Studia philosophica 66 / 2019 / 1
https://doi.org/10.5817/SPh2019-1-2
and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical
Viewpoint of the World by Pyrrho of Elis
Problém pravdy, blaženosti a sebavyvrátenia
vo filozofickom pohľade na svet u Pyrrhóna z Elidy
Andrej Kalaš
Abstract
This paper attempts to explore the concept of truth, human happiness and the related problem of self-refutation in the philosophical viewpoint of the world by Pyrrho of Elis. I argue
that according to the so-called metaphysical interpretation of Pyrrho, the reason for our
radical incompetence when it comes to knowledge is not our cognitive inability to grasp the
truth, but rather the very nature of things of the world. I provide an alternative philosophical
interpretation which is based on a philological conjecture in the preserved textual source.
I then point out a surprising connection between this radical attitude and the achievement of
human happiness, which constitutes the ultimate goal of Pyrrho’s philosophy. Finally, I present a possible solution to the problem of self-refutation, which is in a sense a challenge for
radical Pyrrhonian agnosticism. By this paper, I endeavour to show how bizarre could be the
image of the world viewed by the prism of radical skepticism of the early Pyrrhonism. Nevertheless, it is a world, wherein the philosopher vindicates his/her eudaimonia and defends
the logical consistency of one’s own claims.
This publication was made possible through the support of the grant project APVV-18-0103
Paradigmatic changes in the understanding of Universe and Man from philosophical, theological, and physical perspectives.
9
STUDIE / ARTICLES
The Problem of Truth, Happiness
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
Keywords
Pyrrho of Elis – ancient skepticism – the nature of things of the world – truth – happiness –
self-refutation
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Abstrakt
Štúdia sa snaží vysvetliť pojem pravdy, ľudského šťastia, a súvisiaci problém sebavyvrátenia
vo filozofickom pohľade na svet u Pyrrhóna z Elidy. Snažíme sa dokázať, že v duchu tzv. metafyzickej interpretácie tohto filozofa dôvodom našej totálnej poznávacej inkompetencie nie
je neschopnosť našich kognitívnych mohutností uchopiť pravdu, ale sama povaha vecí sveta.
Naznačujeme alternatívnu filozofickú interpretáciu, ktorá sa zakladá na filologickej konjektúre
zachovaného textu. Následne poukazujeme na prekvapivé prepojenie medzi týmto radikálnym skeptickým postojom a dosahovaním ľudskej blaženosti, ktorá konštituuje posledný cieľ
Pyrrhónovej filozofie. Napokon predstavujeme pozitívne riešenie problému sebavyvrátenia,
ktoré je v istom zmysle oslabením radikálneho Pyrrhónovho agnosticizmu. Predkladanou
štúdiou sa snažíme ukázať, aký bizarný môže byť obraz sveta nazeraného cez prizmu radikálneho skepticizmu raného pyrrhonizmu. Napriek tomu je to svet, v ktorom filozof zdôvodňuje
svoju blaženosť a bráni logickú konzistentnosť vlastných tvrdení.
Kľúčové slová
Pyrrhón z Elidy – antický skepticizmus – povaha vecí sveta – pravda – šťastie – sebavyvrátenie.
The present study1 is an attempt to depict the notion of truth, happiness and
self-refutation in Pyrrho of Elis (365–275 BC). Pyrrho was the first important
Hellenistic skeptic philosopher, who lived at the turn of the Classical and
Hellenistic periods of Greek philosophy. Despite the fact that he did not
write any philosophical treatises, he gained many admirers and followers.2
1
The paper offers a significantly elaborated version of the sketches I presented at the conference Truth: Theoretical and Practical Aspects, organized by the Slovak Philosophical Association in Smolenice on October 18–20, 2017. For invaluable remarks and comments,
I owe special thanks to Ulrich Wollner. This paper also brings together many scattered
and isolated findings presented in a number of my previous publications, especially in my
monograph on Pyrrho (KALAŠ, A. Pyrrhón z Élidy...). Nevertheless, the added value of the
text is not merely my novel rearrangement of the data but, in particular, my proposal in
the final chapter of an elegant and inventive explanation of how to save Pyrrho from selfrefutation.
2
A testimony on the absence of Pyrrho’s writings can be found in Aristocles, preserved by
Eusebius: “Pyrrho came across the books of Democritus, he neither found anything useful
there nor wrote anything good himself, but spoke evil of all, both gods and men” (Aris-
10
The later neo-Pyrrhonian skeptic school was named after him. However, taking into account historical authenticity, this denomination cannot be correct.
It is even outright misleading, since these philosophers called themselves οἱ
Πυρρώνειοι (“the Pyrrhonists”, i.e. “followers of Pyrrho”).3 Nevertheless, in
comparison with this “Pyrrhonian tradition”, Pyrrho’s own philosophy was
much more radical. To make Pyrrho’s philosophy usable in relation to their
goals, the ancient “Pyrrhonists” had to alter it significantly. Pyrrho served
more as an ideological trademark for these philosophers. They borrowed
from the monumental authority of the skeptic sage, who – as W. Görler succinctly put it – gave to later skepticism nothing but its name.4 Considering
the doctrinal discontinuity between Pyrrho and his Hellenistic followers, the
ancient designation οἱ Πυρρώνειοι could express the will of ancient thinkers
to pay respect to and join the tradition represented – on the neo-Pyrrhonian
view – by the majestic personality of Pyrrho of Elis. It is precisely in terms
of the issue of truth, which is the first topic of this study that Pyrrho significantly differs not only from neo-Pyrrhonism but also from a major part of
the Greek philosophical tradition. His answer to the problem of happiness is
equally atypical in the Greek context, resembling the nirvana of the Eastern
tocles apud Eusebium, Praep. evang. XIV,18,27,3–5, fr. 23 Caizzi). The fact that Pyrrho did
not write at all but nonetheless exercised an epochal influence on his followers and a whole
generation of philosophers has prompted scholars to draw a parallel between him and
Socrates. A. A. Long, for instance, writes that among the Hellenistic philosophers, Pyrrho
played a role which is in many ways comparable to that of Socrates in the philosophical context of the 4th century BC (LONG, A. – SEDLEY, D. The Hellenistic Philosophers I…, p. 16).
3
See e.g. οὗτοι πάντες Πυρρώνειοι μὲν ἀπὸ τοῦ διδασκάλου [...] προσηγορεύοντο (“after their
teacher, all of these men were called Pyrrhonists”; Diogenes Laertius, Vitae 9, 69, 12); cf.
Sextus Empiricus, Pyrrh. hyp. 1,232,2–3; 1,7,6–7.
4
GÖRLER, W. Pyrrhon aus Elis..., p. 732. The alternative point of view is represented by
scholars who tend to minimize or completely deny the differences between the early Pyrrhonism of Pyrrho himself and neo-Pyrrhonism, e.g. BECKWITH, CH. Greek Buddha...,
p. 20; STOPPER, M. Schizzi...; SVAVARSSON, S. Pyrrho’s..., pp. 280 ff.; STOUGH, CH.
Greek Scepticism..., pp. 16–34; ANNAS, J. The Morality..., pp. 204–205 and KUZMINSKI,
A. Pyrrhonism and the Madhyamaka..., pp. 485–486. Similarly, Horyna’s popularizing philosophical account of Pyrrho (HORYNA, B. Filosofie skepse..., pp. 28–31), besides other drawbacks (the absence of exact quotations, generalizations about the whole of Greek skepticism (ibidem, pp. 37 ff), suffers from the erroneous attribution to Pyrrho of a complex
of mostly neo-Pyrrhonian positions. Although interesting, Horyna’s elaborations on the
concept of truth in ancient skepticism (ibidem, pp. 53–56) have no relevance for my paper,
because they draw ahistorically from reproduced thoughts reported in Sextus Empiricus’
writings.
11
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
STUDIE / ARTICLES
sages more than the eudaimonia of the Greek philosophers.5 Finally, in the
third part of the paper, I will show that the core of Pyrrho’s philosophy can
be interpreted as a religious tenet – a viewpoint that is radically different
from that of the argument-based skepticism of the neo-Pyrrhonists.
1 Truth
When Pyrrho appeared on the scene of Greek thought, epistemology underwent a significant turn. Not only was the theory of knowledge concerned
with the nature of knowing, the transfer mechanism of sensations and the
emergence of rational knowledge, but it was tasked with justifying the very
existence of knowledge itself. Brunschwig says that with Pyrrho, and after
Aristotle’s death, “philosophy saw itself driven from a happy paradise of
epistemological innocence”.6 An explicit confirmation of this can be found
in the opening words of Aristocles’ account of Pyrrho, where he says that
the first subject of inquiry is our capacity or incapacity to know anything
at all. This primary moment of examination determines, according to the
doxographer, the entire course of our philosophical endeavors.7 The key
testimony for unveiling Pyrrho’s attitude toward truth is Aristocles’ text, contained in a fragment from Eusebius, which figures as fragment 53 of Caizzi’s
5
The hypothesis that Eastern thought influenced Pyrrho is the basis of the so-called Orientalizing interpretation of Pyrrho. I will not follow this lead in this paper, however. As early
as the 19th century, this interpretation was embraced by Brochard (BROCHARD, V. Les
Sceptiques..., p. 53) and Campbell (CAMPBELL, L. V. Brochard, Les Sceptiques..., p. 112). As
for more recent authors, see Frenkian (FRENKIAN, A. Scepticismul grec...); FLINTOFF, E.
Pyrrho..., pp. 88–108; KALAŠ, A. Pyrrhón z Élidy..., 46–50; BECKWITH, CH. Greek Buddha...). The latter authors adduce solid conclusions about early Buddhist influences on Pyrrho. I sympathize with these proposals, agreeing strongly with the argumentation that Pyrrho must have visited India with Alexander’s army at a very young age, in his early twenties
(BECKWITH, CH. Greek Buddha..., pp. 13–14). A. Kuzminski’s monograph (KUZMINSKI,
A. Pyrrhonism: how the ancient Greeks...) offers a systematic comparison of later Pyrrhonism
and the doctrine of later normative Buddhism (the so-called Madhyamaka School). Although the influence of Eastern wisdom on Pyrrho is Kuzminski’s fundamental premise,
readers of his lengthy book are likely to be bewildered by the fact that for him, the thought
of Pyrrho of Elis and the skepticism of the neo-Pyrrhonian school are one and the same.
6
BRUNSCHWIG, J. Introduction..., p. 229.
7
“Before all things it is necessary to make a thorough examination of our own knowledge;
for if it is our nature to know nothing there is no further need to inquire about other
things” (Aristocles apud Eusebium, Praep. evang. XIV,18,1,1–2,1, fr. 53 Caizzi).
12
collection. Although the fragment has had quite a complicated history in the
doxographic tradition, passing through as many as three intermediaries,8
it remains a crucial source of our information on Pyrrho’s philosophy.9 It
contains three philosophical questions, answered one after another, which
must be correctly solved by anyone who wants to live a happy live: What is
the nature of things? In what way should we be disposed towards them? And
what advantage will there be for those who are so disposed?10 If we are to
determine Pyrrho’s notion of truth, the answers to the first two questions
will be important for us:
... τὰ μὲν οὖν πράγματά φησιν αὐτὸν ἀποφαίνειν ἐπ᾿ ἴσης ἀδιάφορα καὶ ἀστάθμητα καὶ
ἀνεπίκριτα, διὰ τοῦτο μήτε τὰς αἰσθήσεις ἡμῶν μήτε τὰς δόξας ἀληθεύειν ἢ ψεύδεσθαι.
διὰ τοῦτο οὖν μηδὲ πιστεύειν αὐταῖς δεῖν, ἀλλ᾿ ἀδοξάστους καὶ ἀκλινεῖς καὶ ἀκραδάντους
εἶναι...
... concerning the things themselves, as he [Timon] says, he [Pyrrho] declares,
that they are equally indifferentiable and unmeasurable and undecidable, and
therefore neither our perceptions nor our beliefs are either true or false. For
this reason then we must not trust them, but we must be without opinions, and
without inclinations, and without wavering...11
In order to understand logic of Pyrrho’s thought, it is important to see
that the answer to the first question (What is the nature of things?) is a logical
ground for the assertion that answers the second problem (In what way should
we be disposed towards them?). In the original ancient Greek text, this logical
structure is indicated by the expression διὰ τοῦτο (“as a consequence of what
8
For a detailed account see KALAŠ, A. Pyrrhón z Élidy..., pp. 104–111.
9
The authenticity of Timon’s information about Pyrrho in Aristocles’ version, reported by
the Church Father Eusebius, is defended by I. Ch. Beckwith (BECKWITH, CH. Greek Buddha..., p. 17, n. 61). On the other hand, it is questioned by A. Kuzminski, who, in disagreement with R. Bett, argues that the peripatetic philosopher Aristocles, as a dogmatist, could
not understand the philosophy of Pyrrho adequately (KUZMINSKI, A. Pyrrhonism and the
Madhyamaka..., pp. 484–485). In any case, it is obvious that Kuzminski’s unwillingness to
admit the historical authenticity of Aristocles’ testimony on Pyrrho is simply a byproduct
of his identification of Pyrrho with neo-Pyrrhonism (see footnotes 3 and 4).
10
... δεῖν τὸν μέλλοντα εὐδαιμονήσειν εἰς τρία ταῦτα βλέπειν· πρῶτον μέν, ὁποῖα πέφυκε τὰ πράγματα·
δεύτερον δέ, τίνα χρὴ τρόπον ἡμᾶς πρὸς αὐτὰ διακεῖσθαι· τελευταῖον δέ, τί περιέσται τοῖς οὕτως
ἔχουσι (Aristocles apud Eusebium, Praep. evang. XIV,18,2,4–3,1, fr. 53 Caizzi).
11
Aristocles apud Eusebium, Praep. evang. XIV,18,3,1–3,5, fr. 53 Caizzi. Here, I am following
Svavarsson’s translation of the Greek text, with modifications (cf. SVAVARSSON, S. Pyrrho’s..., p. 269).
13
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
was stated before…”), which implies a relation of consequence.12 It means
that what precedes is a cause or a logical reason for what follows. What,
then, is Pyrrho’s conception of truth? The philosopher gives us a surprising
answer. He does not claim that this truth is hidden, unreachable or even
difficult to discover. Pyrrho frankly asserts that our perceptions (αἰσθήσεις)
and beliefs (“and opinions” – δόξαι) are beyond true and false, do not report
truthfully, but also do not lie. Why? The answer is given in the previous claim
about the nature of things. Things in the world are, according to Pyrrho,
equally indifferentiable (ἐπ᾿ ἴσης ἀδιάφορα), unmeasurable (ἀστάθμητα) and
undecidable (ἀνεπίκριτα). What the skeptic means is that there is no such
thing as truth because the nature of things is such that it simply does not allow for the categories of “true” and “false”, nor for the true/false distinction.
This manuscriptal reading of the text reported by Eusebius, i.e. the rejection
of Zeller’s conjecture διὰ τό but the preservation of the original διὰ τοῦτο of
the manuscripts, is the basis of the so-called metaphysical interpretation of
Pyrrho, which is upheld by several commentators.13
Quite different consequences follow from accepting Zeller’s conjecture.
According to this author and his text-critical proposal, the course of reasoning would be reversed: what follows is a logical reason for what precedes.
The consequences of Zeller’s approach support the so-called epistemological
interpretation of Pyrrho. The reason for this interpretation is offered in the
following section of Pyrrho’s text, emended by Zeller:
... concerning the things themselves, as he [Timon] says, he [Pyrrho] declares,
that they are equally indifferentiable and unmeasurable and undecidable, and it
is because (διὰ τό) neither our perceptions nor our beliefs are either true or false.
12
For this original ancient Greek version, E. Zeller (ZELLER, E. Die Philosophie..., pp. 494–
506) suggests the conjecture διὰ τό (“because of”, “since”). It is worth mentioning that the
meaning of the non-emended original διὰ τοῦτο depends on the syntactic rule that οὗτος,
αὕτη, τοῦτο (“this one”) refers to the preceding part of the text (SMYTH, H. Greek Grammar..., § 1245). Those scholars who accept Zeller’s conjecture favor the so-called epistemological interpretation of Pyrrho: e.g. M. R. Stopper (STOPPER, M. Schizzi..., pp. 292–293,
n. 53); J. Annas (ANNAS, J. The Morality..., p. 203) and T. Brennan (Brennan, T. Pyrrho...,
pp. 432–433). The epistemological interpretation will be treated below.
13
E.g. F. Decleva Caizzi (CAIZZI, D. Pirrone..., pp. 226–227); R. Bett (BETT, R. Pyrrho, His
Antecedents..., p. 19). A comprehensive list of scholarly authorities who uphold the metaphysical interpretation can be found in the study by S. H. Svavarsson (SVAVARSSON, S.
Pyrrho’s..., p. 271, n. 34).
14
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
In this view, our own cognitive incapacity is the primary reason for the fact
that the things of the world are equally indifferentiable (ἐπ᾿ ἴσης ἀδιάφορα),
unmeasurable (ἀστάθμητα) and undecidable (ἀνεπίκριτα). These three adjectives, which characterize the nature of things on the grounds of epistemological interpretation, cannot be understood “ontologically”, but only in an
epistemological sense: things are indifferentiable “for us”, unmeasurable for
our measuring tools and undecidable by means of our intellect.15
The principal argument in favor of the metaphysical interpretation is
this: If we can explain Pyrrho’s philosophy consistently without philological emendation, the latter is redundant. If the decision to follow the metaphysical interpretation among several others16 is correct, and if we take the
non-emended Greek text of fragment 53 Caizzi to be historically plausible,
Pyrrho appears to be a very radical philosopher, not only with regard to his
concept of truth. Can we even imagine what consequences follow from his
radical position on the nature of things? Answering the third question of
Aristocles’ fragment from Eusebius (What advantage will there be for those who
are so disposed?), Pyrrho promises the best that anyone can wish for. Those
who are so disposed, according to Pyrrho’s recommendations, will be given
first speechlessness (ἀφασία), then tranquility (ἀταραξία), and – as stated by
Aenesidemus – even pleasure (ἡδονή).17 However, what are the requisites for
such a blissful condition? Pyrrho requests one thing only, namely, that one
14
Aristocles apud Eusebium, Praep. evang. XIV,18,3,1–3,5, fr. 53 Caizzi.
15
There is a special group of authors who, on the one hand, do not accept Zeller’s conjecture, which means that they – as it were – maintain a sort of metaphysical interpretation
but, on the other hand, put the stress on the subjective, epistemological aspect of Pyrrho’s
conception of things (STOUGH, CH. Greek Scepticism..., pp. 17–19; Long, A. Hellenistic Philosophy..., pp. 81–82). This stance is unacceptable, however, because there is no midpoint
between these two extreme positions: either there is no truth about things, and then any
epistemology loses its ground, or there is a truth about things, but our epistemological
capacities are completely unable to grasp it.
16
An inquisitive reader can find as many as eight possible interpretation of Pyrrho in KALAŠ,
A. Pyrrhón z Élidy..., p. 8. Among them, the most serious pretenders to historical plausibility
remain the metaphysical, the epistemological, the ethical and the phenomenalistic interpretations (for a comparison between them and on the advantages of the first, see KALAŠ, A.
Pyrrhón z Élidy..., p. 126).
17
Aristocles apud Eusebium, Praep. evang. XIV,18,4,2–4,3, fr. 53 Caizzi.
15
STUDIE / ARTICLES
For this reason then we must not trust them, but we must be without opinions,
and without inclinations, and without wavering…14
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
STUDIE / ARTICLES
make, in every possible circumstance, of every possible thing, the following
sublime assertion:
... περὶ ἑνὸς ἑκάστου λέγοντας ὅτι οὐ μᾶλλον ἔστιν ἢ οὐκ ἔστιν ἢ καὶ ἔστι καὶ οὐκ ἔστιν ἢ
οὔτε ἔστιν οὔτε οὐκ ἔστιν.
We should say of every single thing that it no more is than is not, that it no more
is than both is and is not, that it no more is then neither is nor is not.18
It would go beyond the constraints of this paper to provide a detailed
commentary on this “magical” formula, or – as it were – this quasi “mantra” of Pyrrhonian skepticism.19 Generally, there are three possible ways to
translate, and consequently three possible philosophical interpretations of,
the text. In any case, all of them confirm Pyrrho’s conviction concerning
the fundamentally indefinite (unknowable) nature of things.20 But how can
we reconcile any assertion – even of this skeptical mantra – with the radical
epistemological agnosticism based on a metaphysical belief in the agnostic
nature of things themselves? If Pyrrho is unconditionally convinced about
the radical unknowability of the world, if he is, with regard to this very belief
about the world, a “dogmatist”,21 why does he command us to say something
18
Ibidem, XIV,18,3,5–4,1 (my translation).
19
In the syntactic structure of Pyrrho’s dictum, certain scholars detect a form often used
by Indian philosophers, the so-called quadrilemma. In describing certain problems, the
Indian sages endeavored to show, in four consecutive steps, that they were unsolvable
(see FLINTOFF, E. Pyrrho..., p. 93; BRUNSCHWIG, J. Introduction..., p. 244). However,
R. J. Hankinson (HANKINSON, R. The Sceptics..., pp. 64–65), a keen adversary of the Orientalizing interpretation, argued against the hypothetical influence of Indian quadrilemma
on Pyrrho’s thought. His polemic dispute with J. Brunschwig was critically reviewed by
A. Kalaš (KALAŠ, A. Pyrrhón z Élidy..., pp. 100–103).
20
As I argue elsewhere (KALAŠ, A. Pyrrhón z Élidy..., pp. 77–86), no epistemological value,
according to Pyrrho, can be attributed to a simple assertion (“is”) or to its negation (“is
not”), or to a composite assertion (“both is and is not”) or to its negation (“neither is nor
is not”).
21
Pyrrho’s radical conviction about the unknowability of the world led several modern (and
perhaps even ancient) authors to consider him a “dogmatist”, or, to be more exact, a “negative dogmatist” (in the literature, we also find the expressions “skeptical dogmatist” and
“dogmatic skeptic”), i.e. someone who held dogmatic beliefs about the unknowability of
the world. Proving this thesis, and stressing the difference between Pyrrho and the neo-Pyrrhonists, who were the typical ancient “non-dogmatists”, is the aim of the crucial chapter in
R. Bett’s book Pyrrho the Non-Sceptic (BETT, R. Pyrrho, His Antecedents..., pp. 14–62). Pyrrho’s
dogmatism in ethics is pointed out by those scholars who consider him a chiefly ethical
thinker who never dealt seriously either with epistemology or with other philosophical
16
about every single thing around us? If our knowledge is fundamentally impossible because of the unknowable nature of things, why should we say
anything at all about these things – even the fact that they are unknowable? Isn’t Pyrrho contradicting himself? Does he not refute himself if, on
the one hand, he forbids something and, on the other hand, he commands
us to do something? Let us postpone for the moment this serious issue of
self-refutation, which has confounded more than a few skeptics, and let us
consider, at least in a brief excursus, a more pleasant topic – the issue of
happiness in Pyrrho.
2 Happiness
Let us consider the question of how the radical denial of the possibility of
knowing anything corresponds with the achievement of happiness promised
by Pyrrho. If our philosopher disavows knowledge in general, he must disavow knowledge of values as well, i.e. knowledge of which values should determine our decisions, refusals, choices and actions. Can a human being who
does not have knowledge of values achieve happiness? Pyrrho’s affirmative
answer may sound surprising or even shocking from a “human” viewpoint,22
but it results directly from the stance expressed in the following fragments:
disciplines (BRUNSCHWIG, J. Introduction..., p. 249; BURNYEAT, M. Tranquillity..., p. 91).
This opinion was adopted by many in Antiquity as well. Cf. Cicero, who says of Pyrrho:
“[...] (scil. Pyrrho) having posited virtue he leaves nothing as an object of desire whatever.
[…] for the effect of their (scil. Pyrrho’s and Aristo’s) wish to make virtue on its own so allembracing was to rob virtue of the capacity to select things, and to grant it nothing either
as its source or its foundation; consequently they undermined the very virtue which they
embraced”; translation by Long – Sedley (LONG, A. – SEDLEY, D. The Hellenistic Philosophers II…, p. 19 ([...] qui [scil. Pyrrho] virtute constituta nihil omnino, quod appetendum
sit, relinquat [...] dum enim in una virtute sic omnia esse voluerunt [scil. Pyrrho et Aristo],
ut eam rerum selectione expoliarent nec ei quicquam, aut unde oriretur, darent, aut ubi niteretur, virtutem ipsam, quam amplexabantur, sustulerunt. De fin. IV,43,3–4, fr. 69C Caizzi;
De fin. II,43,5–9, fr. 69B Caizzi).
22
It is this Pyrrhonian idea, i.e. that holding “no views” and “not deciding” leads to imperturbability and inner tranquility, that, according to several authors, constitutes an unparalleled element in Greece and in overall Greek philosophy (cf. BECKWITH, CH. Greek
Buddha..., p. 18; BETT, R. Pyrrho, His Antecedents..., pp. 179 and 220). Only few of them
plucked up the courage to look for its origins in the Eastern wisdom of ancient India (for
bibliographical references, see footnote 5).
17
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
The distress of the soul can be only avoided if we show to those who suffer from it
because they want to avoid evil and chase after good that there is nothing which is
either good or evil by nature, “but only among humans the convention23 sets thus
down” – as Timon says24 (ἀλλὰ πρὸς ἀνθρώπων ταῦτα νόμῳ κέκριται, κατὰ τὸν Τίμωνα).
Timon, also, said very rightly: “Foremost among all evils is desire” (πάντων μὲν
πρωτίστα κακῶν ἐπιθυμία).25
Wise man will neither avoid anything nor choose anything (ἀφυγὴς καὶ ἀναίρετος
ἔσται).26
Consequently, the strongest enemies of inner tranquility – according to Pyrrho – are evaluating beliefs and judgements, which dictate what to choose and
what to refuse, what to strive for and what to avoid, in our lives. Knowledge of
good and evil is the greatest human illusion because this distinction is given by
mere convention among people and does not have any substantial foundation.
Nevertheless, choices based on the difference between good (desirable) and evil
(refutable) produce the deepest inner agitation (ταραχή), and precisely their
disavowal – which is, for Pyrrho, a part of the overall disavowal of knowledge
itself – leads us, according to Pyrrho, first to speechlessness (ἀφασία), then to
tranquility (ἀταραξία), and then, in some authors’ opinion, even to pleasure
(ἡδονή).27 In this way, it seems that the core of Pyrrhonian happiness is a state
of lacking any motivation to make decisions and to perform actions of any
sort – a state of speechlessness “blissful idleness”.28 This attitude was viewed
23
Here, I accept Hirzel’s emendation νόμῳ for νόῳ. This reading fits well with Diogenes Laertius, Vitae IX,61,10, fr. 1 Caizzi, where we have νόμῳ δὲ καὶ ἔθει πάντα τοὺς ἀνθρώπους πράττειν
(“custom and habit are the basis of everything that men do”).
24
Sextus Empiricus, Adv. math. XI,140,1–6, fr. 64 Caizzi.
25
Athenaeus VIII,337 A, fr. 65 Caizzi. According to A. A. Long (LONG, A. – SEDLEY, D.
The Hellenistic Philosophers II, 13), the hexameter verse was a part of Timon’s ᾿Ινδαλμοί (Images), and Athenaeus probably found it in a gnomologium. On the historical authenticity
of Timon’s reproduction of Pyrrho’s philosophy, see e.g., KALAŠ, A. Pyrrhón z Élidy..., pp.
108–111.
26
Sextus Empiricus, Adv. math. XI,164,5, fr. 66 Caizzi.
27
Aristocles apud Eusebium, Praep. evang. XIV,18,4,2–4,3, fr. 53 Caizzi.
28
The possible Eastern provenience of this philosophical stance is hinted at in footnote 5.
18
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
less favorably by neo-Pyrrhonists, who attempted to re-interpret it,29 and to
ancient non-skeptic authors, who engaged in criticizing it.30
Following this brief excursion into Pyrrho’s “ethics without values”, let us
finally return to the issue of the self-refutation of his own assertions. How
can Pyrrho be so sure that our beliefs and opinions, as well as our sensations,
are neither true nor false if this claim itself entails disavowal of knowledge
and thus makes the very assertion inadmissible? How can he proclaim, with
such self-assuredness, propositions which claim to bear truth values while at
the same time denying that our sensations and opinions have a share in the
categories “true” and “false”?
The problem of Pyrrho’s self-refutation is closely related to the radical denial of the possibility of knowledge that some scholars call negative dogmatism.31 We will see this more clearly when we further examine the meaning
of negation in Pyrrho’s mysterious, vigorously expressed claim about things
in the world. According to Pyrrho, of every single thing we should assert,
first, that “it no more is than is not”, second, that “it no more is than both
is and is not, and finally, that it no more is than neither is nor is not”. I assume that for understanding the philosophical significance of these words,
it is crucial to comprehend the meaning of the negation “no more” (οὐ
μᾶλλον), which occurs several times in the sentence. If Pyrrho’s dictum really
bears deep epistemological validity, and if it means that no epistemological
relevance can be assigned either to a simple sentence (“is”) or to its negation
29
The neo-Pyrrhonian re-interpretation of Pyrrho consists in accepting “appearance” (τὸ
φαινόμενον) as the relevant criterion for decisions and action, although the essence of
things always remains hidden for neo-Pyrrhonians and is practically irrelevant to attaining
happiness. This so-called phenomenalistic interpretation of Pyrrho will also be attractive to
certain modern authors, who will assign to him – anachronistically, let us note – precisely
these neo-Pyrrhonian views, while at the same time minimizing or completely denying the
differences between Pyrrho and neo-Pyrrhonism (bibliographical references can be found
in footnote 4). For more on the phenomenalistic interpretation, see in KALAŠ, A. Pyrrhón
z Élidy..., pp. 121–126.
30
In Antiquity, criticism of Pyrrho’s notion of happiness usually came from the Stoic ranks,
especially Cicero: cf. Cicero, De fin. II,43,5—9, fr. 69B Caizzi; ibidem IV,43,1—5, fr. 69C
Caizzi.
31
See footnote 21.
19
STUDIE / ARTICLES
3 Self-Refutation
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
(“is not”), or to a compound sentence containing a simple sentence and its
negation (“both is and is not”) or to a negation of such a compound sentence
(“neither is nor is not”), then the first negation in the expression “no more
is than is not” (οὐ μᾶλλον ἔστιν ἢ οὐκ ἔστιν) cannot be a logical one and must
instead be a negation that we might call “epistemological”. The meaning of
the verb “is” (ἔστιν), then, is clearly not existential, i.e. it does not reveal anything about the existence or non-existence of an external thing (or things).
The expression “is”, in this case, is rather elliptical for “is something”, “is of
some specific kind”, “is such and such”. Negations such as “no more” in Pyrrho’s famous sentence bear “epistemological” meaning because, I assume,
when such a negation (or better, such a “denial”, “refusal”, or “rejection”) is
applied to any utterance, Pyrrho wants to say that that utterance – however
complicated or even logically contradictory it may be – has absolutely no
epistemological relevance. This is the needed “epistemological” negation,
which has no logical dimension and which therefore does not change the
meaning of the negated statement to its logical opposite, but rather refutes
it, or “negates” it, epistemologically.32
An interesting solution to Pyrrho’s self-refutation has been offered by
R. Bett, who shows that Pyrrho’s assertion about the nature of things and
about the epistemological character of our perceptions and beliefs is a specific statement – or better, a “meta-statement” – which is, according to Bett,
“exempt from its own scope”.33 Bett’s reasons for holding this are threefold:
(1) The term “things” (πράγματα), the nature of which Pyrrho declares to
be unknowable, refers, according to the everyday ancient Greek usage, to
common single objects and states in the world around us. Therefore – let us
complete Bett’s insight – πράγματα does not refer to what Pyrrho is talking
about when he makes apodictic assertions about things and the nature of
32
The fact that I am forging the term “epistemological negation” here does not mean that
I prefer the epistemological interpretation of Pyrrho described above. By using the negation, Pyrrho simply denies the meaningfulness of each possible utterance without telling us
why. R. Bett puts this succinctly, noting that “if they (scil. our opinions) were simply false,
we could simply switch to a contrary set of opinions; but since they are neither true nor
false (but purport to be true), we can avoid misconception only by avoiding opinions entirely” (BETT, R. Pyrrho, His Antecedents..., p. 30). A different opinion, based on the assumption that Pyrrho admitted the distinction between true and false, has been expressed by
M. R. Stopper, in line with his favorite epistemological interpretation: “I think that Timon
means not that ‘our senses never tell the truth and never lie’, but rather that ‘our senses are
neither constant truth-tellers nor constant liars’” (STOPPER, M. Schizzi..., p. 292, footnote
53).
33
BETT, R. Pyrrho, His Antecedents..., p. 24.
20
our perceptions and beliefs. (2) Apparently, Pyrrho’s “dogmatic” dicta are
not derived from our perceptions (αἰσθήσεις), so it cannot be inferred of
them that they are neither true nor false. (3) Pyrrho’s key claims cannot be
included in the realm of beliefs and opinions (δόξαι) either, which, in Pyrrho’s view, have no epistemic relevance (ibidem, p. 24).
All three of Bett’s arguments apparently attempt to vindicate, within Pyrrho’s doctrine, the special status of Pyrrho’s assertions about the unknowable nature of things and the epistemic value (or better, the “non-value”) of
statements acquired by means of reason and the senses. However, these arguments (especially the first) appear overly complicated and philosophically
speculative, which apparently runs against Pyrrho’s taste for straightforward
and basic solutions. Particularly questionable is Bett’s speculative assumption
that Pyrrho had an exact understanding of the semantic range of the concept “things” (πράγματα), such that his apodictic statements about things and
the nature of our perceptions and beliefs could be excluded by Pyrrho from
the above semantic range of “things” (πράγματα). If I have Bett’s reasoning
right, it is precisely this exclusion of Pyrrho’s key skeptic statements from
the realm of “things” (πράγματα) – which, let us recall, are indifferentiable
(ἀδιάφορα), unmeasurable (ἀστάθμητα) and undecidable (ἀνεπίκριτα) – that
guarantees their real epistemic validity.
At this point, I would like to offer my own solution to the problem of
self-refutation in Pyrrho. Like Bett, I am convinced that Pyrrho considered
his key statements about the fundamental unknowability of the world to be
excluded from the realm of common opinions (δόξα). However, I would like
to emphasize that he understood his “philosophical discovery” as a species of
superhuman, divine wisdom which he himself had achieved and which was
later glorified by his disciple Timon. In Sextus Empiricus, for instance, Timon
says of his worshiped teacher that as a right criterion, Pyrrho had applied the
word of truth. At the same time, he attributes to Pyrrho the claim that the
nature of the divine and the good is the firm fundament for the most just
life of man.34 Timon adored Pyrrho because he had managed to set himself
free from the enslavement of people’s opinions,35 and he elsewhere recounts
34
μῦθον ἀληθείης ὀρθὸν ἔχων κανόνα ... ὡς ἡ τοῦ θείου τε φύσις καὶ τἀγαθοῦ αἰεὶ // ἐξ ὧν ἰσότατος
γίνεται ἀνδρί βίος; Sextus Empiricus, Adv. math. XI, 20, fr. 60 Caizzi. In my translation, I treat
the phrase ὀρθὸν κανόνα as a predicate to μῦθον ἀληθείης. For a different interpretation and
translation of the line, see LONG, A. – SEDLEY, D. The Hellenistic Philosophers II, 19.
35
῏Ω γέρον, ὦ Πύρρων, πῶς ἢ πόθεν ἔκδυσιν εὗρες // λατρείης δοξῶν [τε] κενεοφροσύνης τε σοφιστῶν,
// καὶ πάσης ἀπάτης πειθοῦς τ’ ἀπελύσαο δεσμά; Diogenes Laertius, Vitae IX,65,1–3.
21
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
his divine way of life, which made him similar to the sun god.36 The divine
truth, prophetically announced by the great philosopher Pyrrho as a messianic
message37 directed (perhaps) to all humankind, thus achieves the status of
a specific statement that is exempt from the sphere of its own autodestructing
self-reference. Pyrrho’s prophetic statements, being virtually the statements of
a god, have every right to refute the epistemological relevance of statements
about the things of the world because these refer only to human knowledge,
not divine knowledge, which he possesses. In a certain sense, I consider my
solution a development of the second and third points of Bett’s suggestion
(see above), pointing out that the different quality of Pyrrho’s key declarations in comparison with other (mostly human) opinions and views (δόξαι)
and perceptions (αἰσθήσεις) is a consequence of their divine origin.
According to my interpretation, Pyrrho tries, in a majestic way, to announce
a kind of divine truth to us, which produces an intellectual astonishment,
a religious ecstasy, that cannot be subject to any (self-)refuting questioning.
It seems very likely that in his answers to the three questions concerning the
happy life, our philosopher wants to communicate at least a part of his divine
nature (ἡ τοῦ θείου φύσις), which can significantly transform our lives. I maintain that one of the most cogent arguments in support of the “prophetic”
character of Pyrrho’s statements38 is the fact that he uses a specific stylistic
figure: asyndeton. In addition, it shows that Pyrrho was not only a profound
thinker, but also an outstanding man of letters and an adept stylist.39
I shall proceed with a short excursion into the theory of ancient Greek
stylistics. In Greek, a series of multiple equivalent elements (sentences, attributes, predicates, etc.) can be linked together either by polysyndeton40 or
36
... Τίμωνός τε τοῦ Φλιασίου τὸν Πύρρωνα ἡλίῳ ἀπεικάζοντος ἐν οἷς φησι μοῦνος δ’ ἀνθρώποισι θεοῦ
τρόπον ἡγεμονεύεις, // ὃς περὶ πᾶσαν ἐλῶν γαῖαν ἀναστρέφεται, // δεικνὺς εὐτόρνου σφαίρας
πυρικαύτορα κύκλον... Sextus Empiricus, Adv. math. I,305,1–5, fr. 61 D Caizzi.
37
See especially Timon’s conviction that Pyrrho “has broken shackles of every illusion of
persuasion” (πάσης ἀπάτης πειθοῦς τ’ ἀπελύσαο δεσμά; Diogenes Laertius, Vitae IX,65,3, fr. 60
Caizzi).
38
In Antiquity, the proposed thesis finds particular support in Timon’s declarations, quoted
above.
39
One might rightfully ask why I think it is legitimate to put so much stress on the use of
stylistic and rhetorical devices when it comes to a philosopher who is thought to have never
written anything. I maintain that the use of stylistic figures described below was not limited,
in Pyrrho’s time, to written texts. The ancient Greeks, especially of the Classical era, appreciated spoken language much more than we do today.
40
SMYTH, H. Greek Grammar..., § 3043.
22
by asyndeton.41 In short, polysyndeton is the multiple repetition of a connective, e.g. the conjunction “and” (καί) in the sentence “Those who came were
Michael and John and James and Frank”. Asyndeton is defined by Smyth
as follows: “Two or more sentences (or words) independent in form and
thought, but juxtaposed, i.e. coordinated without any connective, are asyndetic … and such absence of connectives is called asyndeton.”42 Let us use as
an example of asyndeton the same sentence, but without connective words:
“Those who came were Michael, John, James, Frank.” In fact, in the text by
Pyrrho analyzed above concerning what should and should not be said about
things, we do encounter asyndeton, an enumeration of alternative assertions
about the world without connectives:
... περὶ ἑνὸς ἑκάστου λέγοντας ὅτι οὐ μᾶλλον ἔστιν ἢ οὐκ ἔστιν ἢ καὶ ἔστι καὶ οὐκ ἔστιν ἢ
οὔτε ἔστιν οὔτε οὐκ ἔστιν
We should say of every single thing that it no more is […] than [anaphora] is not,
[…] [asyndeton] than [anaphora] both is and is not, […] [asyndeton] than [anaphora]
neither is nor is not.43
I maintain that Pyrrho used asyndeton deliberately and that it had a philosophical function. Incidentally, the text also includes anaphora, which is
a device typically used along with asyndeton.44 The anaphora consists of
the thrice-recurring comparative particle ἤ (= “than”), which in our text introduces (but does not connect, in which case it would be a polysyndeton)
various alternatives of utterances about the world that are – according to
the definition of asyndeton – independent and equivalent.45 The graphically
modified text above makes clear that it contains at least two asyndeta and
three anaphorae. The text is an instance of so-called rhetorical asyndeton,46
41
Ibidem, § 1033, §§ 2165–2167, § 3016.
42
Ibidem, § 2165.
43
Aristocles apud Eusebium, Praep. evang. XIV,18,3,5–4,1, fr. 53 Caizzi. A more explicit translation which fills in the elliptic gaps in the Greek text runs as follows: “We should say of
every single thing that it no more is than is not, […] that it no more is than both is and is
not, […] that it no more is than neither is nor is not.” This version may be more reader
friendly, but it is not very convenient for a philological and stylistic analysis of the original
text.
44
SMYTH, H. Greek Grammar..., § 2167c.
45
See Smyth’s definition of asyndeton in footnote 41.
46
SMYTH, H. Greek Grammar..., § 2165a.
23
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
which has philosophical significance. Pyrrho knowingly expressed the emotive charge, vividness and impressiveness of his “philosophical discovery”,
namely the announced superhuman truth with a divine dimension. The
emotiveness of this rhetorical asyndeton is even emphasized by the abovementioned anaphora.47 The emotional engagement is very likely identical
to the intellectual astonishment which in Pyrrho results in religious awe and
is closely related to the specific status of the “higher” truths communicated
by him. Pyrrho’s wisdom must have sounded like a majestic rhetorical symphony to the ancient Greek audience, a magnificent “Ode to Joy” announced
to all.
Conclusion
In this paper, I have examined Pyrrho of Elis’s specific, even agnostic, attitude toward the problem of truth. For Pyrrho, there is no truth that can be
grasped by humans. The reason for this is not our inability to comprehend
truth, but rather the very nature of things, which does not allow it. I have
indicated how, according to Pyrrho, someone who is epistemologically and
axiologically “emptied” can achieve happiness. I have also tried to address
the issue of Pyrrho’s self-refuting skepticism and have offered an elegant
solution, identifying the rhetorical asyndeton and anaphora in Pyrrho’s text.
These rhetorical devices convey the status of specific utterances to Pyrrho’s
words – the status of “divine” (revealed) truths, which are exempt from the
range of self-destructing auto-reference. If our inferences are correct, then
Pyrrho shines forth on the horizon of Greek thought not only as an original
thinker but as an outstanding orator. Taking into account his philosophy, we
might wonder whether, with the exception, perhaps, of the worshippers of
nirvana, his philosophical message might lead us to genuine happiness.
References
ANNAS, Julia. The Morality of Happiness. New York: Oxford University Press 1993.
ATHENAEUS. Deipnosophistae. 3 vols. Edited G. Kaibel. Leipzig: Teubner 1887 (repr.
1966).
BECKWITH, Christopher. Greek Buddha. Pyrrho’s Encounter with Early Buddhism in
Central Asia. Princeton: Princeton University Press 2015.
47
Ibidem, § 2166.
24
BETT, Richard. Pyrrho, His Antecedents, and His Legacy. Oxford: Oxford University
Press 2000.
BRENNAN, Tad. Pyrrho on the Criterion. Ancient Philosophy. 1998, 18(2), pp. 417–433.
BROCHARD, Victor. Les Sceptiques grecs. Paris: Imprimerie Nationale 1887.
BRUNSCHWIG, Jacques. Introduction: the Beginnings of Hellenistic Epistemology.
In ALGRA, Keimpe – MANSFELD, Jaap – SCHOFIELD, Malcolm (eds.). The
Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
1999, pp. 220–259.
BURNYEAT, Myles Fredric. Tranquillity without a Stop: Timon, frag. 68. The Classical Quarterly. 1980, XXX (1), pp. 86–93.
CAIZZI, Decleva Fernanda. Pirrone. Testimonianze. Napoli: Bibliopolis 1981.
CAMPBELL, Lewis. V. Brochard, Les Sceptiques grecs, Paris, 1887 (review). The Classical Review. 1888, II (4), pp. 111–113.
CICERO, Marcus Tullius. De finibus bonorum et malorum. In SCHICHE, Theodor
(ed.). M. Tulli Ciceronis scripta quae manserunt omnia, fasc. 43. Leipzig: Teubner 1915.
DIOGENES, Laertius. Vitae philosophorum. In LONG, Herbert S. (ed.). Diogenis
Laertii vitae philosophorum, 2 vols. Oxford: Clarendon Press 1964, pp. 1–565.
EUSEBIUS, Caesarensis. Die Praeparatio evangelica. In MRAS, Karl (ed.). Eusebius
Werke, VIII. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag 1954, pp. 3–613.
FRENKIAN, Aram M. Scepticismul grec i filozofia indiana. Bucuresti: Academia Republicii Socialiste Romania 1957.
FLINTOFF, Everard. Pyrrho and India. Phronesis. 1980, 25(1), pp. 88–108.
GÖRLER, Woldemar. Pyrrhon aus Elis. In FLASHAR, Hellmut (ed.). Grundriss der
Geschichte der Philosophie. Die Philosophie der Antike, IV: Die Hellenistische Philosohie.
Basel: Schwabe 1994, pp. 732–759.
HANKINSON, Robert J. The Sceptics. London: Routlege 1995.
HORYNA, Břetislav. Filosofie skepse. Olomouc: Nakladatelství Olomouc 2008.
KALAŠ, Andrej. Pyrrhón z Élidy alebo blažený život bez hodnôt. Bratislava: Univerzita
Komenského v Bratislave 2009.
KUZMINSKI, Adrian. Pyrrhonism and the Madhyamaka. Philosophy East & West.
2007, 57 (4), pp. 482–511.
KUZMINSKI, Adrian. Pyrrhonism: how the ancient Greeks reinvented Buddhism. Lanham:
Lexington Books 2008.
LONG, Anthony A. Hellenistic Philosophy. London: Duckworth 1974.
LONG, Anthony A. – SEDLEY, David N. The Hellenistic Philosophers, I–II. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press 1987.
SEXTUS, Empiricus. Adversus mathematicos. In MUTSCHMANN, Hermann – MAU,
Jürgen. (eds.). Sexti Empirici opera, vols. 2, 3. Leipzig: Teubner 1961.
SEXTUS, Empiricus. Pyrrhoniae hypotyposes. In MUTSCHMANN, Hermann (ed.).
Sexti Empirici opera, vol. 1. Leipzig: Teubner 1912, pp. 3–209.
SMYTH, Herbert W. Greek Grammar. Harvard: Messing 1957.
STOPPER M., R. Schizzi Pirroniani. Phronesis. 1983, 28(3), pp. 265–297.
STOUGH, Charlotte L. Greek Scepticism. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of
California Press 1969.
SVAVARSSON, Svavar Hrafn. Pyrrho’s Undecidable Nature. In Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 2004, 27, pp. 249–295.
25
STUDIE / ARTICLES
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
Andrej Kalaš
The Problem of Truth, Happiness and Self-Refutation in the Philosophical Viewpoint of the World …
STUDIE / ARTICLES
ZELLER, Eduard. Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung.
Leipzig: O. R. Reisland 1922.
doc. Andrej Kalaš, PhD.
Department of Philosophy and History of Philosophy, Faculty of Arts, Comenius University
in Bratislava
Šafárikovo nám. 6, 814 99 Bratislava, Slovak Republic
[email protected]
26