V O X PAT R U M 8 2 ( 2 0 2 2 ) 4 0 5 - 4 2 6
DOI: 10.31743/vp.12178
Matthew Drever1
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
1. Hope in Times of Suffering
Chan Hellman, a researcher at the University of Oklahoma, with joint
appointments in Social Work and the Medical School, has developed
a body of research that argues that for those who face trauma and suffering
hope is a lead indicating factor for recovery2. This has led Hellman to found
the Hope Institute, which offers training, especially to poor and adversely affected communities, that promotes the development of practices that
cultivate hope. In a world of war and pandemic, I would like to consider
what Augustine might offer us on the topic of hope. Known as the doctor
of grace, Augustine is not often associated with hope. Indeed, of the three
theological virtues – faith, hope, and love – his views on faith and love
receive the most attention within secondary scholarship3. This may in part
be a function of where and how hope and its related concepts (e.g., spes,
sperare, expectare) show up in Augustine’s writings. Though present, his
discussion of hope is less directly evident in the writings that have tradi1
Prof. Matthew Drever, University of Tulsa, Bell Associate Professor of Anglican
and Ecumenical Studies, Department of Philosophy and Religion; email:
[email protected]; ORCID: 0000-0003-4780-3794.
2
C. Gwinn – C. Hellman, Hope Rising: How the Science of Hope Can Change
Your Life, New York 2019.
3
A good example of this is found in the popular and well-written: Augustine
Through the Ages: An Encyclopedia, ed. A. Fitzgerald, Grand Rapids 1999. Though comprehensive in its coverage of topics and themes in Augustine, it lacks any heading on
‘hope’. Studor is a notable exception here. B. Studor, Hope, in: Encyclopedia of Ancient
Christianity, ed. A. Berardino, Downers Grove 2014, p. 288-295.
Matthew Drever
406
tionally garnered the most scholarly attention (e.g., Confessions, City of
God, On the Trinity)4. The only work systematically dedicated to an analysis of hope, at least ostensibly, is Augustine’s Enchiridion, a late work on
the virtues of faith, hope, and love. This text, however, is oddly weighted
with only 3 paragraphs out of 121 devoted to hope5. Beyond this, the theme
of hope appears widely in certain writings, though often as a sub-theme
within a wider discussion (e.g., resurrection, immortality) or in conjunction with certain Bible verses (e.g., Jeremiah 17:5, Romans 8:24, Romans
12:12, 1 Timothy 6:17)6. These discussions of hope are most prevalent in
Augustine’s Narrations on the Psalms and in his Sermons on the Old and
New Testaments, especially those that cluster around Easter7.
At times contemporary scholarship has been skeptical and dismissive
of Augustine on the topic of hope. Often the criticism goes something
like this: Augustine’s references to hope throughout his corpus reduce to
an avoidance strategy of enduring suffering and repressing emotions in
the hope of future reward, coalescing into an otherworldly prescriptive
and unhelpful approach to human suffering. For those who would bring
Augustine’s account of hope into a contemporary context, such a critique
should not be ignored. It is part of a wider contemporary suspicion of the
perceived otherworldly focus of traditional Christian eschatology. In his
work Theology of Hope, Jürgen Moltmann identifies this critique as a cen4
Augustine’s political theology, especially as it emerges from De civitate Dei,
is one area that draws some contemporary scholarship on the theme of hope. See,
for example: M. Lamb, Between Presumption and Despair: Augustine’s Hope for the
Commonwealth, “American Political Science Review” 112/4 (2018) p. 1036-1049; A.
Mittleman, Hope in a Democratic Age, Oxford 2009; D. Billings, Natality or Advent:
Hannah Arendt and Jürgen Moltmann on Hope and Politics, in The Future of Hope:
Christian Tradition amid Modernity and Postmodernity, ed. M. Volf – W. Katerberg,
Grand Rapids 2004, p. 125-145.
5
The connection between faith, hope, and love is one cluster that has drawn some
contemporary scholarship. See, for example: M. Jackson, Faith, Hope and Charity and
Prayer in St. Augustine, “Studia Patristica” 22 (1989) p. 265-270; J. Pieper, Faith, Hope,
Love, San Francisco 1997.
6
On the role of Pauline passages in the formation of Augustine’s views on hope,
see: B. Studor, Augustine and the Pauline Theme of Hope, in: Paul and the Legacies of
Paul, ed. W. Babcock, University Park 1990, p. 201-225.
7
For examples from Augustine’s sermons (Sermo), see: 198, 2-3 (PL,1024-1026);
213, 5-9 (PL 38, 1062-1065); 232, 5-8 (PL 38, 1110-1112); 255, 2-5 (PL 38, 1186-1188);
261, 1 (PL 38, 1203-1204). Augustine’s discussions of hope are scattered throughout his expositions on the Psalms. For a study on expositions 1-91, see: L. Ballay, Der
Hoffnungsbegriff bei Augustinus, Munich 1964.
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
407
tral difficulty for modern audiences and their reception of Christian eschatology8.
Vincent Lloyd’s recent work, The Problem with Grace, provides
a provocative take on how contemporary suspicion against Christian eschatology can be brought to bear against Augustine. When he turns to hope,
Lloyd begins with the general claim that hope is not a virtue but rather
a rhetorical technique9. For Lloyd, this is not necessarily bad, and it does
not inevitably lead to a rejection of hope. It depends on the object of hope
and how hope is deployed to reach one’s goals. Here, Lloyd finds Augustine
troubling and potentially dangerous. He develops his critique of Augustine
in part through the work of Gillian Rose, a 20th century scholar writing at
the intersection of social thought (sociology) and philosophy (Hegel), who
reflected a great deal on human suffering while she was dying of terminal
brain cancer10. Lloyd notes that Rose had much to say about faith but little
about hope because: “the object of hope, Rose seems to suggest, is to be free
from laws, free from social norms – and so hope must be resisted. Faith,
in contrast, is commended by Rose because it grapples with both good and
evil; it grapples with the realities of the world without solace in any fantasy
of escape”11. Lloyd traces Rose’s reticence to speak about hope back to
Augustine’s contention that hope seeks only the good and never the bad,
while faith wrestles with both the good and bad. On this account, Lloyd
seems to agree with Rose that Augustinian hope is an avoidance strategy
that ignores the existential and moral challenges of suffering. Against this,
he cites a saying from the Russian monk Staretz Silouan that Rose was fond
of repeating – “keep your mind in hell and despair not” – which she drew
on amid her own struggle with cancer as the way human suffering ought to
be approached12.
Perspicuous as Lloyd’s work is in its wider discussions, it mischaracterizes Augustine’s account of hope. In so doing, it misses the resources it
might offer to contemporary scholars like Hellman who draw on hope to
help treat trauma and the wide-spread suffering of our current context. To
glimpse these resources, I will analyze Augustine in a thematic rather than
8
J. Moltmann, Theology of Hope, Minneapolis 1993.
V.W. Lloyd, The Problem with Grace: Reconfiguring Political Theology, Stanford
2011, p. 70.
10
G. Rose, The Broken Middle: Out of Our Ancient Society, Blackwell 1992; G.
Rose, Mourning Becomes the Law: Philosophy and Representation, Cambridge 1996.
11
Lloyd, The Problem with Grace, p. 71-72.
12
Lloyd, The Problem with Grace, p. 65.
9
Matthew Drever
408
chronological manner. That is, I will begin with Augustine’s Enchiridion,
a late work, which will provide a framework and overview of his approach
to hope that allows us to recognize and organize themes present in his other
writings. From there, I will turn to a few of his Letters and Sermons that
concisely raise key moral and spiritual themes prevalent in his wider discussions of hope, and that highlight biblical texts – 1 Tim. 6:17, Romans
12:12, Jeremiah 17:5 – central to his wider interpretation of hope. Here
we can also glimpse how the Bishop of Hippo drew on the virtue of hope
to counsel those within his community and beyond who sought answers
amidst life’s suffering.
2. Hope in the Enchiridion
We can begin with Augustine’s short treatise, the Enchiridion, which is
a late work he composed at the request for a short handbook on Christian
education13. As I have indicated, Augustine’s handling of faith, hope, and
love is uneven, but it gives us a baseline from which to work. He opens
with the claim that wisdom is the aim of Christian catechesis14. This leads
to a refrain common in his writings that wisdom is piety, and piety is the
worship of God (Job 28:28)15. From there, Augustine grounds worship in
faith, hope, and love, thereby connecting the triad of virtues to wisdom and
the Christian liturgy. Both connections are worth underscoring, and we will
examine further the way Augustine anchors hope to Christian sacramental
and liturgical practices. But first we should note the intimate connection
between faith, hope, and love that Augustine advances: “faith believes,
hope and charity pray. But hope and charity cannot be without faith, and
so faith prays as well […]. What is there that we can hope for without
believing in it?”16. Beyond this, hope and love are closely related in that
hope is grounded in love not fear: “So love cannot exist without hope nor
13
Augustine, Enchiridion de Fide, Spe et Charitate 1, 6, CCL 46, 50-51.
Augustine, Enchiridion de Fide, Spe et Charitate 1, 1-3, CCL 46, 49.
15
For example, see: Augustine, Confessiones 5, 5, 8, CSEL 33, 94; 8, 1, 2, CSEL 33,
171; Augustine, De spiritu et littera 11, 18, CSEL 60, 170.
16
Augustine, Enchiridion de Fide, Spe et Charitate 2, 7-8, CCL 46, 51, tr. B.
Harbert, On Christian Belief, in: The Works of Saint Augustine: A Translation for the
21st Century, New York 2005, p. 275-276. “fides credit, spes et caritas orant. sed sine
fide esse non possunt, ac per hoc et fides orat […] quid autem sperari potest quod non
creditur?”.
14
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
409
hope without love”17. Additionally, faith and hope share common ground
in that both are oriented toward things unseen – God, heaven, and the like.
Each of the three, however, is also irreducible to the other two. Hope and
love are different in that love can be for things seen (neighbor) and unseen
(God), while hope is always for things unseen. Hope and faith are distinguished in three ways18. First, we can have faith in good and bad things
– there is a heaven and a hell – but we hope only for good things. Second,
faith applies to past, present, and future: Christ was crucified, Christ is in
heaven, Christ will return. Hope applies only to things in the future. Third,
faith can pertain to us or to others: I believe things about my own origin,
and I believe things about the origin of angels. But hope has an irreducible
personal, existential component – it is always a claim about my existence.
Thus, hope is always about good things, the future, and me.
In saying this, we should not mistake such hope for a myopic, solipsistic vision of naïve bliss. Such a vision is well on the road to what Lloyd
terms enchantment: “This is the language of enchantment. It smoothes.
The failure of every practice to match a norm is hidden. Everything makes
sense: everything happens because it was supposed to happen […]. In other
words, enchantment fills the gap between practices and norms”19. Lloyd
argues that such enchantment can be theistic or atheistic, sacred or secular,
but that they both reduce to the same problem: in refusing to examine critically the gap between practice and norm, between what is and what should
be, enchantment ignores or rationalizes away the real emotions, struggles,
and suffering of human life. In the end, he concludes both forms of enchantment collapse into a singular idolatrous vison that:
makes us feel comfortable in our world. It makes us fell as if everything fits together nicely, as if we will always do the right thing, or have an explanation for
why we did not […]. And this is idolatrous. An idol captures and fills the gaze.
It dazzles. But it ultimately mirrors rather than reveals. It mirrors the desires of
the viewer, mirrors with an ‘invisible mirror’. The mirror is invisible because
sight has been saturated with the idolatrous reflection. Everything is seen, there
is no need to see more. Enchantment is the hegemony of the visible20.
17
Augustine, Enchiridion de Fide, Spe et Charitate 2, 8, CCL 46, 51-52, tr. B.
Harbert, On Christian Belief, in: The Works of Saint Augustine: A Translation for the 21st
Century, New York 2005, p. 276: “proinde nec amor sine spe est nec sine amore spes”.
18
Augustine, Enchiridion de Fide, Spe et Charitate 2, 8, CCL 46, 51-52.
19
Lloyd, The Problem with Grace, p. 213.
20
Lloyd, The Problem with Grace, p. 214.
Matthew Drever
410
Lloyd is critical of the Augustinian account of hope in part because
he thinks it is an accomplice to the crime of enchantment on a theological
and psychological level. Theologically, hope ends in idolatry and so fails
the first great commandment to love God. For Augustine, this would lead
inevitably to the failure to honor the second great commandment to love
others, given his view that true love of other people forms properly through
our love for God21. The cascading failure would also be felt at the level of
self-knowledge and love, given the intimate role that God and others play
in the formation of our selfhood22. On Lloyd’s critique, this would presage
the psychological trauma that hope inflicts as it dilutes the hard work of
critically confronting and addressing human suffering with a morphine drip
that feeds into a naïve panacea of peaceful delusion.
At this point, we seem far afield from a serious engagement with suffering, that is, from Rose’s cry for: “the mind to be in hell and not despair”.
Can Augustinian hope voice such anguish and not crumble in despair or
retreat into illusory enchantment? I think the answer is yes, but we must be
careful not to mistake the Augustinian good with anodyne elevator music
that blissfully carries us upward out of misery. For Augustine, the good
things hope seeks are ultimately connected to the Good, which renders
hope’s vision more akin to Moses on Sinai than a child on Santa’s lap. The
existential entanglement hope entails shakes, challenges, and convicts us to
the core. But the vision of hope is also of one’s inclusion within the Good
rather than exclusion from it, and it is precisely this inclusion that allows
one to face and endure suffering.
To see more precisely the way this vision of hope unfolds, we can begin by looking more closely at the Enchiridion. Here, Augustine correlates
21
Modern commentators sometimes worry that Augustine’s reading of our love
of neighbor through our love of God within the uti/ frui framework of De Doctrina
Christiana reduces the neighbor to a utilitarian means for our own return to God that
violates the neighbor’s integrity. Such criticism, however, is misguided and unfortunate
since Augustine shares the same basic concern of his modern critics to preserve the
integrity of the neighbor, which Augustine thinks can only be done when human love is
elevated through the divine love of the Spirit. Canning provides a prophylactic against
contemporary misreads in his excellent account of the reciprocity between divine and
human love. R. Canning, The Unity of Love for God and Neighbor in St. Augustine,
Leuven 1993.
22
This is one of the lessons I draw from the way Augustine weaves the influence
of God and other people into his own spiritual formation in Confessiones. M. Drever,
Creation and Recreation, in: The Cambridge Companion to Augustine’s Confessions, ed.
T. Toom, Cambridge 2020, p. 75-91.
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
411
faith, hope, and love to Christian liturgical practice: we learn about faith
from the creed, and hope and love from the Lord’s Prayer23. In this, we
see foremost the proper orientation of hope, namely, toward God: “of all
those things that must be faithfully believed, the only ones that concern
hope are those that are contained in the Lord’s Prayer, since, as the word
of God attests, cursed are those who trust in mere mortals (Jer. 17:5)”24.
One can sense an anti-Pelagian undertone to Augustine’s remark, which is
underscored as he goes on to emphasize that God alone is the proper source
of hope for both good deeds and good rewards. Augustine’s opening claim
that the unseen provides the shared orientation of faith and hope returns
now to voice a warning that true hope does not look toward us – the visible,
the historical, the mutable, the idol.
We should also note that the future orientation of hope straddles the
juncture of the historical (good deeds) and eschatological (good rewards)
future. True hope does not reduce to an otherworldly escapism but rather
sees the connections between the historical and eschatological. Augustine
drives this point home in Enchiridion when he turns to the seven petitions
of the Lord’s Prayer in Matthew as a guide to understanding Christian
hope25. He argues that the first three petitions refer to eternal goods but
are also temporal in the sense that they begin here and are perfected in the
future. For example, in the second petition – hallowed be thy name – we
honor God’s name now, but this comes to perfection in eternity. In the third
petition – thy kingdom come – God begins to establish his kingdom through
the historical church, but this also comes to perfection in eternity. The final four petitions refer to temporal goods because they are problems that
concern us now that will not be present in heaven. For example, the fifth
petition seeks forgiveness for sins, a problem that will not exist in heaven.
Augustine also argues that these petitions strike a balance between, on one
hand, the material and spiritual, and on the other hand, the individual and
communal. For example, the fourth petition – give us today our daily bread
– can be taken literally to refer to the material needs of the body – ours and
others – or spiritually to the Eucharist.
23
Augustine, Enchiridion de Fide, Spe et Charitate 2, 7, CCL 46, 51.
Augustine, Enchiridion de Fide, Spe et Charitate 30, 114, CCL 46, 110, tr. B.
Harbert, On Christian Belief, in: The Works of Saint Augustine: A Translation for the 21st
Century, New York 2005, p. 339: “Sed de his omnibus quae fideliter sunt credenda, ea
tantum ad spem pertinent quae in oratione dominica continentur. Maledictus enim omnis,
sicut divina testantur eloquia, qui spem ponit in homine”.
25
Augustine, Enchiridion de Fide, Spe et Charitate 30, 115, CCL 46, 110-111.
24
Matthew Drever
412
Augustine further underscores the historical/ eschatological connection he derives from the Lord’s Prayer in Letter 157, written in 414415 during the Pelagian controversy. Here, Augustine begins with the
contention that the petitions of the Lord’s Prayer all presuppose grace:
for example, lead us not into temptation is grounded on divine aid26.
More generally, Augustine argues that grace helps (adiuvetur) free will
(liberum arbitrium), and if God abandons free will we fall into pride.
While much could and has been said on the later Augustine’s account
of human will, I would note here how it illustrates the way Augustine
treats divine agency as inclusive of, rather than exclusive to, human
agency. God’s love enables and perfects human free will rather than
limits and destroys it. When we place God ahead of self, we do so not to
the exclusion, neglect, or detriment of self, but rather to achieve the full
potential and well-being of the self. This is also to say, then, that hope in
God is about embracing rather than abandoning self, history, and temporality. The beacon of hope calls us to God, and the divine shadow of
providence cast over human affairs is one of light not darkness, guiding
us to the fullness of being.
Within the seven petitions, the hard work of hope emerges at a complex, multivalent intersection that looks within the anguish of suffering
to voice the desire for healing. The Lord’s Prayer acknowledges the hardships of physical and spiritual life, and guides us to hope and seek after
the material well-being of adequate food and shelter while also pursuing
the spiritual well-being of forgiveness and renewal. The Lord’s Prayer
also recognizes that such forgiveness and renewal involve the individual,
community, and God. It is the hope of every individual to be reconciled
to God – forgive us our sins – even as there is a communal hope for reconciliation with others – as we forgive those who sin against us. This is
the hope of every individual who prays, but it is also the prayer of the
community expressed within liturgy and sacrament. The Lord’s Prayer
acknowledges such layers of suffering and renewal within an overarching
and anchoring voice of optimism. We pray and hope for a future, one that
represents material and spiritual betterment within historical life, but one
that is also oriented toward the eschatological future when suffering and
sin will be no more.
26
Augustine, Epistola 157, 2, 5, CSEL 44, 451-452.
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
413
3. The Spiritual Lessons of Hope
We can see, then, that the Enchiridion offers important lessons on hope,
even if in truncated fashion. In looking beyond this text, I would like to
turn to a couple of letters where Augustine addressees how hope intersects,
guides, and transforms human life. The overarching twofold theme I wish
to underscore is that hope does not represent either an anesthetizing, otherworldly vision that neglects suffering or an extreme ascetic embrace of suffering in search of a better tomorrow. We can begin by returning to Letter
157 and Augustine’s exegesis of Matthew 19:21, and Jesus’ command to
the rich man – Go, sell all that you have, and give it to the poor, and you
will have a treasure in heaven, and come follow me. Augustine rejects a literal reading of the passage that would have Christians sell their material
possessions in hope of attaining salvation. Such a reading suggests a spiritual/material dualism with an attendant ascetic rejection of material wealth
in favor of spiritual wealth. Instead, Augustine interprets Jesus’ command
as a demonstration that the rich man was dishonest in his prior claim that
he had kept all of God’s commandments (Matthew 19:20)27. The point of
Matthew 19:21 is not to establish a narrow spiritual precedent of rigorous
asceticism but rather to set a broader spiritual principle that God must be
honored above all other things. To underscore this claim, Augustine raises
the example of the patriarchs who did not sell all they owned in order to
follow God, but rather were people of wealth and faith28. Augustine drives
this point home by reading the passage in Matthew 19 in conjunction with
1 Timothy 6:17 – do not place hope in the uncertainty of riches29. He argues that the rich man’s failure was not in his refusal to sell all that he had,
but rather in a prior, more fundamental failure of placing his hopes in his
wealth rather than in God. The point is not to reject the material world but
rather to embrace God as the center of one’s life. In this, Augustine draws
on hope to moderate the potentially strong ascetic passage in Matthew 19,
intimating that hope offers an inclusive vision of spiritual life in the world
and does not reduce to an exclusivist, either/or account of God and world.
Stated differently, hope signals that we are not to despise the world but
rather to love God – hope is about love not fear. We might see the example
27
Augustine, Epistola 157, 4, 25, CSEL 44, 474-475.
Augustine, Epistola 157, 4, 24, CSEL 44, 473-474.
29
Augustine, Epistola 157, 4, 26, CSEL 44, 475; 157, 4, 30, CSEL 44, 478; 157, 4,
33, CSEL 44, 480.
28
Matthew Drever
414
of the rich man as a failure in love and hope grounded in the fear that he has
not fulfilled the requirements of the spiritual life.
When hope is aligned to God, we follow the commandments to love
God and neighbor. Regarding the latter commandment, Augustine notes
Paul’s counsel on maintaining a Christian household, which is aided by
material wealth (e.g., a home, family property)30. Here again, the point is
not to reject the world, but rather to use it in service to the love of God and
neighbor. Augustine’s claims about the household and neighbor also point
us toward the broader socio-historical ramifications of his understanding of
hope. In Letter 155, written between 413-414, Augustine takes up an ongoing fight he is waging, most notably in City of God, with various GrecoRoman philosophies on the nature of the good life in relation to human
suffering. In Letter 155, the Epicureans are in Augustine’s crosshairs:
But those who in this painful life, in these dying members, under this burden
of the corruptible flesh, wanted to be the source and the creators, as it were, of
their own happiness, seeking after it and retaining it as if by their own powers,
not asking and hoping for it from that fountain of virtues, were unable to grasp
God, who resists their pride. For this reason, they fell into the most absurd error.
When they claim that the wise man is happy even in the bull of Phalaris, they
are forced to admit that at times we should flee from the happy life31.
Augustine is referring to a supposed ancient ritual practice in which
victims were roasted alive inside a bronze bull, and to Epicurus’ claim that
the wise person who has conquered the fear of death can remain happy
even within the bull. Augustine rejects this idea as absurd. He also rejects
Cicero’s argument that suicide is justified under such circumstances of extreme suffering. Augustine goes on to draw on Cicero’s argument and its
wider philosophical use as evidence of contradiction in those who advocate
the twofold claim: the wise person can achieve happiness even in extreme
30
Augustine, Epistola 157, 4, 30, CSEL 44, 478.
Augustine, Epistola 155, 1, 2, CSEL 44, 431-432, tr. R. Teske, Letters 100—155,
in: The Works of Saint Augustine: A Translation for the 21st Century, New York 2003,
p. 408. “Illi vero qui in hac aerumnosa vita, in his moribundis membris, sub hac sarcina
corruptibilis carnis, auctores suae beatae vitae et quasi conditores esse voluerunt, velut
propriis eam virtutibus appetentes, iamque retinentes, non ab illo fonte virtutum petentes
atque sperantes, Deum superbiae suae resistentem sentire minime potuerunt. Unde in errorem absurdissimum lapsi sunt; ut cum asseverant etiam in Phalaridis tauro beatum esse
sapientem, cogantur fateri vitam beatam aliquando esse fugiendam”.
31
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
415
suffering; and the wise person is justified in committing suicide in cases of
extreme suffering. How is suicide justified if the person is happy?32 I do not
wish to dwell on the logic or details of this argument, which Augustine adjudicates here and elsewhere33. Rather, I raise it to illustrate how Augustine
draws on hope as an alternate model of human happiness amid suffering.
Echoing the Enchiridion, Augustine connects wisdom and happiness to piety and the worship of God, and positions hope as a guide to this vision of
happiness. Those who fail to hope in God and seek happiness instead in
the world commit a form of idolatry, positioning goodness and happiness
within their own (material) powers rather than the (immaterial) power of
God, leading to a vision of happiness that maximizes pleasure in this world
but ultimately fails on the crucible of human suffering. Grounded in the
proper worship of God, hope offers a vision of a transcendent good that
guards against such idolatry by refusing to reduce happiness to any form
of pleasure in this world we might achieve through our own power. In this,
hope reframes our understanding of happiness in relation to suffering, offering a vision of ultimate happiness that transcends suffering rather than
one forged within and despite suffering.
To many a modern eye, from Nietzsche forward, such a vision of hope
might seem deeply misguided. Within a secular model, it is sometimes
viewed as a tragic, even cowardly vision that sacrifices the only real opportunity for happiness in this world for the false promise of eternal happiness34. Even within theistic models, however, such a vision can receive
withering criticism from thinkers such as Lloyd who argue that it amounts
to what he terms “enchantment”: an immoral and spiritually bankrupt vision that refuses to address life’s sufferings. In seeking the good and never
the bad, as Augustine would have it, critics worry that hope’s vision becomes a grand, ephemeral illusion of human wish-fulfillment to avoid suffering. Such a vision is not of the true God but rather of the God we would
wish. Consequently, this vision deconstructs itself in ironic fashion, falling
into idolatry as we become beholden to it in an ever vainer and more vig32
Augustine, Epistola 155, 1, 3, CSEL 44, 432-434.
Augustine, De civitate Dei 1, 23-27, CSEL 40/1, 42-49.
34
Here, I am less concerned with such a critique, not because it is less serious, but
rather because it is grounded on the assumption of atheistic secularism, which is a debate
that would take us afield from the topic of this article. Suffice to say, if one assumes atheistic secularism, any religious model of hope that promises happiness beyond this life would
de facto fail. The only religious model of hope that might be endorsed is one that could
also maximize happiness in this world.
33
Matthew Drever
416
orous attempt to avoid and ignore suffering with the same misguided gusto
as those who argue that happiness can be found even while roasting alive
inside a bronze bull.
In addressing such criticisms, it is important to keep a few things in
mind. Foremost, it bears repeating that Augustine’s claim that hope seeks
only the good is not a form of wish-fulfillment that beckons toward some
trivial, superficial good like that hocked by contemporary televangelists
and prosperity gospel gurus: that we should try and feel good and avoid
bad feelings, or that the spiritually good amounts to little more than material goods. Hope’s vision for the good is ultimately a call to seek the
universal good, namely God, and so one that resists the reduction to any
limited, temporal pleasure35. In seeking this good, hope does not propagate
a grand avoidance strategy that refuses to take seriously suffering and evil.
Rather, the opposite is the case. Hope refuses to trivialize suffering by covering it over with false illusions of pleasure, as if we could and should be
happy amidst suffering if we just tried harder. In offering a vision of the
transcendent good, hope acknowledges the profound depth of suffering in
maintaining that it is irreconcilable with the achievement of true happiness
in this life. Here, Augustine recalls and affirms Cicero’s claim: “That statement of the same Cicero is certainly sounder where he says, ‘for this life
is indeed a death that I could lament if I wanted’. How, then, if this life is
rightly lamented, is it shown to be happy? And is it not rather proven to be
miserable because it is rightly lamented?”36. In the contemporary parlance
of a terminal cancer patient, we might return to Rose’s epigraph to “keep
your mind in hell and despair not” and recognize in the symbolism of hell
the irreconcilable conflict between happiness and suffering in this life.
The latter half of Rose’s epigraph – “despair not” – also reminds us
that we cannot give suffering too much power or it will overwhelm us.
Augustine argues that we must reframe suffering and view it through the
lens of endurance rather than pleasure as we seek for happiness beyond
suffering37. This takes suffering seriously, but not as the final word. Here,
Augustine reads Paul’s exhortation in Romans 12:12 – Rejoice in hope;
35
Augustine, Sermo 4, 2, CCL 41, 21; 4, 7, CCL 41, 23-24; 41, 3, CCL 41, 496-497;
255, 5, PL 38, 1188.
36
Augustine, Epistola 155, 1, 4, CSEL 44, 435, tr. R. Teske, Letters 100—155,
p. 409-410: “Sanior quippe est eiusdem Ciceronis illa sententia, ubi ait: Nam haec vita
quidem mors est, quam lamentari possem, si liberet. Quomodo ergo si recte lamentatur,
beata comprobatur; ac non potius quoniam recte lamentatur, misera esse convincitur?”.
37
Augustine, Epistola 155, 1, 4, CSEL 44, 434-435.
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
417
be patient in tribulation – through his own Christology to elaborate on
the details of this framework38. Augustine draws on the hidden/revealed
(invisible/visible) dynamic of the incarnation to argue that in Christ’s suffering we see an example of patience and endurance, while in Christ’s resurrection we find hope for happiness in the unseen life to come. Noting
the connection between hope and faith, Augustine argues that our faith in
God’s promise in Christ leads to our hopeful expectation of happiness to
come. Augustine’s Christological claims lend context to his model of hope
in a few respects. His play on the visible (suffering)/invisible (resurrection)
in Christ returns us to the claim that hope is in the unseen. If we take this in
conjunction with his reading of Matthew 5:839, that only the pure in heart
will see God, it means that the vision of the divine Christ toward which
hope points is reserved for the fully purified at the eschaton40. This process
of purification reminds us of the soteriological and moral dimensions that
accompany Augustine’s model of hope. Hope calls us to a patience and
endurance that does not passively accept or blissfully ignore the reality of
suffering. Rather, true hope must grapple with the evil, injustice, and tragedy in suffering as part of our spiritual and moral reconciliation with God
if we are to achieve the promised vision of God. This process of reconciliation does not leave us bereft of all happiness. Augustine points to Paul’s
claim to “rejoice in hope” as a type of happiness we experience now in
hope – “beatus esse interim spe”41. Augustine is trying to work between the
extreme ends of hedonism and the mortification of the flesh. Hope does not
leave us unhappy in this life, but neither does it reduce to a temporal form
of happiness. Rather, hope gives us happiness now as a proleptic vison of
Christ’s resurrection, which is to say a happiness in time that also points beyond the times – the saeculum – toward true happiness. We should also notice a reciprocity within Augustine’s hope-patience pairing: patience leads
us to the promise of hope even as hope gives us courage to endure suffering
in patience. Or, we might say that Christ’s patience in suffering informs and
transforms our understanding of the world as it prepares us for the promise
of happiness glimpsed in hope’s vision, even as Christ’s resurrection gives
38
Augustine, Epistola 155, 1, 4, CSEL 44, 434-435.
M.R. Barnes, The Visible Christ and the Invisible Trinity: Mt. 5:8 in Augustine’s
Trinitarian Theology of 400, “Modern Theology” 19/3 (2003) p. 329-355.
40
M. Drever, De Genesi ad litteram 12: Paul and the Vision of God, in: Augustinus:
De Genesi ad litteram. Ein kooperativer Kommentar, ed., J. Brachtendorf – V.H. Drecoll,
Augustinus – Werk und Wirkung 13, Paderborn 2021, p. 313-329.
41
Augustine, Epistola 155, 1, 4, CSEL 44, 434-435.
39
Matthew Drever
418
hope vision of this promise that lends us the courage to confront the reality
of suffering and not despair. Finally, we experience this vision and its transformative effects in rejoicing, that is, within the worship and liturgy of the
church. This returns us to the Enchiridion and Augustine’s claims that hope
connects with wisdom and the worship of God, even as it reminds us that
true hope, like true worship, is always of the good because it is the worship
of God and never of the bad, lest one fall into idolatry.
4. The Moral Lessons of Hope
At various points, I have indicated that Augustine connects hope with
virtue. In the quote above, for example, Augustine comments that hope,
in orienting us to God, opens us to virtue. In connection with this, he cites
Psalm 18:2 – I shall love you, O Lord, my virtue – and Psalm 40:5 – Happy
is the man for whom the name of the Lord is his hope and who has not search
after vanities and insane lies – and argues that the “vanities and lies” of sin
disclose the necessity of hope’s vision of God, which opens us to the divine aid necessary to achieve happiness and virtue42. Augustine also quotes
Jeremiah 17:5 – cursed is everyone who put his hope in a human being – as
evidence that happiness is not grounded in any human capacity or dimension of finite existence: the visible and bodily (e.g., material wealth) or the
invisible and intellectual (e.g., human knowledge)43. Here again, hope does
not issue in a rejection of human life, but rather in the affirmation that God
is the source of meaning and value. As in the Enchiridion, we do not abnegate moral responsibility on the hope that providential divine grace will
save us by divine fiat. Hope reorients rather than rejects virtue.
Importantly, Augustine identifies an individual and communal dimension within this process of reorientation. We should seek our own happiness
and the happiness of the city (civitas)44. This leads Augustine into a discussion of the cardinal political virtues of courage, prudence, temperance, and
justice45. These virtues too must be transformed through hope’s vision of
42
Augustine, Epistola 155, 2, 6, CSEL 44, 436-437.
Augustine, Epistola 155, 2, 8, CSEL 44, 438-439.
44
Augustine, Epistola 155, 3, 9, CSEL 44, 439.
45
Augustine, Epistola 155, 3, 10, CSEL 44, 440-441. Dodaro provides an excellent
analysis of Augustine’s characterization of the virtues in Letter 155. R. Dodaro, Political
and Theological Virtues in Augustine, Letter 155 to Macedonius, “Augustiniana” 54
(2004) p. 431-474.
43
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
419
God: “And those virtues will be true virtues and, by the help of him by
whose bounty they were given, they will grow and become perfect so that
they will without any doubt bring you to the truly happy life, which is none
other than eternal life”46. This transformation in God leads to the end of the
four virtues, viewed as both their perfection and cessation: prudence will
no longer distinguish evil (cessation), but it will unite with divine foresight (perfection); courage will not endure adversity (cessation), but it will
cling eternally to the good (perfection); temperance will not wrestle with
desire (cessation), but it will control it (perfection); and justice will not aid
the poor (cessation), but it will possess full righteousness (perfection)47. In
saying this, Augustine is careful to identify a connection between hope’s
vision of the happy life and virtue without reducing the former to the latter.
The life of virtue lived now is not identical to the happy life to come:
with these virtues given by God we now live a good life (bona vita), and
afterwards we will be given its reward, the happy life (beata vita), which can
only be eternal life. For the same virtues are practiced here and will have their
results there. Here they involve work; there they will be our reward. Here
they are our duty (officio); there they will be the end (fine) we attain48.
This is part of Augustine’s wider endeavor to maintain a transcendental
foundation for the good irreducible to any finite goods, but one that, nonetheless, does not leave us bereft of hope and beholden to despair: “And so
all good and holy people, even amid torments of every sort, supported by
God’s help, are called happy because of the hope for that end, the end in
which they will be happy. For if they were always in the same torments and
the fiercest pains, no sound mind would doubt that they were miserable no
matter what virtues they had”49. The proleptic vision hope offers of a happiness to come, which we have seen is grounded in Christ, is glimpsed now
46
Augustine, Epistola 155, 3, 12, CSEL 44, 442, tr. R. Teske, Letters 100—155, p.
413: “et verae illae virtutes erunt, et illius opitulatione, cuius largitate donatae sunt, ita
crescent et perficientur, ut te ad vitam vere beatam, quae non nisi aeterna est, sine ulla
dubitatione perducant”.
47
Augustine, Epistola 155, 3, 12, CSEL 44, 442-443.
48
Augustine, Epistola 155, 4, 16, CSEL 44, 446, tr. R. Teske, Letters 100—155, p.
415: “his, inquam, virtutibus divinitus impertitis, et bona vita nunc agitur, et postea praemium eius, quae nisi aeterna esse non potest, beata vita persolvitur. Hic enim sunt eaedem
virtutes in actu, ibi in effectu; hic in opere, ibi in mercede; hic in officio, ibi in fine”.
49
Augustine, Epistola 155, 4, 16, CSEL 44, 446-447, tr. R Teske, Letters 100—155,
p. 415: “Itaque omnes boni et sancti, etiam in tormentis quibuslibet divino fulti adiutorio, spe
420
Matthew Drever
in support of virtue. It is such hope that, in Rose’s words, allows us to dwell
within the hell of life’s suffering, despair not, and seek a virtuous engagement with and transformation of the world.
This process of transformation is completed upon the eschaton, but it
begins now in the love that connects us with God: “yet even in this life there
is no virtue but to love what one should love. To choose it is prudence; to be
turned away from it by no difficulties is courage; to be turned away from
it by no enticement is temperance; to be turned away from it by no pride
is justice”50. Drawing on the connection between hope and love, Augustine
argues that love enacts hope’s reorientation of the virtues. This leads back
to the two great commandments to love God and neighbor, which encapsulate virtue51. The love of God must come first in an inclusive rather than
exclusive sense, enabling and not denigrating the love of neighbor. That is,
hope’s vision of the good (and not the bad) is also that of the true and just,
and love’s enactment of this vison allows us to love others and ourselves in
a just manner: “there is no other love by which one loves himself but that by
which he loves God. For one who loves himself in another way should rather be said to hate himself. He, of course, becomes unjust and is deprived of
the light of justice when he turns away from the better and higher good”52.
Here again, in the connection between hope and love we see that hope’s vision of God is not wish-fulfillment that leads one to ignore the suffering of
others, but rather a vision engaged in the difficult work of aiding the unjust
and suffering. Even more, in this context Augustine defines the neighbor in
universal terms: our neighbors are not simply those with whom we share
a “blood relationship” but rather includes all who belong to the “rationis
societate”53. The mandate to love others includes all of humanity54.
illius finis beati vocantur, quo fine beati erunt: nam si in eisdem tormentis et atrocissimis doloribus semper essent, cum quibuslibet virtutibus eos esse miseros nulla sana ratio dubitaret”.
50
Augustine, Epistola 155, 4, 13, CSEL 44, 443, tr. R. Teske, Letters 100—155, p.
413: “Quamquam et in hac vita virtus non est, nisi diligere quod diligendum est: id eligere,
prudentia est: nullis inde averti molestiis, fortitudo est; nullis illecebris, temperantia est:
nulla superbia, iustitia est”.
51
Augustine, Epistola 155, 4, 14, CSEL 44, 444.
52
Augustine, Epistola 155, 4, 15, CSEL 44, 445, tr. R. Teske, Letters 100—155, p.
414: “nullam esse aliam dilectionem qua quisque diligit seipsum, nisi quod diligit Deum.
Qui enim aliter se diligit, potius se odisse dicendus est: fit quippe iniquus, privaturque luce
iustitiae, cum a potiore ac praestantiore bono aversus”.
53
Augustine, Epistola 155, 4, 14, CSEL 44, 444.
54
Building on Augustine’s reading the neighbor through the language of Matthew
25:40 – “the least of these” – Canning argues that Augustine extends the love we are
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
421
5. Perishing from Hope
Augustine opens Sermon 4, dated between 410-419, with a reference
to Romans 8:6 – to have a materialist understanding is death – and a caution against “fleshly (carnaliter) understandings” that oppose the Spirit
of truth55. He goes on to cite the trio of faith, hope, and love as the path
to avoid such error: “hoping for what we do not yet possess, believing
what we do not yet see, loving what we do not yet embrace”56. All three
are oriented toward the future, the unseen, and what is not possessed. But
they also position us within the present: “Let us go forward then, walking
in hope”57. Hope lives at the tension between present and future, standing against both the flight of fantasy from suffering and an idolatrous
reduction of virtue to the secular and material. This is how one ought
to approach a life of uncertainty and suffering, which Augustine reads
through the peregrinatio theme that is prevalent in this sermon – “in peregrinatione se vivere, patriam desiderare (living as travelers, desiring
their homeland)”58. Here, Augustine connects hope to baptism, returning
us to the liturgical role of hope in guiding the proper worship of God. He
maintains that baptism elevates one to the spiritual through the material,
taking the element of water to signify the spiritual forgiveness for sins
and the promise of eternal life, which gives sacramental voice to hope’s
calling to live now in patience for the future (unseen) divine promise.
This is not an avoidance strategy, as Augustine reflects on the fact that
Christians do not immediately receive the salvation promised in baptism,
but rather must live in hope amidst suffering while journeying as pilgrims
toward the homeland.
In Sermon 20, dated to around 419, Augustine turns to the question
of how Christians, having been baptized, should live in hope while surrounded by suffering and sin. He argues there are two basic dangers, one in
to give to our neighbor beyond impoverished Christians to the poor generally (minimi
mei). Similarly, O’Donovan contends that Augustine’s ethics universalize the ‘neighbor’. Canning, The Unity of Love for God and Neighbor, p. 383-394. O. O’Donovan, The
Problem of Self-Love in St. Augustine, Eugene 1980, p. 121-122.
55
Augustine, Sermo 4, 1, CCL 41, 20.
56
Augustine, Sermo 4, 1, CCL 41, 20, tr. E. Hill, Sermons, in: The Works of Saint
Augustine: A Translation for the 21st Century, New York 1992, p. 21: “sperans quod nondum tenet, credens quod nondum videt, amans cui nondum haeret”.
57
Augustine, Sermo 4, 1, CCL 41, 20, tr. E. Hill, Sermons, p. 21: “Intendat ergo
ambulans in spe”.
58
Augustine, Sermo 4, 9, CCL 41, 26.
Matthew Drever
422
a deficient and the other in an excessive kind of hope59. The former weighs
sin and suffering too strongly, the latter too lightly. The former is trapped
in the past, the latter in the future. To return to Rose’s epigraph, the former
is unable to “despair not” and the latter does not take seriously the need to
“keep your mind in hell”.
The first type of false hope Augustine argues is a deficient hope, or
a lack of hope. It leads to despair (desperatio) because one thinks there is
nothing that can be done about sin or a life filled with suffering. This causes
one to give into sin and embrace suffering in nihilistic fashion. Augustine
calls this the “gladiator mentality” and argues it breeds false courage that is
nothing more than a primitive hedonism of living for the moment because
one is unable to see beyond the immediacy of suffering and death60. This
puts on tragic and vivid display Augustine’s warning against “materialist
(carnaliter) understandings” that have reduced the transcendental good to
temporal goods, casting Romans 8:6 – to have a materialist understanding
is death – as a harbinger of spiritual and moral ruin. Against this, and tracking the transformation of virtue that occurs in hope, Augustine contrasts the
gladiator with the Christian martyr who also faces immanent death but lives
in hope and exhibits genuine courage: “this was the kind of confidence that
filled all the martyrs. Holding fast to right faith, not dying and suffering for
a false belief, a vain illusion, an empty hope or any uncertainty, but for the
promise made by Truth”61.
The second type of false hope Augustine details is an excessive hope
that cuts in two directions62. Excessive hope can lead one to expect that
the promise and pardon for sin means that heaven is at-hand and that there
will be no more suffering and temptation. Alternatively, excessive hope
can lead one to expect that God will easily and totally forgive sin whenever
one desires it. Hope makes sin light here; repentance is put off into the indefinite future. Both versions of excessive hope are false in their failure to
weigh properly sin and suffering. While they are a hope in the good and not
the bad, they are bad forms of hope – “male sperantes” – because they are
visions of a false good63. Augustine cautions that one can perish from such
59
Augustine, Sermo 20, 3-4, CCL 41, 264-267.
Augustine, Sermo 20, 3, CCL 41, 264-265.
61
Augustine, Sermo 4, 2, CCL 41, 21, tr. E. Hill, Sermons, p. 22: “Hac fiducia repleti omnes martyres, tenentes rectam fidem, non morientes nec patientes pro falsa fide, pro
vano phantasmate, pro spe inani, pro re incerta, sed pro veritatis pollicitatione”.
62
Augustine, Sermo 20, 4, CCL 41, 265-267.
63
Augustine, Sermo 20, 4, CCL 41, 265.
60
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
423
hope – “spe perit” – underscoring again that hope’s vison of the good and
not the bad does not reduce to psychological wish-fulfillment, but rather
opens one to the difficult road of reconciliation with the Good64.
6. Conclusion
Augustine may not give us a systematic account of hope, but he does
have much to say on the topic that he intended to help those suffering in his
own time and that can continue to offer us guidance today. Augustine develops nuanced stances on hope, using it to bridge the historical and eschatological without a reduction to either. Here, he draws on hope to maintain
a tension between temporal and eternal life, between the present reality of
suffering and the future hope of happiness. We can see also a close connection between hope and its compatriots of faith and love, a connection
Augustine utilizes to explore how hope epistemically and affectively transforms the moral and spiritual principles that guide our actions in the world.
Reading Augustine’s views on hope as superficially otherworldly, mistakenly reduces the historical-eschatological tension in such way that the hope
of eternal life eclipses and neglects the reality of temporal sufferings. This
misses the way Augustine treats hope as a bridge to the promise of eschatological happiness in a transformative manner that realigns and reevaluates
both spiritual practice and civic (public) virtue without reducing either to
a purely otherworldly end.
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
(summary)
This article examines the way Augustine draws on the theological virtue of hope to address
how people should live in times of suffering. Of the three theological virtues – faith, hope,
and love – hope is the least explored theme in contemporary Augustinian scholarship. This
article develops a framework for Augustine’s model of hope from his Enchiridion and
then applies it to select Sermons and Letters. Through this, we see that for Augustine hope
does not represent either an anesthetizing, otherworldly vision that neglects suffering or an
extreme ascetic embrace of suffering. Rather, hope seeks the transcendent good that acknowledges the profound depth of suffering while also maintaining a vision of happiness to
come. Here, Augustine draws on hope to maintain a tension between temporal and eternal
life, between the present reality of suffering and the future hope of happiness. We will also
64
Augustine, Sermo 20, 4, CCL 41, 264.
424
Matthew Drever
see a close connection between hope and its compatriots of faith and love, a connection
Augustine utilizes to explore how hope transforms the moral and spiritual principles that
guide our actions in the world.
Keywords: Augustine; Hope; Suffering; Theological Virtues; Sermons; Letters; Enchiridion
Bibliography
Augustine Through the Ages: An Encyclopedia, ed. A. Fitzgerald, Grand Rapids 1999.
Ballay L., Der Hoffnungsbegriff bei Augustinus, Munich 1964.
Barnes M.R., The Visible Christ and the Invisible Trinity: Mt. 5:8 in Augustine’s Trinitarian Theology of 400, “Modern Theology” 19/3 (2003) p. 329-355.
Billings D., Natality or Advent: Hannah Arendt and Jürgen Moltmann on Hope and
Politics, in: The Future of Hope: Christian Tradition amid Modernity and Postmodernity, ed. M. Volf – W. Katerberg, Grand Rapids 2004, p. 125-145.
Boros L., Aurelius Augustinus, Aufsteig zu Gott, Olten 1982.
Canning R., The Unity of Love for God and Neighbor in St. Augustine, Leuven 1993.
Dodaro R., Political and Theological Virtues in Augustine, Letter 155 to Macedonius,
“Augustiniana” 54 (2004) p. 431-474.
Drever M., Creation and Recreation, in: The Cambridge Companion to Augustine’s
Confessions, ed. T. Toom, Cambridge 2020, p. 75-91.
Drever M., De Genesi ad litteram 12: Paul and the Vision of God, in: Augustinus: De
Genesi ad litteram. Ein kooperativer Kommentar, ed. J. Brachtendorf – V.H. Drecoll, Augustinus – Werk und Wirkung 13, Paderborn 2021, p. 313-329.
Elliot D., Hope and Christian Ethics, Cambridge 2017.
Gwinn C. – Hellman C., Hope Rising: How the Science of Hope Can Change Your Life,
New York 2019.
Jackson M., Faith, Hope and Charity and Prayer in St. Augustine, “Studia Patristica”
22 (1989) p. 265-270.
Jameson J., Erotic Absence and Sacramental Hope: Rowan Williams on Augustinian
Desire, “Anglican Theological Review” 102/4 (2020) p. 575-595.
Kärkkäinen V.-M., Hope and Community, Grand Rapids 2017.
Kaufman P., Augustine, Martyrs, and Misery, “Church History” 63/1 (1994) p. 1-14.
Lamb M., Between Presumption and Despair: Augustine’s Hope for the Commonwealth,
“American Political Science Review” 112/4 (2018) p. 1036-1049.
Lloyd V.W., The Problem with Grace: Reconfiguring Political Theology, Stanford 2011.
Metcalfe J., Hoping Without a Future: Augustine’s Theological Virtues Beyond Melancholia, “Anglican Theological Review” 95/2 (2013) p. 235-250.
Mittleman A., Hope in a Democratic Age, Oxford 2009.
Moltmann J., Theology of Hope, Minneapolis 1993.
O’Donovan O., The Problem of Self-Love in St. Augustine, Eugene 1980.
Augustine on Hope in Times of Suffering
425
Pieper J., Faith, Hope, Love, San Francisco 1997.
Rose G., The Broken Middle: Out of Our Ancient Society, Blackwell 1992.
Rose G., Mourning Becomes the Law: Philosophy and Representation, Cambridge 1996.
Studor B., Augustine and the Pauline Theme of Hope, in: Paul and the Legacies of Paul,
ed. W. Babcock, University Park 1990, p. 201-225.
Studor B., Hope, in: Encyclopedia of Ancient Christianity, ed. A. Berardino, Downers
Grove 2014, p. 288-295.
TeSelle E., Augustine the Theologian, Eugene 2002.