Bernard Andrieu UHP Nancy University and ACCORPS/CNRS, Archives Poincar Translated from French to English with the assistance of Charles Wolf and Brent Robbins
Te relations between the neurosciences and phenomenology enable us to- daythanks to the works of M. Merleau-Ponty, G. Simondon, F. Varela, A.R. Damasio and V.S. Ramachandranto dene the brain as a biosubjective organ: its constitution, its functioning, and its interactions prove that a description of individuation can t in a cognitive neurophenomenology. In this framework, the mental state acquires a subjective autonomy even if it is an illusion in regard to the determining conditions of brain functioning. Relations between phenomenology and the neurosciences, which appear to be impossible in principle, have now focused on the question of the cognitive body. Tis notion refers to the presence, in that part of organized matter termed the body, of intentional elements for organizing the treatment of information. Perception and action both belong to and work on this cognitive body. Now, the development of these two disciplines, phenomenology and the neurosciences, may have been independent and even antagonistic, but the description of the bounds between body and brain has now become an obligation for philosophy. In what she called neuro- philosophy, Patricia Churchland (P.S. Churchland 1986) had proposed an eliminativist solution: the neurosciences would be sucient to explain the constitution of the body by means of the natural basis of the brain, without any reference to phenomenology. I critiqued this type of reductionist reasoning because another de- scription of the construction of the body is possible: the interaction of the body with its environment begins in the formation of the nervous system by the dierent levels of plasticity (Andrieu, 1998). Neural plasticity is the experimental proof that determinism is not strict in the development of the body. Phenomenology performs the distinction between the lived body and the subjective body and at the same time enables a new description thereof, including biology and neurobiology. Janus Head, 9(1), 135-155. Copyright 2006 by Trivium Publications, Amherst, NY All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America 136 Janus Head Te publication of the notes of Merleau-Pontys last lectures at the Collge de France between 1956-1960 (F. Evans, S. Lawlor eds., 2000) provides a new basis on which to launch a phenomenological approach to the relations between the body, the brain and the world. Te 1957-58 lecture on the concept of Nature examines the trends of modern biology. Coming back to this analysis of behaviour, Merleau-Ponty uses the book by G.E. Coghill, Anatomy and the problem of behavior in 1929, to set the principles of dynamic anatomy against strict behaviorism. Strict determinism would have summed up nervous conduction to a univocal information. But after examination of the work on embryology, which belongs to the model of neurobiology of development (M. Reuter, 1999, 73), Merleau-Ponty writes: Te nervous system emerges from a preneural dynamic. Tus when the nervous excitation occurs, it cant play an important role in the organization of the nervous system. Tis organization is not so much due to the functioning of the neuron as to the growth of the total or- ganism. Te preneural system of integration strides across the nervous functioning and it doesnt stop when it appears. So the nervous system cant be the ultimate explanation. Ten we must admit an intrinsic potentiality of growth, a dynamic system reacting to its surroundings as an organism would do. It replaces the function of conduction as being a consequence, not a principle of the system. (Merleau-Ponty, 1995, 192). Merleau-Ponty emphasizes the reciprocal character of the notion of body and the notion of behaviour whereas A.R. Damasio (1999) sets it between the body and the brain. In his last lecture, Nature and Logos: Te human body (1960), Merleau-Ponty says the human body is the place where Nature emerges into ontological layers. Te body is subject of movement and subject of percep- tion. Tis theory of the esh formulates a coiling up of the body-object on itself, thanks to which it is touching/touched, visible/invisible. Tus the organism is not simply its psychochemical reality, because the esh of the body could be understood from the modes of constitution of the human body (A.F. Ashbaugt, 1978). Te neurophenomenology (F. Varela, 1996) is a new perspective in the philosophy of embodied mind ( F. Varela, E. Tompson, E. Rosch, 1991).
Bernard Andrieu 137 Te publication of Notes de cours conrms how much Merleau-Ponty remained haunted by the link between biology and phenomenology (D. Borrett, S. Kelly, H. Kwan, 2000). His translation of and comment upon the Beilage XXII of the Krisis is the opportunity to nd in Husserl the in- carnation of consciousness from biology. What I propose to call the esh (A. Ainley, 1997) of the brain denes the historic construction of the nervous system through the interaction of the body with the world and the progressive embodiment of these incor- porations. To think the body which enables me to think the body. Vicious circle or badly put question? If we keep on distinguishing what enables us to think the body from the thought object, then we wont be able to think the body thinking. For we must admit as mans existential presupposition that without the body, there is no thinking; we must come back to the de- scription of the internal relationships of the body with its thought in order to found dynamic materialism, but neurophilosophy (P.S. Churchland, 1986) has popularized a strictly reductionist version (Andrieu B., 1998). I argue that we should instead have a philosophy of neuroscience (Gold, I. & Stoljar, D. 1999, 827) because there is an epistemological distinction between philosophy and neuroscience. Te role of interaction Te human body must be rst understood as in interaction with its environment because it is itself the receptive matter both informed and informing. Te human body is not a monad but has a temporal character in phenomenology (Sara Heinmaa, 1999, 58). If isolated from the world, it is unable to build itself up, for nature has only endowed it with poten- tialities that have to meet the circumstances of an environment to become actual. As an interface, the body doesnt remain passive: it doesnt obey the orders of the nervous system in a servile manner, neither is it an objective reection of the world. Failing to be this recording chamber, according to the mechanical metaphor, the human body is the way in and out, through which the inside communicates with the outside (and vice-versa). Tis cross- ing is subjectifying in the sense that the matter of the body is the result of this building up interaction. By subjectifying I mean the movement which singularizes each human body by successive incorporations. Subjectivity is a result, in continuous movement, of adaptation and regulation. Te human body is subjectivized as soon as its conception by the mother and childs interactions. Nothing completely objective can be known, thus making the 138 Janus Head knowledge of the world relative to each human body. Each ones relativity doesnt preclude scientists from approximately establishing a temporary truth on the human body. Tis knowledge remains approximate because of the very constitution of the body: the sensation is felt through the nervous structure in the body so that two human bodies can never feel the same intensity for the same object. Psychometrics, modernized by electrophysiology, quanties the quality of the experiences of what has been lived by the body: this method establishes an objective knowledge by measuring the times of reaction, the thresholds of perception. But the visualization of electric exchanges will never tell anything about the way the body feels them in itself. If neurosciences have a good knowledge of the bodys functioning, they describe the biological side as being felt psychophysiologically or even exclusively psychologically by the body itself. Te distinction between levels of description does not lead to a new dualism since one could not exist without the other. Should the body owe its activities to the strict application of neuronal networks, nevertheless, the contents of the thought make the subject believe in a natural illusion of independence from the matter of his body. Our point is not to deny the determining character of matter in body functioning but to refuse the reduction of the organ to the function. By the esthesiology of the body proper, two human bodies can never feel the same intensity for the same object. Tis impossible intersubjectivity holds the bodies (C. Lefort, 1991) out of themselves and each body in itself, making it dicult to express linguistically what has been lived esthesiologi- cally. Te lack of objectivity is constituent of any human bodys relations with the world. At least any human body can be described from outside as an objective structure but the neurobiology of development must describe a process of subjective individuation rather than draw out a universal type of incorporation. Te notion of plasticity explains this adaptability of the human body to its environment, each body being a single body. So the body appropriates the information of its senses and the brain processes it. Te brain is not the center of cognition but the necessary way to it. Does the physico-chemical transformation of nervous information presuppose a reduction of quality? Te conversion of what is felt into nervous material is nonstop: the sum of the visual neurons produces the picture I see, the tips of my nger are nothing but the polished surface of the sensitive nerves. Te human esh (D. Lever,
Bernard Andrieu 139 1990) works at transforming and giving a denite shape to the physico- chemical matter of information. Te esh is proposed as a category, which, standing between soul and body, grounds the possibility of their relation (J. Mensch, 1994). But for the description of the esh, we must go beyond the oppressive nature of binary terms, body and mind (D. Enns, 1995). Which individuation? Te physical and scientic dividuation is the opposite of what G. Simondon called the psychic individuation. In describing ontogenesis, his aim is to explain the individual through individuation. Tus individua- tion is not an antecedent stage preceding the appearance of the individual being. Psychic individuation could be understood as a means of ghting against the physical dividuation of the human body. For, by oering the shapes, modes and degrees of individuation to replace the individual into the being, G. Simondon wants to renew the scattering of the being caused by the development of human sciences. Tey multiply psychism but do not manage to dene the movement through which the individual comes out as a somato-psychic totality. Faced with the physical dividuation of the human body, psychic individuation would take into account, from a subjective point of view, the individuals capacity to perceive, know and feel the worlds totality. So, coming back to the Bergsonian opposition of time and space, Si- mondon calls the physical individual what we have discovered as physical dividuation. By losing all dynamic balance, his individuality analyses and intervenes on physical elements but the individual cant produce a sucient activity to stop the reduction of psychic totality to his physical parts. Psychic individuation, relevant to understand the genesis of the indi- vidual, cant resist physical dividuation. Simondons scientic model, used through notions of potential, information, metastability and trans- ductivity still depends on a biological presupposition whose metaphorical limit was revealed by Jacob (1970). On the contrary, we think that if the individual has problems today with his identity and his unity, the reason is to be found in the change of an informative paradigm to a predictive and programmatic paradigm. 140 Janus Head Negative induction or pathological reasoning Te study of dysfunctionings and other anomalies (P.J. Harisson, 1991) is very helpful in understanding the etiologic modes of the body. For interac- tive individuation depends on the quality of the successive incorporations: if the reception of incorporations is impaired, the body itself is modied. What is lacking for normal functioning is a guide for the description of the constitutions of the body. Pathological reasoning shows the cause/eect relation between this mat- ter and these mental shapes. If destroyed or damaged, the physico-chemical matter of our sensitivity cant provide the matter for thinking: or rather, there is a proportional ratio between the quality of sensations and the qualities of mental activities. Te body provides the matter for thinking even if the way the thought pictures its mental states is perceived by it as independent. Tis illusion of independence is well within the normal functioning of the thinking body but this partial autonomy of thought doesnt prevent it from having the illusion of its independence. While writing these words, I dont feel the direct determination of matter. Are we to conclude, as reduc- tionists have it, that the content of the thought would be the strict application of the state of this matter? Is it because we dont know how the brain really works that we keep the hypothesis of an independence of the thought or does the thought as result of the brain always produce for itself the illusion of this independence? I shall defend the second thesis, because the brain produces thought as extra activity whose causes are complex because of the number of networks involved. Nobody can deny there is an element of determinism here: the slightest illness conrms by a kind of negative induction the mutual implication of the body and the mind states; the experience of pleasure or pain proves how much the content of my thought can be invaded, even obsessed by the state of my body: thus the erotic image would be caused by hormonal excita- tion, as some biologies of the passions claim (e.g. J.-D. Vincent, 1986); by caused we must understand that subjective imagination is oered with this felt sensation the opportunity to be fanciful. In the same way, the intensity of pain can be such that it forbids any autonomy of thought as if the body dominated and imposed its whole ma- terial content on thought. Extreme pain or pleasure are moments when the continuity from body to mind is preserved almost in spite of us. Yet when we go beyond subjective control, it shows the permanent character of this
Bernard Andrieu 141 continuity which we dont feel in normal life. However the unawareness of the life of the body doesnt put us out of the body. Tus, imagination leans on biological conditions through humours. Te state of the body acts upon the representation and the aects by hor- monal intensity. But the content of these dimensions of imagination isnt set in hormones, contrary to what reductionists who favour brain medicine put forward. Te distinction of dierent levels of explanation acknowledges against dualism the necessary complementarity between the brain and the unconscious, but it poses the problem of the continuity between the two of them. We cant recognize the determining role of biological processes without analyzing the nature and the limit of this determination. Refusing strict determinism because of the dierence of level or organization of matter, our philosophy of the thinking body cant expect science to exhaustively describe the functioning of mental states, on the one hand because of the disposition of organic networks, on the other hand because of the lack of an explanation for the change of quantity into quality. We must admit that the complex organization of matter products a superior level of reality, like in an emergence theory. Tis superiority, due to the results of network activity, seems independent if the mind observes this activity from itself whereas the superiority is just autonomous. Mental autonomy Tis feeling, favoured by the experience of thought, of being out of the bod,y is actually a mental autonomy allowed by the functional coher- ence of the body. Te body keeps on nding in the contents of thought the modes of its representation of the world. It is not thought that thinks itself, or considers itself independent from the body. Mental states produce the natural illusion in Kants sense, of an independence of the mind from the body. By natural we mean that the mind is not conscious of it, and that the body is the cause of it. However this continuity of oneself in one self doesnt show a homoge- neity in levels. Organic dysfunctioning proves that thinking requires certain neurobiological conditions to become conscious of the dierent levels. For a long time, the criterion of the consciousness of oneself was considered as a limit beyond which there would be no thought: thinking should be reserved to the consciousness of the contents of ones thought (C. Smith, 2001). 142 Janus Head But, without going so far as hemispheric division whose purpose is to eliminate the concept of consciousness (the works on the split brain have as their therapeutic aim to prevent the spreading of epilepsy from one hemi- sphere to the other, and they gave the opportunity to neurophilosophers (G.S. Stent, S.F. Spicker, 1990) to deny the mental unity of consciousness) we must consider thinking less as a threshold in the cerebral organization than as the very activity of the body. Te notion of threshold, on this view, serves to retain of neurobiologi- cal activity nothing but conscious intensity. But the body thinks conscious and unconscious contents from implicit or explicit perceptions. Te crite- rion of the threshold holds dualism where the corporeal matter organizes dierent levels. Te reex should be understood as the natural unthought of the body itself. From reex to mental representation, the distinction traditionally made between the voluntary and the involuntary is a criterion of the denition of the thought: what would be human would be set in the voluntary activity of the mind, thus oering freedom and choice. Does acknowledging a determinism of the reex prevent one from admitting the existence of an unconscious thought of the body? Isnt the reex a content of thought that we dont think, a corporeal knowledge unthought out and yet determining? Te reex is a material content unthought whereas reection is a mate- rial content wholly thought. Te determinism of the one is necessary to the freedom of the other. Yet it is the same body even if the levels of organization of matter allow the presence or the absence of free activity of the thought. How can one and the same matter (but is it the same matter?) produce within itself an unthought content and pure thought? We must admit that human matter has dierent degrees of complexity according to which mental activity is more or less freed from strict natural determinism. Except probably for the reex level, for which the body is subjected to natural determinism, all the other degrees of the organization of matter depend in their constitu- tion on an interaction between nature and culture. Tinking matter Te opposition between the innate and the acquired is renewed by cellular and molecular embryology which species the conditions of the programmed development and the limited possibilities of plasticity. Te
Bernard Andrieu 143 matter of which the human body is made becomes the human body as successive incorporations take place (A.R. Damasio, 1994). Tis historical dimension of any human body is a psychosocial propping up: any learning requires a material support to be selected by living matter and thus be used as the informative basis for mental activity. Tis mental activity is autonomous for it is allowed by every human body according to the development of its history: the thought goes through the folds and layers of the subjective esthesiology and of the biopsychologi- cal memory. Te subjective esthesiology depends on the perception of the world, the latter being introduced into the body by the senses. Objective knowledge doesnt exist as every human body must create for itself proto- types built empirically. Every thought is a coming back of the self to the self which results from the central nervous system going through the body: yet if it is true that every thought is an eect of the thinking body, its contents are not the exact reproduction of the neuronal networks but their subjective produc- tion. By subjective production we mean the eect of neuronal networks inside the human body, historically built and with a material organization providing a specic mental activity: incorporation cant be but subjective. Its materialization cant be set in the brain. Cognitive activity is based on maps, networks, neurofunctional areas rather than on single elements. Te gregarious necessity of neuronal collections ensures the communication necessary to the autonomous activity of the thought. When we think, we are not aware of the neuronal networks which however are at work. Tis unawareness of our brain gives thought an imaginary indepen- dence as long as no damages limit or inuence this activity. Mental states must be understood as forms crystallized at some time, chosen or not by the thinking body. Te mental picture may as well come from mnesic recompo- sition as from imaginary composition. It gives the thought its matter with representations of words or things. Yet no materiality could be grasped since the mental image is an immaterial form produced by matter, which seems paradoxical in a materialistic position. How could some matter produce something immaterial? Should the whole thing be dierent and superior to the sum of the parts? Maintaining a non-reductionist materialistic position presupposes that one allows for the creation of forms by matterthis position can be described as a dynamic materialism. Morphogenesis nds its reason and its dynamism in the matter of the genes of development. In the same way, couldnt we 144 Janus Head describe mental states as an endogenesis of the matter of the thinking body? Trough its networks, the brain produces the form of thought whose content is found in the connection and the conjunction of materials constituting the thinking body. Te endogenesis of mental states is to a certain extent (the problem comes from this proportion) similar to the morphogenesis described by embryology. Te building of neuronal networks is submitted to equal biological constraints and the propping up structures of mental states. In order not to reduce the thought to the body, we must admit the body is materially able to produce not only organic forms (body states) and programmatic forms (children) but also ideal forms. Tis endogenesis of ideal forms, as worked out by Gilbert Simondon, presupposes their crystallization into a mental state for the thinking body to be able to think them. Tis crystallization is the product, that we call reection, of the real dynamics of matter. We must distinguish the subjective representation of the matter of the thinking body from the objective descrip- tion of it. Not because the subjective representation would be erroneous or would not be able to know anything of the formal reality it has produced. Not because the objective reality of the idea of the thinking body would be, as far as quality is concerned, imperfect compared to the formal reality of its cause: the thinking body itself. But the mental state is a synthetic form of the material dynamics of the thinking body. Without this causality, it couldnt exist, but conversely, without the mental state, the body couldnt be thought. Tis functional complementarity doesnt introduce a qualitative leap of the body to its thought. Te mental state makes the body think whereas the living matter provides by the means of the body the thinking matter. Mental autonomy is part of the logic of the living because the material conditions of the living produce the conditions of mental representations. Te liberation of the cortex-brain and its specic hypertrophy allows the production of mental states. Te illusion of mental localization Te reason why not all neuroscientists will manage to localize the change of the quantitative into the qualitative is that the neurofunctional level of the mental state explains this change in its conditions but never in its contents, except in the case of lesions. Te changing of a level of organi- zation to another, whose quality seems heterogeneous in the previous level, can be measured at the time of the visualization of neuronal networks, of the intersynaptic communication of neurotransmitters (G. Edelman, 1987).
Bernard Andrieu 145 But this measurement nds a cause-eect relation between the organization of living matter and what would be its eective result. Actually, a direct cau- sality produces a mental state as its dysfunctioning disqualies the thought of the body. But the thought cant be directly localized as it comes from a dynamic process. Te reductionist illusion consists in xing this process in several stages or levels of material organization. Yet it is true that a certain level of orga- nization of the matter is needed, below which the production of conscious thought is impossible. Tus nature, in its dynamic evolution, has not pro- duced the same degree of organization. Te distinction of nature between animal and man is superseded; it is now time we acknowledged a dierence of degree in the organization of the matter. Anthropologists endeavoured to emphasize the role of the human body in the singularity of its mental activity. Without the release of the hand by bipedy and the growth of the brain volume, the interaction of the human body with surroundings wouldnt have been able to create a sociocultural environment where education and speech ensured the classic transmission. Te plasticity of ontogenesis made the socialization of the human body possible because cultural factors further collective integration and personal identication. Animals cant be compared to us except if we establish a functional hierarchy. Teir bodies manage to dene a very limited part of freedom even if the interaction with the environment, provided in their degree of plasticity by Nature, ensures a dynamic dimension. Te specic dierence of the human body is to become a thinking body: thinking doesnt lie in a localizable part of the body because the body organizes itself, thinks itself in producing its level of mentalization that we separate in an abstract way by instituting it as thought. Te humanization of the body requires a continuous interactive elaboration between environ- ment and body. Brain plasticity and body construction
From its conception onwards, the human body is a person thanks to the inuences it receives from its environment. By isolating consciousness from body sensitivity, some would like to determine the movement of birth of human identity. Yet, even during the forming in utero, the ftus (Lecanuet J.P., Fifer W.P., Krasnegor N.A., eds., 1995) feels and reacts to the food and aects his mother receives (P. Rochat, 2001). When we count the 146 Janus Head age of a child from his birth, we forget stages already incorporated during intra-uterine life. Te human body should be understood as soon as the germinal movement of its matter. Te nervous system, as the base of sensitivity, ceases its activity only with cerebral death. Te continuity, from the conception of the body to the destruction of its somato-psychic unity, renews the denition of per- sonal history. Being born incomplete and indeterminate, the human body has to incorporate the information coming from its environment. Tis incorporation consists in a progressive determination throughout learning. Genetic inheritance denes the structures and modes of the human body functions. But the opposition between innate and acquired becomes meaningless when no potentiality becomes necessarily actual. Te human body nds a form between personal identity and social existence. Plasticity of the brain structures makes it possible: it would be wrong to think eyes see immediately and naturally since David Hubel (1988) and his experiments with Torse Wiesel prove that it is the interaction of light with visual neurons which makes us see the world. Otherwise, the human body loses the capacity of sight it has potentially in itself. Nothing is naturally acquired. Human nature has to experience the world in order to qualify (AQ). Te neurobiology of development, a new version of the man without qualities, gives to the human subject the free- dom of building itself up. But this construction turns out to be denitive: the initial plasticity loses its suppleness with the myelenisation of nervous bers (Spemann H., 1938) which preserves the information of successive incorporations. Language learning is a good example of this preserving specialization. From intra-uterine life (Ph. Evrard, A. Minkowski, 1989), the human body hears sounds to which it reacts by movements at birth; its relatives speak to it in a language whose sound quality becomes more and more specic to the ear. Ten language mastery (B. de Boysson-Bardies, S. de Schonen, P. Jusczyk, P. MacNeilage & J. Morton, eds., 1993) is reached with the in- denite repetition of the babble in which syllables are associated together. Language, as conventional support between the signifying and the signied, will be recognized at the end of this specialization. Each child must lose an incredible linguistic potential when he becomes a French or an English speaker. As he doesnt remain a polyglot, the human body cant express itself without the language it kept on incorporating during the early years (J. Mehler, Bertoncini J., Barrire M. & Jassik-Gershenfeld D., 1978).
Bernard Andrieu 147 It would be futile to limit the forming of the human body only to the biological progress from childhood to adulthood. Troughout its life, the human body keeps having dynamic interactions with its environment. Te quantitative development of the brain does not last more than the rst quarter of our biological life, yet the brain goes on receiving information from its body. Tis information creates new connections between the dif- ferent brain areas so that it increases the complexity of memory. Even if the clinical descriptions of lesions fail to identify all the mnesic contents, P. Broca taught us how much the state of the body determines the state of the brain and conversely. Te brain incorporates what the body individualizes. Tis double movement of incorporation of the world and of individualization of the body can be understood only from a conception of living matter. Incorporation and individuation
Any nervous lesion prevents the brain from using what it has incor- porated. It causes a loss of identity as well as a functional imbalance. As a disease weakens the body, the neurofunctional lesion prevents the subject from exercising his cognitive autonomy. As long as the brain provides the body with the means of its individuation, the authority called subject gets the conditions of its exercise: then consciousness is freed thanks to the proper functioning of the brain. However, contrary to what those who support the notion of neuronal man (J.-P. Changeux, 1983) think, the content of thought cant be com- pletely determined by the matter of its brain. We may refuse to consider the brain as the organ of thought, but we cant separate thought from its neurophysiological conditions of activity. It would be a mistake to consider brain and consciousness as opposites, like matter and thought, and fail to see the embodied link which holds them together. Te distinction between levels of functioning must not hide the representation and/or cause one to believe in the scattering of the body. Te human body has been scattered and reduced by the human sci- ences which have studied it. Te body gives its brain sucient information to enable it to embody its representations and feelings, and derives its role as the main mediator as much from its phylogenesis as from its ontogenesis. With its phylogenesis, the body can genetically use specializations transmit- ted since the beginning of human mind. Te succession of species made our body better and better adapted to its surroundings. In the absence of instinct, 148 Janus Head technique had to provide the means of replacing natural surroundings by an environment. Tis evolution has freed the body from servitudes in making the cerebral organization complex enough to think this freeing. Nature has produced a species likely to become completely cultural, including as genetics and procreatics prove it in the production of its own body. As far as ontogenesis is concerned, each human body is singular even if the individual shares the same genetic inheritance with the other members of the species. Te proteic synthesis of our genes is so peculiar that no individual is identical. Helped by these singularities, each human body incorporates every experience. So the esh of the human body could be dened as the sum of all these experiences, forming many layers, networks and intertwin- ings. Te brain, being incorporated, cant resist this subjective construction of the matter: it takes the form of its body (N. Le Douarin, 1982). But during its construction, the brain in turn determines the body (D. Purves, 1988). Tis permanent retroaction provides a reciprocal limitation to the brain and to the body. So the esh of the body chooses its modes of constitution and its possibilities of incarnation. Incarnation is no longer the appearance of the mind in the matter but the expression in the body and by the body of its constituent layers. Either memory is stimulated by the presence of something known, or creative imagination is activated by the absence of something experienced. Our body, always present in the world by its senses, conceals a great number of signs to be discovered. Out of its prospect, this body is understood today as an indierent neutral matter. Yet the human body becomes such only if it manages to incorporate its history. We only know the outer world by means of our body. Te role of the body During its construction, the brain, following the model of interaction rather than the internal model of emergence, denes its plasticity according to the cultural forms which determine the body. Te brain has a singular esh for each human body. Even if the natural elements are determined by the genetic inheritance, the natural surroundings have to actualize and direct the plastic potentialities of the brain in construction. Tis singular development gives the human body the role of a determining, the transla- tion of which will be eective in the neurobiological data. Ten the nervous messages would not be prior to the esthesiologic activity of the body. Te brain is not the condition of the body. It would mean mixing up cause and
Bernard Andrieu 149 eect. Tere is no neurobiological basis to corporeal consciousness since as soon as intra-uterine life, it is the relation of the body with the world which informs, directs and selects the nervous networks and circuits. If the human being is born with an incomplete brain, it is precisely so that culture may be the necessary element of its qualication. Te neurobiology of development refuses to link the corporeal consciousness to the result of brain activity. Te body is a mediator (R. Barbaras, 1999, 529-230) because it informs the brain about sensitive data, because it conveys the communications of the mind/brain, because it expresses a relational aectivity with its sociocultural environment. Te physiological or psychoaective state of the body depends of course on hormones, on the quantities of active neuronal networks, on the quality of its genetic code. But the dierence between an animal body and human body lies in the capacity of the latter to acquire learnings which modify the consciousness of itself. Te link between the unconscious and memory is founded in the brain which records and reorganizes the represen- tations in as many neuronal associations. Of course the dream is the warden of brain individuation but the historical involvement of a subject in the world is more than the deterministic result of endocrine hormones. So the human body is a place of conversion: it means that its form retro-acts upon its matter. In the same way, its matter determines inde- nitely its forming. So we must distinguish several subjective levels in order to understand, if not objectively explain, the modes of relations with the brain. Dualism as a real distinction of substances cant subsist for it admits the relations only in intersection. A dierence of degree is necessary, where each level corresponds to a level of representation for the human subject. So the unconscious is the subjects intimate representation which can be modied by the brain/mind with psychoanalysis or because of physi- ological damages. Te human beings brain/mind enables him to represent himself and develop representation by giving the thought a material support during the subjects activity. Te esh (D. Enns, 1995) is a dimension of aectivity where feelings and imagination feed the subjects experience in the singularity of its geohistory. Te body proper is the image of the body, resulting from the narcissistic representation of the subject such as he sees himself or represents himself through others. Te objective body is this exte- rior body, visible surface for others, organism objectied by the mechanisms of techno-science (H.L. Dreyfus, 2000). Te world is not in front of the subject because the subject is a being in the world. 150 Janus Head Te consciousness of the brain Te dualistic tradition has always supported the opposition between mind and body: as the seat of thought, the mind had to maintain the com- munication with the world to nd a meaning. Except for this allotted role, the body was not important: even the passions of the soul found in animal minds a mechanically determined matter. So the brain couldnt be under- stood otherwise than as an organ of the body. Descartes, who discovered the cogito, granted the brain the pineal gland in order to maintain the minimum communication between body and mind. Te failure of subjective idealism is due to the substantial isolation of the res cogitans. And Denis Kambouchner (1995) shows that Descartes, in his 1649 treatise Te Passions of the Soul, had to grant the body not only the determinism of animal but also modes of series of objective and functional operations. Tough medical description has found in biology its means of objec- tifying the body, it would be ignorant to believe in functional monotypy. Te biology of development takes the relational modes of the human body so much into account that it considers interaction as a structuration mode by incorporation. Tus, though not completely subjective, as Michel Henry (1999) thinks, the human body biopsychologically builds its esh. Each body is this historical esh, whose etiology has been embodied and shaped by the interaction with environment. By its character yet to be determined rather than undetermined, the human body contains all its history at the end of life. If its matter is marked with traces, scars and symptoms, the exhaustion of the esh is nevertheless translated into the modes of symbolic expression. As Jean-Louis Chrtien (1990) shows, tiredness, as ontological condition of embodied being, comes from the indenite gap between the human body and its esh, a gap so wide it can never be lled. Yet the fault of this mechanical model is the lack of mutual determina- tion of mind and body. Te birth of biology at the beginning of the twen- tieth century put natural surroundings in between: the surroundings have become the environment in which the body has to develop. Rather than dened as a creature, the human body must build itself in a double way: on the one hand, it is a natural product nding in physical development the means of acquiring a consciousness of itself, and on the other hand it is a cultural result incorporating all the information from its environment and thus increasing its degree of consciousness. Te human body cant remain indierent to this double determination.
Bernard Andrieu 151 Consciousness cant be completely separated from the brain (D.C. Dennett, 1991) because the human body builds cerebral connections in establishing the sensitive qualities of information which will be coded by the brain. Te brains organization in two hemispheres, presented by many as a split brain, doesnt eliminate the unity of consciousness. Trough the studies of lesions of the callous body linking up the two hemispheres, split brain specialists have shown how much this cognitive lateralization owed to neurofunctional specialization. Te wish to explain consciousness rather than describe its activity derives its legitimacy from the progress of the neurosci- ences. For this purpose, however, consciousness should have to be reduced to its neurobiological conditions, since the slightest failure modies the state of consciousness. And here is the main logical fault of this argument: from the clinical acknowledgement of the link between lesion and state of consciousness, one induces the necessary connection between brain and matter, thus disqualifying consciousness. Memory would be a succession of engrammes and programmes, perception would come to neuronal networks of vision, imagination would have to create new networks, and desire would nd its modes of regulation in the hormonal system. To cope with this drifting, cognitive scientists have been tempted to keep mental states of consciousness apart from neurobiological states of the brain, which may be a temporary solution. For supporters of cognitivism, mental states describe consciousness activities enough to be the specically human level. Tis new humanism has however ignored the neurosciences, renewing the phenomenological reection on consciousness. Neurophi- losophers took advantage of this isolation to develop with hardly any real opposition, a cerebral denition of consciousness. Te alternative between cognitivists and neurophilosophers isnt based on a debate but on the mutual exclusion of points of view. Ten how can we give the brain the material principles of consciousness while acknowledging that the latter has its own level of activity? Tis research, which can only be worked out in a dynamic conception of matter, doesnt really aim at what is scientically correct but at the description of the dierent levels of human embodiment. Tough I grant that corporeal matter is the seat of the complex dif- ferentiation of these levels, I feel that we must recognize that the brain has a determining importance in the activity of consciousness. As all human brains are the product of body/environment interaction (S. Todes, 2001), consciousness then produced will be able to incarnate the incorporated neu- ronal networks. But this incarnation, the successive layers of which amount 152 Janus Head to its phenomenology, is an autonomous eld in which consciousness carries on its subjective activity. Te objective determination of the incorporated brain remains inuential through the quality of mental images according to the variability of its neuronal networks. Conclusion: Te interactionist thesis Tis change from the brain of consciousness, which makes it relative, to consciousness of the brain, which makes it believe in its subjective inde- pendence, proves how much brain and consciousness are complementary. As brain of consciousness, the incorporated brain provides information and ways to become conscious. Ten this develops the consciousness of the brain by determining the brain in order to achieve the cognitive command of the thought: Tought autonomy of consciousness Brain of Consciousness Consciousness of the Brain Incorporated brain Body in the world Environment Tis dialectical movement from the brain of consciousness to the con- sciousness of the brain doesnt prevent consciousness from operating its own reection: the process of thought. Tought is dierent from the conscious- ness of the brain due to its functional autonomy: the mental state is able to have a singular activity whereas the consciousness of the brain orders the brain to fulll the orders of the will. With the consciousness of the brain, the human body reexively thinks itself, thereby forgetting the relative autonomy of the thinking consciousness from the brain of consciousness. Tought turns real autonomy into a subjective independence, producing mental states such as dreaming, imagination, ideation, representation and intentionality. From the subjects point of view, his thought is free because he can no longer see the determinism of the brain of consciousness. His power on the body, through the means of the consciousness of the brain, holds him in the illusion of his spiritual power on the matter. But from the
Bernard Andrieu 153 point of view of this matter, the modication of its states can always limit the exercise of this freedom. Human thought is produced by human bodies, but thought believes in its freedom because of the natural illusion of forgetting its relative autonomy. Yet this illusion has a real power over the body. Reducing thought and brain, neurophilosophy has chosen to deny this essentially human level of consciousness to institute a determinism where there is nothing but determination. References Ainley, A. 1997. Te Invisible of the Flesh: Merleau-Ponty and Irigaray, J. of the British Society for Phenomenology, 28 (1): 20-29. Andrieu, B. 1993. Le corps dispers. Une histoire du corps au XXe sicle, Paris: LHarmattan,3d ed 2000. __________ 1998. La neurophilosophie, Paris: P.U.F. __________, 2002. La chair du cerveau. Phnomnologie et biologie de la cognition, Belgique: Ed. Sils-Maria. __________, 2003. Le cerveau psychologique, Histoires et Modles, Paris: Ed. CNRS. Ashbaugt, A.F. 1978. Te Philosophy of the Flesh and the Flesh of Philosophy, Res. Phenomenology, 8: 217-223. Barbaras, R., 1999. Te Movement of the Living as the Originary Foundation of Perceptual Intentionality, trans. C.T. Wolfe, in J. Petitot, F.J. Varela, B. Pachoud, J.M. Roy, (eds)., Naturalizing phenomenology. Issues in Contemporary Phenomenology and Cognitive Science, pp. 525-538. Stanford: Stanford U.P. Borrett, D., Kelly, S., Kwan, H., 2000. Bridging Embodied Cognition and Brain Function: the Role of Phenomenology, Phil.Psych, 13, 2: 261-266. Boysson-Bardies, B., de Schonen, S., Jusczyk P., MacNeilage P.and Morton J, eds., 1993. Developmental Neurocognition: Speech and Face Processing in the First Year of Life, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Changeux, J.P. 1983. LHomme neuronal, Paris: Fayard. Churchland, P.S. 1986. Neurophilosophy. Toward a Unied Science of Mind-Brain, Cambridge: M.I.T. Press. Chrtien, J.L. 1990. La Voix nue. Phnomnologie de la promesse, Paris: Ed. Minuit Damasio, A.R. 1994. Descartess Error. Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain, A. Grosset/Putnam Books. Damasio, A.R. 1999. Te Feeling of What Happens. Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness, N.Y: Harcourt Brace & Compagny. Davies, M. 2000. Interaction without reduction: Te Relationship between Personal and Subpersonal Levels of Description, Mind & Society, 2, vol. 1: 87-105. Dennett, D.C. 1991. Consciousness Explained, Little, Brown & Compagny. Dreyfus, H.L. 2000. A Merleau-Pontyian Critique of Husserls and Searles Represen- tationalist Accounts of Action, Proc. Aris. Soc., 100: 287-302. 154 Janus Head Edelmann, G. 1987. Neural Darwinism: Te Teory of Neuronal Group Selection, N.Y.: Basic Books. Enns, D. 1995, We Flesh: Re-membering the Body Beloved, Philosophy Today Celina, 39, 3: 263-279. Evans F., Lawlor L. (eds). 2000. Merleau-Pontys Notion of Flesh, Albany: Suny Press. Evrard, P., Minkowski, A., 1989. Developmental Neurobiology, Raven Press. Gold, I., Stoljar, D. 1999. A Neuron Doctrine in the Philosophy of Neuroscience, BBS, vol. 22: 809-830. Harisson, P.J. 1991. Are Mental States a Useful Concept? Neurophilosophical Inu- ences on Phenomenology and Psychopathology, J. Nerv. Ment. Dis., Jun, 179, 6: 309-316. Heinmaa, S. 1999. Merleau-Pontys Modication of Phenomenology: Cognition, Passion and Philosophy, Synthese 118: 49-68. Henry, M. 1999. Incarnation, Paris: Le Seuil. Hubel, D., 1988. Te Eye, Te Brain and the Vision, Scientic American Book. Jacob F., 1970, La logique du vivant. Une histoire de lhrdit, Paris, Gallimard. (Eng. trans. Te Logic of Life) Kambouchner, D. 1995: LHomme des passions. Commentaires sur Descartes, Paris: Albin Michel, 2 vols. Lecanuet, J.P., Fifer, W.P., Krasnegor, N.A. (eds.), 1995, Fetal Development: A Psycho- biological Perspective, Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associate Publishers. Le Douarin, N. 1982. Te Neural Crest, Cambridge University Press. Lefort C. 1991. Flesh and Otherness, in Johnson Galen A.(ed.), Ontology and Alterity in Merleau Ponty, pp. 3-13. Evanston: Northwestern Univ. Pr. Lever, D. 1990. Flesh and Blood: A Proposed Supplement to Merleau-Ponty, Human Stud., 13, 3: 209-219. Mehler, J., Bertoncini, J., Barrire, M. and Jassik-Gershenfeld, D. 1978. Infant Rec- ognition of Mothers Voice, Perception, 7: 491-497. Mensch, J. 1994. Te Mind-Body Problem: Phenomenological Reections on an Ancient Solution, Amer. Cath. Phil. Quart., 68, 1: 31-56. Merleau-Ponty, M. [1945]. Phenomenology of Perception, Transl., 1962, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Merleau-Ponty, M. 1995, La Nature. Notes de cours du Collge de France, Paris: Le Seuil. Purves, D. 1988. Body and Brain: A Trophic Teory of Neural Connections, Harvard University Press. Reuter, M. 1999. Merleau-Pontys Notion of Pre-reective Intentionality, Synthese, 118: 69-88. Rochat, P. 2001. Te Infants World, Te Developing Child Series, Harvard University Press. Simondon, G. 1989. Lindividuation psychique et collective la lumire des notions de Forme, Information, Potentiel et Mtastabilit, Paris: Aubier. Smith, C. 2001. Renatus renatus: Te Cartesian tradition in British Science and the Neurophilosophy of J. Carrew Eccles, Brain Cognition, Aug., 46, 3: 364-372. Spemann, H. 1938. Embryonic Development and Induction, New Haven: Yale Uni- versity Press. Stent, G.S., Spicker, S.F. 1990. Te Poverty of Neurophilosophy. Biological Research
Bernard Andrieu 155 and Reality, J. of Medecine and Philosophy, 15,5: 539-557. Todes, S. 2001, Body and World,Cambridge: MIT Press. Varela, F. 1979, Principles of Biological Autonomy, Amsterdam: North Holland. Varela, F., 1996, Neurophenomenology: A Methodological Remedy for the Hard Problem, J. Consc. Studies, 3: 330-350. Varela, F., Tompson, E. and Rosch, E. 1991. Te Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience, Cambridge: MIT Press. Authors note: Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Bernard Andrieu. Email: [email protected].