Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
”Thinking publicly otherwise” is one of the foundations of democracy. The task of the
opposition in a democratic system is to express distrust, to criticize the actions of the
government and to provide an alternative. The opposition institutionalizes distrust, and,
paradoxically, the presence of this institutionalized distrust is, for the citizens, one important
reason to trust the democratic system. The claim defended here is that the relationship between
the government and the opposition can be understood in terms of Hegel’s dialectics. Although
Hegel’s political theory as formulated in his Philosophy of Right emphasizes the unifying role of
the State, his earlier philosophy contains more democratic potential.
Modern democracy cannot be conceived only in terms of political equality, mass participation,
competition, or tolerance. Nor can it be defined as a system where the public good is
determined through rational or ethical deliberation. All these are, at least in principle, possible
even in autocratic or oligarchic systems. What is peculiar for modern democracy is that
opposition and dissent are not only tolerated, but they are recognized as necessary aspects of
the system. Governments need oppositions, because their right to govern is legitimized only
through the presence of an opposition. The task of the opposition in a democratic system is to
express distrust: to criticize the actions of the government and to provide an alternative. The
opposition institutionalizes distrust, and, paradoxically, the presence of this institutionalized
distrust is, for the citizens, one important reason to trust the democratic system. Insofar as the
opposition is incompetent, or bribed or otherwise made toothless, the system appears as less
democratic, and the democratic legitimacy of the government is consequently diminished.
The idea that an organized or institutionalized distrust embodied in the opposition could
ultimately be the basis of legitimacy is complex and even paradoxical. It is no wonder that the
classical normative theories of democracy have not been able to conceptualize the role of
opposition. The idea of democracy as the sovereignty of the People was born in the French
Revolution. Typically it conceived the People as united and homogeneous. The Marxist and
nationalist conceptions of democracy (for example, that of Carl Schmitt 1985; 2008) are direct
descendants of this idea. Even when it was admitted that the “Will of the People” could, in
practice, only mean the will of the majority, the unavoidable presence of a distrusting minority
was conceived as a defect, a deviation from the pure ideal of democracy. The perfect
democracy was, ideally, based on unanimity and a complete identity between the rulers and the
ruled (see Rosanvallon 2006, ch 3.). There was no room for organized opposition in this
conception.
The liberal version of popular sovereignty presented in John Locke’s Second Treatise (Locke
1988) was not based on the hypothetical identification of the rulers and the ruled. According to
Locke, the government was based on trust. Trust was, unlike a contract or identity, an
asymmetrical relationship. The people or the community could unilaterally withdraw its trust and
replace the government by another. If the rulers refused to obey, the ruled had a right to resist
the rulers, and if necessary, rise to arms. Nevertheless, trust was for Locke, the normal and
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
natural situation. Distrust remained exceptional and external.
The epistemic conception of democracy as a method to find the true, best or most justified
solutions to problems which concern all derives from Aristotle’s Politics. There, Aristotle
famously argues that a decision-making group may be wiser or better informed than any of its
individual members. In The Social Contract Jean-Jacques Rousseau expressed this idea in the
following terms:
When in the popular assembly a law is proposed, what people is asked is not exactly whether it
approves or rejects the proposal, but whether it is in conformity with the general will, which is
their will. Each man, when giving his vote, states his opinion on that point; and the general will is
found by counting votes. When therefore the opinion that is contrary to my own prevails, this
proves neither more nor less than that I was mistaken, and that what I thought to be the general
will was not so. (Rousseau 1973, p. 250)
In this conception, disagreement is the starting point. Yet, opposition becomes irrational and
unjustified when the democratic decision has been made. The legitimacy of democratic
decisions is based on the hypothesis that a democratic majority is more likely to find the correct
solution than any individual voter or a sub-group of voters. Hence, post-decisional opposition
must be a sign of irrational stubbornness. The contemporary theories of deliberative democracy
(for example that of Jürgen Habermas 1986) are partly based on the epistemic conception.
Habermas and his followers (Benhabib 1994; Cohen 1989) argue that in the ideal conditions
constituted by free, unlimited discussion, the discussion partners would ultimately agree on
reasons as well as on conclusions. This rational consensus would guarantee the truth or validity
of the conclusions, for, ideally, it would incorporate into itself all imaginable counter-objections
and criticisms. The deliberative theorists are ready to admit than in the real life, disagreements
are unavoidable. But, again, such disagreements only show that the democratic process falls
short of the ideal. Again, the presence of a persistent opposition appears as a (perhaps
unavoidable) defect.
Finally, the “realist” theorists of democracy (for example, Weber 1994, or Schumpeter 1962)
conceive democracy in terms of power struggle. For them, struggle for power is the essence of
all politics, and democratic competition is one form of it. The “realists” admit the unavoidability
of disagreements in democratic politics. However, when conceptualizing democratic politics as
“war by other means” they neglect an important difference between the democratic competition
and other forms of power struggle. In democracy, unlike, say, in international politics, the
relations between the competing parties are internal rather than purely external and contingent.
True, parties compete for power. However, power in a democratic society is not simply an ability
to realize one’s own will. The winning party, which forms the government, has power only
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
because it is obeyed by the citizens, and it is obeyed (at least partly) because the citizens see
its claim for power as legitimate; it deserves its power. It is perceived as legitimate because it
has temporarily won its opponents in a fair competition, yet those opponents may challenge it
again. Hence, the permanent presence of an opposing force is a necessary condition for the
power of the government. Within the democratic political body, the idea is thus not to press into
consensus, or to silence the parties which do not belong to the government after the last
elections. The winners are winners because there are losers who recognize their defeat, but still
continue to disagree. While competition for power may be a near-universal phenomenon (as the
“realists” claim), this mutual dependence between competitors is a unique property of
democracies.
Opposition as an internal controller
I would characterize democracy as a necessarily contradictory whole, in which the parties are
internally related to each others. The idea is to continue the struggle over matters which
concern “all”. This internal struggle between mutually contradicting parties serves democratic
purposes. There can, of course, be no opposition without a government which it opposes, but
equally, there cannot be a democratic government without an active opposition. The opposition
provides, by its public criticism and inspection of the government’s actions, a “system of
checking” of whether the government is doing what it has promised to do and whether it is
acting in the best interest of “all”. In fact, the role of the opposition is to try to reveal that the
government is actually not acting in the best interest of the community as a whole, but, instead,
pursues more or less parochial aims i.e. it pursues too much the aims of the party which has
last won in the elections. Interestingly, a system which comprises of a government, checked and
radically criticised by a sort of “internally external” opposition that also provides an alternative
choice for voters in the next election, is considered a trustworthy democratic system. While an
external controller, for example a Supreme Court or a body of scientists or experts, are
supposed to present impartial, disengaged, neutral and apolitical (“power-free”) evaluation, the
role of opposition is to be fully engaged concerning the things under discussion. One important
aspect of the opposition is to criticise the rationale, by which the government legitimizes its
decisions, for being biased or parochial.
In her article ‘Unpolitical Democracy’ Nadia Urbinati (2009) discusses the role of contestation
and criticism in various theories of democracy (for example, in those of Pierre Rosanvallon and
Philip Pettit). She promotes the idea that democracy, as a system in which things that concern
“all” are decided by all, should not diminish the role of partisan, engaged opposition. If the
evaluation of things is transferred away from the area where politically engaged parties confront
each others, into an area where neutral parties are supposed to evaluate or judge the public
good impartially (from the point of view of an apolitical judge or a scientist), democratic decision
making is compromised. Power becomes hidden behind the veil of a neutral judge or some
other external evaluator. Issues under discussion become easily divided into “political” and
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
“apolitical” parts, into issues which can be struggled upon politically and issue which are
thought to belong to the sphere of external evaluation. Urbinati writes:
It prefigures a transformation of the meaning of politics according to goals and criteria that recall
the nineteenth-century utopia of the rational power of the experts. It suggests that politics is a
cognitive practice for reaching true outcomes, solving problems, and moreover eradicating
“politically-relevant reasonable disagreement. (Urbinati 2009, 74)
For Urbinati, one problem with the external controlling is that experts typically give evaluations
on a restricted frame of questions, the framing of which is not part of the political process itself:
in the deliberative fora the formation of the agenda and the frame of questions to be discussed
by the selected citizens are not part of the political process. They are instead kept outside the
forum as the task of the mediators and organizers of these deliberative experiments. In clear
violation of the democratic principle of autonomy, both the issues to be discussed without
prejudice, and the procedures regulating the discussion, are not decided and chosen by the
participants. (Urbinati 2009, 74)
The practice of splitting issues into political and apolitical aspects is not itself part of the
democratic (political) process. It is done externally by actors which are not themselves exposed
to democratic criticism. The grounding idea of democracy is that it exercises autonomous power
over things which concern “all” (res publica). There is no party external, beyond or not
accessible to it, which would determine the problems to be discussed, or which would set the
frame, outline or circumscribe the politically relevant aspects of things under discussion. When
issues are divided into those aspects which are discussed politically and into those which are
left to neutral, external experts, it can be forgotten that there are hardly any aspects which do
not relate to questions of power or carry ethical implications. Few aspects are purely technical,
power-free or abstract. Moreover, even that neutral parties, like judges, scientists or various
selected citizen bodies are important sources of knowledge and opinions, they are not external
in the sense of being completely “power-free”. Scientific or legal expertise is always practiced
in a cultural context and, hence, it should not be considered as beyond democratic criticism and
analysis.
Hegel and the dialectics between the self and the Other
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
The claim defended here is that the relationship between the government and the distrusting,
internal opposition can be understood in terms of Hegel’s dialectics. At the first sight, Hegel is
not a promising starting point for democratic theorizing. His main political work, Philosophy of
Right, is not a particularly democratic work. Admittedly, Hegel does defend representative
institutions, constitution, and the basic rights. Thus, the once widespread claim that Hegel was
simply an apologist of the contemporary Prussian state is mistaken, for Hegel’s Prussia had
none of these. Moreover, in the lectures held before the publication of Philosophy of Right
Hegel did discuss the principle of opposition (see, for example, Hegel 1974, 707-9).
Nevertheless, in the published version of Philosophy of Right Hegel conceived the State
basically in terms of a unity. Conflicts appear at the level of the civil society where parochial
aims are pursued; nevertheless, they are superseded and reconciled rationally at the level of
the State. Thus, it is not surprising that both Hegel’s right-wing adherents and his liberal and
leftist critics have emphasized the unifying aspects of his philosophy: disagreements are solved
by rational communication. Even his radical interpreters, who – like Alexandre Kojève – have
emphasized the more conflictual aspects of Hegel’s theory, have seen a “homogeneous state”
as the ultimate outcome of the historical process.
However, other readings are possible. The British Idealist political theorist Sir Ernest Barker
(1942; 1951), while accepting the standard liberal criticism of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,
nevertheless argued that the other aspects of Hegel’s philosophy had democratic potential:
His conception of the eternal debate of thesis and antithesis, and of the opposition of thought to
thought in the operation of Mind [Geist], involves the necessary conclusion that debate and
discussion must always be at work in any society of minds, now emphasizing this idea, and now
emphasizing that, but always seeking to achieve a synthesis, or as we also say, in one of our
common terms, ‘to find a compromise’. If we think of political parties as representing thesis
and antithesis, and of Parliament as seeking to find a reconciling synthesis, we can defend
parliamentary democracy in terms of Hegelian ideas. We can even argue that Hegel himself
was untrue to his own ideas when he became a political absolutist. He failed to see that the
sovereign thing in political thought, as in all the thought of the world is the process of thought
itself, as it works its way between the clashing rocks of thesis and antithesis. (Barker 1951, p.
23)
According to my interpretation, the dialectics between the self and the Other, presented in
Hegel’s earlier work, Phenomenology of Spirit, offers still a valid theory of why the on-going
clashing of thesis with antithesis is the base for democratic equality and freedom between
people. An important instance of this dialectics appears in the contemporary parliamentary
systems where the government clashes with the opposition. In the next chapter I will go shortly
through Hegel’s theory of the dialectics between the self and the Other. Then I will offer an
interpretation of how it relates to the theme of democracy and distrust.
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
For Hegel, self-consciousness – in short, “self” – is a complex construction. The basic feature
of the self is thinking. Thinking is situated: it is conditioned by time, place, cultural context and
various individual, personal and material factors. Consequently, thinking makes up a limited,
interpretative system, a particular universe. Thinking is a universalizing and generalizing activity,
yet, at the same time it is parochial and limited. By conceptual and abstract thinking the thinker
may obtain a critical distance towards itself and its cultural limits. However, even abstract
thinking is situated because it is internally linked to, and it mediates with, the subjective parts of
the thinking system. Thinking is always subjective. The Other is, like the self, a complex
construction: subjective particularity is one of its features. Like the self, the Other is an
interpretative, meaning-giving system: a particular universe. A grounding idea in
Phenomenology of Spirit is that with the Other or, ideally, from a point of view which is
constituted jointly by the self and the Other, the self can go over its respective limits. In fact,
only by trying to see the world from the point of view of the Other, the self can acknowledge that
it’s own universe is particular and limited. With the Other, the self may go over its limits and see
the world, including its own self, from a new perspective which can be called a more democratic
perspective, even that democracy did not belong to Hegel’s terminology. However, the new
perspective is also a located perspective. The self cannot rise above perspectivity as such,
because subjectivity continues to be a basic feature of its thinking. (Hegel 1977, pp. 109-112)
Self’s way to relate to the Other is, however, not easy. The relationship between the self and
the Other can be called a radical difference, or, mutual otherness. It might, however, be also
called a radical similarity. The Other is, like the self, its own, self-determining, internally
differentiated system of subject-object-relations. Both the self and the Other are centres of their
own universes. Consequently, both selves appear to be, from the point of view of the other,
threatening. Freedom of the Other – the Other as a self-determining being and a universalizing,
generalizing being (a being who has views about things which concern “all”) – appears as a
threat. (Hegel 1977, pp. 111-119.)
Nevertheless, the dialectical narrative in Phenomenology shows that the self is not satisfied until
it creates a relationship of reciprocal recognition with Other. What self yearns for most is
freedom and only reciprocal recognition - or, actually an ethical society which is based on
reciprocal recognition of parties which are “other” to each other - satisfies this yearning.
According to Hegel, the self strives for a contact with the Other because, ultimately, it wants to
be free. Freedom includes various inter-related aspects such as epistemological freedom
(knowledge which is not parochial, instead, constituted in mutual recognition, for self and for
Other), inner freedom at a psychological level, and social freedom. For Hegel, the self can live a
satisfactory life – at these various levels – only if it acknowledges Other as its equal and enters
into a recognizing relationship with it. In recognizing the Other as an equal self and, reciprocally,
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
recognizing itself as the Other’s Other, the self is able to reconcile contradictions at the
aforementioned levels. In Hegel, freedom means that people and societies can, both, reconcile
contradictions, and, at the same time, see contradictions as the permanent part of a free, ethical
society. This means that both the self and the Other, as bearers of mutually contradicting
world-views, are recognized as valid sources of knowledge, views and opinions over things
which concern “all”. A free society does not try to silence contradicting world-views because
that would mean that some specific, parochial world-view, of some specific particular self, would
gain a dominating position in the society. Freedom as reciprocal recognition is a process where
the existence of, and the on-going clashing together, of contradicting world-views are
recognized as a permanent part of the society. Contradicting world-views clash together, yet,
the clash is considered a source of freedom and good, ethical life. Mutually contradicting selves
can all contribute to the constructing of the society, its basic principles, institutions and laws.
The clashing together of mutually contradicting selves cannot be disposed of because, at any
given time, the particular synthesis which governs or which has a hegemonic status in the
society (i.e. displayed at the level of, for example, commonly shared beliefs) cannot take all
possible views into consideration equally.
In Hegel, the complex structure of the thinking self is shown also in the complex structure of the
things, which are thought by the self. Thought things are complex structures which means, for
example that limited subjectivity is always an internal aspect of them. Things cannot be divided
into parts which are external to each others in the sense that they would not affect each others.
We can not bracket off subjective aspects from things and think of them as pure abstractions.
When things are thought rationally, or as abstractions, subjective limitedness continues to be
present, too. Things are complex constructions in which political, ethical, cultural and personal
aspects are internally mediated with each other.
Hegel, democracy and distrust
According to my interpretation Hegel’s seemingly abstract figures “self and “Other” may be
seen to stand for groups, comprising of like-minded individuals. Thinking, which is the basic
feature of both the self and the Other, does not develop in a social vacuum. Instead, individuals
are, to a great extent, born into those “particular universes”, which render them social subjects.
By linguistic, communicative internalization of selfhood, individuals become thinking selves and
subjects. Like-minded individuals can be thus seen to constitute the particular universes. These
universes may be also called as discursive, cultural contexts. Within them meanings, ethical and
moral principles and world-views are generated and kept alive by the individuals committing to
them and reproducing them. Hegel suggests that in order for the society to be free, these
groups as well as individuals comprising them, need to acknowledge that there is an outside
(Other) to their own group. In order for the society not to be parochially constituted - which
would mean the suffocation of some groups and closing them out from amongst those who
determine what the society as a whole is like – the groups and their world-views would need to
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
clash together. This clashing together of one particular universe with another, or, one thesis with
its antithesis, would mean that contradictions are acknowledged as an internal part of the
society.
How can Hegel’s theory of the need for contradicting parties to clash together inside a social
community be seen to promote an idea of the need for an institutionalized distrust in
democracy, embodied in the government-opposition-relationship? As said above, Hegel is often
seen to promote the idea of unifying and synthesizing rationality as the way to reconcile
disagreements at the level of the state. Theorists like Habermas, with his idea of communicative
ethics, draws from this line of thought. To claim that Hegel’s theory would support an idea of
an institutionalized distrust and government-opposition- relationship would mean that conflict or
distrust between parties, which decide about matters of state concerning “all”, is seen as
an internal aspect of a free society. Freedom as reciprocal recognition between its members
would not be understood in terms of reaching consensus by rational communication only, say, in
the ordinary way of continuing discussion until agreement, compromise or consensus is found.
Instead, it would emphasize the clashing together – feature of the mutually recognizing parties
as well as the idea that genuine and even passionate conflicts and distrust are a necessary part
of how the parties relate to each other in order to produce ethically sound and free decisions
concerning “all”. This way to interpret Hegel’s notion of freedom as the on-going clashing
together of the self and the Other – thesis with its anti-thesis – implies that the syntheses are
temporary and open for further debate and revision.
For Hegel, the self, as a thinker, is a complex system where different aspects influence each
others internally. This implies, importantly, that rational thinking, also at the state level, is not
neutral or impartial in the sense that it would take place in a power-free or apolitical vacuum. It
also supports the idea that any synthesis, resulting from the clashing together of selves and
Others with their theses, makes up a new thesis, a particular universe, which should be open to
further dialectical revision. Every state-level synthesis is limited because one of its aspects is
material objectivity, i.e. the level of limited economical and material resources. When ever a
synthesis is made, it is based not only on what the outcome is from the struggle between the
conflicting parties in the last elections. When elections are over, the parties, forming the
government, make decisions, on how various material resources are concretely distributed
between all the members of the society. The government often also makes some alterations to
laws, institutional principles and so forth, according to the deliberations of its member parties. In
other words, the struggle between conflicting groups leads, through elections, to the formation
of a new government and, by the government’s deliberations, to some alterations at the level of
the objective reality. The transformation of any synthesis into a new thesis, open to the criticism
of opposition, takes place at this point. The government is formed by some parties, enough
like-minded to be able to make decisions and compromises together and execute its will through
administrative and bureaucratic bodies. The decisions must be particular and limited in order to
mean something concrete. The decisions cannot be vague or ambivalent; otherwise they would
give room for arbitrary interpretations and arbitrary application. Nevertheless, this rationality,
shared by the “like-minded” members of the government renders the government also a
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
“particular universe”. The government provides rational arguments for the decisions it
executes, and claims to act in the best interest of all. This claim becomes, however, the base for
criticism – or, in Hegelian words claim for recognition - coming from those who claim that it,
nevertheless, acts more in the interest of just some, not all. It needs to be checked and critically
analyzed by its outside, and clash with its outside (the Other as opposition), in order for its
rationality not to fall into parochialism which compromises the democratic idea that the state
ought to be governed by “all”.
The agonistic theory of democracy
The Hegelian dialectic insight of democracy, presented in this paper, resembles in some ways
the agonistic theory of democracy. Especially the political theorist Chantal Mouffe has spoken
for an idea of democracy in which a permanent, agonistic conflict between mutually
contradicting parties (between “we” and “them”) is considered as a constitutive and an
indispensable feature. Mouffe’s idea of the relationship between “we” and “them” resembles
in some ways the dialectical relationship between the self and the Other, defended in this text.
However, there are important differences between the dialectical notion of democracy defended
in this paper, and the theory of Chantal Mouffe. I shall argue that the idea of agonism as
formulated by Mouffe is actually incoherent.
In criticizing consensus-oriented authors like Rawls or Habermas, Mouffe uses the following
argument: The criticized authors try to solve the “paradox of democracy” by presenting a
comprehensive theory of democracy, and claim that all consistent democrats should agree with
them. However, an actual consensus on the truth of any particular interpretation of democracy
would, in effect, destroy the agonistic tensions which are central for democracy. An agreement
on the basic principles of democracy would stop the movement of democratic society, create a
stasis. It is this very process, produced by the tensions and differences that is really important
and valuable in democracy. Thus, all attempts to provide a comprehensive theory of democracy
are (indirectly) self-defeating. If the correct, true theory of democracy were to be found, and if it
were generally accepted it would undo the whole democracy. If a theory of what the relations
between the various mutual “others” (the political subjects) were recognized by the political
subjects themselves, there would be no attitude of exclusion any more. The political subjects
(which constitute each others “others”) would not exclude each others any more from their
vision of the ideal society, and try to gain universal recognition just for their own particular ideal
any more. This kind of “reciprocally recognitive” attitude would undo the democracy itself:
To believe that a final resolution of conflicts is eventually possible – even if it is seen as an
asymptotic approach to the regulative idea of a rational consensus – far from providing the
necessary horizon of a democratic project, is something that puts it at risk. Indeed, such an
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
illusion carries implicitly the desire for a reconciled society where pluralism is superseded. When
it is conceived in such a way, pluralist democracy becomes a “self-refuting ideal” because the
very moment of its realization would coincide with its disintegration (Mouffe 2000, 32)
For Mouffe, pluralism and difference are themselves positive goods. They are something we
should “valorize” and “be thankful for” (Mouffe 1993, 139). All attempts to “close” the
democratic process are dangerous because conflicts and confrontations are the very essence
of democracy:
One of the keys to the thesis of agonistic pluralism is that, far from jeopardizing democracy,
agonistic confrontation is in fact its very condition of existence (Mouffe 2000, 103)
Of course, not any confrontation or conflict would do. Pure power-struggles between
self-interested actors or clashes of forces between fanatical groups are not radical in the
required sense. A radical agonist does not praise all conflicts. Democratic conflicts are, in a
sense, always conflicts about democracy, about its content. They arise between principled and
sincerely held views:
Without a plurality of competing forces which attempt to define the common good, and aim at
fixing the identity of the community, the political articulation of the demos could not take place.
(Mouffe, 2000, 56)
According to Mouffe, the existence of different genuinely competing conceptions is essential:
Ideally, such a confrontation should be staged around the diverse conceptions of citizenship
which correspond to the different interpretations of the ethico-political principles:
liberal-conservative, social-democratic, neo-liberal, radical-democratic, and so on. Each of them
proposes its own interpretation of the ‘common good’… A well-functioning democracy calls for a
vibrant clash of democratic political positions. (ibid.., 103-4)
Thus, Mouffe shares the idea that a dialectical conflict is fundamental for democracy. However,
her own view remains thoroughly relativistic. No dialectical synthesis is possible. This makes
her own position ambivalent. Obviously, all the proponents of the different democratic
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
conceptions are expected to defend their own conception as true (correct, valid). Otherwise the
views would not “clash”. The theorist of agonistic democracy appears here as a stage-master,
as someone standing outside and above the confrontation. She knows that none of the
protagonists playing their part in the democratic drama is actually defending the true view, for
there cannot be any correct interpretation of the common good or the democratic basic
principles – that was her starting point. Nevertheless, because the confrontation between
different conceptions of citizenship and/or common good is the very condition of the existence
of a working democracy, it is important that there are sufficiently many people around who
sincerely hold these various convictions, however misguided they might be.
To conclude, Mouffe’s theory can be criticized by using the same form of argument she herself
uses against Rawls and Habermas. The theory of agonistic democracy is self-defeating in the
same way as the criticized theories are claimed to be. If all (or sufficiently many) citizens would
actually accept the agonistic view that there are no justifiable solutions to the problems of justice
and of common good, the essential agonism would disappear. In order to work, the agonistic
democracy has to presuppose that most people do not share the agonist view. To put it in
Hegelian terms, it presupposes a Lord-Bondsman –relationship.
For this reason, the agonistic theory cannot work as a basis for the self-understanding of those
subjects who themselves participate in political struggles. In Mouffe, politics is divided
dualistically into two realms. There is concrete politics, where hegemonic claims are made. This
realm is conflictual, and its processes take place through a “struggle for recognition”. Then
there is the realm of the observing theorist, who does not itself take part in the struggle for
recognition. Instead, the external theorists just observes how the various “terms” such as
“common good” become politically constructed within the various struggles. This agonistic
democracy is possible only when most people continue to believe in something which,
according to this theory, is actually impossible, a “necessary error”. I claim that my account
does not have these paradoxical consequences. The rival parties are not simply clashing and
struggling for hegemony. They may also recognize each others as legitimate rivals who are
continuously needed as rivals, because only their continuous presence makes the process itself
democratically legitimate.
Conclusion: distrust as the basis for trust
In modern western democracies people are expected to trust a political system which consists
of a government and a contradicting, distrusting opposition. Acting and decision-executing
government ought to be controlled and checked by an alert opposition, in Hegelian words an
Other. The Other provides a necessary “look from the outside” which cannot be disposed of in
order for the political system to be considered democratic. According to my analysis Hegel’s
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
theory of the dialectics between the self and the Other, presented in Phenomenology of Spirit,
supports this idea. Through it, it can be argued that any government which produces particular
decisions, based on specifically circumscribed arguments and rationale (as governments always
necessarily and rightfully do, in order not to give room for arbitrary governing) constitutes a
“particular universe”. Particular universes carry within them an aspect of particular political
subjectivity, democratic checking of which cannot be left to the hands of disengaged external
controllers, like judges or experts. Instead, internal controlling of those Others who are fully
engaged and fully affected by the governments decisions, is necessary, in order for not only
some specific aspects of government (falling under the expertise of for example juridical
experts) to be scrutinized. In order for the various inter-related aspects of the acting
governments actions to be critically evaluated “from the outside”, the political realm of the
outside opposition should not be diminished. The central and seemingly widely acknowledged
reason why the existence of an institutionalized opposition is considered as the base for the
legitimacy of the political system is that democratic changes in the substantive inside of the
government takes place through the distrusting criticism, coming from the outside. The criticism
comes from those who are inside the democratic society yet not under the pressure to consent
to or comply with the government’s rationale, because of a joint membership in the present
synthesis (unity) of the government. In fact, it is considered the ultimate role, even a democratic
and ethical duty, of the opposition to look at the government from a critical distance.
The idea that an institutionalized and internal conflict (carried by an institutionalized distrust
embodied in the opposition) is the source of general good and ethical life is a novel
development. It challenges most of the traditional political theories which considered conflict as
a potentially dangerous defect, feared to lead into disorder or possibly even to a violent
disintegration or fragmentation of the political body. The important idea in the internal conflict
and its capacity to give legitimacy to the political system, lies in the fact that through the
dialectics between the government and opposition, things concerning “all” (the present
synthesis, unity or “substance” of the state, shown as positive laws, institutions, distribution of
material resources and so forth) is in a constant democratic process and under critical ethical
evaluation “from the internal outside”.
I have argued that an organized distrust, in the form of opposition, is the fundamental source of
trust in democratic societies, and that this paradoxical unity of trust and distrust can be
conceived in terms of the dialectics of Hegel’s early philosophy. Would this kind of view help us
to understand any real-life political phenomena? Let me conclude this essay with an
example. An example of a political community which is often said to suffer from a “democracy
deficit” is the European Union. One possible reason why the EU is perceived as undemocratic
is the absence of a recognized government-opposition dimension. The Commission is officially
an “apolitical” government of technocrats, while in the European Parliament the majorities are
built on issue-by-issue basis. While the Parliament is constituted in a democratic way – by free
and equal elections - the lack of a responsible government and of an organized opposition
which would channel the distrust is the main cause of the perceived “deficit”. According to my
hypothesis, the low turnout in the elections of the Parliament and the increasing scepticism and
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
even cynicism towards the Union itself reflects this problem. The Euro-citizens, in Finland for
example, are not convinced that the power-holders within the Union have really deserved their
power in a meaningful, democratically dialectical process. Without an opposition, this distrust
may take a malign form.
References
Aristotle 1996. The Politics and The Constitution of Athens. Ed. S. Everson. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Barker, E. 1942. Reflections on Government, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Barker, E. 1951. Principles of Social & Political Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Benhabib, S. 1994. Deliberative Rationality and Models of Democratic Legitimacy.
Constellations 1. 2652.
Cohen, J. 1989. Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy. In A. Hamlin and P. Pettit (eds.) The
Good Polity. Oxford: Blackwell, 1734.
Habermas, J. 1996. Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a discourse theory of law and
democracy. Tr. W. Rehg, Cambridge (Mass.): MIT Press
Hegel, G. W. F. 1974. Philosophien des Rechts nach der Vorlesungsnachschrift K. G. von
Griesheims 1824/25. In K.-H. Ilting (ed.) G.W.F. Hegel: Vorlesungen über Rechtsphilosophie
1818-1831. Vol. 4. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog.
Hegel, G. W. F. 1977. Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. A. V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. [1807]
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
Hegel, G. W. F. 1967. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right,. Trans. T. M. Knox. Oxford: Oxford
University Press [1821]
Locke, J. 1988. Two Treatises of Government. Ed. P. Laslett. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. [1689]
Mouffe, C. 1993. The Return of the Political. London: Verso.
Mouffe, C. 2000. The Democratic Paradox. London: Verso.
Mouffe, C. 2005. On the Political. London: Routledge.
Roman-Lagerspetz, S. 2009. Striving for the Impossible. The Hegelian background of Judith
Butler. Acta Politica 16. Department of Political Science, University of Helsinki
Rosanvallon, P. 2006. Democracy Past and Future. Ed. S. Moyn. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Rousseau, J.-J. 1973. The Social Contract and Discourses. Ed. and tr. G. D. H. Cole. London:
Dent.
Schmitt, C. 1985. The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy. Tr. E. Kennedy. Cambridge (Mass.):
MIT Press. [1923]
Schmitt, C. 2008. Constitutional Theory. Tr. J. Seitzer. Durham (NC): Duke University Press.
[1928]
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Vol. 7, no. 2 (2012)
Category: Conference paper
Written by Sari Roman-Lagerspetz
Schumpeter, J. 1962. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy. New York: Harper & Row. [1942]
Urbinati, N. 2010. Unpolitical Democracy. Political Theory 38 (1): 65-92.
Weber, M. 1994. Political Writings. Tr. and ed. P. Lassman and R. Speirs. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Nordicum-Mediterraneum [nome.unak.is]
Phoca PDF
Powered by TCPDF (www.tcpdf.org)