A Lockean Theory of Intellectual
Property Revisited
ADAM D. MOORE*
TABLE OF CONTENTS
1.
II.
INTRODUCTION........................................................1070
A LOCKEAN THEORY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY...
.................
1071
A.
B.
III.
PROBLEMS FOR THE PROPOSED LOCKEAN ACCOUNT
A.
B.
C.
D.
E.
IV.
B.
C
D.
........................
1078
................ 1079
Measuring Value..........................
.................. 1082
Baseline Worries....................
FinalThoughts About the Baseline Problem............1086
Mere Use and PossessionRights Objection.............1088
..................... 1090
The Right To Defend Value..........
GENERAL PROBLEMS FOR INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY.....
A.
V.
................ 1073
Bettering, Worsening, and the Baseline Problem
..................... 1076
Illustrations.....................
...............
1091
The Nonrivalrous Argument: But They Still
Have Their Copy!.....................................1091
The FreeSpeech Argument Against
IntellectualProperty...................................1094
The Social Nature ofIntellectual Works Argument
............... 1096
Against IntellectualProperty...............
............ 1099
IntellectualProperty Rights Violate Individual Liberty
CONCLUSION.
..........................................................
101
*This Article was presented at the University of San Diego School of Law Institute
for Law and Philosophy 2012 Editors' Symposium: The Philosophical Foundations of
Intellectual Property conference. I would like to thank Larry Alexander, Steven Smith,
Wendy Gordon, Ken Hirnma, Justin Hughes, David McGowan, Robert Merges, Stephen
Munzer, Randy Picker, Ted Sichelman, Shubha Ghosh, Gary Chartier, and the other
conference participants for providing helpful comments and suggestions. I would also
like to thank the editors of the San Diego Law Review, including Ryan Doyle, Laurel
Gilbert, Tripp May, and Nicholaus Norvell, for all of their help.
1069
I. INTRODUCTION
A general form of Locke's famous argument for property rights includes
self-ownership, labor, value creation, nonwaste, and leaving "enough
and as good" for others.' For Locke, there had to be a process whereby
individuals could unilaterally expand self-ownership rights to include
objects external to one's body, capacities, and powers. Independent of
the consent of one's fellows, individuals could change the moral landscape
by creating property rights. Moreover, this expansion of rights allowed
individuals the moral space to order their lives as they saw fit, resistant
to the demands of society or culture. In this way, Locke offered a view
that was deeply individualistic.2
The primary, and perhaps sole, function of government according to
Locke was to secure and protect the lives, liberties, and property of
individuals who consented, explicitly or tacitly, to a specific political
union. The question that I will address in this Article, and one that I
took up over fifteen years ago, is: should we consider intellectual works
to be the proper subjects of Lockean property claims? My answer then
and now is "yes," with the acknowledgement that such a view may require
substantial revisions to Anglo-American systems of intellectual property.
I will argue that intellectual property rights are no different from rights
to lives, liberties, and estates-that is, intellectual property rights should
not be seen as state-created entities offered as an inducement to bring
forth new knowledge.
The upshot of viewing intellectual property rights as state-created
monopolies, far too often controlled by the powerful and well-connected,
is the seemingly pervasive opinion that systems of intellectual property
represent the mafia family on a global scale. In my view, to be justified
and to warrant worldwide coercion, systems of intellectual property
should be grounded in a Lockean theory of property-a theory that
acknowledges and protects the natural rights of authors and inventors.
Part II of this Article will present the main outlines of a Lockean
theory of intellectual property. Part III will take up several specific
objections that have been leveled against my preferred view. Finally,
Part IV will consider several general objections to intellectual property.
1. JOHN LOCKE, THE SECOND TREATISE OF GOVERNMENT § 27, at 17 (Thomas P.
Peardon ed., Liberal Arts Press, Inc. 1952) (1690).
2. Some scholars deny this claim about Locke. See, e.g., C.B. MACPHERSON, THE
POLITICAL THEORY OF POSSESSIVE INDIVIDUALISM: HOBBES TO LOCKE 1-4 (1962); JAMES
TULLY, A DISCOURSE ON PROPERTY: JOHN LOCKE AND His ADVERSARIES 174-76 (1980);
Lior Zemer, The Making of a New Copyright Lockean, 29 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 891,
912-14 (2006).
1070
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
II. A LOCKEAN THEORY OF INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY 3
Independent of social progress or utility maximization arguments,
John Locke offered what has become known as the "labor theory of
acquisition." Locke claimed, "[fjor this labor being the unquestionable
property of the laborer, no man but he can have a right to what that is
once joined to, at least where there is enough and as good left in
common for others."4 As long as the proviso that "enough and as good
[is] left" is satisfied, an acquisition is of prejudice to no one.
Suppose that mixing one's labor with an unowned object creates a
prima facie claim against others not to interfere that can be overridden
only by a comparable claim. The role of the proviso is to provide one
possible set of conditions where the prima facie claim remains
undefeated.5 Another way of stating this position is that the proviso, in
addition to X, where X is labor or first occupancy or some other weak
claim-generating activity, provides a sufficient condition for original
appropriation.
Justification for the view that labor or possession may generate prima
facie claims against others could proceed along several lines. First,
labor, intellectual effort, and creation are generally voluntary activities
that can be unpleasant, exhilarating, and everything in between.' That
we voluntarily do these things as sovereign moral agents may be enough
to warrant noninterference claims against others.
A second and possibly related justification is based on merit. Sometimes
individuals who voluntarily do or fail to do certain things deserve some
outcome or other. Thus, students may deserve high honor grades and
criminals may deserve punishment. When notions of desert are evoked,
claims and obligations are made against others-these nonabsolute
claims and obligations are generated by what individuals do or fail to do.
3. A longer version of this Part appears in ADAM D. MOORE, INTELLECTUAL
PROPERTY & INFORMATION CONTROL: PHILOSOPHIC FOUNDATIONS AND CONTEMPORARY
ISSUES 71-194 (2001), and Adam D. Moore, A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property,
21 HAMLINE L. REV. 65 (1997).
4. LOCKE, supra note 1, § 27, at 17 (emphasis added).
5. This view is summed up nicely by Clark Wolf, ContemporaryProperty Rights,
Lockean Provisos,and the Interests ofFuture Generations, 105 ETHICS 791, 795 (1995).
6. Ken Himma notes that the creation of intellectual works involves using one of
our most precious commodities-bits of our lives. See Kenneth Einar Himma, Justifying
Intellectual Property Protection: Why the Interests of Content Creators Usually Win
Over Everyone Else's, in INFORMATION TECHNOLOGY AND SOCIAL JUSTICE 47 (Emma
Rooksby & John Weckert eds., 2007).
1071
Thus, in fairly uncontroversial cases of desert, we are willing to
acknowledge that weak claims are generated, and if desert can properly
attach to labor or creation, then claims may be generated in these cases
as well.
Finally, a justification for the view that labor or possession may
generate prima facie claims against others could be grounded in respect
for individual autonomy and sovereignty. As sovereign and autonomous
agents, especially within the liberal tradition, we are afforded the moral
and legal space to order our lives as we see fit. As long as respect for
others is maintained, we are each free to set the course and direction of
our own lives, to choose among various lifelong goals and projects, and
to develop our capacities and talents accordingly. Simple respect for
individuals would prohibit wresting from their hands an unowned object
that they acquired or produced. I hasten to add that at this point we are
trying to justify weak noninterference claims, not full-blown property
rights. Other things being equal, when an individual labors to create an
intellectual work, weak presumptive claims of noninterference have
been generated on grounds of labor, desert, or autonomy.
The underlying rationale of Locke's proviso is that if no one's
situation is worsened, then no one can complain about another individual
appropriating part of the commons. If no one is harmed by an
acquisition and one person is bettered, then the acquisition ought to be
permitted. In fact, it is precisely because no one is harmed that it seems
unreasonable to object to what is known as a Pareto-superior move. 7
Thus, the proviso can be understood as a version of a "no harm, no foul"
principle.
Before continuing, I will briefly consider the plausibility of a Paretobased proviso as a moral principle. First, to adopt a less-than-weak
Pareto principle would permit individuals, in bettering themselves, to
worsen others. Such provisos on acquisition are troubling because at
worst, they may open the door to predatory activity, and at best, they
may give antiproperty theorists the ammunition to combat the weak
presumptive claims that labor and possession may generate. Part of the
7. One state of the world, S;, is Pareto-superior to another, S2, if and only if no
one is worse off in S; than in S2 and at least one person is better off in S, than in S2. S, is
strongly Pareto-superior to S2 if everyone is better off in S, than in S2 and weakly Paretosuperior if at least one person is better off and no one is worse off. State S, is Paretooptimal if no state is Pareto-superior to Sj, strongly Pareto-optimal if no state is weakly
Pareto-superior to it, and weakly Pareto-optimal if no state is strongly Pareto-superior to
it. Throughout this Article I will use Pareto superiority to stand for weak Pareto superiority.
This construction is adapted from G. A. Cohen, The Pareto Argument for Inequality, 12
Soc. PHIL. & POL'Y 160 (1995). The Pareto condition is named after Vilfredo Pareto
(1848-1923), an Italian economist and sociologist.
1072
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
intuitive force of a Pareto-based proviso is that it provides little or no
grounds for rational complaint. Moreover, if we can justify intellectual
property rights with a more stringent principle, a principle that is harder
to satisfy, then we have done something more robust, and perhaps more
difficult to attack, when we reach the desired result.
To require individuals, in bettering themselves, to better others is to
require them to give free rides.8 In the absence of social interaction,
what reason can be given for forcing one person, if she is to benefit
herself, to benefit others?9 If absent social interaction, no benefit is
required, then why is such benefit required within society? The crucial
distinction that underlies this position is between worsening someone's
situation and failing to better it, and I take this intuition to be central to a
kind of deep moral individualism.10 Moreover, the intuition that grounds
a Pareto-based proviso fits well with the view that labor, and possibly
the mere possession of unowned objects, creates a prima facie claim to
those objects. Individuals are worthy of a deep moral respect, and this
grounds a liberty to use and possess unowned objects.
A. Bettering, Worsening, and the Baseline Problem
Assuming a just initial position and that Pareto-superior moves are
legitimate, there are two questions to consider when examining a Paretobased proviso. First, what are the terms of being worsened? This is a
question of scale, measurement, or value. An individual could be
worsened in terms of subjective preference satisfaction, wealth, happiness,
freedoms, opportunities, et cetera. Which of these count in determining
8.
1 have in mind the Robinson Crusoe case in ROBERT NOZICK,
ANARCHY, STATE,
AND UTOPIA 185 (1974).
9.
The distinction between worsening someone's position and failing to better it is a
hotly contested moral issue. See DAVID GAUTHIER, MORALS BY AGREEMENT 204 (1986);
SHELLY KAGAN, THE LIMITS OF MORALITY (1989); John Harris, The Marxist Conception of
Violence, 3 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 192 (1974); John Kleinig, Good Samaritanism, 5 PHIL. & PUB.
AFF. 382 (1976); Eric Mack, Bad Samaritanism and the Causation of Harm, 9 PHIL. & PUB.
AFF. 230 (1980); Eric Mack, Causingand Failing To Prevent,7 Sw. J.PHIL. 83 (1976).
10. This view is summed up nicely by Anthony Fressola:
Yet, what is distinctive about persons is not merely that they are agents, but more,
that they are rational planners-that they are capable of engaging in complex
projects of long duration, of acting in the present to secure consequences in the
relatively distant future, of ordering their diverse actions into programs of activity,
and ultimately, into plans of life.
Anthony Fressola, Liberty andProperty: Reflections on the Right ofAppropriation in the
State ofNature, 18 AM. PHIL. Q. 315, 320 (1981).
1073
moral bettering and worsening? Second, once the terms of being
worsened have been resolved, which two situations are we going to
compare to determine if someone has been worsened? In any question
of harm, we are comparing two states-for example, "now" after an
acquisition compared to "then" or before an acquisition. This is known
as the baseline problem.
In principle, the Lockean theory of intellectual property being
sketched is consistent with a wide range of value theories. So long as
the preferred value theory has the resources to determine bettering and
worsening with reference to acquisitions, Pareto-superior moves can be
made and acquisitions justified on Lockean grounds. For now, assume
an Aristotelian eudaemonist account of value exhibited by the following
theses is correct":
1. Human well-being or flourishing is the sole standard of
intrinsic value.
2. Human persons are rational project pursuers, and well-being
or flourishing is attained through the setting, pursuing, and
completion of life goals and projects.
3. The control of physical and intellectual objects is valuable.
At a specific time, each individual has a certain set of things
she can freely use-and other things she owns-but she also
has certain opportunities to use and appropriate things. This
complex set of opportunities, along with what she can now
freely use or has rights over, constitutes her position
materially-this set constitutes her level of material wellbeing.
Although it is certainly the case that there is more to bettering and
worsening than an individual's level of material well-being, including
opportunity costs, I will not pursue this matter further at present.
Needless to say, a full-blown account of value will explicate all the ways
in which individuals can be bettered and worsened with reference to
acquisition. Moreover, as noted before, it is not crucial to the Lockean
model being presented to defend some preferred theory of value against
all comers. Whatever value theory that is ultimately correct, if it has the
11. For similar views, see ARISTOTLE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS (G.P. Goold ed., H.
Rackham trans., Harvard Univ. Press rev. ed. 1934) (c. 384 B.C.E.); PHILIPPA FOOT, NATURAL
GOODNESS (2001); IMMANUEL KANT, FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSICS OF
MORALS (Thomas K. Abbott trans., Liberal Arts Press, Inc. 1949) (1785); RALPH BARTON
PERRY, GENERAL THEORY OF VALUE: ITS MEANING AND BASIC PRINCIPLES CONSTRUED IN
TERMS OF INTEREST (1926); JOHN RAWLs, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 424-32 (1971); and
HENRY SIDGWICK, THE METHODS OF ETHICS § 4, at 6-11 (7th ed. 1907).
1074
[VOL. 49: 1069,2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectualProperty
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
ability to determine bettering and worsening with reference to acquisitions,
then Pareto-superior moves can be made and acquisitions justified on
Lockean grounds.
Lockeans, as well as others who seek to ground rights to property in
the proviso, generally set the baseline of comparison as the state of
nature. 12 The commons, or the state of nature, is characterized as that
state where the moral landscape has yet to be changed by formal
property relations.13 For now, assume a state of nature situation where
no injustice has occurred and where there are no property relations in
terms of use, possession, or rights. All anyone has in this initial state are
opportunities to increase his material standing. Suppose Fred creates an
intellectual work-perhaps a new gathering technique-and does not
worsen his fellows; alas, all they had were contingent opportunities, and
Fred's creation and exclusion adequately benefits them in other ways.
After the acquisition, Fred's level of material well-being has changed.
Now he has a possession that he holds legitimately, along with all of his
previous opportunities. Along comes Ginger, who creates her own
intellectual work and considers whether her exclusion of it will worsen
Fred. But what two situations should Ginger compare? Should the
effects of Ginger's acquisition be compared to Fred's initial state, where
he had not yet legitimately acquired anything, or to his situation
immediately before Ginger's taking? If bettering and worsening are to
be cashed out in terms of an individual's level of well-being with
opportunity costs, and this measure changes over time, then the baseline
of comparison must also change. In the current case, we compare Fred's
level of material well-being when Ginger possesses and excludes an
intellectual work to his level of well-being immediately before Ginger's
acquisition.
A slightly different way to put this Lockean argument for intellectual
property rights is:
12. Note a common misrepresentation of Locke's view is that in advancing his proviso
on acquisition-those who acquire must leave "enough and as good"-he is talking about
physical objects or things. But this sets up a straw man and ignores Locke's numerous
examples of justified appropriation. For example, taking a good long drink from a river does
remove some "stuff' from common use, but it also does not fail to leave enough and as good.
Locke is advancing a complex view about value and fungibility. If I put a fence around an
apple tree in a forest of other fruit-bearing trees, I have left enough and as good-my
acquisition may have left you, in terms of value, unaffected.
13. See NOZICK, supra note 8, at 172-82; Jeffery M. Gaba, John Locke and the
Meaning ofthe Takings Clause, 72 Mo. L. REV. 525, 533-36 (2007).
1075
Step One: The Generation of Prima Facie Claims to Control.
Suppose Ginger creates a new intellectual work-creation,
effort, et cetera-yielding her prima facie claims to control,
similar to student desert for a grade.
Step Two: Locke's Proviso. If the acquisition of an intellectual
object makes no one else worse off in terms of level of wellbeing compared to how he or she was immediately before the
acquisition, then the taking is permitted.
Step Three: From Prima Facie Claims to Property Rights.
When are prima facie claims to control an intellectual work
undefeated? Answer: When the proviso is satisfied. Alas, no one
else has been worsened-who could complain?
Conclusion: So long as no harm is done, the proviso is
satisfied-the prima facie claims that labor and effort may
generate turn into property claims.
If correct, this account justifies moral claims to control intellectual property
like genetic enhancement techniques, movies, novels, or information.
When an individual creates an intellectual work and fixes it in some
fashion, then labor and possession create a prima facie claim to the work.
Moreover, if the proviso is satisfied, the prima facie claim remains
undefeated and moral claims or rights are generated.
B. Illustrations
Consider the simplest of cases. After weeks of effort and numerous
failures, suppose I come up with an excellent recipe for spicy Chinese
noodles-a recipe that I keep in my mind and do not write down.
Would anyone argue that I do not have at least some minimal moral
claim to control the recipe? Suppose that you sample some of my
noodles and desire to purchase the recipe. Is there anything morally
suspicious with an agreement between us that grants you a limited right
to use my recipe provided that you do not disclose the process? Alas,
you did not have to agree to my terms, and no matter how tasty the
noodles, you could eat something else.
Here at the micro level, we get the genesis of moral claims to
intellectual works independent of social progress or incentive-based
arguments. Also, it should be highlighted that, like other rights and
moral claims, effective enforcement or protection may be a matter left to
governments-protection of rights is one thing, while the existence of
rights is another.
1076
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
Consider a second case. Suppose Fred, in a fit of culinary brilliance,
scribbles down a new recipe for spicy Chinese noodles and then forgets
the essential ingredients. Ginger, who loves spicy Chinese food, sees
Fred's note and snatches it away from him. Under my view of Locke's
theory, the proviso has been satisfied by Fred's action, and Ginger has
violated Fred's right to control the collection of ideas that compose the
recipe. We may ask, "What legitimate reason could Ginger have for
taking Fred's recipe rather than creating her own?" If Ginger has no
comparable claim, then Fred's prima facie claim remains undefeated.
We can complicate this case by imagining that Fred has perfect
memory, and so Ginger's theft does not leave Fred deprived of that
which he created. It could be argued that what is wrong with the first
version of this case is that Fred lost something that he created and may
not be able to recreate-Ginger betters herself, without justification, at
the expense of Fred. In the second version of the case, Fred has not lost
and Ginger has gained, and so there is apparently nothing wrong with
her actions.14 But from a moral standpoint, the accuracy of Fred's
memory is not relevant to his rights to control the recipe, and so this case
poses no threat to the proposed theory. Moreover, the fact that intellectual
property rights are hard to protect has no bearing on the existence of the
rights themselves. Similarly, that it is almost impossible to prevent a
trespasser from walking on your land has no bearing on your property
rights. In creating the recipe and not worsening Ginger compared to the
baseline, Fred's presumptive claim is undefeated and thus creates a duty
of noninterference on others. In both versions of this case, Fred has lost
the value of control and the control of the value that he created.
Rather than creating a recipe, suppose Fred writes a computer program
and Ginger simultaneously creates a program that is in large part a
duplicate of Fred's. To complicate things further, imagine that each will
produce and distribute the software with the hopes of capturing the
market and that Fred has signed a distribution contract that will enable
him to swamp the market and keep piinger from selling her product. If
opportunities to better oneself are included in the account of bettering
and worsening, then it could be argued that Fred violates the proviso
because in controlling and marketing the software he effectively
14. This case trades on the nonrivalrousness of intellectual works-unlike an apple, we
both can benefit from a recipe. The force of nonrivalrous arguments against intellectual
property will be considered below. See infra Part IV.A.
1077
eliminates Ginger's potential profits. The problem this case highlights is
that what individuals do with their possessions can affect the opportunities
of others in a negative way. If so, then worsening has occurred and no
duties of noninterference have been created. In cases of competition, it
seems that the proviso may yield the wrong result.
This is just to say that the proviso, as I have interpreted it, is set too
high or that it is overly stringent. In some cases where we think that
rights to intellectual property should be justified, it turns out, on the
theory being presented, that they are not. But surely this is no deep
problem for the theory. In the worst light, it has not been shown that the
proviso is not sufficient but only that it is overly stringent. And given
what is at stake-the means to survive, flourish, and pursue lifelong
goals and projects-stringency may be a good thing. Nevertheless,
the competition problem represents a type of objection that poses a
significant threat to the theory being developed. If opportunities are
valuable, then any single act of acquisition may extinguish one or a
number of opportunities of one's fellows. Obviously, this need not be
the case every time, but if this worsening occurs on a regular basis, then
the proposed theory will leave unjustified a large set of acquisitions that
we intuitively think should be justified.
Before concluding this brief overview of a Lockean theory of
intellectual property, I would like to discuss a strategy for answering the
competition problem and related concerns. Continuing with the Fred
and Ginger example, it seems plausible to maintain that her complaints
are, in a way, illicit. The very opportunities that Ginger has lost because
of Fred's business savvy are dependent on the institution of property
relations that allows Fred to beat her to market. Moreover, her
opportunities include the possibility of others undercutting her potential
profits. Contingent opportunities are worth less than their results, and so
compensation will be less than it would seem. Compensation for
worsening could proceed at two levels. In acquiring some object, Fred
himself could better Ginger's position, or the system that they both
operate within could provide compensation. This is just to say that it
does not matter whether the individual compensates or the system
compensates; the agent in question is not worsened.
1II. PROBLEMS FOR THE PROPOSED LOCKEAN ACCOUNT
While admittedly brief and incomplete, the sketch of the Lockean
model of intellectual property offered above indicates the strengths of
such an account. I will now turn to several specific objections that have
been leveled against this account. My hope is to address these worries
and thereby further strengthen and clarify the view.
1078
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectualProperty
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
A. Measuring Value
On the account that I have sketched, moral bettering and worsening
are to be measured in term of an individual's level of material wellbeing. As I have argued elsewhere, this view is both objective and
An objective account of value holds that value exists
relational."
independent of human affective states. As I have stated, "[T]here are
reasons for action, and we have to discover them instead of deriving
them from our preexisting desires or preferences."' 7 A relationalist
about value claims that value is always related to objects-persons,
groups, or times, for example.' More specifically, I have argued that
moral value is species-relative.' 9 What is valuable for human beings
may not extend to nonhuman animals or other living entities, and viceversa.
Subjective accounts of moral value, on the other hand, hold that value
is conferred on an otherwise valueless state of the world by our
preferences and desires. David Gauthier, a subjectivist about value,
writes:
Value does not afford a single uniform measure of preference but a measure
relative to each valuer. And although values are ascribed to states of affairs,
the ascription is attitudinal, not observational, subjective, not objective. As a
measure of preference value is and must be contingent on preferences for its
very existence. 20
I believe that such views fall prey to the problems of arbitrariness,
preference manipulation, and value elitism. In any case, a presentation
and defense of my preferred account of value is beyond the scope of this
Article. Instead, I will focus on some of the common mistakes that
scholars have made with how we measure moral bettering and
worsening. Consider the following case presented by Jeremy Waldron:
Suppose Q is dying of a disease for which he knows there is no cure; he
resigns himself to his fate and prepares for a stoic death. Then the news comes
in: a drug has been developed which will remit the disease. The person who
ADAM D. MOORE, PRIVACY RIGHTS: MORAL AND LEGAL FOUNDATIONS 34 (2010)
15.
[hereinafter MOORE, PRIVACY RIGHTS]; Adam D. Moore, Values, Objectivity, and
Relationalism, 38 J. VALUE INQUIRY 75 (2004).
16. MOORE, PRIVACY RIGHTS, supra note 15, at 35.
17.
18.
19.
Id. at 38.
See id.
Id.
20.
GAUTHIER, supra note 9, at 25.
1079
made and tested it, P, did so in his own laboratory with his own hands using
his own materials. P makes the drug available to a number of his friends, but
excludes Q because he dislikes Q's politics. Clearly Q will suffer something as
a result of this. instead of the stoic death he prepared for, it is likely that the
rest of his life will be spent in painful bitterness and anger as he endures the
thought that he might have lived and flourished but will not, thanks to P's
exercise of this exclusionary right. 2 1
Waldron concludes, "Material loss, relative to a given baseline, need not
be the only sort of hardship people experience. . . . Q is not feigning his
distress ....
bitterness ....
There is real misery that could be relieved, a real
22
Acknowledging that Q may indeed have suffered mental distress,
frustrated preferences, and painful bitterness does not establish morally
relevant harm. Switching the case slightly drives this point home. Suppose
that Q and P are lovers and P ends the relationship so that she can have
other partners. Q may suffer mental distress, frustrated preferences, and
painful bitterness, but few would maintain that he has been morally
worsened by P's actions.
A critic, perhaps Waldron, may charge that these cases are importantly
different. In the first case, we are considering the generation of a
property right, while in the second case we are considering what someone
may do with her property-in this case, her body. The second case may
be an example of self-ownership rights or liberty rights trumping the
morally relevant suffering of Q.23
Nevertheless, this reply does not solve the worry. Imagine that P was
not a self-owner or in possession of liberty rights. However contentious,
suppose that P has sold her liberty rights and self-ownership rights to a
third party and is seeing Q "on the side," so to speak. When P ends the
relationship and causes Q's heartfelt misery, Waldron would seem to be
driven to conclude that P has done something morally blameworthy.
A strength of an objective account of moral bettering and worsening is
that we can resist this conclusion.
Consider a different case. Suppose Fred and Ginger inhabit a two-person
world and neither has established rights to anything, including their own
bodies, capacities, and powers. Fred, however, prefers that Ginger not
21. Jeremy Waldron, From Authors to Copiers: Individual Rights and Social Values in
IntellectualProperty, 68 CHI.-KENT L. REv. 841, 866 (1993) (emphasis omitted).
22. Id. at 867.
23. Suppose Q wakes every morning and obtains peace and serenity by staring at a
beautiful fir tree growing in the commons across the valley. After a series of unforeseen
accidents, P destroys this tree, causing Q to suffer greatly. Or suppose P chops down the
unowned tree and hauls it away to make his house. Sure, we may all agree that Q's suffering
is important and should be met with some compassion, and yet deny that P has done
anything morally blameworthy in each of these cases.
1080
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
use or control her body, capacities, or powers. In fact, suppose this
preference consumes him and generally centers his world. If bettering
and worsening are couched in terms of subjective preferences, like
painful bitterness or misery, then in controlling her body, capacities, and
powers, Ginger worsens Fred's situation. Put aside for a moment the
baseline-how Fred would be were Ginger absent. The question at hand
is why would Fred's arbitrary, and perhaps silly, preference matter in
any way when determining value and bettering or worsening? 24
Sometimes this sort of attack against Lockean accounts of intellectual
property comes in terms of frustrated interests. For example, Wendy
Gordon presents a case where a preacher harms the interests of his
followers by restricting access to an original text:
[S]uppose a preacher instructs his flock to follow precepts that he claims are
based on divinely inspired writings, and his audience does in fact follow these
rules. Perhaps the precepts contain a ban on birth control, or perhaps a general
ban on seeking the help of doctors... . If the doubters in the congregation
cannot quote, print, and distribute to like-minded persons the portions of the
only or best one,
writings that suggest the preacher's interpretation is not the 25
the doubters and those whose interests they serve are harmed.
Perhaps Gordon is using the term interests in an objective way-as a
measure of material well-being or species-based flourishing. If so, then
I would have no objection. In most cases, however, authors use the term
as a subjective notion synonymous with desire, preference, or want. If
we want to avoid the view that Fred's mere interests, desires, or
preferences in having access to Ginger's body have moral standing, then
we need some defensible method for ruling out such preferences. Absent
some such method, these accounts of moral bettering and worsening are
problematic because they are too broad.
24. The reply usually voiced at this point is that the worry depends on an "odd" or
irrational preference. If we rule out such preferences, there is no problem. While initially
plausible, I have yet to come across any generally accepted procedure that tells us which
preferences count that does not also introduce an "objectifying" element into the
account. See MOORE, PRIVACY RIGHTS, supra note 15, at 34-35.
25. Wendy J. Gordon, A Property Right in Self-Expression: Equality and
Individualism in the Natural Law of Intellectual Property, 102 YALE L.. 1533, 1568
(1993) (emphasis added).
1081
B. Baseline Worries
Probably the most common worry that has been leveled against the
Lockean view that I have defended focuses on the baseline of
comparison. On the account being offered, we determine if worsening
has occurred by comparing two states-how someone is before and after
an act of creation and exclusion. Consider the Chinese noodles example
once again. Prior to my act of creation, the recipe did not exist, so there
was no way for others to be worsened because of lack of access. After
my creation, others are still without access, so there has been no
lessening of flourishing or well-being.
Opponents have rejected this baseline and proposed others.2 6
Consider a different case. What if a perverse inventor creates a geneticenhancement technique that cures cancer, but decides to keep the
technique secret or charge excessive prices for access? This case is
similar to Waldron's P and Q example mentioned above.27 Those
individuals who had, before the creation, no chance to survive now have
a chance and are worsened because of the perverse inventor's refusal to
let others use the machine.
The baseline this case implies cannot be correct. On this view, to
determine bettering and worsening, we compare how individuals are
before the creation of some value-in this case, the genetic enhancement
technique-to how they would be if they possessed or consumed that
value. 28 But we are all worsened in this respect by any value that is held
exclusively. I am worsened by your exclusive possession of your car
because I would be better off if I exclusively controlled the car-even if
I already owned hundreds of cars. If this were the correct comparison,
then my exclusive possession of my heart-a value-would worsen
others who did not have possession and exclusive title. All individuals,
especially those who have faulty hearts, would be better off if they held
title to my heart compared to anyone else's holding the title. Moreover,
this would be true independent of anyone's choices. Imagine that you
voluntarily toss your dinner into a vat of acid and then complain to me
that I am worsening you because I, who happen to have two dinners,
refuse to give you one. Clearly, this account of the baseline makes the
notions of bettering and worsening too broad. Simple failures to benefit
26. See id.; Waldron, supra note 21, at 866.
27. Waldron, supra note 21, at 866.
28. This sort of baseline confusion infects Professor Colin Farrelly's argument that
social justice considerations lower the threshold for overriding intellectual property and
privacy rights. Colin Farrelly, Genes and Social Justice: A Rawlsian Reply to Moore, 16
BIOETHIcs 72, 75 (2002).
1082
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
cannot constitute morally relevant worsenings that may in turn justify
moral or legal sanctions.
Reconsider Waldron's case where P creates a cure for cancer and
excludes Q from the drug.2 9 Rather than focusing on the measure that
Waldron selected-painful bitterness-consider the baseline. In Waldron's
case we compare how Q is prior to the creation of the cure to how he is
after the creation. Before, Q is not doing so well, but after, he is doing
even worse. Rather than considering the distribution of value in two
states, we compare the distribution of disvalue.
It should be obvious that Waldron's baseline in this case is too
broad-determining moral bettering and worsening with this comparison
will get it wrong. For example, on this account, when Jones fails to take
a punch for Smith, Jones has worsened Smith. Smith compares how he
is having been punched by some third party to how he would be if Jones
had suffered the punch.
Consider the case where Fred says to Ginger, "I will save your life,
but only if you become my house servant." Independent of whether this
is a coercive threat or offer, we may ask at least two important questions.
First, assuming that Ginger does not indicate agreement with the offer,
does Fred's inaction-and Ginger's subsequent death-worsen her?
Second, would Ginger's agreement under duress and subsequent failure
to comply with Fred's terms constitute a harm to Fred? Assuming that
there are no other moral obligations in force, Fred's inaction and
Ginger's death would not constitute a morally relevant harm. If they
did, then any inaction where some action could prevent a harm would
violate this baseline and constitute a morally relevant worsening.
I hasten to note that I do not deny the possibility of positive obligations
existing among individuals where failure to live up to an obligation
would constitute a morally relevant worsening. What I deny is that such
positive obligations exist between any two individuals or groups of
individuals regardless of history, circumstance, agreement, or prior
choices.
Taking up the second question, I would argue that Ginger's agreement
under duress and subsequent failure to comply with Fred's terms do not
constitute a harm to Fred. Fred's baseline does not include all the
benefits he could secure through "forced" contracts any more than
Ginger's baseline includes all the benefits she could obtain if others gave
29.
See Waldron, supra note 21, at 866.
1083
her things. To put the point another way, Ginger has a legitimate
complaint against Fred's insistence that she has agreed to and therefore
should become his servant.
Moreover, those of us who fail to aid others or prevent harms to others
have a legitimate complaint as well. Why should our lives be subject to
the demands of others without conditions? Suppose I could easily reach
out, take an apple, and eat it-thus providing myself sustenance-but
fail to do so. It seems quite implausible to say that in this case, those
who fail to act and provide the apple have harmed me.
Shelly Kagan's King and Queen case3 o provides an interesting challenge
to "moment before compared to moment after baselines." Suppose that
while eating dinner, the Queen begins to choke and the King rushes to
her aid. As he pounds her on the back in an attempt to dislodge the food,
he also deliberately stabs her in the leg. While her life is saved, the
Queen's leg is severely damaged.3 1 The problem should be obvious.
Prior to the King's action, the Queen was going to choke to death, while
after his action she is going to live, albeit hobbled. So by simultaneously
saving her and stabbing her, the King does not worsen the Queen. Yet
there is something wrong about saying that the King bettered, or at least
did not worsen, the Queen in this case.
Such examples trade on a difficulty in describing acts. We could
describe the action in this case numerous ways: the King saved the
Queen's life by pounding her on the back and dislodging the food; the
King stabbed the Queen in the leg; the King exhaled, jumped three feet
across the room, dropping his napkin, and hit the Queen in the back
while imagining how his actions would cause others to worship him as a
hero; and so on. I hope it is clear that simply because there is practically
an infinite number of ways to describe an action it does not follow that
each description is equally good.32
Taken by itself, the first action, dislodging the food that the Queen
was choking on, would pass the proviso, while the second, stabbing the
Queen in the leg, would not. It is not as if these two actions must come
30.
31.
See KAGAN, supra note 9, at 97.
Id.
32. Eric D'Arcy and David Lyons both independently develop answers to the
problem of act description. In general, their theories distinguish between acts, circumstances,
and consequences. The solution that both seem to advocate is that we use moral norms
to determine the relevant description of a particular act. Because utilitarians are concerned
with the goodness of consequences, we should describe an act in such a way that all the
relevant consequences are included. See ERIC D'ARcY, HUMAN ACTS: AN ESSAY IN
THEIR MORAL EVALUATION
UTILITARIANISM 30-61 (1965).
1084
1-61 (1963); DAVID LYONS, FORMS AND LIMITS OF
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
together-as if a necessary part of the act of saving included the act of
stabbing. If it did, then there would be no worsening.
Also, this case, along with many of the others that have been
discussed, tends to trade on our moral feelings in an illicit way-there is
a moral swamping phenomenon present. Perhaps the moral aversion we
have with these cases has more to do with the intentions and sentiments
of the agents involved than a rejection of a specific baseline. The King
does not have to stab the Queen to save her, and Waldron's P seems like
an ass by excluding Q from a cancer cure for political reasons. Take a
less emotionally charged example. Friday comes along and he has a
choice to do nothing and allow a piano to fall and be destroyed, or he
could prevent the piano from being damaged. Beyond this, Friday
knows nothing else about the piano-for all he knows, destroying the
piano is exactly what the owner wants. Friday does nothing and the
piano is destroyed. Crusoe, the owner, confronts Friday and declares
that he has lost something of value-Friday's inaction has caused a loss
of value for Crusoe. Again, such baselines appear too broad.
A different sort of swamping occurs when we test a baseline with a
case that is based upon unjust actions-these cases are morally loaded in
a different way, but nonetheless swamp our moral intuitions. Take the
case where Friday punches Crusoe in the face several times and is about
to make a second round of swings. Crusoe protects himself by striking
first. Few would deny that Crusoe has harmed Friday in this case. But it
is equally true that few would maintain that this harm constitutes a moral
worsening. 33 An example of swamping is also found in the following
case presented by Gordon:
[A]ssume that A takes substances from the common from which, with great
ingenuity, she manufactures an enzyme that greatly improves one's health.
Because of its salutary properties, a decision is made to include the enzyme
in the drinking water. The benefits, however, come at the cost of a particular
form of addiction: some people who drink the enzyme become unable to
metabolize carbohydrates without continued intake of this elixir. To people so
33. James Wilson's dismissal of what he calls a nonnormative baseline provides a
different sort of mistake. Historical baselines, now compared to some point in the past, are
rejected en masse because of the case where slave owners would be harmed by legislative
changes that outlaw slavery. But this is precisely why theorists who defend such accounts use
examples where there are no moral obligations or injustices in place. As discussed, there is a
moral-swamping phenomenon present that clouds our judgments. A baseline that concludes
that slave owners are morally harmed with emancipation legislation just cannot be correct.
See James Wilson, Could There Be a Right To Own Intellectual Property?, 28 LAW & PIL.
393, 406 (2009).
1085
affected, ordinary food becomes valueless for nourishment-it is useless
unless eaten along with the enzyme. In such a case, the fact that the common
continues to have an ample supply of both food and the elements from which
the enzyme can be made is not sufficient to protect the public from harm. The
addicted public also needs A's knowledge of how the enzyme is manufactured,
for without it, they will starve in the midst of plenty. If, after the enzyme is put
into the water supply, the inventor is given a right to prohibit others from using
are worse
her manufacturing technique, addicted members of the community
34
off in their ability to use the common than they were before.
My first question when considering this case was, did everyone agree to
have the enzyme included in the drinking water? Gordon merely says "a
decision [was] made." Suppose not. Suppose this is just an example of
a foisted benefit with a huge risk attached. I would agree that if this
benefit and risk were foisted, then withdrawing the enzyme after
numerous individuals have become addicted and causing their deaths
would be a morally relevant harm. But suppose, on the other hand,
Jimmy, the risk taker, agreed to ingest the enzyme along with all the
associated risks. Now it is not at all clear that our inventor, A, has done
something wrong when she decides to remove the product from
circulation.35 Simply put, without the past injustice of the foisted benefit,
risk, and addiction, there would be no morally relevant worsening.
C. Final Thoughts About the Baseline Problem
As the cases discussed indicate, we need to be cautious when testing a
specific baseline. Moreover, providing an argument for a particular
baseline-independent of the case-based strategy I have used above-is
difficult, although I have attempted such an argument elsewhere.36
Nevertheless, there are some general guidelines that fall out of the
discussion so far.
First, any baseline that offers a simple comparison of having some
value to not having it, or having some disvalue to having more disvalue
or no disvalue, is not suitable. All of these baselines fail because they do
not take into account the free choices and actions of individuals. Again,
suppose I could easily reach out, take an apple, and eat it-thus providing
myself sustenance-but fail to do so. It seems quite implausible to say
that in this case those who fail to act and provide the apple have morally
harmed me. If so, when Jones fails to take a punch for Smith or if I fail
34. Gordon, supra note 25, at 1567.
35. This possibility would be a good reason for Jimmy to never agree to becoming
addicted in the first place-or a reason to insist on learning how to make the enzyme
himself or having a lifetime supply, et cetera.
36. See MOORE, PRIVACY RIGHTS, supra note 15, at 63-66.
1086
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectualProperty
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
to provide you dinner after you have destroyed your own, morally
relevant worsenings will have occurred. These baselines are too broad.
Another important restriction is that baselines should be tied to the
measure or account of value being employed. Suppose pleasure and
pain are the measures, and we compare how Smith is now after Linda
punches him in the face with his state two weeks ago when he was in a
car wreck and in great pain. Because Smith is better off now in
terms of pain compared to immediately after the wreck, we would
conclude that he has not been worsened by Linda's punch. But this
cannot be correct-we have the wrong baseline.
Although I remain skeptical, consider a different measure-suppose
some version of preference theory is correct. Because preferences
change over time, baselines that do not reflect these changes will not
work. Suppose we compare my level of preference satisfaction now to
some week when I had massive preference frustration. In such a case,
you would be able to frustrate most or all of my current preferences
because your actions would not drive my preference levels below what
they were during the comparison week. Thus, if the measure changesif it is dynamic rather than static-then the baseline of comparison must
also change.
We must also take care to avoid different swamping phenomena or
morally loaded situations that predetermine some result we desire.
Simultaneously saving and crippling someone or being overly callous
with the health or well-being of others are not positions from which we
arrive at cool and reflective endorsement of some principle of moral
worsening.
Consider,
once
again,
the
baseline
that
I
have
offered.
We
determine
if moral worsening has occurred by comparing an individual's level of
well-being or flourishing after the act in question to how they were
immediately before the action. In the case of intellectual property, we
are considering the moments before and after an act of creation and
exclusion.3 7 It is important to note that we also must take a morally
37. Take the simplest of cases-what I call a face-puncher case. In a morally
neutral world with no past injustices, wrongs, or provocations, suppose Ginger punches
Fred in the face. We compare Fred's state after the punch to before and conclude that
Ginger's action has morally worsened Fred. To be sure, we could complicate this case.
Assume that prior to Ginger's punch, Fred was in great pain-so great that a punch from
Ginger would have no overall effect. We could also complicate the case by assuming
that Fred cannot feel pain, is compensated by Ginger after the fact, or has agreed to being
1087
neutral stance in considering the appropriateness of this or any baseline.
Assuming no past injustice, moral wrongs, or bad choices, and insisting
on a defensible measure, we can clear away much of the rubbish that has
been offered concerning baselines for determining moral bettering and
worsening.3 8
D. Mere Use and PossessionRights Objection
A different sort of objection to the view that I have defended centers
on the type of rights generated by labor and nonworsening. According
to this worry, my Lockean account generates nothing more than use and
possession claims for authors and inventors. Use and possession claims
fall well short of the bundle of rights associated with full ownership.
Full legal ownership includes:
1. The right to possess-that is, to [enjoy] exclusive physical control of the
thing owned ....
2. The right to use-that is, to personal enjoyment and use ....
3. The right to manage-that is, to decide how and by whom [the object] shall be
used.
4. The right to the income-that is, to [enjoy] the benefits derived from
foregoing personal use . . ..
5. The right to the capital-that is, the power to alienate the thing and
to consume, waste, modify, or destroy it.
6. The right to security-that is, immunity from expropriation.
7. The power of transmissibility-that is, the power to devise or bequeath the
[object].
8. The absence of term-that is, the indeterminate length of one's ownership
rights.
9. The prohibition of harmful use-that is, one's duty to forbear from using
the thing [to harm] others.
10. Liability to execution-that is, liability to having the thing taken away for
repayment of a debt.
11. Residuary character-that is the existence of rules governing the reversion
of lapsed ownership rights.W
punched. Nevertheless, as a first step, we need to get the easy cases correct and then
move on to more difficult ones.
38. Perhaps John Rawls's original position may be of some service here. According to
Rawls, we pick the principles of justice that will determine the benefits and burdens of
social interaction from a situation where individuals are ignorant of their real-life
concems-they are behind a veil of ignorance that ensures an unbiased choice situation.
RAWLS, supra note 11, at 12. Rather than picking principles of justice from this position,
suppose we were trying to determine the correct baseline and measure for analyzing
moral bettering and worsening. Arguably many of the considerations that I note would
be confirmed by such an analysis.
39. LAWRENCE C. BECKER, PROPERTY RIGHTS: PHILOSOPHIC FOUNDATIONS 19
(1977); see also A. M. Honord, Ownership, in OXFORD ESSAYS IN JURISPRUDENCE:
A COLLABORATIVE WORK 107, 113 (A. G. Guest ed., 1961) (describing these eleven
rights as the "leading incidents" of property ownership).
1088
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
At best, so the objection goes, the Lockean account under consideration
provides a compelling rationale for (1) and (2)-we get nowhere near
(3) through (11).40
First, it should be noted that the Lockean account under consideration
is not intended to establish full legal ownership of intellectual works.
By my lights, if exclusive use, possession, and management rights could
be justified, that would be good enough.
Second, in a range of cases, this sort of objection might simply be
false. On my view, authors and inventors-on the basis of use and
possession claims along with a general right to make contracts-may
justifiably bargain for the rights codified in (3) through (11). In small
communities it may even be possible to contract with all of one's
fellows, securing all or some of the bundle of full ownership. In this sort
of example, every single member of the community would be directly part
of the agreement. Ginger says to her peers, "If you want access to my
recipe, then you will have to agree to my right to enjoy income," and
they reply, "But such rights cannot be indefinite-we as a community
will not be on the hook for defending this agreement indefinitely." In
the ensuing give-and-take, an agreement is hammered out. It is
important to note that the moral bindingness of such an agreement is
crucially dependent on the initial set of entitlement claims generated by
labor, desert, and nonworsening. If Ginger, in this case, was not the
author of the recipe-suppose she took it from someone else-it is not at
all clear that the resulting contract would be morally or legally binding.4'
Moving from small communities to larger ones, we can consider a
more general form of agreement among authors, inventors, and society.
If intellectual works are to be held as anything other than trade secrets,
walled off with narrow contracts like nondisclosure agreements or
noncompetition arrangements, there must be a way of securing access.
Society may purchase access by offering limited rights to authors and
inventors. Moreover, if some society does not offer this sort of
40. I would like to thank Wendy Gordon for this objection.
41. Justin Hughes offered the following counterexample to this view. Suppose
indigenous person X is in possession of some intellectual work B. Xis in possession of B
via theft or fraud. Along comes Y, who obtains an agreement regarding the use of B.
Yagrees to the terms in question because X either threatens Y with a poison dart-gun or
promises to destroy or hide B. Although it is true that Y may indeed agree to a set of
ownership policies regarding X and B, it is not at all clear that this agreement morally or
legally binds Y. To see this, switch the case to one where X is a mafia thug who is in
possession of powerful weapons and stolen intellectual works.
1089
protection, innovators would likely employ their talents in other areas or
simply move to a society where such agreements are recognized. Rather
than a contract between some inventor and each member of her community,
we imagine a more general agreement among inventors and the larger
society where they reside. In either case, the relatively modest claims
secured by labor, desert, and nonworsening may be strengthened into
full or nearly full property claims.
E. The Right To Defend Value
While admittedly speculative and independent of agreements among
citizens or innovators and society, there is at least one other argument
that might establish exclusivity beyond possession and use. Imagine that
Smith has spent days working on an artifact that has great value in terms
of providing for human well-being. Assuming the proviso is passed-as
I have construed it-and the other conditions are satisfied, we may claim
that Smith has use and possession rights to the artifact. Smith wanders
off and returns to find Jones has taken possession of the artifact. In
reply to various warnings, Jones simply claims that all of Smith's efforts
to create the artifact in question yield nothing more than mere use and
possession claims-claims that vanish once Smith has given up immediate
possession.
I would argue that this is incorrect for two reasons. First, Smith has
invested part of his life in creating the artifact. By itself, it would seem
that such effort should yield stronger moral claims than what is asserted
by Jones when he takes possession. There is a moral difference-one
has invested part of his life while the other has simply taken possession.
Moreover, Smith can justifiably complain in a way that Jones cannot.
Had Smith not created or had Smith never given up possession of the
artifact, Jones's position would remain unchanged. This is not true
when Jones takes possession.
Second, given the investment, it may be reasonable for Smith to
defend the value in question from Jones or anyone else. Jones may
destroy the artifact or treat it harshly given that he has not invested
anything significant in its creation or maintenance. If we assume that
bits of our lives-the time we invest-are one of the most valuable of
commodities we control, then on grounds of self-defense we may insist
that Smith has the right to defend the value that he created. When Jones
unjustifiably attacks Smith, most would agree that self-defense would be
an option. Smith has the right to defend his body, capacities, and powers
from the attack. Certainly, for Smith, his body, capacities, and powers
are valuable, and it is appropriate that he defend these values. By
extension, Smith would be permitted to defend the artifact that he
1090
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectualProperty
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
created from Jones, and a step toward exclusivity will have been
established. Although it is true that we are far from justifying full legal
ownership, which may fall out of the social contract view already
discussed, we have nonetheless secured exclusive use and possession
claims that hold independent of immediate possession.
IV. GENERAL PROBLEMS FOR INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY
Assuming the account offered so far is compelling, there are several
general arguments against intellectual property and systems of intellectual
property protection to consider. This is important because it could be
that intellectual property rights are overridden by competing or weightier
moral claims.
A. The NonrivalrousArgument: But They Still Have Their Copy!42
A common argument given by scholars who defend "free access" is
that making a copy does not deprive anyone of their possessions.
Intangible works are nonrivalrous, meaning that they can be used and
consumed by many individuals concurrently. Edwin Hettinger argues:
The possession or use of an intellectual object by one person does not
preclude others from possessing or using it as well. If someone borrows your
lawn mower, you cannot use it, nor can anyone else. But if someone borrows
your recipe for guacamole, that in no way precludes you, or anyone else, from
using it. This feature is shared by all sorts of intellectual objects ....
This characteristic of intellectual objects grounds a strong prima facie case
against the wisdom of private and exclusive intellectual property rights. Why
should one person have the exclusive right to possess and use something that
all people could possess and use concurrently? ...
43
... [T]he unauthorized taking of an intellectual object does not feel like theft.
Consider a more formal version of this argument:
42. For an interesting analysis of this argument, see Kenneth Einar Himma,
Abundance, Rights, and Interests: Thinking About the Legitimacy of Intellectual
Property Rights, in ETHICS OF NEW INFORMATION TECHNOLOGY: PROCEEDINGS OF THE
SIXTH INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE OF COMPUTER ETHICS: PHILOSOPHICAL ENQUIRY
(Philip Brey et al. eds., 2005), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?
abstract id=727469.
Edwin C. Hettinger, Justifying Intellectual Property, in INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY:
43.
MORAL, LEGAL, AND INTERNATIONAL DILEMMAS 17, 20 (Adam D. Moore ed., 1997)
(footnotes omitted).
1091
Pl. If a tangible or intangible work can be used and
consumed by many individuals concurrently (nonrivalrous),
then access and use should be permitted.
P2. Intellectual works falling under the domains of copyright,
patent, and trade secret protection are nonrivalrous.
C3. So it follows that there is an immediate prima facie case
against intellectual property rights or for allowing access to
intellectual works.
The weak point in this argument is the first premise-especially given
that the second premise is generally true.4 Consider sensitive personal
information. It seems patently false to claim that just because this
information can be used and consumed by many individuals concurrently
that there is a prima facie moral claim that this be so. Snuff films,
obscene pornography, information related to national security, personal
financial information, and private thoughts are each nonrivalrous.
Nevertheless, this fact does not, by itself, generate prima facie moral
claims for maximal access and use.
Hettinger would likely reply that these sorts of examples would
violate a "no harm, no foul" rule that underlies this argument. Taking
personal information from someone harms them in a way that copying
intellectual works does not. This view lies at the heart of the Lockean
argument establishing intellectual property rights. But consider a case
provided by Don Hubin and Mark Lambeth:
Dr. Demento ... has discovered a drug that will put people into a trance for
eight hours and rejuvenate their bodies so that they need no sleep. The fiendish
doctor realizes that he has a way to use the bodies of others without making
them any worse off than they would be in his absence. ... In addition to
making his temporary zombies work in his lab at night, he engages in vile and
disgusting sex acts with them which he videotapes . . . [and] then sells the
tapes at great profit in foreign countries. 45
Arguably, Demento's actions are immoral even though, ex hypothesi, no
harm has been done to his subjects. Similarly, a Peeping Tom may
engage in immoral activity without harming his victims-perhaps there
will be no consequences to the victims and they will never know of the
peeping.
44. Some kinds of information are rivalrously consumed-for example, stock tips, et
cetera.
45. Donald C. Hubin & Mark B. Lambeth, Providingfor Rights, 27 DIALOGUE
489, 495 (1988).
1092
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory of IntellectualProperty
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
More forcefully, however, if Demento's victims have moral claims to
control their own bodies, then they will be worsened by his activity-a
moral claim or obligation will have been violated and certain risks
imposed without consent.
In summary, the claim that access should be allowed and perhaps
promoted for goods that are nonrivalrous is without merit. Intangible
works of all sorts are nonrivalrous, including sensitive personal information,
financial records, and information related to national security. It may
even be the case that our bodies could be nonrivalrously used by others.
Nevertheless, this feature of most intangible goods and some tangible
goods does not obviously justify such use.
A similar anti-intellectual property argument has been offered by
Arthur Kuflik.46 Kuflik writes:
[W]hen the inventor makes wheels and starts wheeling things around, he does
not interfere in the lives of others or limit their liberty in any way that could
provide legitimate ground for complaint. But the same could be said of the
others: when they make wheels for their own personal use, they are not interfering
in his life or limiting his liberty to make and to use wheels. 47
Kuflik uses this case to show that laboring on and creating ideas, and
reducing these ideas to practice does not, and cannot, ground monopoly
control because of the nonrivalrous nature of ideas. This also shows,
according to Kuflik, that inventors have no exclusive minimal moral
claims to the ideas they create. 48
First, note that monopoly control, a feature of patent protection, is not
a necessary feature of systems of intellectual property. Second, I would
argue that Kuflik moves too fast. Imagine our inventor had shielded his
invention behind a cloak of invisibility and protection. We can see that
he is doing something productive and his efforts seem to be more fruitful
than his old methods. Suppose Arthur approaches the inventor and
demands to see what is behind the cloak. The inventor refuses and claims
that what is behind the cloak is his property and if Arthur wants to see
and use the item or produce his own copy, he will have to agree to terms.
What grounds the force of the contract, assuming that Arthur comes to
terms, is the prior entitlement of the inventor.
46.
Arthur Kuflik, Moral FoundationsofIntellectual Property Rights, in OWNING
SCIENTIFIC AND TECHNICAL INFORMATION: VALUE AND ETHICAL ISSUES 219, 223 (Vivian
Weil & John W. Snapper eds., 1989).
47. Id.
48. Id. at 223-24.
1093
The problem with Kuflik's original case is that the inventor seemingly
offers his idea to others without strings, so to speak. In fact, by simply
using the wheel within sight of his peers, the inventor foists this idea on
others-we are not the sort of beings that can see or hear about an idea
and then delete it from memory. Moreover, without any prior agreements
regarding use after access, one would assume that making and using a
wheel would be fine. 49 As already noted, however, we can view the
Lockean model as a bargain -between authors and inventors, who may
invest great amounts of time and energy in the production of ideas, and
society, which reaps the benefits of this innovation. In return for disclosure
and, perhaps, fair use, authors and inventors are protected from those
who would copy and use intellectual works after being granted access.
Without such agreements, those who innovate would likely either
engage in some other productive activity or wall off their creations in
other ways.
B. The Free Speech Argument Against IntellectualProperty
A prominent and widespread argument against legal protection of
intellectual property is that these systems are inconsistent with our
commitment to freedom of thought and speech.5 0 For example, consider
how the Church of Scientology has used copyright and other legal
protections to restrict access to their religious views. 5 ' According to this
objection, intellectual property rights are troublesome because they limit
access to and uses of intellectual works. This sort of restriction
impoverishes the commons of thought and discussion. Lawrence Lessig
writes:
Gone with the Wind was published in 1936 ... [and] the copyright would
have expired at the end of 1992.
But because of . . . extensions . .. that
copyright now extends until 2031....
49. 1 would not make this claim when considering private information. I have argued
at length that just because someone allows access to private information, it does not
follow that those whom have been granted access are at liberty to use this information in
any way whatsoever.
50. See, e.g., JAMES BOYLE, THE PUBLIC DOMAIN: ENCLOSING THE COMMONS OF
THE MIND 15 (2008); LAWRENCE LESSIG, FREE CULTURE: How BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY
AND THE LAW To LOCK DOWN CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY (2004); John Perry
Barlow, The Economy of Ideas: Everything You Know About Intellectual Property Is
Wrong, in INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY, supra note 43, at 349; Gordon, supra note 25; Edwin C.
Hettinger, Justifying Intellectual Property, 18 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 31 (1989); Melville B.
Nimmer, Does CopyrightAbridge the FirstAmendment Guaranteesof Free Speech and
Press?, 17 UCLA L. REV. 1180 (1970); L. Ray Patterson, Free Speech, Copyright, and
Fair Use, 40 VAND. L. REV. 1 (1987); Waldron, supra note 21.
51.
See Church of Scientology Int'l v. Fishman, No. 94-55443, 1994 U.S. App.
LEXIS 23848 (9th Cir. 1994).
1094
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
In 2001, Alice Randall tried to publish [a parody of Gone with the Wind] called
The Wind Done Gone .... The Mitchell estate ... brought a federal lawsuit to
stop its publication ...
To most people, this is plainly absurd. Gone with the Wind is an extraordinarily
important part of American culture; at some point, the story should be free for
others to take and criticize in whatever way they want.52
The problem with this objection to intellectual property should be
obvious. By allowing robust control with specific limits-fair use,
idea/expression, sunset on rights-we enhance rather than impoverish
the commons of thought and discussion. To put the point another way, a
system that allows initial restricted access incentivizes authors and
inventors to create intellectual works. These works are then published or
distributed, and the result is an enhanced commons of thought and
discussion. Simply put, we get more to talk about and build upon by
adopting a system of intellectual property.
Moreover, consider the contentious, yet established, idea/expression
rule of copyright.53 Copyright applies only to fixed expressions-not to
ideas that may make up a fixed expression. For example, I may read
Einstein's original articles on special and general relativity, express his
ideas in my own words, and obtain a copyright in my expression. Sure,
I may be guilty of plagiarism, but so long as my expressions are not
copied from or substantially similar to Einstein's original, I can obtain a
copyright. Perhaps a Lockean could justify this legal rule by appealing
to the labor and effort that goes into producing a fixed expression.5 4
If correct, the primary thrust of the free speech argument against
intellectual property rights misses an important point. Aside from fair
use, the idea/expression distinction in copyright provides a way for ideas
to have an impact independent of how authors control their intellectual
works. Although it is true that a specific expression and substantially
similar artifacts may be controlled and restricted, the ideas that make up
the work are, in most cases, free for anyone to consider-information
52. LAWRENCE LESSIG, THE FuTuRE OF IDEAS: THE FATE OF THE COMMONS IN A
CONNECTED WORLD 198-99 (2001).
53. See 17 U.S.C. § 102(b) (2006) ("In no case does copyright protection for an
original work of authorship extend to any idea, procedure, process, system, method of
operation, concept, principle, or discovery, regardless of the form in which it is described,
explained, illustrated, or embodied in such work.").
54. Justin Hughes first suggested this analysis. See Justin Hughes, The Philosophy
ofIntellectualProperty,77 GEO. L.J. 287, 296-330 (1988).
1095
storehouses like libraries, and now the Web, ensure that access is
widespread.
Finally, it is not at all clear that free speech is so presumptively
weighty that it nearly always trumps other values. Shouting at someone
over a bullhorn all day is not something we would countenance as
protected free speech. Hate speech, obscene expressions, sexual
harassment, and broadcasting private medical information about others
are each examples of speech that we are willing to limit for various
reasons-perhaps intellectual property rights can be viewed in this light.
C. The Social Nature ofIntellectual Works Argument
Against IntellectualProperty
According to the "social nature of intellectual works" argument,
intellectual property unjustly benefits authors and inventors by allowing
individuals monopoly control over what is a social product. Proponents
of this "shared culture" view would have us imagine that allowing
intellectual property rights is like giving the person who places the last
brick in a "public works" dam exclusive ownership of the dam.55
But like the defender of the first cause argument for the existence of
God who rides the principle of sufficient causation to a certain point and
then conveniently abandons it-every event or object needs a sufficient
cause and nothing is self-caused except God-the proponents of the
shared culture view are guilty of a similar trick. Shared culture or the
social nature of intellectual property view is sufficient for undermining
intellectual property rights or robust control of intellectual works, but
conveniently not strong enough to undermine student desert for a grade,
criminal punishment, or other sorts of moral evaluation.
More specifically, it is doubtful that the notion of "society" employed
in this view is clear enough to carry the weight that the argument
demands. In some vague sense, we may know what it means to say that
Lincoln was a member of American society or that Aristotle's political
views were influenced by ancient Greek society. Nevertheless, the
notion of society is conceptually imprecise-one that it would be dubious to
attach ownership or obligation claims to. Those who would defend this
view would have to clarify the notions of society and "social product"
before the argument could be fully analyzed.
But suppose for the sake of argument that supporters of this view
come up with a concise notion of society and social product. We may
55. This view is widespread, and virtually every attack on intellectual property includes
some version of it. See, e.g., BOYLE, supra note 50; LESSIG, supra note 50; Barlow,
supra note 50; Kuflik, supra note 46.
1096
[VoL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
ask further, why think that societies can be owed something or that they
can own or deserve something?56 Surely, it does not follow from the claim
that X is a social product that society owns X. Likewise, it does not
follow merely from the claim that X is produced by Ginger that Ginger
owns X. It is true that interactions between individuals may produce
increased market values or add to the common stock of knowledge.
What may be denied is that these by-products of interaction, market
value and shared information, are in some sense owned by society or
that society is owed for their use. This should not be assumed without
argument. It is one thing to claim that information or knowledge is a
social product-something built up by thousands of individual
contributions-but quite another to claim that this knowledge is owned
by society or that individuals who use this information owe society
something in return.57
Suppose that Fred and Ginger, along with numerous others, interact
and benefit me in the following way. Their interaction produces
knowledge that is then freely shared and allows me to create some new
value, V. Upon creation of V, Fred and Ginger demand that they are
owed something for their part. But what is the argument from thirdparty benefits to demands of compensation for these benefits? Why
think that there are "strings" attached to freely shared information? And
if such an argument can be made, it would seem that burdens create
reverse demands. Suppose that the interaction of Fred and Ginger
produces false information that is freely shared. Suppose further that I
waste ten years trying to produce some value based, in part, on this false
information. Would Fred and Ginger owe me compensation? Would'
56. Do notions of ownership, owing, or deserving even make sense when attached
to the concept of society? If so, and if different societies can own knowledge, do they
not have the problem of original acquisition? See NOZICK, supra note 8, at 178 (pointing
out that collective property societies still need to justify why locals have property rights
while outsiders do not). Seana Valentine Shiffrin's interpretation of Locke's theory of
property appears to fall prey to this worry. See Seana Valentine Shiffrin, Lockean Arguments
for Private Intellectual Property, in NEW ESSAYS INTHE LEGAL AND POLITICAL THEORY
OF PROPERTY 138 (Stephen R. Munzer ed., 2001).
57. Lysander Spooner argued that one's culture or society plays almost no role in
the production of ideas. "Nothing is, by its own essence and nature, more perfectly
susceptible of exclusive appropriation, than a thought. It originates in the mind of a single
individual. It can leave his mind only in obedience to his will. It dies with him, if he so
elect." LYSANDER SPOONER, The Law of IntellectualProperty; or An Essay on the Right
of Authors and Inventors to a Perpetual Property in Their Ideas, in 3 THE COLLECTED
WORKS OF LYSANDER SPOONER 2, 58 (Charles Shively ed., 1971).
1097
society? The position that "strings" are attached in this case runs
In Nozick's
parallel to Robert Nozick's benefit "foisting" example.
case, a benefit is foisted on someone, and then payment is demanded.59
This seems an accurate account of what is going on in this case as well.
One cannot, whatever one's purposes, just act so as to give people benefits and
then demand (or seize) payment. Nor can a group of persons do this. If you
may not charge and collect for benefits you bestow without prior agreement,
you certainly may not do so for benefits whose bestowal costs you nothing,
and most certainly people need not repay you for costless-to-provide benefits
which yet others provided them. So the fact that we partially are "social
products" in that we benefit from current patterns and forms created by the
multitudinous actions of a long string of long-forgotten people, forms which
include institutions, ways of doing things, and language, . . . does not create in
us a 60general floating debt which the current society can collect and use as it
will.
Arguably, common knowledge and shared culture are the synergistic
effects of individuals freely interacting. If a thousand of us freely give
our new and original ideas to all of humankind, it would be illicit for us
to demand compensation after the fact from individuals who have used
our ideas to create things of value. It would even be more questionable
for individuals ten generations later to demand compensation for the
ideas that we freely gave. Lysander Spooner puts the point succinctly:
What rights society have, in ideas, which they did not produce, and have never
purchased, it would probably be very difficult to define; and equally difficult
to explain how society became possessed of those rights. It certainly requires
something more than assertion, to prove that by simply coming to a knowledge
of certain ideas-the products of individual labor-society acquires any valid
title to them, or, consequently, any rights in them. 6 1
But once again, suppose for the sake of argument the defender of this
view can justify societal ownership of general pools of knowledge and
information. Nevertheless, it could be argued that we have already paid
for the use of this collective wisdom when we pay for education and the
like. When a parent pays, through fees or taxation, for a child's education,
it would seem that the information-part of society's common pool of
knowledge-has been fairly purchased. And this extends through all
levels of education, even to individuals who no longer attend school.
Finally, in many contexts where privacy interests are at stake, for
example, an appeal to the social nature of intellectual property and
information seems unconvincing-assuming that this view can be saved
from the points already discussed. The fact that sensitive personal
58.
59.
60.
61.
1098
See NOZICK, supra note 8, at 95.
Id.
Id.
SPOONER, supra note 57, at 103.
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectualProperty
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
information about an individual's medical history is a social product
may have little force when it comes to questions of access and control.
This is also true of information related to national security and financial
information.
D. IntellectualPropertyRights Violate Individual Liberty
Libertarians have attacked the notion of intellectual property on the
grounds that it violates individual liberty rights. Tom Palmer argues:
Liberty and intellectual property seem to be at odds, for while property in
tangible objects limits actions only with respect to particular goods, property in
ideal objects restricts an entire range of actions unlimited by place or time,
involving legitimately owned property (VCRs, tape recorders, typewriters, the
human voice, and more) by all but those privileged to receive monopoly grants
from the state.62
When an individual owns a physical item, her rights exclude others
from interfering with her control of it. But intellectual property rights
sweep across the entire domain of human action, restricting individual
liberty even in the privacy of one's own home. Palmer continues:
My ownership claim over my computer restricts your access to that computer,
but it is not a blanket restriction on your liberty to acquire a similar computer,
or an abacus, or to count on your fingers or use pencil and paper. In contrast,
to claim a property right over a process is to claim a blanket right to control the
actions of others. For example, if a property right [to control] the use of the
abacus were to be granted to someone, it would mean precisely that others
could not make an abacus unless they had the permission of the owner of that
right. It would be a restriction on the liberty of everyone who wanted to 63make
an abacus with their own labor out of wood that they legitimately owned.
Palmer concludes that intellectual property rights are morally objectionable
and that patent and copyrights institutions should be dismantled.64
It is interesting to note, however, that Palmer advocates market and
contract, rather than legal, solutions for protecting or fencing intellectual
works.65 But binding contracts related to intellectual works presuppose
justified prior entitlements-thus, to replace Anglo-American copyright
and patent institutions with a market and contract model presupposes
62. Tom G. Palmer, Are Patents and Copyrights Morally Justified? The Philosophy
ofPropertyRights andIdeal Objects, 13 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 817, 830 (1990).
63. Id. at 831.
64. See id. at 861-65.
65. See id. at 855, 860.
1099
that authors and inventors have justified entitlements to what they fence.
And if authors and inventors have justified entitlements to intellectual
works-works that they would not produce or bring forth without certain
protections in place-a system of copyright, patent, and trade secret may
be adopted.
In response to Palmer's view that intellectual property rights are
objectionable because they limit individual liberty, I have two main
criticisms. First, this worry may be addressed by adopting specific legal
rules. For example, current Anglo-American institutions of intellectual
property have built-in provisions that limit the rights of authors and
inventors.6 6 These limitations, for example "fair use" and "first sale,"
allow individuals to use a patented or copyrighted work for personal,
nonprofit, or educational purposes.67 Under current law it is permissible
that I make backup copies of my computer games or copy a chapter of a
book from the library. Perhaps these kinds of limitations could be built
into the bargain between society and those who create intellectual works.
A second criticism of Palmer's view is that rights of all sorts restrict
what individuals can do with their bodies and property. Palmer acts as if
restricting individual liberty is a special feature of intellectual property
rights and not of other rights. But this is clearly false. My right to a car
prohibits all of humanity from swinging a bat and damaging my car.
Other people's life rights prohibit you from drinking martinis and
playing with a nuclear bomb in your basement. Most rights restrict
liberty and prohibit what others can do with their property.68 Even in the
privacy of your own home, you cannot punch me in the face, destroy my
property, or engage in risky activities that threaten your neighbors.
Thus, if Palmer's argument works against intellectual property rights, it
would seem that it works against all rights, including life rights and
tangible property rights. If rights are not a license to do whatever one
wills, then Palmer's worry vanishes.
V. CONCLUSION
It is important to note that Anglo-American systems of intellectual
property are not grounded in a natural rights tradition that Locke or
66. See, e.g., 17 U.S.C. § 107 (2006) (fair use); id § 109(a) (first sale); id § 304
(limited duration); see also New Era Publ'ns Int'l v. Henry Holt & Co., 695 F. Supp.
1493, 1499-1525 (S.D.N.Y. 1988) (discussing fair use), aff'd, 873 F.2d 576 (2d Cir.
1989).
67. See 17 U.S.C. § 107.
68. See, e.g., U.S. CONST. amend. IV; Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld, Some Fundamental
Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning, 23 YALE L.J. 16, 32-35 (19131914).
1100
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectualProperty
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
Lockeans may champion. Beginning with the first Patent Act of 1790
and continuing through the adoption of the Berne Convention standards
in 1988, the basis given for Anglo-American systems of intellectual
property is utilitarian in nature and incentives based.69 Thomas Jefferson, a
central figure in the formation of American systems of intellectual
property, expressly rejected any natural rights foundation for granting
control to authors and inventors over their intellectual work. 7 0 "The
patent monopoly was not designed to secure to the inventor his natural
right in his discoveries. Rather, it was a reward, an inducement, to bring
forth new knowledge." 7 1 Society seeks to maximize utility in the form
of scientific and cultural progress by granting rights to authors and
inventors as an incentive toward such progress.72 In general, patents,
copyrights, and trade secrets are devices created by statute to prevent the
diffusion of information before the author or inventor has recovered
profit adequate to induce such investment. This view is echoed by the
committee report that accompanied the 1909 Copyright Act:
69. Limited rights are granted to authors and inventors of intellectual property "to
promote the Progress of Science and the useful Arts." U.S. CONST. art. I, § 8, cl. 8.
70. Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (Aug. 13, 1813), in 8 THE
WRITINGS OF THOMAS JEFFERSON 326, 333 (Andrew A. Lipscomb ed., 1904).
71.
WILLIAM H. FRANCIS & ROBERT C. COLLINS, CASES AND MATERIALS ON
PATENT LAW: INCLUDING TRADE SECRETS-COPYRIGHTS-TRADEMARKS 93 (4th ed. 1995)
(quoting Graham v. John Deere Co., 383 U.S. 1, 9 (1966)). Prior to the enactment of the
Constitution, a number of states adopted copyright laws that had both a utilitarian component
and a natural rights component. See COPYRIGHT ENACTMENTS OF THE UNITED STATES,
1783-1906 (Thorvald Solberg ed., 2nd ed. 1906). A major turning point away from a
natural rights framework for American institutions of intellectual property came with the
decision in Wheaton v. Peters, 33 U.S. 591, 660-61 (1834). "Unquestionably, the 1834
decision marked an important turning-point, in that it distanced American copyright law
from the natural law perspectives which were very much in evidence at the end of the
eighteenth century." Alain Strowel, Droit d'auteur and Copyright: Between History and
Nature, in OF AUTHORS AND ORIGINs 235, 244 (Brad Sherman & Alan Strowel eds.,
1994); see also Edward C. Walterscheid, Inherent or CreatedRights: Early Views on the
Intellectual Property Clause, 19 HAMLINE L. REv. 81, 103 (1995) ("[The Court] chose to
interpret the [intellectual property] clause in favor of the granting of an authority to
create a future right rather than an authority to protect an existing one."). Nevertheless,
anomalies still pop up. "In 1984 the Supreme Court cited Locke when it held that intangible
'products of an individual's "labor and invention"' can be 'property' subject to the protection
of the Takings Clause." Gordon, supra note 25, at 1540 (quoting Ruckelshaus v.
Monsanto Co., 467 U.S. 986, 1002-03 (1984)).
72. For a critique of utilitarian incentive-based justifications of intellectual property,
see Adam D. Moore, Intellectual Property, Innovation, and Social Progress: The Case
Against Incentive BasedArguments, 26 HAMLINE L. REv. 601 (2003).
1101
In enacting a copyright law Congress must consider ... two questions: First,
how much will the legislation stimulate the producer and so benefit the public;
and, second, how much will the monopoly granted be detrimental to the public?
The granting of such exclusive rights, under the proper terms and conditions,
upon the public that outweighs the evils of the temporary
confers a benefit
73
monopoly.
Control is granted to authors and inventors of intellectual property
because granting such control provides incentives necessary for social
progress.
As noted in the opening, it seems that adherence to an incentivesbased social progress foundation for institutions of intellectual property
has given way to a system where economically privileged elites shape
our policy. How else could one interpret Eldred v. Ashcroft, which
addressed a challenge to a twenty-year extension of copyright protection
provided by the Copyright Term Extension Act of 1998 (the Sonny
Bono Act).74 In Eldred, seventeen prominent economists, including five
Nobel laureates, claimed that adding twenty years to copyright protection
would have little impact on incentives to innovate.75 The Supreme Court
ignored the views of these economists and simply affirmed Congress's
decision to extend copyright protection.76 If we continue down the road
of economic privilege, then we risk undermining both the institutions
and the very idea of intellectual property. We end up with the view that
intellectual property rights and systems of intellectual property protection
are state-created entities controlled by the privileged, connected, and
economically advantaged. This would explain the current attitudes
about copying and piracy.
Locke wrote, "Nobody could think himself injured by the drinking of
another man, though he took a good draught, who had a whole river of
Given allowances
the same water left him to quench his thirst . . ..
for independent creation and that the frontier of intellectual property is
practically infinite, the case for Locke's water drinker and the author or
inventor are quite alike. Once a defensible measure and baseline are
adopted, we are in a position to consider the actual contributions of
authors and inventors. In most cases we are bettered by these intellectual
73. H.R. REP. No. 60-2222, at 7 (1909); see also Sony Corp. of Am. v. Universal
City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 477 (1984) (Blackmun, J., dissenting) (describing the
copyright system as based on a belief that granting authors exclusive rights over their
works would incentivize creativity and ultimately benefit the public welfare).
74. Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 193 (2003).
75. See generallyStan J. Liebowitz & Stephen Margolis, Seventeen FamousEconomists
Weigh In On Copyright: The Role Of Theory, Empirics, and Network Effects, 18 HARV.
J.L. & TECH. 435 (2005).
76. Eldred, 537 U.S. at 194.
77. LOCKE, supra note 1, § 33, at 20.
1102
[VOL. 49: 1069, 2012]
A Lockean Theory ofIntellectual Property
SAN DIEGO LAW REVIEW
efforts. Perhaps less controversially, we are, at least, not worsened by
these activities. In any case, by working out the theoretical underpinnings
of a Lockean theory of intellectual property, we may provide a
defensible moral foundation for systems of copyright, patent, and trade
secret protection. Intellectual property is not theft-rather, intellectual
property reflects our commitments to innovative activity and to
protecting the natural rights of authors and inventors.
1103
1104