The Theory of Algebraic Numbers
By Harry Pollard and Harold G. Diamond
4/5
()
About this ebook
The authors, a pair of noted mathematicians, start with a discussion of divisibility and proceed to examine Gaussian primes (their determination and role in Fermat's theorem); polynomials over a field (including the Eisenstein irreducibility criterion); algebraic number fields; bases (finite extensions, conjugates and discriminants, and the cyclotomic field); and algebraic integers and integral bases. After establishing a firm introductory foundation, the text explores the uses of arithmetic in algebraic number fields; the fundamental theorem of ideal theory and its consequences; ideal classes and class numbers; and the Fermat conjecture (concluding with discussions of Pythagorean triples, units in cyclotomic fields, and Kummer's theorem).
In addition to a helpful list of symbols and an index, a set of carefully chosen problems appears at the end of each chapter to reinforce mathematics covered. Students and teachers of undergraduate mathematics courses will find this volume a first-rate introduction to algebraic number theory.
Related to The Theory of Algebraic Numbers
Related ebooks
Number Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Fundamentals of Number Theory Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Elementary Theory of Numbers Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Algebraic Theory of Numbers: Translated from the French by Allan J. Silberger Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Gamma Function Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSet Theory: The Structure of Arithmetic Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Elementary Number Theory: Second Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Elements of Number Theory Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIntroduction to Algebraic Geometry Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Understanding Proof: Explanation, Examples and Solutions Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings100 Great Problems of Elementary Mathematics Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Algebraic Extensions of Fields Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHistory of the Theory of Numbers, Volume II: Diophantine Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGroup Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5What Is Mathematical Logic? Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Transcendental and Algebraic Numbers Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5A Brief Introduction to Theta Functions Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsLinear Algebra Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Number Theory Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIntuitive Concepts in Elementary Topology Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Introductory Discrete Mathematics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Differential Topology: An Introduction Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIntroduction to Topology: Third Edition Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Elliptic Tales: Curves, Counting, and Number Theory Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Green Book of Mathematical Problems Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Theory of Approximation Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMatrices and Linear Algebra Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Extremal Graph Theory Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Summing It Up: From One Plus One to Modern Number Theory Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Mathematics For You
What If?: Serious Scientific Answers to Absurd Hypothetical Questions Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Quantum Physics for Beginners Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Solve It: A New Aspect of Mathematical Method Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Algebra - The Very Basics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Algorithms to Live By: The Computer Science of Human Decisions Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Game Theory: A Simple Introduction Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Summary of The Black Swan: by Nassim Nicholas Taleb | Includes Analysis Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Mathematics for the Nonmathematician Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5My Best Mathematical and Logic Puzzles Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Little Book of Mathematical Principles, Theories & Things Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Introducing Game Theory: A Graphic Guide Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Logic: How to Make Sense in a World that Doesn't Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsLearn Game Theory: Strategic Thinking Skills, #1 Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Think Like A Maths Genius: The Art of Calculating in Your Head Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCalculus For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Shape of a Life: One Mathematician's Search for the Universe's Hidden Geometry Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5How Minds Change: The New Science of Belief, Opinion and Persuasion Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Art of Statistical Thinking Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Fermat’s Last Theorem Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Geometry For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Statistics: a QuickStudy Laminated Reference Guide Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBasic Math & Pre-Algebra For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Introductory Discrete Mathematics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Vedic Mathematics Made Easy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Calculus Made Easy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Longitude Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Reviews for The Theory of Algebraic Numbers
1 rating0 reviews
Book preview
The Theory of Algebraic Numbers - Harry Pollard
NUMBERS
CHAPTER I
DIVISIBILITY
1. Uniqueness of factorization. Elementary number theory has for its object the study of the integers 0, ±1, ±2, …. Certain of these, the prime numbers, occupy a special position; they are the numbers m which are different from 0 and ±1, and which possess no factors other than ±1 and ±m. For example 2, 3, –5 are prime, whereas 6 and 9 are not, since 6 = 2·3, 9 = 3². The importance of the primes is due to the fact that, together with 0 and ±1, all the other integers can be constructed from them. The fundamental theorem of arithmetic asserts that every integer greater than 1 can be factored in one and only one way, apart from order, as the product of positive prime numbers. Thus
are the only factorizations of 12 into positive prime factors, and these factorizations all yield precisely the same factors; the only difference among them is in the order of appearance of the factors.
We shall give a proof of the fundamental theorem of arithmetic. In the course of it the following fact will play a decisive role: every collection, finite or infinite, of non-negative integers contains a smallest one. The validity of this assumption will not be debated here; it is certainly clear intuitively, and the reader may take it to be one of the defining properties of integers. Some preliminary theorems will be established first.
THEOREM 1.1. If a and b are integers, b > 0, then there exist integers q and r such that
where 0 ≤ r < b. The integers q and r are unique.
Consider the rational number a/b and let q be the largest integer which does not exceed it. Then q ≤ a/b, but q + 1 > a/b. Define r as a – bq. Since r/b = (a/b) – q ≥ 0, and b > 0, it follows that r ≥ 0. Also from 1 > (a/b) – q = (a – bq)/b = r/b we conclude that r < b.
To show that q and r are unique suppose that q′ and r′ is any pair of integers for which
If q′ > q, then q′ ≥ q + 1, so that
this contradicts r′ ≥ 0. If q′ ≤ q, then q′ ≤ q – 1, so that
this contradicts r′ < b.
Then both possibilities q′ > q, q′ < q are ruled out. It follows that q′ = q, and hence that r′ = r. This completes the proof of Theorem 1.1.
We shall say that two integers a and b are relatively prime if they share no factors except ±1. Thus 5 and 9 are relatively prime, whereas 6 and 9 are not.
THEOREM 1.2. If a and b are relatively prime then there exist integers s and t for which as + bt = 1.
Observe that there is no assertion about the uniqueness of s and t. In fact if a = 3, b = 5 we have
To prove the theorem note first that neither a nor b can be zero unless the other is ±1. In that case the theorem is trivial. Otherwise consider the set of all numbers of the form ax + by, where x and y are integers. If we choose x = 1, y = 0, and then x = –1, y = 0, it is clear that a and –a are both in the set. Since a ≠ 0, one of a and –a is positive, so the set contains some positive numbers. Let d be the smallest positive number in the set, and write d = as + bt.
By Theorem 1.1 we can find q and r so that
Then
so that r is also in the set. Now 0 < r < d is not possible, since d is the least positive number in the set. The only alternative is r = 0. Hence b = dq. A similar argument, beginning with
shows that r′ = 0, a = dq′.
This proves that d is a factor shared by both a and b. But a and b are relatively prime, so that d = ±1; moreover d is positive, so it must be 1. Hence 1 = as + bt.
In what follows the notation "m | n means
m divides n or
m is a factor of n". If m is not a factor of n . The following theorem is the key to unique factorization.
THEOREM 1.3. If p is a prime number and p | ah, then p | a or p | b.
The possibility that p | a and p | b is not excluded by the theorem.
If p | a ; we shall show that in this case p must divide b.
Since p and a are relatively prime there exist integers l and m for which
This follows from the preceding theorem. Since p | ab we can write ab = pq. The last formula becomes p(lb + mq) = b, so that p | b.
COROLLARY 1.4. If a prime number p divides a product a1a2 ··· an of integers, it divides at least one of the ai.
For if p divides no ai, then by Theorem 1.3 it cannot divide any of
We are now in a position to prove the fundamental theorem stated in the opening paragraph of the chapter. Let m be a positive integer not 1. If it is not prime suppose it factors as m = m1m2, where m1 > 1, m2 > 1. If m1 and m2 are primes, stop; otherwise repeat the procedure for m1 and m2, and continue it for the new factors which appear. Eventually we must arrive at a stage where none of the factors will decompose again. Otherwise m, which is a finite integer, would be the product of an arbitrarily large number of factors all greater than 1.
Thus we arrive at a factorization
where each pi is positive and prime. Suppose
is any other factorization of m into positive primes. We must prove that the two factorizations differ at most in the order in which the primes appear. Since
it follows from Corollary 1.4 that q1 must divide one of the pi. We may suppose it to be p1, by renumbering the pi if necessary. Then q1 | p1. Since p1 and q1 are positive and prime p1 = q1. Hence, dividing out p1 = q1, we obtain
This procedure can be repeated with q2, …, until all the prime factors on one side are exhausted. At this stage all the factors on the other side must also be exhausted; otherwise we should have a product of primes on one side equal to 1 on the other. Then r = s and we are done.
If we try to apply the principle of unique factorization to negative integers, we encounter an obvious difficulty in the possible presence of minus signs in the factors. Thus
are two factorizations of –12 into primes, and these factorizations differ not merely in the order of the factors, but in the factors themselves. For in the first case the factors are 2, 2, –3; in the second case they are –2, –3, –2. This difficulty can be remedied by a slight restatement of the fundamental theorem to include negative numbers. Let 1 and – 1 be called units. The new statement is this.
THEOREM 1.5. (The Fundamental Theorem). Each integer not zero or a unit can be factored into the product of primes which are uniquely determined to within order and multiplication by units.
The slight change in the original proof which is needed here will be left to the reader.
2. A general problem. We are now in a possition to state the basic problem of algebraic number theory: if we extend the meaning of integer
to include a wider class of numbers than the numbers 0, ±1, ±2, … is there still a valid analogue of Theorem 1.5? The nature of the question can best be made plain by examples.
For this purpose we select first the Gaussian integers. By such an integer we shall mean a number of the form a + bi, where a and b . To avoid confusion later we shall refer to the ordinary integers as the rational integers. Let G denote the set of all Gaussian integers, and J the set of all rational integers. We shall sometimes write α ∈ A if α is a member of a set A. Note that in each set the sum, difference and product of integers are integers.
If α and β are numbers in G we say that α divides β, written α | β, if there is a number γ in G such that β = αγ. An element of G is a unit if it divides 1, and hence also every element of G. A number π is prime if it is not a unit and if in every factorization π = αβ one of α or β is a unit. With this terminology Theorem 1.5 becomes meaningful for the integers of G.
But is it true? It is, as we shall show presently. This fact may strike the reader as only what is to be expected. That such an impression is erroneous we demonstrate by exhibiting another simple class of integers
for which Theorem 1.5 is meaningful, but false.
, where a and b are rational integers. Clearly the sum, difference and product of such integers are of the same form. We shall denote the totality of them by H. Define unit and prime just as we did for the Gaussian integers by simply reading H for G wherever the latter occurs. As we shall prove a little later, ±1 are the only units in Hwill turn out to be prime in H. But observe that
so that the factorization of 21 into prime factors is not unique to within order and multiplication by units.
It is therefore reasonable to ask for which classes of integers
the fundamental theorem holds, and for which it does not. In particular how does one explain the discrepancy in behavior between the sets J and G on the one hand and H on the other? The answer to these questions must be postponed until later. For the present we content ourselves with demonstrating the assertions just made concerning the sets G and H.
3. The Gaussian integers. If α = a + bi is an element of G its norm N(α), or simply Nα= | α |² = a² + b². (
α
is the complex-conjugate of α). The following list contains the fundamental properties of the norm.
The proof of (i) is obvious since b = 0. To prove (ii) observe that if α = a + bi, β = c + di, then
As for (iii), suppose first that α is a unit. Then α | 1, so αβ = 1 for some β. By (ii) NαNβ = N1 = 1, and Nα | 1. Since Nα must be a non-negative integer, Nα = 1. Conversely if Nα = 1, a² + b² = 1, so that a = 0 or b = 0. Then α = 1, –1, i or –i, and these are obviously units. This argument also establishes most of (iv); the rest we leave to the reader.
Finally to prove (v), suppose Nα is prime and α = βγ. Then Nα = NβNγ is prime in J. So one of Nβ or Nγ is equal to 1, and by (iii) either β or γ is a unit.
The converse of (v) is false. To see this it is enough to show that 3 is prime in G, for N3 = 3² = 9. Suppose 3 = αβ. Then 9