Making enactivism even more embodied
AVANT, Vol. V, No. 2/2014
ISSN: 2082-6710 avant.edu.pl/en
DOI: 10.12849/50202014.0109.0011
Making enactivism even more embodied
*
Shaun Gallagher
Department of Philosophy, University of Memphis;
School of Humanities, University of Hertfordshire;
School of Humanities and Social Inquiry, University of
Wollongong
*
s.gallagher[]memphis.edu
Matthew Bower
Department of Philosophy
University of Central Florida
Received January 2014; accepted August 2014; published Autumn 2014.
Abstract
The full scope of enactivist approaches to cognition includes not only a focus
on sensory-motor contingencies and physical affordances for action, but also
an emphasis on affective factors of embodiment and intersubjective affordances for social interaction. This strong conception of embodied cognition
calls for a new way to think about the role of the brain in the larger system of
brain-body-environment. We ask whether recent work on predictive coding
offers a way to think about brain function in an enactive system, and we suggest that a positive answer is possible if we interpret predictive coding in
a more—enactive—way,—i.e.,—as—involved—in—the—organism s—dynamic—adjustments—
to its environment.
Keywords: enactivism; sensory-motor contingencies; affect; intersubjectivity;
predictive coding.
Enactivism is one version of recently developed embodied approaches to cognition. It offers an approach that is more informed by phenomenology and
pragmatism than other versions of embodied cognition, such as the extended
mind hypothesis (Clark 2008; Clark and Chalmers 1998), and more radical
than— the— kind— of— moderate — ”Goldman— 2012)— or— weak — ”Alsmith— and—
Vignemont 2012) embodied cognition found in theorists who locate the body
in—the—brain —or—who—translate—all—bodily—action—into—body-formatted representations (e.g., Berlucci and Aglioti 2010; Gallese and Sinigaglia 2012; Goldman
and Vignemont 2010). Enactivists have entered into various debates with
these other approaches (see Di Paulo 2009; Gallagher 2011a; Thompson 2007),
and clear lines have been drawn to distinguish the differences that involve
questions about functionalism, the importance of the body, the way one is
coupled to the environment, and so forth. At the same time, however, there
p. ??
AVANT Vol. V, No. 2/2014 www.avant.edu.pl/en
are a number of differences to be found within the enactive camp itself, so
that—the— early —enactivism—of—Varela,—Thompson—and—Rosch—”1991),—closely—continued by De Jaegher and Di Paulo (2007) is not exactly—the—same—as—the— middle —enactivism—of—O Regan—and—Noë—”2001;—Noë—2004),—or—the— latest—enactivism —
of Hutto and Myin (2013). There are some obvious differences among these
authors simply in terms of pedigree: Varela et al. are strongly influenced by
phenomenology—”as—well—as—Buddhism),—O Regan—and—Noë—by—cognitive—science,—
and Hutto and Myin by analytic philosophy of mind. While enactivists should
be—pleased—with—these—convergences—of—disciplines—and—traditions,—we re—going—
to suggest that they should also be critical with respect to the question about
how embodied enactivism is.
To pose this critical question we want to focus on the work of those enactivists
who emphasize the role played by sensorimotor contingencies in perception,
especially— O Regan— and Noë.— While— this— is— clearly— an— embodied— approach— to—
cognition, we want to argue that it is not as richly embodied as it should be.
One starts to see this in some recent authors who have distinguished the
O Regan—and— Noë—brand— of—enactivism—as—the— sensorimotor—approach — in contrast to the enactive approach (see, e.g., Kyselo and Di Paolo 2013; also Stapleton 2013). The focus on sensorimotor contingencies emphasizes a narrow conception of embodiment in terms of neuro-muscular function. In contrast to
this narrow focus, we want to suggest that these versions of sensorimotor enactivism—need—to—be—made—more—embodied.—We ll—focus—on—three—issues:—”1)—affectivity; (2) intersubjectivity; and (3) a dynamic attunement theory of brain
function. Emphasis on these issues is consistent with the enactivism associated with Varela, Thompson, and Di Paolo, and offers a positive account of enactivism that goes beyond the incisive critique of representationalism offered by
Hutto and Myin. We also note that although the sensory-motor contingency
approach focused on perception, the enactivist project concerns more than
just perception. That is, the project is to develop an account of cognition more
generally, including perceptual judgments and higher-order cognitive processes such as deliberation, decision, memory, and so forth.
Our goal is to make clear that these issues are important ones for continuing
development of the enactivist approach. Elsewhere we have developed some
critical considerations with respect to the first two issues (Bower and Gallagher—2013).—We ll—briefly— rehearse—these—considerations—in—the—next—two—sections.—We ll—then—focus—on—the—third,—and—argue—that—to—have—a—more—embodied—
enactivism we need a different understanding of how the brain works. Specifically we want to explore recent predictive coding models from an enactivist
perspective.— In— this— regard— we— generalize— suggestions— about— the— interactive—
brain—hypothesis —made—by—Di—Paolo—and—De—Jaegher—”2012).—
p. ??
Making enactivism even more embodied
Affectivity
An enactive account of cognition and perception integrates a variety of bodily
factors into cognitive processes. The body, understood as what phenomenologists—call—the— lived—body, —includes—the—related—notion—of—a— body—schema —”Gallagher 2005). The role of the body schema pertains to motor control and precisely the kind of sensory-motor— contingencies— emphasized— by— O Regan— and—
Noë—”2001)—and—Noë—”2004);—it—facilitates—interactions—with—one s—surroundings,—
and—it—contrasts—to—the— body—image, —a—term—that—designates—the—ways—in—which—
the body shows up for consciousness, in certain circumstances, as its intentional referent.
The lived body in its full sense, however, involves more than the sensorimotor
body schema and body image. It involves the full ensemble of bodily factors
that govern conscious life, but that operate in a pre-noetic fashion, below the
level of conscious monitoring and manipulation. Such factors may or may not
be accessible to conscious awareness. They include the large realm of affect.
This rich affective set of bodily factors is partially constitutive of perception in
ways that go beyond sensorimotor contingencies. An account that focuses
only on sensorimotor contingencies falls short due to its neglect of the relevance of the affective aspects including proprioceptive and kinaesthetic aspects factors that should be of high interest since they derive from movement— and— contribute— to— one s— practical— grasp— of— sensorimotor— contingencies.—
Affective factors, however, also involve a complex motivational dimension
that animates body-world interaction (Bower and Gallagher 2013; Stapleton
2013; Colombetti 2013).
Meaningful encounters with the world imply a perceiving agent with some
basic motivation to perceptually engage her surroundings. Schemata of sensorimotor contingencies give an agent the how of perception, a tacit
knowledge of potential sensorimotor engagements, without giving its why,
which depends on latent valences that push or pull in one direction or another for attention and for potential sensory-motor engagement, reflecting, for
example,—a—degree—of—desirability.— The—endogenously—originating—motivational—
viscera of the body are just as important to perception as the exogenously
oriented sensory-motor—elements —”Bower—and—Gallagher—2013: 111).
Affects are not restricted to the domain of phenomenal consciousness, although they may certainly have an effect on what experience feels like. I may
consciously experience the blues, or I may be unaware that my whole demeanor reflects the blues. Affect is deeply embodied even to the extent that
affective phenomena may be constrained by the functioning of the circulatory
system. For example, heartbeat influences how and whether fear-inducing
stimuli (images of fearful faces, in the reported experiments) are processed
(Garfinkel et al. 2013). When the heart contracts in its systole phase, fearful
p. ??
AVANT Vol. V, No. 2/2014 www.avant.edu.pl/en
stimuli are more easily recognized, and they tend to be perceived as more
fearful than when presented in its diastole phase. That is, the fact that, rather
than brains in vats, we are flesh and blood creatures equipped with beating
hearts, explains in part why we have just the sorts of affective states that
we do.
Consider particular instances of the affects involved in hunger and fatigue.
Somaesthetic factors such as hunger delimit our perception and action possibilities, as well as our cognitive possibilities. William James once noted that an
apple appears larger and more invitingly red when one is hungry than when
one is satiated. A recent study (Danziger et al. 2011) reinforced the idea that
hunger can shape, and perhaps even distort, cognitive judgment processes.
The study shows that the rational application of legal reasons does not sufficiently explain the decisions of judges. Whether the judge is hungry or satiated may play an important role.
The—percentage—of—favorable—rulings—drops—gradually—from—≈65%—to—nearly—zero—
within each decision session [e.g., between breakfast and lunch] and returns
abruptly—to—≈65%—after—a—[food]—break.—Our—findings—suggest—that—judicial—rulings—
can be swayed by extraneous variables that should have no bearing on legal
decisions. (Danziger et al. 2011: 1).
In—one—sense,—such—affective—factors—appear— extraneous —only—if—we—try—to—think—
of cognition as something that is disembodied, although clearly they may be
extraneous to the formal aspects of legal reasoning. In any case, it seems reasonable to think that this embodied affective aspect of hunger has an effect on
the—jurist s—perception—of—the—facts,—as—well—as—on—the—weighing—of—evidence,—and—
doesn t—appear—out of nowhere just when the judicial decision is made.
Typically our embodied condition does not reflect a simple, isolated affect
rather,— there— is— a— cocktail,— a— mélange— of— aspects— that— make— up— one s— affective—
state. After a day of trekking up a mountain,— one s— perception— may— be— informed by a combination of hunger, pain, fatigue, troubled respiration, feelings—of—dirtiness,—and—the—kinaesthetic—difficulty—involved—in—climbing.—It s—likely—
that that the mountain path looks more different and less challenging than
after—a—good—night s—sleep,—not—because—of—certain—objective—qualities—that—belong—
to the path, but because of my affective state. Such affective aspects color my
perception as they more generally constrain my being-in-the-world.
Affective phenomena are pervasively integrated into our perceptual and cognitive experiences (Pessoa 2013; Barrett and Bliss-Moreau 2009), as noted by
many enactivists (Colombetti 2007; Ellis 2005; Thompson 2007; Thompson and
Stapleton 2009). Shifts of attention may be led in one direction or another by
the affective ebb and flow of what we experience. From a phenomenological
perspective Husserl (2004) describes such affective states involving tension,
resolution, exertion, unease, and satisfaction/dissatisfaction as modulating our
perceptual (but not only perceptual) attention. Attention, in this sense, is em-
p. ??
Making enactivism even more embodied
bodied in a variety of related ways. In visual experience, for example, attending to something may involve squinting or opening the eyes widely, it may
involve a contortion of the face all the way from the scalp down to a gaping
mouth or pursed lips, and so on (Bergson 2001: 27-28).
Affect is closely related to the phenomenon of perceptual presence elaborated
by—Noë—”2004),—and—specifically—involves—a—sense—of—interest—or investment. Perceptual presence is the sense one has of the perceptual accessibility of nonapparent aspects or sides of a perceived object, or, more broadly, of what is
not directly sensed in the present moment (e.g., the side of the object that is
not visible).— The— notion— of— perceptual— interest — ”Bower— and— Gallagher— 2013)—
denotes the affective sense of the stakes or the costs involved in exchanges
with— one s— environment.— This— is— not— the— same as— Husserl s— concept— of— the—
I can, — which— signifies— the— intuitive possession of a sense of skill or competence. Rather, even if one is capable of accomplishing some feat in those
terms,— one— might— still— not— feel— up— to— the— task, — or— not— feel— inclined— to— do— the—
work it might take, which is the affective nuance the sense of interest is supposed to highlight. Thus, interwoven with that perceptual sense of presence is
a sense of the affective stakes of making something available or present. To
make something available involves definite costs in following through on
transactions— with— environmental— affordances.— One s— environment— affords—
many possibilities for action, but each has its affective price tag, and they are
not all equally affordable. One thus not only has a practical (sensorimotor)
understanding of accessibility, but an affective take on that same accessibility,
in terms of interest or inclination to follow through. The latter may also involve a perceptual sense of the ease or difficulty of making something present.
It s— true— that— a— perceiving— agent s— perceptual— stance is determined by a mastery of sensorimotor contingencies needed to access environmental affordances in suitable ways. Such mastery, however, once acquired, may be
a relative constant, and more or less generic or standard set of skills suitable
for most transactions with the world. Anyone with that same skill set might
perceive in the same way. In contrast, the particularities of affect will differ
from one individual to another, or from one day to another. Taking affective
phenomena into account importantly—enriches—one s—understanding—of—perception, since it clarifies the nature of individual perspective in perception.
A broad spectrum of individual life circumstances may, in terms of affect, be
brought to bear on perception, as well as other forms of cognition. These circumstances include not only physical burdens and impediments, such as the
impediment of fatigue from physical exertion, but also broader circumstances
having to do with time of day, since one typically is energized at the start of
the day and tired out toward the end, or with longer-term life phases, since
youth—and—old—age—surely—shape—one s—perceptual—interest.—
p. ??
AVANT Vol. V, No. 2/2014 www.avant.edu.pl/en
While everyone is affected by such circumstances in one way or another, each
individual lives them out in a unique way. The sense of the presence of the
other side of an object, of what is behind one, of what is in an adjoining room,
and the like, touches over—and—above—one s—generic—strategies—for—bodily—coping with the environment one s—individual—condition—with—all—of—its—strengths—
and—weaknesses.—In—a—very—simple—example,—what—Noë—calls—the— grabbiness —of—
an—object—is—dependent—not—only—on—one s—sense—of—the—pertinent—sensorimotor—
contingencies, whether the object is near or far, and properly shaped and
weighted, etc., and not only on whether one is in a state of pain, or fatigue, or
fear, etc., but on whether one is even concerned about (or inclined to) the possibility of grabbing the object.
Intersubjectivity
A series of experiments conducted by Proffitt et al. (1995; Proffitt 2003) purportedly show that the estimation of distance is influenced by anticipated effort. Subjects saddled with a heavy backpack tend to overestimate perceived
distance, whereas those without backpacks do not. Proffitt et al. (1995) similarly describe how subjects overestimate the degree of incline of a slope when
fatigued,—and—this—may—translate—into—the—subject s—lack—of—inclination—”to—climb),—
which further informs perception. The hill looks not only steeper, but also
uninviting. This might count as at least indirect evidence that perceptual experience—and/or—judgment—is—informed—by— one s—present—affective—state.—These—
results, however, have been challenged by Durgin et al. (2009), in a way that
nicely points in a different, but equally important direction for our considerations here. They show that steeper estimates of incline while wearing a backpack— are—judgmental—biases—that—result—from—the—social,—not—physical,—demands—
of the experimental— context — ”p.— 1).— Without— awareness— of— this— bias,— subjects—
who sense the aim of the experiment estimate a steeper incline than subjects
who are misled about the purpose of the backpack (e.g., that it contains electromyographic equipment to measure muscle tension). In other words, those
subjects—who— had— a—sense—of—the—experimenters —intentions—were—biased— in—favor of those intentions, without necessarily knowing it.
If Proffitt is right (see Proffitt 2009; 2013 for further discussion), his experimental results could be taken to point to the embodied-affective nature of
perception. But if Durgin et al. (2009; 2012) are right, their results still point to
an embodied phenomenon namely, the significance of others on our percep1
tions and/or judgments.
1
We note that there is continuing debate about whether these are effects on perception itself or
on perceptual judgments, a distinction that can be clearly made in the experimental lab (see Firestone and Scholl 2014 experiments on the El Greco fallacy). This is an important issue in regard to
claims about cognitive penetration of perception, but for our limited purposes here it is sufficient
p. ??
Making enactivism even more embodied
There are several ways to understand intersubjectivity as an embodied phenomenon. For example, some simulation theorists, like Gallese (2001; Gallese
and Sinigaglia 2012) understand empathic consciousness or social cognition to
be embodied in at least a weak sense. That is, they understand social cognition
to depend on body-formatted neural processes, specifically the activation of
2
mirror neurons (MNs). A more enactive approach, however, interprets the
mirror system to be activated in preparation for or anticipation of a response
to the other. That is, MN activation does not ordinarily involve matching (in
one s—own—system)—or— imitating—the—action—of—the—other—person—”see— Catmur et
al. (2007); Dinstein et al. 2008; Csibra 2005 for empirical evidence; also Gallagher 2008); it involves anticipatory processes that are keyed in with affordances for further interaction, or preparation for a complementary action
in response to an observed action (Newman-Norlund et al. 2007). In other
words, it is part of a response to social affordances.
On the enactive view, social cognition is characterized by, and sometimes constituted by embodied interaction (Di Jaegher, Di Paulo and Gallagher 2010).
This view is usually worked out in contrast to theory of mind (ToM) approaches that emphasize mindreading by either theoretical inference or simulation (Gallagher 2001; 2005; 2008). Intersubjective interaction is not about
mindreading the mental states of others, but about directly perceiving their
intentions and emotions in their postures, movements, gestures, facial expressions, vocal intonations, etc., as well as in their highly contextualized (by physical environment, social roles, culture, etc.) actions (Gallagher and Varga
2013).
One important aspect of intersubjective interaction that shows up even in
cases where we are not explicitly interacting with the other, although another
person is present, is the effect that his or her presence has on learning and
perception. One can understand this developmentally in regard to how we
learn—what—is—important.—Studies—of— natural—pedagogy, —where—there—is—explicit—
interaction, show that how the caregiver relates to the child influences what
the child learns. Natural pedagogy, which involves ostensively directing the
infant s—attention—to some object or event,
enables fast and efficient social learning of cognitively opaque cultural
knowledge that would be hard to acquire relying on purely observational learning— mechanisms— alone….— [H]uman— infants— are— prepared— to— be— at— the— receptive—
side of natural pedagogy (i) by being sensitive to ostensive signals that indicate
that there are such effects on cognition, whether perception, perceptual judgment, memory, etc.
and specifically in everyday pragmatic environments.
2
For the notion of body-formatted (or B-formatted) representations, see Goldman and de
Vignemont— ”2010),— and— Goldman— ”2012)— who— propose— a— moderate — or— weak — ”Alsmith— and— de—
Vignemont 2013) conception of embodied cognition.
p. ??
AVANT Vol. V, No. 2/2014 www.avant.edu.pl/en
that they are being addressed by communication, (ii) by developing referential
expectations in ostensive contexts and (iii) by being biased to interpret ostensivereferential communication as conveying information that is kind-relevant and
generalizable. (Csibra and Gergely 2009: 148).
More generally, it is through our interactions with others that we learn what
objects are significant or valuable. We learn to understand the world along
these lines of significance and value, and often objects that fall outside of such
lines—don t—even—register.—In—the—same—way—that—expert—training—hones—the—perceptual system so that experts are able to perceive things that non-experts fail
to perceive, in some sense, we all become experts in everyday life through our
interactions with others.
Indeed, this intersubjective education of perception and judgment continues
throughout life. Adult subjects presented with a face looking towards (or away
from) an object evaluate the object as more (or less) likeable than those objects—that—don t—receive—much—attention—from—others.—If—one—adds—an—emotional—
expression—to—the—face—and—one—get s—a—stronger—effect—”Bayliss—et—al.—2006;—2007).—
Furthermore, seeing another person act with ease (or without ease) toward an
object—will—influence—observers —feelings—about—the—object—”Hayes—et—al.—2007).—
Social interactions, social roles and groupings also have their influence on
how one perceives the world. In a modification—of—Proffitt s—scenario,—imagine—
being exhausted, but the incline is a hill that you are climbing with friends or
to meet a loved one (Schnall et al 2008). Or, again, think of the affective import
in situations where one would be seen by others as not up to the task, negatively— impacting— one s— image.— In— some— social circumstances one may find
a particular setting to be of more interest and more attention grabbing than if
one were with a different group, or alone.
The embodied and enactive brain
Following the weak embodiment strategy, one might argue that all such effects of affectivity and intersubjectivity are ultimately processed in the brain,
so that even the most enactive aspects of perception are reducible to brain
processes. After all, even if one interprets MNs as part of an enactive system,
they are neurons located in certain brain areas. Moreover, when we look at
how the brain works, we need concepts like representation and inference to
explain it, and these go against strong enactivist claims that tend to be antirepresentationalist and dismissive of the idea of subpersonal inferences. On
the weak embodiment view (e.g., Goldman 2012), claims about enactive perception, affectivity, and intersubjectivity can all fit neatly into orthodox internalist accounts.
p. ??
Making enactivism even more embodied
The notion of an enactive system requires conceiving of the brain in a different way. In evolutionary terms, the brain does what it does and is the way it
is, across some scale of variations, because it is part of a living body that has
hands that can reach and grasp in certain limited ways, and because it has
eyes structured to focus, and so on. The sensorimotor system is the way it is
because of the kind of organism the human body is. In addition the organism
has an autonomic and peripheral nervous systems, and not just a central system. It attains an upright posture, which, in evolutionary terms reshapes essential features, including the brain (Gallagher 2005), allowing the person to
cope with specific kinds of environments, and with other people. Changes to
any of the bodily, environmental, or intersubjective conditions elicit responses from the organism as a whole. On this view, rather than representing or
computing information, the brain is better conceived as participating in the
action.
The enactive interpretation is not simply a reinterpretation of what happens
extra-neurally, out in the intersubjective world of action where we anticipate
and respond to social affordances. An enactive interpretation of the MN system, for example, points beyond the orthodox explanation of information
processing to the possibility of rethinking not just the neural correlates of perception or intersubjectivity, but the very notion of neural correlate, and how
the brain itself works. More than this, it suggests a different way of conceiving
brain function, specifically in nonrepresentational, integrative and dynamical
terms (see, e.g., Gallagher et al. 2013; Hutto & Myin 2013).
This—doesn t—mean—that—we—should—simply—turn—the—issue—over—to—neuroscientists
to adjudicate, or simply consult what the neuroscientists say about subpersonal neural processes. Most neuroscientists are Helmholtzian and would
endorse the idea that the neural processes underlying perception are inferen3
tial and representational. Even the Bayesian predictive coding account treats
perception and object recognition as an inferential process. As Friston puts it,
predictive— coding— is— now— a— widely— accepted— view— of— perception— that— can— be—
traced back to Helmholtz's original writings on unconscious—inference —”2012:
4
248; also see Clark 2013).
It s—obviously—important—to—understand—brain—dynamics.—More—generally,—we ve—
known for a long time that anticipatory processes are hugely important for
perception and action. In neuroscience we have the work of Berthoz (2000),
3
The Helmholtzian idea that perception involves subpersonal inferences may or may not be
correct (see Bennett and Hacker 2003; Orlandi 2012; Hutto and Myin 2013).
The—unconscious—processes—performed—by—the—brain— are—like inferences insofar as from the observed effect on our senses we arrive at some conception of the cause of this effect. This is the
case even though we only in fact have direct access to the events at the nerves; we sense the effects and never the external objects —”Helmholtz—1867: 430).
4
p. ??
AVANT Vol. V, No. 2/2014 www.avant.edu.pl/en
for—example;—and—in—phenomenology,—Husserl s—account—of—temporal—structure—
remains important (1991; Gallagher 1998; 2011b). Work in predictive coding
provides an account of how neural processing participates in these pervasive
dynamic anticipatory processes. But again there are questions of how to interpret what we are learning about such processes. The assumption about
visual perception, for example, is that the brain has no direct access to the
outside world, so it needs to interpret or decode neuronal firing patterns that
are— generated— by— light— hitting— our— retinas.— Sensory— data— is— all— the— brain— has—
access—to —”Hohwy—2013,—13).—If—you—think—of—this—in—terms—of—inference—then—the—
brain is seemingly deducing to the best explanation of what has caused a particular pattern of neuronal activation and thereby representing that cause via
a process of causal inference. Since a given pattern could be caused by any
number of different stimulus configurations, the task involves figuring the
probabilities based on current neural states of the system that may relate, for
instance, to context.
How does this Bayesian process work in strict neuronal terms? There is general agreement that the process is a hierarchical one involving synaptic inhibition based on an empirical prior something that depends on the organism s— previous— experience— and— context-sensitive learning. This means that
specific neural networks, currently in a particular state because the organism
has previously encountered a particular stimulus or environment, or has
a particular history, determine ongoing processes that lead to top-down synaptic inhibition (a modulation of connections) anticipating further processing
consistent with prior processing. Such inhibitory patterns constitute a prediction which is then matched against ongoing sensory input. If there is a mismatch, i.e., if the new stimulus generates a different firing pattern than the
one anticipated, prediction errors are sent back up the line and the system
adjusts dynamically back and forth until there is a relatively good fit. So on
the predictive coding model, this or something like this is going on when we
perceive the world.
If— that s— the— case,— if— these— are— the— kinds— of— things— that— are— happening— in— the—
brain,— it s— not— clear— that— we— need— to— think— of— it— as— a— kind— of— inference— rather—
than a kind of dynamic adjustment process in which the brain, as part of and
along with the larger organism, settles into the right kind of attunement with
the environment an environment that is physical but also social and cultural
(Bruineberg and Rietveld 2014).
Whether or not we should think that beliefs, values, as well as affective states
and perspectives can shape the way that one quite literally sees the world, or
can enter into subpersonal processes in terms of predictive coding models
(Stapleton 2013), it remains an open question about how the neural (synapticinhibitory) processes described by such models are best characterized
whether as inferential (e.g., Hohwy 2013), or as part of a dynamical attune-
p. ??
Making enactivism even more embodied
ment of organism to environment, and/or in terms of plasticity where sensory-motor neurons have become attuned by associative processes and prior
experience. In any case, on the enactive view, the explanatory unit of perception (or cognition, or action, etc.) is not the brain, or even two (or more) brains
in the case of social cognition, but a dynamic relation between organisms,
which include brains, but also their own structural embodied features that
enable specific perception-action loops involving social and physical environments, which in turn effect statistical regularities that shape the structure
and function of the nervous system.
The question is, what do brains do as part of a dynamical attunement of organism to environment in the complex mix of transactions that involve moving, gesturing, and interacting with the expressive bodies of others, with their
eyes and faces and hands and voices; bodies that are gendered and raced, and
dressed to attract, or to work or play; bodies that incorporate artifacts, tools,
and technologies, that are situated in various physical environments, and defined by diverse social roles and institutional practices?
Di Paolo and De Jaegher (2012) have proposed the Interactive Brain Hypothesis in order to help model the possible relations between social interaction
and— neural— processes.— The— hypothesis— states— that— interactive— experience— and—
skills play enabling roles in both the development and current function of
social brain mechanisms, even in cases where social understanding happens
in— the— absence— of— immediate— interaction — ”p.— 1).— We— can— extend— this— idea— beyond the intersubjective context by following the suggestion that the brain is
primarily and more generally an organ of relation (Fuchs 2011). Evan Thompson (2014) provides a good analogy to indicate that the mind is relational, and
that the brain plays its part in that relationality. Saying that cognition is in the
brain is like saying that flight is inside the wings of a bird. But just as flight
doesn t—exist—if—there—is—just—a—wing,—without—the—rest—of—the—bird,—and—without—an—
atmosphere to support the process, and without the precise mode of organism-environment— coupling— to— make— it— possible,— so— cognition— doesn t— exist— if—
there is just a brain without bodily and worldly factors. Can this way of thinking be made consistent with predictive coding models?
Barrett—and—Bar s—affective prediction hypothesis suggests a positive answer. On
their predictive coding model responses— signaling— an— object s— salience,— relevance or value do not occur as a separate step after the object is identified.
Instead, affective responses support vision from the very moment that visual
stimulation— begins — ”Barrett— and— Bar,— 2009,— p.— 1325).— At— the— earliest— point— of—
visual processing, the medial orbital frontal cortex is also activated initiating
a train— of— muscular— and— hormonal— changes— throughout— the— body,— interoceptive—sensations —from organs, muscles, and joints associated with prior experience, and integrated with current exteroceptive sensory information that
p. ??
AVANT Vol. V, No. 2/2014 www.avant.edu.pl/en
helps to guide response and subsequent actions. In this respect, perceiving the
environment involves not just a set of neurons firing in the brain, but also
undergoing certain bodily affective changes that accompany this integrated
processing. Before we consciously recognize an object or other person, for
what it or he or she is, our bodies are already configured into overall peripheral and autonomic patterns based on prior associations. In terms of the predictive coding model used by Barrett and Bar, priors, that include affect, are
not just in the brain, but involve a whole body adjustment to the environmental stimulus.
This suggests that the brain participates in a system, along with eyes and face
and hands and voice, and so on. And the brain would work differently if its
embodiment lacked eyes, face, hands, voice, and so on. This is a fully embodied system that enactively anticipates and responds to its environment. How
an agent responds and what an agent perceives will depend to a great degree
on the overall dynamical state of the brain, but also on environmental factors,
embodied affective and intersubjective factors, the person(s) with whom she
is interacting, her worldly and intentional circumstances, the bodily skills and
habits she has formed, her physical condition, as well as her history of personal experiences, and what the other person may expect in terms of normative standards stemming from communal and institutional practices (Gallagher et al. 2013). Change any of these things and we can expect changes in
neural processing, not because the brain represents such changes and responds to them in central command mode, but because the brain is part of the
larger embodied system that is coping with its changing environment.
Conclusion
We ve—argued—that—it s—not—enough—to—model—an—enactivist—approach—to—perception and cognition on sensorimotor contingencies alone, even if they do play
an important role in such matters. There is good evidence that affective and
intersubjective aspects of embodiment are also important contributories to
perceptual and cognitive processes. In addition, this realization pushes us to
re-think the role played by neuronal processes in the brain. Even a neuroscience that frames brain function in terms of predictive coding needs to recognize that the brain is part of a system that attunes to and responds to its environment in a way that enacts a meaning relative to the particularities of
its embodiment.
p. ??
Making enactivism even more embodied
References
Alsmith, A. J. T. and De Vignemont, F. 2012. Embodying the mind and representing the
body. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. 3 (1): 1-13.
Barrett, L. F. and Bar, M. 2009. See it with feeling: affective predictions during object
perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B,
Biological Sciences, 364 (1521):1325 1334.
Barrett, L. F. and Bliss-Moreau, E. 2009. Affect as a psychological primitive. Advances in
Experimental Social Psychology 41, pp. 167-218.
Bayliss, A.P., Paul, M.A., Cannon, P.R. & Tipper, S.P. 2006. Gaze cueing and affective
judgments of objects: I like what you look at. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 13:
1061 6.
Bayliss, A.P., Frischen, A., Fenske,M.J. & Tipper, S.P. 2007. Affective evaluations of objects are influenced by observed gaze direction and emotional expression. Cognition 104: 644 53.
Bennett, M.R. and Hacker, P.M.S. 2003. Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience.
Oxford: Blackwell Publishing
Bergson, H. 2001. Time and Free Will. F. L. Pogson (Trans.), Mineola, NY: Dover Publications.
Berlucchi, G. and Aglioti, S. 2010. The body in the brain revisited. Exp. Brain Res. 200:
25 35.
Berthoz, A. 2000. The Brain’s Sense of Movement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bower, M. and Gallagher, S. 2013. Bodily affectivity: Prenoetic elements in enactive
perception. Phenomenology and Mind 2:108-131.
Bruineberg, J. and Rietveld, E. 2014. Self-organization, free energy minimization, and
optimal grip on a field of affordances. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 8: 1-14
Catmur, C., V. Walsh, and C. Heyes. 2007. Sensorimotor learning configures the human
mirror system. Current Biology 17(17): 1527 1531.
Clark, A. 2008. Supersizing the Mind: Reflections on Embodiment, Action, and Cognitive
Extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Clark, A. 2013. Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of
cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36(3), pp. 181-204.
Clark, A. And Chalmers, D. 1998. The extended mind. Analysis 58 (1): 7-19.
Colombetti, G. 2007. Enactive appraisal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6:
527-546.
Colombetti, G. 2013. The Feeling Body: Affective Science Meets the Enactive Mind, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
p. ??
AVANT Vol. V, No. 2/2014 www.avant.edu.pl/en
Csibra, G. 2005. Mirror neurons and action observation. Is simulation involved? ESF
Interdisciplines. http://www.interdisciplines.org/mirror/papers/.
Csibra, G., and G. Gergely. 2009. Natural pedagogy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13:
148 153.
Danziger, S., J. Levav, L. Avnaim-Pesso. 2011. Extraneous factors in judicial decisions.
PNA S.First published online: www.pnas.org/cgi/doi/10.1073/pnas.
De Jaegher, H., and Di Paolo, E. 2007. Participatory Sense-Making: An enactive
approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6, 485-507
De Jaegher, H., Di Paolo, E. and Gallagher, S. 2010. Does social interaction constitute
social cognition? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14 (10): 441-447.
Dinstein, I., C. Thomas, M. Behrmann, and D.J. Heeger. 2008. A mirror up to nature.
Current Biology 18 (1): R13 R18.
Di Paolo, E. 2009. Extended life. Topoi 28 (1): 9-21.
Di Paolo, E., & De Jaegher, H. 2012. The interactive brain hypothesis. Frontiers in human neuroscience, 6.
Durgin, F.H., Baird, J.A., Greenburg, M., Russell, R., Shaughnessy, K., & Waymouth, S.
2009. Who is being deceived? The experimental demands of wearing a backpack.
Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 16: 964 969.
Durgin, F. H., Klein, B., Spiegel, A., Strawser, C. J., & Williams, M. 2012. The social psychology of perception experiments: Hills, backpacks, glucose, and the problem of
generalizability. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 38(6), 1582.
Ellis, R. 2005. Curious Emotions: Roots of Consciousness and Personality in Motivated
Action. Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.
Firestone, C., & Scholl,—B.—J.—2014.— Top-down —effects—where—none—should—be—found—the—
El Greco Fallacy in perception research. Psychological Science 25(1): 38-46.
Friston, K. 2012. Prediction, perception and agency. International Journal of Psychophysiology 83 (2): 248-252.
Fuchs T. 2011. The brain: a mediating organ. J. Conscious. Stud. 18: 196 221
Gallagher, S. 1998. The Inordinance of Time. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Gallagher, S. 2001. The practice of mind: Theory, simulation, or primary interaction?
Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8 (5 7): 83 107
Gallagher, S. 2005. How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallagher, S. 2008. Inference or interaction: Social cognition without precursors. Philosophical Explorations 11 (3): 163-73.
Gallagher, S. 2011a. Interpretations of embodied cognition. In W. Tschacher and
C. Bergomi, eds. The Implications of Embodiment: Cognition and Communication
(59-71) Exeter: Imprint Academic.
p. ??
Making enactivism even more embodied
Gallagher, S. 2011b. Time in action. Oxford Handbook on Time (419-37). C. Callender,
ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gallagher, S. 2007. Simulation trouble. Social Neuroscience. 2 (3-4), 353-65.
Gallagher, S. and Varga, S. 2013. Social constraints on the direct perception of emotions
and intentions. Topoi. DOI 10.1007/s11245-013-9203-x
Gallagher, S., Hutto, D. D. Slaby, J. and Cole, J. 2013. The brain as part of an enactive
system. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (4): 421-422.
Gallese— V.— 2001.— The— shared— manifold — hypothesis:— From— mirror— neurons— to— empathy.—
Journal of Consciousness Studies 8: 33 50.
Gallese, V., & Sinigaglia, C. 2011. What is so special about embodied simulation? Trends
in cognitive sciences, 15(11), 512-519.
Garfinkel, S., Minati, L. and Critchley, H. 2013. Fear in your heart: Cardiac modulation
of fear perception and fear intensity. Poster presented at the British Neuroscience Association Festival of Neuroscience. (8 April 2013).
Goldman, A. and De Vignemont, F. 2009. Is social cognition embodied? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13 (4), 154‐59.
Hayes, A. E., Paul, M. A., Beuger, B., & Tipper, S. P. 2008. Self produced and observed
actions influence emotion: The roles of action fluency and eye gaze. Psychological research, 72(4), 461-472.
Helmholtz, H. 1867. Handbuch der Physiologishen Optik. Leipzig: Leopold Voss.
Hohwy, J. 2013. The Predictive Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Husserl, E. 2004. Wahrnehmung und Aufmerksamkeit: Texte aus dem Nachlass (18931912). T. Vongehr and R. Giuliani, eds. Dordrecht: Springer.
Husserl, E. 1991. On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time (19831917). Trans. J. Brough. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Hutto, D. and E. Myin 2013. Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds Without Content.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Kyselo, M. and Di Paolo, E. (in press). Locked-in syndrome: A challenge for embodied
cognitive science. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences.
Newman-Norlund, R.D., M.L. Noordzij, R.G.J. Meulenbroek, and H. Bekkering. 2007.
Exploring the brain basis of joint attention: Co-ordination of actions, goals and
intentions. Social Neuroscience 2(1): 48 65.
Noë,—A.—2004.—Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
O Regan,—K.—and—Noë,— A.—2001.—A— sensorimotor—account—of—vision—and— visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23, 939 973.
Orlandi, N. 2012. Embedded seeing-as: Multi-stable visual perception without interpretation. Philosophical Psychology 25 (4): 555-573.
p. ??
AVANT Vol. V, No. 2/2014 www.avant.edu.pl/en
Pessoa, L. 2013. The Cognitive-Emotional Brain: From Interactions to Integration, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Proffitt D. R. 2009. Affordances matter in geographical slant perception. Psychonomic
Bulletin & Review 16: 970 972.
Proffitt, D. R. 2013. An embodied approach to perception by what units are visual perceptions scaled?. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8(4), 474-483.
Proffitt, D., M. Bhalla, R. Gossweiler, and J. Midgett (1995). Perceiving geographical
slant. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. 2(4). 409-428.
Proffitt, D., J. Stefanucci, T. Banton, and W. Epstein (2003). The role of effort in perceiving distance. Psychological Science 14(2), 106-112.
Schnall, S., Harber, K. D., Stefanucci, J. K., & Proffitt, D. R. 2008. Social support and the
perception of geographical slant. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 44(5),
1246-1255.
Stapleton,—M.—2013.—Steps—to—a— properly—embodied —cognitive—science.—Cognitive Systems
Research 22-23, pp. 1-11.
Thompson, E. 2014. The embodied mind: An interview with Evan Thompson. Fall 2014.
http://www.tricycle.com/interview/embodied-mind
Thompson, E. 2007. Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology and the Sciences of Mind,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Thompson, E. and Stapleton, M. 2009. Making sense of sense-making: Reflections on
enactive and extended mind theories. Topoi 28: 23-30.
Varela, F. J., Thompson, E. and Rosch, E. 1991. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science
and Human Experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.
p. ??