Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political
Treatise
University of Otago
[email protected]
In his Political Treatise, Spinoza repeatedly compares states to human beings. In
this interpretation of the comparisons, I present a progressively more restrictive
account of Spinoza’s views about the nature of human beings in the Ethics and
show at each step how those views inform the account of states in the Political
Treatise. Because, like human beings, states are individuals, they strive to persevere
in existence. Because, like human beings, states are composed of parts that are
individuals, states’ parts also strive to persevere in being. Finally, because in states,
as in human beings, a change to the power of striving of a part can be at the same
time a change to the whole that differs in kind, strong states can be bad for their
citizens and states that serve their citizens well may nevertheless be weak. Spinoza’s
principal project in the Political Treatise is to design states that are stable and good
for their citizens. This account of the comparisons shows why that project is so
difficult: one cannot design a good state simply by designing a stable state.
1. Introduction
In his Political Treatise, Spinoza repeatedly compares states to human
beings. He writes, for example, that ‘like each citizen or like a man in the
state of nature, the greater reason for fear a state has, the less it is its own
master’ (TP 3.9); that ‘the rules and causes of fear and respect bind the
state by no reason other than that by which they bind a man in the state
of nature: so that he can rule himself and not be an enemy to himself, he
must take care not to kill himself’ (TP 4.5); and that ‘the best life is that
which a man or a state leads insofar as it is most its own ruler’ (TP 5.1).1
These comparisons promise needed insight into Spinoza’s understanding of the nature of states in the Political Treatise. Spinoza’s
stated purpose in the work is to show how, given the way human
beings actually are, states may remain stable (TP 1.6) and help people
1
I use the following abbreviations for references to Spinoza 1925: Ethics¼E followed by
conventional abbreviations for the apparatus; Political Treatise¼TP; Theological Political
Treatise¼TTP; Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect¼TIE. References include Chapter
or Section number and Gebhardt volume, page, and line where necessary. Translations of
Spinoza’s Latin are my own, frequently in consultation with Curley (Spinoza 2016).
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
doi:10.1093/mind/fzaa028 Advance Access publication 5 August 2020
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
Michael LeBuffe
810
Michael LeBuffe
2
Central issues include the relation of the God of the Ethics to the tenets of universal faith
that Spinoza presents in TTP 14 and the theory of contract as a basis for states, which is
explicit at TTP 16 but absent in the TP.
3
See, notably, TP 1.5, which makes several doctrines in the Ethics bases for arguments to
follow. Other prominent references include TP 2.1, 2.24, and 7.6.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
to live cooperatively and securely (TP 1.3). The Theological Political
Treatise, although of course a valuable source of insight into the
Political Treatise, has a different purpose, the defence of the freedom
to philosophize; moreover, the relation between its doctrines and
those of Spinoza’s other works is contentious.2 Neither work offers
a detailed account of the metaphysical status of the state. That leaves
the Ethics, among Spinoza’s mature works, as the source for understanding his views. Spinoza does rely upon the Ethics in the Political
Treatise, evidence that the latter builds upon the former.3 The Ethics,
however, offers only a sketchy account of states, the bulk of which
may be found in two scholia to E4p37. In contrast, Spinoza devotes
four of the five parts of the Ethics to the human being. The comparisons in the Political Treatise, then, explain the state in terms of the
finite thing that Spinoza describes in the greatest detail.
Here, I defend an interpretation of the comparisons. I present a
progressively more restrictive account of Spinoza’s views about the
nature of human beings in the Ethics and show at each step how those
views inform the account of states in the Political Treatise. I argue first
that Spinoza characterizes the human being as an individual and a
singular thing. All such things, Spinoza maintains, strive to persevere
in existence. The comparisons suggest, therefore, that the state does
also. Next, I describe a further property that Spinoza takes to be distinctive of human beings: we are composed of parts that are themselves individuals. Spinoza’s comparisons suggest that he takes this
also to be true of states. Attention to the association of individuality
and striving requires that we understand this view to mean, principally, that in human beings and states alike the whole strives to persevere in its existence but each part also strives to persevere in its
existence. Third, I argue that there is a property that, on the account
of the Ethics, distinguishes human beings even from some other highly
composite individuals. Changes that increase the power with which
parts of the human body strive can at the same time decrease the
power of the body as a whole, and changes that decrease the power
of parts of the human body can at the same time increase the power of
the body. Spinoza’s comparisons offer a metaphysical basis, then, for
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
811
2. Citizens and states as finite things
For Spinoza, to suggest that the state is like a human being is in the
first instance to say that it, like a human being, is a finite thing. To be
a finite thing, for Spinoza, is to strive to persevere in being. The
comparisons therefore suggest that states, like human beings, strive
to persevere in being.
Two technical terms in the Ethics, ‘singular thing’ and ‘individual’,
characterize finite things in causal and structural ways respectively.
Spinoza offers a definition of ‘singular things’ at the beginning of his
account of the human mind in Ethics 2:
By ‘singular things’ I understand things that have a finite and determinate existence. If many individuals concur in such a way in
one action that they are all together the cause of one effect, I consider them all to this extent a singular thing. (E2d7)
4
See Meinecke (1965); Matheron (1969, pp. 37-62); Garrett (1996, n. 42); Balibar (1998);
Blom (2007); and Steinberg (2019).
5
See Joachim (1901, p. 130); McShea (1968, pp. 129-136); Den Uyl (1983, pp. 68-80); Rice
(1990, pp. 271-286); Barbone (2002); Negri (2004, p. 45); and Campos (2010).
6
See Steinberg (2013, §5).
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
the conclusions that strong states may be bad for their citizens and
that states that serve their citizens well may nevertheless be fragile.
Scholarly attention to the comparisons has focused on the question
of realism. Some critics argue that in the comparisons Spinoza takes
states to be real individuals.4 Others defend antirealist positions on
which Spinoza’s language is merely figurative.5 One, Justin Steinberg,
finds that the question of realism does not matter greatly.6
In the conclusion, I address the implications of this interpretation
for the debate. I take Spinoza to be a realist in the disputed sense.
States really are finite things, on Spinoza’s account. They really strive
to persevere and have parts that strive to persevere. A state’s power to
persevere in being really correlates only imperfectly with the power to
persevere in any of its parts. These conclusions show why the debate
matters. To deny the reality of states is to underestimate the challenge
that Spinoza sets himself in trying to secure both the stability of states
and the good of citizens.
812
Michael LeBuffe
When some bodies, of the same or of different sizes, are so constrained
by others that they press upon one another, or if they move with the
same or different grades of speed so that they communicate their
motions to one another by a certain fixed ratio, we will say that those
bodies are united with one another and likewise that they all compose
one body or individual, which is distinguished from others through
this union of bodies. (Definition following E2p13 at G II/99-100)
The definition introduces two sufficient conditions on individuality:
(1) if bodies press upon one another or (2) if bodies communicate their
motions to one another by a certain fixed ratio, they compose one
individual. This is perhaps not a hard distinction, sorting all individuals
into one type or the other. Not being in motion with respect to one
another and in effect locking each other into this relation by pressing
against one another may be a basic way of having a certain fixed ratio. If
so, everything that satisfies the first condition also satisfies the second.
In any case, it is the language of the second condition—the language of
ratio—that appears frequently in subsequent arguments in the Ethics
and in Spinoza’s characterizations of human beings.
Propositions and other claims concerning striving to persevere in
being in Ethics 3 associate the causal language of E2d7 with the structural language of the definition of ‘individual’. At E3p6, Spinoza claims
that each thing, to the extent that it can, strives to persevere in being.
The demonstration, which begins, ‘For singular things are modes. . .’,
makes it clear that ‘each thing’ in the proposition refers to each singular
thing. So understood the proposition offers an account of what it is that
things cause insofar as they are singular things: their own perseverance.
The proposition that follows suggests that any singular thing’s striving
to persevere is its essence (E3p7), a characterization that Spinoza takes
to imply that all of the human mind’s effects are to be understood in
terms of this striving (E3p9). Where Spinoza offers an account of the
essence of a human body in the demonstration to E2p24, however, he
identifies the body’s certain fixed ratio as its essence: ‘The parts composing the human body pertain to the essence of the body itself only
insofar as they communicate their motions to one another in a certain
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
Here, Spinoza’s language is explicitly causal: insofar as individuals
collectively cause some effect, they are a singular thing.
The definition of ‘individual’, which may be found several pages
later in an interruption to the account of mind in Ethics 2 known as
the ‘physical discursus’, emphasizes structure:
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
813
7
E4p39 includes a similar passage.
8
How to understand relations among these concepts, and particularly between power and
essence, remains a subject of debate. Letter 64, to Tschirnhaus, E3p7, and E4p5 are central
passages. Recent discussions include LeBuffe (2009); Marshall (2013, pp. 58-103); and Hübner
(2017).
9
Bennett (1984, pp. 138-139) and Gueroult (1974, p. 165) argue that there is a distinction
between singular things and individuals. For arguments against a sharp distinction, see Curley
(1988, pp. 156-157); Garrett (1994); and Melamed (2013, pp. 74-79). Because ‘individual’ on
Spinoza’s definition clearly refers only to composite things, one might begin the task of
arguing against the material equivalence of the terms by noting that what Spinoza calls ‘simple
bodies’ may, on the basis of the first sentence of E2d7, be singular things but are not composite. Another salient difference is that E2d7 explicitly invokes an incremental notion, on
which causes are singular things to an extent, whereas the definition of ‘individual’ does not.
10
Campos (2010, pp. 16-23) argues that Spinoza could take the state to be a genuine thing
only at the cost of making any given ‘set of parts’ an individual. It is not clear that this is a
cost, however. The position, universalism or unrestricted composition, continues to have
prominent, sophisticated adherents (see, for example, Lewis 1986, pp. 212-213 or Sider 2001,
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
fixed ratio (see the definition [following E2p13])’.7 The ratio that makes
a human body an individual on the account of the definition of ‘individual’ is therefore also the causal power by which it strives by E3p6 and
in virtue of which it is to some extent a singular thing by E2d7.8
The account at E2p24 explicitly concerns human beings rather than
finite things more broadly. This need not matter a great deal in the
present context: the passages in the Political Treatise are comparisons of
the state not to a finite thing generically but to a human being. There is
nevertheless reason to take the argument of the last paragraph to have
broad implications that ought to matter to critics who take Spinoza to
deny individuality to states. Spinoza contends that much of what he
shows about human beings in the Ethics is perfectly general (E2p13cs,
E3Pref), and the propositions in question appear to depend upon no
views that characterize human beings narrowly. Because the account is
general, it suggests that ‘singular thing’ and ‘individual’ are materially
equivalent;9 that any finite cause is a finite thing; and that any finite
thing strives to persevere in being. Spinoza’s claim in the Political
Treatise that ‘man, like all other individuals, strives to the extent that
he can to preserve his being’ (TP 2.7) is evidence both that he continues
there to maintain material equivalence, because he uses ‘individuals’
where at E3p6’s demonstration he uses ‘singular things’, and also that
he continues to take all finite causes to strive to persevere in being,
because that is the doctrine of E3p6. These doctrines suggest, even setting the comparisons of the Political Treatise to one side, that Spinoza
takes states—and many, many more things—to be individuals.10
814
Michael LeBuffe
pp. 120-139). Recent interpretations of Spinoza’s accounts of finite things by Lord (2010, pp.
61-63), LeBuffe (2018, Chapter 1) and Newlands (2018, Chapter 6) do not rule out universalism; Melamed (2013, Chapter 2) explicitly attributes it to Spinoza.
11
Prominent uses of ‘stable’ (stabile) include TP 1.6, 5.7, 6.8, 6.39, and 7.1. Spinoza also uses
‘to last’ (permanere) to express this aim (TP 1.6, 7.25, 8.1).
12
See also E2p30, E2p45s, E3p8, and the end of E4Preface.
13
Spinoza’s views on the relation between human perseverance and life remain a subject of
critical debate. Notable contributions include Youpa (2003), Della Rocca (2010), and Nadler
(2016), which distinguish between perseverance in being and duration; Garrett (1990) and
LeBuffe (2017, pp. 112-119) find a close association. Central texts include E4p20s, on suicide;
and recommendations of honesty (E4p72) and loyalty (TTP 20, G III/241), which at least
appear to value them above life.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
Because Spinoza aims at stable states in the Political Treatise, the
relation between perseverance and duration is of particular interest
here.11 In the Ethics, Spinoza distinguishes between eternity and duration (E1d8Exp.); rejects a straightforward association of perseverance
and duration (E3p8); and identifies a greater power to persevere for
minds with a more robust existence in some eternal sense (E5pp2042). These positions show that he does not simply equate a greater
power to persevere with greater duration. The clearest expression of
this view is Spinoza’s conviction that, however great a finite thing’s
power may become, there will always be more powerful forces external
to it (E4pp3-5).12
Spinoza nevertheless maintains that the power a body possesses is a
power to resist the destructive influence of external forces and so to
preserve the fixed ratio of motion among its parts that characterizes it.
This position suggests that more powerful bodies tend to endure
longer than less powerful ones. Evidence that Spinoza accepts this
implication may be found in both the Ethics and, as we have seen,
the Political Treatise (TP 4.5), where he opposes the striving to persevere and death. At the scholium to E4p18, for example, he writes
that ‘reason demands that everyone. . .strive to preserve his own
being’. Then he argues that it follows from this account of striving
that those who kill themselves are weak and overcome by external
causes. Similarly he maintains that if, per impossibile, human beings
were not vulnerable to external forces, we would ‘not die’ (non posset
perire) and ‘always exist’ (semper existere).13
Further evidence may be found in Spinoza’s accounts of bodies’
complexity, capability, and power. His accounts of complex bodies
(E2pp13-14), some of which I discuss below in §3, suggest that more
complex bodies persist through more changes in their parts. For
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
815
14
Recent accounts of consciousness in Spinoza (Garrett 2008; Nadler 2008; LeBuffe 2010b)
emphasize the relation between complexity and power.
15
For the association of power and right, see E4p37s1; TTP 16, G III/189-190; and TP 2.3-2.4.
16
Other relevant passages include TP 2.13-17, 3.6, and 3.11-12. See also TTP 16, G III/193-194
and, what may be its basis, TTP 3, G III/47. Garrett (2010) and Grey (forthcoming) inform my
account of right. Barbone (2002, p. 106), who nevertheless differs, informs my account of TP
3.2.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
example, he argues that the most complex body, the whole of nature,
persists through all changes (E2p13L7s). Spinoza argues in Ethics 4 that
such complexity makes bodies more capable (E4p38). There he also
argues that more capability is good (E4p39), an indication that an
increase in capability is an increase in power. Spinoza’s association of
more capable bodies with minds that have a more robust eternal
existence (5p39) suggests a similar conclusion.14 Spinoza therefore
associates complexity and the ability that it gives bodies to persist
through change—that is, to endure—with capability and the power
to persevere.
Because human beings are individuals, Spinoza’s comparisons of
states to human beings in the Political Treatise suggest, then, that
states are also individuals. The state therefore strives for its own perseverance in being. Perseverance is certainly something more than
duration. States that strive with more power tend to endure longer,
however, and Spinoza’s effort to produce stable states emphasizes this
aspect of power.
Other features of the text support this interpretation. Spinoza frequently mentions the power of the state or, what he takes to extend as
far as power extends, its right.15 He uses both terms, for example, in
his comparison of the state to a human being at TP 3.2: ‘[J]ust as each
person [unusquisque] in the state of nature, so also the body and mind
of the whole state [imperii] has as much right as it has power’.16 As we
have seen, anything’s power just is a power to persevere, so passages
like this one suggest that a state strives to persevere.
A few passages suggest this conclusion more explicitly. At TP 4.5,
recall, Spinoza argues that states are bound by the laws of nature, just
as individual human beings are, not to kill themselves. This suggests
that states strive to persevere in being and that more powerful states
tend to last longer. In the same passage, Spinoza goes on to argue that
the state is bound by natural law ‘to hold nothing to be good or evil
unless it has judged it to be good or evil for itself’, a passage that
echoes his account at TP 2.18 of the way natural law binds individual
816
Michael LeBuffe
Because the best way of living, to preserve oneself as much as possible, is founded upon the prescription of reason, it follows therefore that the best life is that which a man or a state leads insofar as
it is most its own ruler . . . I say that it is one thing to defend
oneself, preserve oneself, and judge for oneself by right and that
it is another thing [to do these] in the best way. (TP 5.1)18
Like human beings, states should preserve themselves, and they
should do so in the best way.
Finally, Spinoza refers to the state’s health and associates it closely
with preservation. He argues at TP 10.1, for example, that because
dictators’ authority is not usually stable, ‘the health and preservation
of the republic’ in a dictatorship will usually be uncertain.19 The instability of dictatorships makes them weak. They will not necessarily
fall as a consequence, just as strong individuals do not necessarily
endure. Their weakness, however, does make them more vulnerable
to existential threats.
In the Political Treatise, then, Spinoza treats states as finite things.
That is, a state is a singular thing with its own effects and an individual with its own structure. Spinoza’s account of the effects that any
singular thing has at E3pp6-9 suggests, moreover, that the activity of a
state, like that of a human being, is that which, if unimpeded,
17
For Spinoza’s theory of the good, see E3p9s, E3p39s, E4Pref, E4d1-d2, and E4p8. How
precisely Spinoza associates perseverance and the good is a matter of on-going debate. Recent
discussions include LeBuffe (2010, pp. 160-174); Della Rocca (2010), which emphasizes politics;
Kisner (2011, pp. 87-111); and Youpa (2020, Chapter 3).
18
Spinoza suggests here that states judge for themselves (sese judicium ferre), a central issue
for a prominent recent discussion of the individuality of states (List and Pettit 2006). Spinoza
tends to write, however, about the highest authority’s judgment (TP 6.2, 7.30, 10.1). Sharp
(2011) and Tucker (2019) are recent works on Spinoza’s importance for political theory today.
19
See also TP 1.6, 3.14, and 8.48.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
human beings. Spinoza’s understanding and use of value terms
remains a subject of critical debate. However, he certainly associates
a human being’s judgment that something is good, in some way, with
what increases that person’s power to persevere.17 A state’s judgment
that something is good, then, reflects its nature in a similar way.
In building toward another of the comparisons, Spinoza argues that
reason prescribes self-preservation to a state just as it does to a human
being and that there is a best way for a state to live just as there is a
best way for a human being to live:
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
817
preserves it. The project of the Political Treatise, in part, is to design
stable states. These points suggest that one way to do so is to build
powerful states that will tend to strive successfully.
On a second, more restrictive understanding of what Spinoza takes a
human being to be, to suggest that the state is like a human being is to
suggest that the state is an individual composed of individuals. As in
§1, the most important implications of this view concern striving. Any
individual, for Spinoza, strives to persevere in being. To attribute this
structure to the state, then, is to suggest that, while the state strives to
persevere in its being, each of its citizens also strives to persevere in
being. Although states and their citizens are interdependent, their
striving, power, and perseverance differ.
Spinoza’s foundational account of the structure of the human body,
in a postulate of the physical discursus, emphasizes the point that it is
composed of individuals: ‘E2p13P1: The human body is composed of
many individuals diverse in nature, each of which is highly composite’. Supposing a hand to be a part of the body, Spinoza’s characterizations of individuals together with this postulate suggest that the
hand strives to persevere in its being.20 Like other composite individuals, moreover, changes to the hand can be changes in its striving,
which can be more or less powerful.
Spinoza recognizes these points in the Ethics, where his accounts of
the human affects incorporate them. Spinoza introduces the claim
that the human body’s power can change in a postulate at the beginning of Ethics 3. At Ep11, he argues that changes to the body’s power
are also changes to the mind’s power. In the demonstration, he identifies these changes with changes in the perfection of mind and body.21
Then, in a scholium, he introduces the human affects:
By ‘joy’ [laetitia], therefore, I shall understand in what follows a
passion by which a mind passes to greater perfection. By ‘sadness’
[tristitia], however, a passion by which it passes to lesser perfection.
From this point, I shall call the affect of joy, when it is related to
20
Here I follow the example in Aristotle’s Politics (1253a). James (2012, p. 244) notes the
importance of this discussion to Spinoza. Letter 32, to Oldenburg, suggests that Spinoza would
agree that hands are parts of the body.
21
See also the General Definition of the Affects following E3.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
3. Citizens and states as individuals composed of individuals
818
Michael LeBuffe
Joy has two basic forms: an increase in power to the whole of a
person’s body, which is cheerfulness, and an increase in power to
one part of a person’s body more than the others, which is pleasure.
Similarly, sadness can relate to the whole body (melancholy) or to one
part of it more than the others (pain). Pleasure and pain and their
forms, on this account, are changes primarily in the power of parts of
the body. Again, supposing that a hand is a part of a body, an increase
in the hand’s power is pleasure (rather than cheerfulness) for the
whole, and a decrease in the hand’s power is pain.
As he does at E3p11s, Spinoza tends to emphasize mind in his
accounts of the affects.22 There is nevertheless a strand of argument
building on this proposition that indicates the importance of pleasure
and pain to his psychology. At E4p60, Spinoza argues that in desires
arising from these passions we have no regard for the advantage of the
whole. Then, in a scholium, he writes that most human desire is like
this: ‘Because, then, most joy is related to one part of the body, we
therefore mostly desire to preserve ourselves with no consideration of
our health as a whole’ (E4p60s).23
A strong view of biological unity might be one on which the nature
of the whole saturates it, excluding any independent nature in its
parts. On such a view, there is no sense in saying that something
makes my hand more or less powerful unless perhaps this is a way
of referring indirectly to what makes me so. Likewise, if the state were
such a unity, there would be no sense in saying that something makes
a citizen more or less powerful unless perhaps doing so were a way of
referring to what makes the state so.24 Spinoza’s account of the human
body and subsequent account of the passions rule out such a view of
the biological unity of the human being. My parts are individuals, so
22
See the end of E3p59s or E3App.3Exp.
23
The doctrine of E3p11s associates with these passages by way of Ep43 (see §3 here), Ep44,
Ep44s, and E4p60.
24
This worry seems to push Barbone (2002, p. 107; cf. Berlin 2002, p. 193) to take Spinoza
to deny genuine individuality to states. Steinberg (2019, §2) offers an effective response.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
mind and body at once, ‘pleasure’ [titillatio] or ‘cheerfulness’
[hilaritas]; that of sadness, however, ‘pain’ [dolor] or ‘melancholy’
[melancholia]. But, it should be noted, pleasure and pain are
ascribed to a man when one part of him is affected more than
the others, but cheerfulness and melancholy when all parts are
equally affected. (E3p11s)
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
819
As far as politics is concerned, the difference you ask about, between Hobbes and me, is this: I always preserve natural right unimpaired, and I maintain that in each state the supreme magistrate
has no more right over its subjects than it has greater power over
them. (Letter 50, Spinoza 2016, vol. 2, p. 406)25
Certainly, on Spinoza’s view, human beings arrange their power in
different ways in different states, and a group of human beings entering a state for the first time would gather the powers of each together,
at least for certain purposes, in contributing to the great power of this
new entity. In distinguishing himself here from Hobbes (who nevertheless conceives of natural right in a different way), Spinoza emphasizes the point, however, that the organization of individual human
beings’ powers in a state is not any kind of intrinsic change to the
individuals’ powers.26
Spinoza’s accounts of individuals and states in the Political Treatise
retain the notions of right and power that distinguish Spinoza from
Hobbes in Letter 50.27 Any individual’s right, by nature, is a function
of its power: ‘[E]ach natural thing has as much right by nature as it
25
This is Curley’s translation of Spinoza’s Dutch, lightly edited.
26
Garrett (2010, p. 205) informs my interpretation of Letter 50.
27
Some closely related views do change over Spinoza’s different works. An earlier explicit
theory of contract (TTP, Chapter 16) is not present in the Political Treatise. Grey (forthcoming) points out that in an earlier account, the association of individual right and power derives
from the power of the whole of nature (TTP 16, G III/189), whereas in the TP, drawing
probably upon the demonstration to E3p6, Spinoza derives the association from the power
of God (TP 2.3).
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
they have their own striving and power, which can be characterized
independently of my own.
Comparisons of the state to a human being in the Political Treatise
suggest that the state is similar: it strives and has power, and each
person who lives in the state also strives and has power. Spinoza’s
commitment to this view is evident in his accounts of right. We have
seen that right is a function of power and that for a thing to have
power, it must strive and be an individual. To give up one’s right in
belonging to a state, then, would, for Spinoza, be to give up one’s
own power and individuality. Spinoza, however, forcefully maintains
that citizens do not give up their right in belonging to a state. A letter
to Jarig Jelles, in which he distinguishes between his view and
Hobbes’s, is clear:
820
Michael LeBuffe
4. Citizens and states as highly complex individuals
This section offers a still more restrictive characterization of the
human being: on Spinoza’s account, the human being differs even
from other individuals that are composed of individuals in virtue of
its high degree of complexity. In the human being, but not in some
less complex individuals, a change to the individuals that compose the
whole can be at the same time a change to the whole that differs in
kind. If my hand is a part of me, for example, an increase in the power
of my hand might be at the same time a decrease in my own power.
28
In addition to Aristotle, cited above, Machiavelli and Hobbes were important sources for
Spinoza. Spinoza refers to Machiavelli’s comparison of the state to a human being explicitly at
TP 10.1. See Machiavelli (1996 III.1). Spinoza owned and clearly read carefully Hobbes’s de Cive
(1983 5.9-10). He may also have been familiar with Leviathan (see Malcolm 2002, p. 47).
Compare TP 3.11-13 to de Cive 10.17 or Leviathan (Hobbes 2012 vol. 2, p. 196, ll. 1-9).
29
Balibar (1998, pp. 64-72) emphasizes correctly that the state for Spinoza is an individual
of individuals. This characteristic, however, does not distinguish states from their own citizens.
30
By ‘natural individual’, which might have a pragmatic sense in other contexts for
Hobbes, I mean one that strives to preserve itself. Hobbes reserves striving, so understood,
to animals where Spinoza does not. See de Corpore 25.12 (Hobbes 1839-1845 1.332). James (1997,
Chapter 6) offers a useful comparison of striving in Hobbes and Spinoza.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
has power to exist and work’ (TP 2.3; cf. TTP 16, G III/189). Any two
individuals might have more right, just as they have more power, by
cooperating in bringing about some effect (TP 2.13). Therefore, a great
number of individuals cooperating in a state, which Spinoza calls ‘the
multitude’, have a great right and a great power (TP 2.17). The multitude’s power and its use by the state, however, is a function of individuals’ on-going, contingent cooperation.
The point that the state is an individual composed of individuals is
familiar in Hobbes, whose views Spinoza clearly considered, and in
the history of philosophy generally.28 However, Spinoza’s comparison
of the human being and the state is, in this respect, closer than the
analogy in Hobbes. Spinoza’s comparison emphasizes the point that
the state and the human being share this particular kind of composition: from the facts that the human being is an individual composed
of individuals and that the state is like the human being, we learn that
the state is an individual composed of individuals.29 Hobbes makes
the state an artificial man, and one sense in which for Hobbes the
artificial man differs from the natural is that an artificial man has,
where a natural man does not, natural individuals for parts.30
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
821
To this point, we have considered an individual that is composed
only of bodies that are distinguished from one another by motion
and rest, speed and slowness, that is, that are composed only of the
simplest bodies. But if we now consider a different individual
[aliud], composed of many individuals diverse in nature, we will
discover that it can be affected in many other ways with its nature
nevertheless preserved (E2p13L7S)
In this scholium, Spinoza introduces a new kind of individual, different from what he has discussed so far. He describes the difference first
in structural terms. A complex individual is not composed only of the
simplest bodies. Instead it is composed of ‘many individuals diverse in
nature’, a phrase that, as we have seen, recurs in the discursus’ account
of the human body. Spinoza goes on to assert that such individuals
can survive kinds of change beyond those described in the lemmata.
The scholium does not describe these changes. Because, however,
Spinoza does introduce a paradigm of such an individual, the human
body (E2p13P1), we may look to subsequent arguments in the Ethics
31
Majores minorsve is difficult to translate. In letter 39, to Jelles, the only other occurrence
in Spinoza’s works, it means simply ‘bigger or smaller’ (G IV/193). Spinoza’s application of L5
at E3Post.1 may suggest that the phrase there means ‘more or less powerful’.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
Likewise, a decrease in my hand’s power may be an increase in my
own. To say that the state is like a human being is, once again, to say
something similar about the state. Notably (for Spinoza might conceive of the state as having parts greater or smaller than its citizens),
the power of citizens and that of the state may diverge on Spinoza’s
account. We want our states to secure our own good, that is, to make
us more powerful. Spinoza’s comparisons of the state to the human
being warn us that we cannot secure that end simply by making the
state more powerful.
Spinoza distinguishes between particularly complex individuals,
such as the human being, and others by referring to persistence conditions. Four lemmata (LL4-7) in the physical discursus describe persistence conditions for any individual. Any individual persists without
any change to its form (absque ulla formae mutatione) through some
replacements of parts (L4); some changes in which its parts become
greater or lesser (majores minoresve) (L5)31; some changes to the
motions of its parts (L6); and some motions of the whole (L7). At
the end of the lemmata, Spinoza proceeds to refer to changes that
more complex individuals only might survive:
822
Michael LeBuffe
E4p43: Pleasure can be excessive and bad; pain, however, can be
good to the extent that pleasure, or joy, is bad.
Dem.: Pleasure is joy, which, insofar as it is relates to a body,
consists in this: one or some of its parts are affected more than
others (see 3p11s). The power of this affect can be so great that it
exceeds other actions of the body (4p6); sticks stubbornly to it; and
so renders the body less able to be affected in many other ways.
Therefore it can be bad. . . [A similar argument concludes that pain
can be good if it counteracts a bad pleasure.]
On this view, parts of the body can gain power in such a way that the
body as a whole loses power and can lose power in such a way that the
body as a whole gains power. For example, an immoderate devotion to
sit-ups might strengthen my abdominals in a way that harms my posture
and so my overall strength. Likewise, in such a predicament, neglecting
and so weakening my abdominals might improve my overall strength.33
Spinoza does not describe changes of this sort in his account of the
persistence conditions for individuals generally at LL4-7, nor does he
refer to the lemmata in the demonstration to E4p43. He leaves the
claim that there are such changes without detailed explanation.
Nevertheless, as we have seen in the scholium following Lemma 7,
Spinoza maintains that there are changes that complex individuals but
not other individuals can survive but that are not described in the
32
As Peterman (2017, p. 116) notes, L4 and L6 suggest that the human body can also survive
changes which do not change its power.
33
Spinoza himself does not offer an example that names particular parts of the body.
Instead he refers to different corporeal pleasures and simply asserts that each relates to one
part of the body more than others (E4p44s, E4p45s). Because, as we have seen, most of our
desires arise from such affects, Spinoza recommends that we please ourselves in many different
ways in moderation, so that the body’s ‘many parts of diverse natures’ flourish equally
(E4p45s). In effect, he recommends a diversified exercise regimen.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
for accounts of the sorts of changes that a human being can survive
but which LL 4-7 do not describe. The best candidate for the sort of
change the survival of which marks the great complexity of the human
body is a change to the power of its parts that is not reflected in the
same change to the power of the whole. We have already seen that the
human being can undergo changes in power and that some of these—
pleasure and pain—are changes principally to some parts.32 Later in
the Ethics, Spinoza offers more detail, arguing that such changes need
not even be the same kind of change to the whole:
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
823
But if we conceive of yet a third kind of individual composed of
[individuals of the second kind], we will discover that it can be
affected in many other ways without any change to its form [absque
ulla ejus formae mutatione]. And if we go in this way to infinite, we
can easily conceive the whole of nature to be one individual whose
parts—that is, all bodies—vary in infinite ways without any change
to the whole individual. (E2p13L7S)
On the supposition that the state is still more complex than the human
being, we might conclude that in virtue of this complexity it is closer to
the whole of nature than a human being. So understood, the state will
have still further persistence conditions than a human being.
Spinoza’s accounts of right, on which, as we have seen in §2, natural
human beings who combine their rights create a more powerful thing
(TP 2.13, 2.17), may support this interpretation. Given the correlation
between complexity and power, the greater complexity of the combination may, at least in part, explain its greater power. Nevertheless it
is difficult to support a general version of the conclusion. Although
the whole of nature presumably does incorporate all of the complexity
of its parts, the incrementalism of Spinoza’s accounts of singular
things suggests that finite things frequently do not.34 A pyramid built
of philosophers, for example, would not fully incorporate the
34
As I read E2p13L7s, Spinoza maintains that any given individual, I2, more complex than
another, I1, will be more complex in virtue of its structure, and that one way of conceiving of
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
lemmata. It is therefore plausible to conclude that the human being’s
persistence through these sorts of changes distinguishes it from many
other, simpler individuals.
Highly complex individuals, then, have parts that are themselves
highly composite individuals of different natures and, presumably in
virtue of this complexity, survive some changes that other kinds of
individuals do not. This capacity in the human body shows itself when
it persists through a change to the power of some of its parts that is at
the same time a change to the power of the whole that differs in kind.
A specific way of understanding Spinoza’s comparison of states to
human beings is to take him to suggest that states are similar: what
makes a citizen more powerful can weaken the state and what weakens
a citizen can make the state more powerful.
One might be tempted, on the basis of the rest of the scholium to
Lemma 7, to argue that the state can survive an even greater variety of
changes than a human being:
824
Michael LeBuffe
such an individual is to conceive of I2 as composed of I1 and similar individuals in such a way
as to incorporate all of their complexity.
35
Because states may integrate their citizens incompletely, some properties of citizens may
not belong to the state at all. Della Rocca (2008, p. 117) makes a similar point about the
human body. Letter 32 to Oldenburg, E2d7 (see §1 here), and E2p24 are central texts.
36
Barbone and Rice (Spinoza 2000, pp. 26-27) argue that Spinoza cannot be a realist
because he takes citizens, not external forces, to be the greatest threat to states (TP 6.6).
The imperfect integration of states suggests that this is a false dichotomy. A citizen can at
once be part of a state and also an external force acting on the state. The case of suicide in a
natural human being is similar, as Steinberg (2013 §5) notes.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
complexity of its components into its structure; mannequins might
serve just as well. Spinoza’s scholium rules out neither an account of
states on which they are more complex nor one on which they are, like
the human pyramid, less complex than their human parts.35 It leaves
the complexity of nearly all finite things unspecified. Spinoza’s comparisons of the state to the human being in the Political Treatise are
particularly valuable, then, because they do offer a specific account of
the complexity of the state: among the whole range of complex individuals introduced by the scholium following Lemma 7, the state is
like a human being.36
At this finest level of detail that Spinoza’s accounts of things and their
parts offer, the comparisons of the Political Treatise suggest that in
states, as in individual human beings, changes in parts may differ in
kind from changes in the whole. In the best circumstances, for both the
human being and the state, what serves the whole also serves its parts. To
be characterized by ideas of reason, for an individual human being, is to
have joy as a characteristic affect (E3p58). Joy, as we have seen, is an affect
in which all of the body’s parts are affected equally: the power of the
parts and those of the whole correlate closely. To the extent that a state is
founded on reason, the dynamic is the same: each citizen becomes more
powerful in acting freely from reason, and the state as a whole is more
powerful as a result of the coordination and cooperation of powerful
citizens. As we have seen, several of the comparisons in the Political
Treatise emphasize the point that individual human beings and states
are alike in this respect (TP 3.7, TP 5.1). Spinoza maintains that the most
powerful states, like the most powerful people, are led by reason.
Spinoza also maintains, however, that consistently acting from reason is rare for individuals and that having citizens who act wholly
from reason is an unreachable ideal for societies. In the introduction
to the Political Treatise, he criticizes philosophers for conceiving of
societies ideally, in ways that are possible only in the ‘poets’ golden
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
825
age’. Later, he characterizes this mistake as one in which we attribute
too great a role to reason:
Spinoza’s practical approach to politics emphasizes the imperfect nature of actual citizens and actual states. It is an attempt to design states
that can be better for their citizens and more stable even if the ideal
state is out of reach.37 The stability and strength of even imperfect
states, as Spinoza presents it, is typically a great good to citizens,
which they should promote and in which they should tolerate some
irrationality (E4p40; TTP 16, G III/194; TP 3.6). In actual states, however, Spinoza’s theory of complex individuals suggests that what promotes the stability of the state and what serves the citizen can
sometimes conflict. Institutions that help citizens to become more
powerful may present hazards for the state and those that weaken
citizens can make the state more powerful. In attempting to secure
both ends, Spinoza may have to accept some instability in order to
have institutions that promote the power of citizens and some compromise of free institutions in order to promote stability.38
Here, however, a salient difference between societies and human
beings arises not from Spinoza’s metaphysics but from his priorities.
What Spinoza values, ultimately, is the good of human beings.39 In the
37
Spinoza frequently refers to groups of people being led as if by one mind (TP 2.16, 2.21,
3.2, 3.5, 3.7, 4.1, 6.1, 8.6, and 8.19). The qualification ‘as if’ is sometimes cited as evidence for
the view that states are not real things (Rice 1990, pp. 274-275; Barbone 2002 §8). This is a
distraction, I think. To act as if from one mind, as TP 6.1 indicates most clearly, is to act on a
common passion—such as fear or, better, hope—in a way that approaches the coordination
that reason would bring. Action truly from one mind, so understood, would be action wholly
from reason. In this sense, a conflicted person can, like a group, be of two minds.
38
Chapters 19 and 20 of the TTP concern Spinoza’s views about such institutions in a
republic.
39
Critics note that Spinoza’s anthropocentrism in ethics is striking given his emphasis on
the eternal perspective (Moore 2017, pp. 51-53) or, similarly, his commitment to treating
human beings like all other natural things (LeBuffe 2010, pp. 162-166). The choice to focus
on the human good certainly reflects Spinoza’s over-arching project, which is to promote
human welfare (E2Pref; TIE §14; TP 1.3, 5.2). It may also have a basis in the ordinary use
of value terms (E3p9, E3p39s), which serves as a basis for Spinoza’s formal theory of value in
Ethics 4.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
We have shown that reason can do a great deal to restrain and
moderate affects but we have seen also that this path which reason
shows us is arduous. People who persuade themselves, then, that a
multitude. . .can be led to live from the prescriptions of reason
alone dream of the poets’ golden age. (TP 5.1; cf. E4p37s2)
826
Michael LeBuffe
No empire has stood for so long without notable change [absque ulla
notabili mutatione stetit] as that of the Turks, and, on the other hand,
none has been less enduring than popular or democratic states.
Nowhere else have so many rebellions arisen. But if slavery [servitium], barbarity and solitude are to be called peace, nothing is more
miserable for men than peace. (TP 6.4)
In its fourth century and at its greatest extent at the time of the
composition of the Political Treatise, the Ottoman Empire was the
clearest example available to Spinoza of a state that endures.40
Spinoza’s account of the persistence of the Ottoman Empire— absque
ulla notabili mutatione stetit— resembles, moreover, his descriptions
of the persistence of composite individuals repeated in Lemmata 4-6
as well as Lemma 7 scholium: ‘absque ulla formae mutatione’. Its duration suggests that, among actual states, it is particularly strong. What
is notable about this individual, however, is that its strength is not
reflected in the strength of the people who live in it. ‘Servitus’ is
Spinoza’s preferred label for human weakness. The implication is
40
Gundogdu (2017) argues that the empire lost significant territory in a series of defeats
beginning in 1683. Perhaps the decline began less than a decade after Spinoza took the empire
to be a paradigm of endurance.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
case of a human being a given affect or desire, even if it is passive, is
better or worse than others to the extent that it makes the whole more
or less powerful. The parts of the human being matter only to the
extent that they contribute to the good of the whole. Because of
Spinoza’s emphasis on human good, the converse is true of human
societies. Spinoza values the strength of the whole state only instrumentally to the extent that it serves those who live in it. His metaphysics of complex individuals shows that this value does not arise as
a matter of course. To the extent that what makes a state powerful
harms citizens, Spinoza will consider it to be bad. The basis for
choosing among the different compromises that we might reach in
actual states will be the good of the human beings that compose
them.
In Chapter 6, Spinoza refers both to a strong state that harms its
citizens and therefore is bad and also to states that serve their citizens
well, and so are good, but that are also weak. Here, the contrast between the state’s power and that of its citizens is stark:
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
827
41
The Ottoman Empire is Spinoza’s preferred example of a state that is brutal and bad for
its people. See also TTP Preface (G III/7) and the account of monarchy in the TP (7.23). The
choice of example may follow Machiavelli, whom Spinoza cites in his discussion of slave states
in TP 5. Machiavelli (1857, Chapter 4) characterizes the same state (though more than a
century earlier) in cognate terms (turco, servi).
42
See TP 7.5, 8.12; TTP 16, G III/193-194, 20, G III/239, 245. Steinberg (2018, pp. 163-189)
rightly emphasizes in Spinoza a preference not only for democracy but also for the democratisation of monarchy and aristocracy.
43
A good state emphasizes security (securitas) for Spinoza (TTP 20, G III/240-241; TP 1.6,
5.2). Beyond physical security, this is a confident expectation of the good that develops from
hope (E3def.aff. 14). This is a theme of Steinberg (2018, pp. 80-100), which draws my attention
to these passages.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
that the Ottoman Empire is strong in spite of—even because of—the
weakness of its people.41
Just as what is pleasant may weaken the body, Spinoza’s account of
democracies in this passage suggests, states that are good for their
citizens may nevertheless be weak. Spinoza consistently maintains
that democracies are the best states for peace, harmony, and meaningful freedom.42 That is, they are best for those who live in them.
Strong citizens, however, do not necessarily make states strong, and,
where he warns readers about an instance of a strong slave state,
Spinoza also warns of instances of the weakness of free states, which
are susceptible to rebellion. In other passages, he argues that such
states are susceptible to war (TP 7.5) and to degradation into less
and less democratic forms of government (TP 8.12).
In the case of states that are strong at the expense of their citizens,
the contingent value of state power is particularly clear. On Spinoza’s
account, security, or a confident hope of a good life, depends upon
both political stability and good institutions.43 More powerful states
will tend to endure longer. States that are powerful, then, are good if
they also serve their citizens by having good institutions. Perhaps the
Dutch Republic is an example of such a state for Spinoza (TP 8.4; cf.
TTP 20, G III/246). The example of the Ottoman Empire shows,
however, that power in a state is not necessarily good. Spinoza makes
this point in general terms at TP 5. He argues that states acquired by
war, and with slaves rather than subjects, can endure by means that
differ from those that sustain a free commonwealth. In such states
power is instrumental not to the good but to the enduring misery of
people who live in them. Spinoza does not value power in this kind of
case: it contributes nothing to genuine peace or harmony (for these
828
Michael LeBuffe
see TP6.4) or, therefore, security. That is why he contends that such a
state is better called a wasteland than a commonwealth (TP 5.4).
Justin Steinberg concludes his summary of the debate over the meaning of Spinoza’s comparisons with a shrug:
[T]he collectivist can embrace the normative primacy of the individual human being. If this is allowed, the matter of whether the
state is a literal or merely metaphorical individual seems to matter
far less than many scholars have supposed. (Steinberg 2013, §5)
This is an appropriate response to some antirealists. Antirealists tend
to think that the debate matters because they find in Spinoza a view
on which, if human beings were to be parts of a genuine individual,
they would lose their own interests and individuality.44 As §2 shows,
however, Spinoza’s difficult metaphysics of individuals and their parts
suggests that a real individual with a genuine interest can have parts
that are also real individuals with genuine interests. Indeed, he makes
the defining feature of the human body composition from other
individuals. Therefore, the conclusion that individual human beings
do not matter—which would indeed be at odds with Spinoza’s explicit, enduring commitment to the good of all in society—does not
follow from realism. As Steinberg suggests, the concern is not wellfounded.
Here I have taken Spinoza to be a realist. Spinoza’s permissive
ontology of finite things makes states genuine finite things. His comparisons of states to human beings reaffirms that point: even critics
who find a less permissive ontology in Spinoza should agree that, for
Spinoza, human beings are things. The comparisons therefore reaffirm that states are things, and they also show us what kind of things
states are.
This realist interpretation suggests a different account—now from
the perspective of the realist—of the importance of the debate. The
complex nature of states shows how they can be strong even as they
fail their citizens and can be weak even as they serve their citizens. It
shows how a state can become more powerful in ways that harm its
44
See Barbone (2002, p. 107) and Berlin (2002, p. 193).
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
5. Conclusion: Spinoza’s realism and the importance of the
debate
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
829
References
Aristotle 1984, The Complete Works of Aristotle, translated by Barnes
Jonathan (Princeton: Princeton University Press)
Balibar, Etienne 1998, Spinoza and Politics, translated by Peter
Snowdon (London: Verso)
Barbone, Steven 2002, ‘What Counts as an Individual for Spinoza?’
in Spinoza: Metaphysical Themes, edited by Olli Koistinen and
John Biro (New York: Oxford University Press)
Bennett, Jonathan 1984, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics (Indianapolis:
Hackett)
Berlin, Isaiah 2002, Liberty (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
Blom, Hans 2007, ‘Spinoza on Res Publica, Republics and
Monarchies’, in Monarchisms in the Age of Enlightenment:
Liberty, Patriotism, and the Public Good, edited by Hans Blom,
John Christian Laursen, and Luisa Simonutti (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press)
Campos, Andre Santos 2010, ‘The Individuality of the State in Spinoza’s
Political Philosophy’, in Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 92
Curley, Edwin 1988, Behind the Geometrical Method (Princeton:
Princeton University Press)
Della Rocca, Michael 2008, Spinoza (New York: Routledge)
—— 2010, ‘Getting his hands dirty: Spinoza’s criticism of the rebel’,
in Spinoza’s Theological-Political Treatise: A Critical Guide, edited
by Yitzhak Melamed and Michael Rosenthal
Den Uyl, Douglas 1983, Power, State, and Freedom: an Interpretation
of Spinoza’s Political Philosophy (Assen: Van Gorcum)
45
Many thanks to audiences at the Conference on Spinoza and the Human Individual at
the ENS Lyon, the Australasian Seminar in Early Modern Philosophy at the University of
Queensland, and the Philosophy Programme at the University of Otago, and especially to
Ursula Renz, Pierre-François Moreau, Daniel Garber, Sarah Tropper, and Deborah Brown.
Thanks also to the Editors and two referees at Mind whose careful work with this essay has
been a great help to me.
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
citizens and how a state that promotes the welfare of its citizens may
nevertheless be susceptible to rebellion or deterioration. Spinoza’s
project in the Political Treatise is to design states that are good and
also stable. The individuality and complex nature of states explainwhy
that project is difficult.45
830
Michael LeBuffe
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
Garrett, Don 1990, ‘A Free Man Always Acts Honestly, Not
Deceptively’ in Spinoza: Issues and Directions, edited by Edwin
Curley and Pierre-François Moreau (Leiden: Brill)
—— 1994, ‘Spinoza’s Theory of Metaphysical Individuation’, in
Individuation in Early Modern Philosophy, edited by Kenneth F.
Barber and Jorge J.E. Gracia (Albany: State University of New
York Press)
—— 1996, ‘Spinoza’s Ethical Theory’, in The Cambridge Companion
to Spinoza, edited by Don Garrett (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press)
—— 2008, ‘Representation and Consciousness in Spinoza’s
Naturalistic Theory of the Mind and Imagination’ in
Interpreting Spinoza, edited by Charles Huenemann
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
—— 2010, ‘Promising Ideas: Hobbes and Contract in Spinoza’s
Political Philosophy, in Spinoza’s Theological-Political Treatise:
A Critical Guide, edited by Yitzhak Melamed and Michael
Rosenthal (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
Grey, John forthcoming, ‘The Metaphysics of Natural Right in
Spinoza’, in Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy
Gundogdu, Birol 2017, ‘Political and Economic Transition of
Ottoman Sovereignty from a Sole Monarch to Numerous
Ottoman Elites, 1683-1750’s’, in Acta Orientalia Academiae
Scientiarum Hungaricae 70
Gueroult, Martial 1974, Spinoza: L’âme (Paris: Aubier-Montaigne)
Hobbes, Thomas 1839-1845, Operae Philosophica quae Latine scritpsit
Omnia, edited by William Molesworth, 5 vols (London: John
Bohn)
—— 1983, De Cive: The Latin Version, edited by Howard Warrender
(Oxford: Clarendon Press)
—— 2012, Leviathan, edited by Noel Malcolm, 3 vols., (Oxford:
Clarendon Press)
Hübner, Karolina 2017, ‘The Trouble with Feeling, or Spinoza on the
Identity of Power and Essence’ in Journal of the History of
Philosophy 55
Joachim, Harold 1901, A Study of the Ethics of Spinoza (Oxford:
Clarendon Press)
James, Susan 1997, Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth
Century Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
—— 2012, Spinoza on Philosophy, Religion, and Politics (Oxford:
Oxford University Press)
Citizens and States in Spinoza’s Political Treatise
831
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
Kisner, Matthew 2011, Spinoza on Human Freedom (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press)
LeBuffe, Michael 2009, ‘The Anatomy of the Passions’ in The
Cambridge Companion to Spinoza’s Ethics, edited by Olli
Koistinen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
—— 2010, From Bondage to Freedom: Spinoza on Human Excellence
(New York: Oxford University Press)
—— 2010b, ‘Theories about Consciousness in Spinoza’s Ethics’, in
Philosophical Review 119
—— 2018, Spinoza on Reason (New York: Oxford University Press)
Lewis, David 1986, On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Basil
Blackwell)
List, Christian and Philip, Pettit 2006, ‘Group Agency and
Supervenience’, in The Southern Journal of Philosophy 44
Lord, Beth 2010, Spinoza’s Ethics (Edinburgh, Edinburgh University
Press)
Machiavelli, Niccolo 1857, Il Principe, e Discorsi sopra la prima deca
di Tito Livio, edited by Sergio Bertelli (Firenze, Le Monnier)
—— 1996, Discourses on Livy, translated by Harvey Mansfield and
Nathan Tarcov (Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
Malcolm, Noel 2002, Aspects of Hobbes (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
Marshall, Eugene 2013, The Spiritual Automaton (New York: Oxford
University Press)
Matheron, Alexandre 1969, Individu et Communauté chez Spinoza
(Paris: Les Editions de Minuit)
McShea, Robert 1968, The Political Philosophy of Spinoza (New York:
Columbia University Press)
Meinecke, Friedrich 1965, Machiavellism (New York: Westview Press)
Melamed, Yitzhak 2013, Spinoza’s Metaphysics: Substance and
Thought (New York: Oxford University Press)
Moore, Adrian 2017, ‘Sense-Making from a Human Point of View’,
in The Cambridge Companion to Philosophical Methodology,
edited by Giuseppina D’Oro and Soren Overgaard (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press)
Nadler, Steven 2008, ‘Spinoza and Consciousness’, in Mind 117.
—— 2016, ‘Spinoza on Lying and Suicide’ in The British Journal for
the History of Philosophy 24
Negri, Antonio 2004, Subversive Spinoza (Manchester: Manchester
University Press)
Newlands, Samuel 2018, Reconceiving Spinoza (Oxford: Oxford
University Press)
832
Michael LeBuffe
Mind, Vol. 130 . 519 . July 2021
ß LeBuffe 2020
Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/130/519/809/5881448 by 81695661, OUP on 02 August 2021
Peterman, Alison 2017, ‘The "Physical" Interlude’ in Spinoza’s Ethics:
a Critical Guide, edited by Yitzhak Y. Melamed (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press)
Rice, Lee 1990, ‘Individual and Community in Spinoza’s Social
Psychology’, in Spinoza: Issues and Directions, edited by Edwin
Curley and Pierre-François Moreau (Leiden: Brill)
Sharp, Hasana 2011, Spinoza and the Politics of Renaturalization
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press)
Sider, Theodore 2001, Four Dimensionalism: An Ontology of
Persistence and Time (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
Spinoza, Benedictus 1925, Opera, edited by Carl Gebhardt, 4 Vols
(Heidelberg: Carl Winter)
—— 2016, Collected Works of Spinoza, translated by Edwin Curley, 2
Vols (Princeton: Princeton University Press)
—— 2000, Political Treatise, translated by Samuel Shirley
(Indianapolis: Hackett)
Steinberg, Justin 2013, ‘Spinoza’s Political Philosophy’, in the
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
—— 2018, Spinoza’s Political Psychology: The Taming of Fortune and
Fear (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
—— 2019, ‘Bodies Politic and Civic Agreement’, in Spinoza and
Relational Autonomy, edited by Aurelia Armstrong, Keith
Green, and Andrea Sangiacomo (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press)
Tucker, Ericka 2019, ‘Power, Freedom, and Relational Autonomy’, in
Spinoza and Relational Autonomy, edited by Aurelia Armstrong,
Keith Green, and Andrea Sangiacomo (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press)
Youpa, Andrew 2003, ‘Spinozistic Self-Preservation’ in The Southern
Journal of Philosophy 41
—— 2020, The Ethics of Joy: Spinoza on the Empowered Life (New
York: Oxford University Press)
© 2021 Mind Association. Copyright of Mind is the property of Oxford University Press /
USA and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv
without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print,
download, or email articles for individual use.