Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2014, Analysis Reviews
…
3 pages
1 file
The recent explosion of interest in consciousness has undoubtedly taught us much, but certain aspects of consciousness have not received the attention that they deserve. One such aspect is the unity of consciousness. The Unity of Consciousness has three central aims. The first aim is to provide an account of what the unity of consciousness consists in. What might it mean to say that consciousness is -or, as the case may be, is not -unified? The second aim of the volume is to determine whether consciousness is unified. Is consciousness necessarily unified, or are there conditions in which the unity of consciousness breaks down? The third aim of the volume is to explore the implications of the unity of consciousness. What might the unity of consciousness teach us about the nature of consciousness or the self?
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 2013
The explosion of research on consciousness in the last two decades has undoubtedly deepened our understanding of the phenomenon. We have a better sense of what the options are for theories of consciousness, and progress has been made in identifying the neural and information-processing basis of consciousness. There are, however, a number of aspects of consciousness that have been largely overlooked. One such aspect is the unity of consciousness. With some notable exceptions, neither philosophers nor the scientists have paid serious attention to the ways in which consciousness is unified. 1 This is a surprising, for not only is the unity of consciousness an important topic in its own right, it also promises to provide much-needed constraints on theories of consciousness. If consciousness is necessarily unified, then any account of consciousness must accommodate and perhaps even explain that fact, and if consciousness is not necessarily unified, then any account of consciousness must also accommodate and perhaps even explain that fact.
Proceedings of the Twenty-second Annual …, 2000
The unity of consciousness is our capacity to be conscious of a number of items all at once, in what could be called a single conscious act. Such unity is found in at least three places: consciousness of the world in general, consciousness of self in general, and paying focal attention to aspects of either. In all three, unified consciousness has both a synchronic and a diachronic dimension. That is to say, consciousness is unified both at a given moment and over time. Unified consciousness can be breached in two ways: by splitting (into two unified centres of consciousness, as in brain bisection operations) and by shattering (as in some severe schizophrenias and dysexecutive disorder). Studying it in its breakdown conditions is a good way to throw light on it. In this paper, we will delineate the unity of consciousness, explore some situations in which it breaks down, and relate it to some other mental unities.
Oxford Handbooks Online, 2009
Despite a burst of work in the past decade or so, some of it by us, there is still no general agreement on what unified consciousness is. This despite increasing recognition of its importance. Once more into the breach!
Oxford University Press eBooks, 2009
Despite a burst of work in the past decade or so, some of it by us, there is still no general agreement on what unified consciousness is. This despite increasing recognition of its importance. Once more into the breach!
The unity of consciousness is our capacity to be conscious of a number of items all at once, in what could be called a single conscious act. Such unity is found in at least three places: consciousness of the world in general, consciousness of self in general, and paying focal attention to aspects of either. In all three, unified consciousness has both a synchronic and a diachronic dimension. That is to say, consciousness is unified both at a given moment and over time. Unified consciousness can be breached in two ways: by splitting (into two unified centres of consciousness, as in brain bisection operations) and by shattering (as in some severe schizophrenias and dysexecutive disorder). Studying it in its breakdown conditions is a good way to throw light on it. In this paper, we will delineate the unity of consciousness, explore some situations in which it breaks down, and relate it to some other mental unities.
The unity of consciousness has so far been studied only as a relation holding among the many experiences of a single subject. I investigate whether this relation could hold between the experiences of distinct subjects, considering three major arguments against the possibility of such 'between-subjects unity'. The first argument, based on the popular idea that unity implies subsumption by a composite experience, can be deflected by allowing for limited forms of 'experience-sharing', in which the same token experience belongs to more than one subject. The second argument, based on the phenomenological claim that unified experiences have interdependent phenomenal characters, I show to rest on an equivocation. Finally, the third argument accuses between-subjects unity of being unimaginable, or more broadly a formal possibility corresponding to nothing we can make sense of. I argue that the familiar experience of perceptual co-presentation gives us an adequate phenomenological grasp on what between-subjects unity might be like.
The Routledge Handbook of Consciousness, 2018
The unity of consciousness I turn my head to gaze out the screen door to my left. It's a pretty scene-grass, rocks, flowers, and woods beyond-but I'm not inspecting it closely. Out of the corner of my eye I see someone crossing the kitchen, and hear someone else walking on the floor above me. Water is running somewhere. I've paused to consider whether I should go to the supermarket before or after lunch.
Sensory Integration and the Unity of Consciousness. MIT Press., 2014
The debate about the unity of consciousness in split-brain subjects has for the most part been pitched between two positions: that a split-brain subject has a single, unified stream of consciousness, or that she has two streams of consciousness, one associated with each hemisphere. A prima facie appealingly intermediate position, proposed most explicitly by Lockwood, is that a split-brain subject has a single but only partially unified consciousness. Philosophers have overwhelmingly rejected Lockwood’s proposal. This paper issues a prelimary defense of the partial unity model (PUM) of split-brain consciousness. I argue that the major philosophical objections to that model apply no more to it than they do to the conscious disunity or duality model. In particular, both models imply that a split-brain subject has two phenomenally conscious perspectives, and both raise questions about the relationship between having such a perspective and being a subject of experience.
International Journal of Scientific Research in Science, Engineering and Technology, 2023
THE INDO NORDIC AUTHORS’ COLLECTIVE, 2024
Developmental Neuropsychology, 2009
Repenser l’institution et la désinstitutionnalisation à partir du handicap. Actes de la Conférence Alter 2022, 2024
International Journal of the Classical Tradition, 2019
Working Paper, 2023
Зороастрийская символика в узбекском текстиле XIX — начала XX века: от предметности к абстрактности, 2022
Mitteilungen des Deutschen Archäologischen Instituts Kairo 75. In press., 2019
BMC Research Notes, 2015
Clinical Nutrition Supplements, 2008
Journal of Applied Physics, 2010
2015
British Journal of Surgery, 2020
Jurnal Eeccis, 2013