Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2018, Debating Transformations of National Citizenship
…
4 pages
1 file
This paper critiques the notion of birthright citizenship (ius sanguinis), arguing it is a political decision that masks deeper inequalities. Citing authors like Costica Dumbrava and Rainer Bauböck, it challenges the idea that birthright citizenship promotes equality, highlighting the political implications and exclusions inherent in such frameworks. It calls for a re-evaluation of citizenship definitions that prioritizes human rights over established traditions, advocating for more inclusive methods of membership.
Identities, Affiliations, and Allegiances
While the topic of immigration attracts considerable attention, it is by means of birthright, and not naturalization, that approximately 97 percent of the global population acquires political membership. 1 In distributing membership and entitlement, or what Michael Walzer calls "the most important good" 2 within our communities, modern polities have long adhered to a formal, legal connection between entitlement to membership and circumstances of birth. This adherence automatically bequeaths to some a world replete with opportunity and condemns others to a life with little hope. There is no doubt that membership status in any given state or region-with its particular level of wealth, degree of stability, and human rights record-is, even in the current age of increasing globalization and privatization, a crucial factor in the determination of life chances. Political and legal theory has, however, had remarkably little to say about the system of distributive injustice attributable to current birthright citizenship laws. This lacuna is especially surprising in light of recent and vibrant citizenship debates concerning topics closely related to the injustice in question-for example, the claims of minority groups, the narratives of collective-identity formation, and the ethics of political boundaries. These debates engage with what can be referred to as the "identity-bonding" This research was generously supported by grants from the Cecil A. Wright Foundation for Legal Scholarship and the Connaught Research Fellowship in the Social Sciences at the University of Toronto. Earlier versions were presented at the Yale "Identities, Affiliations, and Allegiances" conference; the University of Toronto Faculty of Law "Globalization, Justice, and the Law" workshop; and the American Political Science Annual Meeting, "Questioning the Aspiration to Global Justice" panel. I would like to express thanks to Casiano
Perspectives on Politics, 2011
We inhabit a thoroughly globalized world. People are increasingly and visibly connected by a “World Wide Web,” by a world market, and by universalist discourses of human rights and democracy. At the same time, full citizenship in a political community—and the rights conferred by such citizenship—is an exclusive status that remains, remarkably, tied to accidents of birth and historical circumstance. And what one has a right to—gainful employment, education, health care, political voice, mere presence—is largely a function of whether one has the precious status of citizenship or is, alternatively, regarded as an alien. Ayelet Shachar's The Birthright Lottery: Citizenship and Global Inequality is a compelling account of the moral arbitrariness of this state of affairs. A study in “normative political theory,” it is a work of political science that incorporates legal theory, moral philosophy, political economy, and public policy. The author tackles issues of increasing global politi...
Chapman Law Review, 2020
During the 2020 election cycle, we began to once again hear rumblings that a prominent Democratic candidate for higher office was not really a natural born United States citizen. 1 This charge, advanced by Professor John Eastman 2 as a sincere constitutional question, is ripe to be weaponized against immigrants and their children to question their "American-ness," and the legitimacy of their place in the body politic. Contrary to Professor Eastman's assertions, there is no legitimate question that Senator Kamala Harris 3 is a United States citizen who is eligible to serve as Vice President or President of the United States. She was born in the United States of America. 4 She was not the child of a diplomat or invading soldier not subject to U.S. jurisdiction. Her birth in the United States makes her a natural born American citizen under the Fourteenth Amendment. 5 Arguments to the contrary serve only to further inflame political divisions and attempt to attack political opponents as "un-American." Jus soli, the legal principle of citizenship based on place of birth (with extremely limited exclusions for persons born into a status of legal immunity), has a four-hundred-year old history in Anglo-American jurisprudence. 6 This principle is not only
Issues in Legal Scholarship, 2000
International Journal of Constitutional Law, 2020
Ethical Perspectives, 2014
This paper argues that by overestimating the importance of citizenship rights, the ethics of immigration turns away from the more serious problem of closed borders. Precisely, this contribution is a threefold critique of Carens’ idea that "justice requires that democratic states grant citizenship at birth to the descendants of settled immigrants" (Carens, 2013: 20). Firstly, I argue that by making 'justice' dependent on states and their attributes (birthright citizenship), this idea strengthens methodological nationalism which views humanity as naturally divided into bounded nation-states. Secondly, I analyze its justification and argue that grounding (citizenship) rights on the existence of social connections is logically and morally problematic. Thirdly, I analyze its scope (granting rights to the descendants of the ‘settled’) and its method of implementation (granting citizenship rights automatically ‘at birth’). While from a less sedentarist perspective, no one can be considered ‘settled’ in advance, I will express some doubts that granting citizenship rights is always automatically a way to extend people’s rights. All in all, I argue that by its justification, scope and method of implementation, this idea moves us away from, rather than gets us closer to, an open-borders world.
Ethics & International Affairs, 2010
Globalization and Human Rights, 2002
Noncitizen populations pose a quandary for the administration of human rights because human rights norms have generally been enacted within the nation-state system and administered as the rights of citizens. While the human rights regime is international, its greatest influence has been to establish standards for states’ obligations vis-à-vis their own citizenries. Hence, even in Western states that are vocal champions of human rights, policymakers debate the extent to which they are responsible for protecting the full range of human rights for noncitizen migrants, particularly migrants lacking state authorization. Universal personhood is subordinated to citizenship as a basis for rights. The violations and vulnerabilities of migrant rights in the U.S. can be understood as extensions of a cultural logic in which even human rights are framed as entitlements exclusive to citizens. My analysis suggests that popular and political discourse in this context conceptualizes citizenship less in objective terms (as a legal status) than as a relational identity defined in opposition to “aliens,” particularly in reference to labor migrants from less developed states. This constructed opposition—positioning migrants as lacking a legitimate claim to rights—has two dimensions. The first dimension of the citizen-alien opposition rests on logics grounded in liberal notions of contract and property that position migrants as criminals, trespassers, and usurpers who have forfeited claims to rights by virtue of individual breaches of contract or law. The second reflects a neocolonial logic that legitimates differential claims to rights in accordance with an individual’s position in a racialized international division of labor, equating the privileges that accompany First World status with a greater entitlement to rights. These oppositions between citizens and aliens pose obstacles for migrants’ claims to rights based on universal personhood, even within a state that formally supports international human rights norms.
Law & Social Inquiry, 1994
"Concepts of citizenship have been formulated and thought about for centuries, from Plato and Aristotle to more recent accounts by the likes of Jürgen Habermas and Michael Ignatieff. All of them rely on a particular and divisive view of human nature. The division generalises between those who think that people can lead themselves and those who think that people need to be led by others. But such a division relies on both a misreading of human nature and the classical literature of citizenship and democratic theory. I intend to chart the development of the definition of citizenship and how the theory of citizenship differs from the actuality of citizenship. Part of this process will involve examining and clarifying the various misreadings of citizenship, which continue to this day. Once this is accomplished, it is then possible to look at how the theory of citizenship acts as a “conceptual cover” for the practice of citizenship. States use this “conceptual cover” to discriminate against some of their citizenry. That is, they undermine or completely negate the citizenship rights of some of their citizens, whilst at the same time claiming to respect equally the rights of all citizens under their jurisdiction. How they utilise this cover will be examined in detail within the context of a new theory of citizenship."