Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Essay
()
About this ebook
Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant wird 1724 in Königsberg geboren. Mit 16 Jahren beginnt er das Studium der Theologie, Philosophie und Naturwissenschaften an der Königsberger Universität. Jedoch erst im Alter von 46 Jahren erhält er eine ordentliche Professur für Logik und Metaphysik in Königsberg. Als wirkungsmächtigster deutscher Philosoph neben Hegel erlangt Kant schon zu Lebzeiten einen legendären Ruf. Er verbringt sein Leben alleinstehend und einem strengen selbstauferlegten Tagesablauf folgend, der Anlaß zu zahlreichen überlieferten Anekdoten bietet. Kant stirbt in hohem Alter von 80 Jahren 1804 in Königsberg.
Read more from Immanuel Kant
Collected Works of Immanuel Kant: Complete Critiques, Philosophical Works and Essays (Including Kant's Inaugural Dissertation): Biography, The Critique of Pure Reason, The Critique of Practical Reason, The Critique of Judgment, Philosophy of Law... Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsKant: Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Kant’s Critiques: The Critique of Pure Reason; The Critique of Practical Reason; The Critique of Judgement Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Kant's Prolegomena: To Any Future Metaphysics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGroundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals (Translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Quotable Kant Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Perpetual Peace: A Philosophic Essay Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Introduction to Logic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5On the Metaphysics of Morals and Ethics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Logic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Critique of Judgment Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Kant's Critiques Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (Barnes & Noble Digital Library) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Greatest Works of Immanuel Kant: Complete Critiques, Philosophical Works & Essays (Including Inaugural Dissertation & Biography) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Critique of Pure Reason: Bestsellers and famous Books Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Related to Perpetual Peace
Related ebooks
The Designed World of Information: Unveiling the Incredible Realm Beyond Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Nature of Infinitesimals Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPhilosophical Methodology in Classical Chinese and German Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBuilding Bridges between Chan Buddhism and Confucianism: A Comparative Hermeneutics of Qisong's "Essays on Assisting the Teaching" Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWhen Right Makes Might: Rising Powers and World Order Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Greatest Investment of the 21st Century Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFuture Agenda: Six Challenges for the Next Decade Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsLife, Liberty, and the Pursuit of Dao: Ancient Chinese Thought in Modern American Life Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Development, Democracy, and Welfare States: Latin America, East Asia, and Eastern Europe Rating: 1 out of 5 stars1/5Toward a Theory of Peace: The Role of Moral Beliefs Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA Global Security System: An Alternative to War (2018-19 Edition) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThucydides, Hobbes, and the Interpretation of Realism Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Unanswered Threats: Political Constraints on the Balance of Power Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Japan in the American Century Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFull Spectrum Dominance: Irregular Warfare and the War on Terror Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsChinese Economic Statecraft: Commercial Actors, Grand Strategy, and State Control Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsLogics of War: Explanations for Limited and Unlimited Conflicts Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Discovery of Things: Aristotle's Categories and Their Context Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsNeurophilosophy of Consciousness, Vol. V and Yogi Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWho Turned Out the Lights?: Your Guided Tour to the Energy Crisis Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Dependency and Development in Latin America Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Divided Dynamism: The Diplomacy of Separated Nations: Germany, Korea, China Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Republic of Beliefs: A New Approach to Law and Economics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Explanation and Progress in Security Studies: Bridging Theoretical Divides in International Relations Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsStrategic Reassurance and Resolve: U.S.-China Relations in the Twenty-First Century Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsStatecraft and Society in China: Grassroots politics in China Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMind Set!: Eleven Ways to Change the Way You See—and Create—the Future Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHow Knowledge Moves: Writing the Transnational History of Science and Technology Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSun Tzu and the Rise of China: Why Taiwan Is Being Forced Back to the Mainland, the Fall of Hong Kong and Other Collected Essays Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
German For You
German For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5German Short Stories for Beginners Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/51000 German Flash Cards Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/52,001 Most Useful German Words Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5German Frequency Dictionary - 1000 Key & Common German Words in Context: German-English, #0 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Everything Essential German Book: All You Need to Learn German in No Time! Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Intermediate-Advanced German Vocabulary Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Everything German Phrase Book: A quick refresher for any situation Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Learning German With Stories And Pictures: Fred Der Fisch Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5German All-in-One For Dummies Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPractice Makes Perfect German Vocabulary Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5German Grammar in Exercises Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Learn German: German for Kids - Bilingual Stories in English and German Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Conversational German Dialogues: Over 100 German Conversations and Short Stories Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Everything German Practice: Practical Techniques to Improve Your Speaking And Writing Skills Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5German Vocabulary Drills Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Easy Learning German Vocabulary: Trusted support for learning Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Easy German Dialogues: Fun & Simple Conversation Practice For Beginners And Intermediates Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Learn German with Stories: 12 Inspiring Short Stories with Secret Life Lessons (for Intermediates) Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Related categories
Reviews for Perpetual Peace
0 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
Perpetual Peace - Immanuel Kant
PUBLISHER NOTES:
Take our Free
Quick Quiz and Find Out Which
Best Side Hustle is ✓Best for You.
✓ VISIT OUR WEBSITE:
→ LYFREEDOM.COM ← ← CLICK HERE ←
PREFACE
This
translation of Kant’s essay on Perpetual Peace was undertaken by Miss Mary Campbell Smith at the suggestion of the late Professor Ritchie of St. Andrews, who had promised to write for it a preface, indicating the value of Kant’s work in relation to recent discussions regarding the possibility of making wars to cease.
In view of the general interest which these discussions have aroused and of the vague thinking and aspiration which have too often characterised them, it seemed to Professor Ritchie that a translation of this wise and sagacious essay would be both opportune and valuable.[1] His untimely death has prevented the fulfilment of his promise, and I have been asked, in his stead, to introduce the translator’s work.
This is, I think, the only complete translation into English of Kant’s essay, including all the notes as well as the text, and the translator has added a full historical Introduction, along with numerous notes of her own, so as (in Professor Ritchie’s words) to meet the needs (1) of the student of Political Science who wishes to understand the relation of Kant’s theories to those of Grotius, Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau etc., and (2) of the general reader who wishes to understand the significance of Kant’s proposals in connection with the ideals of Peace Congresses, and with the development of International Law from the end of the Middle Ages to the Hague Conference.
Although it is more than 100 years since Kant’s essay was written, its substantial value is practically unimpaired. Anyone who is acquainted with the general character of the mind of Kant will expect to find in him sound common-sense, clear recognition of the essential facts of the case and a remarkable power of analytically exhibiting the conditions on which the facts necessarily depend. These characteristics are manifest in the essay on Perpetual Peace. Kant is not pessimist enough to believe that a perpetual peace is an unrealisable dream or a consummation devoutly to be feared, nor is he optimist enough to fancy that it is an ideal which could easily be realised if men would but turn their hearts to one another. For Kant perpetual peace is an ideal, not merely as a speculative Utopian idea, with which in fancy we may play, but as a moral principle, which ought to be, and therefore can be, realised. Yet he makes it perfectly clear that we cannot hope to approach the realisation of it unless we honestly face political facts and get a firm grasp of the indispensable conditions of a lasting peace. To strive after the ideal in contempt or in ignorance of these conditions is a labour that must inevitably be either fruitless or destructive of its own ends. Thus Kant demonstrates the hopelessness of any attempt to secure perpetual peace between independent nations. Such nations may make treaties; but these are binding only for so long as it is not to the interest of either party to denounce them. To enforce them is impossible while the nations remain independent. There is,
as Professor Ritchie put it (Studies in Political and Social Ethics, p. 169), only one way in which war between independent nations can be prevented; and that is by the nations ceasing to be independent.
But this does not necessarily mean the establishment of a despotism, whether autocratic or democratic. On the other hand, Kant maintains that just as peace between individuals within a state can only be permanently secured by the institution of a republican
(that is to say, a representative) government, so the only real guarantee of a permanent peace between nations is the establishment of a federation of free republican
states. Such a federation he regards as practically possible. For if Fortune ordains that a powerful and enlightened people should form a republic—which by its very nature is inclined to perpetual peace—this would serve as a centre of federal union for other states wishing to join, and thus secure conditions of freedom among the states in accordance with the idea of the law of nations. Gradually, through different unions of this kind, the federation would extend further and further.
Readers who are acquainted with the general philosophy of Kant will find many traces of its influence in the essay on Perpetual Peace. Those who have no knowledge of his philosophy may find some of his forms of statement rather difficult to understand, and it may therefore not be out of place for me to indicate very briefly the meaning of some terms which he frequently uses, especially in the Supplements and Appendices. Thus at the beginning of the First Supplement, Kant draws a distinction between the mechanical and the teleological view of things, between nature
and Providence
, which depends upon his main philosophical position. According to Kant, pure reason has two aspects, theoretical and practical. As concerning knowledge, strictly so called, the a priori principles of reason (e.g. substance and attribute, cause and effect etc.) are valid only within the realm of possible sense-experience. Such ideas, for instance, cannot be extended to God, since He is not a possible object of sense-experience. They are limited to the world of phenomena. This world of phenomena (nature
or the world of sense-experience) is a purely mechanical system. But in order to understand fully the phenomenal world, the pure theoretical reason must postulate certain ideas (the ideas of the soul, the world and God), the objects of which transcend sense-experience. These ideas are not theoretically valid, but their validity is practically established by the pure practical reason, which does not yield speculative truth, but prescribes its principles dogmatically
in the form of imperatives to the will. The will is itself practical reason, and thus it imposes its imperatives upon itself. The fundamental imperative of the practical reason is stated by Kant in Appendix I. (p. 175):—Act so that thou canst will that thy maxim should be a universal law, be the end of thy action what it will.
If the end of perpetual peace is a duty, it must be necessarily deduced from this general law. And Kant does regard it as a duty. We must desire perpetual peace not only as a material good, but also as a state of things resulting from our recognition of the precepts of duty
(loc. cit.). This is further expressed in the maxim (p. 177):—Seek ye first the kingdom of pure practical reason and its righteousness, and the object of your endeavour, the blessing of perpetual peace, will be added unto you.
The distinction between the moral politician and the political moralist, which is developed in Appendix I., is an application of the general distinction between duty and expediency, which is a prominent feature of the Kantian ethics. Methods of expediency, omitting all reference to the pure practical reason, can only bring about re-arrangements of circumstances in the mechanical course of nature. They can never guarantee the attainment of their end: they can never make it more than a speculative ideal, which may or may not be practicable. But if the end can be shown to be a duty, we have, from Kant’s point of view, the only reasonable ground for a conviction that it is realisable. We cannot, indeed, theoretically know that it is realisable. Reason is not sufficiently enlightened to survey the series of predetermining causes which would make it possible for us to predict with certainty the good or bad results of human action, as they follow from the mechanical laws of nature; although we may hope that things will turn out as we should desire
(p. 163). On the other hand, since the idea of perpetual peace is a moral ideal, an idea of duty
, we are entitled to believe that it is practicable. Nature guarantees the coming of perpetual peace, through the natural course of human propensities; not indeed with sufficient certainty to enable us to prophesy the future of this ideal theoretically, but yet clearly enough for practical purposes
(p. 157). One might extend this discussion indefinitely; but what has been said may suffice for general guidance.
The wise and sagacious
thought of Kant is not expressed in a simple style, and the translation has consequently been a very difficult piece of work. But the translator has shown great skill in manipulating the involutions, parentheses and prodigious sentences of the original. In this she has had the valuable help of Mr. David Morrison, M.A., who revised the whole translation with the greatest care and to whom she owes the solution of a number of difficulties. Her work will have its fitting reward if it succeeds in familiarising the English-speaking student of politics with a political essay of enduring value, written by one of the master thinkers of modern times.
R. LATTA.
University of Glasgow, May 1903.
CONTENTS
PAGE
PREFACE BY PROFESSOR LATTA
v
TRANSLATOR’S INTRODUCTION
1
PERPETUAL PEACE
106
FIRST SECTION CONTAINING THE PRELIMINARY ARTICLES OF PERPETUAL PEACE BETWEEN STATES
107
SECOND SECTION CONTAINING THE DEFINITIVE ARTICLES OF PERPETUAL PEACE BETWEEN STATES
117
FIRST SUPPLEMENT CONCERNING THE GUARANTEE OF PERPETUAL PEACE
143
SECOND SUPPLEMENT—A SECRET ARTICLE FOR PERPETUAL PEACE
158
APPENDIX I.—ON THE DISAGREEMENT BETWEEN MORALS AND POLITICS WITH REFERENCE TO PERPETUAL PEACE
161
APPENDIX II.—CONCERNING THE HARMONY OF POLITICS WITH MORALS ACCORDING TO THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEA OF PUBLIC RIGHT
184
INDEX
197
TRANSLATOR’S INTRODUCTION
This
is an age of unions. Not merely in the economic sphere, in the working world of unworthy ends and few ideals do we find great practical organizations; but law, medicine, science, art, trade, commerce, politics and political economy—we might add philanthropy—standing institutions, mighty forces in our social and intellectual life, all have helped to swell the number of our nineteenth century Conferences and Congresses. It is an age of Peace Movements and Peace Societies, of peace-loving monarchs and peace-seeking diplomats. This is not to say that we are preparing for the millennium. Men are working together, there is a newborn solidarity of interest, but rivalries between nation and nation, the bitternesses and hatreds inseparable from competition are not less keen; prejudice and misunderstanding not less frequent; subordinate conflicting interests are not fewer, are perhaps, in view of changing political conditions and an ever-growing international commerce, multiplying with every year. The talisman is, perhaps, self-interest, but, none the less, the spirit of union is there; it is impossible to ignore a clearly marked tendency towards international federation, towards political peace. This slow movement was not born with Peace Societies; its consummation lies perhaps far off in the ages to come. History at best moves slowly. But something of its past progress we shall do well to know. No political idea seems to have so great a future before it as this idea of a federation of the world. It is bound to realise itself some day; let us consider what are the chances that this day come quickly, what that it be long delayed. What obstacles lie in the way, and how may they be removed? What historical grounds have we for hoping that they may ever be removed? What, in a word, is the origin and history of the idea of a perpetual peace between nations, and what would be the advantage, what is the prospect of realising it?
The international relations of states find their expression, we are told, in war and peace. What has been the part played by these great counteracting forces in the history of nations? What has it been in prehistoric times, in the life of man in what is called the state of nature
? It is no easy enterprise,
says Rousseau, in more than usually careful language, to disentangle that which is original from that which is artificial in the actual state of man, and to make ourselves well acquainted with a state which no longer exists, which perhaps never has existed and which probably never will exist in the future.
(Preface to the Discourse on the Causes of Inequality, 1753, publ. 1754.) This is a difficulty which Rousseau surmounts only too easily. A knowledge of history, a scientific spirit may fail him: an imagination ever ready to pour forth detail never does. Man lived, says he, without industry, without speech, without habitation, without war, without connection of any kind, without any need of his fellows or without any desire to harm them ... sufficing to himself.
[2] (Discourse on the Sciences and Arts, 1750.) Nothing, we are now certain, is less probable. We cannot paint the life of man at this stage of his development with any definiteness, but the conclusion is forced upon us that our race had no golden age,[3] no peaceful beginning, that this early state was indeed, as Hobbes held, a state of war, of incessant war between individuals, families and, finally, tribes.
The Early Conditions of Society.
For the barbarian, war is the rule; peace the exception. His gods, like those of Greece, are warlike gods; his spirit, at death, flees to some Valhalla. For him life is one long battle; his arms go with him even to the grave. Food and the means of existence he seeks through plunder and violence. Here right is with might; the battle is to the strong. Nature has given all an equal claim to all things, but not everyone can have them. This state of fearful insecurity is bound to come to an end. Government,
says Locke, (On Civil Government, Chap. VIII., § 105) is hardly to be avoided amongst men that live together.
[4] A constant dread of attack and a growing consciousness of the necessity of presenting a united front against it result in the choice of some leader—the head of a family perhaps—who acts, it may be, only as captain of the hosts, as did Joshua in Israel, or who may discharge the simple duties of a primitive governor or king.[5] Peace within is found to be strength without. The civil state is established, so that if there needs must be war, it may not yet be against all men, nor yet without some helps.
(Hobbes: On Liberty, Chap. I., § 13.) This foundation of the state is the first establishment in history of a peace institution. It changes the character of warfare, it gives it method and system; but it does not bring peace in its train. We have now, indeed, no longer a wholesale war of all against all, a constant irregular raid and plunder of one individual by another; but we have the systematic, deliberate war of community against community, of nation against nation.[6]
War in Classical Times.
In early times, there were no friendly neighbouring nations: beyond the boundaries of every nation’s territory, lay the land of a deadly foe. This was the way of thinking, even of so highly cultured a people as the Greeks, who believed that a law of nature had made every outsider, every barbarian their inferior and their enemy.[7] Their treaties of peace, at the time of the Persian War, were frankly of the kind denounced by Kant, mere armistices concluded for the purpose of renewing their fighting strength. The ancient world is a world of perpetual war in which defeat meant annihilation. In the East no right was recognised in the enemy; and even in Greece and Rome the fate of the unarmed was death or slavery.[8] The barbaric or non-Grecian states had, according to Plato and Aristotle, no claim upon humanity, no rights in fact of any kind. Among the Romans things were little better. According to Mr. T. J. Lawrence—see his Principles of International Law, III., §§ 21, 22—they were worse. For Rome stood alone in the world: she was bound by ties of kinship to no other state. She was, in other words, free from a sense of obligation to other races. War, according to Roman ideas, was made by the gods, apart altogether from the quarrels of rulers or races. To disobey the sacred command, expressed in signs and auguries would have been to hold in disrespect the law and