by metacontrast. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 63, 143-147.
FELFOLDY, G. L., and GARNER, W. R. (1971) The effects on speeded classification of implicit and explicit instructions regarding redundant dimensions. Perception and Psychophysics, 9, 289-292.
FELLOWS,. B. J. (19'68) The discrimination process and development. Oxford:
Pergamon Press.
FITTS, P. M., and BIEDERMAN, I. (1965) S-R compatibility and information reduction. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 69, 408-412.
- - - , and POSNER, M. I.' (1967) Human performance. Belmont, Calif.:
Brooks Cole Publishing Co.
.214
References
215
216
References
217
218
References
219
220
References
221
222
LIBERMAN, A. M., COOPER, F. S., SHA~WEILER, D. P., and STUDDERTKENNEDY, M. (1967) Perception of the speech code. Psychological Review, 74, 431-461.
LINDSAY, P. H. (19'70) Multichannel processing in perception. In Attention:
Contemporary theory and analysis, ed. D. I. Mostofsky.New York:
Appleton-Century-Crofts. Pp. 149-171.
- - - , CUDDY, L. L., and TULVING, E. (1965) Absolute judgments of simultaneously presented visual and auditory stimuli. Psychonomic Science, 2,
211-212.
- - - , and NORMAN, D. A. (1969) Short-term retention during a simultaneous
detection task. Perception and Psychophysics, 5, 201-205.
- - - , TAYLOR, M. M., and FORBES,S. M. (1968) Attention and multidimensional discrimination. Perception and Psychophysics, 4, 113-117.
LOCKHEAD,G. R. (1966a) Effects of dimensional redundancy on visual discrimination. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 72, 95-104.
- - - . (1966b) Visual discrimination and methods of presenting redundant
stimuli. Proceedings of the Seventy-fourth Annual Convention of the
American Psychological Association, 1, 67-68.
LO~ENS, S. A., JR., and DARROW, C. W. (1962) Eye movements, EEG, GSR
and EKG during mental multiplications.EEG and Clinical Neurophysiology, 14, 739-746.
LOVEJOY, E. P. (1966) Analysis of the overlearning reversal effect. Psych'ological Review, 73, 87-103.
- - - . (19'68) Attention in discrimination learning: A point of view and a
theory. San Francisco: Holden-Day.
LOWE, D., and MERIKLE, P. M. (1970) On the disruption of short-term memory
by a response prefix. Canadian Journal of Psychology, 24, 169-177.
LUBORSKY, L., BLINDER, B., and SCHIMEK, J. (1965) Looking, recalling and
GSR as a function of defense. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 70,
270-280.
LURIA, A. R. (1961) The role of speech in the regulation of normal and abnormal behavior, ed. J. Tizard. New York: Liveright.
LYNN, R. (1966) Attention, arousal and the orientation reaction. Oxford:
Pergamon Press.
MACKINTOSH, N. J. (1964) Overtraining and transfer within and between dimensions in the rat. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 16,
250-256.
- - - . (1965) Selective attention in animal discrimination learning. Psychological Bulletin, 64, 124-150.
- - - . (1971) An analysis of overshadowing and blocking. Quarterly Journal
of Experimental Psychology, 23, 118-125.
MACKWORTH, J. F. (1969) Vigilance and habituation: A neuropsychological
approach. Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England: Penguin Books.
References
223
- - - . (1970) Vigilance and attention: A signal detection approach. Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England: Penguin Books.
MACKWORTH, N. H. (1965) Visual noise causes tunnel vision. Psychonomic
Science, 3, 67-68.
- - - , and BRUNER, J. S. (1970) How adults and children search and recognize pictures. Human Development, 13, 149-177.
- - - , and MORANDI, A. J. (1967) The gaze selects informative details within
pictures. Perception and Psychophysics, 2, 547-552.
MADSEN, M. C., ROLLINS, H. A., and SENF, G. M. (1970) Variables affecting
immediate memory for bisensory stimuli: Eye-ear analogue studies of
dichotic listening. Journal of Experimental Psychology Monograph
Supplement, 83, 1-16.
MALMO, R. B. (19'59) Activation: A neuropsychological dimension. Psychological Review, '66, 367-386.
- - - . (19'65) Physiological gradients and behavior. Psychological Bulletin,
64, 225-234.
- - _ . (1966) Cognitive factors in impairment: A neuropsychological study
of divided set. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 71, 184-189.
- - - , and SURWILLO, W. W. (1960) Sleep deprivation: Changes in performance and physiological indicants of activation. Psychological Monog.raphs, 74, 502.
MALTZMAN, I., HARRIS, L., INGRAM, E., and WOLFF, C. (1971) A primary
effect in the orienting reflex to stimulus change. Journal of Experimental
Psychology, 87, 202-206.
- - - , and RASKIN, D. C. (1965) Effects of individual differences in the
orienting reflex on conditioning and complex processes. Journal of Experimental Research in Personality, 1, 1-16.
MARCEL, A. J. (1970) Some constraints on sequential and parallel processing,
and the limits of attention. Acta Psychologica, 33, 77-92.
MASSARO, D. W. (1972) PreperceptuaI images, processing'time, and perceptual
units in auditory perception. Psychological Review, 79, 124-145.
MCCORMACK, P. D., and HALTRECHT, E. J. (1966) Monitoring eye movements
under two conditions of presentation of paired-associate materials.
Canadian Journal of Psychology, 20, 154-159.
- - - , HALTRECHT, E. J., and HANNAH, T. E. (1966) Monitoring eye move..
ments in nonlearning situations. Psychonomic Science, 6, 371-372.
- - - , HALTRECHT, E. J., and HANNAH, T. E. (1967) Monitoring eye movements during the learning of successive paired-associate lists. Journal of
Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 6, 950-953.
- - - , and HANNAH, T. E. (1967) Monitoring eye movements during the
learning of high and low meaningfulness paired-associate lists. Psych0nomic Science, 8, 443-444.
- - - , and MOORE, T. E. (1969) Monitoring eye movements during the
224
References
225
226
References 227
228
References
229
230
References
231
232
References
233
234
References
235
236
References
237
Name Index
Adams, J. A., 176, 192
Agnew, M., 39
Agnew, N., 39
Aldridge, V. J., 32
Allport, D. A., 153, 154, 198, 199
Alpern, M., 50
Amadeo, M., 64
Ambler, B., 74, 127
Anderson, D. R., 99
Anderson, J. R., 137
Antonis, B., 198
Antrobus, J. S., 64
Archer, E. J., 101, 109
Argyle, M.,63
Atkinson, R. C., 122
Attneave, F., 5, 74
Avetbach, E., 83, 103
Avner, D., 143, 150, 151, 162
Axelrod, S., 154
Baddeley, A. D., 42, 179, 182
Badia, P., 43
Bahrick, fI. P., 37
Bakan, P., 35, 54, 64
Bankart, B., 32
Barenfeld, M., 62
Barnett, T., 138
Bartz, D. H., 139
Bashford, M. B., 54
Beatty, J., 16-17, 19-20, 25-26, 46, 85,
94, 125, 185
Beck, J., 74-75, 127-29
Belton, J. A., 35
Ben-Ishai, R., 119
Berkson, G., 52
Berlyne, D. E., 3, 41, 43, 52-54, 137
Bernstein, A. S., 46
Bernstein, I. H., 175
Bersh, P. J., 31
Bertelson, P., 168, 175, 176
Bever, J., 43
Bever, T. G., 137
Biederman, I., 106, 109
Biryukov, D. A., 45
Blake, M. J. F., 42
Blake, R. R., 186
Blecker, D. L., 110, 193
Blinder, B., 59
Boggs, D. H., 35
Boies, S. J., 16, 33, 41, 187, 188, 194,
195
Borger, R., 176
Boring, E. G., 137
Borsa, D. M., 41, 43
Bower, G. H., 98-99, 101.
Bradshaw, J. L., 19, 26
Brand, J., 87
Briggs, G. E., 183
Broadbent, D.E., 6, 8, 12, 34-36, 38-39,
41, 70-71, 76, 84, 87-88, 91,
93-94, 96, 103, 112, 114, 116-18,
120-23, 125, 130, 135-39, 143,
146, 168, 170, 171, 175, 177, 179,
238
Broadbent (cont.)
182, 193, 195, 196
Broadhurst, P. L., 39
Brooks, L. R., 196, 197
Brown, C. R., 94
Brown, I. D., 182, 196
Brown, J., 118
Brown, L. T., 53-54
Bruner, J. S., 56, 58, 88, 93
Bryden, M. P., 41, 61, 64, 138-39, 140
Buggie, S., 41, 188, 194, 195
Bursill, A. E., 37, 38
Callaway, E., 38-40
Campbell, H., 29
Campos, J. J., 33
Carey, S. T., 42
Carver, R. P., 25
Catlin, J., 94
Cavanagh, J. P., 83
Chase, W. G., 31, 48, 75, 83
Checkosky, S. F., 106
Cherry, E. C., 112-13, 117
Clark, M. H., 175
Climan, M. H., 20
Cohen, J., 32
Cohen, M. J., 32
Colavita, F. B., 141, 151, 157, 162
Collins, J. F., 80, 83, 193
Colman, F. D., 18-20
Connor, W. H., 31, 32, 48
Conrad, C., 86, 161
C'oombs, C. H., 88
Cooper, F. S., 125
C'ooper, R., 32
Coquery, J. M., 31
Corballis, M. C., 140
Corcoran, D. W. J., 35
Coriell, A. S., 83
Comsweet, D. J., 38
Comsweet, J. C., 58
Cornsweet, T. W., 58
Corteen, R. S., 41, 118, 130
Craft, J. L., 48
Craik, K. J. W., 162, 163
Craw, M. A., 41
Creamer, L. R., 176
Crider, A., 18, 31
Crovitz, H. F., 61
Crowder, R. G., 121, 132-33
Cuddy, L. L., 146
Curtis, J. F., 114, 118, 138
Dallett, K. M., 132
Darrow, C. W., 64
Daves, W., 61
Davies, A., 142, 153, 154, 196, 199
Davies, D. R., 35
Davis, R., 29, 175
Davis, R. C., 163, 173
Dawes, R. M., 88
Day, H., 53, 54
Day, M. E., 63-64
Dean, J., 63
Deane, G. E., 31
Decker, L., 94
Defran, R. H., 43
De Groot, A. D., 56, 62
Deutsch, D., 6, 123-25, 135, 136, 143,
144, 145, 148, 155, 169
Deutsch, J. A., 6, 123-25, 135, 136, 143,
144, 145, 148, 155, 169
Diamond, I. T., 154
Dill, A. B., 59
Dillon, R. F., 179
Dimond, S., 162
Drynan, R., 179
Duchknowsky, A., 22
Duffy, E., 34
Dulewicz, V., 81
Durham, R. L., 54
Eason, R. G., 181
Easterbrook, J. A., 16, 28, 37, 38, 40,
42, 49
Edelstein, B. A., 175
Egeth, H., 103, 105, 108-10, 193
Ehrlich, S., 59
Eisler, H., 108
Elithom, A., 175, 176
Elliott, R., 32-33
Ellis, S. H., 75
Ells, J., 187
Epstein, W., 45
Eriksen,C. W., 78-80, 83-84, 193
Ettema, J. H., 17
Exline, R. V., 63
Eysenck, H. J., 35, 180
Fantz, R. L., 52
Farha, W., 54
Faw, T. T., 54
Feamley, J. S., 123, 145, 148
Fehrer, E., 70
Felfoldy, G. L., 107
Fellows, B. J., 98, 102
Fennell, E., 139
Ferguson, J. B., 25
Fisher, R. P., 179, 183
Fitts, P. M., 5, 37, 109
Fodor, J. A., 137
Forbes, S. M., 149, 200
Forrin, B., 109
Fox, L. A., 110
Fox, R., 186
Fraisse, P., 59, 175
Freud, S., 128
Furedy, J. J., 45
Furst, C. J., 59
Galanter, E., 192
Gardner, G. T., 16
Gamer, W. R., 5, 101, 106, 107, 108, 109
Garvey, W. D., 181
Gates, B. A., 137, 193
Geffen, G., 88, 94, 96, 141, 143
Gelman, R. S., 41
Germana, J., 43
Gesell, A., 52
Gibson, E. J., 86, 87, 102
Gibson, J. J., 63
Gold, C., 122
Goldstein, E., 133
Goldwater, B. C., 19
Gomez, E., 64
Goodwin, W. R., 101
Gopher, D., 62, 63, 119, 151, 154
Gordon, I. E., 81
Gottsdanker, R., 175
Gottwald, R. L., 106
Gould, J. D., 57, 58, 59, 60, 191
Graham, D. T., 31, 48
Graham, F. K., 31, 70
Gray, J. A., 139
Green, D. M., 88
Greenberg, S. N., 16, 85, 130, 179, 183,
187
Greenwald, A. G., 118, 198
Gregory, L. P., 53
Gregory, M., 85, 91, 94, 96, 122, 125,
138, 139, 168, 170, 171, 175, 177
Grindley, G. C., 59
Grings, W. W., 43
Guzy, L. T., 154
Haber, R. N., 103, 104
Hakerem, G., 46
Hale, S. M., 19, 184
Haltrecht, E. J., 61
Hamacher, J. H., 41
Hannah, T. E., 61
Harasymin, S. J., 19
Hardwick, J., 142, 148, 150, 192
Harris, C. S., 103, 104
Harris, L., 45
Hastings, S. E., 31
Hatter, J. E., 42
Haviland, S.E., 86
Hawkins, H. L., 106
Heider, F., 76
Held, R., 127
JIelmholtz, H. von, 59
Henik, A., 115
Herman, L. M., 174, 175, 176
Hernandez-Peon, R., 40, 78
Hershenson, M., 52
Hess, E. H., 19
Hillyard, S. A., 32
Hintzman, D. L., 110
Hitchcock, C. H., 140
Hochberg, J. E., 125, 127, 128, 131
Hockey, G. R. J., 34, 35, 38
Hoenig, Y. J., 133
Hoffman, J. E., 79, 84
Holgate, V., 101
Holloway, C. M., 132
House, B. J., 99, 100
Houston, B. K., 35, 39
Howard, J. L., 31, 32
Howes, D. H., 93
Hyman, R., 108
Ilg, F. L., 52
Imai, S., 101, 109
Ingle, D., 127
Ingram, E., 45
Ittleson, W. H., 92
James, W., 137
Jenks, R. S., 31
Jensen, A. R., 109
Johnson, D. A., 20
Johnson, H. J., 32, 33, 50, 65
239
Johnson, L. C., 43
Johnston, W. A., 179, 183
Jones, L. V., 101
Jones, T. M., 39
Jongman, R. W., 56, 62
Jordan, A., 138
Kafry, D., 172, 173, 175, 176, 177
Kagan, J., 29, 102
Kahneman, D., 15, 16, 17, 18, 19,20,22,
24, 25, 26, 46, 60, 61, 70, 85, 94,
114, 115, 11~ 125, 14~ 14~ 154,
180, 184, 185, 200
Kalafat, J., 29
Kalsbeek, J. W. H., 17, 181
Kamlet, A. S., 110
Kantowitz, B. H., 174, 175
Kaplan, I. T., 62
Kaplan, S., 41
Karlin, L., 169, 175, 177
Kaufman, L., 51, 56, 60
Kay, H., 175
Keefe, F. B., 43
Keele, S. W., 8, 9, 12, 16, 27, 106, 110,
143, 158, 177, 180, 186, 189
Keeley, S. M., 84
Kendon, A., 63
Kernler, D. G., 99, 100
Kessen, W., 52, 56
Kestenbaum, R., 169, 175, 177
Keuss, P. J. G., 162, 168, 175
Kienstra, R. A., 43
Kilpatrick, R., 92, 93
Kinsbourne, M., 63
Klein, G. S., 110
Klein, J. A., 25
Klein, R., 41
Klein, R. M., 187, 188, 194, 195
Kleinsmith, L. J., 41
Kleitman, N., 42
Knoll,R. L., 137, 193
Knoppel, J. K., 108
Knott, P. D., 22
Koenig, I. D., 41
Koffka, K., 119
Kohn, B., 41, 64
Korchin, S. J., 41
Kornblum, S., 12
Kotses, H., 43
Krechevsky, I. A., 99, 102
Kristofferson, A. B., 137
Kroll,- N. E. A., 154
Kiilpe, 0., 103, 105, III
La Berge, D. L., 103, 104
Lacey, B. C., 19, 29, 31, 32
Lacey, J. I., 19, 29, 31, 32
Ladefoged, P., 137
Landsown, E. L., 59
Lang, P. J., 31, 32, 48
Lappin, J. S., 84, 104, 105, 123
Lashley, K. S., 98, 99, 102, 191
Lass, N., 60, 61
Lawrence, C., 176
Lawrence, D. H., 83, 99, 101, 103
Lawrence, G. H., 53, 54
Lawson, E. A., 114, 123, 144
Lazar, R., 80
. Leckart, B. T., 54
240
McCallum, W. C., 32
McCauley, M. E., 175
McCormack, P. D., 61
McDonnell, P., 53
Mackintosh, N. J., 98, 99, 100, 101
Mackworth, N. H., 56, 58, 84
Madsen, M. C., 138, 139
Malmo, R. B., 34, 36, 196
Maltzman, I., 43, 45
Mandell, E. E., 41
Marcel, A. J., 107
Martin, D. W., 179, 180, 183, 187
Massaro, D. W., 122, 140
Merikle, P. M., 198
Michon, J. A., 181, 182
Michotte, A., 76
Miller, F. L., 43
Miller, G. A., 192
Mitchell, R. F., 86
Molloy, F. M., 20
Montague, W. E., 109
Moore, T. E., 61
Morandi, A. J., 56
Moray, N., 8, 12, 91, 94, 114, 115, 117,
122, 125, 137, 138, 141, 142, 143,
148, 149, 150, 151, 162, 200
Morin, R. E., 109
Morton, J., 8, 58, 85, 93, 110, 122, 132,
133
Moss, H. A., 29
Mowbray, G. H., 138, 141, 153
Munsinger, H., 52
Murdock, B. B., 25, 179
Murray, D. J., 140
Naylor, J. C., 183
Neisser, D., 7, 57, 71, 75, 80, 81, 117,
122, 125, 126, 127, 128, 129, 132,
133, 135, 137, 140, 143, 193
Nickerson, R. S., 168, 175, 176
Ninio, A., 115, 146, 148, 186
Noble, M., 183, 184, 185
Norman, D. A., 17,88,96,122, 124, 125,
136, 137, 143, 145, 148, 155, 169
Notterman, J. M., 31
Novick, R., 80
Nunnally, J. C., 22, 54
Salapatek, P., 56
Sanders, A. F., 57, 60, 139, 162, 168, 175
Satz, P., 139
Saur, D. P., 45
Savin, H. B., 139
Schaefer, T., 25
Schaffer, A., 57, 58, 191
Schiller, P. H., 128
Schimek, J., 54
Schlosberg, H., 34
Schneider, G. E., 127
Schoenfeld, W. N., 31, 62
Schouten, J. F., 181
Schroots, J. J. F., 139
Schultz, R. W., 61
Schvaneveldt, R. W., 157-61, 162, 177
Schwartz, F., 31, 128
Scott, D., 42, 179
Scull, J., 45
Seibel, R., 162
Senders, J. W., 58, 60
Senf, G. M., 138, 139
Shaffer, L. H., 142, 148, 150, 176, 192
Shankweiler, D. P., 125
Shapiro, D., 18
Shepard, R. N., 101, 108
Shepp, B. E., 99
Shiffrin, R. M., 16, 122
Shor, R. E., 110
Shotland, R. L., 64
Shulman, H. G., 16, 85, 130, 180, 187
Simmel, M., 76
Simmons, D. C., 182
Simon, H. A., 62
Simon, J. R., 35, 48
Simpson" H. M., 19, 20, 25, 184
Singer, J. L., 64
Small, A. M., Jr., 48
Smith, E. E., 86, 106, 183
Smith, F., 85
Smith, J. C., 179
Smith, M. C., 166, 169, 175, 176, 177,
195
Snashall, A., 42
Snyder, C. R. R., 84
Sokolov, E. N., 42, 43, 44, 46, 81, 126
Solomon, L. N., 138, 196
Solomon, R. L., 93
Spaulding, S. J., 29
Sperling, G., 84, 103, 114, 120, 121
Spieth, W., 114, 118, 138
Spoehr, K. T., 86
Steinman, R. J., 110
Stennett, R. G., 34
Sternberg, S., 137, 138, 193
Stone, G., 38, 39, 40
Stoper, A., 57
Strongman, K., 63
Stroop, J. R., 32, 33, 39, 40, 64, 98, 109,
110
Studdert-Kennedy, M., 125
Suchman, R. G., 102
Summers, J., 41, 188, 194, 195
Surwillo, W., 36
Sutherland, N. S., 98, 99, 100, 101, 102
Sutterer, J. R., 31, 32
Sutton, S., 46
Swets, J. A., 88
Swink, J., 183
241
Talland, G. A., 39
Tanner, W. P., Jr., 88
Tarte, R. D., 41
Taylor, A., 35
Taylor, F. V., 181
Taylor, M. M., 149, 200
Taylor, W.K., 113
Tecce, J. J., 32
Telford, C. W., 163
Thackray, R. I., 17
Thomas, E. L., 59
Thompson, P.O., 141
Thompson, S. V., 38
Tickner, A. H., 182
Tikhomirov, O. K., 62
Tinker, M. A., 58
Tisseyre, F., 175
Titchener, E. B., 1, 78
Toth, J. C., 35
Townsend, V., 59
Trabasso, T. R., 98, 99, 101
Trask, F. P., 139
Treisman, A. M., 3, 8, 70, 75, 76, 88,96,
102, 105, 114, 116, 117, 118, 121,
122, 123, 125, 127; 128, 131, 135,
137, 139, 141, 142, 143, 144, 145,
148, 152, 153, 154, 196, 199
Treisman, M., 94
Trevarthen, C. B., 127
Triggs, T. J., 172, 175, 195
Trumbo, D,., 183, 184, 185
Tulving, E., 122, 146
Tursky, B., 18, 31
Tversky, A., 88
Uleman, J. S., 72
Underwood, B. J., 61, 115
Unger, S. M., 43, 44
Uno, T., 43
Van Sant, C., 175
Subject Index
Alertness, 33, 194-95
Allocation policy, 10-11, 201
and demand1, demand2, 190
in divided attention, 149-52
effects of arousal, 37-42
and perceptual emphasis, 69, 84
and preparatory set, 195
and the PRP, 172
in spontaneous looking, 54
Analysis-by-synthesis \
and focal attention, 125-27
and the prefix effect, 133
Analyzers
and discrimination learning, 99, 102,
III
and parallel processing, 105, 123, 137,
152-53
Anxiety, 23, 24
Arousal
and the allocation policy, 37-42
242
Arousal (cont.)
and capacity, 10
and directional fraetionation, 29-33
and effort, 17-24
and intensive attention, 3-5
in the OR, 43, 48
and performance, 33-42
preparatory, 194-95
Attensity, 78
Attention
to attributes, 98-111
bottleneck models, 5-7
capacity theory, 7-11, 13-17
characteristics of, 201
divided (see Divided attention)
and figural emphasis, 79
focal, 126-27
focused (see Focused attention)
guidance of, 71-72, 83-84, 114
intensive aspects, 3-5
Attention (cont.)
lability, 40-42
narrowing of, 37-42
selective, 2-3
taxonomy of, 70-72
spontaneous, 52-54
theories of, 6-7
unitary versus divisible, 5, 136
voluntary versus involuntary, 3-4, 42
Attenuation (see Filter attenuation theory)
Attributes
report of, 103-5
selection of, 70-71
Autonomic changes
directional fractionation, 29-33
in foreperiod of RT, 31-32
in looking, 19, 29-31
in mental effort, 16-20
in OR, 42-43
in resisting distraction, 114
in Stroop test, 32
Awareness (see Conscious perception)
Beta (see Criterion)
Bi-sensory stimuli (see Modality effects)
Bottleneck models, 5-7, 182
Capacity (see Attention, Effort, Spare
capacity)
and arousal, 10
and demands, 13-17
model, 7-11
Card sorting, 105-8, 110
Cardiac deceleration, 29-33, 48
Categorizing, 103
Category state, 8, 87
Channel
capacity, 5
in filter theory, 120, 121
and grouping processes, 132-35, 138-39
City-block model, 108
Classification task, 105-9, III
Cocktail-party problem, 7, 112, 129
Coding, 102
dimension, 104
object, 104
Collative properties (see also Enduring
dispositions), 3, 52-55, 60, 64, 7879, 81
Compatibility, S-R, 170-72, 180
Complexity, of visual scene, 52-53
Condensation, 106
Conscious perception, 70, 118, 126-28,
130-31
Conservation, 40
Contingent negative variation (CNV), 32
Criterion (Beta)
in filter-attenuation theory, 122
in Norman's theory, 125
and perceptual readiness, /91-95
and preparatory set, 195
and response readiness, 94-96
in signal-detection theory, 89-91
Cue dominance, 101-2
d' (see Sensitivity)
Defensive reaction, 43
Delayed auditory feedback (DAF), 116
Demand t , Demand2 (see Effort)
Deutsch-Norman theory
and divided attention, 136-37
and focused attention, 123-25
and the suffix effect, 134
tests of, 143-45
Dichotic stimulation, 75, 113, 115-19,
122, 125, 138-52
Dictionary unit, 8, 122-23
Digit-transformation, 20, 23, 186
Directional fractionation
and looking, 29-31
and response inhibition, 32-33
and waiting, 31-32
Discontinuity theory, 99-100
Discrimination
and arousal, 34,. 38
learning, 98-103
learning and perception, 102-3
tasks, and effort, 19, 20, 26, 148-49
Dispositions, enduring (see also Collative properties), 42, 52, 60, 78
Distorted room, 91-93
Diurnal rhythm, 42
Divided attention (see also Processing,
parallel or serial)
and the Deutsch-Norman theory, 124,
136-37, 143-45
and effort, 148-52
eye-movements in, 63, 154
and filter theory, 136, 138, 143, 147,
148
modality effects in, 152-54
in monitoring, 141-42, 144-46, 14853, 155
and Neisser's theory, 137
and the PRP, 170, 172, 174
in psychophysical judgments, 146--49
in the recognition task, 144-45, 14752, 190
in the split-span design, 137-41
Treisman's theory of, 137
Drug effects, 32, 38, 39, 41, 64
Dual-tasks (see also Divided attention,
Interference, Subsidiary tasks)
and arousal, 37-38
method, 181-82
Easterbrook's hypothesis, 16, 37-42, 149
EEG, 32, 42-43, 64
Effort (see also Attention, Capacity)
and attention, 4, 9
and consciousness, 131
demands
demand t , demand2, 189-91, 202
and perceptual readiness, 193
and response organization, 191-92
and response readiness, 193
of response selection, 185
supply of, 13-17
and divided attention, 148-52
dual-task measures, 179-82
and focused attention, 116, 130
and interference, 20-22, 177-91, 199201
and the OR, 46-47
in perceptual processing, 84-85, 169,
188-91,202
physiological measures, 17-24, 184-85,
188
and the PRP, 170-74
243
Effort (cont.)
and spare capacity, 15-16, 20-22,
185-88
and task difficulty, 24--26
and time pressure, 25-26
voluntary control of, 14-15
Electrodermal response (see Skin conductance)
Emphasis
figural (see Figural emphasis)
in report of attributes, 104
Encoding, 103-4, 106, Ill, 187
Epistemic motivation,. 54
Euclidian model, 108
Evaluation of demands (see also Effort
.
demands, Recursive effects), 11,
42
Expectancy wave, 32
Expectations
and consciousness, 130-31
in Hochberg's theory, 128, 130
and the OR, 45, 49
and organization of responses, 192
and perceptual readiness, 91-93, 193
and recency, 45
Extroversion, 35
Eye-blinks, 64
Eye movements (see also Fixation, Looking)
of chess players, 62
lateral, in problem-solving, 63-64
in learning tasks, 61-62
in listening tasks, 62-63, 64, 119, 151,
154
pursuit, 51
in search tasks, 56-60, 81, 191
in social interaction, 63
and tachistoscopic accuracy, 61
and thought, 60-62, 64-65
types of, 50-51
Eye-voice span, 192
Feedback (see Evaluation of demands,
Recursive effects)
Figural emphasis
determinants of, 76-80
and effort, 84-85, 189
in focused attention, 129-30, 134-35
and Kiilpe's task, 105
in search tasks, 80-84, 193
and selection of inputs, 70
stage of, 67-68, 97
Figure-ground (see Figural emphasis)
Filter-attenuation theory
and divided attention, 137
and focused attention, 122-23, 125, 135
Filtering
and figural emphasis, 130
and selection of inputs, 70-71, 112
in speeded classification, 106, 109
Filter theory, 6-7, 120-23, 135
and divided attention, 136, 138, 143,
147, 148
and focused attention, 116, 118, 134~
35
Moray's version of, 142
of the suffix effect, 132-33
Fixation (see a~o Looking)
duration of, 58-59, 81
and Haidinger brush, 51, 60-61
244
Focused attention
and analysis-by-synthesis, 125-26, 133
and arousal, 38-39
on channels or on units, 129, 132-35
and definition of relevant message, 114,
'143-45
Deutsch-Norman theory of, 123-25,
143-45
and effort, 116, 130
eye-movements in, 64-65
and figural emphasis, 129-30, 134-35
filter-attenuation theory of, 122
filter theory of, 116, 120-21
individual differences in, 119
measures of, 113
and memory, 115, 117, 122, 139-40
and message duration, 118-19
in monitoring tasks, 114-15
and processing of unattended stimuli,
116-18, 122, 124, 130-31, 143-45
and the production of expectations, 128
psychoanalytic view of, 128
in recognition task, 115
and resistance to distraction, 113
and RT, 115, 153
in shadowing task, 113-14, 115, 14344
and signal-detection theory, 125
and suffix effect, 132-35
in tachistoscopic task, 112-13, 114
Foreperiod
autonomic changes in, 31-33, 41
effect
and alertness, 194
and errors, 41, 194-95
and RT, 41, 176, 194
Gating, 106
Gestalt
figure-ground, 76-79
laws of grouping, 68, 139
theory, 1-2
Grouping (see also Unit formation)
in filter theory, 130
laws of, 72-74
and response to rejected channel, 131
of responses, 156-62, 164, 165, 191
of responses and anticipation, 192
and TOTE, 192
and search, 74
in speeded classification, 106
in split-span design, 138-41
and the suffix effect, 132-35
GSR (Galvanic Skin Response) (see Skin
conductance)
Habituation, 43, 47-48, 59
Haidinger brush, 51, 60
Hardware models, 172
Hypotheses, in discrimination learning,
99, 102
Imagery tasks, 19, 20, 25-26
Incentives, 14-15, 37
Incongruity, 53, 65
Information theory, 5
Inhibition, motor
and directional fractionation, 31-33
in the OR, 48
Integrality
of dimensions, 107-9, Ill, 156
of responses, 156-62
Interference
capacity, 178-82, 196
in concurrent monitoring, 141-42 153
196
'
,
by distracting stimuli 113
in divided attention, '141-45, 148
effort theory of, 16, 199-201
as measure of effort 179-82 185-88
in memory tasks, 179-80 198
in motor learning, 180 '
output, 139-40
and response conflict 109 III
in shadowing, 127, i41 i53
and similarity of tasks '153 199
in speeded classificati~n, 107-8
in the Stroop test, 109-11, 189
structural, 178, 196-99, 202
suffix effect, 132-35
and task difficulty, 200
Inter-re7~onse interval (IRI), 158, 176-
Orientation (cont.)
versus reorientation, 119
and RT, 48
tendencies, 154
Orienting response (see Orientation reaction)
Overshadowing, 101
Overtraining-Reversal Effect, 100
Orientation
reaction (OR), 42-49, 126-27, 190
reaction to unattended message, 126,
131
245
Reaction-time (cont.)
in focused attention, 115, 118
to a probe signal, 180, 186-88, 196
and the PRP, 162-77
to simultaneous stimuli, 157-62
Recognition memory
in divided attention, 144-45, 147-48,
150-52
in focused attention, 115
intederence with, 152, 190
Recognition units, 67-68, 94, 97, 130,
189
acquisition of, 87
organization of, 85-87
parallel processing in, 86-87
Recursive effects
and demand2, 190, 193
in Norman's theory, 125
and OR, 44, 81
in perception, 69-70
in search, 81, 193-94
Redundancy gain, 107
Rehearsal, 19,.26, 140, 179, 180, 202
Response conflict
and collative properties, 53
and the Stroop test, 109-11
theory of the PRP, 174-75
Response readiness, 69
and attention to attributes, 105
and preparatory set, 193
and signal-detection theory, 94-97
in the Stroop test, 110
Response selection (see also Response
readiness)
and attention to attributes, III
effort demands of, 185
free, and effort, 19, 183-84
as single-channel, 182-84
stage, 67, 69-70
Response set, 70, 71, 114, 121, 124-25
Reversal shift, 100
Rod and frame test, 39, 40
Saccade, 50
Scanning, 40-41
Search
control of, 71-72, 74
and figural emphasis, 80-84, 193-94
and grouping, 74-75
learning to, 81, 87
recursive process in, 81, 194
visual, 57
Selection
of attributes, 71, 98-111
of inputs, 70-71, 79, 112, 119 (see
Focused attention, Stimulus set)
of outputs, 70-71 (see Response set)
of perceptual interpretations, 67-70,
85 (See Perceptual readiness)
in focused attention, 130
and signal-detection theory, 94
of response (see Response selection)
of targets, 70-71 (see Search)
Sensitivity (d')
and attention, 94-95, 125
and availability of recognition units,
94-95
in signal-detection theory, 88-91
Set (see also Stimulus set, Response set,
Expectations)
246
Set (cont.)
divided, 195-96
preparatory, 191-95
Shadowing
of alternated messages, 154
and focused attention, 113-14, 115,
143-44
intederence with, 127, 141, 153
latency of, 118, 192
and processiJ;lg of other messages,
113-14, 117, 122, 198
Short-term memory
and arousal, 42
and attention, 116, 117-18, 122, 13235, 139-40
and effort, 19-20, 25, 26, 179-81
types of, 121-22
Signal-detection theory
and attention, 94-96, 125
basic concepts of, 87-90
and distorted room, 91-93
and word-frequency effect, 93-94
Similarity judgments, 102-3, 108
Single-channel theory
and dual-tasks, 182-85
and the PRP, 163-65, 167, 170
Sinus arrhythmia, 17
Skin conductance, 18, 32-33, 42-43
Sleep deprivation, 35-36
Spare capacity, 16
and arousal, 38
and demandt, demand2, 190-91
and primary effort, 15-16
probe measures of, 16, 202
perceptual, 16, 20-22, 180, 185,
186, 196
RT, 16, 180, 186-88, 195-96
Speed-accuracy tradeoff, 41
Split-span design
attention and retention in, 139-41
content effects in, 139
and perceptual grouping, 138-40
S-system, 120, 136, 138
Stimulus set, 70, 71, 114, 120, 124-25
Stroop test, 32, 33, 39-40, 64, 109-11
Structural models, 8, 11
Subsidiary tasks
other variants, 179-84
perceptual measures, 20-22, 180, 18586
probe RT, 180, 186-88
Suffix effect, 132-35
Sympathetic activity (see Autonomic
changes)
Tachistoscopic perception
and arousal, 38-39
eye movements in, 61
and focused attention, 38-39, 112-13,
114
selection of targets in, 83-84
of words and letters, 85-86
Time pressure, 25-26, 191
TOTE, 192
Tracking, 162, 179-81, 183-84
Vigilance, 35, 41
Word-frequency effect, 93-94