Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $9.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures
Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures
Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures
Ebook308 pages3 hours

Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Hailed by the Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society as "easy to use and a pleasure to read," this research monograph is recommended for students and professionals interested in model theory and definability theory. The sole prerequisite is a familiarity with the basics of logic, model theory, and set theory.
The author, Professor of Mathematics at UCLA and Emeritus Professor of Mathematics,University of Athens, Greece, begins with a focus on the theory of inductive and hyperelementary sets. Subsequent chapters advance to acceptable structures and countable acceptable structures, concluding with the main result of the Barwise-Gandy-Moschovakis theory, which is the key to many applications of abstract recursion theory. Exercises at the end of each chapter form an integral part of the text, offering examples useful to the development of the general theory and outlining the theory's extensions.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateJun 10, 2014
ISBN9780486152011
Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures

Related to Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures

Related ebooks

Mathematics For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Elementary Induction on Abstract Structures - Yiannis N. Moschovakis

    SYMBOLS

    INTRODUCTION

    which are inductively definable in the same language.

    Consider first a typical example of the kind of inductive definition we have in mind.

    be a group and b1, . . ., bk fixed members of G, and take

    H = [b1, . . ., bk] = the subgroup generated by b1 , . . ., bk.

    There are two traditional ways of defining this notion in an algebra course.

    One is to say that H is the least subset of G which satisfies

    Putting

    we have the explicit definition

    ,

    and put

    It is an easy exercise to show that both definitions yield the same set. The advantage of the first method is that it yields an explicit definition for H. The second approach makes clear that there is an induction involved in the definition and appears to be more constructive.

    From our point of view the significant observation is that with either explication the clauses (1), (2) of the induction . Equivalently, the formula φ(x, S. Moreover, the relation variable S occurs positively in φ(x, S); it is not hard to see that whenever we have clauses like (1), (2) then the formula that combines them will be positive in the relation variable of the induction.

    In the most general case we will study, there will be a formula

    , with n free variables and only positive occurrences of the n-ary relation variable S. The set built up by φ is defined explicitly by

    The second approach of the example may lead to a transfinite induction in the general case,

    but as in the example, the two methods lead to the same set,

    These sets of the form that come directly from inductions are the fixed points . We will call a relation R on A inductive on if there is a fixed point and constants ā = a1, . . ., ak in A such that

    i.e., the inductive relations are those reducible to fixed points. Finally the hyperelementary relations will be those which are inductive and have inductive complements.

    One meets inductive and hyperelementary relations in practically every field of mathematics. The examples in algebra are rather obvious, e.g. the algebraically closed subfield of F generated by b1, . . ., bk is inductive in the field structure of an algebraically closed field F.

    In logic, perhaps the typical example is the truth set for arithmetic,

    which is hyperelementary.

    In set theory we can cast all transfinite recursions in this form; for example, if

    is the Gödel function enumerating the constructible sets of order less than the infinite cardinal λ, then the relation

    .

    Finally in recursion theory, the basic definitions in the theories of constructive ordinals and recursion in higher types are the most obvious important examples, but of course inductive definitions of various types pervade the whole subject.

    It is perhaps amusing that a notion which appears to be fundamental and widely applicable has not been explicitly isolated in any published paper that we can find. The very recent papers Grilliot [1971], Barwise–Gandy–Moschovakis [1971], Moschovakis [1970] and [1971a] come close to an abstract approach, but they only study rather special structures. In fact, in Barwise–Gandy–Moschovakis [1971] we read "given a set A equipped with some recursion theoretic structure, one can attempt to formulate. . .". Before these, the most general attack on the problem is Spector’s fundamental [1961] where he defines and studies extensively the inductive relations on the structure of arithmetic.

    But the preceding paragraph is very bad history. Specifically for the structure of arithmetic, long before Spector’s [1961] Kleene had obtained all the key results in the pioneering papers [1944], [1955a], [1955b], [1955c]. In these, Kleene is consciously studying inductive definitions, even though he explicitly draws back from considering all of them sets which Kleene had already identified with the hyperarithmetical sets and which he had studied exhaustively.

    and hyperarithmetical sets. The approach to this theory through inductive definitions was not made explicit until Spector’s [1961] and was not followed up very much after that, simply because Kleene and his students and followers looked at the subject as recursion theorists and chose to formulate their results in recursion theoretic rather than model theoretic terms.

    The theory was extended to almost arbitrary structures in Moschovakis [1969a], [1969b], [1969c]. Here again the approach was entirely recursion theoretic in form, so much so that the identification of semihyperprojective relations with the inductive relations of the appropriate structure was only added as an afterthought in Remark 21 of the revised version of [1969b]. Nevertheless, the introduction to [1969a] says the main technical contribution of this paper is the introduction and systematic exploitation of existential, nondeterministic clauses in inductive definitions, i.e. again the results were mostly about inductive definability even though they were cast in recursion theoretic terms.

    During UCLA’s Logic Year 1967–1968, Gandy argued repeatedly and forcefully that the key notion of abstract recursion theory should be that of an inductive definition. There is a counterargument to this, that recursion theory should have something to say about computations. Nevertheless, it was obvious that it would be useful to have a development of the theory in Moschovakis [1969a], [1969b], [1969c] from the point of view of inductive definability, as many of the recursion theoretic arguments and methods of these papers seemed somehow irrelevant to the main results. To do this is one of our aims here.

    One of the important tools for an exposition of these results from a model theoretic, inductive definability approach is the introduction and systematic exploitation of open games. There was a glimpse of this idea in the last section of Moschovakis [1969b] titled A game theoretic characterization of semi-hyperprojective sets, but some of the missing tricks did not become available until Moschovakis [1970] and [1971a]. This allowed for a neat exposition of most of the first two papers [1969a] and [1969b].

    The present work was motivated by some further extensions of these game theoretic ideas which yielded fairly comprehensible proofs of the rather delicate theorems in the third paper [1969c]—this was where we generalized Kleene’s deepest results on the hyperarithmetical sets in Kleene [1959a].

    A byproduct of attempting to lecture on these matters in a seminar was the somewhat surprising discovery that a very substantial part of the theory of inductive and hyperelementary sets goes through for completely arbitrary structures. This comprises the first four chapters here. Afterwards we specialize to acceptable structures and then in Chapter 8 to countable acceptable structures, but even then the flavor is decidedly model theoretic and there are no explicit references to recursion theory. In Chapter 9 we prove a very general version of the main result of Barwise–Gandy–Moschovakis [1971] which is the key to many applications of the present methods to abstract recursion theory.

    sets of integers.

    The text is technically accessible to a student who is familiar with the basic notions of logic, model theory and set theory, the material usually covered in the first semester of a graduate or advanced undergraduate logic course. Some of the exercises require a deeper knowledge of set theory. However, the motivation and some of the implications of the results will be better understood by those students who have some acquaintance with the classical theory of recursive and hyperarithmetical sets, e.g. as developed in Rogers [1967] and Shoenfield [1967].

    I have tried hard to attribute all results and ideas to the mathematicians who first discovered them, but the task is difficult and I am sure that there are both errors and omissions.

    Much of the exciting current research in abstract recursion theory is concerned with very general inductions—nonmonotone inductive definitions and definitions in very restricted or very rich languages. We hope that this work will provide a point of reference by giving a neat exposition of the simplest and most developed part of the theory of inductive definability. We also have hopes that the model theorists may find something to interest them here, both in the results and in some of the methods.

    CHAPTER 1

    POSITIVE ELEMENTARY INDUCTIVE DEFINITIONS

    In this first chapter we introduce the classes of inductive and hyperelementary relations on a structure, we prove some of their simple properties and we discuss briefly some important examples of the theory.

    1A. Monotone operators

    Let A be an infinite set. We use a, b, c, . . ., x, y, z, . . . to denote members of A and P, Q, R, . . . to denote relations on A of any (finite) number of arguments. Barred letters will denote finite sequences from A, e.g.

    If P An is an nan n-tuple, we write interchangeably

    The cardinal number of a set X is |X|, so in particular for every n 1,

    |An| = |A|,

    since A is infinite. If λ is an ordinal number, then

    λ+ = least cardinal number greater than λ.

    An operator

    Γ: Power (An) → Power (An)

    is monotone if it preserves inclusion, i.e.

    For each such monotone Γ and each ordinal ξ by the transfinite recursion

    is an n-ary relation on A. We let

    be the relation defined inductively by Γ, or simply the set built up by Γ.

    It is also convenient to put

    so that for each ξ,

    1A.1. THEOREM. Let A be an infinite set, let Γ be a monotone operator on the n-ary relations on A, let , IΓ be defined as above.

    .

    (ii) For some ordinal κ of cardinality |A|,

    we call the least such κ the closure ordinal of Γ, κ = ||Γ||.

    (iii) The set built up by Γ is the smallest fixed point of Γ, i.e.

    PROOF, (i) follows directly from the monotonicity of Г, since for ζ ξ,

    To prove (ii) notice that if we had

    for every ξ < |A|+, then we could choose some

    for each ξ < |A|+ and then the set

    would be a subset of An of cardinality which is absurd. Hence for some κ < |A|+ we have

    from which an immediate transfinite induction shows that for every ξ κ.

    This argument also proves part of (iii), that IΓ is a fixed point of Γ, since if κ is the closure ordinal we have

    On the other hand, if P is any fixed point, i.e.

    Γ(P) = P,

    we can show by transfinite induction on ξ that

    because

    1B. Relative positive inductive definability

    Again let A be an arbitrary set. We will be working with formulas of the lower predicate calculus with individual and relation constants from Ahas an infinite list of individual variables x, y, z, . . ., a constant c for each element c of A, an infinite list S, T, U, . . . of n-ary relation variables for each n 1, a constant relation symbol P for each relation P on A, in particular the identity symbol =, and the usual logical symbols ¬, &, ∨, →, ∃, ∀. Formulas are defined as usual, with the quantifiers ∃, ∀ applied only to the individual variables—this is a first order language. Individual terms are the individual variables and constants and relation symbols are the relation variables and constants. Relation variables are always freewith no free variables of either kind are called sentences; they are either true or false under the natural interpretation of this language.

    We write

    φ ψ

    to indicate that "φ and ψ" are names of the same formula. This meta-mathematical convention is useful in defining formulas and establishing notation.

    Let S of formulas in which S occurs positively, briefly S-positive formulasof formulas with the following properties:

    (i) All formulas in which S .

    (ii) If S is nis an n.

    (iii) If φ, ψ and x is any variable, then φ & ψ, φ ∨ ψ, (∃x)φ, (∀x.

    An easy induction on the length of formulas proves the following.

    1B.1. MONOTONICITY PROPERTY OF POSITIVE FORMULAS. Suppose S is an n-ary variable which occurs positively in φ(S) and suppose no other variable of either kind occurs free in φ(S). If P, P′ are n-ary relations on A, then

    if P ⊆ P′ and φ(P), then φ(P

    Here of course φ(P) is the result of substituting the relation constant P for the relation variable S in φ(S) and similarly for P′.

    Suppose now that A is infinite. An operator

    Γ: Power(An) → Power(An)

    is positive elementary in Q1, . . ., Qm if there is a formula

    such that the following conditions hold:

    are among =, Q1, . . ., Qm is the n-ary variable S.

    (ii) The symbols S, Q1, . . ., Qm .

    are among x1, . . ., xn.

    defines Γ, i.e. for each S An,

    as well as arbitrary occurrences of =, but we insist that all the other relation symbols occur positively.

    It is immediate from the monotonicity property of positive formulas that if Γ is positive elementary, then Γ is monotone. If φ defines Γ in the sense of (i)–(iv) above, it is convenient to put

    we then have for each ordinal ξ,

    and

    We call the set built up by φ.

    An n-ary relation R on A is positive elementary inductively definable in Q1, . . ., Qm, or simply inductive in Q1, . . ., Qm, if there are constants ā = a1, . . ., ak in A and an operator

    Γ: Power(Ak+n) → Power(Ak+n)

    which is positive elementary in Q1 . . ., Qm, such that

    By the definition above, we then have a formula

    in which the only relation symbols that occur are those that show, and except for = they all occur positively, such that

    The constants ā are called the parameters of the induction, but recall that there may be other individual constants occurring in φ.

    We can picture the construction of the fixed point plane and the definition of R from -axis as shown in Fig. 1.1.

    Fig. 1.1.

    We are mostly concerned in this book with inductive definability on a structure which is a bit different from the notion above and which we will define in Section 1D. However, the present notion is

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1