The full reference for this article is:
Kaidesoja, Tuukka & Ilkka Kauppinen. 2014. How to Explain Academic Capitalism: A
Mechanism-based Approach. In Cantwell, Brendan & Ilkka Kauppinen (eds) Academic
Capitalism in the Age of Globalization, The Johns Hopkins University Press: Baltimore, 166186.
How to Explain Academic Capitalism: A Mechanism-Based Approach
Tuukka Kaidesoja and Ilkka Kauppinen
Empirical studies on academic capitalism have mostly described the changing relations and
blurring boundaries between universities, markets, and states in different contexts. This chapter
asks whether it is possible to take one step further, to develop systematic causal explanations of
this restructuring of the systems of higher education. Our goal is to propose an affirmative
answer to this question by outlining a mechanism-based approach to social explanation and
applying it to the phenomenon of academic capitalism. We also suggest that when we are
explaining the emergence of academic capitalism, there is a need to investigate how
globalization and academic capitalism are interrelated.1
Previous studies on academic capitalism have aimed to provide not only descriptions but
also explanations. For example, in their book Academic Capitalism and the New Economy,
Slaughter and Rhoades (2004) write: “we present a theory of academic capitalism that explains
the processes by which colleges and universities are integrating with the new economy, shifting
from a public good knowledge/learning regime to an academic capitalist knowledge/learning
10-1
regime” (7; emphasis added). They also identify several “processes by which universities
integrate with the new economy” (14) as well as explicate an array of “mechanisms and
behaviors that constitute an academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime” (15; emphasis
added). Slaughter and Leslie (2001, 155) accordingly discuss various external and internal
mechanisms through which concrete actors and organizational units have enacted or adapted to
academic capitalism. They also write that, in comparison to competing theories that seek to
explain recent changes in higher education, a theory of academic capitalism “focuses more
clearly on mechanisms, enabling the identification of strategic points of change around which
resistance can be mobilized” (156). Slaughter and Cantwell further extended this theory in 2012.
One could thus argue not only that the explanatory theory of academic capitalism has already
been developed, but also that this theory cites a number of social mechanisms and processes that
are either constitutive of the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime or have contributed
to its emergence in various national contexts.
Though we do not deny that the research literature on academic capitalism contains
important sketches of those processes and mechanisms that have contributed to the shifts toward
the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime in various national contexts, we nevertheless
suggest that the theory of academic capitalism can be further developed as an explanatory theory
because Slaughter and Rhoades (2004) do not specify in what sense the theory of academic
capitalism should be considered as explanatory, nor do they specify their concept of explanatory
mechanism. It is also unclear what exactly is the phenomenon or range of phenomena of which
this theory is supposed to explain. As we indicate below, there are also some conceptual
ambiguities in this theory.
The aim of this chapter is to advance explanatory research on academic capitalism by
10-2
outlining a methodological framework for that purpose. The framework we go on to develop is
based on the concepts of social mechanism and the model of mechanism-based explanation. We
do so by building on some recent methodological discussions on mechanism-based explanations
in the philosophy of social sciences and historical sociology. Drawing on the existing research
literature, we also illustrate how this framework could be applied to the phenomenon of
academic capitalism. Before addressing these methodological issues, we take a closer look at
some aspects of the theory of and empirical studies on academic capitalism.
The Need for Explanatory Studies
In many recent studies on academic capitalism (e.g., Slaughter and Leslie 2001; Slaughter and
Rhoades 2004), the concept of academic capitalism performs a double role. First, it is used to
refer to a collection of empirically identifiable behaviors, activities, practices, mechanisms, and
processes that are conceived as objects of empirical study. Second, it functions as a name of the
theory that aims to explain the emergence of these empirically identifiable phenomena that
characterize the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime. In our view, this ambiguity in
the concept of academic capitalism involves a risk of confusing explanandum (a phenomenon to
be explained) and explanans (factors that are cited in the explanation of the phenomenon) in
explanatory studies on this topic. Such ambiguity is one of the reasons we believe that more
precise and explicit articulation of the methodological ideas that could provide guidance for
building of causal explanations is needed.
In addition, though Slaughter and Rhoades (2004, 1) claim that the theory of academic
capitalism is meant to provide an explanation for the recent restructuring of systems of higher
education as well as for the blurring boundaries between universities, states, and markets, we
10-3
nevertheless argue that research literature on academic capitalism has so far been mostly
descriptive. It has focused on identifying and characterizing recent trends and changes in
universities and in their relations to other social systems. Some studies have also examined how
these institutional changes have given rise to increasingly contradictory demands experienced by
various groups of academic workers in universities (e.g., Ylijoki 2003). As a result, relatively
few efforts have been made to provide causal explanations to these phenomena. In addition,
while the theory of academic capitalism provides a set of interconnected theoretical concepts that
are useful in conceptualizing the recent restructuring of higher education systems, it nevertheless
does not provide methodologically conscious causal explanations for the emergence of academic
capitalist knowledge/learning regimes in various contexts.
There is nothing wrong with descriptive (in contrast to explanatory) studies in social
sciences. Descriptive studies not only provide useful information for various practical purposes
(e.g., policy making), but they are also often indispensable in identifying and specifying
empirical phenomena that are worth explanatory studies as well as in providing empirical
evidence that can be used in evaluations of the proposed explanations. Descriptive studies may
also offer useful cues for the construction of tentative theoretical ideas and models about the
explanatory mechanisms that have brought about empirically identified phenomena.
Nevertheless, given the numerous descriptive studies that have addressed the phenomenon of
academic capitalism in different contexts, we believe that the time is right to start developing
more specific causal explanations to these empirically documented changes in higher education.
As mentioned above, we acknowledge that there are some important explanations in the relevant
research literature, but argue that these sketches can be fruitfully elaborated by using some fresh
methodological ideas.
10-4
Because our point of departure is the mechanism-based model of explanation, something
should said about the uses of the concept of mechanism in the academic capitalism literature
(e.g., Slaughter and Leslie 2001; Slaughter and Rhoades 2004). In contrast to the notion of social
mechanism developed below, the meaning of the term “mechanism” is typically left unspecified
in the academic capitalist literature. It is also used rather ambiguously, as it refers to social
entities and processes of various kinds. Slaughter and Leslie (2001), for example, specify a
number of “external and internal mechanisms”—such as market contraction, increased
competition, privatization, commercialization, deregulation of public entities, and interstitial
organizational emergence—that involve “the enactment or adaptation of academic capitalism by
concrete actors and organizational units” (155). Just like the concept of academic capitalism,
these mechanisms have a double role in that some of them appear to constitute the phenomena
that characterize the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime while others could be seen
as causal processes that have contributed to the emergence of this regime. Furthermore,
Slaughter and Cantwell (2012) state that narratives, discourses, and social technologies are
mechanisms that explain the emergence of academic capitalism. As we show below, our
understanding of what constitutes an explanatory mechanism is different and more specific.
In this chapter we try to disentangle the social mechanisms that constitute the academic
capitalist knowledge/learning regime from the social mechanisms that have brought about the
restructuration of higher education and universities, resulting in the rise of this regime. In order
to do so, we first specify the nature of mechanism-based explanations and social mechanisms.
Mechanism-Based Explanations and Social Mechanisms
Recent decades have witnessed discussions on social mechanisms and mechanism-based
10-5
explanations in many contexts in the methodology and philosophy of the social sciences (for a
review, see Hedström and Ylikoski 2010). These ideas have nevertheless received relatively little
attention in the field of higher education studies (for an important exception, see Bastedo 2012).
Here we try to change this situation by briefly introducing some of the ideas that we consider
promising in the context of explanatory studies on academic capitalism.
Sociologist Peter Hedström (2005) states that “the core idea behind the mechanism
approach is that we explain not by evoking universal laws, or by identifying statistically relevant
factors, but by specifying mechanisms that show how phenomena are brought about” (24).
Mechanism-based explanations are thus different from covering-law explanations, as the former
do not typically involve any general law statements, nor is the deductive form necessary to
mechanism-based explanations (Hedström 2005, chap. 2; Hedström and Ylikoski 2010, 54–55;
see also Bastedo 2012; Tilly 2001). Because social mechanisms are typically assumed to consist
of interacting social actors and their activities, mechanism-based explanations are also regarded
as alternatives to functionalist and structuralist explanations, which either abstract from the
social actions of concrete social actors or see these actions as inevitable consequences of the
larger social structures or systems.
In addition, the model of mechanism-based explanation in the context of the social
sciences is often connected to the Mertonian idea of middle-range theory (e.g., Hedström 2005),
meaning that the mechanism-based approach is distinguished not only from “grand” social
theories—which are often deemed too general, abstract, and conceptually ambiguous for
explanatory purposes—but also from the tradition of correlation-based statistical “causal
modeling,” which is criticized for its eclectic empiricism and tendency to replace real social
actors with statistical variables (e.g., Hedström 2005, chaps. 1 and 5). Nevertheless, the
10-6
usefulness of statistical analysis in empirical testing of theories and models about social
mechanisms cannot be denied. But what exactly are these social mechanisms that are said to
bring about social phenomena?
Drawing on Machamer, Darden, and Craver’s (2000) influential paper on mechanismbased explanations in biology, Hedström (2005) answers: “A social mechanism, as here defined,
describes a constellation of entities and activities that are organized such that they regularly bring
about a particular type of outcome” (25). Elsewhere, Hedström (2005, 2) makes it clear that in
the case of social mechanisms the key entities and activities are social actors and their actions.
Though this view is not included in his definition of social mechanism, as an advocate of
methodological (or structural) individualism, Hedström makes an additional assumption that
social actors in social mechanisms are always individual human beings. Mario Bunge’s account
of social mechanisms rejects this methodologically individualist view.
For Bunge (1997), a social mechanism is “a mechanism in a social system” (447). He
also writes, “a social mechanism is a process involving at least two agents engaging in forming,
maintaining, transforming, or dismantling a social system” (447). Social systems are in turn
“composed of people and the artefacts they use to communicate” (Bunge 1998, 311), or, in the
case of more complex social systems, they are composed of social subsystems. Furthermore,
Bunge (1996) holds that all social systems are ultimately “held together (or torn asunder) by
feelings (e.g., of benevolence or hatred), by beliefs (e.g., norms and ideals), by moral and legal
norms, and above all by social actions such as sharing and cooperating, exchanging and
informing, discussing and commanding, coercing and rebelling” (21; see also Bunge 2003;
Kaidesoja 2013; Wan 2011). According to his CESM model of systems, every social system can
be analyzed in terms of its Composition, Environment, (relational) Structure, and Mechanisms
10-7
(e.g., Bunge 2003, 35–36). He thus ties the concept of social mechanism to that of social system.
Four things in Bunge’s (1996, 2003) view on social systems (see also Kaidesoja 2013;
Wan 2011) should be emphasized: (1) social systems have ontologically emergent properties that
their individual members lack and that are not mere ontological aggregates (or resultants) of the
properties of the systems’ parts; (2) social systems are concrete and dynamical entities ultimately
composed of people and their artifacts; (3) social systems are inherently dynamical entities that
continuously interact with their changing social (and natural) environments (including other
social systems), meaning that the members, structures, environments, boundaries, and functions
of social systems tend to change over time; and (4) social systems not only interact with but also
intersect each other, in the sense that most people living in modern societies are members of
more than one social system at the same time.
Examples of emergent properties of social systems include the relational structure,
norms, institutions, and cohesion of a system. According to Bunge (2003), emergent properties
of this kind are not unexplainable mysteries because they are dependent on the properties of the
parts of these systems as well as their mutual relations and interactions. They therefore can be
explained in terms of the properties, relations, and interactions of the components of the system
as well as, at least in some cases, in terms of their relations and interactions with their
environment. But explanations of this kind do not eliminate the properties that have been
explained from our social ontology, as “explained emergence is still emergence” (Bunge 2003,
21). Hence Bunge advocates a weak (or rationalist) variety of the concept of emergent property
that should be distinguished from the strong forms of this concept because the latter deny the
possibility to scientifically explain emergent properties of social systems.
What is more important in this chapter is that there are two points separating Bunge’s
10-8
understanding of social mechanisms from that of Hedström’s. Bunge holds that (1) every social
mechanism exists in some social system and (2) there are social mechanisms not just at the level
of interacting individual human beings but also at the level of interacting collective actors, such
as organizations (see Wan 2011). Both of these views run counter to the methodological
individualism advocated by Hedström (2005).
Bunge’s (1997) ideas on mechanism-based explanations suggest that, from the viewpoint
of theory development, the most interesting social mechanisms recur in many social systems.
Hence, though he tends to equate mechanisms with concrete processes, Bunge’s (2004) concept
of social mechanism is meant to explicate the causal interaction structures that a certain class of
social systems shares and that drives systems of this kind—or “makes them tick.” Furthermore, it
can be expected that in all complex social systems composed of social subsystems there are
many interacting and intersecting mechanisms operating at different levels of organization
(Bunge 1997, 431; 2004, 193). According to Bunge (1997), it follows that “the mechanism of
every major social change is likely to be a combination of mechanisms of various kinds coupled
together” (417) and that “all unifactorial (in particular unicausal) explanations of social change
are at best partial” (417–18).
We believe that the best way to understand the concept of social mechanism is to
combine some ideas from both of these views. Like Hedström (2005), we emphasize that social
mechanisms consist of interrelated and interacting social actors and their activities in certain
contexts, but deny his view that these actors should always be individual human beings. In
addition to social mechanisms that are composed of interacting individuals, we maintain that
there are important social mechanisms in which the core actors are concrete social systems (in
Bunge’s sense), such as formal organizations.2 Hence social mechanisms can be said to exist at
10-9
different levels of organization in the social world depending on what type of entities they
consist of. Following Bunge, we admit that many social mechanisms could be usefully construed
as mechanisms of social systems (i.e., the interaction structures of social processes that result in
the formation, sustenance, transformation, or dismantling of social systems) but deny that this
point applies to all social mechanisms. In our assessment, his view that ties all social
mechanisms to some social system is too limited for the purposes of developing mechanismbased explanations of social phenomena, as there appear to be interesting social mechanisms that
are not necessarily connected to any specific (kind of) social system (Maynzt 2004, 243).
Drawing selectively on both Hedström’s (2005) and Bunge’s ideas, we thus maintain that
social mechanisms could be best understood as structures of interlinked actions or organized
interactions of many social actors (either individuals or organized collectives) that drive social
processes, and that these mechanisms may (but do not have to) be connected to some systemic
context. Sometimes it is also necessary to pay attention to the artifacts that mediate the actions
and communications between these social actors. In addition, unlike what is sometimes assumed
in the social mechanism literature, we believe that the concept of social mechanism does not
imply a commitment to any specific theory of action even though it highlights the importance of
environmentally embedded social action in explanations of social phenomena (Kaidesoja 2012;
Maynzt 2004). This understanding entails the possibility of utilizing conceptual resources of
different action theories for different explanatory purposes and that, for some explanatory
purposes, collectives (e.g., formal organizations) may be regarded as social actors.
10-10
Social Mechanisms Contributing to the Emergence of Academic Capitalism
There are some plausible candidates for social mechanism that have contributed to the
emergence of the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime in the United States and
elsewhere. Here we focus on social mechanisms that (1) are compatible with the previous
characterization of this concept; (2) have been mentioned in, or assumed by, the existing research
literature on academic capitalism (though not always termed social mechanisms); and (3) can be
considered as explanatory mechanisms in the sense that they have participated in the causal
generation of the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime by restructuring higher
education and universities in the United States as well as in other contexts. We suggest that there
are at least four generic mechanisms that meet these requirements: global economic competition,
coalition formation, legislation, and organization design (and redesign).
Here we view narratives, discourses, and social technologies as components of social
mechanisms of different kinds rather than as distinct social mechanisms (cf. Slaughter and
Cantwell 2012) because we like to stress that interacting social actors of various kinds always
(re)produce, circulate, and use these entities in order to achieve certain objectives or to pursue
their interests—regardless of whether they are successful. It is also methodologically important
to emphasize that narratives and discourses are often embedded in artifacts like strategy papers,
reports, policy programs, university rules, and legislative texts generated and circulated by
various social actors for various purposes. Insofar as we are interested in mechanism-based
explanations of social phenomena, it is not enough to focus only on the abstract contents of these
texts, but they should be rather seen as artifactual components of social systems and mechanisms
of various kinds.
10-11
Global Economic Competition
The rise of the neoliberalist ideology promoted by the Reagan and Thatcher administrations
(among others), the collapse of the Soviet Union and its satellite countries, the end of Cold War,
the deregulation of capital flows in and between many countries, as well as the invention and
diffusion of new information and communication technology tools and infrastructures have all
contributed to a new round of globalization of the capitalist economy that accompanied the
intensification of the global economic competition. Intensified global economic competition in
turn characterizes the social environment of higher education systems throughout the world. But
how exactly should we understand the mechanism of global economic competition?
In general terms, competition can be seen as a process whereby two or more social actors
pursue the same scarce resource in mutually exclusive ways that over time result in the uneven
distribution of this resource between the competing actors and the increased efficiency (in some
respect) of the most successful actors (i.e., the winners of the competition). It is then possible to
apply this abstract mechanism scheme to more concrete processes of competition, such as global
economic competition between companies for market shares and profits in global markets or
competition between states for drawing new investments and mobile economic capital to a
country by means of creating institutional environments (e.g., in terms of a national innovation
system and low taxation) that advance the competitiveness of companies in a country. These
competition mechanisms could be further specified, for example, by relying on theories of global
capitalism (e.g., Centeno and Cohen 2010; Robinson 2004; Sklair 2002). But all processes of
competition are regulated by moral or legal norms (or both), which is what separates competition
from war or violence. The processes of global economic competition related to global capitalism
thus presuppose a historically created institutional framework. Though different mechanisms of
10-12
global economic competition could be further theoretically specified, here we nevertheless rely
on more intuitive understandings of these mechanisms and consider their relation to academic
capitalism.
The mechanisms of economic competition between private companies (both national and
transnational), regional industries, and national economies can be considered one of the key
drivers of the development toward academic capitalism. Increasing economic competition
between companies in global markets accompanied by the recent crises of global capitalism have
created serious fiscal problems for rich industrial states, resulting in cuts to public spending as
well as searches for new sources of revenues. Given the intensified global economic competition,
current political climate, massification of higher education, and decreased budget funding,
universities have been forced to search for new sources of external funding to cover their
operational expenditures. They have also faced intensified expectations to contribute to the new
knowledge-driven economy by means of more efficient commodification and commercialization
of the results of scientific research and education services (see Rhoades, Maldonado-Maldonado,
Ordorika, and Velásquez 2004; Slaughter and Cantwell 2012; Slaughter and Leslie 1997;
Slaughter and Rhoades 2004). As discussed below, neoliberalist ideology and the related
competitiveness narrative are essential elements in understanding how various social actors—
who are responsible for science and education policy, university legislation, university
administration, as well as applied research—responded to the outcomes of the increasing global
economic competition.
There are also competition mechanisms that characterize (or constitute) the academic
capitalist knowledge/learning regime, including competition between universities for wealthy
and bright students as well as for external funding and rankings, competition between
10-13
departments for budget funds and external funding, and competition between research teams and
individual researchers for prestige and external funding. Also, many of these competition
mechanisms are by nature transnational or even global (e.g., student markets; see chap. 14 in this
volume).
Creation, diffusion, and intensification of these types of competition mechanisms and
respective markets that constitute the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime, however,
can be seen as consequences of the workings of the explanatory mechanisms that we have
identified here rather than as generators of the institutional restructuring of higher education. For
example, not only new legislation and regulation policies produced by powerful political
coalitions but also designing (and redesigning) of both intermediating and interstitial
organizations by academic and nonacademic actors have enabled universities to act more
smoothly in various types of markets as well as to create new types of “academic quasi-markets”
(e.g., building new kinds of funding mechanisms of universities that are based on the
competition between departments in terms of their academic production). Nonetheless, for other
explanatory purposes, these types of competition mechanisms may well be seen as explanatory.
Coalition Formation
Coalition formation can be defined generally as a process in which a temporal alliance or union
between two or more individuals or groups is established for some specific purpose. Coalition
formation between individuals or groups thus requires the creation of a shared representation of
the aims of the coalition, which often demands compromises between parties. In order to achieve
its intended aims (such as certain kind of new legislation), a coalition often draws upon the
expertise (e.g., to identify the problem and to provide information) and framing skills (e.g., to
10-14
translate some specific issue into an instrument of policy making) of its members (see Sell and
Prakash 2004).
In the US context, Slaughter and Rhoades (1996, 2004, chap. 2) have analyzed the
formation of the political competitiveness coalition that, according to their view, followed and
partially intersected the Cold War<th>/<th>health war coalition. The competitiveness coalition
was gradually formed during 1970s. Its aims were to: “(1) win control of global markets through
privatization and commodification of intellectual property; (2) establish government subsidies
for high-technology and producer services industries; and (3) move R&D, including university
R&D, toward commercial science and technology” (Slaughter and Rhoades 1996, 314).
According to their analysis, this coalition was composed not only of the Republican Party and
most Democrats but also of state and local governments, universities (or certain groups within
universities), and certain corporations (Slaughter and Rhoades 1996, 308). Profound changes in
defense, health, agricultural, and insurance industries that facilitated the interests of companies to
promote the new competitiveness coalition in R&D policy preceded the formation of this
coalition (Slaughter and Rhoades 1996).
In order to pursue these goals, the coalition rewrote “the narrative that privileged basic
science” in a way that promoted “a more commercial science and technology” (Slaughter and
Rhoades 1996, 307) in order to secure the competitiveness of the private companies in the United
States. In the new competitiveness narrative, “knowledge was valued not for its own sake, or for
what it might someday contribute to economic development, but for its contribution to the
creation of products and processes for the market of the moment” (Slaughter and Rhoades 1996,
317). The coalition then employed this narrative as a source of reasons to publicly justify new
legal reforms and university policies. As we shall see, the mechanism of coalition formation is
10-15
tightly interconnected to that of legislation.
At the transnational level we can identify a formation of a similar competitiveness
coalition within Europe in the 1980s. In crude terms, the key actors of this European-wide
coalition were the transnational policy-making group European Round Table of Industrialists
(ERT) and European political leaders (especially the European Commission). This coalition
successfully promoted the competitiveness agenda and, more broadly, the Single European
Market project (e.g., Bradanini 2009; van Apeldoorn 2000, 2002). And, just like in the case of
US-based business leaders (see Slaughter and Rhoades 1996), the ERT was also reacting in
many ways to destabilizing events, external threats, and perceived problems and challenges. In
the European context, these included the advantages of both the United States and Japan in terms
of university-industry collaboration, threats posed by the emerging East Asian economic
competitors, and the fragmentation of European higher education. One of the aims of this
coalition was to restructure European higher education in a way that would strengthen linkages
between higher education and industry between and in European national states (Kauppinen
forthcoming). This example nicely illustrates how a shift toward academic capitalism in Europe
cannot be explained by referring only to the social mechanisms that take place within nationstate borders. Rather, we should remain open to the possibility that at least some of these social
mechanisms are constituted across nation-state borders. The same applies to legislation.
Legislation
The legislation process proceeds somewhat differently depending on the context even though in
most cases it has an identifiable interaction structure. In parliamentary democracies, legislation
usually involves the following steps: (1) preparation of the legislation proposal; (2) a
10-16
parliamentary process that leads to either acceptance or rejection of the proposal; and (3)
implementation of the accepted law. It also typically involves state agencies, political parties,
and lobbyists (e.g., interest organizations) of various kinds.
As emphasized by Slaughter and Rhoades (1996, 2004), many of the laws that enabled
and created new opportunities for academic capitalist activities and practices in US universities
were supported by a bipartisan coalition in the Congress that was receptive to the
competitiveness narrative. They also importantly indicate that, although the congressional
coalition that “legislated the privatization and commercialization of federal research” was
“bipartisan, it was political” (Slaughter and Rhoades 2004, 229). “The coalition drew together
Democrats and Republicans who worked with the business class . . . to develop neoliberal
policies that fostered privatization, deregulation, and commercialization under state auspices and
with state support” (Slaughter and Rhoades 2004, 229). So there is an important connection
between the mechanisms of coalition formation and legislation.
In general, empirical studies on academic capitalism have focused on “national and
international legislation, treaties, and trade agreements that create opportunities for academic
capitalism in postsecondary education” (Slaughter and Rhoades 2004, 35) as well as in research
universities (Slaughter and Rhoades 2004, chaps. 2 and 3). For example, legislation that pertains
to US academic capitalism at federal, state, and international scales includes the following laws
(for a more complete list, see Slaughter and Rhoades 1996, 317):
•
1980 Public Law 65<H>517, the Bayh-Dole Act, and Reagan’s 1983 memo on
government patent policy;
•
1984 Public Law 98<H>462, National Cooperative Research Act;
•
1988 Public Law 100<H>418, Omnibus Trade and Competitiveness Act;
10-17
•
1993 Public Law 103<H>182, North American Free Trade Agreement; and
•
1994 Public Law 103<H>465, General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade.</BL>
Similar legislative changes have been discussed in other national contexts. As already noted,
however, it is not only national legislation that has contributed directly or indirectly to the shift
toward academic capitalism, but also international legislation. For instance, the Trade-Related
Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights agreement of the World Trade Organization (WTO)
facilitated universities’ patenting activities, and hence a shift toward academic capitalism, in
WTO member countries because it strengthened the protection of intellectual property (IP) and
broadened the category of IP (Kauppinen 2012). Various studies have revealed how the
promotion of this agreement was a transnational process and that some of the main actors in this
respect were transnational corporations (e.g., Braithwaite and Drahos 2000; Kauppinen 2012;
Sell 2003). Also, this example suggests that methodological nationalism is an inadequate
framework to explain a shift toward academic capitalism both in some particular nation-state and
a region (e.g., Europe).
As Slaughter and Rhoades (1996, 323–24) indicate, the legislation mechanism is related
to the mechanisms of organization design and redesign: new legislation that promoted the
competitiveness of US companies by removing the barriers of fluid capital from the boundaries
between private, nonprofit, and public organizations enabled the emergence of new types of
intermediating organizations between universities and markets, which in turn blurred the
boundaries between universities, markets, and states (see Slaughter and Rhoades 2004, chap. 2).
Legislation may thus be understood as one of the most important social mechanisms contributing
to academic capitalism in the United States as well as at the transnational scale (e.g.,
restructuring European higher education), as new legislation enabled and stimulated the
10-18
emergence of novel organizations, activities, and practices that characterize academic capitalism.
Organization Design and Redesign
The creation of intermediating and interstitial organizations is one of the key elements of the
theory of academic capitalism. These organizations promote and create policies, practices, and
activities that characterize the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime, as well as blur the
boundaries between markets, state, and universities (Slaughter and Rhoades 2004). Here we
emphasize that intermediating and interstitial organizations have been all designed in the sense
that they did not emerge spontaneously. Rather, they were intentionally established by means of
design plans, policies, and blueprints developed by specific social actors in order to secure and
increase external resources of their universities in competition against other universities. Some of
these organizations were also generated by redesigning previously existing organizations within
universities.
Though we regard design and redesign of organizations as important social mechanisms
contributing to the emergence of the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime, we
emphasize that the implementation of the plans, policies, and blueprints of designers tend to
produce both intended and unintended consequences. In other words, it is an empirical matter to
what extent the designed organizations have succeeded to meet their designers’ objectives and
what kind of unexpected side effects the workings of these organizations have brought about. In
addition, particular aims and plans of designers do not come out of the thin air, but institutional
and cultural environments have a rather heavy influence. For this reason, we also address some
mechanisms that mold the entire organizational field through affecting the activities and plans of
10-19
organization designers.
Social mechanisms operating at the level of organizational fields have been discussed
under the institutional isomorphism literature. They are typically invoked in explanations of why
organizations of certain kind, such as universities, tend to become structurally similar to each
other within a particular organizational field (e.g., DiMaggio and Powell 1983). These wellknown mechanisms can be labeled as mechanisms of coercion, mimesis, and attraction (Beckert
2010; DiMaggio and Powell 1983). In the case of European and Latin American higher
education systems, for example, many designers of new higher education organizations (and
redesigners of the old systems) imitated the organizations and policies of US universities (cf.
mimesis) that they considered successful as well as tried to translate them to meet the
requirements of local institutional contexts (cf. coercion; see Rhoades et al. 2004; Slaughter and
Cantwell 2012). We do not assume that these mechanisms necessarily push higher education
organizations toward homogenization; however (following Beckert 2010), those same
mechanisms (depending on conditions) may also lead toward divergence and, in this case,
divergent organizational ways to adopt and participate in those networks and activities that
characterize academic capitalism. This assumption is in line with the idea that there is not just
one but many types of academic capitalism (e.g., Slaughter and Leslie 1997; Slaughter and
Rhoades 2004). Furthermore, we assume this divergence can be found both between and within
nation-states.
We also include a fourth mechanism to the previous list—competition between
organizations (see Beckert 2010)—that may or may not contribute to academic capitalism in
various contexts, as competitive pressures can lead either to the homogenization or
diversification of organizations in a field depending on the interpretations of the designers (and
10-20
redesigners) of the organizations in different contexts. It may also contribute to the hybridization
of academic capitalism in various national contexts because the competition may lead to the
(re)design of “diverse political-legal rules and organizational models that allow for niches”
(Beckert 2010, 160) in which universities may specialize.
The key here is that mechanisms operating at the level of organizational fields can trigger
and influence organization design and redesign.3 The questions of under which conditions these
mechanisms would contribute to the homogenization and when heterogenization would occur are
fundamentally empirical. Organizations that are developed in some African, Asian, or European
countries do not have to be exact copies of the organizations found in the United States in order
to qualify as organizational examples of academic capitalism. Just as it makes sense to speak
about various capitalist economic systems, it makes sense to consider varieties of academic
capitalism and respective organizations for numerous reasons (e.g., differences in regulatory
environment).
Moreover, social technologies, such as European-level benchmarking (e.g., Slaughter and
Cantwell 2012) and global university rankings, can help produce structural similarity by
advancing competition through identifying what types of universities are successful in global
competition over prestige. As far as these university types are successful not only in terms of
how prestigious they seem but also in terms of operating in markets or interacting with market
actors (either nationally or transnationally), one might suggest that there are regionally or even
globally affective mechanisms (e.g., competition and “soft” coercion) that tend to encourage
academic capitalism at organizational levels in different countries and regions. In such cases,
organizational (re)designers are both pushed and pulled toward certain types of solutions.
Furthermore, as has been well documented by empirical research on academic capitalism (e.g.,
10-21
Rhoades et al. 2004; Slaughter and Cantwell 2012), international organizations such as the
European Union, International Monetary Fund, Organisation for Economic Co-Operation and
Development, and WTO have also had a major impact on the diffusion of specific designs,
policies, and strategies of organizations that aim to promote the academic capitalist
knowledge/learning regime in different contexts. These processes thus provide an explanation of
the partial isomorphism of education institutions in different contexts (e.g., in different European
countries).
Mechanisms of the design and redesign of particular organizations are neither morally
nor politically neutral (see Bunge 1998, part B). Design plans and policies for new organizations
as well as for organizational reforms, instead of being mere technocratic matters, are always
based on designers’ (or redesigners’) conceptions of the proper structure, goals, and social
functions of the organization under design, which have their origins in the social and institutional
environments of the designers. Individuals whose moral and political views differ from the
designers often contest these conceptions. In addition, design policies and plans for new
organizations typically define the norms and rules that the members of these organizations are
expected to follow in their social actions and interactions. These norms and rules may also be
enforced by designed incentives, sanctions, and social technologies (e.g., systems of quality
control) that are supposed to guide and regulate the behaviors of the organization’s members.
Not all relevant parties have equal opportunities to affect the formulation of design (or reform)
policies and plans (and the same applies, of course, to legislation).
Three types of designed organizations characterizing academic capitalism and their
design mechanisms are particularly instructive. First, the design of “intermediating organizations
external to universities that promote closer relations between universities and markets”
10-22
(Slaughter and Cantwell 2012, 585) has contributed to the emergence of academic capitalism in
various contexts. Organizations like the Business-Higher Education Forum (United States);
Carnegie Commission on Science, Technology, and Government (United States); ERT (Europe);
and Higher Education-Business Forum (European Union) were all designed (or redesigned) to
promote and lobby neoliberal ideology as well as to reshape the political agenda with respect to
higher education and its functions in society (Slaughter and Cantwell 2012).4 Second, another
important part of the restructuring of higher education has been the design of “interstitial
organizations that emerge from within universities that intersect various market oriented
projects” (Slaughter and Cantwell 2012, 585). For example, technology transfer offices were
designed to establish patent policies for universities as well as to promote patenting of research
discoveries and emergence of spin-off companies. Third, the redesign of higher education
systems and universities by policymakers, university administrators, and managers has also
paved the way for academic capitalism. The diffusion and implementation of management fads
and ideologies—such as new public management, total quality management, and business
process reengineering (e.g., Olssen and Peters 2005; Slaughter and Cantwell 2012)—are
important for empirical studies on these processes because management theories do not function
solely as (true or false) descriptions of educational organizations. They also include prescriptions
as to how these organizations should be changed in order to achieve some more or less clearly
defined goals. These theories are thus best termed as social technologies because they always
contain moral and political elements regardless of whether their proponents are ready to admit it.
Conclusion
A mechanism-based approach to academic capitalism provides a fruitful framework for
10-23
explanatory studies on the subject. Four generic social mechanisms that have contributed to the
emergence of the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime in the United States and
elsewhere support our argument. Yet we do not claim that these mechanisms exhaust the list of
all social mechanisms that have participated in the generation of academic capitalism. It is our
opinion, however, that the generic mechanisms considered above are among the most important
with respective to explanatory studies on academic capitalism in different contexts.
At this point it is not possible to focus systematically, owing to a lack of relevant
empirical studies, on how transnationally or even globally operating social mechanisms have
promoted academic capitalism. For this reason, we focused in this chapter on the United States
but also provided some illustrative examples of regionally/globally operating social mechanisms.
From this perspective, studies on the academic capitalism–globalization relationship are not only
about finding empirical examples of transnational academic capitalism, but also exploring how
academic capitalism has been enhanced at regional and global scales. The regional/global
promotion of academic capitalism, as well as diffusion of such organizations that characterize it,
does not necessarily lead to the strengthening of transnational academic capitalism, but rather
(more or less) simultaneous adaptation of academic capitalism in different national contexts.
Such adaptation occurs because transnationalization of those activities, flows, and networks that
characterize academic capitalism does not automatically occur in different nation-states. Thus it
is a fundamentally empirical question whether the globalization of academic capitalism is about
the relative convergence of national higher education systems or the transnationalization of those
elements that characterize academic capitalism. Of course, it can involve both of these trends.
In any case, even if a global trend toward the academic capitalist knowledge/learning
regime did exist, this model nevertheless provides room for specialization and differentiation in
10-24
different institutional contexts. Also, institutions and organizations in various national contexts
do not have to be exact copies of each other in order to qualify as elements of the academic
capitalist knowledge/learning regime. So, for instance, in Finland we find technology transfer
offices, and they are not exactly like those in the United States, but they are similar enough to
make it plausible to claim that academic capitalism has found its way into the Finnish higher
education system (see Kauppinen 2013a). Further studies could determine what sorts of national
and regional varieties of academic capitalism exist there, and to what extent these varieties also
involve transnational aspects. Overall, we suggest there is a trend toward the model of academic
capitalism in different national contexts owing to variety of reasons, but because of competition
between universities, it is likely that this trend supports national and organizational specialization
in order to achieve comparative advantage even if there seems to be also powerful templates,
such as global research universities, for (re)designers to consider.
The methodological framework developed above is compatible with different types of
research strategies on phenomena that characterize academic capitalism at different levels in
higher education systems as well as at the transnational level. These research strategies may
include case studies, comparative studies, and perhaps also survey studies. Different types of
methods, including both qualitative and quantitative ones, may be utilized in explanatory studies
that are based on a mechanistic approach. In these respects, the mechanism-based approach is
compatible with a moderate methodological pluralism.
Notes
1.
A growing number of studies suggest that developments toward academic capitalism can
be identified not only in the United States but also in many European (e.g., Kauppinen and
10-25
Kaidesoja 2014; Slaughter and Cantwell 2012) and Latin American countries (Rhoades et al.
2004), as well as at the transnational scale (e.g., Kauppinen 2012, 2013b).
2.
This finding is in line with the literature on academic capitalism because “the theory of
academic capitalism sees groups of actors—faculty, students, administrators, and academic
professionals—as using variety of state resources to create new circuits of knowledge and link
higher education institutions to the new economy” (Slaughter and Rhoades 2004, 1). Slaughter
and Rhoades (2004) also emphasize that they “have come to see colleges and universities (and
academic managers, professors, and other professionals within them) as actors initiating
academic capitalism, not just as players being ‘corporatized’<TH>” (12). The theory of
academic capitalism thus explicitly recognizes role of various social actors in the emergence of
the academic capitalist knowledge/learning regime, and these actors include both individuals and
environmentally embedded organizations.
3.
A similar type of categorization of social mechanisms recognizes three mechanisms that
are active in cross-national policy transfer: imposition, harmonization, and diffusion (e.g.,
Dahan, Doe, and Guay 2006).
4.
In the case of ERT, its aim was not to restructure higher education per se, but rather to
increase the competitiveness of European-based transnational corporations in global capitalism.
It was under this agenda that the ERT also identified the restructuring of European higher
education as one of its key goals (e.g., Kauppinen forthcoming).
10-26
References
Bastedo, Michael N., ed. 2012. The Organization of Higher Education: Managing Colleges for a
New Era. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Beckert, Jens. 2010. “Institutional Isomorphism Revisited: Convergence and Divergence in
Institutional Change.” Sociological Theory 28, no. 2: 150–66.
doi:10.1111/j.1467<H>9558.2010.01369.x.
Bradanini, Davide. 2009. “The Rise of the Competitiveness Discourse—A Neo-Gramscian
Analysis.” Bruges Political Research Paper 19. Bruges: College of Europe.
Braithwaite, John, and Peter Drahos. 2000. Global Business Regulation. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Bunge, Mario. 1996. Finding Philosophy in Social Science. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
———. 1997. “Mechanisms and Explanation.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 27, no. 4: 410–
65. doi:10.1177/004839319702700402.
———. 1998. Social Science under Debate: A Philosophical Perspective. Toronto: Toronto
University Press.
———. 2003. Emergence and Convergence: Qualitative Novelty and the Unity of Knowledge.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
———. 2004. “How Does It Work? The Search for Explanatory Mechanisms.” Philosophy of
the Social Sciences 34, no. 2: 182–210. doi:10.1177/0048393103262550.
Centeno, Miguel A., and Joseph N. Cohen. 2010. Global Capitalism: A Sociological Perspective.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Dahan, Nicholas, Jonathan Doe, and Terrence Guay. 2006. “The Role of Multinational
10-27
Corporations in Transnational Institution Building: A Policy Network Perspective.”
Human Relations 59, no. 11: 1571–600. doi:10.1177/0018726706072854.
DiMaggio, Paul J., and Walter W. Powell. 1983. “The Iron Cage Revisited: Institutional
Isomorphism and Collective Rationality in Organizational Fields.” American
Sociological Review 48, no. 4: 147–60.
Hedström, Peter. 2005. Dissecting the Social: On the Principles of Analytical Sociology.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hedström, Peter, and Petri Ylikoski. 2010. “Causal Mechanisms in the Social Sciences.” Annual
Review of Sociology 36: 49–67. doi:10.1146/annurev.soc.012809.102632.
Kaidesoja, Tuukka. 2012. “The DBO Theory of Action and Distributed Cognition.” Social
Science Information 51, no. 3: 311–37. doi:10.1177/0539018412441750.
———. 2013. Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology. London: Routledge.
Kauppinen, Ilkka. 2012. “Towards Transnational Academic Capitalism.” Higher Education 64,
no. 4: 543–56. doi:10.1007/s10734<H>012<H>9511<H>x.
———. 2013a. “A Moral Economy of Patents: Case of Finnish Research Universities’ Patent
Policies.” Studies in Higher Education doi:10.1080/03075079.2013.806457.
———. 2013b. “Academic Capitalism and the Informational Fraction of Transnational Capitalist
Class.” Globalisation, Societies and Education 11, no. 1: 1–22.
doi:10.1080/14767724.2012.678763.
———. Forthcoming. “European Round Table of Industrialists and the Restructuring of
European Higher Education.” Globalisation, Societies and Education.
Kauppinen, Ilkka, and Tuukka Kaidesoja. 2014. “A Shift towards Academic Capitalism in
Finland.” Higher Education Policy 27: 23–41. doi:10.1057/hep.2013.11.
10-28
Machamer, Peter, Lindley Darden, and Carl F. Craver. 2000. “Thinking about Mechanisms.”
Philosophy of Science 67, no. 1: 1–25.
Mayntz, Renate. 2004. “Mechanisms in the Analysis of Social Macro-Phenomena.” Philosophy
of the Social Sciences 34, no. 2: 237–59. doi:10.1177/0048393103262552.
Olssen, Mark, and Michael A. Peters. 2005. “Neoliberalism, Higher Education and the
Knowledge Economy: From the Free Market to Knowledge Capitalism.” Journal of
Education Policy 20, no. 3: 313–45. doi:10.1080/02680930500108718.
Rhoades, Gary, Alma Maldonado-Maldonado, Imanol Ordorika, and Martín Velásquez. 2004.
“Imagining Alternatives to Global, Corporate, New Economic Academic Capitalism.”
Policy Futures in Education 2, no. 2: 316–29.
Robinson, William I. 2004. A Theory of Global Capitalism: Production, Class, and State in a
Transnational World. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Sell, Susan K. 2003. Private Power, Public Law: The Globalization of Intellectual Property
Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sell, Susan K., and Aseem Prakash. 2004. “Using Ideas Strategically: The Contest between
Business and NGO Networks in Intellectual Property Rights.” International Studies
Quarterly 48, no. 1: 143–75. doi:10.1111/j.0020<H>8833.2004.00295.x.
Sklair, Leslie. 2002. Globalization: Capitalism and Its Alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Slaughter, Sheila, and Brendan Cantwell. 2012. “Transatlantic Moves to the Market: The United
States and the European Union.” Higher Education 63, no. 5: 583–606.
doi:10.1007/s10734<H>011<H>9460<H>9.
Slaughter, Sheila, and Larry L. Leslie. 1997. Academic Capitalism: Politics, Policies and the
10-29
Entrepreneurial University. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
———. 2001. “Expanding and Elaborating the Concept of Academic Capitalism.” Organization
8, no. 2: 154–61. doi:10.1177/1350508401082003.
Slaughter, Sheila, and Gary Rhoades. 1996. “The Emergence of a Competitiveness Research and
Development Policy Coalition and the Commercialization of Academic Science and
Technology.” Science, Technology and Human Values 21, no. 3: 303–39.
doi:10.1177/016224399602100303.
———. 2004. Academic Capitalism and the New Economy: Markets, State, and Higher
Education. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Tilly, Charles. 2001. “Mechanisms in Political Processes.” Annual Review of Political Science 4,
no. 1: 21–41. doi:10.1146/annurev.polisci.4.1.21.
van Apeldoorn, Bastiaan. 2000. “Transnational Class Agency and European Governance: The
Case of the European Round Table of Industrialists.” New Political Economy 5, no. 2:
157–81.
———. 2002. Transnational Capitalism and the Struggle over European Integration. London:
Routledge.
Wan, Poe Yu-ze, 2011. Reframing the Social: Emergentist Systemism and Social Theory.
Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
Ylijoki, Oili-Helena. 2003. “Entangled in Academic Capitalism? A Case-Study on Changing
Ideals and Practices of University.” Higher Education 45, no. 3: 307–35.
doi:10.1023/A:1022667923715.
10-30