The Secret Life of Literature
The Secret Life of Literature
Lisa Zunshine
The MIT Press
Cambridge, Massachusetts
London, England
© 2022 The Massachusetts Institute of Technology
This work is licensed to the public under a CC-BY_NC_SA license.
Subject to such license, all rights are reserved.
The MIT Press would like to thank the anonymous peer reviewers who provided
comments on drafts of this book. The generous work of academic experts is essential
for establishing the authority and quality of our publications. We acknowledge with
gratitude the contributions of these otherwise uncredited readers.
This book was set in Stone Serif and Stone Sans by Westchester Publishing Services.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Zunshine, Lisa, author.
Title: The secret life of literature / Lisa Zunshine.
Description: Cambridge, Massachusetts : The MIT Press, [2022] | Includes
bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2021031221 | ISBN 9780262046336 (hardcover)
Subjects: LCSH: Literature—Psychological aspects. | Cognition in literature. |
Psychology and literature. | Narration (Rhetoric)—Psychological aspects. |
Discourse analysis, Literary—Psychological aspects.
Classification: LCC PN56.P93 Z86 2022 | DDC 801/.9—dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2021031221
Contents
List of Illustrations
Preface
vii
ix
1
The Secret Life of Literature
2
Mindreading and Social Status
3
“Deep” History: Evolutionary and Neurocognitive Foundations
of Complex Embedment
1
59
99
4
Cultural History: Ideologies of Mind
5
Literary History: The Importance of Being Deceived
6
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
113
141
193
Conclusion: On the Future of the “Secret Life” of Literature
Notes
223
Bibliography
Index
305
273
219
List of Illustrations
Figure 1.1. Thompson, Tom Sawyer stamp, 1972
Figure 5.1. Frol Skobeev, dressed as a woman
Figure 6.1. Hutchins, Rosie’s Walk
Figure 6.2. Frazee, Hush, Little Baby
196
217
152
xiv
Preface
The Secret Life of Literature brings together cognitive science and literary
history to trace a series of patterns that made their early, modest, appearance in literature at least four thousand years ago and have, since then,
grown to become the cornerstone of literary imagination, while remaining largely invisible to readers and critics. It shows how social institutions
and political regimes can strengthen or weaken the hold of those patterns
and how they present in North American, British, Chinese, Russian, German, and Melanesian, as well as ancient Greek, Roman, and Mesopotamian
cultures.
“Cognitive” literary criticism is a relatively new field, yet one already
well populated by studies ranging across a variety of genres and cultures.1
Readers familiar with such studies will notice that this book is organized
differently from others. Instead of starting out by reviewing cognitive foundations of my argument, as is often done in such cases, I postpone this
review until chapter 3. I do this because I want my readers to be excited
about discovering something new about literature, before learning how
cognitive psychology and social neuroscience support these discoveries and
sharpen their meaning.
A brief road map: The volume is divided into six chapters. Chapter 1
introduces what I call the “secret life of literature,” showing how specific
patterns of “mindreading” (that is, of the capacity to explain people’s
behavior as caused by their unobservable mental states, such as thoughts,
desires, and intentions) have come to shape our interaction with novels,
plays, and narrative poems, as well as with memoirs focusing on imagination and consciousness. The conversation here is more practical than
theoretical: I use numerous examples to train the reader to recognize those
x
Preface
mindreading patterns in a variety of literary contexts. This chapter also
explores the fraught issue of the difference between popular and literary
fiction (e.g., Can a computer program distinguish between the two?) and
recounts my experience of taking a graduate seminar in creative writing, at
my home university, which I did in order to learn if writers themselves are
aware of their role in supporting the secret life of literature. (Spoiler alert!)
They mostly aren’t, and that’s a good thing.
Chapter 2 shifts the focus from what the secret life of literature is to
what it does, and the argument becomes more theoretical and historical.
I show that writers can intuitively experiment with the real-life relationship between social status and mindreading. Briefly, in real life, the lower
one’s relative social standing, the more active and perceptive a mindreader they are; in fiction, not necessarily. Here are some highlights of
this chapter. If you want to see how characters’ mindreading disparity is
used in works of literature foregrounding race, go to section 2.6. If you are
interested in the work of Mikhail Bakhtin and want to see how this disparity can become a form of heteroglossia in a novel obsessed with social
class, turn to section 2.8. To learn what happens to fictional characters’
mindreading profiles under totalitarian regimes, take a look at sections
2.10 and 2.11.
Chapters 3, 4, and 5 deal with the history of the secret life of literature, focusing, respectively, on its evolutionary and neurocognitive foundations, its relationship with community-specific mindreading values,
and its migration across different genres and national literary traditions.
Chapter 3 presents perspectives from social, developmental, clinical, and
evolutionary psychology, as well as cognitive neuroscience. Chapter 4 aims
to provide a comparative context for some of our unspoken but pervasive
beliefs about mindreading. Specifically, it builds on the insight of linguistic
anthropologists studying language socialization in Papua New Guinea, that
“the similarities and differences between these two practices—thinking
about others’ internal states and/or talking about them—are often at the
heart of culture.”2 We do not often think of literature as expressing a particular mindreading ideology—that is, who gets to talk about people’s mental states and who does not and which cultural institutions promote this
kind of talk and which suppress it. Once we start thinking about it this way,
however, a broad range of practices that we take for granted—for example,
Preface
xi
readers talking unembarrassedly about characters’ intentions; writers using
deception, eavesdropping, and shame as recurrent plot devices—appear in
new light. Chapter 5 explores the role of those plot devices, particularly
lying, in shaping the secret life of literature in ancient China and earlymodern Russia.
Chapter 6 turns to children’s literature. It follows treatment of mindreading in stories targeting one- to two-year-olds, three- to seven-year-olds,
and nine- to twelve-year-olds, as well as, provisionally, young adult audiences. It inquires, in particular, into the role of tricksters in stories geared
toward three- to seven-year-old children, and it looks at the interplay of
cognitive and historical factors involved in designating some texts as serious novels and others as “kiddie lit.”
A short conclusion speculates about the future of the secret life of literature, imagining travails of an author who decides to write a novel that
would break with this pattern. It revisits cultural institutions that would
make it hard for the author to do so—hard but not impossible, for, as the
preceding chapters will have demonstrated, mindreading ideologies that
underwrite the secret life of literature are not cut in stone.
Although this book is a work of literary criticism, it is not intended only
for literary critics. I tried to keep it as reader-friendly as possible, by banishing discursive scholarly references to endnotes and not assuming any
specialized knowledge on the part of my audience. While working on this
project, I shared my research-in-progress not just with literary scholars but
also with cognitive and social psychologists, as well as with anthropologists, ethnographers, philosophers, and students of media and communication. My hope is that my argument will continue to be of interest to
scholars from those disciplines, as well as to any habitual, or occasional,
readers of fiction.
Meanwhile, I gratefully acknowledge the valuable feedback provided
by my colleagues from the International Society for the Study of Narrative; the Forum for Cognitive and Affect Studies at the Modern Language
Association; the annual conference “Cognitive Futures in the Arts and the
Humanities”; the Chinese Association of Cognitive Poetics and Cognitive
Literary Studies at China University of Petroleum (Beijing), Hainan Normal
University (Haikou), and Guandong University of Foreign Studies (Guangzhou); the Program in Literary Linguistics and Cognitive Literature Studies
xii
Preface
at the Smolny Institute in Saint Petersburg State University; the Religion,
Cognition and Culture Research Unit of the Aarhus Institute for Advanced
Studies; the Cambridge Symposium on Cognitive Approaches to Children’s
Literature; the European Association of Social Psychology; the Center for
the Study of the Novel at Stanford University; and the Center for Science
and Society at Columbia University.
I am also grateful to friends and colleagues who have, for the past several
decades, provided me with invaluable support and whose brilliance and
kindness have kept me going: Porter Abbott, Denis Akhapkin, Frederick Luis
Aldama, Elaine Auyoung, Michael Austin, Alexandra Berlina, Guillemette
Bolens, Fritz Breithaupt, Rhonda Blair, George Butte, Emanuele Castano,
Terence Cave, Rita Charon, Mary Crane, Amy Cook, David Richter, Nancy
Easterlin, Felipe de Oliveira Fiuza, William Flesch, Monika Fludernik, Thalia R.
Goldstein, Paul L. Harris, David Herman, Patrick Colm Hogan, Tony Jackson, Isabel Jaén-Portillo, Suzanne Parker Keen, David Comer Kidd, Karin
Kukkonen, Joshua Landy, Haiyan Lee, Howard Mancing, Bruce McConachie, Muqing Xiong, Pascal Nicklas, Keith Oatley, Aaron Ngozi Oforlea,
Laura Otis, Alan Palmer, Jim Phelan, Natalie Phillips, Carl Plantinga, Merja
Polvinen, Peter Rabinowitz, Alan Richardson, Naomi Rokotnitz, MarieLaure Ryan, Ralph James Savarese, Bambi Schieffelin, Casey Schoenberger,
Nicola Shaughnessy, Julien Jacques Simon, Ellen Spolsky, Gabrielle Starr,
Francis Steen, Simon Stern, Peter Stockwell, John Sutton, Mark Turner,
Blakey Vermeule, J. Keith Vincent, and Wen Yongchao.
My special thanks are to Michael Holquist (who, sadly, passed away in
2016) and Douglas H. Whalen, my coauthors in a series of experiments
carried out at the Haskins Laboratories in New Haven and CUNY Graduate
Center and seeking to find out if the “secret life of literature” can be tested
empirically. I could not have wished for more creative and encouraging
friends and collaborators.
At the MIT Press, I am grateful to Philip Laughlin and his team of anonymous reviewers, whose detailed suggestions for revision have been truly
invaluable. In a couple of instances when I could not follow them, the
fault is all mine. I am also thankful to Andrew Katz for his thoughtful copyediting of the manuscript.
Some of this book’s arguments have first been published elsewhere. I
am grateful to the editors of PMLA, Narrative, and Eighteenth-Century Fiction
for letting me include material from my essays “The Secret Life of Fiction”
Preface
xiii
(PMLA 130, no. 3 [2015]); “Bakhtin, Theory of Mind, and Pedagogy: Cognitive Construction of Social Class” (Eighteenth-Century Fiction 30, no. 1
[2017]); and “What Mary Poppins Knew: Theory of Mind, Children’s Literature, History” (Narrative 27, no. 1 [2019]).
Last but not least, I thank Joel Kniaz, Etel Sverdlov, and Harry Zunshine.
Figure 1.1
Bradbury Thompson, Tom Sawyer stamp, 1972.
1
The Secret Life of Literature
1.1 What It Looks Like
In a famous scene from an American novel, one twelve-year-old boy is
hoodwinking another. The occasion is so iconic that, in 1972, the US Postal
Service honored it with a special stamp. Designed by the artist Bradbury
Thompson (figure 1.1), the stamp depicts Tom Sawyer pretending to be
absorbed in whitewashing a fence, while Ben Rogers watches intently.
Only a minute ago, Ben was playing a game—impersonating a Missouri
steamship—but now it has lost all charm for him. All he wants is to take
over Tom’s chore, and, after appropriate hesitation and negotiation, Tom
obliges, quietly exulting in his cleverness: “Tom gave up the brush with
reluctance in his face, but alacrity in his heart. And while the late steamer
Big Missouri worked and sweated in the sun, the retired artist sat on a barrel
in the shade close by, dangled his legs, munched his apple, and planned the
slaughter of more innocents. There was no lack of material; boys happened
along every little while; they came to jeer, but remained to whitewash.”1
Ben is sweating in the sun, Tom is sitting in the shade, and Twain is having
fun with a biblical reference. His twelve-year-old Herod will soon “slaughter”
more “innocents.” With macabre logic, Twain describes those innocents as
things inanimate. They merely “happen along,” as a “material” on which “the
retired artist” can work at leisure, dangling his legs and munching an apple.
What underlies these ironic twists—that is, the reason that we understand why the boys are described as being massacred and manipulated—is
a series of psychological insights developed by Twain’s protagonist. Tom
doesn’t want his friends to realize that he hates whitewashing the fence.
He discovers that if he makes them think that he enjoys it, they’ll see it as
play instead of work and even pay him for the privilege of doing his chore.
2
Chapter 1
Take another look at those insights. Each of them is structured as a
mental state within a mental state within yet another mental state: Tom
doesn’t want his friends to realize that he hates whitewashing the fence; he
wants them to think that he enjoys it. Granted, these are my formulations,
but if you try to come up with one of your own, you will discover that, if
you want to capture the complexity of the social situation conjured up by
Twain, simpler descriptions of mental functioning, such as “he wants them
to do his work for him” or “they think that he likes painting the fence,”
won’t do. In fact, they’ll misrepresent what’s going on, until you find a way
to connect them, through another thought or intention. It seems, in other
words, that, however you choose to phrase it, you’ll need to recursively
embed mental states on at least the third level.
Cognitive psychologists and philosophers of mind talk about “mental
states” in conjunction with “theory of mind” and “mindreading,” which
are metaphorical terms2 used to describe our capacity to see behavior as
caused by mental states, such as thoughts, desires, feelings, and intentions.3
Embedment is yet another metaphor, which comes in handy when we want
to talk about complex social dynamics that depend on people’s awareness
of their own and other people’s states. (Although cognitive scientists have
several different terms to talk about this kind of awareness, including, for
instance, “recursive intention-reading” and “recursive mind-reading,”4 I
prefer the shorter “embedment.”) To illustrate the way the term “mental
states” will be used throughout this study, here are some examples, with
mental states italicized:
•
“My last name begins with a Z” contains no mental states, embedded or
otherwise.5
•
“I’m glad that my last name begins with a Z because the teacher may not
get to the end of the list today” contains just one mental state: my being
happy about being at the end of the class list.
•
“I am afraid that the teacher will remember that she hasn’t called on me
for a while” contains two embedded mental states: my thinking about
what my teacher may be thinking.
•
Finally, “I wonder if the teacher realizes that I’m hoping that she won’t call
on me today because my last name begins with a Z and will thus on purpose start at the end of the list” contains three embedded mental states:
my thinking about the teacher’s thinking about my thinking.
The Secret Life of Literature
3
Note that we have to rely on this kind of propositional, or representational, language (“I wonder if she realizes that I’m hoping”) to talk about
embedded mental states, because it is the tool that we have at our disposal to model the complex intersubjective dynamic of such situations. The
actual cognitive processes involved in our experience of those situations
may not be structured like embedded representations or may not even “be
structured at all.”6 Moreover, mindreading, especially in face-to-face communication, depends on embodied feedback loops (for instance, there may
be something about the expression on my teacher’s face, as she catches me
watching her intently, that may strengthen or weaken my hopes), but these
important nuances are left out of our crude linear diagrams.
Later, in chapter 3, I will consider in detail this problem of our limited
vocabulary. Here, I want us to focus on something else. Ask yourself, How
often, in our daily goings-on, do we thus embed mental states on the third
and fourth levels? Or, to put it differently, how often do we find ourselves
involved in social situations that would require this kind of language to
describe them? Although it certainly happens—I am thinking now about
faculty meetings, fraught family get-togethers, and love triangles—a majority of our routine social interactions probably don’t require such complex
embedments. For instance, I see my neighbor coming out of his house and
strolling toward his car, and I assume that he wants to go somewhere; or
I see my son pulling out a box of pencils, and I assume that he intends to
draw. (I may not be consciously aware of my assumptions, yet they may
influence my subsequent course of action.)
So, on the one hand, yes, “human collaborative activity and cooperative
communication both rest on . . . recursive intention-reading.”7 But, on the
other hand, thinking about thinking about thinking (third-level embedment) “occurs in interpersonal cognition in real life less frequently” than,
for instance, thinking about thinking (second-level embedment). The former, as the psychologist Patricia Miller et al. put it, “has a lower ecological
plausibility.”8
Hence an important difference between our daily mindreading and our
experience of reading literature. Literature creates intersubjective situations
of a kind that can be described as depending on “complex embedments of
mental states” at a much greater frequency than it happens in our daily
life. Specifically—and this is what I call the secret life of literature—to make
sense of what’s going on in novels, plays, and narrative poems, as well as in
4
Chapter 1
memoirs focused on imagination and consciousness, we constantly embed
mental states on at least the third level. The key word here is “constantly,”
for neither literary critics nor lay readers appreciate the true scale of this
phenomenon. To put it starkly, literature, as we know it today (this is an
important point that I will keep emphasizing) cannot function on lower
than the third level of embedment. As such, it differs, for example, from
expository nonfiction, such as newspaper articles and textbooks,9 which
may contain occasional forays into the third level but can also subsist, quite
happily, on just the first and second levels.
Literature, of course, is a capacious concept, and it encompasses many
more genres than I just listed. To give just a few examples, it includes personal essays by writers ranging from Sei Shonagon and Michel de Montaigne
to Wole Soyinka and Joan Didion; mirrors for princes, from Augustine’s The
City of God to Machiavelli’s The Prince; and political speeches, from Lincoln’s “The Gettysburg Address” to King’s “I Have a Dream.” While these
texts range widely in their frequency of complex embedment (and there
are, among them, some pretty spectacular embedders), they mostly do not
depend on it to the same high degree as do novels, plays, narrative poems,
and memoirs concerned with consciousness.
In the latter, embedded mental states can be found on the level of individual sentences, paragraphs/stanzas, and whole chapters/acts.10 They can
belong to characters, narrators, (implied) authors, and readers, in a vast
variety of combinations.11 In “Tom wants his friends to think that he enjoys
his chore,” the third-level embedment involves the novel’s characters. But
at the same time, yet another complex embedment arises from an intricate
give-and-take between the narrator and his audience.12 The narrator expects
that his readers will appreciate his mischievous intention, as he likens Tom,
in the same breath, to King Herod and to a retired artist. Again, this is my
formulation, but if you try to explain how this passage achieves its ironic
effect, you are likely to find yourself speculating about how the author
might have been intuitively anticipating his readers’ thinking.13
It would be wrong to assume, however, that we factor mental states of
the implied author and reader into any complex embedment. Of course, we
can say, “the implied author wants us to know that Tom wants his friends to
think that he enjoys his chore,” and call it a case of fifth-level embedment
instead of third, but those extra levels are redundant because they don’t
contribute anything to our understanding of the passage. In contrast, the
The Secret Life of Literature
5
references to King Herod and to a retired artist are the kind of “communicative event”14 that necessitates a recognition of a particular intentionality
behind it.15
When we read, we do not spell it out to ourselves the way I just did.
Indeed, in spite of the language that I may use to describe it—such as “we
are aware” or “the author wants us to know”—most of it doesn’t rise to the
level of conscious awareness. Nevertheless, on some level we must be keeping
track of those complex intentionalities (which is a term I will use interchangeably with “mental states” to avoid sounding repetitive), because, otherwise,
how would we explain to ourselves, say, Twain’s evocation of the Massacre of
Innocents in a scene that had nothing to do with infanticide? To recognize
an allusion or to appreciate a metaphor is to acknowledge an intention.16
Throughout this book, I use the term “implied mental states” to refer
to thoughts and feelings of characters, narrators, authors, and readers that
are thus not spelled out but are nevertheless integral to our making sense of
what we read. But, of course, a work of fiction may also contain complex
embedments of mental states that are explicitly spelled out by the author.
For instance, think of the time when Tom first encounters Becky Thatcher
and starts showing off by engaging in various “dangerous gymnastic performances.” Becky observes him for a while, then throws him a flower and
disappears inside her house. Tom keeps up his antics for some time, because
he hopes that she is still aware of his interest in her. Or, as Twain puts it,
explicitly describing Tom’s embedded thoughts, “Tom comforted himself
a little with the hope that she had been near some window, meantime, and
been aware of his attentions.”17
Here is another explicitly spelled-out complex embedment. When Aunt
Polly punishes Tom for breaking a sugar bowl and then finds out that it was
Sid who broke it, she can’t bring herself to confess that she has been in the
wrong—for “discipline forbade that”—and goes “about her affairs with a
troubled heart,” while Tom, perfectly aware of her remorse, is quietly exalting
in it. He knows that his aunt is yearning for his forgiveness (third-level embedment), and he enjoys knowing that she is yearning for his forgiveness (fourthlevel). Or, as Twain puts it, “He knew that in her heart his aunt was on her
knees to him, and he was morosely gratified by the consciousness of it.”18
What is crucial about these third- and fourth-level embedments is that
they do not just occasionally happen along. Instead, any given paragraph
contains multiple complex embedments, sometimes implied, sometimes
6
Chapter 1
explicitly spelled out, sometimes a combination of the two. As I am writing this and leafing through Tom Sawyer, I reach almost at random for a
complex embedment here and a complex embedment there; but in pretty
much every case, I can turn to a group of sentences preceding or following
any passage that I just quoted for you, and it will contain another implied
or explicitly spelled-out complex embedment.
I started this chapter with a picture of a postal stamp, so before moving
on, let us briefly circle back to the visual. Do visual representations, such
as paintings and movies, also depend on complex embedment of mental
states? A short answer to this question is that they do—feature movies more
consistently than paintings—and in ways specific to their contexts.
For instance, Bradbury Thompson’s portrayal of Tom and Ben is brimming
with intentionalities: that of the artist (who apparently decided to portray
the boys younger than they are in the story); that of the particular beholder
(for I am aware, as I am looking at this stamp, of trying to square the artist’s
vision with my own perceptions of Tom Sawyer, formed years ago, in a different language, and then layered with the later, “American” impressions); and,
of course, that of the characters themselves (i.e., Tom wants Ben to think that
he is too absorbed in his task to even notice him). As we take in this stamp, we
may toggle between different constellations of complex embedments. This
“secret life” of visual images deserves its own study, but for now we return
to literature.
1.2 A Dime a Dozen
Sometimes, shortly after I’d given a talk about embedded mental states, I
would receive emails from members of my audience, something to the effect
of “Have you noticed this embedment in such and such work of fiction?”
On the one hand, such letters make me happy: they show that the senders
are now aware of this phenomenon and want to share their new awareness.
On the other hand, a part of me is wondering if it means that I failed to
get across one of my key points, which is that third-level embedments in
literature are nothing to write home about: they are a dime a dozen. True,
their frequency increases dramatically with the advent of certain genres,
such as ninth-century Chinese tales of romance, eleventh-century Japanese
novels, sixteenth-century Spanish novels, and eighteenth-century English
novels. But even the earliest works of literature available to us, such as The
The Secret Life of Literature
7
Epic of Gilgamesh (ca. 2100 BC), already feature some complex embedments.
And, generally (although with some fascinating exceptions, which I address
later), when it comes to a work of fiction written within the past three hundred years, to discover a third-level embedment in it is roughly as exciting
as to discover a noun.
Along the same lines, I suggest to students interested in “cognitive”
approaches to literature that merely locating a series of complex embedments in this or that text does not constitute literary analysis. The question
is not whether such embedments are there—for they are pretty much guaranteed to be there—but what effect they have on our interaction with the
text. For instance, if complex embedments involve mental states of characters and are explicitly spelled out, then the text in question is more likely
to be considered “popular fiction.” In contrast, “literary fiction” of the kind
that may end up on a college syllabus tends to include embedded mental
states of narrators and implied authors and readers (in addition to mental
states of characters) and to imply mental states (in addition to or instead of
explicitly spelling them out). So thinking about different types of complex
embedment allows us to understand something new about the distinction
between “low-brow” and “high-brow” literature.
It also alerts us to cultural contexts that sustain those distinctions. For
instance, when students encounter a work of fiction in a college literature
course, they tend to work harder on reading implied complex embedments
into it and expect to be rewarded for doing so (more about that in chapter
4). In contrast, when readers are faced with a text that they judged a priori as
“having lower literary merit”—as, for instance, may be the case with readers
prejudiced against science fiction—they may “exert less inference effort”19
in situations that require supplying mentalistic explanations of characters’
behavior. This is not to say that our intuitions about embedded mental states
are solely determined by the context in which we read a given text but that
we are sensitive to both such contexts and the cues supplied by the text.
Here is another way in which paying attention to complex embedments
opens up new venues in literary analysis. It turns out that some fictional
characters are consistently portrayed as more capable of embedding mental
states on a high (i.e., third and fourth) level than are others. What factors inform the intuitive decision, on the part of the author, to make one
character more “sociocognitively complex” than another? More often than
not, the decision seems to be influenced by the character’s social status,
8
Chapter 1
which is figured out along the lines of class, gender, or race. A “cognitive”
approach thus builds on and complements the rich literary-critical tradition of exploring the role of class, gender, and race considerations in the
construction of fictional subjectivity.
Then there is also the issue of the history of complex embedment in literature. What combinations of cognitive/cultural/historical contingencies
make it more or less likely that a particular literary tradition would be characterized by a commitment to complex embedments? In some ways, this is
the most difficult question one can ask, and we may never come up with
a definitive answer. Yet exploring this issue is important, if only because it
forces us to become aware of a broader range of historical factors than we
usually settle for, in our critical studies.
So the question is not “Are there any complex embedments in this text?”—
because, almost always, there are—but “What work do they do?” and “How
has it come to be that way?” These are the questions that I encourage my
students to ask and that I, myself, ask in the chapters that follow. But, first, I
want to give you a range of examples of complex embedments, to show what
forms they take in different texts. I hope that, after reading this chapter, you,
too, will be struck by this phenomenon: apparently so essential to our interaction with literature yet so invisible, flying, mostly, under the critical radar.
1.3 Explicitly Spelled-Out Mental States
The majority of complex embedments in literature are implied rather than
explicitly spelled out. In fact, some texts contain next to zero explicitly
articulated embedments. Still, many do. In this section, I present examples of such explicit embedments, starting with works of fiction published
recently and then moving back in time and ending with The Epic of Gilgamesh. I do not analyze any of the passages—that will come in later sections. I just pile them up to give you some idea of the range of literary texts
that depend on explicit complex embedments. (In what follows, emphasis
is mine throughout, unless stated otherwise.)
In Elena Ferrante’s The Story of the Lost Child, the protagonist says to a
friend, “I’m laughing out of despair, because I’ve never been so offended,
because I feel humiliated in a way that I don’t know if you can imagine.”20 In
Sally Rooney’s Conversations with Friends, Frances reports her thoughts as
she observes a man raising both eyebrows at another man in response to
The Secret Life of Literature
9
something another woman has said: “I thought it was cowardly of Philip to
look at Andrew, whom I knew he didn’t even like, and it made me uncomfortable.”21 In Rachel Cusk’s Transit, a woman gets up to leave after a lunch
with her friend, while “darting frequent glances” at her: “It was as if she
was trying to intercept my vision of her before I could read anything into what
I saw.”22 In Tsitsi Dangarembga’s Nervous Conditions, the narrator doesn’t
want to think through the implications of the “treacherous mazes” of her
thoughts about the inescapability of female victimization: “I didn’t want
to reach the end of those mazes, because there, I knew, I would find myself
and I was afraid I would not recognize myself after taking so many confusing
directions.”23 In Jokha Al Harthi’s Celestial Bodies, a young woman named
Khawla cannot understand why her sister, Asma, does not realize that the
religious texts that she is so fond of bore other people to death: “Khawla was
astonished at how oblivious Asma seemed to the awful boredom these ancient
books induced.”24 In Ben Lerner’s Leaving the Atocha Station, the protagonist
thinks that his communication with his Spanish friend, Theresa, is becoming a travesty: “I saw her reflected in my eyes, saw that she knew, or was
coming to know, that what interest I held for her, all of it, was virtual, that
my appeal for her had little to do with my actual writing or speech, and
while she was happy to let me believe she believed in my profundity, on
some level she was aware that she was merely encountering herself.”25
I chose my next example on a lark. The sentence that contains the spelledout embedment is the story in its entirety, Joy Williams’s “The Museum.”
Here it is: “We were not interested the way we thought we would be interested.”26
With my next example, I want to show you that science fiction writers
do not shun complex embedment. This, in response to the assumption that
I encounter often enough (and that has served as the impetus for the study
quoted earlier),27 which is that works of science fiction get by without representing complex mental states.28 In Philip K. Dick’s Do Androids Dream of
Electric Sheep?, characters can preprogram their feelings on a special “mood
organ.” This allows the author both to depict complex emotions arising
during a marital quarrel and to comment on the presumably mechanical
nature of their emotional life.
So here is Rick Deckard trying to decide how he wants to make himself
feel during an unpleasant conversation with his wife: “At his console he
hesitated between dialing for a thalamic suppression (which would abolish
his mood of rage) or a thalamic stimulant (which would make him irked
10
Chapter 1
enough to win the argument).” Rick wonders if he wants to quell or to ratchet
up his feeling of rage. Moreover, his wife is watching him closely, ready to
“dial the maximum” on her mood organ if he dials “for greater venom” on
his, that is, intending to become even angrier in response to his anger.29
To run a bit ahead of myself, this scene also contains some implied
embedments, though, perhaps, to appreciate them one has to be rereading
the novel. Repeat readers may enjoy the irony of the situation in which the
character whose job it is to hunt down and kill androids—those, presumably, not capable of feeling genuine emotions—himself uses a mood organ.
As Ralph James Savarese puts it, “here, the technological apparatus is active
and animate; the human hero, passive and inanimate. . . . Even his feelings
aren’t strictly organic.”30 Were we to spell out the underlying embedment
(which, again, is not something we consciously do when we read), we may
say that the author wants his readers to be aware of the muddled thinking
behind the discrimination between those who “truly” experience emotions
and those who “choose” to experience them.
Back to explicit embedments. In Shirley Jackson’s short story “The Beautiful Stranger,” an unhappily married suburban wife has a sudden revelation that her emotionally abusive husband is gone and in his place there
is a “beautiful stranger.” This new man, moreover, knows that she is afraid
that her husband may return and is thus not surprised when she looks up
at him for reassurance that he is not her husband: “She was aware from his
smile that he had perceived her doubts, and yet he was so clearly a stranger
that, seeing him, she had no need of speaking.”31
In E. M. Forster’s Howards End, Margaret Schlegel’s fiancé, Henry Wilcox,
is revealed to have had an affair, ten years before, with a woman who is now
Leonard Bast’s common-law wife, Jacky. Margaret’s sister, Helen, fresh from
the ruckus at the Wilcox’s garden party, at which Henry and Jacky have
accidentally come face-to-face, flies back to London and forces her brother,
Tibby, to consider a baffling dilemma that he’d rather not consider: “Ought
Margaret to know what Helen knew the Basts to know?”32
These were all examples from relatively recent literary past. Let us now
start moving further back in time. In Lev Tolstoy’s Anna Karenina (1877),
Alexei Karenin is made to listen to Anna’s delirious speech while she, as
everybody believes, is dying: “Alexei Alexandrovich’s inner disturbance
kept growing, and now reached such a degree that he ceased to struggle
with it; he suddenly felt that what he had considered an inner disturbance
The Secret Life of Literature
11
was, on the contrary, a blissful state of soul, which suddenly gave him a
new, previously unknown happiness.”33
In Jane Austen’s Pride and Prejudice (1813), Miss Bingley talks to Elizabeth
about Mr. Wickham’s regiment in Mr. Darcy’s hearing, because she hopes
that Elizabeth will be embarrassed imagining Mr. Darcy thinking about the
Bennett girls’ involvement with that regiment: “[She] had . . . intended to
discompose Elizabeth, by bringing forward the idea of a man to whom she
believed her partial, to make her betray a sensibility which might injure her in
Darcy’s opinion, and perhaps to remind the latter of all the follies and absurdities by which some part of her family were connected with that corps.”34
In Cao Xueqin’s novel Dream of the Red Chamber, also known as The Story
of the Stone (ca. 1750–1760s), Dai-yu explains to Bao-yu why she is angry at
him for having earlier tried to prevent their cousin Xiang-yun from making fun of her: “But what about that look you gave Yun? Just what did you
mean by that? I think I know what you meant. You meant to warn her that
she would cheapen herself by joking with me as an equal.”35
In Shakespeare’s sonnet 42, the speaker is constructing a complicated
argument in order to console himself for the heartbreaking discovery that
his mistress and his friend are having an affair. The “loving offenders,” he
proposes, are actually doing it for his sake: they want to prove their devotion to him. The young man wants to love what the speaker loves: “Thou
dost love her, because thou know’st I love her.” Just so, his mistress allows
herself to be loved by the young man because she, too, wants to be loved by
a man whom the speaker loves: “And for my sake even so doth she abuse
me, / Suffering my friend for my sake to approve her.”
The ending of the poem (“But here’s the joy; my friend and I are one; /
Sweet flattery! then she loves but me alone”) is open to two different interpretations. Either the speaker is happy that his mistress wants to find new
ways of expressing her love for him, or the speaker is aware that he is trying
to make himself feel better by thinking that his mistress wants to find new
ways of expressing her love for him. It is a choice between self-flattery and
self-awareness, and it is a complex embedment of mental states either way.36
In Nizami Ganjavi’s twelfth-century narrative poem The Story of Layla
and Majnun, Kais doesn’t feel jealous of other boys in school who stare “at
Layla open-mouthed” or, if the school is closed, “roam the alleyways and
the passages between the market-stalls, all in the hope of catching a tiny
glimpse of her dimpled face,” because he knows that they don’t love her as
12
Chapter 1
much as he loves her: “Naturally, Kais knew that the other boys desired
[Layla], but he also knew that they could not desire her as much as he did, and
so their antics did not perturb him in the least.”37
Let us go yet further back, to the ninth century’s Book of Exeter. In the
Old English poem “The Wanderer,” the speaker wonders why he is not more
depressed when he thinks about death:
Indeed I cannot think
why my spirit
does not darken
when I ponder on the whole
life of men throughout the world,
How they suddenly
left the floor (hall),
the proud thanes.38
In Petronius’s Satyricon (first century AD), Lichas wants to sleep with
Encolpius to make up for Encolpius’s currently sleeping with Lichas’s longterm mistress, Tryphaena. Encolpius is not interested, and Lichas arranges for
Tryphaena to fall for Encolpius’s slave and lover, Giton. Lichas hopes that the
jealous Encolpius will want to make Tryphaena angry by taking up with him
and thus takes “the trouble to draw [his] attention” to Tryphaena’s relationship with Giton. The plan works well. As Encolpius reports, “Therefore I was
the more ready to treat him nicely, and he was delighted beyond measure—
being of course quite sure that my lady’s ill-treatment of me would kindle my
disgust, and that in my anger I should feel more kindly disposed to him.”39
In The Odyssey (eighth century BC), one of Penelope’s suitors, Eurymachus, wants to assure her that her son, Telemachus, mustn’t be afraid of
him: “To this Eurymachus son of Polybus answered: . . . ‘Telemachus is
much the dearest friend I have, and has nothing to fear from the hands
of us suitors. Of course, if death comes to him from the gods, he cannot
escape it.’ He said this to quiet her, but in reality he was plotting against
Telemachus.”40 Eurymachus wants Penelope to stop worrying about the suitors’ intentions vis-à-vis Telemachus. (Homer, of course, hastens to explain to
us that Eurymachus is lying, but our conversation about lying and literary
history will have to wait until a later chapter.)
In The Epic of Gilgamesh (ca. 2100 BC), the king of the city of Shurrupak,
named Utnapishtim, is told by God Ea to tear down his house and build
a boat that would allow him and his family to survive a great flood that
The Secret Life of Literature
13
is about to kill everybody else. Utnapishtim then asks Ea, very reasonably,
how he should explain his actions to other people in Shurrupak: “Then Ea
opened his mouth and said to me, his servant, ‘Tell them this: I have learnt
that Enlil is wrathful against me, I dare no longer walk in his land nor live in
his city; I will go down to the Gulf to dwell with Ea my lord. But on you he
will rain down abundance, rare fish and shy wild-fowl, a rich harvest-tide.
In the evening the rider of the storm will bring you wheat in torrents.’”41
Ea wants the people to believe that another god, Enlil, is angry at Utnapishtim and that by going down to the Gulf, Utnapishtim hopes to escape
Enlil’s wrath. There is plenty of cruel irony in the picture of abundance
about to rain on the city that Ea expects Utnapishtim to plant in the heads
of his doomed compatriots. By the time Utnapishtim is telling this story to
Gilgamesh, the giant flood has already taken place, so he must be aware of
this irony. That is, he knows that Ea wanted to make sure that the citizens of
Shurrupak wouldn’t get alarmed at the sight of his boat and try to do something to escape the coming disaster, just as he knows what Ea’s fanciful talk
of “rich harvest-tide” and “wheat in torrents” truly portended. But to talk
about irony and implicit realizations, we must go to the next section.
1.4 Implied Mental States: Dramatic Irony and Beyond
In ancient Mesopotamia, Ea was associated with wisdom, magic, and mischief—a trickster figure. Indeed, trickster tales, with their plots of deception,
may have been the earliest fictional contexts for implied complex embedments. And so must have been drama, for what is “dramatic irony” but a
cultural shortcut for implicitly acknowledging a particular mindreading
dynamic? The audience knows that a character doesn’t know. And what is it
that the poor character is so fatally unaware of? More often than not, it has
something to do with the intentions of another character, of a deity, or, even,
with the character’s own intentions, which have been rendered calamitously
obscure to them. This state of affairs doesn’t have to be explicitly spelled out,
yet the audiences must be aware of it (an awareness that necessitates embedding complex mental states!) in order to make sense of what is going on.
Because dramatic irony is thus a prototypical implied third-level embedment, I start this section with several examples from plays and then segue
to narrative poems, short stories, and novels. The trickster tales will have to
wait until a later chapter, dealing with the history of complex embedments.
14
Chapter 1
Note, too, that, when talking about drama, I focus on playscripts and not
performance. The latter, of course, brings in more and different complex
embedments than are present in the script. For instance, the social psychologist Tiziano Furlanetto and his colleagues have found that when an actor’s
“gaze and action [do] not signal the same intention,” observers engage in
a stronger “spontaneous perspective-taking,” which suggests that, “in presence of ambiguous behavioral intention, people are more likely take the
other’s perspective to try to understand the action.” Thus, if we imagine a
character onstage who, in the middle of a complex social interaction with
someone else, would start reaching for an object without looking at it, that
action alone would complicate our perception of their intentions vis-à-vis
others.42 As Furlanetto et al. put it, “observing a person grasping without
looking may thus be perceived as ambiguous. What is he planning to do?
Why is he not looking at the object he is reaching for?”43
This is just one small example of the role of embodiment in modulating and complicating an audience’s perception of actors’ embedded intentionality.44 In general, exploration of embedded mental states that emerge
when actors widen and explore the space between their characters’ words
and their body language deserves a separate study. It is not my aim here
to undertake such a study, so we return to mental states implied by texts
alone.
In Shakespeare’s Othello, Iago wants Othello to think that Desdemona is in
love with Cassio. In Romeo and Juliette, Romeo does not know that Juliette is
not dead but merely wants some people to think that she is dead. In Measure
for Measure, Duke Vincentio wants Isabella to think that he doesn’t believe her
story about Angelo’s “intemperate lust.”45 In Twelfth Night, Maria, Sir Toby
Belch, and Fabian want Malvolio to think that Olivia loves him.
These are all act- and scene-level implied embedments. For a quick example of a sentence-level implied embedment in drama, consider a scene from
Twelfth Night, in which Malvolio first courts Olivia and then exits the stage
in full anticipation of the “greatness” that will soon be “thrust upon” him.
Once he is gone, Shakespeare has another character, Fabian, make a “nod
to the audience,”46 which starts off a complex embedment involving the
audience, the author, and the characters. When Fabian says, “If this were
played upon a stage now, I could condemn it as an improbable fiction,”47
the author slyly tells his spectators that he knows that they know that the
characters don’t know that they are upon a stage now.
The Secret Life of Literature
15
More scene-level complex embedments: In George Etherege’s The Man
of Mode (1676), Dorimant knows that his new mistress, though believing
herself injured by him, will nevertheless help him to deceive his old mistress (who also happens to be her friend) because she is afraid that the old
mistress will realize that the new mistress has been lying to her.48 In Oliver
Goldsmith’s She Stoops to Conquer (1773), Hastings doesn’t want his friend
Marlow to know that he is mortified that Marlow gave the jewels that Hastings had earlier entrusted him with, to Mrs. Hardcastle for safekeeping.
In Wang Shifu’s play The Story of the Western Wing (thirteenth century),
Oriole’s maid, Crimson, encourages student Zhang to pursue her young mistress, because she thinks that she knows Oriole’s true feelings about the attractive young man. As Zhang becomes too importunate, however, and Oriole
responds with indignation, Crimson realizes that she must have been wrong
in assuming that Oriole cares less about her honor than her love for Zhang.
In Layla and Majnun, when the main protagonists, still children, are
basking “in the glow of each other’s love,” the narrator asks us—that is,
wants us—to imagine what other people around them may be thinking about
their feelings: “Did others realize what had happened between Kais and his
Layla? Did they see the stolen looks, the furtive glances that passed between
them? Could they read the signs and crack the codes of secret love that
bound their hearts together? Who knew about them and how much was
known? Until one day, in the market, a voice was heard to say, ‘Kais and
Layla are in love. Have you not heard?’”49
In Austen’s Emma (1815), Frank Churchill wants onlookers to think that
he is interested in Emma in order to conceal his engagement with Jane Fairfax. In Forster’s Howards End, all throughout the novel, that is, “throughout
Margaret’s various conversation with the Wilcoxes, her marriage to Henry
Wilcox, and her sister’s involvement with the Basts,” readers know that
Margaret doesn’t know (while the Wilcoxes do know) that the late Mrs. Wilcox had wanted her to inherit Howards End.50
In the opening of Anton Chekhov’s short story “Rothschild’s Fiddle”
(1894), we learn that the “town was small, worse than a village, and populated almost only by old people, who died so rarely that it was quite annoying.”51 One can’t help wondering what kind of person would consider it so
patently obvious that old people should hurry up and die. To map out our
implicit reaction explicitly, the narrator wants the reader to wonder who
would want old people to die and why.
16
Chapter 1
In Lu Xun’s “A Madman’s Diary” (1918), the protagonist finds it infinitely amusing that a doctor, whom his older brother brought in to consult,
says that he’ll be “better” if he rests “quietly for a few days.” Because he
thinks that the doctor is “the executioner in disguise” and that what he
and the brother really want is to eat him, resting quietly for a few days will
only fatten him up and thus give them “more to eat.” So he laughs uproariously and watches them turn pale, “awed” by his “courage and integrity”:
“I could not help roaring with laughter, I was so amused. I knew that in
this laughter were courage and integrity. Both the old man and my brother
turned pale, awed by my courage and integrity.”52 The reader knows, however, that the protagonist doesn’t realize that the reason that the two men
turn pale is that they think that his laughter is a sure sign of his insanity. Or,
to put it differently, the implied author wants the readers to realize that the
mad protagonist misinterprets the body language of his visitors.
When Maggie, the protagonist of Hannah Pittard’s novel Listen to Me
(2016), finds an empty bottle of champagne in the recycling bin, her heart
sinks. Her husband, Mark, has apparently tossed “without ceremony” the
bottle left over from their last anniversary, which she has been saving. She
wonders, next, if this is a test and if Mark is “measuring her steadiness”—
for she has been going through a rough time lately—“by relieving her of an
ultimately trivial trinket.” If so, she decides, she “would pass his test with
flying colors.” That is, she wants him to think (were he to see the bottle, now
placed “at the very top” of the bin) that she is not overly sentimental about it.
Except that (dramatic irony!) Maggie has just torn off and saved as a keepsake “a sliver of the pink foil,” which means that she is actually failing the
test that she imagines Mark has set up for her.53 Or, to spell out this embedment explicitly, the implied author wants the reader to realize that Maggie
is fooling herself. (And so is, for that matter, Mark, but the implied embedments involved in his self-deception are constructed on other occasions.)
The first sentence of Zadie Smith’s On Beauty (2005), “One may as well
begin with Jerome’s emails to his father,” overflows with embedded intentionality.54 The implied author wants her readers to know that the action
will be filtered through the consciousness of a reflective narrator. And there
is more, of course. Those who are familiar with the opening of Howards End,
“One may as well begin with Helen’s letters to her sister,” will sense yet
another set of intentions in Smith’s first sentence.55 The author wants her
readers to know that the action will be filtered through the consciousness
The Secret Life of Literature
17
of a reflective narrator—and that she means her novel to be a meditation
on Forster’s novel. There are no direct references to mental states in the
sentence about Jerome’s emails to his father, yet its impact on the reader is
directly bound to its embedded intentionality.56
I don’t think we notice it, though. Were I to articulate my feelings upon
first opening Smith’s novel, I would say that I experienced a pleasing jolt
of recognition and something that could be expressed in words as, “Oh, so
it’s that kind of book!” It is when I try to slow down and figure out what
kind of mental work goes into “Oh, so it’s that kind of book!” that I end up
considering the embedded intentions of the author.
Let us now revisit Williams’s one-sentence story “The Museum”: “We
were not interested the way we thought we would be interested.”57 I used it
in the previous section as an example of explicitly spelled-out embedments
in literature, but its affective punch may actually reside with its implied
embedments. “The Museum’s” protagonists watch closely their emotional
responses, especially when they find themselves in a cultural context that
is expected to elicit a particular kind of response. The story thus draws the
reader’s attention to a specific sensibility: one predicated on self-awareness
yet not always happy about the burden of such awareness. This may be the
reason why at least one reviewer characterized “The Museum” as “rueful.”58
As with explicit embedments, discussed earlier, I want to see here how
far back into literary history I can reach to find examples of implied complex embedment, especially those involving implied authors and readers.
Let’s start with a novel written in the second century AD, Apuleius’s The
Golden Ass. When one of its characters, goddess Venus, learns that her son,
Cupid, has ignored her order to humiliate and destroy Psyche (of whose
beauty Venus was jealous) and instead married Psyche and that they are
now expecting a baby, she rushes into the bedroom where Cupid lies and
begins “roaring with all the strength in her”:
Pretty classy goings-on, huh? A nice way to make your family look good! . . . I
was in a fight to the finish with a girl, and now I have to put up with her as my
daughter-in-law? And what’s more, you worthless, disgusting hound, you assume
that you’re the only one fit to breed, as if I’m too old to have a baby. This is just
to let you know: I am going to have another son, much better than you, and to
humiliate you even more I’m going to adopt one of the slaves born in my house,
sign everything over to him: those wings and that torch, and that bow, and your
actual arrows—all the tools of my trade, which I didn’t give you to use like this.
18
Chapter 1
It’s totally up to me, because there was no money set aside from your father’s
estate to buy you this equipment.59
Venus wants Cupid to know that she is extremely angry. What Venus
doesn’t know, however, is that, just now, Cupid has abandoned Psyche
for not trusting him and following the advice of her envious sisters and
that Psyche is desperate to win back Cupid’s love. (Were Venus to know all
this, she might try attacking Psyche while the girl is lonely and vulnerable,
instead of simply venting her anger at her son.)
Those are straightforward enough embedments, but they are not what
makes the passage hilarious. What makes it hilarious is the interplay of mental states of the implied author and the reader. As the novel’s recent translator
Sarah Ruden puts it, Apuleius “exquisitely [manages] the tension between
the high and low, the inside and outside points of view.”60 The goddess
of love, beauty, fertility, and prosperity comes across as garrulous, jealous,
feeling her age, and penny-pinching. Apuleius knows that we don’t expect
Venus to sound like this, and we know that he knows that we didn’t expect this.
The comic effect of Venus’s speech—if, that is, we find it funny!—stems
from this embedded awareness. This point is worth emphasizing because to
phenomenologically “get” the joke, readers must swiftly process embedded
mental states. My map here thus seeks to capture something that readers
actually interpretively do, “rather than being an analytical account of the
semantics of the text, divorced from the reader.”61
As always with complex passages, there are often several ways to map
them out. I just suggested one—“we know that Apuleius knows that we
didn’t expect Venus to sound like this”—but a different mapping is also possible. Readers may or may not remember that, within the novel, the story of
Cupid and Psyche is narrated by an old crone who keeps house for pirates
and who wants to soothe and entertain a young woman kidnapped by those
pirates. So if we do remember it, we can say that “Apuleius uses the old crone
as his framing device because he wants a narrator incapable of imagining a
Venus who would feel differently from herself under these circumstances.”
Let us revisit Gilgamesh, which is considered to be one the earliest surviving works of literature. When we learn that Ea wants Utnapishtim to tell the
people of Shurrupak that the same god who is angry at Utnapishtim will
bless them with good fortune (“But on you he will rain down abundance,
rare fish and shy wild-fowl, a rich harvest-tide. In the evening the rider of
The Secret Life of Literature
19
the storm will bring you wheat in torrents”), it is difficult not to think that
Ea is having a joke at the expense of the Shurrupakians.62 Not only does
he want those people to think that they are beloved by a god (when exactly
the opposite is the case), but he also chooses a very particular vocabulary
to convey his lie. How we read the complex give-and-take of intentions
implied by his evocation of rain, tide, and torrents depends on whether
we perceive Ea as being sadistic, philosophical, or just true to his trickster
“nature.” But whichever way we view him, we seem to assume that the narrator of Gilgamesh wants to draw the audience’s attention to Ea’s desire to
comment on what is to come. This is to say that to judge the ethics of the
situation, we have to be intuitively aware of the underlying mental states
and hence the irony implied by the disjunction between what is stated and
what is intended.
1.5 Who Are “We”? Historical Speculations and Empirical Studies
Do we have any evidence that Gilgamesh’s early audiences were also aware
of this ironic disjunction? While we may never be able to know for sure,
thinking about this question raises important issues. One such issue is the
identity of the “we” whose reaction to Gilgamesh I seem to be quietly presenting as normative and then comparing with that of its early listeners/
readers. To put it broadly, are some readers more aware of implied mental
states in literature than are others? Does it take a particular training in reading and interpreting works of literature to become a part of this enlightened
“we” community?
I can tell you right away that I do not have definitive answers to these
questions. What I do have is a series of considerations that bear upon them,
directly or indirectly: some based on historical analysis of patterns of reading, others on ethnographical studies of indigenous performance genres,
yet others on lab experiments conducted by interdisciplinary teams of literary critics and cognitive scientists. I will share these considerations with
you, and then we can see if they add up to any kind of provisional answer.
Let us start with studies that suggest that expert readers of literature
become sensitized to certain features of literary texts, including various
types of implied intentionality. The social psychologists David Comer Kidd
and Emanuele Castano, who study effects of reading fiction on theory of
20
Chapter 1
mind, have shown that long-term exposure to literary fiction makes readers less willing to settle for unambiguous interpretation of mental states
and more eager to look for cues of intentionality.63 This may mean that the
more literature one reads, the more implied mental states one is prepared
to see in what one is reading.
Moreover, the literary critic and neuroscientist Natalie Phillips has found
that professors of literature did not make good subjects in fMRI experiments
that focused on reading for pleasure, because they found it hard to stop
close reading, that is, analyzing what they read. (At least that was what happened when the text in question was deemed worthy of close reading; one
wonders if those professors would have a similarly hard time refraining from
analyzing a work of science fiction.) In contrast, graduate students qualified
for participation in such experiments because they still seemed to be able
to read classic literature for pleasure, even though they were en route to
becoming professional close readers. (Note that Phillips does not explicitly
equate close reading with uncovering new embedded mental states,64 while I
believe that close reading typically involves such uncovering.65) So one takehome message from her experiments is that if you spend a good portion of
your life not just reading literature but also thinking about it, your experience of reading (which, as I have argued elsewhere, necessarily involves
mindreading)66 becomes different from that of people who either don’t read
literature or read it but don’t think about it professionally.
What we should not do, however, based on these studies, is to overstate
that difference and treat it as a constant. Consider the work of the cognitive
literary critic Andrew Elfenbein, who brings together empirical studies of
what readers do today and historical reconstructions of the eighteenth- and
nineteenth-century practices of reading. Elfenbein emphasizes continuity
between different kinds of reading, reminding us that “many readers . . . are
neither novices nor experts but somewhere in between” and that even expert
readers are routinely faced with pressures and distractions that lead them
to engage in merely “good enough processing, which occurs when [they]
process what they have read just enough to make sense of it.”67 What this
means is that we should not assume that experienced readers of literature
(even, perhaps, the professors from Phillips’s experiment) would always see
more implied embedments in the text than would less experienced readers.
This may be a good time to bring up the difference between reading
and interpretation. Although I would dearly love to believe that my maps
The Secret Life of Literature
21
of mental states reflect something obvious and hence do not require any
special interpretive effort, the truth is that some of them do, and I am not
always the best judge of the extent to which such maps depend on my having taken extra time to think about the passage under consideration. To
put it bluntly, if I am giving you the results of my interpretive effort while
claiming that this is really an effortless reading of the kind that just about
any expert reader would produce under the circumstances, then I am inflating the difference between expert reading and novice reading. To quote
Elfenbein again, “full comprehension and reading do not co-occur, which
is why literary scholars should hesitate more than they do to make ‘reading’
synonymous with ‘interpretation.’”68
That said, there is some room between “full comprehension” and
“good enough” comprehension. While neither expert nor novice readers
may immediately and fully comprehend a rich variety of complex embedments structuring a given passage, they may grasp enough of some of those
embedments’ meaning to carry them through. In fact, Elfenbein’s discussion of automatic processes involved in reading literature provides a useful
framework for thinking about fictional mindreading. If we adopt his model
(which itself is based on the work of the psychologist Agnes Moors), we can
characterize embedment of complex mental states as “top-down automatic
processing: processes that have become automatic as a result of training
and repetitive practice.”As Elfenbein explains, “[Such] processes are usually unconscious, but they are not inaccessible to consciousness. They can
become conscious when attention is directed to them. . . . Some of these
processes include comprehending (understanding the meaning of what is
read) and situation model building (integrating what has been read with
general world knowledge, cognitive and emotional inferences, predictions,
and evaluations).”69
More often than not, such “understanding the meaning of what is read”
and “situation model building” involve attributing mental states to fictional characters, narrators, and the author. And, just as in real life, much
of this fictional mindreading does not rise to the level of awareness, except
when we consciously direct our attention to it.
Expert readers of literature may, indeed, develop, “through long practice, a set of strategies for understanding imaginative literature,”70 which
means that sometimes they would indeed be more attuned to intentionality cues in the text than would be less experienced readers. That said,
22
Chapter 1
automatic ascription of mental states to observed behavior is something
that, arguably, all readers do. Literary scholars may thus regularly shift
“between strategies common to many readers” and those that they have
developed as professionals.71 While in the latter mode, they are more likely
to be aware of a richer set of counterintuitive implied embedments—and
thus begin to interpret the text—than they are when in the former mode,
when, for instance, they may be distracted or in a hurry or uninterested in
what they are reading or having decided that this particular text does not
deserve much attention.
So where does all this leave us in respect to the initial question of whether
Gilgamesh’s earliest audiences might have been as aware of its ironic interplay
of intentionalities as “we” can be today. I suspect that, even then, some members of the audience—those whose experience with imaginary intentionalities was, for whatever reason, more extensive than that of other people—were
particularly eager, on some occasions, to intuit more implied mental states in
the text. To them, Ea’s promise to the people of Shurrupak, that soon they will
be happily drowning in the torrents of fish and fowl and wheat, might have,
sometimes, felt more “dramatically ironic” than it did to others.
But, one may argue, surely, given the variety of artifacts that experiment
with nuances of intentionality today (all those novels and movies!), surely,
our culture, as a whole, must be more attuned to implied embedded mental
states than would be a culture not exposed to such an abundance. I agree
with this argument on the condition that we humbly acknowledge that we
often have no clue what performative and literary genres may be thriving
(or had thrived, thinking back to Gilgamesh) in a culture different from
ours.72 So, as long as we keep our potential ignorance in mind, I would say
that, yes, a community with a long and rich tradition of representing mental states might be more open to intuiting complex mental states in a given
cultural artifact, though, even within that community, some people would
still be more eager to look for cues of intentionality than would be others.
So here is one way to think about a hypothetical community of readers—
those “we” and “us” and “ours”—which I regularly evoke in this book
when I describe embedded intentions along the lines of, “the narrator of
Gilgamesh wants to draw our attention to Ea’s intentions, as Ea refers to the
flood that will soon destroy the unsuspecting Shurrupakians, as a downpour of abundance.” My hope is that such first-person plural pronouns
designate readers who are paying “good enough” attention to what they
The Secret Life of Literature
23
are reading, which is to say that they are neither terribly distracted nor
engaged in the act of professional literary interpretation. Perhaps I don’t
always manage to hit that sweet spot (i.e., that “good enough” state of the
reading mind) in my mapping of mental states, but this is to what I aspire.
Moreover, given the pragmatics of when and where I wrote and you are
reading this book, it is reasonable to assume that these “good-enough” readers have had some exposure to cultural artifacts—such as novels, plays, television series, and movies—that call for attribution of mental states to a broad
variety of actual and imagined entities. It remains open to debate whether
such exposure makes them (us) better mindreaders in their daily life.73 Still,
it provides them with some training in teasing out hidden intentionalities of
characters, authors, and implied audiences, a training that comes in handy
in a culture that (mostly) values thinking and talking about one’s own and
others’ mental states. (I have more to say about this in chapter 4, in which I
talk about cultures that may not encourage such conversations.)
1.6 Studying “Us” in the Lab
Now I will tell you about a different kind of attempt to figure out if there
is such a thing as a collective of readers when it comes to the processing of
complex embedment of mental states. To see if there is any evidence that
different readers are likely to agree on their estimate of the level of embedment in a given passage, a team of cognitive scientists and literary scholars,
headed by Douglas H. Whalen, (late) Michael Holquist, and myself, ran a
series of experiments at Yale University, Haskins Laboratories in New Haven,
and the CUNY Graduate Center. The first set of experiments presented participants with short vignettes, crafted specifically for the occasion and featuring different levels of embedment; the second, with an excerpt from an
actual work of literature, Harper Lee’s novel To Kill a Mockingbird.
To give some idea of what our artificial vignettes looked like, here are two
of them, one in which each sentence contains a second-level embedment
and another in which each sentence contains a fourth-level embedment:
•
[second level ] I am not even sure why Stephanie wants to go the movies
with Alice and me. She hates the kinds of movies that we like. I remember the last time Alice wanted us to see this retrospective of silent films.
We both thought that Stephanie wouldn’t enjoy it at all. She went along
24
Chapter 1
and sat through the whole four-hour thing, but we could tell that she
was bored. I think I need to figure out how to talk to the two of them
about this problem.
•
[ fourth level ] I think my daughter begins to find it a bit irksome that
when we visit my aunt she has to be very careful about choosing topics
of conversation that won’t offend. She knows, for example, that my aunt
can’t stand it if we suggest that it’s not a good idea for her to live alone.
We also have to keep in mind not to argue with her about her conviction
that she can remember her doctor appointments without ever writing
anything down.74
Altogether, we had eighty-four vignettes (387 sentences) ranging in their
level of embedment from zero to five. When it comes to results, the “great
majority of responses were within one level (94.2%), but differences did
account for 25.54% of the judgments.”75 This is to say that the participants’
judgments were in perfect agreement with the experimenters’ judgments
in 74.5 percent of cases, while the greatest difference involved one level of
embedment in either direction. (That is, in 10.5 percent of cases, participants
judged the vignettes to have one more mental state than did the experimenters, and in 9 percent of cases, they judged the vignettes to have one
fewer mental states.) In contrast, the participants judged the vignettes to
have two more mental states than did the experimenters only in 2 percent of cases, and they judged them to have two fewer mental states only
in 0.78 percent of cases; and the numbers went even further down with the
difference of three levels, to 0.17 percent and 0.21 percent, respectively.
What we found in the second set of experiments was that an excerpt
from To Kill a Mockingbird, which featured twelve sentences (three consecutive paragraphs), yielded a lower rate of agreement. Specifically, in half the
cases, the participants’ judgments were essentially the same as the experimenters’, while in three cases, they were above the experimenters’ judgments, and in three cases, below.76 I will not discuss here the setup of our
studies, because we already have done it, extensively, elsewhere.77 I will
focus only on three take-home lessons that are relevant for us now.
First, as we realized in the process of devising our vignettes, elements of
style such as metaphors, alliterations, and allusions bring in mental states.78
A single metaphor, even a subdued one, can inadvertently change the tone
of a whole vignette, evoking a mental state in a reader, even if that mental
The Secret Life of Literature
25
state may be too subtle to describe in a propositional format.79 To adapt
Patrick Colm Hogan’s argument from a related context, such a mental state
may not be “strongly activated.” It will be, “rather, ‘primed’ in the cognitive sense of the term. Thus [it will be] partially activated in such a way as
to affect the orientation of thought and feeling without entailing precise,
reasoned consequences.”80 While we did our best to control for this “priming” factor in our synthetic vignettes by draining them of anything that
could be seen as a sign of style, we were forcefully reminded that it is style
rather than straightforward propositional statements (such as “I know that
she knows that I know”) that may generate complex embedments in literary texts.
Second, during one of the sessions in which we introduced our subjects
to the concept of counting embedded mental states on the level of an individual sentence (i.e., the unit level on which we eventually settled), we
discovered something similar to what Natalie Phillips later observed in her
fMRI studies of pleasure reading. It became clear to us that when our subjects happened to be expert readers—such as graduate students in English
and comparative literature—they sometimes saw more mental states in a
given sentence/paragraph than did lay readers.81 This observation made a
lot of sense if you would consider that people who apply to graduate programs in literary studies may already have higher-than-average interest in
intricate social situations that call for attribution of complex mental states82
and that they may become even more so after spending years dissecting and
interpreting mental states of literary characters, authors, and other scholars.83
Still, even with those complicating factors (that is, mental states introduced by various elusive elements of style and the difference in our subjects’
expertise), “the broad agreement about the levels of embedment in individual sentences demonstrated by our experiment [showed] that sentencelevel embedment of mental states is a real phenomenon that can be reliably
assessed in a laboratory setting.”84 Studying “us” in the lab is, thus, a legitimate endeavor, especially if one clearly differentiates between one’s expectations, in the case of artificial vignettes, and excerpts from literature.
For here is the third take-home lesson from our experiments. It was very
encouraging to learn that both researchers and subjects could be trained to
judge levels of embedment quickly. It was also heartening to see that their
subsequent judgments—in the case of vignettes—displayed a sizable agreement. That said, disagreements—which were especially pronounced in the
26
Chapter 1
case of To Kill a Mockingbird—turned out to be illuminating in their own
right. In fact, one of the conclusions of our last study was that, particularly
when it comes to individual sentences in works of literature, high agreement rates on their levels of embedment should not be expected. While
disagreements may have multiple causes, including flaws in the design
of experiments, one clear cause must be the “necessary complicating role
of large-scale (i.e., paragraph, chapter, and cross-chapter) embedments of
mental states in the perception of the sentences,” while another may have
to do with the role of personal responses to literature.85
To illustrate how such complications work, I will now turn to a novel
that our last study mentioned only briefly: E. M. Forster’s Howards End. Specifically, I will show that a seemingly clear-cut sentence carries the potential
for expanding, contracting, and otherwise changing its levels of embedment. This happens because, far from being a one-shot game, the sentence
is part of the dynamic mindreading ecology of the novel—what the philosophers of mind Hanne De Jaegher and Ezequiel Di Paolo would call “the
ongoing engagement” between the text and its readers.86
1.7 Are Embedments in the Text?
“Ought Margaret to know what Helen knew the Basts to know?”
What could be more straightforward than this example of explicitly
spelled-out embedded mental states from Forster’s Howards End? Yet this
straightforwardness is treacherous. The sentence is a Trojan horse harboring
implied mental states that rush at us as soon as we move in for a closer look.
Until now, I avoided providing much context for my examples of spelledout embedments. I did so because I wanted to first clearly lay out the terms
of my discussion: “here are the explicits, and here are the implieds.” But
reality is messier than this neat division may imply: explicitly spelled-out
embedments are often integrated with implied ones. Sometimes the relationship between the two is complementary, but, just as often, the implied
embedments subvert the explicit ones.
For instance, taken on its own, “Ought Margaret to know what Helen
knew the Basts to know?” seems to present a social dilemma and invite a discussion of what to do next. However, if we look at its context, we realize that
this sentence actually does something very different. It mocks drawn-out
conversations about relationships and refuses to discuss the social dilemma
The Secret Life of Literature
27
in question. It thus makes it possible for us to pass over the question about
what Margaret ought to know, filing it away, as it were, as a bit of a tedious
joke.
To see how it works, let us expand the quote:
[Tibby Schlegel] had never been interested in human beings, for which one must
blame him, but he had had rather too much of them at Wickham Place. Just as
some people cease to attend when books are mentioned, so Tibby’s attention
wandered when “personal relations” came under discussion. Ought Margaret to
know what Helen knew the Basts to know? Similar questions had vexed him
from infancy, and at Oxford he had learned to say that the importance of human
beings has been vastly overrated by specialists. The epigram, with its faint whiff
of the eighties, meant nothing. But he might have let it off now if his sister had
not been ceaselessly beautiful.87
This is a very complex passage, and, as is often the case with such, I expect,
as I map out its implied embedments, that my understanding of what is
going on may not coincide with yours. Still, different as your understanding may be, I encourage you to take note of the mental states involved. For
my argument depends not on the unique perceptiveness of my interpretation but on the complexity of embedments expected from a reader to make
sense of this passage.
The narrator anticipates that readers will dislike Tibby for not being interested in personal relations. The narrator wants his readers to imagine what
it might have felt like for Tibby to grow up in a household where such
relations were constantly discussed. By doing so, the narrator wants us to
recognize Tibby’s aversion to such discussions as a self-defense mechanism,
even as he lets us suspect that he himself may still consider Tibby’s supercilious thinking unsympathetic.
Planted in the middle of these implied embedments, “Ought Margaret
to know what Helen knew the Basts to know?” acquires rather unflattering
overtones. Instead of signaling social complexity, it signals impatience with
overthinking “personal relations.” To put it differently, instead of taking
the content of the phrase at its face value and engaging earnestly with the
question of whether Margaret ought to know and so on, we may now dismiss this content, because, as Tibby has shown us, one way of dealing with
this dilemma is to say, “Who gives a hoot?” The implied embedments thus
undercut the explicit one.
“Ought Margaret to know what Helen knew the Basts to know?” can be
said to be a case of “free indirect discourse,” which is yet another term that,
28
Chapter 1
similar to “dramatic irony,” functions as a cultural shortcut designating a
specific mindreading dynamic. To use our present vocabulary (instead of
a more traditional literary-critical one)88 to describe this dynamic, we can
say that free indirect discourse occurs when the implied author wants the
reader to distrust information that the text seems to be treating as true.
Thus, while it may seem that whether Margaret knows what Helen knows is
a real concern, on closer inspection, it turns out to be just another example
of the type of question that Tibby doesn’t like thinking about.
But guess what? The question whether Margaret knows and so on may
be a red herring, but it won’t be put to rest. Far from being confined to the
immediate environs of one paragraph, some of its implied complex embedments continue to unspool throughout the novel. For instance, we learned,
in Forster’s previous chapter, that Margaret already knows that her fiancé,
Henry Wilcox, had had an affair, ten years ago, with the woman who was to
become Leonard Bast’s common-law wife and that Margaret has already forgiven Henry. This means that Helen’s present worries are misplaced. That
is, Helen doesn’t know that Margaret already knows “what Helen knew the
Basts to know.”
But wait, there is more: Margaret had written a note to Helen—before
she realized that Helen may already know about the affair—and that note
was driven by Margaret’s wish (anticipating and mirroring Helen’s present
wish!) to preserve Helen from knowing what Margaret knew. Over that note,
Forster explains, Margaret “took less trouble than she might have done; but
her head was aching, and she could not stop to pick her words.”89 Ironically,
upon receiving that less-than-carefully-worded letter, Helen can’t make any
sense of it and thus assumes that it is the doing of Henry Wilcox (as she
puts it to Tibby, “He makes Meg write”)90 and that Henry wants to prevent
Margaret from learning the truth about his past. For readers who remember
Henry’s role in suppressing his late wife’s will (which would have Margaret
inherit the Wilcoxes’ country house, Howards End), Helen’s assumption
may ring less mistaken than it is.
In other words, every time you change the context for the original
straightforward embedment, “Ought Margaret to know what Helen knew
the Basts to know,” your interpretation shifts,91 and every one of these
interpretive shifts (i.e., on the level of individual sentences, paragraphs,
or chapters) unfolds as yet another complex embedment of mental states
involving characters, readers, and the implied author.
The Secret Life of Literature
29
Let me pause here, before you start feeling like Tibby and ask exasperatedly, “Ought readers to know what Zunshine considers the implied author
to intend?”—a question that may really mean, as we have seen, “Who gives
a hoot?”—and decide how many hoots we should give about any of this.
There are two points I want to make here. The first is a simple assertion: to
read Howards End is to embed complex mental states incessantly, whether
you are aware of it or not. Yours may not be the same as mine, but that difference in content is less important than the structural similarity: the fact
that neither of us can make sense of the text without constantly embedding
some complex mental states.
The second point is that complex embedments are not merely in the
text, ready to affect the same way whoever opens the book.92 Instead, they
emerge as a specific reader acts on what they are reading by intuitively
choosing a context in which to make sense of a potential embedment.
Thus, while one reader may indeed focus on the question of whether Margaret ought to know what Helen knew the Basts to know, another reader
(or the same reader on a different occasion) may adopt some of Tibby’s
indifferent perspective on personal relations and pass over that question;
while yet another may particularly respond to the implied author’s attitude
toward Tibby’s superciliousness regarding Helen’s concern, and so forth. I
suspect that were we to bring Howards End to the lab and ask our subjects
to count the levels of embedment involved in this paragraph, the numbers that they would report would remain generally high—that is, between
three and five—but there would be quite a bit of fluctuation within that
range, given that the content and configuration of embedments would differ from one reader to another.
Here is, then, one way to describe the experience of reading literature.
As we read, we construct contexts in which to make sense of potential
embedments, and then we use the information that we derived from
those embedments to construct contexts for subsequent embedments. We
can think of this process of continuous and contingent construction as
“participatory sense-making”—to borrow the term that De Jaegher and
Di Paolo use to characterize mindreading involved in daily social interactions.93 This means that by the time readers arrive to “Ought Margaret to
know what Helen knew the Basts to know,” they already “have a history
of interaction” with the novel,94 that is, they have already been primed,
by preceding embedments, to treat some contexts as more relevant than
30
Chapter 1
others. Some of this priming has been planted (so to speak) by the author,
but some has not.95
Let us take a closer look at the aspects of priming that are less predictable
and thus fall outside the range of responses that I seek to capture with my
hopeful “we.” So far I have described the construction of contexts for complex embedments as a forward-oriented process: with past embedments
influencing embedments-to-come. But the “participatory sense-making”
can move backward as well as forward. Something that we just read may
trigger a complex embedment that hails from a preceding chapter, an
embedment that has been lying dormant until now.
For instance, perhaps I did not pay much attention, the first time
around, to the nuances of the narrator’s view of Tibby’s attitude toward
his sister’s dilemma, yet, later, as I come across another social situation
involving Tibby’s perspective of other people’s emotions, I may find myself
realizing that the narrator has been feeling less than charitable toward this
character for a while and thus retroactively revise the meaning of “Ought
Margaret to know . . .” The cognitive literary scholar Anezka Kuzmičová
describes this reverse sense-making in terms of “probes” that illuminate this
or that aspect of our past reading experience. As she explains, “in reading
long-form narrative . . . the number of verbal probes that can guide one’s
grasp of the preceding text . . . is endlessly [high]. In light of this insight, it
seems a mystery how any two people can ever come close to converging in
their subjective experience of a story or novel.”96
Here is something to deepen this mystery yet further. Kuzmičová
observes that “for many leisure readers” (a group that comes closest to my
ideal of “good-enough” readers), “the added value of narrative lies . . . in
momentarily becoming conscious of one’s self and one’s problems in specific ways that may be less readily available otherwise.” These “personal
realizations inform consciousness” in a variety of ways. “Often enough,
they may come in the form of propositional thought (‘Oh my, this character is acting just like me’). Just as often, however, they may assume the form
of mental imagery,” feeding on “personal memories triggered by the narrative.” To psychologists, such associations are known to be “much more
common in literary narrative compared to other types of reading materials.” Their frequency “directly affects the pleasure taken in reading. . . . It is
in this sense that literature affords a unique form of self-consciousness, in
The Secret Life of Literature
31
which you focus on yourself and yet you do not, because the story you are
reading is really about others.”97
To give you an example of this kind of unique (no we here—only me!)
experience of embedding, imagine that I am reading the “Ought Margaret
to know” passage at a particular juncture in my life at which I may feel a
sharp pang of recognition by thinking of myself as a beleaguered Tibby surrounded by overbearing Helens. I would thus be more likely to construct
an embedment in which I would give more weight to the nuances of that
paragraph that portray Tibby with sympathy and compassion. The problem
is that were that process to take place in a lab and were someone to ask me
to map out the embedments of mental states present in this paragraph, I
would not include any of my personal reflections into my report and instead
would come up with something along the lines of, “The narrator wants his
readers to imagine what it might have felt like for Tibby to grow up in a
household where such relations were constantly discussed. By doing so, the
narrator wants us to recognize Tibby’s aversion to such discussions as a healthy
boundary-setting reaction.”
What does it mean for the experiment—for its accuracy, reliability, replicability, and so on—that my map would effectively bury that very important aspect of self-consciousness, in which I focus on myself and yet I do
not, because the story I am reading is really about others?98 At the very
least, it means that we have to remember that, as any other literary-critical
tool, our maps of embedment may conceal as much as they reveal about
readers’ interactions with the text.
1.8 Enactive Embedments
Each instance of reading thus has its own unfolding history dependent on
a uniquely situated reader—a particular person at this exact point in their
life.99 There is no predicting how a literary text will meet a reader at a given
time; in what direction the probes “of consciousness will be thrust”;100
which contexts will have more traction and which will have less; and, ultimately, what specific sequence of complex embedments the text and the
reader will jointly create.101
This perspective on reading is congenial with the so-called enactive school
of cognitive science, which emphasizes that mind is always constituted by
32
Chapter 1
“organism-environment interactions.”102 In particular, cognitive scientists
committed to the enactive paradigm caution against thinking of mindreading as a form of problem-solving: one “detached individual trying to figure
out the other.”103 To be fair, cognitive literary critics, such as myself, have
never approached mindreading as problem-solving. As I have emphasized
on numerous occasions, mindreading takes place away from conscious
access: it is too fast and intuitive and enmeshed with body language to be
thought of along the formal lines of “figuring out the other.” Still, there are
some occasions on which we would do well to heed that warning, and one
such occasion is studying embedments in the lab.
For think again about the first part of our experiment, in which we presented our subjects with context-free synthetic constructs such as “I am not
even sure why Stephanie wants to go the movies with Alice and me.” Our
expectations certainly conformed to the model of “detached individuals trying to figure out the other.” There was a “correct” answer associated with
each sentence; the vignettes were to be decoded, and our subjects were the
decoders.
In contrast, reading a work of literature does not reduce the text and
the reader to those roles. Instead, reading can be described as a form of
social interaction between the two autonomous agents (i.e., the text and its
reader) that unfolds as they settle on a particular sequence of contexts for
complex embedments.104 Unlike decoding, this enactive process of cocreation is less predictable, less likely to yield high agreement rates, and harder
to study in the lab.105
Still, harder does not mean impossible, and there are some unexpected
bonus points along the way. For instance, when my colleagues and I were
working on tallying the data collected from our subjects, I noticed that
cognitive scientists began to sound like literary critics, that, in fact, we all
began to sound like participants in a literature seminar, avidly discussing
motivations of characters, narrators, and readers in order to figure out why
this or that sentence was assigned this or that level of embedment. As far
as interdisciplinary projects go, a study of embedded mental states may
thus be a particularly gratifying experience for a literary scholar, because
it builds on the strengths of each participating discipline (e.g., I had to
defer to my colleagues from the Haskins Laboratories for their expertise in
brain-imaging techniques and statistical analysis) without losing sight of
the complexity of the issues under consideration.106
The Secret Life of Literature
33
Elfenbein has pointed out that scholars of literature have long been
prone to “quick condemnation” of each other’s work as “reductive,” so
it is “not surprising” that, given what they think psychologists are doing,
they now accuse them “of the same perceived sin.”107 What my experience
suggests is that one way to put that stale prejudice to rest is to develop a
collaborative project with one’s colleagues from cognitive science: to hear
them talk your language and to attempt to understand theirs.108 Then even
those aspects of the project that would seem to point toward shortcomings
of studying literature in the lab (such as a failure to obtain high agreement
rates on the level of embedment in passages from a novel) may yield important insights about the participatory nature of literary mindreading.
1.9 Sitting Ducks
It seems that in literature certain types of explicitly spelled-out complex
embedment—specifically those involving characters’ assertions about their
own and other characters’ mental states—may function as sitting ducks.
Just like “Ought Margaret to know what Helen knew the Basts to know?”
they may be set up to be upended by their contexts. So when we come
across a sentence that reads suspiciously like one of my awkward mindreading maps—for example, “he thinks that she knows that he knows”—we
may want to be on the lookout for implied embedments that would subvert
these explicit ones.
Here are some examples of such subversion.
Recall Shirley Jackson’s “The Beautiful Stranger.” While its protagonist
is happily interpreting the man’s smile as an indication that he knows that
she has been worried that he may be her husband, after all (“She was aware
from his smile that he had perceived her doubts”),109 readers may have a
reason to doubt her insight. Although it is possible that the husband has
been (say) abducted by aliens and somewhat imperfectly replicated, which
means that the smiling man is a beautiful stranger,110 another explanation
is that the protagonist has gone insane. If this is what we think is happening, then, even while we’re following the wife’s train of (embedded)
thoughts, we are also aware that the implied author wants us to consider that
she is misinterpreting the meaning of her husband’s smile.
My second example comes from Lara Vapnyar’s Still Here (2016), which
tells several interlocking stories of Russian immigrants in the United States
34
Chapter 1
during the dot-com bubble of the late 1990s. At one point in the novel, a
recently-separated-from-her-husband woman named Vika meets an attractive stranger. He tries to start a conversation with her, but she rejects his
overture outright because he strikes her as a variation on “type of Husband.”
And, as we learn through a spelled-out embedment, she thinks that, right
now, she needs something different: “A Husband knew her the way she didn’t
want to be known, at her worst, her ugliest, her most embarrassing. . . . What
she needed was a Lover.”111
Though not quite reaching, in its bluntness, the parodic level of Forster’s
explicit embedment, Vapnyar’s “a Husband knew her the way she didn’t want
to be known” still stands out in the sea of implied embedments surrounding it. These embedments include Vika reflecting with anguish on having
disappointed a terminally ill patient in her care, who had hoped for an
emotionally honest response from her; Vika deciding to visit the Metropolitan Museum of Art because she “truly enjoys” it and not because she cares
whether other people think that she likes art; and readers beginning to suspect that Vika doesn’t realize how much she misses her estranged husband.
And so, perhaps, the real reason that Vika rejects the stranger is not that
he is a “type of Husband” but that he is not her husband.112 Of course, it
will take many chapters before she becomes aware of that. Right now she is
denied that intuition. All she has at her disposal is an explicit embedment,
which is compact and expressive and almost aphoristic (“a Husband knew
her the way she didn’t want to be known”) and, as such, provides Vika with
a convincing (perhaps too convincing!) explanation of her own behavior.
Muriel Spark’s The Girls of Slender Means (1963) takes place in bombed-out
London in the early summer of 1945. The novel centers on a group of young
women living in the dormitory-style “May of Teck Club” and on their male
admirers. In the following passage, the explicit embedments describe one of
these men’s awareness of his thoughts, while the implied embedments make
us wonder whether this self-awareness truly differentiates him from another,
much less sympathetic character: “The Colonel seemed to be in love with
the entire club, Selina being the centre and practical focus of his feelings in
this respect. This was a common effect of the May of Teck Club on its male
visitors, and Nicholas was enamoured of the entity in only one exceptional
way, that it stirred his poetic sense to a point of exasperation, for at the same
time he discerned with irony the process of his own thoughts, how he was
imposing upon this society an image incomprehensible to itself.”113
The Secret Life of Literature
35
Nicholas thinks of the girls from the May of Teck Club as beautiful and
pathetic in their communal poverty and, moreover, glorying in their economic hardship. In their heroic penury, they are emblematic of war-torn
England at its best. Of course, the girls themselves experience their poverty
as a temporary evil that they can’t wait to overcome. Not altogether blind to
their perspective, Nicholas is aware that the girls wouldn’t recognize themselves
in his vision of them, or, as Spark puts it, Nicholas “discerned with irony” that
“he was imposing upon this society an image incomprehensible to itself.”
Those are the spelled-out mental states. But then Spark also seems to
want us to suspect a certain affinity between the feelings of Nicholas and
an American colonel (especially since they both sleep with the same girl,
Selina). This is not a pleasant comparison, for, the colonel is obtuse and
philistine, while Nicholas is sensitive and sophisticated. Still, the way I see
it, Spark won’t let her readers off this hook. We wonder uncomfortably—
that is, she wants us to wonder—if Nicholas’s self-awareness is enough to
mark him as different from other men who are “in love with the entire club”
(as opposed to being attracted to one particular person) and thus displace
onto it their sexual or political fantasies.
Hence a word of caution to a fictional character: thinking that you know
well your own, or someone else’s, mind—especially if you are spelling it out
as a complex embedment—may not bode well for you.
1.10 Why Maps of Mental States Are Ugly
Bitter is the fate of the literary critic who has selflessly dedicated herself to
pursuing the secret life of literature. Droning on that “the implied author
wants the implied reader to understand that this character doesn’t know . . .”
does not endear her to her readers. And who can blame them? There is
nothing appealing about such mindreading “maps.” They are boring, repetitive, almost grotesque, and often hard to follow. They look pathetic next
to the texts that they claim to represent. There is even a vague feeling of
violence being inflicted on the elegant originals. The originals recover well
(they have seen it all), but the critic may be stuck with the reputation of a
plodding pedant.
Recent work by Max Van Duijn, Ineke Sluiter, and Arie Verhagen may
help to explain why mindreading maps look so off-putting next to original
texts. As these scholars suggest, by the end of the second act of Othello,
36
Chapter 1
“the audience has to understand that Iago intends that Cassio believes that
Desdemona intends that Othello believes that Cassio did not intend to disturb
the peace.”114 This looks, to me, like a very complex embedment (in fact,
I would make it simpler, by scaling this map at least one level down), but
imagine Shakespeare actually making Iago step forward and regale his audience with an aside in which he would say something along the lines of, “I
want Cassio to believe that Desdemona intends that Othello . . .” and so
forth.
Better to not imagine it. Not only would it sound unbearably stilted, but
also, after a while, it would become “hard or even impossible for a reader
or hearer to make the right inferences” about the characters’ intentions.115
For, as the cognitive evolutionary psychologist Robin Dunbar and his colleagues have shown, “fifth-order intentionality” (fifth-level embedment of
mental states) represents “a real upper limit for most people,” that is, the
level at which their understanding of the situation worsens dramatically.116
(Works of literature, I should add, do not often go the fifth level and higher.
Extremely intricate social nuances can be conveyed on the third and fourth
level of embedment. Even for such authors as Henry James—who, one may
assume, would soar freely in the fifth-level empyrean—there is plenty to do
on the third level. Shakespeare, Jane Austen, Muriel Spark, and Penelope
Fitzgerald; Pushkin, Dostoevsky, Tolstoy, and Tatiana Tolstaya; Apuleius and
Heliodorus, Cao Xueqin and Murasaki Shikibu, ply most of their unhumble
trade on the seemingly humble third level.)
And so Shakespeare does not make Iago step forward and spell out his
intentions as a sequence of embedded mental states. Instead, as Van Duijn
and his coauthors explain, “narrative takes over”; that is, readers and viewers have at their disposal a number of “strategies characteristic of (literary)
narrative discourse that support [their] ability to keep track of the [mental
states] of characters.” These strategies supply “support and scaffolding for
readers’ abilities to process [embedded mental states] by providing cues that
prompt them to construct a fictional social network using mainly the same
socio-cognitive skills as in real-life interaction.”117
To construct a map, we strip off this vital scaffolding. While embedded
mental states in their natural environment are often implied, distributed
over a paragraph or a scene, and embodied, we spell them out and force
them into sentence-like propositions. “He thinks that she thinks that he
The Secret Life of Literature
37
wants X”; “she remembers that she used to think that were X to happen,
she would feel Y.” But who in their right mind would enjoy reading that
kind of stuff? If a work of fiction is a living, breathing body, then a map of
embedded mental states is a skeleton, with all the appeal and charm of a
skeleton.
There is, thus, a good reason why writers themselves don’t let those
bones stick out. “He thinks that she thinks that he wants X” may be what’s
going on, but they do not put it that way. If they do, then, as we have seen
with the “Ought Margaret to know what Helen knew the Basts to know”
example, it may be a joke, a parody, or a comment on someone’s lack of
interest in social subtleties.
In the section that follows, I consider a fascinating case of the difference
between the skeleton and the body. It shows that thinking on at least the
third level of embedment is essential to the writing process, even if writers do not articulate it consciously to themselves. It so happened that this
author (i.e., Patricia Highsmith) articulated it, but one can hardly hope to
find many such examples in print. (Although, as I show immediately after,
there are ways of finding other cultural contexts in which writers can be
observed working through these issues.)
1.11 Do Writers Themselves Make Such Maps?
When the idea for a novel about a passionate love affair, between a gorgeous older woman and a young woman struggling to make it on her own
in New York, occurred to Highsmith, she jotted in her diary the following
description of the first meeting between the protagonists: “I see her the
same instant she sees me, and instantly, I love her. Instantly, I am terrified,
because I know she knows I am terrified and that I love her. Though there
are seven girls between us, I know, she knows, she will come to me and have
me wait on her.”118 I know she knows I am terrified. I know she knows I love
her. This is good enough for a map, so that the writer herself knows what’s
going on in the scene, but it won’t do for an actual novel. Here is how this
scene looks in Highsmith’s The Price of Salt (1952):
Their eyes met at the same instant, Therese glancing up from a box she was opening, and the woman just turning her head so she looked directly at Therese. She
was tall and fair, her long figure graceful in the loose fur coat that she held open
38
Chapter 1
with a hand on her waist. Her eyes were gray, colorless, yet dominant as light or
fire, and caught by them, Therese could not look away. She heard the customer
in front of her repeat a question, and Therese stood there, mute. The woman was
looking at Therese, too, with a preoccupied expression as if half her mind were
on whatever it was she meant to buy here, and though there were a number of
salesgirls between them, Therese felt sure the woman would come to her. Then
Therese saw her walk slowly toward the counter, heard her heart stumble to catch
up with the moment it had let pass, and felt her face grow hot as the woman came
nearer and nearer.119
If we map out this paragraph, we may come up with several third-level
embedments. Some of them may even be similar to “I know she knows I
love her” from Highsmith’s diary. But unlike those explicit embedments, the
ones in The Price of Salt are implied. That is, they may still supply the underlying bone structure for the first encounter between Carol and Therese, but
they are not anymore visible to the naked eye.
No wonder my own maps of embedded mental states—structured as
strings of mentalizing verbs, such as “think” or “believe”—are destined to be
clunky and off-putting. Although reading literature means reading mental
states,120 it seems we can only enjoy those mental states in context. Just as
we, apparently, cannot absorb vitamins when we take them in the form of
pills, “pure” mental states do nothing for us, except, after a very short while,
irritate us. Highsmith’s desiccated embedments, “I know she knows I am terrified. I know she knows I love her,” may have a poetic ring to them. Still, they
accrue a certain interest and cultural value (as, when a literary critic, such
as myself, is thrilled to discover them in the writer’s diary) only because she
has already seduced us with the text in which these mental states are implied.
Moreover, something else happened in the process of building up from
the bare bones of “I know she knows I love her.” Other embedments came
into being, those involving not just the main characters but the implied
author and the implied reader and arising from the style of the narrative and
its historical contexts. Observe, for instance, that, while Therese feels helplessly “caught” by the “light or fire” of Carol’s eyes, Carol, too, is powerfully
compelled to come “nearer and nearer.” If one remembers that this dance of
fatally attracted butterflies is taking place in 1952, one wonders if Highsmith
wanted her audience to fear that her story would fall into the predictable
1950s pattern of depicting a lesbian love relationship as doomed.121
It is an interesting question at what point in the second part of the twentieth century the expectation of that particular doom faded. Or, to put it in
The Secret Life of Literature
39
terms of our present discussion, at what point has it become possible not to
think that the author expects that the reader would assume that a story about
a love affair between two women cannot end well?
Our awareness of historical contexts is thus yet another factor to consider when we ask if implied mental states are already “in” a given text or
are intuited into it by some readers but not others. I suggested earlier that
complex embedments arise as social situations built by a text are filtered
through the unique consciousness of a particular reader. But, as the case of
The Price of Salt shows, specific historical circumstances and their attendant
ideologies also influence what kinds of implied mental states would be read
into a text. A given reader’s awareness of the author’s stylistic choices—
here, reference to “fire” that “catches” the hapless prospective lover—may
alert them to intentionality behind the scene. However, their construction
of the meaning of that intentionality—Is this a common poetic trope or a
sign of danger? Is the protagonists’ relationship doomed because of their
sexual orientation?—would reflect, among other things, their position in a
particular historical moment.
1.12 What Do Writers Actually Say When They Talk
about the Secret Life of Literature?
Several years ago, I enrolled in a graduate seminar in my university’s MFA
program. My goal was to see if writers are aware of the “secret life of literature,” that is, if they are aware of the extent to which their texts depend
on the constant embedment of complex mental states. That meant paying
close attention both to our workshop discussions and to my own writing
process, for, like other students in that class, I had to come up with two
original short stories and have others comment on them.
Here is what I found, in brief. It is impossible to write fiction while thinking about embedding mental states, because the state of mind in which one
puts oneself as a creative writer is different from that of a literary critic. But
here are two important caveats.
First, even though I do not think consciously of embedding complex mental states when I am writing fiction, I, nevertheless, keep coming up with
social situations that call for such embedments. So one way to rephrase what
I said earlier is to say that a creative writer puts oneself into a state of mind in
which one produces complex embedments without being aware of doing so.
40
Chapter 1
Second, after the first draft is done and I start revising it, thinking consciously of ways to add yet another mental state to this or that social situation becomes helpful, to some degree. It seems that, in the process of
revision, a writer begins to think like a critic or, at least, more like a critic
than they did before.
As to whether writers talk about embedding complex mental states during their workshop discussions, the dynamic is similar. They are not familiar with this vocabulary and thus do not use these terms. Nevertheless,
when they comment on each other’s drafts, their suggestions for improvement tend toward making social situations present in the original more
emotionally complex, which, of course, depends on cultivating complex
embedments of mental states.
While some of those suggestions center on characters, many involve various states of awareness between the implied reader and the implied author.
Again, the “implied reader” and the “implied author” are not the terms
writers use. They talk instead about texts, protagonists, narrators, authors,
and readers. Thus, they may say, “The protagonist doesn’t know it, but are
we supposed to think that the text knows it?”122 or “Even if the narrator is
unsure what the story is about, the reader must sense that the author knows
what the story is about, what it’s doing.”123 Or, to quote from a workshop
participant’s written response to one of my stories, “The simplest way I can
think of for this would be to utilize a third-person perspective so that the
narrator could give us insight that the current narrator wasn’t willing to. Or
you could leave it in first person and just use the asides of the narrator to
also give us possible suspicions that might be fleeting in her mind that she
refuses to give much thought to.”124
In other words, when writers are writing and revising/talking about their
craft, they operate on a high level of embedment, even if they are not aware
of it. Indeed, if my own experience is to be trusted, consciously focusing on
embedding mental states is detrimental to all of these processes, although
it is significantly more detrimental during the initial writing stages. The
“secret life of literature” must remain secret even to the people who make
literature happen.
Let me now show you how an author may use a feedback received from
their peers to make a given social situation more emotionally complex, by
bringing in more embedments. Here are two excerpts—an original and a
The Secret Life of Literature
41
revision—from one of my stories written for the workshop. The story features a middle-aged protagonist thinking back to a time when she was nineteen and she and her best friend, “Julia,” were in love with the same man,
“Zhenia.” The man eventually chose Julia, and the protagonist remembers
asking Julia about what the two of them did together: “I don’t wish to know
where Julia and Zhenia go together and what they do. But, of course, I keep
asking, and she tells me.”
There is already one complex embedment here. The protagonist is aware
that she can’t stop herself from doing something that, she knows, will make
her feel bad. But look what happened after I followed the advice given to
me by the workshop participant who suggested highlighting the difference
between the past and the present narrator, so that the asides of the present
narrator can “give us possible suspicions that might be fleeting in her mind
that she refuses to give much thought to”:
I didn’t wish to know where Julia and Zhenia went together or what they did.
But, of course, I kept asking, and she kept telling. Today, I think it is odd that
Julia didn’t seem to realize that it was painful for me to listen to those stories. But,
perhaps, she did realize it, which was yet another sign that she had already given
up on our friendship. I can say that now, knowing how quickly we were about to
grow apart, in spite of my desperate attempts to hold on to her. At the time, however, I interpreted her behavior differently. It made sense to me that she would not
think that I might be hurt by Zhenia’s choice. After all, I didn’t consider myself
lovable either.
To map some of the new complex embedments structuring this passage,
the older narrator thinks it is odd that Julia did not think that her friend
would feel bad hearing her stories; the older narrator wonders if Julia did
know that her friend would feel bad hearing her stories; the older narrator
is aware that her younger self was not willing to consider that Julia did not
care about their friendship anymore; the older narrator is aware that her
younger self believed that no one could love her; and so forth.
I chose an excerpt from the revised version of my story that contains
mostly spelled-out mental states in order to make this discussion more
manageable. Initially I had wanted to give you a passage that contained
no explicit mental states—only implied ones (which are often more
interesting)—but then I realized that doing so would require supplying
much more information about the story’s plot. Because explicit embedments often present on the level of individual sentences, while implied
42
Chapter 1
ones may function on the level of paragraphs, chapters, and plots, explicit
embedments are easier to demonstrate.
Here, then, are two key takeaway messages from my experience of taking
an MFA course. First, the process of generating complex embedments without being aware of it, while writing, provides a useful insight into our reading
practices. For there, too, mentalizing takes place mostly away from conscious
access. The “felt experience of reading,” the cognitive literary scholar Elaine
Auyong reminds us, is “distinct from the mental acts underlying it.”125 To
make sense of what we read, we constantly process complex embedments, yet
if we pause and take a stock of doing so, the pleasure of reading may evaporate.
Second, we can now come back to the main claim of this book—which is
that literature as we know it today cannot exist without embedding mental
states on at least the third level—and add the following. Readers for whom
this secret life of literature is most fully present (even if they do not think
about it in those terms) are writers in the process of writing and revising. I
dedicated several preceding sections of this chapter to figuring out if some
readers are more immediately attuned to complex embedments in literature
than others are. While that question mostly remains open, we can confidently say that there is at least one group highly attuned to such embedments, and these are writers when they are writing.
This view finds support in the work of Robin Dunbar, who has suggested that the reason that “good writers [are] so rare” is that they have to
constantly keep in mind a higher-order intentionality than do readers.126
Dunbar and I differ in one respect: I think that, both in our daily life and
while reading literature, we operate on a somewhat lower level of embedment that he thinks we do. Thus, he writes that “in everyday social life, we
probably don’t work at much beyond the third order most of the time,”127
while I would say (along with Patricia H. Miller et al.) that we don’t work
at much beyond the second level and rise to the third level only occasionally.128 Similarly, Dunbar observes that writers “are among the very small
proportion of individuals who can successfully cope with sixth and seventh
order intentionality,”129 while I think that literature can get plenty complex
on the third level and expect that writers do not have to reach to such highs
as sixth and seventh very often.
But those nuances notwithstanding, I find Dunbar’s argument that
writers have to process more higher-level embedments than do readers
The Secret Life of Literature
43
congenial to my argument that people who are most appreciative of high
levels of embedment in literature are those in the process of creating those
embedments. As Dunbar puts it,
When the audience ponders Shakespeare’s Othello, for example, they are obliged
to work at fourth order intentional levels. . . . [But whatever level of intentionality they are working on], Shakespeare himself is being forced to work at one level
of intentionality higher, because he must intend that we (the audience) believe
that Iago intends . . . , etc. . . . In effect, a successful story-teller has to be able
to work at the very limits of normal adult competence in social cognition. The
significance of this is perhaps best reflected in the contrast with the fact that, in
everyday social life, we probably don’t work at much beyond third order most of
the time. . . . The need to be able to work at one or more orders . . . higher than
the reader means that the story-teller has to be a rather unusual individual: they
are among the very small proportion of individuals who can successfully cope
with sixth and seventh order intentionality.130
Dunbar and I thus focus on different manifestations of the same phenomenon. He says that literature sometimes operates on the sixth and seventh level of intentionality; I say that it constantly operates on at least the
third. As you can see, these claims are complementary rather than mutually
exclusive. The bottom line is that we both think that literature turns up
the volume on something fundamental to our everyday social functioning
(i.e., mindreading) and that people who operate the dial are the ones who
immediately feel the difference.
1.13 Bodies without Minds
“Constant” sounds a whole lot like “universal,” which has a bad rap in
literary studies, so let us face this issue squarely here. When I say that literature as we know it today cannot function without constantly embedding
mental states on at least the third level, do I claim that the secret life of
literature is, in effect, “universal”? And, if so, do I also claim that there are
no exceptions to this unspoken “rule”?
To start with the second question first: of course, there are exceptions.
(For instance, in the next chapter, I will show that some socialist-realist
novels published in the Soviet Union and East Germany operated on a
lower-than-third level of embedment.) This said, before we pronounce a
particular text an exception, we’d better take a good look to make sure that
44
Chapter 1
it actually is. In my experience, works of literature that leap to people’s
minds when they start searching their mental databases for exceptions,
typically do not turn out to be such, upon closer inspection.
Patrick Colm Hogan provides a useful framework for thinking about
exceptions in his work on “literary universals.”131 Perhaps, one day, what I
call the secret life of literature will indeed be considered a literary universal,
on the terms that he outlines, but I don’t think we are there yet. At this
point, it is still an empirical issue. This is to say that we’d do well to keep
our mind open and continue checking for this pattern as we study literature
from different cultural traditions and historical periods. I expect that social
contexts of complex embedment would differ from one author, text, genre,
and culture to another, and I think that sensitivity to those contexts is a
more interesting and immediate research challenge than the adjudication
of the question of universality.
Meanwhile, let us look at some texts that often figure as candidates for
exception. What happens, for instance, when writers craft stories that contain no explicit references to mental states, for instance, when their characters seem to come across as lacking “psychology,” “interiority,” and “depth”
or else live in a dystopian society that eschews any discussion of emotional
life? More often than not, such stories still contain numerous complex
embedments of mental states, but they are all implied. This is to say that
readers have to do all of the heavy lifting associated with reading intentions
into the behavior of characters and/or into stylistic choices of the author.
And readers do step up to that plate—for otherwise they wouldn’t be
able to make sense of what is happening in the story or appreciate its tone.
Yet, ironically, even while they do that, they may continue to take at face
value the text’s claims (so to speak) to “mindlessness.” Consider Evgeny
Zamyatin’s novel We (1921), set in a dystopian future where feelings are
jettisoned for mathematical formulas. We has apparently fooled enough
readers in several languages, because, when I give talks about complex
embedment, it is one of the two novels (the other one being Alain RobbeGrillet’s Jealousy, which I will discuss later) almost inevitably brought up
during the question-and-answer period as an example of a work of fiction
that contains no mental states, much less any embedded ones.
Yet We constantly prompts us to construct embedded mental states to
make sense of what is going on. Look at the first meeting of its protagonists,
D-503 and I-330, narrated by D-503: “All this without smiling, I’d even say
The Secret Life of Literature
45
with certain reverence (perhaps she knows that I’m a builder of the “Integral”). But I’m not sure—in her eyes or eyebrows—there is some strange irritating X, and I can’t quite catch it, can’t assign it a numerical expression.”132
There is a whole constellation of complex embedments here. For
instance, D-503 wonders if I-330 is impressed because she knows what he
does. Also, he is irritated that he can’t fathom her exact attitude. Moreover,
the implied reader understands that D-503 doesn’t realize that he’s falling in
love with I-330. The fact that we don’t notice any of these and even may
end up thinking of Zamyatin’s novel as devoid of mental states testifies to
the unreflective speed with which we attribute thoughts and feelings when
we encounter behavior (more about this in chapter 5, on the history of
complex embedment in literature).
Here is another example. It was suggested to me by a colleague sympathetic to the idea that, in eighteenth- and nineteenth-century Europe,
writers heavily relied on complex embedment—what with all those thick
courtship novels focused on characters’ feelings! Modernists, too: just think
of Proust’s and Woolf’s obsession with the multiply storied consciousness.
But surely (so my sympathetic colleague thought), latter-day postmodernist
authors have outgrown all that preoccupation with psychology. Take Cormac McCarthy’s Blood Meridian: Or the Evening Redness in the West (1985). Its
characters are notorious for their lack of interiority, which means we do not
need to embed mental states as we follow their actions.
To see if this supposition is true, consider the opening of the novel. Blood
Meridian tells the story of a nameless teenager, “the Kid,” who joins a gang
of scalp hunters terrorizing the border between the United States and Mexico in 1849–1850. We start by learning about the birth and upbringing of
“the Kid”:
See the child. He is pale and thin, he wears a thin and ragged linen shirt. He stokes
the scullery fire. Outside lie dark turned fields with rags of snow and darker woods
beyond that harbor yet a few last wolves. His folks are known for hewers of wood
and drawers of water but in truth his father has been a schoolmaster. He lies in
drink, he quotes from poets whose names are now lost. The boy crouches by the
fire and watches him.
Night of your birth. Thirty-three. The Leonids they were called. God how the
stars did fall. I looked for blackness, holes in the heavens. The Dipper stove.
The mother dead these fourteen years did incubate in her own bosom the creature who would carry her off. The father never speaks her name, the child does
not know it. He has a sister in the world that he will not see again. He watches,
46
Chapter 1
pale and unwashed. He can neither read nor write and in him broods already a
taste for mindless violence. All history present in that visage, the child the father
of the man.133
Looking at these three paragraphs, you can see why this novel may strike
some readers as not featuring any thoughts and feelings. This is a far cry
from, say, Marcel Proust’s Remembrance of Things Past, in which a typical
sentence embeds explicit mental states, as in, “Sometimes when, after
kissing me, she opened the door to go, I longed to call her back and say
to her ‘Kiss me just once more,’ but I knew that then she would at once
look displeased, for the concession which she made to my wretchedness
and agitation in coming up to give me this kiss of peace always annoyed
my father, who thought such rituals absurd.”134 On the other hand, even
though McCarthy’s “Kid” doesn’t seem to be able—in stark contrast to the
little boy in Proust—to consider other people’s feelings, McCarthy’s prose
achieves its uncanny effect by embedding mental states of the mysterious
narrator, the implied author, and the reader.
For there is a very peculiar narratorial consciousness at work in these
early paragraphs. McCarthy’s narrator inserts himself in the story (“I looked
for blackness, holes in the heaven”) and starts making the case, as it were,
against the Kid. First, by being born, the Kid murdered his own mother,
though, admittedly, she was complicit in the crime. She “did,” after all,
“incubate in her own bosom the creature who would carry her off.” There
is another victim, too. The mother’s death destroyed her husband, a former
schoolteacher, a weak soul, who now “lies in drink,” quoting from poets
“whose names are now lost.” The child “watches” his father—the word
“watches” is repeated twice. He even “crouches” as he “watches”: a little
predator, in whom there “broods already a taste for mindless violence.” The
puzzling opening sentence now makes sense, too. “See the child,” ladies
and gentlemen of the jury, see the defendant on the stand.
He has known all along how it would turn out—the “I” of the second
paragraph—the narrator who watched the heaven on the night the Kid
was born. God-like he is, but also accomplished, in ways that only certain
sophisticated readers would appreciate. He wants those readers to know
that, unlike other riffraff populating the story, he recognizes the unintelligible sounds issuing from the drunk father as bits of forgotten poems. He also
can cite from the poet whose name has not been forgotten—Wordsworth—
and he does so, appropriately, to support his point: “the child the father of
the man.”
The Secret Life of Literature
47
Thus, already in the first paragraphs of the novel, McCarthy wants his
readers to know that the story will be told by a narrator who is determined
to aggrandize himself and to condemn the Kid. Of course, we don’t put it
this way to ourselves, but to the extent to which we are aware of the strange
tone of the opening, starting with “See the child,” we are embedding the
implied author’s intentions. (To quote again one of the MFA workshop’s
participants, “fiction is a cohesive intentional work.”)135
What it all adds up to is that Blood Meridian embeds complex mental
states just as Remembrance of Things Past does, even if, in direct contrast
to Proust’s novel, Blood Meridian contains almost no explicit references to
mental states. We embed implied intentions of the narrator and the author
to make sense of the novel’s tone—the crucial component of McCarthy’s
poetic prose.
1.14 Minds without Bodies
But if some stories pretend to be “mindless” and thus make us work harder
at reading mental states into their characters’ body language, the opposite—
that is, stories in which mental states are spelled out but there are no bodies behind them—is also possible. Consider Daniel Defoe’s Robinson Crusoe
(1719), whose protagonist regularly ponders intentions of “Providence,”
an entity that has landed him on a desert island: “These reflections made
me very sensible of the goodness of Providence to me, and very thankful
for my present condition, with all its hardships and misfortunes; and this
part also I cannot but recommend to the reflection of those who are apt,
in their misery, to say, ‘Is any affliction like mine?’ Let them consider how
much worse the cases of some people are, and their case might have been,
if Providence had thought fit.”136 As Crusoe imagines people who complain
about their affliction, he wants them to consider that had Providence thought
fit to land them in an even worse situation than they are currently in, it
could have easily done so.
Crusoe is not alone thinking about various “secret intimations” of the
“invisible intelligence.”137 Other fictional instances of such “intelligences”
range in form from the karmic destiny of Cao’s Dream of the Red Chamber
to “Aubrey McFate” of Nabokov’s Lolita. What such nebulous entities have
in common is their apparent capacity for intentions and attitudes, which
characters and readers try to fathom, all the while generating embedded
mental states.
48
Chapter 1
Here, for instance, is Mrs. Plinth, a well-heeled provincial lady from Edith
Wharton’s short story “Xingu” (1916). Mrs. Plinth can’t help feeling keenly
that the heavenly power that has made her rich intended for her the honor
of hosting distinguished visitors, an honor currently usurped by another, less
worthy lady, Mrs. Ballinger: “An all-round sense of duty, roughly adaptable
to various ends, was, in her opinion, all that Providence exacted of the more
humbly stationed; but the power which had predestined Mrs. Plinth to keep
footmen clearly intended her to maintain an equally specialized staff of responsibilities. It was the more to be regretted that Mrs. Ballinger, whose obligations
to society were bounded by the narrow scope of two parlour-maids, should
have been so tenacious of the right to entertain [the current special guest].”138
Mrs. Plinth resents that Mrs. Ballinger refuses to acknowledge the intention of Providence, which wanted Mrs. Plinth to host distinguished visitors.
Providence, apparently, is as invested in Mrs. Plinth’s social success as it is
willing to let some people, including Robinson Crusoe, to get away relatively scot-free, while smiting others. We may have come a long way from
Apuleius’s Venus and Cupid: divine entities that guide fictional characters
have, nowadays, shed their bodies. But their social minds are as keen and
active as ever, plotting and picking favorites among mortals.
1.15 One Body, Many Mental States
Let us stay with Robinson Crusoe a bit longer. If you want to know how
many fictional characters one needs to start generating complex embedments, the answer seems to be just one. A single character can embed
enough mental states to sustain a three-hundred-page novel, as does Crusoe, who spends twenty-three out of his twenty-eight years on a desert
island with nobody to talk to. (Friday joins him only at the tail end of his
confinement.) His loneliness does not prevent him, however, from engaging in introspective musings such as this one:
From this moment I began to conclude in my mind that it was possible for me to
be more happy in this forsaken, solitary condition than it was probable I should
ever have been in any other particular state in the world; and with this thought I
was going to give thanks to God for bringing me to this place.
I know not what it was, but something shocked my mind at that thought, and
I durst not speak the words. “How canst thou become such a hypocrite,” said I,
even audibly, “to pretend to be thankful for a condition which, however thou
mayest endeavour to be contented with, thou wouldst rather pray heartily to be
delivered from?”139
The Secret Life of Literature
49
This passage is typical for Defoe’s novel, which demonstrates on every page
ample narrative possibilities of the embedded consciousness of a solitary
protagonist.140 Crusoe imagines that he can be grateful to God for bringing
him to a place where he can be happier than anywhere else in the world.
But then he is shocked that he would pretend to be grateful for a condition
that he would, in fact, prefer to escape. He accuses himself of becoming a
hypocrite—“hypocrisy” being yet another cultural shorthand for a complex
embedment, for a hypocrite wants to make others think that he or she has
beliefs and moral standards that he or she, in fact, does not have.
Unlike Crusoe, the speaker of William Wordsworth’s poem “Lines Composed a Few Miles above Tintern Abbey, On Revisiting the Banks of the
Wye during a Tour” (1798) is not alone: accompanying him on his “tour”
is his sister, Dorothy. Still, for most of the poem, he is thinking about the
relationship among his various selves situated at different points in time,
watching himself, for instance, to form impressions that, he knows, will
influence him for years to come:
And now, with gleams of half-extinguished thought,
With many recognitions dim and faint,
And somewhat of a sad perplexity,
The picture of the mind revives again:
While here I stand, not only with the sense
Of present pleasure, but with pleasing thoughts
That in this moment there is life and food
For future years.141
The speaker imagines his future self being made happy by remembering how
happy he was here (by remembering, that is, his “present pleasure”). David
Herman has described this literary dynamic as “distributed temporality,”142
and we can see this interplay among the mental states of past, present, and
future selves throughout “Tintern Abbey.” Embedments arising out of a
temporally distributed self can be encountered in any work of literature,
but they may be particularly common in memoirs (be they prose or poetry,
such as Nabokov’s Speak, Memory or Wordsworth’s Prelude) concerned with
imagination and consciousness,
1.16 Many Bodies, One Shared Mental State
But if a single character can be a source of mental states embedded on the
third and fourth level, the opposite is also true. A large group of characters
50
Chapter 1
can share a single mental state—thus forming what the cognitive narratologist Alan Palmer calls an “intermental unit.”143 Such an intermental unit
can then be embedded within other mental states the same way as a mental
state of just one character can be embedded within other mental states.
To illustrate this, here is another, typically self-reflexive sentiment of Crusoe, who begins by contemplating his own feelings and then turns to the
thoughts of an intermental unit comprising, perhaps, millions of people:
“But it is never too late to be wise; and I cannot but advise all considering
men, whose lives are attended with such extraordinary incidents as mine,
or even though not so extraordinary, not to slight such secret intimations
of Providence, let them come from what invisible intelligence they will.”144
Crusoe is thinking about the thoughts of, if not the whole of humankind,
then a large part of it. He wants “all considering men” to pay attention to the
intentions of Providence. This is as large a group of people as they come—a
massive “intermental unit”—all sharing one mental state, which is embedded, in its turn, within the thoughts of the protagonist.
We also may want to take a look into the novelistic construction of
crowds and ask how writers get around the problem of representing a large
number of minds—fifty, a hundred, a thousand—numbers that would
instantaneously take us outside our zone of cognitive comfort were we to
try to imagine the mental states of those people one by one. It seems that
authors can deal with this challenge in several ways. They may portray a
crowd through two or three distinct personalities—the spokespeople who
capture various points of view held by the multitude. Or they may depict
a crowd as being of “one mind,” shouting or grumbling in unison. This, in
turn, makes it possible for this unified “mob mind” to interact with two or
three other distinct individuals, who respond to the mob’s concerns, so that
the cumulative number of embedded mental states still stays within the
comfortable range of four.145
Think, for instance, about the preelection scene in George Eliot’s Middlemarch (1871), which starts with Mr. Brooke, who is running for Parliament, giving a short speech in front of a large crowd of potential voters. In
response to his claptrap, first one heckler and then another (“the invisible
Punch”) make fun of him. Mr. Brooke, however, misunderstands their reactions, thinking that the second heckler intends to ridicule the first, until
“a hail of eggs” directed at him and his effigy makes the crowd’s feelings
abundantly clear:
The Secret Life of Literature
51
“That reminds me,” [Mr. Brooke] went on, thrusting a hand into his side-pocket,
with an easy air, “if I wanted a precedent, you know—but we never want a precedent for the right thing—but there is Chatham, now; I can’t say I should have
supported Chatham, or Pitt, the younger Pitt—he was not a man of ideas, and we
want ideas, you know.”
“Blast your ideas! we want the Bill,” said a loud rough voice from the crowd
below.
Immediately the invisible Punch, who had hitherto followed Mr. Brooke,
repeated, “Blast your ideas! we want the Bill.” The laugh was louder than ever, and
for the first time Mr. Brooke being himself silent, heard distinctly the mocking
echo. But it seemed to ridicule his interrupter, and in that light was encouraging;
so he replied with amenity—
“There is something in what you say, my good friend” . . . here an unpleasant
egg broke on Mr. Brooke’s shoulder.146
Readers may walk away with an impression that a multitude of “weavers
and tanners of Middlemarch” have expressed their opinions about Mr.
Brooke’s candidature,147 when all we really have here are two distinct (if
invisible) spokespersons and Mr. Brooke’s initially mistaken view of their
attitude toward each other. Once the crowd’s minds have thus been compressed to a manageable number, we are ready to process the scene’s complex embedments of mental states and consider its meaning. For instance,
as Eliot’s biographer Nancy Henry explains, a “crowd of [Middlemarch
voters] detects and mocks the insincerity of Mr. Brooke’s commitment to
reform.”148 Or, to put it in terms of our present discussion, this crowd knows
that Mr. Brooke only wants them to think that he cares about reform.149
1.17 Downgrade This!
As we are nearing the end of this chapter, let us revisit the issue of “simplifying” our descriptions of mental functioning, first brought up in the section
on Tom Sawyer. For, I can still imagine a reader who thinks that it just may
be possible to make sense of scenes that, as I claim, embed mental states on
at least the third level while staying on the first or second level. To see what
that would look like—that is, what downgrading the levels of embedment
does to a story—let us take a look at three examples from classical Roman,
Greek, and Japanese literature.
In Apuleius’s The Golden Ass (second century AD), a young widow learns
that her beloved husband was treacherously murdered during a boar hunt
52
Chapter 1
by the man who had long wanted her himself. Unaware that she knows
about his perfidy, that man is now pressing the widow for marriage. She
“pretend[s] to be won over” and suggests that they have a clandestine affair,
“just until the year travels the full length of its remaining days,” at which
point they would wed. She wants him to believe that she is eager to sleep
with him yet is ashamed that people would think it unseemly for a new
widow. So he agrees to come to her house late at night, muffled “from head
to foot and bereft of [his] escort,” thus leaving himself vulnerable to her
gory revenge.150
Let us see how much of this episode’s meaning is retained if we insist on
scaling down its levels of embedment:
•
“The widow is eager to sleep with the man who killed her husband.” This
is one mental state, and you can decide for yourself how accurately it
describes what is going on.
•
“The man thinks that the widow is eager to sleep with him.” That’s two
embedded mental states, and this configuration is still wrong, because it
reflects only the limited perspective of the doomed character.
•
“The widow wants the man to think that she wants to sleep with him” or
“The widow wants the man to think that she is afraid of what people will
say if she becomes his mistress so early into her bereavement.” Once we
start operating on the third level, we, finally, begin to capture the complexity of the situation.
In Heliodorus’s An Ethiopian Romance (third century AD), an Egyptian
priest, Calasiris, tells to his acquaintance Cnemon the story of the first meeting of the protagonists, Chariclea and Theagenes. During a public celebration
at the altar of Apollo, Theagenes is supposed to receive a torch from a priestess (Chariclea) with which to light the altar piled with animal sacrifices. The
surrounding crowd includes Chariclea’s adopted father, Charicles, who is,
however, too busy right now to observe his daughter closely:
At first they stood in silent amazement, and then, very slowly, she handed him
the torch. He received it, and they fixed each other with a rigid gaze, as if they
had sometime known one another or had seen each other before and were now
calling each other to mind. Then they gave each other a slight, and furtive smile,
marked only by the spreading of the eyes. Then, as if ashamed of what they had
done, they blushed, and again, when the passion, as I think, suffused their hearts,
they turned pale. In a single moment . . . their countenances betrayed a thousand shades of feeling; their various changes of color and expression revealed the
The Secret Life of Literature
53
commotion of their souls. These emotions escaped the crowd, as was natural, for
each was preoccupied with his own duties; they escaped Charicles also, who was
busy reciting the traditional prayer and invocation. But I occupied myself with
nothing else than observing these young people.151
Calasiris knows that Charicles doesn’t know that Chariclea and Theagenes are
falling in love with each other. We may not articulate this to ourselves as we
read the novel. But later, when Calasiris hatches a plot to help the young
people elope together, it makes sense to us because it hinges on Calasiris’s
knowing that Charicles doesn’t know that Chariclea loves Theagenes. Get rid
of one of those levels of embedment and the elopement plot falls apart.
In Murasaki Shikibu’s The Tale of Genji (eleventh century AD), shortly
after Genji’s mother’s death, the emperor sends a messenger to the boy’s
grandmother, inviting her and Genji to the palace. Upon receiving the
grieving emperor’s letter, the grandmother talks to the messenger about
what it means for her to have outlived her only daughter:
“Now that I know how painful it is to live long,” she said, “I am ashamed to
imagine what that pine must think of me, and for that reason especially I would
not dare to frequent his Majesty’s Seat. It’s very good indeed of him to favor me
with these repeated invitations, but I am afraid that I could not possibly bring
myself to go. His son, on the other hand, seems eager to do so, although I am
not sure just how much he understands, and while it saddens me that he should
feel that way, I cannot blame him. Please let his Majesty know these, my inmost
thoughts.”152
Observe that, while declining the emperor’s invitation, Genji’s grandmother quotes from a poem, Kokin rokujo 3057, in which, as the translator,
Royall Tyler, explains, “the poet laments feeling even older than the pine
of Takasago, a common [lyrical] exemplar of longevity: ‘No, I shall let no
one know that I live on: I am ashamed to imagine what the Takasago pine
must think of me.’”153 The bereaved mother knows that the emperor will be
pained by her refusal to visit him, and she wants him to understand how she
feels. By evoking the poem (which is itself a third-level embedment of mental states: “I am ashamed to imagine what that pine must think of me”), she
makes him aware of a somewhat unexpected nuance of her grief: shame.
If the emperor considers that even a tree would reproach her for outliving
her child, he would surely understand that she doesn’t want to be seen by
others, especially in a place to which people go with the purpose of being
seen, such as the emperor’s palace.
54
Chapter 1
Try conveying any of this through lower-level embedments. “Genji’s grandmother is thinking about a poem” (one mental state) or “Genji’s
grandmother wants the emperor to recall a famous poem” (second-level
embedment) or “Genji’s grandmother wants the emperor to pity her” (also
second-level embedment) all distort the meaning of what is going on. Until
we start thinking on at least the third level—for instance, “Genji’s grandmother wants the emperor to understand that she is too depressed to make an
effort to be seen by others”—our reading of the passage remains tone-deaf.
1.18 Can a Computer Program Tell the Difference between
“Popular Fiction” and “Literature”?
Can one design a computer program that will count levels of embedment in
a given sentence, paragraph, or chapter? The possibility of such a program
has been mentioned to me on several occasions, with cautious enthusiasm
by computer scientists and with dread by my colleagues from literary studies. I would be excited to see software for counting mental states in fiction
because I suspect that it will fail and that its failure will be as illuminating as
was the failure of various artificial intelligence projects in the 1950s–1970s.
The latter, as you may remember, alerted scientists to the unprecedented
complexity of evolved human cognition. The machines could not replicate
cognitive processes that came so easily to people that they hadn’t even
been aware of them. Just so, by failing to register embedded mental states
in literature, a computer program would illuminate cognitive processes that
make reading literature possible and that we take completely for granted,
such as a constant attribution of embedded mental states to characters,
implied authors and readers, and narrators.
It will be particularly instructive if, in this case, the failure turns out to be
selective. For I believe that a computer may be able to count embedments
in some texts but not in others. That is, it may succeed with works of fiction that embed mental states of their characters and describe these mental
states explicitly but not with those that embed implied mental states of
characters, narrators, implied authors, and readers.
Consider this passage from John Irving’s novel The 158-Pound Marriage
(1974): “‘I am going to get a lover,’ she said, ‘and I’m going to let you know
about it. I want you to be embarrassed when you make love to me wondering if I am bored, if he does it better. I want you to imagine what I say that
The Secret Life of Literature
55
I can’t say to you, and what he has to say that you don’t know.’”154 I believe
that one can indeed design a computer program that will do well with
this novel. Make it pick such words as “want,” “embarrassed,” “wonder,”
“bored,” and “imagine,” and you will have a fairly accurate map of a given
passage’s embedment. “I want you to be embarrassed because you wonder if
I am bored”—that’s fourth-level embedment, and a computer may just be
able to perform this calculation.
Now picture software faced with a sentence from Cao Xueqin’s Dream of
the Red Chamber, in which its female protagonist, Lin Dai-yu, reflects on her
winsome cousin, Xue Bao-Chai: “And now suddenly this Xue Bao-chai had
appeared on the scene—a young lady who, though very little older than Daiyu, possessed a grown-up beauty and aplomb in which all agreed Dai-yu was
her inferior.”155 What’s going on in this sentence? Here is one way to spell out
the mental states that we infer as we make sense of it: the narrator wants his
readers to realize that Dai-yu feels distressed because she is certain that everyone around her considers her inferior to Bao-chai. That’s at least four embedded mental states, but to articulate them, we have to take in subtle cues, such
as the unhappy tone with which Dai-yu refers to her cousin. She calls her “a
Xue Bao-Chai” (一個薛寶釵) or “this Xue Bao-chai” in David Hawkes’s transla-
tion. The use of the pronoun “this” or “a” (yīgè) before a personal name is
particularly important here, because it reflects Dai-yu’s anguished sense of
propriety. She can’t say anything harsh or vulgar, so a vaguely dismissive
“this” becomes an expression of her irritation and jealousy.
If we look for explicit references to mental states that this sentence con-
tains, we notice the word rendered by the translator as “agreed” (wèi, 謂).156
This word may describe an attitude of some people around Dai-yu, but the
meaning of the passage does not reside with it. Instead, as we’ve seen, that
meaning is expressed through embedded mental states implied but not
stated by the text.
What will a computer do in this case? It may pick up on the word
“agreed,” but, as we have already seen, that word contributes little to the
complex embedment present in the sentence. The problem is that a computer program cannot register implied mental states, much less figure out
context-specific relationships that organize these mental states into embedments. Because in Dream of the Red Chamber, any word—including “a” and
“this”—can create an implied embedded mental state, only a human mind,
with its infinite sensitivity to contexts, can follow it.
56
Chapter 1
But what about passages from Dream that spell out embedded mental
states of its characters? After all, Dai-yu’s diatribe about the look that Baoyu gave to Xiang-yun, which I quoted in section 1.3 (“But what about that
look you gave Yun? Just what did you mean by that? I think I know what
you meant. You meant to warn her that she would cheapen herself by joking with me as an equal”), is not terribly different from Irving’s “I want you
to be embarrassed when you make love to me wondering if I am bored.”
The difference between the two is that Cao’s novel (as, indeed, other
texts that we tend to put on our course syllabi) does this only occasionally.
In contrast, The 158-Pound Marriage or, for that matter, Dan Brown’s Da
Vinci Code, Stephenie Meyer’s Twilight Saga, or Danielle Steel’s Against All
Odds do it constantly. Computers will have a ball counting mental states in
the fly-by-night favorites that spell out mental states of their characters and
do not demand that their readers process implied mental states of narrators
and implied authors.
Several strains of research in social and developmental psychology may
bear on these issues. For instance, the social psychologist Emanuele Castano and his colleagues, working with theory of mind and fiction, suggest
that “life-time exposure to literary fiction positively predicts attributional
complexity, while exposure to popular fiction negatively predicts it.”157 (Psychologists use the term “attributional complexity” to describe motivation to
seek complex explanations for human behavior, explanations that include,
though are not limited to, mental states.)158 Although Castano et al. are
careful to observe that “literary and popular fiction foster different sociocognitive processes and cognitive styles, all of which are important,”159 the
distinction between the two has been central to their research projects for a
while.160 Moreover, following up on Kidd and Castano’s earlier studies, the
cognitive neuroscientist Iris van Kuijk and her colleagues have suggested
that, compared “to popular fiction, reading literary fiction might encourage
participants to process the meaning of words, sentences and their relationships more deeply and that might produce [theory of mind] differences.”161
Literary critics may take issue with the term “popular,” on several
counts. For instance, they may object to the cognitive scientists’ identification of popular fiction with “character-based” stories and the consequent
exclusion of science fiction from the domain of the literary.162 They are
also aware of the slipperiness of the term, because historically, it is known
The Secret Life of Literature
57
to have covered a broad range of texts, some of them straddling “the categories of literary, genre, and popular.”163 Nevertheless, when we compare
patterns of embedment in Irving, Meyer, Brown, and Steel with patterns
of embedment that we encounter, say, in Cao, Tatiana Tolstaya, and Zadie
Smith, the difference seems to be quite obvious. However you choose to
call them—popular, genre fiction, mainstream, lowbrow—novels by Meyer,
Brown, and Steel spoon-feed complex embedments to their readers, which
must have an effect on those readers’ theory of mind that is different from
the texts that require them to work at constructing them.
For instance, there are intriguing studies by developmental psychologists who have found that adding explicit references to thoughts, feelings,
and intentions of characters in stories for young children does not promote
their understanding of mental states.164 I will discuss those studies in chapter 6 (i.e., on children’s literature), but, for now, I just want you to note that,
even at a young age, actively figuring out implied mental states based on
context seems to result in different sociocognitive outcomes than merely
being told what this or that character thinks.
1.19 Conclusion: Close (Mind)Reading
If you are a teacher of literature, you may have noticed by now, particularly
with the Cormac McCarthy example but also with the excerpts from Mark
Twain, Cao Xueqin, E. M. Forster, and Patricia Highsmith, that the process
of identifying embedded mental states in literature looks a lot like close
reading—a “fundamental practice” of literary analysis, which consists of
“examining closely the language of a literary work or a section of it.”165 The
reason that an inquiry into embedded mental states may end up as a close
reading is that close reading is often an explication of mental states, those
of characters, narrators, authors, readers, and other critics.
We do not think about it in these terms, but it is worth paying attention
to. Next time you are developing a close reading with your students, pause
and take a closer look at the embedment of mental states that you perform
along the way. Conversely, think about passages that you tend to select for
this kind of exercise. See if they tend to “promise” (something that experienced instructors learn to perceive at a glance) a discussion that is likely to
embed complex mental states.
58
Chapter 1
Of course, as Jonathan Culler observes, “there are all sorts of ways of achieving closeness in reading.”166 These range from memorialization, translation
into a foreign language, and inquiry into how culture shapes the meaning
of the text to looking for “conflicts or tensions” within the text, which can
be manifested by “ambiguous words, undecidable syntax, incompatibilities
between what a text says and what it does, incompatibilities between the
literal and the figurative, . . . and so on.”167 Note, however, how integral attribution of complex mental states is to nearly all of those endeavors. Consider,
for instance, translation as a (somewhat less popular, today) form of close
reading.168 Central to translating is figuring out what the author meant by
this or that choice of word in the source language—and hence, which word
would convey the author’s intention most accurately in a target language.169
Here is one way to think about the sociocognitive role played by all those
various practices of achieving “closeness in reading.” It is as if it were not
enough, for some of us, to merely process texts that continuously embed
complex mental states. If we happen to live in what I have dubbed elsewhere
a “culture of greedy mindreaders,” we may also join special communities for
doing so.170 Those communities reward their members (e.g., students, critics)
who are adept at discerning complex intentionalities present in literature,
prizing, in particular, intentionalities that are unexpected and yet plausible.
Far from being an isolated phenomenon, the omnipresence of complex
embedment in literature is thus supported by a variety of cultural practices. Those practices seem to emerge in response to specific historical circumstances (as did the close scrutiny of textual “conflicts or tensions” in
literary studies) and thus are not typically thought of as bound with the
intricacies of our social cognition. In the chapters that follow, I will bring
the two together. That is, I will show that the cognitive and the historical
are inextricably connected in the case of complex embedment and that to
understand why a particular work of fiction embeds mental states the way
it does, we have to inquire into the political and cultural history of its creation and reception.
2
Mindreading and Social Status
Until now, I have talked about what complex embedments are, that is,
what they may look like in novels, plays, and narrative poems, especially if
they don’t even seem to be there. In this chapter, I focus on what complex
embedments do, that is, how writers use them to shape readers’ perception
of their characters. For, as it turns out, characters may differ in their ability to embed their own and others’ thoughts and feelings. How do writers
(intuitively) decide who should be more capable of complex embedment
and who should be less so and what it may mean in the context of their
stories? To answer these questions, we start with the real-life dynamics of
mindreading and see what makes us better at figuring out the mental states
of other people. “Better” in real life is not exactly the same as “more complex” in fiction, but the underlying cause is, curiously, similar, and it has to
do with one’s social status.
2.1 Confessions of a Bad Mindreader
How good are we at reading other people’s minds? Clearly, not great. Our
“misinterpretations about the intentions of others often provoke responses
that are themselves misinterpreted, leading the interaction into a spiraling
[dynamic] likely to engender a general breakdown.”1 Cultural traditions,
social stereotypes, and professional occupations all play roles in hindering
the way we understand each other’s intentions.2 Some cognitive anthropologists even go so far as to say that while “human society” may “rest on a
bedrock” of mindreading, mindreading is “not a particularly useful tool for
predicting and interpreting” people’s behavior, because it “typically misattributes the mental states of others.”3
60
Chapter 2
Yet the misreading of mental states of others may not always be the main
culprit. What makes it worse is that, in complex social situations, we do not
read other people’s minds in isolation from our own.
Let us say, for instance, that I am angry at someone for what I perceive
as a personal slight. While it may seem that I attribute a certain nefarious
intention to them, the actual mindreading dynamic may be more complicated. For what makes me angry may be not merely my perception of
what they are thinking. Instead, it is my expectation about what I ought to
think in response to what I perceive they are thinking. This may work out
differently on different occasions, but what many of those miserable occasions have in common is my assessment of my possible responses to what I
experience as their intentions.
And that assessment can be wrong.
This is to say that, mistaken as we may be in our unreflective attributions of mental states to others, we can be even more off the mark when
we consciously reflect on our own thoughts and feelings. As the cognitive
anthropologist Dan Sperber puts it, “even in the case of seemingly conscious choices, our true motives may be unconscious and not even open to
introspection; the reason we give in good faith may, in many cases, be little
more than rationalizations after the fact.”4
Moreover, we do not have neat little storage facilities in our minds
where our “true motives” are held and that we could access if only we could
somehow tear through the mist and debris that surround them. Instead
we construct our motives similarly to how we construct memories: ad
hoc, grabbing what seems to be emotionally “good to wear” right now.
In the words of the cognitive literary scholar Patrick Colm Hogan (citations removed), “We often think that we simply and directly know our
own motives, the causes of our emotional responses and behaviors. But
considerable research has shown that this is not the case. . . . [People] tend
to experience their affective feelings as reactions to whatever happens to be
in focus at the time. . . . [If] the person is unable to specify either the origin
or the target of affect he or she is experiencing, then this affect can attach
itself to anything that is present at the moment.”5
So, for instance, when I huff and puff in response to what someone said
or did, something in me is constructing a chain of reasoning along the lines
of, “I am the kind of person who would experience the Y kind of emotional
reaction to X. They are saying/doing X. Don’t they know how I am bound
Mindreading and Social Status
61
to respond to this?” From here, it is a very short step to reading into their
actions a range of disagreeable motives, from thoughtlessness to the intention to aggravate me.
At least this is how it seems to work with me when I am at my worst. I
do not claim that this emotional pattern applies to everyone, or even to me
all the time. But were I to generalize from this private experience, I would
say that reading other people’s minds in complex social situations is often
bound up with reading our own minds. This means, given how strikingly
uninsightful we are when it comes to our motives, that misreading other
people’s minds may also be bound up with misreading our own minds, in
fact, sometimes predicated on it.
We misread other people’s minds alongside misreading our own or even
because we misread our own. One wonders why evolution couldn’t come
up with something better than this hapless “mindreading” adaptation . . .
2.2 How to Become a Better Mindreader
But wait! Becoming better mindreaders is within our grasp. All we have
to do is to take a demotion in our social hierarchy. Studies have shown
that people in weaker social positions engage in more active and perceptive mindreading than do people in stronger social positions. It works even
when we know that it’s just a game: “when one is given the role of subordinate in an experimental situation, one becomes better at assessing the
feelings of others, and conversely, when the same person is attributed the
role of leader, one becomes less good.”6
The scholar of Icelandic sagas William Ian Miller may add to this insight
that to become a better mindreader, one may want to place oneself in a
society in which “margins for error [are] smaller.” For instance, “bloodfeuding people” of medieval Iceland “had to be practically wiser and more
cunning than we are now, if only because . . . the stakes [were] higher for
them in routine social interactions and transactions”:
[Life] hung in the balance more often for them than it does for us in the free
West, considerably more so. You had to be pretty good at discerning motives in
others, reading their inner states—better than we safe souls are, for sure. I marvel
at the unfathomable complacency that can allow someone to walk down the
sidewalk intently texting a message and thinking that if he bumps into someone
or forces them unknowingly to give way, that he will not have to account for
62
Chapter 2
himself, secure that he will not suffer a much deserved beating to help him regain
a modicum of manners, to assist him in the project of avoiding giving unwarranted offence to others.7
By giving oblivious texters a second chance, modern liberal democracies
may be blunting the edge of their mindreading prowess. Though one also
wonders if mindreading prowess purchased at the price of the constant
threat of “beatings” may not be a rather stressful proposition.
There are plenty of commonsense reasons why it would be vitally important for someone in inferior social position to be attuned to the intentions
of people above them. What I want to add to those is a possible psychological reason based in the dynamic that I described in the previous section,
which is that reading and misreading other people’s minds is bound with
reading and misreading our own. Recall my fraught chain of reasoning—
“I am the kind of person who would experience the Y kind of emotional
reaction to X. They are saying/doing X. Don’t they know how I am bound
to respond to this?”—and think what happens when the “they” in question
are of higher social status than I am. How likely is it that I would expect
“them” to care about my feelings and persevere with my high-and-mighty
“I am the kind of person who . . .”?
But if I don’t expect them to care about my feelings and I don’t bother
anticipating my emotional response to their lack of caring, then I effectively remove my mental states from the equation. This may make me less
blinded to their actual intentions and thus turn me into a “more active and
perceptive” mindreader.
Again, as in the case of theory of mind being sharpened by the anticipation of a beating, “more active and perceptive mindreading” does not
necessarily imply a happy or even healthy mindreader. There is plenty of
research in the social sciences about negative effects of low socioeconomic
status on one’s well-being.8 Of course, “weaker social position” is a relative
concept, and it does not always imply a low socioeconomic standing. For
instance, I have a lower social status than the dean of my college, which
means that, in a meeting with her, I would be reading her mind more assiduously and perhaps more accurately than she would be mine. (Indeed, I
have had my share of faculty meetings in which we all sit around the table
and try to figure out what our dean really meant by this or that oblique
promise.) Yet as a tenured faculty member at a research university, I am not
exactly an underprivileged type. Still let us not lose sight of the fact that
Mindreading and Social Status
63
when heightened mindreading ability reflects one’s current weaker social
position, there must always be some degree of stress involved.
Consider, too, that those who are in superior social position may assert
and “exert their status precisely by refusing to read mental states of others.”9
Mindreading obtuseness can function similarly to strategic ignorance: “it is
the interlocutor who has or pretends to have the less broadly knowledgeable understanding of interpretive practice who will define the terms of the
exchange.”10 The powerful, writes Rebecca Solnit, “swathe themselves in
obliviousness in order to avoid the pain of others and their own relationship to that pain. There’s a large category of acts hidden from people with
standing: the more you are, the less you know.”11
On a more personal (and, hopefully, less insidious) level, I can think of
other situations in which one may refuse to read minds of others to assert
one’s power over them. For instance, I am aware of not wanting to look
too closely into what my grade-school son and his friends may be thinking
when I prevent them from doing something that they want to do, because
I think that it is dangerous or inconvenient or that we don’t have enough
time. By choosing to be a bad mindreader, I construct myself as a figure of
parental authority, not a happy or optimal stance but one that may get me
through a busy afternoon.12
Incidentally, what an “American White Middle Class (WMC)”13 parent
may guiltily characterize as “bad” mindreading, a Western Samoan parent
may consider as a prosocial pedagogical measure. For instance, as the linguistic anthropologist Elinor Ochs explains, in Samoa, it is the responsibility of a lower-ranking person (e.g., child) to make their perspective clear to
a higher-ranking person (e.g., adult). Ochs does not talk about mindreading as such, focusing instead on utterance interpretation, but the statussensitive dynamic of “perspective-taking” that she describes maps well onto
our present distinction between high- and low-status mindreaders:
In [a highly stratified] Samoan society, sib and parental caregivers work hard to
get children, even before the age of two years, to take the perspective of others.
This demeanor is a fundamental component of showing respect, a most necessary
competence in Samoan daily life. . . .
In Samoan interactions the extent to which parties are expected to assume the
perspective of another in assigning a meaning to an utterance of another varies
with social rank. In speaking to those of lower rank, higher ranking persons are
not expected to do a great deal of perspective-taking to make sense out of their
64
Chapter 2
own utterances or to make sense of the utterance of a lower ranking interlocutor.
Higher ranking persons, then, are not expected to clarify and simplify for lower
ranking persons. For example, caregivers are not expected to simplify their speech
in talking to young children. . . . And exactly the reverse is expected of lower
ranking persons. Lower ranking persons take on more of the burden of clarifying
their own utterances and the utterances of higher ranking interlocutors.14
All this said, would you want to become a better mindreader? If a blunted
interest in other people’s intentions denotes your higher social standing,
shouldn’t you be grateful for this status quo and not aspire to a greater
mindreading perspicacity?
But here is something else to consider. Better mindreading may be associated with relative powerlessness and social stress, yet it also can be experienced as—and, indeed, become—a source of power on its own. Consider
Héctor Tobar’s meditation on growing up, unbeknownst to him, in the same
community with James Earl Ray, the future killer of Martin Luther King Jr.:
“Whereas Ray denied any commonality with the black people around him,
I believe I have no choice but to study the white people around me, and
to understand them as part of my American story—even men and women
who hate and slander my people. Like many other Latino residents of this
country, I derive a sense of power from observing the lives of people who
cannot see the full measure of my humanity.”15
While Ray (arguably) maintained his social superiority by refusing to
read the minds of the Black people around him, Tobar (arguably) conformed
to his lower social standing as a Latino by making an extra effort to “understand” the white people who refused to see him as fully human. Yet Tobar
felt empowered by his interest in their intentionality, and, in the long run,
his commitment to understanding and describing other people’s complex
subjectivity has fueled his career as an acclaimed writer, while Ray’s whitesupremacism-driven lack of interest in mindreading turned him into an
outcast and a murderer.
Hence, one way of looking at these two outcomes is to register the role
of status-sensitive mindreading in the perpetuation of oppression and discrimination. Another is to note the availability of professions (e.g., writer,
lawyer, psychologist, manager) that require strenuous mindreading efforts
and, as such, may serve as means of elevating one’s social standing. I will
address the subject of institutional venues that reward active mindreading
in chapter 4 of this book; here, I merely want to point out that a “better”
Mindreading and Social Status
65
mindreading skill is not an unmixed blessing in a postmodern industrial
society marked by racism and inequality.
2.3 How It Works in Literature: Two Models
In any given work of literature, some characters may carry on complex
mindreading reflections, whether explicitly spelled out or not, while others
settle for simpler ones. In deciding (not necessarily consciously) which will
do which, writers may end up correlating their characters’ social status and
their mindreading ability. (This “may” is important, because writers may
also end up not correlating the two: the pattern I am describing here is far
from universal.) There are two ways of doing so. The first—let us call it the
first model—is that writers follow the real-life dynamic and make characters of lower social standing capable of embedding more complex mental
states than those above them are. The second—let us call it the second
model—has writers invert that dynamic, making those who are high in the
social hierarchy also high in the mindreading hierarchy.
Here is what these two models do not predict:
•
They do not guarantee that the high-embedding character will be correct
in their attributions of mental states. For instance, Jane Austen’s Emma
embeds complex mental states regularly as she plots her love matches,
yet, just as regularly, she is wrong.
•
They do not define characters’ ethics. As the cognitive literary critic
Blakey Vermuele has shown, crafty villains can be “masterminds” carrying on triple or even quadruple mental embedments.16
•
They do not map neatly, or at all, onto the familiar literary-critical distinction between “round” and “flat” characters.17
•
Finally, they do not say anything about the aesthetic value of the text. A
work of fiction can follow either model, or it may not. Indeed, in some
texts, such as Jennifer Egan’s A Visit from the Goon Squad, social hierarchies are fluid—as it were, intersectional—so it is not clear at any given
point which aspect of a character’s social standing (gender, race, clout,
or salary) ought to be considered as predictive of their relative capacity
for complex embedment.
Here is something that only the second model can predict. When a
writer portrays people in weaker social position as less capable of complex
66
Chapter 2
embedment than people in stronger social position, it may be indicative of
a particular ideological agenda on their part. They may be anxious about
their own position in the class hierarchy or wanting to please a particular
segment of their readership who would prefer to see social inferiors who
“know their place.” Agendas vary. We may speculate about them (as I do in
the sections that follow) and never learn the truth. Still, when a writer seems
to have opted for the second model—the one that inverts the real-life correlation between low social standing and more active mindreading—it alerts
us to a possible point of tension bound to a specific historical moment. This
is one of many occasions on which historically minded literary scholars
and cognitive literary theorists may benefit from each others’ insights.
Before I turn to a series of case studies representing either of the two
preceding models, I want to remind you that the pattern that I am discussing here is far from universal. Writers may not foreground the difference between their characters’ capacity for contemplating complex mental
states, or, if they do end up foregrounding this difference, they may not
correlate it with characters’ social standing. This is to say that factors other
than social status (along the lines of class, race, or gender) may influence
the author’s intuitive decision to make one character more sociocognitively
complex than another.
Consider Lev Tolstoy’s War and Peace (1869), which tells the history of
several Russian aristocratic families against the background of the Napoleonic Wars. Its characters include Napoleon Bonaparte as well as Russian
Field Marshal Mikhail Kutuzov, whose decision to let Napoleon occupy the
abandoned Moscow, in September 1812, led to the eventual demise of the
French army. Tolstoy makes both Napoleon and Kutuzov contemplate Moscow just as it is about to be taken over the by French, but if Napoleon’s
thought processes run along the lines of, “a city occupied by an enemy is
like a girl who lost her innocence,”18 Kutuzov is thinking about the complex
social dynamics engendered by the place’s vulnerability. Thus, he is aware
that, when other Russian generals feel compelled to keep talking about
defending Moscow, they do it not because they believe that it can be done
(i.e., just like him, they know that it “cannot be defended”) but because,
for them, this kind of talk creates a fine “pretext for quarrel and intrigue.”19
Tolstoy’s portrayal of Kutuzov as significantly more sociocognitively complex than Napoleon reflects not the difference in these characters’ social
Mindreading and Social Status
67
standing (which would be hard to define) but the author’s patriotism and
his hatred of “the Corsican monster.”20
I do not want you to think, based on this example, that Tolstoy never correlates his characters’ social standing with their ability to embed complex
mental states. The question of whether he does is an empirical one and
can be explored, if a critic is so inclined. I just want you to observe that
the intuitive decision, on the part of an author, to make some characters
more sociocognitively complex than others may be influenced by a wide
spectrum of factors, ranging from personal political preferences to conventions of the genre (e.g., a sympathetic double agent in a spy thriller may
be expected to embed mental states on a higher level than her counterpart
from an opposing side does). The two models that I discuss here by no
means exhaust the scope of possibilities open to a writer, although they do
provide a fascinating glimpse into literature’s experimentation with real-life
social dynamics.
2.4 The First Model: Reflecting the Real-Life Mindreading Dynamic
in Mansfield Park
The protagonist of Jane Austen’s novel Mansfield Park (1814) is female,
young (merely a child when she first enters the house of her rich relatives),
and poor—a charity case with no obvious claims to beauty or intelligence.
To survive and thrive in social circumstances stacked against her so thoroughly, she has to be particularly attuned to other people’s wishes and
intentions, and so she is. Again and again, the “little” Fanny Price is placed
on the top of the mindreading chain, in direct inversion of her social position vis-à-vis her relatives and acquaintances.
One of several ways in which Austen accomplishes this inversion is
to first present us with a seemingly complete scene, outlining everyone’s
embedded feelings—which seem complex enough, for the time being—and
then superimpose Fanny’s mind on top of that scene. For instance, when
Fanny’s cousins and their guests—the golden youth of Mansfield Park—
embark on their ill-conceived theatrical production, we learn that Julia
Bertram is jealous of her sister Maria, who is clearly preferred by Henry
Crawford; that Maria ignores Julia’s feelings; and that Julia hopes that
Maria’s fiancé, Mr. Rushworth, will become aware of the impropriety of her
68
Chapter 2
behavior and expose her to public humiliation: “[Julia] was not superior to
the hope of some distressing end to the attentions which were still carrying on there, some punishment to Maria for conduct so shameful towards
herself as well as towards Mr. Rushworth. . . . Maria felt her triumph, and
pursued her purpose, careless of Julia; and Julia could never see Maria distinguished by Henry Crawford without trusting that it would create jealousy, and bring a public disturbance at last.”
To this mix of second- and third-level embedments, Austen then adds
Fanny’s awareness of Julia’s feelings, while also making sure that there is
no reciprocal awareness (and hence comparable complexity) on Julia’s side:
“Fanny saw and pitied much of this in Julia; but there was no outward fellowship between them. Julia made no communication, and Fanny took no
liberties. They were two solitary sufferers, or connected only by Fanny’s
consciousness.”21
Fanny’s consciousness is indeed the place where various characters get
“connected” or, to put it differently, where many of the novel’s fourth-level
embedments take shape. To spell one of them out (an exercise that typically
results in painfully pedestrian prose, for, in the original text, those highlevel embedments are often implied rather than laid out in their full propositional glory), we can say that Fanny knows that Julia is miserable because
Julia knows that Henry likes Maria. We can further say that Fanny intuits
that Julia hopes that Mr. Rushworth will realize that Maria’s behavior makes
people around them think that he is a fool and revenge himself on her and
that, though otherwise compassionate toward Julia, she can’t quite find it
in herself to empathize with this particular hope of her cousin’s.
Change of scenery. Maria marries Mr. Rushworth and reconciles with
Julia, and both sisters leave Mansfield Park. The passage that I am looking
at now takes place after Henry Crawford proposes to Fanny, is rejected, and
decides to convince her to reconsider. During a quiet evening in a Mansfield
drawing room, after Fanny, her aunt Lady Bertram, her cousin Edmund,
and Henry have been talking together for some time, Henry turns to Fanny
to inquire more closely about her involuntary response (i.e., a shake of the
head) to something that he just said. Edmund, who approves of Henry’s
courtship, wants to make it easier for Henry to talk to Fanny privately.
Accordingly, he takes up a newspaper and removes himself from the general
conversation. Lady Bertram, he knows, won’t be in Henry’s way because she
rarely thinks of anything other than the convenience of her favorite pug.
Mindreading and Social Status
69
Once again, Fanny’s perspective is added after the scene has been set,
for, much as she wants to come across as focused solely on her needlework,
she can see what Edmund is doing with that newspaper: “[As] Edmund perceived, by [Henry’s] drawing in a chair, and sitting down close by her, that
it was to be a very thorough attack, that looks and undertones were to be
well tried, he sank as quietly as possible into a corner, turned his back, and
took up a newspaper, very sincerely wishing that dear little Fanny might
be persuaded into explaining away that shake of the head to the satisfaction of her ardent lover. . . . Fanny . . . grieved to the heart to see Edmund’s
arrangements.”22
Fanny’s capacity for complex embedment contrasts starkly with that of
Lady Bertram, seated right next to her (who seems incapable of embedding
thoughts and feelings above the second level), but also with that of the two
young men. Henry wants to know what Fanny disapproves of. Edmund
knows that Henry wants to know what Fanny disapproves of. Fanny, however, knows that Edmund knows that Henry wants to know what Fanny
disapproves of. To put it starkly, in terms of embedded intentionalities,
Henry has intentions regarding Fanny; Edmund is aware of Henry’s intentions regarding Fanny, but Fanny is aware of Edmund’s intentions regarding Henry’s intentions regarding herself. Here, as on many other occasions,
“the dear little Fanny” is one or two mental states ahead of whichever Bertram or Crawford happens to be at hand.
In scenes that do not immediately involve Fanny, characters’ ability and
willingness to imagine other people’s mental states is recalibrated to reflect
their immediate power relations. For instance, excited about the theatrical
production, Tom Bertram chooses not to understand Edmund’s warning
that Maria is about to dishonor their family (i.e., by developing a relationship with Henry Crawford while about to be married to Mr. Rushworth).
When Edmund invites Tom to consider their mutual awareness of Maria’s
growing disregard for her fiancé’s feelings (as he puts it, “to attempt [private
theatrics] would be imprudent, I think, with regard to Maria, whose situation is a very delicate one, considering everything, extremely delicate”),23
Tom ignores that invitation and insists that the play will entertain their
mother.
To quote Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, Tom “pretends to have the less broadly
knowledgeable understanding of interpretive practice,” yet he is the one
who will “define the terms” of their conversation. As the older brother
70
Chapter 2
operating within the system of primogeniture, he can afford to be obtuse
when it suits him, while Edmund must keep honing his younger brother’s
skill of being convincing without giving offense. On a gentleman’s estate,
mindreading hierarchies reflect the social pecking order.
2.5 The First Model in Pre-Revolutionary China and Russia
We now turn to authors from very different cultural traditions. In the
eighteenth-century Chinese classic Dream of the Red Chamber, by Cao Xueqin
(ca. 1750–1760), girls and young women typically embed mental states on a
higher level than rich men and older rich women do.24 Moreover, although
these female characters are beautiful, accomplished, and pampered by their
families, they are powerless. Their fates are decided by their elders, who
cannot—and will not—read their emotions and, consequently, doom their
young charges to lives of misery or to early deaths.
The striking mindreading skills of Cao’s young women stand out in the long
history of the literary response to social stratification in premodern China. As
Haiyan Lee observes, “[In societies] structured by kinship sociality . . . theory
of mind is certainly present and useful but not always prized in social life and
does not animate expressive culture to the same extent [as it does] in modern
commercial societies structured by stranger sociality, cosmopolitanism, and
social mobility. . . . The hierarchical structures of [kinship sociality] place a
greater premium on theory of mind for subordinates than for the powerful,
hence attaching a tinge of opprobrium to its exercise.”25 When subordination
follows the lines of gender, mindreading acumen—configured as cunning—
follows closely: “Women in a patriarchal and patrilineal society, especially
young daughters-in-law, are structurally motivated to be inward-looking, to
adopt a calculating, fawning, and defensive mentality, and to orient their
action around the intentions of the more powerful (senior, male) members of
the kin group.”26
Fawning, defensive, and calculating underlings, female or male, do
not make for sympathetic fictional characters, which is why such personages tend to “ply shady trades as go-betweens, procuresses, litigation
masters, soothsayers, brokers, and garden-variety hangers-on who prey on
the honest and unsuspecting.” Yet, as Lee argues, “[In some] exceptional
circumstances . . . mind-reading becomes an asset and the consummate
practitioner is admired and celebrated as a cultural hero. Most of these
Mindreading and Social Status
71
circumstances involve forces of good combatting forces of evil, as in warfare or criminal investigation. More rarely, theory of mind is mobilized to
emplot romantic courtship.”27
In other words, we can read the literary history of premodern China as
punctuated by the appearance of works that valorize a character’s capacity for complex embedment of mental states. Those works include warfare
chronicles (such as Luo Guanzhong’s fourteenth-century The Romance of
the Three Kingdoms) and detective novels (such as the eighteenth-century
case studies of Judge Dee), as well as the bildungsroman-courtship-novel
extraordinaire Dream of the Red Chamber. Although some of Dream’s young
women (most obviously, Wang Xi-feng) still come across as defensive and
calculating, most are true to the ideal that the middle-aged Cao set out to
bring back to life, after finding himself one day, in low spirits, “thinking
about the female companions” of his youth: “As I went over them one by
one, examining and comparing them in my mind’s eye, it suddenly came
over me that those slips of girls—which is all they were then—were in every
way, both morally and intellectually, superior to the ‘grave and mustachioed
signior’ I am now supposed to have become.”28
And so, in direct contrast to the young women of, for instance, the anonymous late sixteenth-century classic The Plum in the Golden Vase, whose
sharpened capacity for high-level embedment of mental states makes them
cheats, liars, and hypocrites,29 the cognitive complexity of the girls from
Dream manifests itself in their admirable social sophistication and poetic
sensibility. Far from damaging their personalities, their subordinate status
lends poignancy to their moral and intellectual superiority.
Let us cross national boundaries again. If we look at Russian literature
before the 1760s (that is, before Russian writers became exposed to western
European models, a topic that I discuss at some length in chapter 5), we
see something very similar to what Lee describes as the association of such
complexity with “pipsqueaks,” that is, with socially insignificant personages who, nevertheless, manage to create problems for “gentlemen.”
There is, for instance, Frol, from the anonymous The Tale of Frol Skobeev
(1680–1720), a social nonentity who rises to wealth and nobility by thinking one step (i.e., one mental state) ahead of various aristocratic figures
who come his way. Frol is a pettifogger (remember Lee’s observation that
a social nonentity may use his mindreading skills to become a “litigation
master”?), who tricks the only daughter of a rich courtier into sleeping with
72
Chapter 2
him (by crossdressing as a woman) and then elopes with her. When the
distraught parents find out what has happened, they first want to prosecute
the rogue but then relent and start showering the young couple with land
and money, all the while cursing their “thief” and “knave” of a son-in-law.30
They relent because Frol knows how to manipulate their feelings. When
they send a servant to inquire about the health of their child, Frol asks his
wife to pretend to be sick and tells the servant, “See for yourself, my friend,
how she’s doing: that’s what parental wrath does—they scold and curse her
from afar, and here she is, dying.”31 Frol wants his parents-in-law to think
that their anger is killing their daughter, a stratagem that quickly cools their
wrath and sets Frol on the way to prosperity.
Critics consider The Tale of Frol Skobeev an early example of Russian
picaresque.32 Viewed in the context of the present argument, this characterization raises the intriguing possibility of a cognitivist reading of the
literary figure of the picaro.33 From Mateo Alemán’s Guzmán de Alfarache
(1599–1604) to Daniel Defoe’s Moll Flanders (1724), picaros use their superior mindreading skills to flatter, bully, cheat, and steal their way to economic survival. They are simultaneously a threat—to the extent to which
their society still retains traces of “kinship sociality” (and what society does
not?—even if just in the form of cultural fantasies about a golden age, when
all behavior was transparent and prosocial and no mindreading acumen
was called for)—and a treat for readers who follow their double-dealing
tricks with guilty delight.
We find the association between characters’ low social status (low, that
is, in relative rather than absolute terms: always in comparison with someone else in the story) and their heightened capacity for complex embedment in a broad spectrum of fictional narratives. Some characters embed
complex mental states as they mastermind a plot to help their bumbling
masters, as do “clever slaves” of ancient Greek and Roman comedies. Some
do it as they trick a larger or more violent and dangerous animal in order
to save their lives, as do Brer Rabbit of West African folklore and the little
mouse of Julia Donaldson’s Gruffalo. Some seem to lack any agenda and
merely display a mastery of innuendo beyond that of their social “betters,”
as does Algernon’s servant Lane in Oscar Wilde’s The Importance of Being
Earnest.34
Some have central billing, as does P. G. Wodehouse’s Jeeves. Others make
only brief appearances in one scene, as Wilde’s Lane. Still others, such as
Mindreading and Social Status
73
the office cleaners from Rachel Cusk’s Saving Agnes (1993), are episodic
characters who lack any identifying features and manage to outclass the
main protagonist in the business of mindreading while remaining nameless
and faceless:
Agnes slammed into the house in a state of considerable distemper. She had been
forced by the nonchalance with which the editorial department was approaching its deadline to stay late in the office, working alone while the cleaners emptied bins and vacuumed floors around her. Watching them sanitize the unsavory
detritus of her day she had been besieged by feelings of shame and guilt, and had
attempted to engage them in pleasantries. Not beguiled by her condescension,
however, they had roundly rebuffed her overtures and left her feeling that a mysterious exchange of power had taken place, the precise manoeuvres of which she
was not able to fathom.35
If we map out this “mysterious exchange of power” in terms of its underlying mental states, we can say that Agnes wants to make herself feel better by
engaging in small talk with the cleaners (second-level embedment). The
cleaners, however, know that she wants to use them to make herself feel
better (third-level embedment) and refuse her that satisfaction. As Agnes
apparently expects that her class privilege will automatically translate into
superior social acumen (even though she can’t see the cleaners as people
with faces and names), when their conversation doesn’t follow that scripted
path, she is left disoriented and angry.
What this example from Cusk’s novel shows is that, just as in real life,
fictional mindreading hierarchies are situation specific. Our common sense
suggests that a protagonist would always be more capable of complex
embedment than would be a minor character, if only because what makes
them the protagonist is their involvement in the great many social interactions depicted in the story. So if we would merely count the occasions
throughout the novel on which Agnes embeds mental states on a high
level (which, I hope, we would never do, because that would be incredibly tedious!), there is no doubt that the number of those occasions would
trump the number of occasions on which a given episodic character (e.g.,
an office cleaner, who only appears once) embeds mental states on a high
level. But if, instead of thinking in such cumulative terms, we look at specific scenes, we may discover patterns that have less to do with the protagonist’s outsize role in the plot and more to do with the novel’s engagement
with its ideological and generic contexts.
74
Chapter 2
2.6 Race and Embedment in Invisible Man
As Ralph Ellison was reflecting, in 1981, on his experience of writing Invisible Man (1947), he explained that he had wanted to “create a narrator who
could think as well as act.” Too many “protagonists of Afro-American fiction” of his day, he felt, “were without intellectual depth, . . . seldom able
to articulate the issues which tortured them.” Real-life models for individuals who could think were not lacking, but even if they were, “it would be
necessary, both in the interest of fictional expressiveness and as examples
of human possibility, to invent them.”36
Other writers, after all, were not shy about inventing deep self-reflexivity
for social groups of their choice. Henry James, Ellison observed, had done
just that. He had taught his readers “much with his superconscious, ‘super
subtle fry,’ characters who embodied in their own cultured, upper-class
way the American virtue of conscience and consciousness.”37 Ellison saw
his task as “revealing the human universals hidden within the plight of
one who was both black and American,” and he considered a crucial step
toward that revelation endowing his protagonist with a capacity for “conscious perception” of forces acting on him within and without. As he put it,
“[To] defeat [the] national tendency to deny the common humanity shared
by my character and those who might happen to read of his experience,
I would have to provide him with something of a worldview, give him a
consciousness in which serious philosophical questions could be raised.”38
I find it significant that Ellison was thinking of Henry James as he contemplated ways to give his protagonist a complex and expansive consciousness, particularly in the light of what I am about to show you regarding
Invisible Man’s capacity for embedment. I have to confess, however, that,
so far, I have avoided any references to James, because quoting him feels like
cheating. James is one author about whom it can be said that he embeds
third-and fourth-level mental states in every single sentence, and I believe
that what I have to say is more convincing if I shun such easy targets. I do
not want my readers to think, “Well, yes, James, of course, but he is exceptional.” When a culture has arrived at the point when its literature cannot
function anymore without constantly embedding mental states on at least
the third level, prose like James’s represents this general tendency, albeit
taken, perhaps, to one of its endpoints. It is thus paradigmatic rather than
exceptional.
Mindreading and Social Status
75
But, guard my argument as I did, James still came in, riding as it were
on the coattails of Ellison. So let us establish one thing about both James’s
and Ellison’s representations of fictional consciousness. While the unceasing complex embedment of mental states may not be a sufficient condition
for creating James’s “superconscious” characters and implied reader, it is a
necessary condition. And similarly, while making Invisible Man conspicuously capable of embedding complex mental states may not be a sufficient
condition for endowing him with intellectual depth, it may be a necessary
condition.
Lest we wonder how Invisible Man’s capacity for complex embedment squares with his naiveté, recall that much of mindreading is mindmisreading. Mindreading is a process of attributing mental states rather than
of telepathic discernment. In fact, as far as mindreading goes, telepathy is
its opposite because this fantastic concept presupposes that mental states
are actually there in people’s minds, available for perusal both by the owners
of those minds and by those who happen to have the special powers.
Embedding mental states on a high level thus does not make a character
particularly penetrating. (It can, but it doesn’t have to. Just think of how
spectacularly misguided James’s characters often are.) Instead, this is one
way in which literature, as we know it today, signals complex consciousness
to its readers, indeed, how it asserts “the common humanity shared by [the]
character and those who might happen to read of his experience.”
Hence, Ellison’s protagonist has a compelling consciousness not when
he knows what people around him are thinking—he mostly does not!—but
when he allows them to have intentions that are mystifying to him and to
themselves. To the extent to which he wonders about their mental states, he
sees those people.39 And, conversely, to the extent to which they refuse to
wonder about his mental states, they do not see him. As he puts it, Jack, Norton, and Emerson each attempted “to force his picture of reality upon me
and neither giving a hoot in hell for how things looked to me.”40 This is to
say that they remain willfully blind to the unpredictable complexity of his
feelings, which translates, in practice (for, again, we are talking here about
practical ways in which literature can represent complex consciousness!)
into their inability to embed mental states on a comparably high level.
Here is a scene, at the end of the book, in which Invisible Man becomes
aware of the confused perspective of people who have tried, at different
times, to control him without actually seeing him. As the leader of the riot
76
Chapter 2
in Harlem, “Ras the Destroyer,” commands his men to seize and hang Invisible Man—to punish him for what they think of as his treacherous collaboration with the white people against the Black—the protagonist meditates
on the levels of unknowing that drive the events of this night:
I looked at Ras on his horse and at their handful of guns and recognized the
absurdity of the whole night and of the simple yet confoundingly complex
arrangement of hope and desire, fear and hate, that had brought me here still
running, and knowing now who I was and where I was and knowing too that I
had no longer to run for or from the Jacks and the Emersons and the Bledsoes
and Nortons, but only from their confusion, impatience, and refusal to recognize
the beautiful absurdity of their American identity and mine. . . . And that I, a
little black man with an assumed name should die because of a big black man
in his hatred and confusion over the nature of a reality that seemed controlled
solely by white men whom I knew to be as blind as he, was just too much, too
outrageously absurd.41
This is a very complex passage, and there are several ways to map out its
implied embedments. Here are some of them. The protagonist is keenly
aware that Ras (“a big black man”) doesn’t realize that his reality is being
controlled by white men who themselves are confused about the significance of their actions. The protagonist realizes that he will no longer be
afraid of or controlled by the people who are confused and impatient. By
calling the situation “absurd,” he is aware that someone capable of a largescale perspective (God? History?) would not be able to see any meaning in
his death were he to die because of other people’s confusion and impatience.
Moreover, the protagonist’s self-description as “a little black man with an
assumed name” brings to mind not just the “little Fanny” of Mansfield Park
but also various picaros and “pipsqueaks” who change their names to survive in a hostile world.42 Like them, Invisible Man has social circumstances
lined up against him: he is young, poor, and Black in the Jim Crow United
States. And, also like them, he makes his way in the world by actively trying to understand other people’s perspectives. He often fails,43 but he never
stops trying because, unlike people in superior social positions, he can’t
afford to remain willfully blind to the subjectivity of others.
Here, for instance, is Invisible Man entering the lobby of the Men’s
House, wearing his overalls—which indicate his descent to working class—
and imagining people thinking that he has lost his pride as an upward-bound
college student and, moreover, has betrayed their expectations of him: “I
could feel their eyes, saw them all and saw too the time when they would
Mindreading and Social Status
77
know that my prospects were ended and saw already the contempt they’d
feel for me, a college man who had lost his prospects and pride. I could see
it all and I knew that even the officials and the older men would despise me
as though, somehow, in losing my place in Bledsoe’s world I had betrayed
them. I saw it as they looked at my overalls.”44
Or consider the conversation between Jack and Invisible Man during
which Jack reproves him for having organized a mass funeral for Tod Clifton, who was murdered by a policeman. Although Jack repeatedly assures
Invisible Man that “he knows what [he] feels,”45 we end the scene convinced that Jack does not really see him—that is, cannot or will not conceive of him as someone with complex subjectivity. For instance, when
Jack hopes that Invisible Man would never find himself in circumstances
in which he would have to sacrifice his eye and get an artificial one (as Jack
had, in service of the Party), Invisible Man responds with a complex embedment that Jack does not seem to understand. Here is their exchange:
“Good,” he said. “I sincerely hope it [i.e., losing an eye] never happens to you.
Sincerely.”
“If it should, maybe you’ll recommend me to your oculist,” I said, “then I may
not-see myself as others see-me-not.”
He looked at me oddly then laughed. “See, Brothers, he’s joking. He feels
brotherly again. But just the same, I hope you’ll never need one of those.”46
Jack treats Invisible Man’s remark as a joke instead of recognizing it as a biting
comment on the selective blindness that enables him not to see, or acknowledge, the complex subjectivity of his “brother.” Of course, to recognize it as
such a comment, he would have to unpack its soaring levels of embedment.
This, after a moment of consideration, he decides not to do. (The narrator
indicates that moment by saying that Jack looked at him “oddly”).
Jack is hardly a stupid man, so his decision may be a strategic one. His
standing as a high-ranking member of the Communist Party is not set in
stone. It has to be maintained and defended—for instance, when a charismatic and intelligent Black “brother” appears on the scene. Racism is a
powerful factor that would keep Invisible Man in his place, yet alone it may
not be enough, especially given the Party’s ostensibly egalitarian outlook.
So mindreading obtuseness comes in handy, for whoever pretends to know
less will (to return once more to Sedgwick) “define the terms of exchange.”
Jack, by showing that he doesn’t need to bother to understand Invisible
Man’s meaning, seeks to reassert his superiority over Invisible Man.47
78
Chapter 2
The Communist Party may thus claim to be color-blind, but it ends up
mind-blind, which serves a rather different purpose: that of keeping some
of its “brothers” down.
2.7 The Second Model: Inverting the Real-Life Dynamic
Here is what we have done so far. We have looked at fictional case studies
in which relative capacity for complex embedment tracks the real-life correlation between weaker social position and more active mindreading. Again,
please remember that this correlation gets reimagined in literature in a very
particular way. Instead of writers making their downtrodden characters into
straightforwardly “better” mindreaders—that is, more perceptive and accurate
in their attribution of mental states—they make them into high-level embedders. “Better” mindreading may occasionally happen too, but it’s not guaranteed; overthinking others’ intentions may just as well lead to one’s undoing.
And so I have shown that the young women from Cao’s Dream of the Red
Chamber, the Russian picaro Frol Skobeev, Austen’s Fanny Price, and Ellison’s
Invisible Man all consistently embed mental states on a higher level than do
other characters around them who have more power and social clout. Indeed,
some of those characters, such as Tom Bertram or Jack, may reaffirm their
clout by refusing to navigate complex embedments offered up to them by
people in weaker social positions, such as Edmund Bertram or Invisible Man.
I now turn to literary texts that do the opposite. That is, they invert the
real-life correlation between lower social standing and active mindreading
and portray socially disadvantaged characters as not being able to embed
complex mental states on the high level of their “betters.” I further suggest
that, more often than not, such an inversion indicates a particular ideological agenda on the part of the author and that those agendas may range
from tacit personal anxiety about one’s social status to a fear for one’s life,
when one happens to be a writer living under a totalitarian regime.
2.8 The Second Model: Bakhtin and the English Comedy of Manners
My first example of the “inverted” model comes from Frances Burney’s Evelina (1778). Evelina is an epistolary novel that, over the past two decades,
has become a staple for college courses on eighteenth-century British literature. Written when the author was in her middle twenties, it portrays
Mindreading and Social Status
79
a beautiful young woman brought up in rural seclusion and thrust onto
London’s bustling social scene. The story has some dark streaks (those will
become more prominent in Burney’s later work), but it is largely a comedy
of manners. As such, it tends to go over well with undergraduates who enjoy
following the romantic adventures of a satirically inclined naïf in a big city.
As befits a romantic heroine, Evelina is a princess in disguise. She is a
daughter of a baronet, who abandoned her mother shortly after their marriage and burned the marriage certificate. This means that, though by birth
and education she belongs to the aristocracy, her social status is ambiguous,
at least until her father publicly acknowledges her as his legitimate heiress.
Until that happens, she is subject to amorous advances by men from an
unusually wide social spectrum, from tradesmen to aristocrats, each with
his own way of speaking and pressing his suit.
In the scene that we are about to look at, one of those men, Mr. Smith,
an offspring of shopkeepers who yet wishes to come across as a gentleman,
is courting Evelina in a particularly obnoxious fashion. Earlier in the novel,
he had invited her to a public ball at the Hampstead Assembly. Although
she told him that she didn’t want to go, he simply ignored her words and
purchased tickets for both of them.
Presented with the tickets, Evelina doesn’t just repeat her earlier refusal.
Instead, she couches her response in such terms as to show her incompatibility with Mr. Smith.48 He understands only part of what she says and
can’t respond properly. This proves her point, because men from the social
class to which she anxiously defends her right to belong would have understood and responded in kind (even those of them whose courtship styles
are offensive in their own ways).
Here is their conversation. Evelina has just reminded Mr. Smith that she
had already told him that she wouldn’t go to the Assembly.
“Lord, Ma’am,” cried he, “how should I suppose you was in earnest? come, come,
don’t be cross; here’s your Grandmama ready to take care of you, so you can have
no fair objection, for she’ll see that I don’t run away with you. Besides, Ma’am, I
got the tickets on purpose.”
“If you were determined, Sir,” said I, “in making me this offer, to allow me no
choice of refusal or acceptance, I must think myself less obliged to your intention
than I was willing to do.”
“Dear Ma’am,” cried he, “you’re so smart, there is no speaking to you;—indeed
you are monstrous smart, Ma’am! but come, your Grandmama shall ask you, and
then I know you’ll not be so cruel.”49
80
Chapter 2
Evelina and Mr. Smith may as well be speaking two different languages, so
loud is the clash of their sensitivities and the social incommensurability that
it implies. Yet how is this impression created? That is, what tools do we have
at our disposal to explain the rhetorical effect of their amusing exchange?
Eventually, as you can easily guess, I will ask you to look at the difference
between Evelina’s and Mr. Smith’s patterns of embedment. But before we
do that, let us consider another, more established and influential interpretive framework: Mikhail Bakhtin’s notion of heteroglossia. For, I believe
that, in this particular case, the two approaches work better in tandem than
my “cognitive” approach would on its own.
Unlike other eighteenth-century authors, such as Fielding, Sterne, and
Smollett, Burney was not on Bakhtin’s radar when he wrote about the “heteroglot, multi-voiced, [and] multi-styled” language of the novel.50 Still, her
writing seems to exemplify what he called a comic style “of the English sort”:
one based on “the stratification of the common language” through the “stylistically individualized speech of characters.”51 Burney’s first novel, in particular, uses heteroglossia in service of a particular ideology: the way Mr. Smith
and Evelina talk underscores their immutable class positions.
Thus, in response to Evelina’s polished sentences, the “low-born” Mr.
Smith uses short, clipped clauses (“don’t be cross”) and vulgar expressions
that brand him as a shopkeeper aspiring to sound genteel, such as “monstrous smart.” His grammar is bad (“you was”). He betrays his crassness, by
reminding her that he paid for the tickets (“I got the tickets on purpose”).
It’s all there, ready for the reader primed to look for sociolectal markers.
But in addition to those obvious markers, we also have here something
less obvious, something we would not see without our “cognitive” perspective. Mr. Smith’s embedments, both implied and explicit, stay around the
second level, whereas Evelina spouts third- to fourth-level embedments one
after another. Let us take another look at their exchange, now mapping its
embedded mental states:
“Lord, Ma’am,” cried he, “how should I suppose you was in earnest? come, come,
don’t be cross; here’s your Grandmama ready to take care of you, so you can have
no fair objection, for she’ll see that I don’t run away with you. Besides, Ma’am, I
got the tickets on purpose.” (Who would think that you meant what you said? [two
embedded mental states]. I know that you worry that there will be no chaperone
[two embedded mental states].)
“If you were determined, Sir,” said I, “in making me this offer, to allow me no
choice of refusal or acceptance, I must think myself less obliged to your intention
Mindreading and Social Status
81
than I was willing to do.” (I might have felt bad turning you down had I thought
that you were aware of my feelings enough to care to give me a choice [at least three,
perhaps four embedded mental states]. But because now I know that you wouldn’t
even care that I don’t want to go, I intend not to feel bad about disappointing you
[two parallel sets of three embedded mental states].)
“Dear Ma’am,” cried he, “you’re so smart, there is no speaking to you;—indeed
you are monstrous smart, Ma’am! but come, your Grandmama shall ask you, and
then I know you’ll not be so cruel” (I know that you are too smart for me [two
embedded mental states]. I hope you’ll listen to your Grandmama [two embedded
mental states]. I know that you will agree eventually [two embedded mental states].)
When I teach Evelina, I ask my students to compare Mr. Smith’s pattern of embedment to that exhibited by two other characters, Sir Clement
Willoughby and Lord Orville, who belong to the aristocracy, that is, the
social class within which Evelina, a daughter of a baronet, will eventually
be ensconced. Here are two typical examples of their speech. (I quote them
out of context, but it is similar in both cases: each man wants to influence
Evelina by disposing her more favorably toward himself.)
Sir Clement Willoughby: “You cannot even judge of the cruelty of my
fate; for the ease and serenity of your mind incapacitates you from feeling
for the agitation of mine!”52 We may map this as, I appreciate that your state
of mind makes it impossible for you understand how unhappy I am (at least
three, possibly four embedded mental states).
Lord Orville: “I greatly fear that I have been so unfortunate as to offend
you; yet so repugnant to my very soul is the idea, that I know not how
to suppose it possible I can unwittingly have done the thing in the world
that, designedly, I would wish to avoid.”53 We may map this as, You must
believe that I am distressed to realize that I have made you feel precisely the
way I would never want to make you feel (at least four embedded mental
states).
Mr. Smith’s limited capacity for embedding mental states is thus dialogic,
another key concept from Bakhtin.54 That is, we may experience it as limited only in contrast with the embedments of other characters, such as Evelina, Sir Clement Willoughby, and Lord Orville. Once we become aware of
this contrast, we realize that it is used throughout the novel in two related
but not identical ways.
First, it marks bona fide, as opposed to in-name-only, gentility. That is,
“real” gentlemen and gentlewomen, such as Lady Howard, Mr. Villars, Mrs.
Selwyn, and Mr. Macartney, who also happen to treat Evelina with kindness
82
Chapter 2
and respect, consistently embed mental states at and above the third level,
while the nominally genteel characters who insult, ignore, and exploit her,
such as Lord Merton, Lady Louisa Larpent, Mr. Lovel, and Captain Mirvan,
stay around a lower (i.e., second) level.55
Besides marking “true” gentility, the differential capacity for embedding
is also used to naturalize characters’ social status. Shopkeepers and parvenus
with shopkeeper mentality don’t rise above the second level in their attribution of mental states. Thus, Evelina’s low-born cousin, Tom Branghton:
“There is nothing but quarreling with the women; it’s my belief they like it
better than victuals and drink.”56 Or her ex-barmaid grandmother, Mme.
Duval: “I’ve no doubt but we shall be all murdered!”57 Or Biddy Branghton:
“I wonder when Mr. Smith’s room will be ready.”58 If you consider the dismal treatment that these characters receive throughout the novel, it seems
that the lack of capacity for embedding mental states on a high level marks
pretty much everyone belonging to this class as not worthy of compassion
or sympathy.
The capacity for embedment thus functions as a form of heteroglossia.
It can be combined with other sociolectal markers, but only for those characters who are not capable of sophisticated layering of social consciousness. Thus, Tom Branghton’s low-level embedments go hand in hand with
contractions, clipped sentences, and colloquialisms: “Didn’t you [hear of
it], Miss? . . . Why then you’ve a deal of fun to come, I’ll promise you; and,
I tell you what, I’ll treat you there some Sunday noon”59; Mme. Duval’s,
with contractions, double negatives, and bad French: “Pardie, no—you may
take care of yourself, if you please, but as to me, I promise you I sha’n’t
trust myself with no such person.”60 Lord Merton, a newly titled nobleman who lacks true gentility, punctuates his first-level embedments with
curses: “I don’t know what the devil a woman lives for after thirty.”61 Captain Mirvan, another character whose behavior belies his nominal status
of gentleman, sprinkles his second-level embedments62 with sailor’s lingo:
“I am now upon a hazardous expedition, having undertaken to convoy a
crazy vessel to the shore of Mortification.”63
In comparison, the speech of unambiguously genteel characters is largely
devoid of such markers. The only feature that is reliably present—and thus
should be considered a marker in its own right—is the ability to embed
mental states on a high level. “Can there, my good Sir, be any thing more
painful to a friendly mind, than a necessity of communicating disagreeable
Mindreading and Social Status
83
intelligence?”; “I am grieved, Madam, to appear obstinate, and I blush to
incur the imputation of selfishness”; “The benevolence with which you
have interested yourself in my concerns, induces me to suppose you would
wish to be acquainted with the cause of that desperation from which you
snatched me”; “I am extremely sorry . . . that you think me too presumptuous”; “To what, my Lord, must I, then, impute your desire of knowing [my
intentions]?”64
Lady Howard, Mr. Villars, Mr. Macartney, Lord Orville, and even Sir
Clement Willoughby (except when he’s trying to overwhelm Evelina with
his dramatic professions of devotion and overblown terms of endearment)
sound nearly interchangeable in their complex embedments. It is almost as
if the relentlessly demanding pattern of such embedments were too metabolically costly for the text, leaving little energy for further verbal idiosyncrasies to be associated with these characters.
I said before that characters who function on the first and second level
of embedment do not, as a rule, elicit much of readers’ compassion. As one
of my students put it, referring to the cruel prank that Captain Mirvan plays
on Mme Duval, “I didn’t care about Mme. Duval’s suffering. It’s one bad
character playing a trick on another bad character.”65 It also works the other
way around. The characters who are portrayed as being able to afford the
cognitive luxury of consistently embedding mental states on this high level
come across as more aware of their own66 and, frequently, other people’s
feelings67 and hence more deserving of readers’ interest and sympathy.68
When my students read Evelina, they find it challenging to imagine that
real-life eighteenth-century shopkeepers, when it came to their mindreading skills, were not inferior to ladies and gentlemen of leisure and that, if
anything, their subservient position would have made them more active
and perceptive mindreaders than those above them. I believe that I know
at least one reason why this is so difficult for them. Burney’s novel equates
capacity for complex embedment with linguistic capacity. To come across
as a sophisticated mindreader, her character must sound like one, but to
sound like one, the character has got to have had a particular kind of education: no education, no eloquence, no mindreading complexity.
One can imagine an alternative scenario in which readers would infer
a “low-born” character’s complex intentionality, based on their behavior
rather than on their words, but Burney does not let it happen. The closest
that her novel comes to this is when a tradesman manages to get a free
84
Chapter 2
ride out of a gentleman. But then the gentleman demonstrates such tact
in responding to this unappealing ploy that the tradesman’s capacity for
complex embedment is left, once more, in the dust.69
To put a sharper point on what Burney is doing here, let us revisit studies that establish the association between lower social standing and more
active and perceptive mindreading. To quote from a recent review of those
studies,
A growing body of behavioural and self-report evidence suggests that people who
are lower in social standing may be more socially attuned than those of higher
social class. Lower social class is associated with greater activation in brain areas
involved in understanding the mental states of other people. Working class people may devote more cognitive resources to processing social information and
they may encode such information more deeply. Lower social class among college
students was correlated with greater activation of the mirror neuron system. . . .
Taken together these studies provide strong support for the notion that working
class people are more socially attuned and that such attunement may be fairly
automatic and visceral.70
Moreover, these effects have been observed across cultures, that is, in Russia and China, as well as in the United States.71 This strongly implies that
the situation was not that different in eighteenth-century England and
that eighteenth-century English tradesmen did not, in fact, lag as hopelessly behind in their mindreading capacities as Burney is at such pains to
demonstrate.72
How does one explain Burney’s drastic reversal of this real-life mindreading dynamic? We may speculate that it reflected the Burney family’s nervousness about their own social standing, for, unlike many other members
of their social circle, they had to work for living. Granted, the work was
intellectual and not manual, but, still, their survival depended on it.
We may also chalk it up to the young writer’s willingness to rely on
the conventional association between landed property and “social personality.”73 At least in this particular regard, Burney was perhaps not yet the
Burney of her subsequent novels, who, as Margaret Doody puts it, would
“examine” and “attack” rather than merely reflect “her society in its structure, functions, and beliefs,” especially those pertaining to “social class.”74
Instead, Evelina soothed the nervousness of Burney’s genteel readers about
the incipient porousness of eighteenth-century class boundaries by inverting real-life mindreading dynamics and portraying tradesmen as stunted
in their capacity for complex motivation and thus harmlessly amusing to
their betters.
Mindreading and Social Status
85
2.9 Shakespeare’s “Problem Play”
How far back does the association of mindreading acumen with superior
social standing go into English literary history? For, inaccurate as this association may be when it comes to real-life communication, it nevertheless
took hold in the eighteenth-century popular imagination, informing certain genres of polite literature, such as sentimental plays and novels.
To reconstruct the genealogy of this association, one may turn to Restoration comedy, in which aristocratic wits, such as Dorimant from George
Etherege’s The Man of Mode (1676), embed mental states on the fourth and
even fifth level, while their mistresses and hangers-on can barely keep up
with them.75 Granted, for many a Horner—the upper-class plotter from William Wycherley’s A Country Wife (1675)—there is a Lucy: the clever servant,
who steps in at a critical juncture to save her “betters” from catastrophe. Still,
after the 1670s, aristocratic high embedders became a recognizable literary
type, paving the way for the letter-writing sophisticates of Richardson and
Burney. Restoration plays obviously came with their own political agendas—
one of which was to please a series of royal patrons and their friends (who
would consider themselves the greatest wits of them all)—which demonstrates yet another way in which ideology can drive the inverse-correlation
model in fiction.
Going yet further back, one finds a ruler high on the sociocognitive
spectrum in Shakespeare’s Measure for Measure (1604). Shakespeare’s men
in power are not generally known for mindreading perspicacity, yet Duke
Vincentio seems to derive a peculiar personal satisfaction from reading and
scripting the complex emotions of his subjects. Thus, he wants Isabella to
think that Angelo beheaded her brother, Claudio—even though Claudio is
alive—so that, later, when she least expects it, he can reveal to her the true
state of affairs and turn her despair into “heavenly comfort”:
Isabella [Within]. Peace ho, be here!
Duke. The tongue of Isabel. She’s come to know
If yet her brother’s pardon be come hither:
But I will keep her ignorant of her good,
To make her heavenly comforts of despair,
When it is least expected.76
The Duke knows that Isabella will be devastated when she hears of her
brother’s execution. He also knows that she will be happy beyond measure
86
Chapter 2
when she learns that he is alive—happier, presumably, than she would have
been had she not first believed that he is dead (fourth-level embedment).
This is to say that the Duke is angling to put himself in a god-like position
in which he will have complete access to Isabella’s feelings both now and
later (i.e., when the truth is revealed). His mindreading hunger is tinged
with sadism, even as he wishes to bring Isabella’s happiness to the highest pitch (a literary mindreading dynamic that I dub, elsewhere, “sadistic
benefaction”).77
Measure for Measure is considered one of Shakespeare’s “problem plays.”
As Steve Vineberg puts it, “the long final scene can strike an audience as
sadistic. . . . And when the Duke proposes marriage to Isabella, after all
he’s put her through, you may wonder what Shakespeare could have been
thinking of.” Directors deal with this problem differently. Some play up
the Duke’s emotional cruelty, showing that Isabella can’t catch a break in
the patriarchal society of Shakespeare’s Vienna; others explain the Duke’s
behavior by his desire to see if Isabella is capable of generosity—of “moving
beyond her own injuries to act on another’s behalf”78—as when she kneels
before the Duke to ask for Angelo’s life while still believing that Angelo
has killed her brother. However charitable toward the Duke, this reading
still can’t explain away his stated intention to plunge Isabella to the lowest
depths of despair in order to render her subsequent joy more intense. He
may claim that he does it for her own good, but he gets out of it an intoxicating fantasy of complete access to her feelings.
What I find striking about the ethical problem that the Duke’s behavior
presents is that it seems to be mainly our problem, rooted in our own particularly historically situated sensibility. Shakespeare himself may not have
viewed the Duke’s actions as objectionable. The reason I say this is that I
can’t discern even a hint of punishment meted out to this “sadistic benefactor.” The Duke remains beloved by his subjects, and as the play ends, he is
on the brink of being rewarded with a marriage to a much younger, beautiful, and virtuous woman. To paraphrase Hamlet, this is hire and salary, not
acknowledgment of a problem.
So let us put aside our “ethical” response for a moment. Let’s remember instead that real-life rulers stink at mindreading and that Shakespeare
didn’t need the research of contemporary cognitive psychology to know
this, and neither did his audience.79 This means that, for them, equating
mindreading prowess with higher social standing may have had a different
Mindreading and Social Status
87
political meaning altogether. The space of the play allowed Shakespeare
and his contemporaries to fantasize about their social betters who would
care about their underlings’ feelings so deeply that they would spend their
time figuring out ways of getting inside their heads and scripting their emotions. For, as sadistic as this endeavor strikes us today, an early-modern
subject might have actually been flattered by the thought of it and wonder
if they might not have deserved more political attention from their rulers
than they had been getting.
Is this the only possible reading of the Duke’s unexpected sociocognitive
complexity? Of course not. I don’t aim to supply such a reading. Instead I
want to stress that this complexity is unexpected—and must have been so
for early seventeenth-century audiences—and that, more often than not,
the association between the capacity for high-level embedment and high
social status has specific political underpinnings.
Observe how using insights from contemporary cognitive science (such as
the association of better mindreading skills with lower social status) can help
us historicize our emotional response to a fictional character, a response that
would otherwise seem obvious (as in, “The Duke is sadistic! Poor Isabella!
What could Shakespeare have been thinking of?”) and thus be ahistorical. A
cognitive approach to literature, in other words, comes into its own when it
combines insights from cognitive science with sensitivity to specific historical contexts (a paradigm known as “cognitive historicism”).80 My next set of
examples comes from the time during which history trod with a particularly
heavy step and when the punishment for not aligning the story’s sociocognitive complexity just so could lead to the author’s death.
2.10 In the Gulag’s Vestibule
When, under oppressive political regimes, literary (and cinematic) production becomes explicitly regulated, mindreading sophistication acquires
new ideological meaning. Thus, in fiction published in the Soviet Union
under the aegis of socialist realism, characters of lower social status would
sometimes be portrayed as less sociocognitively complex than characters of
higher social status. That is, they do not engage in high-level mindreading
when confronted with the machinations of high-status characters.
This may seem like an unambiguous example of the second model, but
it is not. Although technically speaking, these low-embedding characters,
88
Chapter 2
such as unskilled factory workers, indigent peasants, and orphaned vagrant
children, occupy the lowest rung of a socioeconomic ladder, they are not
at all the “pipsqueaks” of yesteryear. Instead they are the new aristocracy—
aristocracy of the spirit, as it were—even if they are never referred to this
way. The future belongs to them. Due to their currently disenfranchised
status, they are ultimately guaranteed privileged access to educational,
political, economic, and reproductive resources. In contrast, various “old
specialists” (“spetsy” in the half-respectful/half-contemptuous jargon of
the 1920s–1930s), who have managed to parlay their education under the
tsarist regime into lucrative high-status jobs under the Soviets, are doomed
to irrelevancy and extinction. It is those well-heeled characters, as well as
their repulsive young protégés, who cheat our low-status protagonists of
their rightful share of socialist paradise, but not for long, never for too long.
For instance, Sania Grigoriev, the protagonist of a widely beloved novel
by Veniamin Kaverin, Two Captains (1938–1945), is shown to be almost
completely without guile, and so are his friends and his girlfriend/wife. It
is his arch-adversary, a stockbroker under the old regime and school principal / distinguished scholar under the new, N. A. Tatarinov, and Tatarinov’s
favorite disciple, Romаshov, who engage in complex mindreading aimed at
destroying the hero. When, at the end of the book, Sania, a former-vagrantchild-turned-arctic-pilot, gains the upper hand, it is because of his determination, courage, and good luck and not because he has more cunning than his
enemies do. In 1948–1956, Kaverin re-created this mindreading dynamic in
another popular (and also repeatedly televised) novel, The Open Book, whose
upright protagonist, a poor-scullery-maid-turned-famous-microbiologist,
ultimately triumphs over her plotting adversaries. Their old-school Machiavellianism is no match for her talent and “open-book” personality.
Call it the first model with a twist. What we have here is our familiar correlation between lower social standing and high-level mindreading skills,
except that low-status characters (i.e., the doomed bourgeois elements)
may initially come across as high-status characters, while the downtrodden
workers, peasants, and vagrants may take some time to reveal themselves
as the new aristocracy. And this proletarian aristocracy presumably does
not need to excel in mindreading, since the Revolution of 1917 has already
stacked the socioeconomic odds in their favor.
Besides, the enemies of this proletarian aristocracy may not be that great
at mindreading either. In Haiyan Lee’s study of the fate of detective fiction
Mindreading and Social Status
89
in the People’s Republic of China, she provides an important insight into
a particular historically specific form that the literary association between
high social status and low mindreading skills can take under the watchful
eye of the Communist Party. As she explains,
After the founding of the People’s Republic in 1949, [the hitherto thriving] detective fiction was labeled a bourgeois conceit and suppressed. The new society was
to be organized as a political communitas in which all were brothers and sisters
under the benevolent paternal care of the Communist Party. Everyone had a designated place in society and everyone was a known quantity. Who would have
any need for mindreading in such a seen-through society? . . . The only genre fiction permitted to flourish in the socialist period was the spy thriller. Crucially, the
mind-game that sustained this genre was directed against “the class enemy,” both
internal and external. Still, enemy agents were not permitted to truly shine sociocognitively. Rather, they schemed and plotted at a low cognitive level, making
laughably naïve assumptions and rudimentary blunders. And it took minimum
twists and turns to ensnare them in the vast net of the people’s justice.81
So while the proletariat had no need to “shine sociocognitively,” their enemies were “not permitted” to do that. Did that result in decades of official
literary production, in the Soviet Union and the People’s Republic of China,
with generally lowered levels of mindreading complexity, while works featuring truly sociocognitively complex characters had to find outlets elsewhere: abroad or in the underground/samizdat?82 And did that mean that
the sociocognitive complexity of narrators, implied readers, and implied
authors had to be dialed down as well?
One factor that seems to bear out this conjecture is the suppression, in
Soviet fiction, of the style of writing that we now describe as unreliable narration. Ilya Ehrenburg’s Julio Jurenito (1922), Yuri Olesha’s Envy (1927), and
Konstantin Vaginov’s Works and Days of Svistonov (1929) still featured unreliable narrators,83 but once socialist realism became the dominant paradigm
in the early 1930s, such stylistic experimentation was put paid to.84 Thus,
Vsevolod Ivanov’s U (1932) was not published in the Soviet Union until
1988, while Leonid Dobychin’s brilliant The Town of N (1935) was singled
out for castigation during the 1936 campaign “against formalism and naturalism,” driving its author to suicide. With the latter novel’s move away
from character-based embedment to embedment emerging almost exclusively from a give-and-take between the implied author and implied reader,
it engaged in an experimentation with literary subjectivity that must have
come across as politically subversive. Indeed, as one critic observes, it is
90
Chapter 2
“something of a mystery how the book was published at all at the height
of Stalinism, when dogmatic conservatism, to say nothing of philistinism,
ruled the art establishment.”85
2.11 Socialist Realism: Turning Back the Clock
on Complex Embedment in Literature
It is easy for us today to dismiss bona fide socialist realist literature as crude
propaganda and a psychological “wasteland.”86 Yet, if we adapt the cognitivist perspective—that is, if we consider socialist realism as a culture-wide
attempt to regulate people’s mindreading practices—it emerges as a fascinating phenomenon, both politically and literary-historically.
What does it mean, for instance, that the Soviet literary scene could not
abide the forms of complex embedment associated with unreliable narration? On the one hand, this seems to exemplify the regime’s intolerance for
experimentation associated with the modernist aesthetics. (After all, unreliable narration in literature is thought to be a mark of modernist sensibility.)
Indeed, the socialist realist condemnation of “decadence” in poetry and art
paralleled the crusade against “degenerate art” in Nazi Germany,87 which
implies that both communist and fascist ideologues experienced modernist
experimentation with subjectivity as politically threatening.
On the other hand, the relationship between experimental aesthetics
and political subversiveness is far from straightforward.88 There are enough
instances of brilliant avant-garde writing and filmmaking (think Mayakovski and Eisenstein) serving ideological agendas of totalitarianism and
thus increasing the affective appeal of such agendas. Indeed, as the cultural
theorist Sabina Hake has shown, film directors at DEFA (i.e., the main state
film studio of the German Democratic Republic, formed in 1946 under the
auspices of Stalinism and dissolved in 1992, after the reunification of Germany) used innovative techniques of modernism to maintain the attractiveness of various foundational myths of the GDR, such as the equation of
socialism with antifascism. As Hake explains,
Just as Georg Lukács’s pronouncements on the nineteenth-century realist novel
as the model for critical realism was used in the 1950s formalism debates to dismiss all modernist experimentation as decadent, the canonization of modernism
in the West as inherently resistant has distracted from the affirmative functions
of formal innovation. Concretely, in the case of DEFA cinema this means that
Mindreading and Social Status
91
an uncritical reliance on the realism-modernism opposition has allowed us to
equate filmic experimentation with political dissent. Just as the ideological effects
produced by the antifascist classics in the socialist realist mode were never as
uncontested as their detractors claimed, the turn to art-cinema traditions never
implied automatic opposition to the ideological and institutional structures that
relied on antifascism as its founding myth. On the contrary, modernist strategies
and techniques often helped to liberate the affective core of antifascism from the
ossifications of cinematic illusionism and to redeem the utopia of socialism in
aesthetic terms.89
This means that if we want to understand why works of literature that foregrounded embedded intentions of implied readers and implied authors
(e.g., those featuring unreliable narrators) did not fare well with socialist
realist censors, we cannot simply say that such experiments with fictional
subjectivity nurtured critical thinking and thus implied political dissent.
While this may be true to a significant extent90 (more about this in the next
section), we may also look for a more immediate explanation, one rooted in
the principles of socialist realism. What we find there, surprisingly or not,
is a certain contempt for cognitive processes of the “proletarian” audiences,
signaled by the effective return to what Hans Günther calls “the preliterate tradition” and constituting an intriguing experiment with patterns of
embedment in modern literature.91
Socialist realist writers were expected to “educate” their readers and
indoctrinate them in the ideological precepts of the Party. These goals,
however, “could be realized only under the conditions of accessibility (comprehensibility) of literature and art for the popular readers and viewers,
under the conditions of conformance to their taste.”92 This led, in practice,
to the reclamation of the sensibilities of epic, with larger-than-life heroes
engaged in monumental labor: harnessing the power of the machine to
transform both the unyielding natural world and the unruly collective.
Officially, socialist realist tradition was supposed to be following in the
footsteps of the nineteenth-century greats, such as Pushkin and Tolstoy.
But, in reality, as Günther points out, “[Insofar as] the nineteenth century
distinguished itself by the predominance of a critical and analytical beginning, now images were needed that reflected the optimism of the official
Stalinist culture, and these images were primarily sought in the preliterate
tradition—myth, folklore, heroic epics, and the like. Paradoxically, a society
with an officially declared orientation toward the future, in which the art of
the avant-garde left indelible marks and that widely used modern means of
92
Chapter 2
communication in propaganda, directs its gaze toward the remote past, the
result of which was a quaint folklorization of modernity.”93
Myth, as Günther observes elsewhere, thus emerged as “the soul of proletarian art.”94 What is important here, for our present purposes, is that myth,
folklore, and heroic epics do not depend on continuous complex embedment of mental states to the same striking degree to which, say, a novel by
Pushkin or Tolstoy does. While we certainly find third-level embedments of
mental states in myths and fairy tales, as well as in epics, such as The Epic of
Gilgamesh and The Odyssey, they are relatively rare there—in fact, incomparably so, if we juxtapose these texts with (for instance) eleventh-century Japanese, eighteenth-century Chinese, or nineteenth-century Russian novels.
This is why fiction produced under the aegis of socialist realism is so
fascinating from the cognitive literary perspective. Many of its early flagship works, from Fedor Gladkov’s Cement (1925) and Nicholai Ostrovski’s
How the Steel Was Tempered (1936) in Russia to Eduard Claudius’s People at
Our Side (1951) in East Germany, feature third-level embedments of mental
states rarely, staying mainly on the first and second level. Yet, even with
these novels’ epic (so to speak) unconcern about embedded subjectivity,
they can still be affectively engaging. What their presence on the literary
scene demonstrates is that fiction did not have to go the route of the hypertrophied embedment and that it was not inevitable that the novel would
become as dependent on continuous complex embedment of mental states
as it is at the present point in our literary history.
Socialist realist novels, especially in 1920s–1930s Russia and in 1950s
GDR,95 thus represent an important and useful exception to my “rule” that
literature, as we know it today, cannot function on a lower-than-third level
of embedment. True, their popularity had been enabled by the powerful
state apparatus (and, when that apparatus disappeared, they have been
forgotten), but, then, many a canonical work of literature depends for its
survival on a system of institutional supports. In any case, they were liked
well enough by several generations of readers (to which I can attest, having
encountered some of them as an adolescent), even when consumed alongside nineteenth-century novels featuring vastly more sophisticated embedment of mental states.
At the same time, it is politically significant that the project of “educating” the proletariat was thus realized by texts with drastically lowered
levels of embedment. Think again of Ralph Ellison’s decision to match
Mindreading and Social Status
93
Henry James’s “superconscious, ‘super subtle fry,’ characters who embodied
in their own cultured, upper-class way the American virtue of conscience
and consciousness.”96 To endow his Invisible Man with “intellectual depth”
and “a consciousness in which serious philosophical questions could be
raised,” Ellison depicted him continuously embedding mental states on a
high level.97 In contrast, when adepts of socialist realism “conformed” to
their readers’ taste, they revealed themselves as thinking about those readers as not amenable to contemplating complex subjectivity.
One is reminded here of Burney’s construction of working- and middlingclass characters, in Evelina (1778), as lagging hopelessly behind their social
“betters” in the business of mindreading, a construction driven by ideology
rather than by real-life mindreading dynamics. Ironically, the socialist realist aesthetics went further and transcended the boundaries of fiction: in a
state aspiring to be “a total work of art,”98 neither characters nor their readers
were “permitted to shine sociocognitively.”99
Let us take a closer look at the so-called production novel (i.e., a novel set
in an industrial collective) exemplifying these aesthetics. Fedor Gladkov’s
Cement (Цемент, 1925) tells a story of a Red Army soldier, Gleb Chumalov, returning home after the Civil War of 1918–1921 and struggling to
restart the production of cement at an abandoned factory. Written in the
early 1920s, Cement went through numerous revisions, which resulted in
the drastic paring down of its characters’ emotional range. (Indeed, the currently available English translation, published by Northwestern University
Press in 1960, seems to be based on one of the earlier drafts and thus may
not give the reader an accurate impression of what the novel had become
in its last draft, the one most familiar to its Russian audiences.)
Here is an excerpt from the final version of Cement, coming from the
chapter featuring one of the novel’s most intense conversations about the
characters’ feelings. Gleb wants to hear about the trials that his wife, Dasha,
went through at the hands of their class enemies while he was away, the
trials that have made her love the Revolution more than she loves her husband (all ellipses are in the original):
Gleb lay his head on Dasha’s knees and saw, above himself, her face, her cheeks,
covered with soft down colored by the fiery sky, and her eyes: intent, large, worried, and loving.
“Here, under this sky, one feels a different person, my little Dasha. Here I am,
laying in your knees . . . When has it been like that? It seems that I have never
94
Chapter 2
experienced anything like it. I only know that your love was larger and bigger
than mine, and I am not worthy of you. I haven’t lived through even one hundredth of what you have lived. So tell me yourself about your trials . . . Perhaps
then I will get to know myself better.
The air was suddenly lit up by the lightning: big and small stars of light
swarmed everywhere. Gleb was swept up by the wave of rapture; excited, he
propped himself up on his elbow.
“Dasha, my little dove, look . . . It’s so good to struggle and build one’s destiny! For, all this—is ours . . . Us! . . . Our power and labor . . . I feel like I am
inhaling . . . the way one inhales before the first strike . . . when one wants to
swing from high . . .
Dasha again put her hands on his chest. She, too, was excited, and Gleb could
hear the heavy muffled pounding of her heart.
“Yes, darling, it is good to struggle for your destiny. Let the sufferings come,
let the death come . . . It is scary . . . and not everyone can bear it . . . I had borne
it, because my love for you is stronger than fear . . . And then I understood something else, and loved something else . . . perhaps even more than I love you . . .
“Speak up, my little Dasha . . . whatever it is—speak . . . I have now learned
not just to listen but also to struggle with myself . . .”100
The characters’ emotions may be larger than life, reaching, as it were,
to the stars. The frequent ellipses, too, are meant to signal the grandeur
of their feelings, for they seem to experience so much more than they are
capable of expressing verbally.101 (No smooth talkers they—none of that
long-winded aristocratic palaver one encounters in old novels!) Yet one
struggles to find embedments rising above the second level—an experience extremely unusual when it comes to critical interaction with a novel.
Gleb knows that Dasha loves him. Gleb feels unworthy of Dasha. Gleb knows
that his happiness is bound up with the industrial collective. Gleb feels that
Dasha is excited too. He hopes that he can control his feelings as he listens to
her story. Dasha wants him to know that she loves the Revolution more than
she loves him.
The last two are perhaps the most unambiguous examples of thirdlevel embedment in this high-wrought chapter, entitled, fittingly, “Inner
Interlayers.”102 The depth of emotions explored here (however smacking
of agitprop) is rather unique for Cement, which tends to report a character’s
response to a specific challenge and then, immediately, to move on. For
instance, captured by the enemies, a woman experiences the arm of the
man who is dragging her to her execution as “monstrous”; when she is
spared the execution and left alone, she feels “blind terror”; when she
Mindreading and Social Status
95
subsequently runs into her comrades, she “laughs and cries.”103 This actionreaction rhythm of narrative is unrelenting, which means that there are
almost no complex embedments on the level of chapters and very few on
the level of paragraphs.
Note the difference between this novel and Evgeny Zamyatin’s We, discussed in chapter 1 of this book. We was written at exactly the same time as
Cement but first published abroad: in New York, in 1924. Standing pointedly
outside the ideological project of “educating” its audiences by talking to
them on their (presumably, benighted) level, We constantly embeds mental
states of characters and implied readers, even while it makes a point of not
mentioning emotions. In contrast, Cement, true to its peculiar educational
mission, refers to emotions frequently yet eschews complex embedment,
and it certainly does not engage mental states of the implied reader/author.
Here is another “production novel,” Eduard Claudius’s People at Our Side
(Menschen an unserer Seite, 1951), “an exemplary work of early socialist realism” from the GDR. (There, writers, too, “were expected to write in a way
that was popular (volkstümlich) [and] accessible.”).104 The novel’s protagonist, a bricklayer named Hans Aehre, is “a forceful person who must persuade his brigade of doubters that they are capable of working collectively
on the [ring] furnace without shutting it down, which would cost the factory six months’ lost production.”105 In between his bouts of heroic labor,
Hans must come to terms with his wife’s desire to be seen as “a whole
human being” and not just “a woman and a wife.”106 This leads to conversations similar to those Gleb was having with his Dasha, in which Hans learns
to listen to his wife and rein in his conservative masculinity.
For most of the novel, however, just as in Cement, complex embedments
are few and far between. Here, for instance, is Hans’s passionate enunciation of his new role at the factory: “Yes, we are workers, Comrade Backhans. We are workers. Even if an engineer or a foreman or the contractor
is present—it’s we who build the furnace, we! And if there is no foreman
who wants to help us or no engineer, well then, we’ll build it anyway . . . of
course we will . . . it must be possible for us to do it by ourselves.”107
Take a good look at this remarkable speech. One would think, given
the history of complex embedment in literature, that it would be impossible for a modern author to escape the gravitational pull of complex intentionality. This is to say that plenty of experimenting authors, from Alain
Robbe-Grillet in Jealousy and Muriel Spark in The Ballad of Peckham Rye to
96
Chapter 2
Zamyatin in We and Cormac McCarthy in Blood Meridian, make a point of
not mentioning mental states explicitly, but their narratives still depend on
their readers constantly supplying implied mental states to make sense of
what is going on. In contrast to those authors, Claudius comes very close
to constructing an actual mental-state-free paragraph and thus modeling a
new golden age in which word and deed are one and (to quote Hayian Lee
again) nobody has “any need for mindreading.”108
It is worth noting that the “production novel,” in and of itself, is by
no means antithetical to complex embedment. Already in 1963, the East
German writer Christa Wolf published They Divided the Sky [Der Geteilte
Himmel ], which takes place, in part, at a train-making factory. Its main protagonist, Rita, witnesses the dramatic endeavor of a “famous brigade” to
build “twelve windows per shift,” even though, a relatively short time ago,
the idea of building a train carriage with ten windows in one shift would
strike the workers as “crazy.”109 This industrial backdrop notwithstanding,
the novel’s complex embedments are off the charts, in typical Wolfian fashion, as we follow Rita’s continuous, sometimes oblique, self-introspection.110
Perhaps not surprisingly, in spite of the novel’s clear political allegiances
(for Rita, unlike her boyfriend, Manfred, is wholeheartedly committed
to the cause of socialism), They Divided the Sky was condemned by East
German reviewers as politically subversive. Still, it became an immediate
best-seller and was soon made into an equally controversial, and popular,
movie. Today it is typically featured on such lists as “100 German MustReads,”111 along with novels of such heavy hitters of complex embedment
as Musil, Mann, and Zweig.
This is why the socialist realist novel of the early, “exemplary” cut (e.g.,
Gladkov’s Cement, Claudius’s People at Our Side) can be viewed as a fascinating experiment with mindreading. Though relatively short-lived and now
largely forgotten, it did turn back the clock on complex embedment and
demonstrated the viability of neo-epic subjectivity in literature. What had
made this kind of experiment possible was a unique combination of factors: the strong political agenda supported by the punitive state; that state’s
apparent contempt for the cognitive processes of working-class readers; the
cultivation of a regressive dream about a golden age in which minds are
transparent; and ubiquitous exposure to well-established literary traditions
(exemplified by the novels of Tolstoy and Theodor Fontane etc.), which
Mindreading and Social Status
97
offered a very different vision of fictional subjectivity yet could, nevertheless, be claimed as precursors to the present one.
Doing full justice to the interplay of these factors is beyond the scope
of my argument. It remains an open question, for instance, if the ready
availability of the nineteenth-century classics had made the socialist realist
experimentation with shallow intentionality more or less compelling or
if the intensified censorship trained at least some readers to look for hidden meaning and thus added an unexpected level of implied mindreading
to those texts. What I want to emphasize, with this case study, as well as
with the preceding ones (i.e., those from English and Chinese literary traditions), is that cognition and ideology are bound with each other in a variety
of historically specific forms, most of which have never been acknowledged
or explored by cultural historians.
In this chapter, I have focused on one particular way of bringing together
cognition and history, namely, on the possibility that patterns of complex
embedment in a work of literature may be correlated with the relative
social status of its characters and readers. In recent years, literary scholars have advanced other, different, models of cognitive historicism.112 Yet,
on the whole, we have barely scratched the surface. The field of cognitive
approaches to literature remains wide open to researchers willing to explore
the proposition that a cognitive literary inquiry is, fundamentally, a historical inquiry.
3
“Deep” History: Evolutionary and Neurocognitive
Foundations of Complex Embedment
3.1 Thinking on Three Historical Levels at Once
What does it mean to think of complex embedment of mental states as an
essential feature of literature, as we know it today?1 It means thinking on
three historical levels at the same time: being aware of the “deep” history of
our species, of the more immediate cultural history, and of literary history.
The “deep” history concerns the evolutionary and neurocognitive foundations of complex embedment. Somewhat paradoxically, this perspective
may be the least rooted of all, because much of it depends on ongoing
research in the cognitive neuroscience of mindreading. To look back at that
history means, in effect, to look forward and to be ready to modify one’s
thinking when more and/or different information becomes available.2
The midlevel perspective is also not quite what literary scholars are used
to when they think of cultural history. While it does not ignore such familiar factors as the role of the means of textual reproduction and changes
in the size and type of the reading public, its main foci are mindreading
histories of specific communities, or the local “ideologies of mind.” To
become aware of those ideologies, I draw on research of anthropologists
and ethnographers who study similarities and differences between the cultural practice of “thinking about others’ internal states and/or talking about
them.”3 As the anthropologist Webb Keane observes, while “theory of mind
and intention-seeking are common to all humans,” they are “elaborated in
some communities [and] suppressed in others.”4 The history of the representation of mental states in literature is profoundly implicated with cultural institutions that “elaborate” or “suppress” mindreading.
Finally, literary history is concerned with the evolution of patterns of
complex embedment in literature, as well as with the migration of such
100
Chapter 3
patterns across different genres, national literary traditions, and individual
texts.
Any given complex embedment of mental states in literature thus relies
simultaneously on the workings of our evolved cognitive architecture, on a
culture-specific “ideology of mind” (which implicitly regulates the public
and print discussion of other people’s mental states), and on the immediate
literary ecology of a particular text.
I can easily imagine how one may focus on one or two of those factors
at the expense of other(s). In fact, the structure of this book may encourage
this kind of thinking, because, for the purpose of my argument, I consider
them in turn—first, the deep-historical (i.e., cognitive), then, the historical,
and, finally, the literary—separately. So it is important that we keep in mind
that none of those factors can be reduced to others or considered sufficient
on their own. For instance, our evolved capacity for complex embedment,
alone, does not determine the appearance of fictional texts that would ratchet
up the frequency of such embedments; neither does a cultural milieu that
encourages public speculation about one’s own and others’ inner states;
and neither does the presence of a long-standing literary tradition steeped
in complex embedment.5 The “secret life” of literature is sustained by the
interplay of all three.
3.2 Makeshift Metaphors Revisited
“Theory of mind,” “mindreading,” and “embedment” are useful metaphors
for evoking mental functioning involved in daily social interactions. Their
utility, however, becomes overshadowed by their clumsiness and inadequacy when we try to understand how the underlying cognitive processes
actually work. Take, for instance, the implications conveyed by these terms,
that we experience mental states in a propositional, disembodied format (as
in, “I know that she doesn’t know that I know”) and that we are, mostly,
aware of our mentalizing.
In reality, this is hardly the case. Mindreading may be said to exist on
several different levels. While there is, indeed, “the level of conscious reflection about the mind, what we might call explicit theories of theory of mind,”
the majority of our daily mindreading “happens largely outside conscious
reflection and probably conscious control,” and it is both grounded in the
body and highly context sensitive.6
“Deep” History
101
Cognitive scientists are quite aware of how incomplete and misleading the “propositional” view of theory of mind is. For instance, when the
social anthropologist Rita Astuti introduces the concept of mindreading,
she illustrates it with the following set of images: “[When] you see someone running, you don’t just see a physical body in acceleration—you see
the intention or the desire to catch the bus or win a medal; when you see a
hand reaching for an object, you don’t just see a trajectory through space—
you see the goal of getting that object.”7
This is mindreading at its most prevalent: rooted in the body and happening outside of conscious reflection. Similarly, the linguistic anthropologist Alessandro Duranti reminds us that mindreading “does not proceed as
a series of self-conscious propositions, as in, I believe that X intends to do
Y.” Instead, it depends on the embodied, intuitive, prerational understanding of another’s actions.8
The cognitive anthropologist Pascal Boyer, too, stresses the automaticity,
speed, and multimodality of mindreading, as well as the fact that we can’t
help attributing mental states, whether correctly or not, when he defines it
as “a whole suite of specialized systems [that] automatically picks up social
information—other people’s behaviors, gestures, utterances, but also their
facial expressions, choice of words, and so forth—to construct, without any
conscious effort, a representation of their beliefs, intentions, and emotional
states, all things that cannot be observed and must be inferred.”9
Slowing down this process, bringing it to conscious awareness, and putting it in words inevitably transforms this experience. The transformation
may be enriching, for instance, by forcing us to develop new ways of representing inner states in our discourse.10 Yet it may also be radically impoverishing, for instance, by stripping mindreading of its contexts and sensory
nuances and by misrepresenting it as a linear process. Writers themselves
know that linearity distorts our experience of the social environment. As
Christa Wolf puts it, “[The] age-old fact that things occur and are felt and
are thought simultaneously but that all those things cannot be put down
simultaneously on paper in linear writing suddenly rattles me so much that
doubt in the realism of my writing grows into a total inability to write.”11
I can thus understand the position of some of my colleagues in literary studies who are turned off by “theory of mind” and “mindreading”
because they object—and rightly so!—to the implications of the conscious,
accurate, disembodied, linear, and context-free processes that these terms
102
Chapter 3
convey. Sadly, however, their quests for alternative accounts of social cognition may thus be driven by putting too much stock in those flawed
metaphors instead of paying attention to the actual phenomenon of mindreading studied by psychologists, anthropologists, and ethnographers.
“Embedment” is another one of those problematic metaphors (though
perhaps not as fraught as theory of mind or mindreading). You will notice, as
I proceed with this chapter, that, in different fields of cognitive science, the
capacity for embedding mental states goes by different names. Those include
“recursive embedment,” “perspective embedment,” “recursive intentionsreading,” “nesting,” “level-two perspective taking,” “second-order theory of
mind,” “second-order false-belief understanding,” “levels of intentionality,”
“multiple-order intentionality,” and so forth. The images of layers, levels,
hierarchies, and thought bubbles recursively nested within each other, which
such descriptors evoke, are not likely to reflect any actual patterns in the
mind/brain. What they are more likely to reflect, instead, is a long cultural
history of visualization of abstract concepts,12 now pressed into the service
of rendering instantly intelligible and familiar complicated processes that we
are only beginning to understand.
Is there a way to talk about mentalizing without relying on the language
of representationality? Here is a perspective from developmental psychology, offered by Mark Sabbagh and Dare Baldwin:
What does a nonrepresentational understanding of intention “look like”? Perhaps the most vivid demonstration of an early appreciation of intention comes
from children’s understanding of goal-oriented action. Gergley and colleagues
(1995) found that even 12-month-old infants were willing to attribute goals to
shapes that showed signs of being animate (i.e. capable of self-propelled motion).
Along these same lines, Woodward (1998) has demonstrated that young infants
construe the actions of humans as goal-directed, though they do not apply the
same construal to the motions of inanimate objects. Still more convincingly,
Meltzoff (1995) found that 18-month-olds reenacted events that correspond with
an actor’s likely goals and intentions, even when those actions are not explicitly
modeled. Across these studies and others (e.g. Carpenter, Akhtar, and Tomasello,
1998), very young infants demonstrate an impressive level of sensitivity to the
fact that others’ actions are motivated by internal mental states. However, these
young infants would fail even the simplest tasks designed to tap a representational understanding of mental states, such as the false belief task (Wellman et al.,
2001). Thus, 18-month-olds clearly understand behavior in a distinctly mentalistic manner, but it is probably a mistake to ascribe a concomitant representational
appreciation to these same children at such an early age.13
“Deep” History
103
Thus developmental psychologists. Philosophers of mind, too, have grappled with the issue of moving beyond representation. For instance, Mark
Johnson speaks of “nonrepresentational theory of mind, where having or
entertaining a concept is merely running a neural simulation in which sensory, motor, and affective areas of the brain are activated, not as representations mediating between an inner and outer world, but rather as the very
understanding of the concept. In other words, the neural activations involved
in the simulations within a specific context just are what is to grasp the
meaning of the concept in question.”14
One can even speculate (by way of taking this insight to its logical
extreme) that propositionally expressed representations of mental states
play no role at all in reading literature. Perhaps, when we read, we grasp the
density and depth of intersubjective situations that define the experience of
literary fiction,15 and it is only when we try to slow down and describe that
experience that we resort to the familiar cultural metaphors of tiers, orders,
levels, and embedded mental states.
This view is in broad agreement with that of the cognitive psychologists Hugo Mercier and Dan Sperber, who point out that the procedures
involved in unconscious inference are not identical or even similar to those
involved in conscious reasoning, and they do not operate on “statements
or statement-like representations.” The concept of representation, in this
view, is understood strictly in terms of its function:
Representations . . . are material things, such as activation of groups of neurons
in a brain, magnetic patterns in an electronic storage medium, or ink patterns
on a piece of paper. They can be inside an organism or in its environment. What
makes such a material thing a representation is not its location, its shape, or its
structure; it is its function. A representation has the function of providing an
organism . . . with information about some state of affairs. The information provided may be about actual or about desirable states of affairs, that is, about facts
or about goals.16
Is it possible or even desirable to avoid the language of representationality, specifically, when talking about complex fictional subjectivity?17 I am
not sure that our gains would outweigh our losses if we were to make a
concerted effort to do so, in the name of hypothetical cognitive purism.
For keep in mind that writers, too, are faced with this challenge when they
try to convey in words deep intersubjective experiences of their characters.
They, too, rely on outright descriptions of embedded mental states—albeit
104
Chapter 3
some of them to a greater and some to a lesser degree—to bring to life their
intuitive visions of intricate social consciousness. To insist that critics must
find a way to describe this phenomenon without talking about embedded
intentionality—because such representations distort what may be really
going on in the brain!—would be similar to insisting that writers must find
a way not to talk about it either, for the same reason.
Some writers indeed rely more on implied mental states than they do
on explicitly spelled-out mental states, but that alone does not make their
writing better or more literary. For instance, as I argued in chapter 1, the
difference between literary and popular fiction does not map onto the difference between implied and explicitly spelled-out mental states. Instead,
literary fiction is often characterized by the two following features (to a
much greater extent, that is, than is popular fiction): first, it embeds mental
states of narrators, implied authors, and readers in addition to mental states
of characters; and, second, it tends to imply mental states in addition to and
sometimes in place of explicitly spelling them out.
Thus, perhaps a more realistic way to approach the problem of representationality in cognitive criticism is to say that we should strive to retain the
view of the multidimensional, multisensory, embodied, and not-yet-wellunderstood phenomenon of “embedded mindreading” even if we must
continue to rely on the terms, currently in wide use, that streamline, decontextualize, and disembody it.18 So as I go on with my argument, try keeping in mind the perennial gap between the actual cognitive processes (all
moving targets, as far as researchers are concerned) and the makeshift, farfrom-perfect metaphors that make it possible to talk about those processes.
3.3 Perspectives from Social, Developmental, Clinical, and Evolutionary
Psychology and Cognitive Neuroscience
One good starting point for a conversation about embedded mental states
is research on the “default network,” which looks at the nexus of interacting brain regions involved, among other things, in “inward contemplation and self-assessment”19 and “conceiving the perspectives of others.”20
What we learn from this research is that, when we engage in a complex
social interaction with other people, attributing mental states to them
(however unselfconsciously) necessitates attributing mental states to ourselves: “understanding complex social interactions among people who are
“Deep” History
105
presumed to be social, interactive, and emotive always involves the processing of self-reflective thoughts and judgments.”21
Handling communicative intentions is thus “a more complex process
than simply thinking about intentions, since we have to recognize that
the communicator is also thinking about our mental state. This involves
a second-order representation of mental state. We have to represent the
communicator’s representation of our mental state.”22 Depending on the
context of the situation, this may translate into a second level of embedment (as in, “she obviously doesn’t know that I know!”) or even a higher
one, third or fourth (as in, “I wish I had known before that she didn’t know
that I knew!”). Again, here I am putting it in a propositional format—because
I have no way of conveying it to you otherwise!—but during actual social
interactions, we do not think propositionally (for one, we don’t have time for
it, except in some special cases).
How involved can such social imagining get? As it turns out, there may be
limits to the levels of embedment. The cognitive evolutionary psychologist
Robin Dunbar and his colleagues have demonstrated that “fifth-order intentionality” (fifth-level embedment of mental states) represents “a real upper
limit for most people,” that is, the level after which their understanding of
the situation drops drastically.23 At the same time, there also “is considerable
inter-individual variation in the highest achievable levels of intentionality.”
Those individual differences correlate with such factors as “the ability to correctly attribute blame” and the number of contacts in one’s support clique,
that is, the number of individuals on whose advice and/or help one would
depend at times of great social or financial trouble.”24
For a quick illustration of how the “upper limit” on levels of embedment manifests itself, when next time, at a party, you find yourself chatting
with four other guests, see how long it takes before your group separates
into two relatively independent conversational units consisting of two and
three people. Presumably it won’t be too long, because keeping track of five
mental states including your own—which may reach a maximum level of
embedment pretty fast—is a cognitive burden. Left to our own devices (as
opposed, for instance, to being committed to a more rigid social situation
such as a five-person discussion panel at a conference), we intuitively try to
lessen than burden by modifying the social context that created it.25
I emphasize the word “intuitively” because we would not be aware of
either carrying any burden or trying to lighten it. It may just so happen
106
Chapter 3
that I “spontaneously” discover that what a person next to me is saying is
really quite engrossing—or that she is the only one whose voice I can hear
over the party’s din—so I end up focusing all my attention on a conversation with her, while the three others continue on their own. Negotiating
a mindreading overload—what mindreading overload? As the clinical psychologist Philipp Kanske and his colleagues put it, the “ease with which we
accomplish [the mindreading] task every day, readily makes us forget the
complex computations and processes it entails.”26
How early does it start? That is, at what age do we begin to attribute
embedded mental states to ourselves and others? Until relatively recently,
developmental psychologists thought that children begin to appreciate
people’s false beliefs—that is, realize that people may believe something
that is not in fact the case—around the age of four.27 Then, between five
and seven, children become attuned to “doubly embedded” representations; that is, they become aware “not just that people have beliefs (and
false beliefs) about the world but that they also have beliefs about the
content of others’ minds (i.e., about others’ beliefs), and similarly, these
too may be different or wrong.” This awareness is “fundamental to children’s . . . understanding of the epistemic concepts of evidence, inference,
and truth,”28 although there are important cultural differences in whether
children are encouraged or discouraged to talk openly about their own and
other people’s mental states.29
In experiments involving kindergarteners and first graders writing letters to hypothetical friends who have never experienced some of the things
familiar to the authors of the letters (such as, for instance, snow, mentioned
in a letter to someone who has never seen snow), the “recursive understanding of embedded mental states” was shown to be implicated with
children’s growing awareness of a reader’s knowledge as distinct from that
of the writer’s. Around seven years of age, children realize that “an effective writer represents how their reader will interpret their textual meaning
(authorial intention) in light of that reader’s experience.”30
The traditional view that before the age of four children are not ready to
attribute false beliefs to others was challenged in 2005 in a study by Kristine
Onishi and Renée Baillargeon, who showed that fifteen-month-old infants
may already understand false beliefs. Since then, numerous other experiments have pushed the age for such understanding even lower.31 While
different theories have been proposed to account for this “puzzle of theory
“Deep” History
107
of mind” in infants,32 for the purposes of my argument, I go with the view
that “the infant mindreading system develops gradually, transforming into
the adult one through incremental learning and piecemeal conceptual
change.”33 The changes that take place around the ages of four, five, and
seven may still represent important milestones in theory-of-mind development (especially, as we have seen, in the nuances of perspective taking), but
they can now be viewed as steps in a continuous integrated process rather
than dramatic breakthroughs.
Embedded mindreading assumes new prominence as children enter
adolescence. In 1970 (even before the term “theory of mind” entered the
lexicon of cognitive scientists),34 Patricia H. Miller and her colleagues concluded their essay “Thinking about People Thinking about People Thinking
about . . . : A Study of Social Cognitive Development” with the following
rueful observation: “often to their pain, adolescents are much more gifted”
at “wondering what he thinks of me” and “what he thinks I think of him”
than “first graders are.”35 The drama and intensity of alliance building and
sexual maturation are inseparable from the reading and, inevitably, misreading of one’s own and others’ embedded intentions.
When it comes to the cognitive neuroscience of embedment, in 2003,
Rebecca Saxe and Nancy Kanwisher published an article, “People Thinking about Thinking People,” which showed, for the first time, that there
is a particular region of the temporo-parietal junction of the brain that is
“involved specifically in reasoning about the contents of another person’s
mind.”36 There was an increased response in that region when subjects read
stories that involved figuring out people’s thoughts and feelings, as opposed
to stories with no social reasoning. Since then, other studies have addressed
questions ranging from whether the same brain region supports thinking
about people’s “appearance, social background, or personality traits” (it
seems that it doesn’t)37 to what neural populations may underwrite the
“representations underlying human emotion inference.”38
To give you an idea about the setup of Saxe and Kanwisher’s study, here
are two of the stories that the subjects of their experiments were exposed
to. The first depicts a woman wanting to get to her office and encountering a construction zone: “Jane is walking to work this morning through a
very industrial area. In one place the crane is taking up the whole sidewalk.
To get to her building, she has to take a detour.” There is some intentionality, yes, but no rich social content and no increased activation in the
108
Chapter 3
brain regions under study, as opposed to the subjects’ response to the other
story: “A boy is making a paper mache project for his art class. He spends
hours ripping newspaper into even strips. Then he goes out to buy flour. His
mother comes home and throws all the newspaper strips away.”39
If I put in propositional format my own response to the latter vignette, I
can say that the mother didn’t know that the boy intended to do something
with the pile of torn newspapers and that the boy may realize that the
mother didn’t know that he intended to do something with that pile. I can
also think what may happen next, imagining that the mother would want
the boy to know that she hadn’t known that he intended to do that and, moreover, that she would want him to know how truly sorry she is.
In other words, both in the process of making sense of this situation
and thinking about it further, I recursively embed thoughts and feelings
within each other. I also explicitly verbalize it all for you, whereas were I to
encounter this vignette in the laboratory, with no time to think it through,
I would just process these embedments automatically, without being aware
of doing so.
It is not impossible that my personal response to this particular vignette
is impacted by my empathizing with its protagonists, for it is easy for me
to start thinking about my own school-age child, who would be very upset
were I to throw away his project-in-progress. This brings us to empathy, an
issue that I haven’t addressed at all so far and plan to continue not addressing, after this short interjection.
Whereas I am aware of the variety of fascinating studies of empathy
in conjunction with the reading of fiction, I do not work with empathy
myself and believe that, for the purposes of studying complex embedment
in literature, theory of mind and empathy should be considered separately.
Conflating the two would ignore research that points toward important differences between them, and, given how little we still know about cognitive
correlates of either, such conflation is not likely to be helpful.
Those of my readers who would like to learn more about these issues
may start with a series of recent studies by clinical psychologists and social
neuroscientists who looked at the behavioral and neurological markers
of theory of mind and empathy in subjects exposed to emotional videos.
What they found, in brief, is that “enhanced activation of the ToM [theory
of mind] related network was linked to better ToM performance, but not to
behavioral measures of empathy. This pattern was replicated when using
“Deep” History
109
composite scores of empathy and ToM performance derived from multiple tasks, which corroborates and generalizes the specificity of the brain–
behavior relations of the two social capacities.”40
So while I admire the work of my colleagues in cognitive literary studies,
such as Fritz Breithaupt, Suzanne Keen, and Ralph James Savarese,41 who
investigate empathy, I neither engage in such investigation myself nor presume to make any claims about the role of empathetic engagement in our
processing of complex embedments.
3.4 Distal and Proximate Causes of Complex Embedment in Literature
To sum up the different strains of research from cognitive psychology and
neuroscience, the capacity for embedment of complex mental states is integral to human mindreading. This capacity matures in development, may
present enough of a cognitive burden to have something resembling an
upper limit set to it, and is supported by specific brain regions.
The deep (that is, the cognitive) history of embedment highlights the
social aspect of our engagement with literature. While theory of mind
evolved, back in the Pleistocene, to track mental states involved in reallife social interactions, on some level, our mindreading adaptations do not
distinguish between mental states of real people and of imaginary entities
whom we “meet” on the page, on-screen, or on the canvas: as soon as we are
faced with behavior, we start attributing intentions to the behaving agents.42
That literature, in particular (as we know it now), seems to demand that
readers continuously process complex embedments of mental states leads one
to wonder what kind of real-life social challenges, persisting throughout our
evolutionary history, this demand on the readers’ cognition may be mimicking and exaggerating. Why should it feel good to follow the intricacies of
what one person (who doesn’t even exist) thinks about what another person
(who doesn’t exist either) knows about the first person’s intentions?
If you are interested in the broader version of this question—which is,
why we may actually enjoy various cognitive burdens that literature places
on our mindreading adaptations—I refer you to my earlier book Why We
Read Fiction: Theory of Mind and the Novel (2006). To focus more narrowly on
the appeal of complex embedments, here are some relevant reflections by
cognitive scientists, which provide useful ways of thinking about this issue
(yet should not be mistaken for conclusive explanations).
110
Chapter 3
The cognitive psychologist Daniel Nettle offers the following observation about the social rewards of situations in our evolutionary past in
which third-level embedments naturally occurred:
[The] natural situation in which we have three-way mind-reading going on is one
that might be rewarding for several reasons. First, if we know what person A is
thinking about person B but person B does not know this, then we are in a position
of privilege and power. Either person A had taken us into their confidence, which
would mean we were a valued coalition partner, or we are very clever, and/or we
now have some leverage over person B because we know something important that
they do not. If we feel well-disposed to B we may want to warn them, and gain their
gratitude and reciprocity; if we are ill-disposed to B we may wish to use it against
them or withhold it spitefully. In any event, this is a very significant situation in
which we, although a spectator, are now part of a social triangle. This would not be
so true if we knew what person A thought about B and B also knew this.43
A related explanation comes from the work of the cognitive anthropologist Pascal Boyer, who suggests that in-group cooperation, which was
absolutely crucial for the survival of our species, may have favored interest in complex mindreading. Developing “social relations and cooperation
among many individuals [allowed] for more efficient cooperation,” but
that also meant that it was important to discriminate between contexts in
which information about others’ intentions could be freely disseminated
and contexts in which it had to be concealed. As Boyer explains, to maintain “small-scale friendly networks, one needs access to individuals as such
and one needs a measure of discretion. Every item of information need not
and in many cases should not be broadcast too widely.”44 So keeping track
of who has access to whose mental state would be just as important as keeping track of who doesn’t and shouldn’t have that access.
Moreover, negotiating complex social situations depended on combining explicit discussions of one’s own and other people’s mental states with
implicit attributions of thoughts and feelings to oneself and others. Behavioral neuroscientists are finding today that “implicit and explicit mentalizing processes may be closely related in a healthy population,”45 which
means that when works of literature combine explicitly spelled-out and
implied mental states, they mimic and intensify patterns of mindreading
that recurred throughout our evolutionary history.
Finally, consider the positive biofeedback associated with the feeling
that the awareness of other people’s mental states is our own. As William
“Deep” History
111
James puts it, “We think; and as we think we feel our bodily selves as the
seat of the thinking. If the thinking be our thinking, it must be suffused
through all its parts with that peculiar warmth and intimacy that make it
come as ours.”46 Joining James’s insight with those of the neuroscientist
Antonio Damasio, the cognitive literary critic Nancy Easterlin suggests that
consciousness and self-consciousness—“not only the awareness that we
know but also the added awareness that the knowing is specifically one’s
own—[feel] good. And when knowledge feels good, [we] are apt to seek it
actively, to want as much of the thought and feeling of mastery as possible.”47 To the extent to which the processing of embedded mental states of
others involves awareness of one’s own mentalizing, the pleasure of social
inclusion is thus further augmented by this feeling of epistemic mastery.
When we turn to proximate causes, it seems that imaginary representations of third-level embedments model certain thorny types of social challenges that we face in our daily lives today. As such, they may feel particularly
attention worthy. It also doesn’t hurt that some fictional narratives present
us with cleaned-up versions of real-life mindreading problems. That is, in
many a work of fiction (though by no means in all!), I actually get to know
what a character X thinks about character Z, whereas in real life I have to
settle for my imperfect constructions of my own and other people’s mental states.48 Add to this a pleasure that I may feel as I discover new depths
of social perception in myself when I think I discern the (implied) author’s
intention regarding my access to a character’s feelings,49 a discernment that
builds on my previous experience with this genre, this author, or this specific
work.
Add, too, my happy awareness of myself as a member of a particular
community in which such discernment is valued. For instance, I may enjoy
realizing that Jane Austen doesn’t want us to know that her Emma is in love
with Mr. Knightley for as long as possible, perhaps even for as long as Emma
herself remains unaware of it. Yet had I been brought up in an environment
in which familiarity with Austen’s novels were considered a pointless affectation and then happened upon a copy of Emma, I may not have brought
to it the kind of attention that would allow me to intuitively appreciate
the intentions of its (implied) author. It wouldn’t have mattered to me
that Emma taps, in so many intricate ways, into the cognitive adaptations
for complex mindreading that may have formed back in the Pleistocene. I
112
Chapter 3
would have skipped and skimmed and missed most of its embedments and
not considered myself worse off for doing so.
This is to say that when we deal with complex cultural artifacts such
as literature, distal causes tend to be conjoined with proximate causes in
ways that make it impossible to disentangle the two or to treat one as more
important than the other. Specifically, when it comes to patterns of embedment in fiction, we can’t just trace them back to the social pressures of
the Pleistocene and ignore the immediate circumstances in which writing/
performing and reading/watching take place today.50 We can’t focus on the
“deep” history at the expense of cultural and literary histories.
4
Cultural History: Ideologies of Mind
The similarities and differences between these two practices—thinking about others’ internal states and/or talking about them—are often at the heart of culture.
—Bambi B. Schieffelin
4.1 The “Opacity of Mind” Model
“There is no doubt that humans in all known cultures learn to infer
intention . . . from the behavior of other humans,” writes the psychological anthropologist Tanya Luhrmann, “yet at the same time, ethnographers
observe that the inferences they draw are probably shaped not only by
developmental capacity but by cultural specificity.”1 Cultural variation of
mindreading practices, underwritten by local ideologies of mind, is not
something that literary historians tend to think about when they consider circumstances in which genres arise, develop, and change into other
genres. Yet, as I hope to demonstrate by the end of this chapter, this factor
is crucial to the production and reception of literature, especially literature
as awash in explicit and implied embedments of mental states as ours has
come to be.
To start thinking of our daily mindreading practices as reflecting a particular model of interiority, we first have to recognize the existence of other
models. Consider, for instance, what is known as the “opacity of mind”
model, “found in varying forms throughout the South Pacific and Melanesia.” Its most striking feature is a consistent and vocal “refusal to infer
what other people are thinking unless they verbalize their intentions.”2
This refusal underwrites a variety of daily practices, ranging from a taboo
against eye contact and a tendency to repeat verbatim others’ statements
114
Chapter 4
about their mental states, without questioning or elaborating them, to the
caretakers’ avoidance of verbally guessing at the “unclear meanings” of very
young children.3
Even just these three examples alert us to the possibility that some of our
familiar cultural rituals (such as looking people in the eye, publicly secondguessing others’ stated intentions, and interpreting toddlers’ babbling for
them) are locally specific ways to perform mindreading, indicative of a particular ideology of mind. Let us consider this possibility in some detail, by
first taking a closer look at the “opacity” model and then thinking through
its implications for our cultural and literary analysis.
4.2 Refusing to Talk about Others’ Mental States
When anthropologists and ethnographers had initially confronted what
they would come to call the opacity model, they wondered if it meant that,
in some Melanesian and Micronesian societies, for instance, among the
Bosavi (aka Kaluli), Korowai, Ku Waru, and Yap, “it is impossible or at least
extremely difficult to know what other people think or feel.”4 This prompted
a conversation about methods used for studying mindreading in concrete
cultural contexts. The distinction, formulated by Rita Astuti (see chapter 3)
between the “conscious reflection about the mind” and the mindreading
that happens “outside conscious reflection and probably conscious control”
is directly relevant here. For, as she points out, “ethnographic methods are
of course well suited to record the former, while experimental methods are
best suited to tap into the latter.”5 This means that ethnographers, used to
ways in which some forms of “conscious reflection about the mind” are
performed in their own communities, should be careful not to substitute
their informants’ assertions “of how the world should be” for a description
of what they may actually “find in the world.”6 Thus, if we focus on the
mindreading that happens outside conscious reflection and control, we discover that, while Bosavi, Korowai, and others may avoid public references
to other people’s minds, they may actually be “more attentive to [their]
intentions as a result.”7
For instance, struck by such a recurrent feature of the opacity model
as the taboo against direct eye contact, an ethnographer may assume that
Bosavi do not pay attention to each other’s facial expressions. She will thus
miss the fact that Bosavi keep their foreheads clear of hair or head dresses,
Cultural History
115
letting others “read” their emotions off their foreheads.8 Similarly, as the
ethnomusicologist Steven Feld explains, while Bosavi may not explicitly
impute thoughts to others, “there is an impeccable and ubiquitous attendance to what others feel, and that is coded at every linguistic level, but
particularly marked by lexical items, emphatics, prosody, and a range of
gestural, stance, facial expressive, and other paralinguistic markers coordinated with everyday speech.”9
Keep in mind, too, a variety of forms that a particular feature associated
with the opacity model may take in different communities. For instance,
the same injunction against looking “directly into another’s eyes” (because
that may lead to “inferring privately held intention”)10 manifests itself differently in Yap (Micronesia) than it does in Bosavi. Here is how the ethnographer C. Jason Throop describes it:
[One] of the first notes I took when arriving in Yap concerned what I held to
be a striking lack of eye contact when individuals spoke to one another and a
marked tendency for speakers to turn their bodies and heads away from their
interlocutors. In fact, it was not uncommon to observe individuals carry on
complete conversations with their backs to each other, gazing off in opposite
directions. Likewise, during community meetings individuals often sat with their
backs against the beams supporting the community house facing out away from
the meeting, gazing at the horizon, the dance ground, or other parts of the village
center. One conversation I noted early on during my second stay in Yap in the
summer of 2001, well before I had acquired the communicative competence necessary to follow along with an ongoing, multi-party conversation, included six
individuals speaking for over an hour, none of which were facing one another.11
As in Bosavi, so in Yap there is a telling tension between publicly performed and private mindreading. On the one hand, Yap practice what
Throop describes as a series of “communicative strategies used to conceal
one’s thoughts from others.” On the other hand, the very fact of using these
strategies implies that they intuitively expect that others will attempt to read
their words and body language as indicative of underlying thoughts and
feelings. Private preoccupation with what people know or don’t know about
each other’s mental states drives the public attempt to prevent mindreading:
By talking in opposites, being elusive, facing meta-pragmatic restrictions on turntaking and questioning, only providing the absolutely minimal amount of information necessary, being sarcastic, playing jokes, teasing, avoiding eye contact, or
situating one’s body such that one’s voice is muted and one’s facial expressions
are concealed from the view of others, individuals are thus able to insure that
116
Chapter 4
their interlocutors are never able to garner a clear idea as to what they are really
thinking or feeling. A significant benefit to engendering such communicative
opacity, one elder noted to me, is that by putting one’s interlocutors off guard
and off balance, and by making them uncertain as to one’s true feelings and
motives, an individual is granted an advantage inasmuch as the speaker is the
only one who truly knows what his or her plans are, which could perhaps be
importantly used to his or her advantage at some later date.12
The gap between publicly following the rules of etiquette associated with
the opacity model and the private preoccupation with others’ mental states
can assume a more obvious form, that is, that of the difference between a
public and a private conversation. For instance, on the island of Vanatinai
(Papua New Guinea), “Islanders publicly, rhetorically deny the possibility
of empathy, of imaginative understanding of and identification with the
thoughts/feelings of another being. In private, within a current, constantly
fluctuating group of trusted confidants—spouses, lovers, siblings, matrilineal kin—they conjecture at length, in exacting detail, based upon a range
of external cues, about what others are thinking and feeling . . . and how
this may affect their interactions with others in the recent past, present, or
future.”13 This avid conjecturing about others’ thinking—conducted with
trusted confidants but not in public—reminds us that the opacity model is
not an all-or-nothing phenomenon.14 A community as a whole may adhere
to principles of opacity, but those principles don’t have to govern every
single aspect of social interaction.
4.3 Not Interpreting Infants’ Babbling
Another important feature of the opacity model is the refusal, on the part
of caregivers, to interpret infants’ babbling as expressive of intentions. To
put this point into sharper perspective, compare some parenting practices
in North America and in Kaluli. North American parents may model their
children’s articulation of mental states by doing it for them early in development, as in, “Aren’t you hungry!” or “It must feel very frustrating not to be
able to reach that ball!” According to the linguistic anthropologists Elinor
Ochs and Bambi Schieffelin, particularly, “In the white middle class developmental story, [assisting the child to clarify and express ideas] is associated
with good mothering. The mother responds to her child’s incompetence
by making greater efforts than normal to clarify his or her intentions.”15 In
Cultural History
117
contrast, when “talking to young children, Kaluli caregivers do not propose
possible internal states of their addressees.” Thus, when “a child whines or
acts inappropriately, caregivers ask, ‘Ge oba?!’ ‘what’s with you?!’ If a child
doesn’t eat, they pose a rhetorical question, ‘Ge mo:nano?!’ ‘you don’t
eat?!’ rather than, ‘are you hungry?’”
Along the same lines, in Kaluli, when young siblings “do put a referential gloss to the babbles of an infant, [older] caregivers repeat the sounds”
but do not use a verb form “which would imply that something meaningful
was produced in such vocalizations. Thus through this type of modeling
and verb choice, small children are gently socialized to use culturally appropriate ways to verbally report what they hear without attributing meaning,
including what constitutes reportable speech and what does not.”16
This does not mean that Kaluli children are not “encouraged to verbalize their own desires and intentions.” They are. It does mean, however, that “they are explicitly socialized,” first, not to “verbally guess at or
express others’ unvoiced intentions and unclear meanings” and, second,
not to feel compelled to explain their own motivations when they don’t
want to.17 This prepares them for functioning in a society in which, while
“almost everything else could be known about a person, people [resist]
being coerced into giving moral accounts or making explicit what they
were thinking about.”18
Furthermore (again, in contrast to some North American parents), Kaluli
parents use
no baby-talk lexicon as such, and claim that children must hear . . . ‘hard [i.e.,
real] language’ if they are to learn to speak correctly. . . . Kaluli recognize babbling
but say that this vocal activity is not communicative and has no relationship
to the language that will eventually emerge. Adults . . . will occasionally repeat
vocalizations back to toddlers (aged 12–16 months), reshaping them into the
names of people in the household or into kin terms of people nearby, but they
do not claim that the toddler is saying these names or wait for the child to repeat
these vocalizations in an altered form.
The absence of baby-talk lexicon does not result in an impoverished verbal environment. As Schieffelin reports, “although there is relatively little
speech directed to preverbal children, the verbal environment of these children is rich and varied, and from the beginning infants are surrounded
by adults and older children who spend a great deal of time talking to
each other . . . [and hearing] their actions . . . referred to, described, and
118
Chapter 4
commented upon by members of the household, especially older children,
speaking to one another.”19
Moreover, Kaluli “mothers and infants do not gaze into each other’s
eyes, an interactional pattern that is consistent with adult patterns of not
gazing when talking to others.” Instead,
Within a week or so after a child is born, Kaluli mothers act in ways that seem
intended to involve infants . . . in dialogues and conversations with others. Rather
than facing their babies and engaging in dialogues with them in ways many
English-speaking mothers would, Kaluli mothers tend to face their babies outward
so that they can be seen by and see others who are part of the social group. Older
children greet and address infants, and in response to this mothers hold their
infants face outward and, while moving them, speak in a special high-pitched,
nasalized register (similar to that Kaluli use when speaking to dogs). These infants
look as if they are talking to someone while their mothers speak for them.20
By speaking “for” their infants, mothers socialize them into a community
in which expressing their own feelings as well as reporting others’ feelings
verbatim are acceptable practices while interpreting others’ feelings is not.
As Schieffelin puts it,
[While] Kaluli obviously interpret and assess one another’s observable behaviors
and internal states, these interpretations are not culturally acceptable as topics
of talk. Individuals talk about their own feelings (“I’m afraid”; “I feel sorry”), but
there is a cultural dispreference for talking about or making claims about what
another might think, and what another might feel, or another is about to do,
especially if there is no obvious behavioral evidence. Kaluli, however, use extensive direct reported speech, and children use this linguistic resource by 24 months
of age. . . . [These] culturally constructed behaviors have several important consequences for the ways in which Kaluli verbally interact with children, and are
related to other pervasive patterns of language and social interaction.21
4.4 Opacity on a Continuum
Compelling as the concept of opacity seems to be, it is important to remember that we have on our hands yet another case of far-from-perfect terminology. The term “opacity of mind” may seem to imply a sharp break between
cultures that are wholly governed by that model and cultures that are not.
In reality, both types of cultures function on “a not-very-rigid continuum”
of opacity.22 This means, among other things, that features strongly associated with the opacity model in one culture may be present in another, and
Cultural History
119
yet that other culture may gravitate, as a whole, toward the transparency
end of the spectrum.23
Sometimes such features would be indicative of specific challenges faced
by members of the community under particular circumstances. Consider,
for instance, that since Bosavi live in close physical proximity to each other,
the inside of a person’s head is often the only private space available to
them. The pragmatics of protecting that space from others are expressed
through specific features of verbal etiquette and contribute to the maintenance of psychological well-being.24 In Bosavi, these features of verbal
etiquette are integrated with the ethos of opacity. Yet as the psycholinguist
Catherine Caldwell-Harris and her colleagues observe, we find similar features geared toward “allowing people their psychological privacy” in other
communities whose members live “in close quarters” but that are not necessarily viewed as conforming to the opacity model.25
Or consider the long history of US racism engendering a behavior on the
part of oppressed minorities that has features of the opacity model, within
what we may broadly characterize as the overall North American model,
which tends toward transparency. For instance, take the African American
practices of “signifyin.” As Aaron Ngozi Oforlea explains, signifyin can function as a mindreading strategy aimed at protecting the self by misleading,
misdirecting, and outwitting “well meaning acquaintances and powerful
adversaries.” Thus, he writes, “Zora Neal Hurston describes her way of disguising her mental state to protect her ‘business’ or personal experiences
from white researchers who often visit her to collect folklore. Aware of the
interloper’s intentions, Hurston strategically decides which information to
share or withhold. [She] writes: [‘The] white man is always trying to know
into somebody else’s business. All right, I’ll set something outside the door of
my mind for him to play with and handle. I’ll put this play toy in his hand,
and he will seize it and go away. Then I’ll say my say and sing my song.’”26
When occurring specifically in the context of interaction between the
oppressor and the oppressed, signifyin may also reflect the status dynamic
discussed in chapter 2, which is that people in stronger social positions
don’t read minds as actively and perceptively as do people in weaker social
positions. This may make the former good targets for signifyin, because
they are easily satisfied with the “toys” (i.e., token insights into the minds
of the oppressed), set outside for them “to play with and handle.” As a protective and defensive measure, opacity can thus be a marker of inequality,
120
Chapter 4
social stress, and communal adversity. This is quite different from the role
it plays in (for instance) highly egalitarian Bosavi, where it is supposed to
contribute to social cohesion.
Here is another example of a particular feature of the opacity model present in a society that does not subscribe to that model. We have already seen
that one aspect of Bosavi socialization is the refusal, on the part of caretakers, to expand on their young children’s utterances (which would necessitate imputing mental states to them). We encounter the same refusal in
Samoa (also already discussed in chapter 2), but there it is driven not by the
opacity model but by rigid social stratification. In Samoa, people of higher
social standing are not supposed to be guessing what people below them in
the social hierarchy mean when they express themselves less than clearly. If
the meaning is unclear, “the burden of clarification” is always on the lowstatus person. As very young children are the lowest-ranking members of
their household, people around them do not attempt to read their minds
(which would mean lowering themselves to their level).
Here is how Ochs and Schieffelin, working, respectively, with Samoan
and Bosavi populations, describe this dynamic: “[Neither] the Kaluli [aka
Bosavi nor] the Samoan caregivers . . . appear to rely on expansions, but
the reasons expansions are dispreferred differ. The Samoans do not do so in
part because of their dispreference for guessing and in part because of their
expectation that the burden of intelligibility rests with the child (the lower
status party) rather than with more mature members of the society. Kaluli
do not use expansions to resay or guess what a child may be expressing
because they say that ‘one cannot know what someone else thinks,’ regardless of age or social status.”27
“One cannot know what someone else thinks” is a key tenet of the opacity doctrine. “It is not one’s business to figure out an underling’s meaning” can be, as it were, a key tenet of a rigidly stratified society. That two
very different ideologies of mind can lead to pretty much exactly the same
observable behavior is something to be aware of as we (i.e., students of
literature) begin to test the usefulness of the “opacity of mind” concept for
our cultural and literary analysis.
4.5 Opacity and Ethics
We have focused, so far, on the psychology and epistemology of the opacity model, but another productive way of approaching it is to think of its
Cultural History
121
ethics. For, as the anthropologist Webb Keane explains, the taboo on attributing intentions to others often reflects the local notion of personal integrity and inviolability, according to which the loss of ability to keep one’s
feelings hidden is considered shameful:
It is not that inner thoughts are inherently unknowable but that they ought to be
unspeakable, or at least, it matters greatly who gets to speak these thoughts. . . . [Thus
it] is not the case that [the Melanesians] have no capacity to read minds or invent
fictions: rather, these capacities serve ethical thought, leading to emphatic denial
of something that they are in fact doing. . . . To reiterate, if Theory of Mind and
intention-seeking are common to all humans, how these get played down or
emphasized can contribute to quite divergent ethical worlds. Elaborated in some
communities, suppressed in others, these cognitive capacities appear as both sources
of difficulties in their own right and affordances for ethical work.28
What happens if we apply these insights—prompted, originally, by the
studies of cultures subscribing to the opacity model—to more familiar cultural settings? The reason that I find this idea appealing is that it offers a
new perspective on a whole array of social practices that we take for granted.
For we do not, usually, go around thinking about how this or that cultural
institution (including literature!) “elaborates” or “suppresses” mindreading.
Yet, once you adapt this perspective, you realize that mindreading does not
take place in a vacuum. Instead, it is shaped by culture-specific ideologies
of mind that have both epistemological and ethical dimensions. This is to
say that it is shaped, first, by people’s beliefs about whether their own and
others’ “inner thoughts” are knowable and, second, by their assumptions
about “who gets to speak those thoughts.” To quote Schieffelin again, the
“similarities and differences between these two practices—thinking about
others’ internal states and/or talking about them—are often at the heart of
culture.”29 What do we learn about our culture by inquiring into our own
practices of talking and thinking about others’ mental states?
4.6 Direct Eye Contact and Ideologies of Mind
She saw something in that image that she hadn’t noticed in person. In the photo,
his eyes shifted away from the camera. Eventually London had understood that
look as one she could not trust.
—Johka Al Harthi, Celestial Bodies
Let us revisit the injunction against direct eye contact among Yap and
Bosavi. First of all, the psychological intuition that underlies this injunction
122
Chapter 4
is the same intuition that, in many Western cultures, makes eye contact a
socially desirable behavior. For, just as we believe, to quote Cicero, that
eyes are “the mirror of the soul,” so do, it seems, the Yap. To quote Throop
again, “It is interesting to note the extent to which the face, and particularly the eyes (laen mit, laen awochean) are held, in local configurations of
subjectivity and social action, to represent that part of the person that is
most susceptible to directly evidencing inner feeling states and thoughts.”30
In cultures subscribing to the opacity model, infants and young children have to be taught not to look people in the eyes. Bosavi “mothers do
not engage in sustained gazing at, or elicit and maintain direct eye contact with, their infants as such behavior is dispreferred and associated with
witchcraft.”31 As to Yap, Throop suggests that the etymology of the Yap
word “child” (tiir) is tied to the expression “is eyes,” and as such, it reflects
the fact that it doesn’t come naturally to children not to betray their feelings by their gaze: “Children simply look at what they desire; they show
no concern for hiding their intentions, emotions, needs, and cravings from
others. They have thus yet to cultivate self-governance and have yet to
learn to manage their emotions in such a way that there is less of a direct
link between their inner feeling states and their expressivity.”32
Now think about the tendency of Western caretakers to look into their
infants’ eyes and to encourage reciprocal gazing. We may experience this
as a default child-rearing behavior (indeed, associate it with good parenting!) and do not think of it as indicative of some special “transparency
of mind” model. Yet, put in the comparativist perspective, this behavior
does indicate a certain ideology of mind, one that gravitates, on the whole,
toward the transparency side of the spectrum. Were we to explicitly formulate this ideology—which may come out sounding awkward and artificial
precisely because we have internalized it—we might say that one can know
what someone else thinks and that making one’s inner thoughts available
to others and attempting to penetrate their inner thoughts are generally
experienced as prosocial behaviors.
(Thinking of transparency as prosocial may seem to contradict our tendency to value “privacy”—unless one recognizes that the concept of privacy may cover a spectrum of practices. For instance, in contrast to Bosavi,
for whom unavoidable physical proximity makes them eager to protect
the privacy of their minds, Western cultures may put more emphasis on
Cultural History
123
physical—which may be relatively easy to achieve, as when one is alone in
a room—than on mental privacy.)
To see how the unspoken ideology of knowable minds undergirds our daily
social interactions, think of how we respond to politicians, doctors, salespeople, or even next-door neighbors when they seem to avoid eye contact.
Instead of experiencing them as virtuously protecting their own and our personal integrity and inviolability—as we might, were we to operate under the
auspices of the opacity of mind model—we perceive them as “shifty-eyed”
and thus untrustworthy (or, perhaps more charitably, as painfully shy).
In fact, there seems to be a gap between the broad range of our reactions to direct eye contact—which are not always positive!—and the cultural ideology that codes such contact as mostly good. This is to say that
even in societies associated with the transparency model, direct eye-gazing
can provoke mixed emotional responses. While it can be experienced positively—as signaling motivation to approach or romantic interest—it can
also be taken as indicating “hostility and impending peril.”33 Still, this variety of actual reactions notwithstanding, the dominant expectation seems
to be, and has been for some time, that people who look at us directly are
“more caring, trustworthy, harmonic, inclusive and respectable” than are
those who avert their gaze.34
Accordingly, consider Western parents’ discomfort when their children
refuse to make eye contact. A popular website that offers “11 Reasons a
Child Cannot Look You in the Eyes” may acknowledge that the dispreference for eye contact may be the result of “cultural differences,”35 yet the
majority of the listed reasons still reflect the belief that all is not well when
a child cannot meet your gaze. The child may be suffering from “social
anxiety” or “low self-esteem” or may be “lying about something.”36 (Ironically, in some cultures of opacity, it is direct eye contact that indicates an
intention to deceive.)37
Generally, it does not take very long for the ideology of knowable minds
to turn ugly. What is felt as the right to read other minds “can run in tandem
with a need for mastery over others that has been the cause of great suffering over the . . . long course of our history.”38 As the cognitive narratologist
Porter Abbott reminds us, what in the context of the European colonial
project was presented as “the heroic quest to penetrate the unknown can
be hard to separate from the desire to appropriate and tame—in effect to
124
Chapter 4
spread knowability.” But this “illusion of knowability” is built “on preexisting terms,” that is, those legible to the colonizer. As Abbott puts it, “when
one is sent into a land where one not only does not know the language of
the people but [also] cannot read their faces, the effect goes deep.” The shattered “illusion of knowability” augments “the fusion of fear and fury that
grip a soldier fighting in a strange land.”39
On a different note, recall the notorious practice of diagnosing autistics
as “mind-blind” (that is, “lacking” in theory of mind) because they fail
to perform such a culturally sanctioned way of mindreading as focusing
on their interlocutors’ eyes.40 In a critique of this practice, the cognitive
neuroscientist Gregory Hickok reminds us that “behavior does not automatically reveal its cause and can be misleading.”41 For instance, the autistic
individual’s Fusiform Face Area could be hyperactive—as opposed to the
conventional view, implied by the “mind-blindness” hypothesis, according
to which it is hypoactive (i.e., inhibited): “Hyperresponse to social stimuli
can be explained in terms of the emotional intensity of the signal, which
triggers anxiety and avoidance responses. [This means that the person’s]
active avoidance of eye contact provides just as much evidence for [the
person’s increased] sensitivity for the information contained [in the eyes]
as does active engagement of eye contact.”42
Or, to quote Lucy Blackman, a nonspeaking autistic writer, “It may be
that the social deficits which are the cornerstone of an autism spectrum
diagnosis tell us far more about the person who made them markers for
such a diagnosis than about the child whom she observes. . . . That is, the
whole testing procedure is somehow actually constructed on whether the
tester observed the person to socialize in a way that the tester understood
to be socialization. . . . We often use the term ‘communication’ when really
we mean that we have observed in another human being a behavior from
which we derive meaning.”43
Because a Western culture may assign a very particular meaning to direct
eye contact, it takes a comparativist perspective to be reminded that it is a
culturally constructed behavior, associated with what we may call an “ideology of transparency,” or the idea that other minds are knowable and that,
under most circumstances, we have a right to know them. When we are
denied the valuable social knowledge that, we believe, can be obtained that
way—or, as it were, denied the right to that knowledge—we may feel a
range of negative emotions toward the person who seems to deny it to us.
Cultural History
125
Keeping in mind this cultural construction of direct eye contact as a sign
of prosocial behavior, imagine how different our art, movies, poetry, and
novels would be if reading assiduously “the language of the eyes” were considered inappropriate, antisocial, and dangerous: associated, for instance,
with the intent to harm by witchcraft (especially in societies in which suspected witches used to be killed, as in Bosavi and Korowai).44
Thus, when the protagonist of Samuel Richardson’s novel Clarissa (1747)
observes that she and her would-be seducer, Robert Lovelace, “are both great
watchers of each other’s eyes,” we make sense of her comment within the
context of a “transparency of mind” model largely governing Western representations.45 We know that Clarissa and Lovelace don’t trust each other
and hope to catch a glimpse of another’s true intentions during unguarded
moments; and we are also aware of erotic overtones of their behavior. But
such interpretations are a product of a particular ideology of mind. Were
we to read the same body language in the context of the “opacity of mind”
model, Lovelace’s and Clarissa’s deliberate eye watching might acquire different overtones, ranging from the socially uncouth to the physically dangerous.
Here, then, is one preliminary observation about fictional narratives.
When works of literature foreground the language of the eyes in their representation of characters’ mental states, they build on a particular aspect of
the mindreading adaptation that can be considered universal. For, both in
cultures of opacity and in cultures of transparency, “the face, and particularly the eyes” are considered a direct conduit to the person’s “inner feeling states and thoughts.”46 But it is reasonable to expect that, in cultures
of opacity, fictional situations featuring direct eye contact would often be
bundled up with contexts and expectations that are less indicative of prosocial behavior than they would be in cultures of transparency.47
4.7 From the “Monastic Theory of Mind” to the Academic One
If communities indeed elaborate some mindreading practices and suppress
others, we can view a variety of cultural institutions as implicated in this
project. For instance, a recent study, Paul Dilley’s Monasteries and the Care of
Souls in the Late Antique Christianity: Cognition and Discipline (2017), builds
on Luhrmann’s view of culture-specific models of mindreading to suggest
that “the training of thoughts practiced by early Christian monks led to the
gradual acquisition of a new and particularly monastic theory of mind.”
126
Chapter 4
Some of the key precepts of this monastic theory of mind were that the
mind was both permeable and accessible. This is to say that monks had
to learn that their cogitations arose “not only from the interior self, but
also through divine guidance or demonic temptation” and that “God was
aware of their private thoughts, which were also known to certain inspired
saints.”48
Learning these precepts demanded introspection, physical exercise, and
communal activities. Also, interestingly, monks were encouraged to read
hagiographies, which, Dilley argues, constituted a particularly instructive
and pleasurable training in mindreading.49 Hagiographies facilitated the
acquisition of “the monastic theory of mind, by offering a privileged perspective on the saints’ internal deliberations, including the use of clairvoyance and other revelations in their disciplinary decisions.”50
Where would the “monastic theory of mind” fall on the continuum
of opacity? It seems that, on the whole, it gravitated toward the transparency end of the spectrum. Other people’s minds were considered inherently knowable, and a particular virtue was attached to being able to figure
out the source of one’s own and other people’s thoughts (i.e., divine or
demonic). Moreover, one’s “secret thoughts” were not really secret, for God
was aware of them and so were the saints.51 This means that “thinking
about others’ internal states and/or talking about them” (Bambi Schieffelin)
was both a useful and an ethical thing to do.
If we remember that monasteries were “the centers of learning before
the rise of the universities”52 and that Sorbonne, Oxford, and Cambridge
continued to be theological schools “until the middle of the fourteenth
century,”53 it makes sense to think about the “academic theory of mind” as
influenced by the monastic one. We can consider, for instance, the role of
the dual belief that other people’s thoughts are knowable and that there is a
particular virtue associated with tracing the provenance of those thoughts
in the development of some academic disciplines; and we can also talk
about the gradual suppression of explicit mindreading as a prerequisite for
the emergence of others. I can’t hope to do full justice to this topic here (it
would require a separate book), but let us take a quick preliminary look at
some forms of mindreading associated with academic learning, in a culture
that edges toward the transparency end of the opacity spectrum.
Cultural History
127
4.8 Patterns of Mindreading in Conversations about Literature
One academic subject that is unthinkable today without mindreading is
literature. Talking about mental states of fictional characters is something
that secondary-school students begin to do quite early. By the time they
reach college, they are, at least in principle, primed for the kind of sophisticated mindreading that will be expected from them in literature courses.
To see how some of them rise to such expectations, consider works of
fiction that intuitively experiment with theory of mind by suppressing all
mentalizing references, explicit or implied. Take, for instance, Alain RobbeGrillet’s Jealousy (1957), which is notorious for its depiction of actions
drained of mental states. Here is a characteristic excerpt from the chapter
describing the banana plantation where the action takes place:
Prolonging this patch toward the bottom, with the same arrangement of rows,
another patch occupies the space included between the first patch and the little
stream that flows through the valley bottom. This second patch is twenty-three
trees deep, and only its more advanced vegetation distinguishes it from the preceding patch: the greater height of the trunks, the tangle of fronds, and the number of well-formed stems. Besides, some stems have already been cut. But the
empty place where the bole has been cut is then as easily discernible as the tree
itself would be with its tuft of wide, pale-green leaves, out of which comes the
thick curving stem bearing the fruit.
Furthermore, instead of being rectangular like the one above it, this patch
is trapezoidal; for the stream bank that constitutes its lower edge is not perpendicular to its two sides—running up the slope—which are parallel to each other.
The row on the right side has no more than thirteen banana trees instead of
twenty-three.
And finally, the lower edge of this patch is not straight, since the little stream
is not: a slight bulge narrows the patch toward the middle of its width. The central row, which should have eighteen trees if it were to be a true trapezoid, has,
in fact, only sixteen.
In the second row, starting from the far left, there would be twenty-two trees
(because of the alternate arrangement) in the case of a rectangular patch. There
would also be twenty-two for a patch that was precisely trapezoidal, the reduction
being scarcely noticeable at such a short distance from its base. And, in fact, there
are twenty-two trees there.
But the third row too has only twenty-two trees, instead of twenty-three
which the alternately-arranged rectangle would have. No additional difference is
introduced, at this level, by the bulge in the lower edge. The same is true for the
fourth row, which includes twenty-one boles, that is, one less than an even row
of the imaginary rectangle.54
128
Chapter 4
How does one respond to a work of literature that makes it this difficult
to read intentionality into it? It turns out that some readers may actually redouble their efforts to discern complex mental states in such texts.
Thus, according to David Richter, who teaches literature at CUNY, when
he assigns Jealousy to his undergraduates, “they read the repeated narrative
about the centipede that horrifies A and is killed by Franck as coming from
a jealously obsessive narrator noticing and recalling over and over Franck’s
responsiveness to A. They even read the chapter in which we are told about
how many banana trees are in each row in each segment of the plantation
as coming from a mind that was forcing itself to pay attention to objective
facts about his banana plantation in an attempt to stop himself from obsessively thinking about his wife A and her possible relation to Franck.”55
Think about what these students are doing. Broadly speaking, they are
“naturalizing” a difficult text, making it easier to comprehend.56 Yet the particular way in which they are achieving it—that is, by constructing complex
embedments of mental states—is a product of a specific culture. This culture
has institutional settings that reward people for speaking and writing about
intentionality. This means that they learn to approach texts marked as fiction with the expectation of mindreading, and of a particularly elaborate
kind at that, if they happen to encounter those texts in a literature course.
As a corollary to Richter’s experience, consider the history of critical readings of Herman Melville’s short story “Bartleby the Scrivener” (1853), whose
protagonist behaves in such a way that neither other characters in the story
nor its readers can attribute any mental states to him. But, as Porter Abbott
puts it, the “experience of unreadable fictional minds, meant as such, is
very hard to maintain.”57 So one strategy for responding to an “unreadable
character” is to interpret him as a “generic stereotype,” as in, Bartleby is
insane, and that explains his incomprehensible behavior. Another strategy
is to shift “the mode of reading” altogether and cease regarding Bartleby
as a human being (or a representation of a human being), whose mental
states can be inferred. Instead, he becomes a “catalyst” for understanding
other characters or an idea, a symbol, as in, “Bartleby is the ghost of social
conscience haunting the precincts of the ruling class.”58
Note that a symbolic reading also involves mindreading. For, when we
say that “Bartleby is the ghost of social conscience haunting the precincts
of the ruling class,” we still attribute a mental state—such as a vague feeling
of guilt—only now not to a specific person but to a more abstract entity
such as the “ruling class.”
Cultural History
129
As Abbott observes, the shift to the symbolic “allows meaning to rush
in” (read: opens up a whole new cluster of mental states), and this is “what
has happened almost invariably in the critical response to Bartleby.” Taken
as a human being, “and not as a symbol, Bartleby remains unreadable.” But
this state of affairs is “unendurable” for Melville’s audiences, so, “one way
or another, [they] will generally find some strategy to make it go away.”59
Yet another course of action for making the unendurable go away is
to use the difficult-to-read characters as catalysts for generating readers’
own complex mental states. Consider the experiment run by the cognitive literary critic Emily Troscianko, who studied readers’ response to a
short story by Franz Kafka, “Jackals and Arabs” (1917). “Kafka’s fictions,”
Troscianko explains, “never really give us privileged access to the workings of his protagonists’ minds.” Instead they confront us with characters “whose capacities for introspection . . . or capacities for insight into
other’s minds . . . are limited.” Troscianko found that her subjects were
“fascinated” by this “scarcity of insight” and that they compensated for it
by constructing embedments that involved their own embedded insights.
As one of them put it (emphasis added): “I find it intriguing, fascinating, to
be guided through the story without ever fully understanding what the narrator feels.”60
Thus, while Richter’s students made sense of Jealousy by force-reading
into it thoughts of its characters, and Abbott’s readers reached out to the
minds radically outside the story (e.g., the mind of the “ruling class”), Troscianko’s subjects responded to Kafka by imagining their own mental states.
Elsewhere, I have discussed a similar dynamic structuring our response to
paintings that actively prevent us from attributing mental states to anybody/anything within them.61 Finding ourselves in situations such as college courses or critical conversations, in which we are expected to talk about
such paintings, we begin to attribute mental states to their creators (by trying to figure out what the artist meant), or to ourselves (by explaining how
these paintings make us feel), or to some external entities (by treating the
work in question as a cultural symbol).
This is to say that while we may be “designed by nature,” as Abbott puts
it, to read mental states into behavior, we still need to be “trained by culture” in the locally appropriate ways to perform such readings.62 Thus, we
respond to cultural incentives to engage in mindreading—but also remain
sensitive to the disincentives—as we learn that intense mindreading is a
prerequisite of success in some academic disciplines but not in others.
130
Chapter 4
It is not surprising that the technique of close reading—or, as I argued
earlier, close mindreading—is closely related to the history of religious
exegesis and, most immediately, to the history of biblical textual criticism. Still, we can’t quite say that talking about the minds of fictional
characters, their authors, other critics, and our own in college literature
courses is the exclusive legacy of the monastic theory of mind. Traditions
of monastic mindreading may have shaped formal practices of Western
literary interpretation, but the tendency to talk about mental states when
discussing literature is not limited to communities influenced by Christian
monasticism.
To take a quick look at the forms that such conversations may take in the
absence of monastic influences, we turn to literary traditions of the Bosavi
and Ku Waru. We will use as our starting point Webb Keane’s observation
that, while cultures of opacity may suppress explicit intention-seeking in
their discourse, “it is not the case that [their members] have no capacity to
read minds or invent fictions,” and we will see what kind of mindreading is
encouraged by their “fictions.”
We start with the Bosavi. On the one hand, “prior to missionization,”
which began in the 1970s, there “were no equivalencies in . . . metalinguistic and metapragmatic repertoire for reporting the private thoughts or
internal states of others,”63 unless one repeated verbatim what the other
person had said about their feelings and used a source tag—an “evidential
marker”—to clearly indicate the original speaker.64 On the other hand, there
was one important exception: a linguistic context that allowed reporting
others’ hidden thoughts. That exception was the “traditional story genres
that recounted Bosavi origins, or the bawdy adventures or social dilemmas
of fictitious cultural heroes, schlemiels, and animals.”65 Such narratives
appeared to “mobilize different linguistic resources as part of the register of
the genre.” For instance, a “morpheme–mosoba [‘I wonder’], relatively rare
in spontaneous speech, was found more in stories” (as in, “o:no gasa a:no:
eno: ko:lo: go:mosoba?”; “that dog I wonder if it was his?”). In addition,
storytellers disclaimed “responsibility for the information” about the characters’ mental states, by reminding listeners that this was all “in the story.”66
Or consider the Ku Waru, who live to the east of Bosavi:
[While] in-principle assertions of the opacity doctrine are common [among the
Ku Waru], they are contradicted by other things that people do, including the
stories that they tell. For example, in a genre of sung tales of courtship that are
Cultural History
131
composed and performed in the region, at the point in the story when the lovers
first meet, there is often a passage such as this: “Right then he wanted to marry
her. / That’s what the man was thinking. / And she thought the same about him.
/ The minds of both, you see / Were working completely as one.” In other words,
given the lovers’ strong mutual attraction, it is possible for each of them to know
what is in the other’s mind because it is the same as what is in his or her own.67
Another important example of mindreading involved in literary
production—especially if we understand “literature” broadly and include
performative genres as well68—has to do with performers attributing mental states to their audiences and adjusting their behavior as they go along
to reflect their perception of those mental states. Consider Gisalo, a song
and dance ceremony practiced by the Kaluli, that is, the people of Bosavi.
(Note that, although I talk about it in the present tense, my discussion of
it refers to the period of the 1960s–1980s, for it is not clear if Gisalos still
take place today.) Gisalos are designed to evoke strong feelings of nostalgia,
sorrow, and loneliness in their audiences by integrating into their sung narratives references to specific locations that have profound personal meaning for the listeners. A Gisalo is considered successful if listeners weep and
try to hurt (i.e., burn) performers in a ritualistic way, to make them pay,
as it were, for having thus gotten under their skin.69 As Edward Schieffelin
explains, “The listeners’ feelings and reactions are not merely a response
to the performance; they are integral to its structure and significance. The
dancing and singing by the performers and the weeping and burning by
the audience stimulate and aggravate one another. If the [listeners] fail to
respond to the songs, even enthusiastic performers soon lose interest, and
the ceremony falls apart before the night is over.”70
Once the ceremony is over, the mindreading continues, albeit now in
a more explicit form. Here, recall again that the Kaluli subscribe to the
opacity model; that is, they consider it inappropriate to talk about other
people’s mental states. Yet they do talk about those mental states—with a
vengeance!—when discussing recent Gisalo songs. Those remain the subject of conversation for many days after a performance, as appreciative
members of the audience keep uncovering “subtlety and complexity in the
[singers’] interweaving of geography and personal allusion.”71 In situations
when a tape recording of a Gisalo made by an ethnographer is available,
hearing this tape may prompt a “discussion session,” which would last “for
hours” and in which “several older Kaluli men” would listen “repeatedly to
132
Chapter 4
the same song, . . . recalling the history of its performance, who had wept
and why, and how the song [reached its emotional climax].”72
It seems, in other words, that to talk about cultural representations that
build on our mindreading adaptations—prose fiction, certainly, but also
performance genres whose success is judged by their capacity to evoke emotional responses in their audience—we have to talk about mental states,
be they those of fictional characters or those of performers and audience
members. Societies closer to the transparency end of the mindreading spectrum, such as ours, may have codified formal venues for doing so (including college courses in film and literature), but societies closer to the opacity
end may engage in such conversations even in the absence of historically
entrenched institutional structures designed to elicit and facilitate them.
Ironically, public exercises in communal mindreading that occur in a literature classroom may be accompanied by disavowals of interest in intentionality that would not be out of place in a community subscribing to
the opacity model. It is not inconceivable that, were an ethnographer to
approach a literature professor and ask her how knowable she considers
various minds under consideration in her course, the professor would deny
any special access to those minds. She might say, for instance, that we have
no way of knowing what the author was thinking, that characters don’t
exist, so they can’t really have thoughts and feelings, and so on.
We may think of this response as underwritten by healthy epistemological skepticism, by the ethics of personal integrity and inviolability, or, more
broadly, by what the linguistic anthropologist Alessandro Duranti characterizes as a “defense strategy against the accountability that comes with
making claims about what others think or want.”73 But however we choose
to account for it, the larger point remains. Even if some of us (i.e., teachers
of literature) sincerely believe that we are not in the business of mindreading, our classroom conversations revolve around mindreading, focusing on
our own and other people’s (including fictional characters’) mental states.
And so do our scholarly conversations. Consider this brief sampler of
quotes from prominent literary critics (with attributions of mental states
italicized). What it shows is that the thoughts and feelings of characters,
authors, and audiences have been their prime subject since Aristotle and
that to talk about those thoughts and feelings, critics have always had
to construct complex embedments of their own. The “monastic theory
of mind” must have both tapped this tendency (what with the monks
Cultural History
133
following avidly mental states of saints, in hagiographies) and given it a
more defined institutional expression.
•
Aristotle mentions disapprovingly those who “make an unreasonable
prior assumption and, having themselves made their decree, . . . draw
their conclusions, and then criticize the poet as if he had said whatever
they think he has said if it is opposed to their thoughts” (Poetics).74
•
Wayne Booth observes in his analysis of Jane Austen’s Persuasion that
upon meeting Captain Wentworth “after their years of separation that
follow her refusal to marry him,” Anne Elliot “is convinced that he is
indifferent,” while the reader “is likely to believe that Wentworth is still
interested” (“Control of Distance in Jane Austen’s Emma”).75
•
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak discusses Victor Frankenstein’s “ambiguous
and miscued understanding of the real motive for the monster’s vengefulness” (“The Women’s Texts and a Critique of Imperialism”).76
•
Susan Sontag wonders if “perhaps Tennessee Williams thinks [A Streetcar
Named Desire] is about what [Elia] Kazan thinks it to be about” (“Against
Interpretation”).77
You may notice that these critics range widely in their choice of people
whose minds they read: Aristotle talks about embedded mental states of
readers; Booth, about those of characters and implied readers; Spivak, about
those of characters; Sontag, about those of the author. It so happens that
the last three scholars discuss works of literature that seem to offer plenty of
room for moving between different types of minds. But in some cases, the
decision to read a text in terms of mental states of its implied readers signals
more than just an immediate interpretive choice of a particular scholar. It
may indicate a change in the wider cultural perception of the text, such as a
redefinition of its genre or a renegotiation of its place in the literary canon.
To put it differently, a cultural repositioning of the text is usually accomplished through switching mindreading targets associated with that text.
For instance, the late sixteenth-century anonymous Chinese novel The
Plum in the Golden Vase (Chin P’ing Mei) has long occupied an ambiguous
place in Chinese literary history. Lay readers consider it pornography, while
scholars treat it as a literary masterpiece. It is reasonable to assume that
readers who turn to this novel for its explicit sex scenes register mainly
mental states of its characters, thus missing the complex mutual awareness
between the implied reader and the implied author. In contrast, students
134
Chapter 4
of classic Chinese literature pay a great deal of attention to mental states
of those nebulous entities, speculating about their intentions vis-à-vis each
other.78
Thus, Andrew Plaks cites the critical responses to The Plum, provided
by medieval Chinese commentators, which contain such observations as,
“the author definitely has his own intentions” and “there is an object to
[the text’s] ironic stabs.” Plaks himself discusses at length “the possibility
of hidden intentions” implied by the author’s use of “borrowed material,”
such as songs and poems, as well as the role that “frequent interpolations of
authorial asides” play “to periodically remind the reader of the presence of
the narrator somewhere between himself and the story.”79 What this focus
on the mental states of The Plum’s narrator and implied reader indicates is
that the novel deserves to be taken seriously as part of the Chinese literary
canon.
To return to European literary history, consider Eliza Haywood’s novella
Fantomina (1725), an amatory romp following sexual stratagems of a young
aristocratic woman in early eighteenth-century London. Fantomina had
remained outside the canon until the 1980s, when feminist literary critics
adjusted drastically the mindreading lens associated with it. Instead of continuing to read it focusing on the mental states of the inventive Fantomina
and her clueless lover, Beauplaisir, they began using those as jumping-off
points for a conversation about the cultural work accomplished by this
piece of genre fiction—this is to say, about the mental states of the novella’s
implied author and its original readers. For instance, the feminist literary
critic Ros Ballaster writes about the novella’s capacity to change the selfperception of women in a world in which they did not have much power.
As she puts it, “by dehistoricizing and mythologizing the public sphere, the
romantic fiction writer provided the female reader with a sense of feminine
power and agency in a world usually closed to her participation.”80
Observe what happens here. Making Fantomina a subject of scholarly
conversation and, consequently, putting it on our course syllabi depend on
opening up a new vein of mindreading associated with it. We talk about
the (hypothetical) mental states of the author, her readers, and the broader
English public (which we imagine here as not willing to grant women much
power or agency). In other words, as with The Plum in the Golden Vase, the
admission of a text into the canon involves recalibration of the mindreading effort associated with it.
Cultural History
135
Moreover, in an environment as fundamentally dependent on elaborate
attributions of mental states as are departments of literature, such recalibrations may be par for the course. Casting out for new minds to read, or else
for new ways to read the minds already associated with a particular text,
constitutes the bread and butter of literary interpretation.
4.9 Critical Thinking and the “Transparency Model”
To give the screw yet another turn, recall that advocates of the humanities
often say that taking courses in literary and film studies develops students’
critical thinking and thus contributes to the well-being of the community
at large.81 Yet what is “critical thinking,” in the particular context of these
disciplines,82 but the heightened capacity for convincingly questioning
and elaborating people’s intentions? If in Bosavi, the statement of one’s
intentions is taken as precluding further public speculation about them
(what goes on in private and how much others actually believe those stated
intentions are, of course, different matters),83 in Western culture, such a
statement often serves as an invitation for open scrutiny. Clever public contestations of other people’s mental states are applauded. An ability to construct a convincing argument about what a politician or a writer must have
really meant—in direct opposition to what they claimed to have meant or
even may have sincerely believed to have meant—is a prized skill. As Elinor
Ochs observes,
In legal and other contexts, if it is established that a negatively valued behavior was consciously intended, then sanctions are usually more severe than if the
speaker/actor “didn’t mean to do it.” . . . [While] establishing intentionality is
not always critical to sanctioning . . . , [the] important point is that . . . what a
person means or meant to do or say is an important cultural variable. For this
social group, what a person means to do is distinguished from what he does. This
orientation leads members to take seriously, and to pursue the establishing of,
individuals’ motivations and psychological states.84
But even when taken “seriously,” the pursuit of someone else’s “motivations and psychological states” is a deeply fraught process, both in legal
contexts and beyond them. The rise of today’s therapeutic culture, for
instance, seems to reaffirm the value of opacity, for the notion of “sharing” one’s emotions emphasizes the deliberateness of the personal choice
of how and when to render oneself transparent to others. And, in general,
136
Chapter 4
if you think of the ethos of transparency as an unalloyed social good, just
recall situations in which someone else (a family member, a colleague, a
reviewer of your book) made assertions about your motivations—this is
to say, interpreted your mental states for you—instead of merely reporting
something that you said. As far as I see, such assertions do not necessarily
lead to greater social cohesion, either in personal communication or on the
global stage. Still, plenty of our cultural institutions—indeed, those that we
may think of as fundamental to a liberal democracy (e.g., the prized right to
“free speech”)—are geared toward rendering people’s motivations transparent, or temporarily legible, by various eloquent others.
This is to say that the “transparency” model works better in some contexts than in others, just as, presumably, does the “opacity” model. To adapt
Webb Keane’s formulation, both models are “sources of difficulties and . . .
affordances” for their respective communities, meeting their needs in some
respects and failing in others. That both prove to be, fundamentally, mixed
blessings is, perhaps, unavoidable, given the precarious nature of the phenomenon that they attempt to regulate and describe (i.e., people’s mental
states).
4.10 Mindreading in the Social, Natural, and Physical Sciences
Academic disciplines, in their current cultural configurations, differ widely
in their attitudes toward using mental states—or referring to intentions—in
their discourses. This means that when a student decides to major in history,
mathematics, chemistry, evolutionary biology, or literary and film studies,
they effectively commit themselves to a mostly unspoken paradigm of mindreading specific to a particular academic environment. We have already
seen how this paradigm plays itself out in literary studies. Let us now take a
closer look at several other academic environments.
Departments of history depend on mindreading in their construction of
narratives of cause and effect (although not everybody is happy about this
state of affairs).85 Indeed, historians routinely attribute feelings and intentions not just to people but also to geopolitical entities. Here is a random
excerpt from Michael Howard’s The First World War (2002), with emphasis
added, in which countries feel “proud” and “anguished,” coalitions “wish”
they could “ignore” certain political realities, and the world is busy keeping
a running total of its great empires:
Cultural History
137
A liberal-radical coalition [that] came to power [in Britain] in 1906 . . . could not
ignore the paradoxical predicament in which Britain found herself at the beginning of the century. She was still the wealthiest power in the world and the proud
owner of the greatest empire that the world had ever seen; but she was more vulnerable than ever before in her history. . . . Ideally [successive British governments]
would have wished to remain aloof from European disputes, but any indication
that their neighbors were showing signs, singly or collectively, of threatening their naval dominance had for the previous twenty years been a matter of
anguished national concern.86
In contrast, the physical sciences have worked long and hard to remove
references to intentionality, divine or human, from their discourses and
have largely succeeded. Still, if you pick up a standard science textbook, you
notice that its authors sometimes liven up their material with appeals to
their readers’ theory of mind. Consider this passage (emphasis added) from
Nivaldo J. Tro’s Chemistry: Structure and Properties (2017): “Table E1 shows
the standard SI base units. For now we focus on the first four of these units:
the meter, the standard unit of length; the kilogram, the standard unit of
mass; the second, the standard unit of time; and the kelvin, the standard
unit of temperature.”87 The phrase “we focus” conjures up a momentary
image of joint attention, a speck of sociality in a sea of data. Because of this
brief evocation of mental state, the data may now be easier to process, especially for readers who find this material only moderately exciting.88
Medical schools present an interesting case. On the one hand, they seem
to actively suppress mindreading, at least in their written discourse, by discouraging students from referring to their own and their patients’ mental
states. According to the physician and literary scholar Rita Charon, as “students are groomed to speak in medicine’s language,” the style of their “written language flattens out.” She offers the following example of an exercise
produced by a third-year student (in which “HPI” stands for “history of
present illness”): “HPI: 51 yo man with HIV (diagnosed in 20xx, recently
began HAART in February, March 20xx CD4 204 / 27%, VL UD, CD4 nadir
191 in 11/20xx, no OIs, RF: multiple transfusions), hemophilia A, HTN
c/b ESRD on HD w/ TLC c/b multiple MSSA infections, HCV (genotype
1b, untreated), with recent prolonged hospitalization 02/4/xx–04/7/xx for
MRSE MV endocarditis c/b MCA CVA 2/2 septic emboli who presents with
high blood pressure and headache.”89
On the other hand, there is a growing recognition that draining medicine of language that serves as “a means to access a person’s inner sensations
138
Chapter 4
and thoughts” denies the humanity of both patients and doctors and is
having devastating effects on the profession.90 Thus, the new field of narrative medicine,91 spearheaded by Charon, challenges this status quo by
reintroducing a conversation about mental states into interactions between
the doctor and the patient.92
References to mental states may also find their way into other disciplines
whose very foundation depended on excising any notion of intentionality
from their discourse. For instance, an evolutionary biologist may write an
article on the genetic basis of color adaptation—a subject in which intentionality has no place—and yet find a way of encouraging mindreading in
her audience. “Thus Hopi Hoekstra (emphasis added): ‘Many aspects of
modern evolutionary research are motivated by the desire to understand how
diversity arises and is maintained in nature. How and why do organisms
look and act so differently, and in some cases, so strangely? In fact, these are
the same questions that inspired Darwin, but thanks to Watson and Crick,
we now can look for the answers in the language of DNA.’ ”93
Hoekstra’s writing has long been admired by her students and colleagues, and we can see one reason why. She evokes mental states: those
of the implied researcher, her readers, and other scientists. The effect is
such that, while not detracting from the rigor of her insights, it makes
those insights easier to follow. A bit of sociality, created by references to
mental states, makes the account of the genes involved in color adaptation
reader-friendly.
What I wanted to show with this set of examples is that, even in a culture that gravitates, on the whole, toward the transparency end of the
spectrum, attitudes toward explicit mindreading remain in flux. Even in a
narrowly circumscribed institutional setting, such as the university, forms,
targets, and ethical meanings of various mindreading practices are subject
to constant renegotiation.
This is not terribly surprising, given the fundamental ontological instability of the phenomenon in question: after all, mental states are not
“really” there—they are something that we cobble together as we move
along, to make sense of our social environment. While communities that
subscribe to the opacity model respond to this instability by claiming that
minds are not knowable (even as their private practices may belie the official doctrine), communities that subscribe to the transparency model insist
that minds must be knowable and scramble to construct those “knowable”
Cultural History
139
minds, with very mixed results, or else declare certain areas of (academic)
inquiry mindreading-free. The historical approach to cognition that I advocate in this book thus proposes to take into consideration this spectrum of
attitudes toward other people’s minds and to view specific cultural developments (e.g., the rise and fall of certain literary genres and practices of interpretation) in relation to these inescapably flawed models of social reality.
Here is, then, how my approach differs from that of more traditionally minded literary historians. They may inquire into ways in which, for
instance, the growth or decline of adult literacy rates or the repeal or introduction of censorship laws may affect a cultural career of a particular literary
genre. What I would also want to know in such cases is whose minds are
rendered as more or less knowable as a result of those changes or, to put it
differently, which mindreading practices are newly perceived as more or less
publicly acceptable, desirable, and ethical. Community-specific ideologies of
mindreading may be all but invisible to members of the community, but they
shape both daily social practices and literary reimaginings of these practices.
5
Literary History: The Importance of Being Deceived
5.1 Realism: Nothing but Trouble
To recap, thinking of complex embedment of mental states as an essential
feature of literature (as we know it today) calls for operating on three historical levels simultaneously. The first level is the “deep,” that is, cognitive,
history. The second is the more immediate cultural history, that is, implicit
expectations about forms, targets, and ethics of mindreading and the social
institutions that support these expectations. In this chapter, we turn to the
third level—literary history—that is, the evolution of patterns of complex
embedment within and across specific literary traditions.
How does one go about reconstructing this kind of history? On the one
hand, even a quick look at ancient epics, novels, and plays, as well as literary texts that defy clear generic classification, shows that third-level embedment of mental states has been around for a long time. It is already there in
Gilgamesh and the Bible, in Homer, Petronius, Apuleius, Heliodorus, Wang
Shifu, and Luo Guanzhong. So, in principle, one should be able to show
how literary embedments change over time: how instances of complex
embedments become more frequent (for, in Gilgamesh, they are relatively
rare), how they come to depend more on particular elements of style, and
how their evolution is driven by specific social and cultural contexts.
On the other hand, the meager number of surviving texts from ancient
literary traditions makes it difficult to construct a responsible argument
about the early history of this trend in different genres. Take fifth-century BC
Greek drama. One may be tempted to contrast Aeschylus with Sophocles—
because the latter seems to embed complex mental states more frequently
that the former does, especially of the explicit kind—and to develop a
claim about an important milestone in the history of embedment that
142
Chapter 5
was reached at that time. Given, however, how few of either Aeschylus’s or
Sophocles’s plays came to us intact and how little of a broader context we
would have for such a claim (with only 1 percent of ancient Greek literature
having survived), its value would be dubious.
Or consider a seemingly straightforward argument that one can make
about the relationship between embedment and the rise of what is commonly
called the “psychological” or “psychologically realist” novel. On the one hand,
there seems to be little doubt that the sheer scale of complex embedment—its
increasing cascading frequency—in such authors as Murasaki Shikibu, Cao
Xueqin, Samuel Richardson, Laurence Sterne, Jane Austen, George Eliot, Gustave Flaubert, Fedor Dostoevsky, Lev Tolstoy, Virginia Woolf, Marcel Proust,
James Joyce, Thomas Mann, Lu Xun, and Henry James dwarfs all preceding
patterns of embedment, making their writing feel drastically different from
that of Homer, Apuleius, Heliodorus, Nizami, and Luo Guanzhong.
On the other hand, the association between psychological realism and
hypertrophied complex embedment is more complicated than it appears
to be. The terminology itself is problematic. If we acknowledge complex
embedment of mental states as an important feature of psychologically
realist novels,1 then one is compelled to ask for whom this experience is
“realist.” It may be so for characters themselves, for they can function on
the first and second level of embedment, with only occasional third- and
fourth-level spikes. But in what sense is it realist for readers—who have to
cope with the ongoing onslaught of mental states embedded on at least the
third level (if they hope to stay on the text’s wavelength)—which is, arguably, not something that they are called on to do in their “real” life?
As a quick illustration of what I mean by the onslaught, consider an
excerpt from Alexander Pushkin’s novel in verse Eugene Onegin (1833),
which is often characterized as a great realist, or pre-realist, work of Russian
literature.2 Here is a description of its title character, who, at eighteen, is
already well versed in the “art of soft passion” of love:
How early he was able to dissemble,
conceal a hope, show jealousy,
shake one’s belief, make one believe,
seem gloomy, pine away,
appear proud and obedient,
attentive or indifferent!
How languorously he was silent,
Literary History
143
how flamingly eloquent,
in letters of heart, how casual!
With one thing breathing, one thing loving,
how self-oblivious he could be!
How quick and tender was his gaze,
bashful and daring, while at times,
it shone with an obedient tear!3
What a tour de force of complex embedments! When the situation calls
for it, Onegin dissembles (i.e., he wants the pursued woman to think that
he feels something that he doesn’t really feel); shows jealousy (wants her to
believe that he is afraid that she may love someone else); seems gloomy (wants
her to think that he is miserable); pines away (wants her to think that he is
despondent); appears proud (wants her to think that he believes himself to be
above the situation), obedient (wants her to think that he will do anything
she wants), attentive (wants her to believe that he can only think of her), or
indifferent (wants her to think that he doesn’t care whether she loves him).
He is “languorously silent” (i.e., he wants her to start wondering what’s on his
mind), “self-oblivious” (he wants her to think that he is not in control of his
feelings), “bashful and daring” (he wants her to think that he is embarrassed of
his passion yet can’t help it), or tearful (he wants her to think that he is deeply
moved by the situation).
And on top of that, we have the complex embedments arising from the
interaction between the narrator and the reader. For that is what all those
frequent “hows” accomplish (as in, “how languorously he was silent”).
The narrator invites the reader to share in his amused admiration of the
hero’s antics: not only does Eugene want the woman to wonder what’s on his
mind, but the narrator wants the reader to be aware of Eugene’s wanting the
woman to wonder what’s on his mind!
So it appears that, in Eugene Onegin, one single stanza can make us process fifteen or so tightly compressed4 complex embedments in about ten
seconds (which is, roughly, the time that it takes us to silently read it). How
often do we do that in the course of our daily life?5 That is, how often do we
find ourselves processing complex embedments with anything resembling
this frequency? Ironically, the works of Homer, Heliodorus, and Nizami may
be said to be more psychologically realist (or, to quote Patricia Miller and her
colleagues again, more “ecologically plausible”) in this respect because their
rate of complex embedment—occasional as opposed to nonstop—may be
closer to what we experience in our daily social interactions.
144
Chapter 5
In fact, if the world conjured by Pushkin feels more psychologically realist to us than the world of Heliodorus does, it may be because reading novels has skewed our idea of what “real” or “realist” is. Perhaps we have even
been flattered into thinking that this is what our daily mindreading might
look like, if only we would find ourselves in the right place with the right
(i.e., introspective, sophisticated) people. But is that indeed the case?
Think of situations in which we are confronted with numerous complex embedments in a short span of time. Do not consider special professional contexts: some occupations, such as family lawyer, psychologist,
poker player, and professor of literature, routinely depend on intense bouts
of complex embedment.6 Instead, recall more mundane occasions. In our
everyday life, when we find ourselves in circumstances that call for processing numerous complex embedments (for instance, when we have to
remind ourselves, first, not to say something about one person’s intentions
in front of another person, who, we know, may use that information to
thwart the first person’s plans, and, then, not to say anything about the
second person’s intentions in front of the first person, and so forth), we
do not perceive that as particularly realistic. In fact, we may complain that
there is “too much drama” in our life just then or observe that there is a
“soap-opera” quality to our experience.
In other words, our “real” life begins to feel rather special when we find
ourselves inexorably processing one complex embedment of mental states
after another, even though—and I hope you appreciate the irony of it—one
of the key components of literary “realism” seems to be its thick sociality,
created by the “ecologically implausible” piling up of complex embedments.
Moreover, literature does not just pile up complex embedments of the
soap-opera-ish kind, as in, for instance, “I must remember that she must
not know anything about his intentions.” Instead it often conceals and
masks embedded intentions and prompts us to ascribe them to entities that
are not involved in actual social interactions that take place in a story, such
as narrators and implied authors/readers.7 Whereas this is not unusual in
real life—indeed, contextual irony can be richly present in some of our
daily conversations—what is unusual is the scale on which it happens in
literature, where a single paragraph, for instance, from Lu Xun or Henry
Fielding, can give us multiple high-level embedments of this kind.
So when my undergraduates, who increasingly (alas) haven’t had much
previous experience reading novels, throw up their hands and tell me that
Literary History
145
they don’t know what is going on in the text, even though they say that they
understand the meaning of individual words, perhaps it is not because their
social life is impoverished and they are not used to complex embedments as
such. Perhaps it is—at least in part, that is—because the frequency and kind
of such embedments in literature place demands on their mindreading skills
that may exceed what they are used to in their daily social exchanges, and it
takes both time and effort to adapt to those demands.
This is why, from a cognitive literary perspective, it makes particular
sense to speak of the novel as experimenting with, rather than reflecting,
“realistically,” this particular aspect of human psychology. I have argued
something along similar lines in chapter 2, in which I showed that writers
can intuitively follow the real-life dynamics of associating more vigorous
mindreading with lower social standing, but then they also can, just as easily, ignore and subvert this particular feature of real-life mindreading. Realism, it seems, is what realism does, particularly in a genre as tightly bound
to it in cultural imagination as is the novel.
“Realism,” of course, is a term that is notoriously slippery and subjective.8 There is something paradoxical, as Troscianko reminds us, about the
fact that we require it “to converge with our expectations about cognition,
which may themselves be subject to (systematic and interesting) errors.”9
Perhaps we are better off shifting the terms of our discussion and considering the critical obsession with realism as a fascinating cognitive cultural
phenomenon in its own right—worthy of studying as such but not something one would want to lean on too heavily in a critical analysis.
5.2 Novels: Still Nothing but Trouble
But let us say that we push aside the pesky issue of realism. Still more trouble awaits us as we consider the relationship between embedded mental
states and the novel as such. Especially in the novel’s more recent incarnation (i.e., Tolstoy’s Anna Karenina as compared to Heliodorus’s Aithiopika),
its treatment of consciousness makes it the genre most dependent on complex embedment. As Andrew Plaks puts it, “to say that the novel as a genre
deals with human consciousness . . . does not set it off from other literary
genres, but, as a matter of proportion, the degree to which the novel does
so is indeed rather unique.”10 Just so, while no work of literature can construct human consciousness without embedding at least some complex
146
Chapter 5
mental states, the degree to which the novel embeds them is indeed rather
unique.
Recall, for instance, that one of the “defining criteria of the genre” is
irony and that an author’s “ironic reflection on the product of his own creation” calls almost incessantly for the reader’s processing of high levels of
intentionality.11 Or consider works that do not cultivate irony but are still
characterized by “radical reflexivity,” for instance, autobiographical novels
about autobiographies, such as Christa Wolf’s Patterns of Childhood (1976).12
While containing “autobiographical traces,” Patterns of Childhood focuses
“more on autobiographical writing as a theme, elaborating and challenging
the genre from within,” a challenge that directly depends on the reader’s
awareness of the author’s embedded intentionality.13
Yet to claim that the novel as a genre is most obviously associated with
complex embedment is to ask for trouble. The reason for this is that the
critical discourse of the “rise of the novel” comes with its own controversies, and if I hitch my cognitivist wagon to that discourse, I inherit those
controversies. Specifically, by saying that massive-scale embedment of
mental states is an essential feature of the psychological novel, I can be seen
as courting the charge of determinism, which has been haunting historians
of the novel. Let us take a closer look at that charge.
As Plaks explains, determinism used to be associated with scholars of the
epic—who “observed the appearance of that form in widely separate cultures and therefore assumed it to be an inevitable phenomenon of human
creativity”—but it has now migrated to the novel. Determinism rears its
ugly head when one notices the “striking correspondence between . . .
essential qualities of the novel” in the European and Chinese traditions and
“the fact that these comparable developments occur” around the sixteenth
to eighteenth centuries, that is, “at a time of limited mutual influence.”14
In addition, one may look at socioeconomic factors that correlate with
the rise of the novel in some cultures and notice that, in other cultures,
the novel arose in their absence. For instance, “the relation demonstrated
by many Western scholars between the rise of the novel and the social and
economic development of the pre-modern period also describes quite well
the context of the emergence of full-length prose fiction in China,”15 but
this relation doesn’t obtain for the history of the early Japanese novel.16
Consequently, one may be tempted “to conclude that the emergence of
such a genre of . . . prose fiction may represent an inevitable function of
Literary History
147
human culture, bound to appear in any literary civilization regardless of its
particular course of historical development.”17 And, with that, the torch of
determinism appears to have been successfully passed from scholars of the
epic to scholars of the novel.
At first blush, the cognitive approach only makes things worse. A cognitive literary theorist, such as myself, who sees the massive embedment
of mental states as constituting an “essential quality” of the eighteenthcentury European and Chinese novel as well as the eleventh-century Japanese novel, may be tempted to see the advent of such an embedment as
a predetermined “outcome of human creativity.” The temptation may be
particularly strong because it is so easy for us to focus on the universalist
aspect of the cognitivist discourse—which is, to quote Webb Keane again,
that “theory of mind and intention-seeking are common to all humans”—
while losing sight of the crucial qualification of that universalist stance,
which is that those cognitive adaptations “are elaborated in some communities and suppressed in others.”18 Both elaboration and suppression can
take myriad forms and be integrated with such factors as socioeconomic
conditions, political agendas, and intellectual history.
But if the massive complex embedment of mental states that we associate with the novel happened to arise in societies that encourage particular
forms of mindreading, then there is nothing predetermined about it. Societies that regulate their mindreading energies differently end up with different clusters of mind-modeling artifacts. I mentioned already the Gisalo
songs of Bosavi. These are deemed successful if the performers manage to
get under the listeners’ skins, while the listeners both want to be affected
by a song and resist it. This give-and-take between performers and listeners
assumes particular poignancy because it takes place in a culture of opacity,
in which people are not supposed to be attributing mental states to each
other.19
Once you learn of such complex forms of literary production, an argument about the “inevitable” rise of the novel as the pinnacle of sociocognitive complexity becomes even less compelling. Because human cultures’
engagement with theory of mind is dynamic and open-ended, so are the
forms that mindreading takes in a given community. Hence, when we talk
about the complex embedment of mental states in plays, novels, and narrative poetry, we must remember that this is literature as it happened to be
here now and not the expression of some platonic ideal of what it should be.
148
Chapter 5
To conclude, reconstructing the history of complex embedment in literature is a tough balancing act. One is hampered by the scarcity of surviving
texts. And even when there are enough texts to go on, one has to resist the
grand narrative of the inevitable rise of a particular genre that would feature
large-scale continuous embedment of complex mental states. One focuses
instead on the probability of the emergence of self-reflective literary narratives in communities that encourage particular forms of mindreading. Keeping these limiting factors in mind—“not inevitable but probable under certain
circumstances”—one may come up with a series of preliminary hypotheses.
These can then be tested and corroborated by others—or refuted!—if the
evidence from a particular literary tradition weighs in against them.20
5.3 “Men Were Deceivers Ever”
Utnapishtim said to his wife, “All men are deceivers, even you he will attempt
to deceive.”
—The Epic of Gilgamesh
When my love swears that she is made of truth, I do believe her, though I know
she lies.
—Shakespeare, Sonnet 138
How early he was able to dissemble . . .
—Pushkin, Eugene Onegin
Lying, in essence, is theory of mind in action.
—Victoria Talwar, Heidi Gordon, and Kang Lee, “Lying in the Elementary
School Years: Verbal Deception and Its Relation to Second-Order Belief
Understanding”
Here, then, is one such working hypothesis. It appears that the further back
one goes in time, the likelier it is that third-level embedments in literature
are created by portraying characters who intentionally deceive other characters.21 This is in contrast to more “modern” literature, in which thirdlevel embedments are created by a much wider variety of social contexts,
which include deception but are by no means limited to it.
Such is my hypothesis, and, right away, I foresee more trouble. For instance,
I put scare quotes around the word “modern,” to stress that modernity, thus
Literary History
149
understood, is diachronic rather than synchronic. This is to say that if a transition from a primarily deception-driven embedment to a more varied type
does take place (for I don’t claim this to be a universal phenomenon), different national literary traditions go through it at different time periods. One
should thus be wary of seeing some form of cultural influence and hence
causality in what is likely to be a coincidence, as, for example, the fact that
both the English and Chinese novel seemed to have gone through that kind
of transition around the same time period.
The flip side of the danger of explaining too much by cultural influence
is explaining too little. Over the past thousand years, very few national literatures existed in isolation from each other. As Haun Saussy puts it, “many
of the most influential works in any tradition are translations, not ‘native’
compositions.”22 And even those that can be considered “native” compositions bear numerous debts to foreign predecessors. Take for instance, Henry
Fielding, one of the avowed “fathers” of the English novel, whose 1749
Tom Jones echoes Don Quixote, the ancient “foundling” romances, and The
Iliad. One cannot, in good faith, speak about a discrete “English” literature:
depending on which genealogical path we choose, we can trace a history
of a particular genre—and thus its patterns of complex embedment—to the
French, Spanish, ancient Roman and Greek, or biblical literary tradition.23
As I see it, it is impossible to use English literature to test my hypothesis
about deception as the primary engine of complex embedment at some
early point in its history. For what would be considered “an early point” for
such a hybrid tradition? Don Quixote? Plutarch’s Lives? Aithiopika? The Iliad?
This is why we should count ourselves very lucky on the rare occasion when we come across a relatively well-preserved national literature
that functioned, for a long period of time, in isolation from other literary traditions and whose formative influences during the shift from complex embedment driven exclusively by deception to complex embedment
driven by a wider set of representational means are well documented. Such
is the case with Russian literature, in which one such shift can be traced to
1760–1830.24 During that period, Russian writers began imitating French
and English models and by doing so drastically changed the pattern of
embedment hitherto prevalent in works of fiction. In the next section, I
first briefly recount the history of this shift and then look at some patterns
of embedment in the works of nineteenth- and twentieth-century Russian
writers.
150
Chapter 5
5.4 What Happened in Russia
If we look at Russian medieval texts, explicitly positioned as literature (as
opposed, that is, to historical chronicles and hagiographies), such as Fedor
Kuritzyn’s The Tale of Dracula (ca. 1490), Ermolay-Erazm’s The Tale of Peter
and Fevroniya (1547), the anonymous Tale of Misery-Luckless-Plight (seventeenth century), and the picaresque The Tale of Frol Skobeev (1680–1720),
we notice that all of them achieve complex embedment through plots of
deception.
For instance, the blood-curdling The Tale of Drakula (Povest’ o Drakule)
tells the story of a Romanian prince, Vlad Drakula, who deceives a Turkish
king. When the king sends his ambassador to Drakula, demanding tribute,
Drakula hosts the ambassador lavishly, dazzles him with his wealth, and
asks him to pass the following message to the king: “Not only am I ready
to pay the tribute, but I also want to become his vassal, putting my army
and my wealth at his beck and call. Only tell him that when I go to him, he
must make sure his people don’t harm me and my army, and I will follow
you very shortly, along with my tribute.” Drakula wants the Turkish king
to think that he intends to become his vassal. When the gullible king lets
Drakula and his army deep into his territory, Dracula attacks the unprotected cities, plunders their wealth, sadistically murders their inhabitants,
repatriates the Christians who used to live there, and sends the king a sarcastic message asking if he wants more of Drakula’s service. “And the king
couldn’t do anything with him and was only covered with shame.”25
In The Tale of Peter and Fevroniya (Povest’ o Petre i Fevronii), an evil dragon
assumes the appearance of a local prince and starts visiting that prince’s
wife, forcing her to have sex with him. When the wife tells her real husband
about those visits, he implores her to use her “seductive charms” to learn
what keeps the dragon alive and how he can be killed. “Holding the husband’s words in her heart,” the wife then approaches the dragon with flattering speeches—she wants him to think that she admires him—and asks if his
omniscience extends to knowing what would cause his death. The dragon
tells the woman that he is destined to be slain by a man named Peter, which
is the name of the prince’s own brother. Then, one day, as Peter is visiting his
brother and his wife, he is confused because, having just seen the prince in
his sister-in-law’s chamber, he then encounters him immediately afterward
in a different room. But when the prince tells him that he has been in this
Literary History
151
room all along, Peter realizes that the dragon wants him to be afraid of killing
his own brother and so appears to him as the prince. (“Those, brother, are
the intrigues of the sly dragon: he assumes my appearance, so that I would
be afraid to kill him, thinking this is you—my brother.”)26
The anonymous seventeenth-century narrative poem The Tale of MiseryLuckless-Plight (Povest’ o Gore-Zloschastii) tells the story of a young man from
a well-to-do family who doesn’t listen to admonitions of his parents and as
a result finds himself alone and destitute, far away from his hometown.27
He works hard, gains wealth and respect, and is about to marry a young
woman of his choice, but then he makes the mistake of boasting at a party
about his recent successes. Misery overhears this bragging and decides to
show him that nobody can outwit it and escape its hold. After giving some
thought about the best way to influence his victim,
evil Misery devised cunningly
to appear to the youth in his dream:
“Young man, renounce your beloved bride,
for you will be poisoned by your bride;
you will be strangled by that woman;
you will be killed for your gold and silver!
Go, young man, to the tsar’s tavern,
save nothing, but spend all your wealth in drink;
doff your costly dress, put on tavern sackcloth.
In the tavern Misery will remain,
and even Luckless-Plight will stay—
for Misery will not gallop after a naked one,
nor will anyone annoy a naked man,
nor has assault any terrors for a barefooted man.”28
Misery wants the youth to think that his fiancée only wants his money and
that to stay safe from people who are after his wealth, he ought not to have
any. When the young man doesn’t believe his dream, Misery hatches a
more devious plan:
The young man did not believe his dream,
but evil Misery again devised a plan,
appeared as the Archangel Gabriel,
and stuck once more to the youth for a new plight:
“Are you not, youth,
acquainted with poverty and immeasurable nakedness,
with great paucity and dearth.
What you buy for yourself is money wasted,
152
Chapter 5
But you, a brave fellow, will still survive!
They do not beat, or torture naked people,
or drive them out of paradise,
or drag them down from the other world;
nor will anyone annoy a naked man,
nor has assault any terrors for a naked man!”
Misery wants the youth to think that Archangel Gabriel himself wants him
to give up his wealth. This time the deception works, and the young man
falls right into Misery’s clutches:
The young man believed that dream:
he went and spent all his wealth in drink.29
And we have already seen how a plot of deception plays itself out in the
late seventeenth-century The Tale of Frol Skobeev. As a “likable and clever
delinquent,” Frol rises to wealth and nobility through bribery, crossdressing
(see figure 5.1), and blackmail, that is, through social situations rich with
opportunities for deception—and complex embedments.30
Figure 5.1
Frol Skobeev, dressed as a woman, is plotting his seduction of a courtier’s daughter.
Scene from the production of the Moscow State Historical-Ethnographic Theater.
(Copyright © 2013 МГИЭТ; http://etnoteatr.ru/komediya-o-frole-skobeeve.html)
Literary History
153
The early 1760s saw a watershed moment in the development of the
national literature because, for the first time, works of European fiction
entered Russian cultural imagination. A group of writers, associated with the
Cadet School, “set about the systematic translation of English and French
novels”: “Lukin and Elagin translated Antoine Prévost’s Adventures of Marquis G., Or, The Life of a Nobleman Who Abandoned the World (1756–61), and
Semyon Poroshin translated the same author’s English Philosopher (1761–7).
The novels of Henry Fielding, René Lesage, Pierre Marivaux, and Daniel
Defoe’s Robinson Crusoe were also translated. These [translations] provided
the Russian public with entertaining reading in addition to acquainting it
with those works which had already become part of the culture of every
literate person in western Europe.”31
And then, almost overnight, Russian literature changed. Alongside
embedment driven by deception, there appeared embedment driven by the
buildup of complex emotions. Fedor Emin (1735–1770) a prolific writer of
foreign extraction (his original name may have been Mahomet-Ali Emin),
known as the first Russian novelist, started publishing works of fiction
imitating French sentimentalism. Here, for instance, is a plea of a young
man from Emin’s 1766 epistolary novel Letters of Ernest and Doravra (Pisma
Ernesta i Doravry), in which the anguished lover hopes that his beloved will
pity the man who knows that he won’t be able to stop thinking about her
even when they part forever:
Forget my fault and know that the love that’s devouring me deserves punishment, not contempt. No one is angry at a person condemned to death; everyone
pities him; and if you, heavenly beauty, follow the way of worldly justice, you
will pity the miserable, from whom this letter will be the last, who can’t cause
you more chagrin, and who, going to his eternal confinement, carries with him
the fiercest memory of your charms, which will never cease tormenting all his
thoughts, his feelings, and his whole nature.32
Complex emotions continue to drive embedment in perhaps the
most famous late eighteenth-century tale, “Poor Liza” (1792), by Nikolai
Karamzin, the writer known as the “Russian Sterne.” “Poor Liza” is a story
of a love affair between a gentleman and a peasant girl who kills herself
after he abandons her. It is told, crucially, by the narrator, who wants his
readers to know early on that he “loves the objects that touch [his] heart
and make [him] cry the tears of tender sorrow.”33
154
Chapter 5
Emotional responses of this sentimental narrator color every important
scene. Here, for instance, Liza is sitting on the riverbank, imagining what
would happen if Erast, the kind and handsome gentleman she met recently,
were a poor shepherd and, hence, her social equal—“He would look at me
affectionately—perhaps take my hand in his. . . . A dream!”—when she
hears the splash of oars and sees Erast approaching her in a boat:
All her little veins trembled, but, of course, not from fear. She rose, wished to go,
and couldn’t. Erast leaped onto the shore, approached Liza and—her dream having come partially true—he looked at her affectionately and took her hand in his. . . .
Ach! He kissed her, kissed with such fervor that the whole universe appeared to
her to be on fire. “Darling Liza!,” said Erast, “Darling Liza! I love you.” These words
resonated in the depth of her soul as a heavenly, ravishing music; she hardly
dared to believe her ears and . . . But I throw down the brush. I will only say
that that minute Liza’s timidity disappeared. Erast learned that he was beloved,
beloved passionately by a fresh, pure, open heart.34
Words fail the narrator, repeatedly. When Liza’s “dream comes true,” he
is so fused with the speechless protagonist that all he can say is “Ach!”
And when Erast confesses his love, the narrator simply “throws down the
brush.” That is, he wants us to know that he is as overwhelmed with emotion
as is his innocent, deeply feeling protagonist.
This pattern of embedment continues throughout the story. The narrator keeps drawing readers’ attention to his own feelings as he paints his
characters’ emotional reactions. Or he claims to be incapable of doing so
and hence invites the reader to imagine those reactions. Although the story
still contains its share of lies—for instance, Erast will eventually abandon
the “poor Liza” in spite of all his promises—complex embedments generated by deception are dwarfed by embedments generated by the give-andtake between the narrator and readers.
5.5 Unreliable Narrators and Eavesdropping Characters
Karamzin’s fiction as well as his autobiographical Letters of a Russian Traveler (1789–1790), modeled on Sterne’s A Sentimental Journey through France
and Italy (1768), had a profound influence on several generations of Russian writers. But, even more important, those writers continued to be
shaped by their contact with European literature, for once those floodgates
opened, they never (fully) closed.35 This meant a constant exposure to the
Literary History
155
eighteenth-century European writers’ experimentation with new ways of
representing fictional consciousness and hence to new ways of embedding
complex mental states.36
We can briefly speculate here about various historical factors—such as
the economic and political reforms of Peter the Great, who forced his compatriots to open up to the world beyond their geographical borders—which
may have made some communities in the early days of the Russian Empire
particularly keen on elaborating their mindreading practices. We can further
say that this new interest in their own and other people’s intentions may
have continued to contribute to the development of literature throughout
the respective rules of Elizabeth and Catherine II, what with their ties to
Europe and their support for the arts and higher education. Conversely, we
can say that, when under socialist realism in the 1930s–1980s, the range
of other people’s intentions, both within and outside the national borders,
was largely constricted to “for us” and “against us,” it hampered the ironic
self-reflectivity of the novel and narrowed down the range of minds to be
read into it. (This argument works as long as we are aware of its limited
scope, for, important as sociopolitical history may be to the history of mindreading in literature, it neither defines nor determines it.)
So keeping in mind those distal historical causes, as well as the more
immediate literary contexts, both European and national, we can say that
one way in which Russian writers of the first half of the nineteenth century
expanded their repertoire of embedments was by focusing on the mind of
the narrator. For to look for complex embedments in the works of Alexander Pushkin, Mikhail Lermontov, and Nicolai Gogol is to come across, again
and again, an idiosyncratic or even unreliable narrator.
Consider, for instance, the opening of “The Shot,” the first short story
from Pushkin’s The Tales of Belkin (1831): “We were stationed in the small
town of ***. Everyone is familiar with the life of an army officer. In the morning, drill and riding practice, dinner at the regimental commander’s or in a
Jewish tavern; in the evening, punch and cards.”37
This is our first sighting of the narrator, who hastens to tell us not just
that the life of an army officer is boring but also that “everyone” knows it’s
boring. At this point, we don’t yet know why it is so important for him to get
this point across. It becomes clear later on, when we realize that this young
officer has “a romantic imagination” and that the tedium of army life may
have made him particularly susceptible to romanticizing his acquaintances.38
156
Chapter 5
To map out this opening in terms of its embedded mental states, the
narrator wants us to think that anyone would be bored with this routine.
Moreover, the implied author wants us to notice the narrator’s eagerness to
establish the dullness of army life as an incontrovertible fact.
Take another opening sentence, that of Nicolai Gogol’s “The Overcoat”
(1842):
In the department of . . . but it would be better not to say in which department.
There is nothing more irascible than all these departments, regiments, offices—in
short all this officialdom. Nowadays every private individual considers the whole
of society insulted in his person. They say a petition came quite recently from
some police chief, I don’t remember of what town, in which he states clearly that
the government decrees are perishing and his own sacred name is decidedly being
taken in vain. And as proof he attached to his petition a most enormous tome
of some novelistic work in which a police chief appears on every tenth page, in
some places even in a totally drunken state. And so, to avoid any unpleasantness,
it would be better to call the department in question a certain department. And
so, in a certain department there served a certain clerk.39
What is going on here? In the words of another devotee of unreliable narration, Vladimir Nabokov, “The Overcoat” can be summed up thus: “mumble, mumble, lyrical wave, mumble, lyrical wave, mumble, lyrical wave,
mumble, fantastic climax, mumble, mumble, and back into the chaos from
which they all had derived.”40 The narrator starts off briskly enough—“In
the department of”—but immediately changes his mind: “it would be better not to say in which department.” He then hastens to justify this mumbling with more mumbling: you know how those officials are; they get
offended easily; just look at that police chief of I-don’t-remember-which
town. By the time we get back to the actual story of the clerk, we are, to
quote Nabokov again, deep in “a grotesque and grim nightmare making
black holes in the dim pattern of life.”41
But let us leave off those lovely metaphors and see what kind of “thinking about thinking people” this paragraph may expect from its readers. The
narrator doesn’t want to name the department because he is afraid of being
persecuted by people who don’t understand the difference between a novel
and a denunciation. The implied author, meanwhile, is doing something
even more interesting. He wants his reader to be that narrator. That is, he
wants his reader to imagine what it feels like to be a person who is compelled
to tell a story yet is anxious about the social implications of the whole business of storytelling.
Literary History
157
Thus Pushkin and Gogol. More odd characters itching to tell their tales
are waiting for us on the pages of Lermontov’s A Hero of Our Time (1840).
This novel is divided into five parts, which are narrated by three different people—in the words of James Wood, not a single “reliable storyteller
among them.”42 Since other scholars have explored this aspect of Lermontov’s writing in depth, I will focus here on something else. Observe that,
even as he experiments with such sophisticated strategies for embedding
complex mental states as the narrator’s unreliability, Lermontov doesn’t
shun other, older and (arguably) cruder ones. Thus, in addition to lying, his
novel often relies on its junior cousin, eavesdropping. For, what is eavesdropping but a shortcut for a very particular mindreading dynamic? If lying
is wanting others to think that your thoughts are something other than what
they really are, then eavesdropping is not wanting others to know that you
know something important about their real thoughts.
Lermontov is no worse an offender here than Cao, Austen, or Emily
Brontë. If Dai-yu can eavesdrop on Bao-yu and Xiang-yun; Anne Elliot on
Captain Wentworth and Luisa Musgrove; and Heathcliff on Catherine and
Nelly,43 then, surely, Lermontov’s protagonist is entitled to one or two—or,
as it happens, eight—instances of fateful overhearing of other people’s conversations in “Princess Mary” alone. (“Princess Mary” is one of the five
stories that make up A Hero of Our Time.) So frequently does Lermontov
arrange putting his narrator in the know through eavesdropping that,
according to Nabokov, we soon stop registering it as something out of the
ordinary: “the author’s use of this device is so consistent throughout the
book that it ceases to strike the reader as a marvelous vagary of chance and
becomes, as it were, the barely noticeable routine of fate.”44
As cognitive literary critics, we must recognize eavesdropping as a handy
sociocognitive tool available to writers. If used sparingly (or, as in the case
of A Hero of Our Time, brazenly), it complements both that old workhorse
of complex embedment—lying—and the shinier, newer machinery of unreliable narration. It takes all kinds of complex embedments to construct a
literary subjectivity, so a writer, even one destined to enter a pantheon of
national literature, can ill afford to spurn any of them.
Speaking of not spurning old workhorses, recall the stanza that describes
the protagonist’s lovemaking in Pushkin’s Eugene Onegin: “How early he
was able to dissemble, / conceal a hope, show jealousy, / shake one’s belief,
make one believe,” and so on. What Onegin is doing here is putting on one
158
Chapter 5
false front after another. Yet he is neither a picaro in the mold of Frol Skobeev, nor what Haiyan Lee would describe as a groveling “pipsqueak,”45 nor
a liar (indeed, he may challenge to a duel a person who would accuse him of
lying). Instead, he is a literary heir of Dorimant and other aristocratic wits
from English Restoration comedy, who signal their depth and complexity
by playing mind games with the willing ladies of their acquaintance. A better social class of deceivers thus comes into play as Russian Romantics keep
mining the mother lode of deception even while discovering new ways to
embed complex mental states.
5.6 The Poetics of Shame and Self-Deception
Back in the 1830s, the idiosyncratic narrator was not the only exciting new
path to third-level embedment explored by Russian writers.46 Other paths
involved portrayal of manipulative behaviors, such as hypocrisy; of tangled
motivations, such as self-deception; and of complex social emotions, such
as shame.47
We start with shame. No national literary tradition is ever the same after
it discovers the sociocognitive potential of shame, especially if it is also
compounded with lying. But before we get to the man who made the most
of it, Fedor Dostoevsky, let us see what shame did for Pushkin in the early
days of modern Russian literature.
Take again “The Shot,” from Pushkin’s Tales of Belkin. Its plot centers on
a gentleman named Silvio, encountered by the narrator during his stint in
the army. One evening, Silvio, who has a reputation for being a crack shot,
is insulted by another officer and, instead of challenging him to a duel, lets
it pass. The narrator, who used to think of Silvio as a mysterious and intrepid
Romantic hero, now feels awkward around him: “But after that unfortunate
evening the thought that his honor was stained and by his own fault had
not been washed clean never left me and prevented me from behaving with
him as before; I was ashamed to look at him.”48 Being ashamed on another’s
behalf presupposes a very complex embedment: the narrator imagines what
it feels like to know that other people think that you are a coward.
Silvio easily intuits his young friend’s feelings: “Silvio was too intelligent
and too experienced not to notice it and not to guess the reason for it. It
seemed to pain him; at any rate I noticed a couple of times that he wished
Literary History
159
to talk with me; but I avoided such occasions, and Silvio gave it up.”49
The story thus continues to unfold through a series of complex embedments. The narrator realizes that Silvio knows that the narrator feels awkward
around him and that Sylvio wants to talk to him, and he makes a point of
avoiding such occasions.
How do we make sense of his behavior? We may assume, for instance,
that the narrator thinks that Silvio would try to justify his reluctance to
fight a duel and cannot conceive of any justification that would make any
difference in his perception of the situation. That is, the narrator is afraid of
feeling more shame on Silvio’s behalf after their conversation and so does
everything he can to prevent it.
But if shame is a highly generative social emotion when it comes to
embedded mental states, so is self-deception, an offshoot of deception. In
“The Shot,” it turns out that the reason that Silvio didn’t want to cleanse
his “stained honor” was that he felt that he couldn’t put his life even at
minimal risk because of another duel that he was hoping to fight one day.
A while back, a dashing young aristocrat had incensed Silvio by seeming to
be indifferent to danger while standing there waiting for Silvio to pull the
trigger during their duel, and Silvio decided to take a rain check on his shot
until the Count would have more reasons to value his life.
When that hour does come (the narrator will learn about it later, from
a different source), Silvio has the satisfaction of seeing his formerly dauntless adversary tremble while waiting for his shot, because, being newly
married to a lovely young woman, he now indeed has strong reasons for
not wanting to die. Silvio spares his victim because he hopes that, from
now on, the Count will live his life writhing in shame, unable to forget his
instance of less-than-manly behavior. The Count, however, is not the type
to obsess over the past. As John Mersereau Jr. explains, “Of course, the mental anguish with which Sylvio [sic] seeks to poison the Count’s life is based
on a reading of how he, Sylvio, would react in the Count’s place, and the
Count behaves otherwise. Ironically, the diabolic revenge to which Sylvio
devotes years of preparation proves worthless.”50
Silvio assumes that the Count will feel as anguished about his humiliation
as Silvio would have felt, but he is mistaken. He is deceiving himself—a
bright early specimen in the gallery of Russian literary protagonists who
find ever new ways to turn their cages into fool’s paradises.
160
Chapter 5
5.7 The Original Cringe Factor
Later in the century, shame becomes a wellspring of complex embedment
in the novels of Dostoevsky. As Deborah A. Martinsen puts it in her study
Surprised by Shame: Dostoevsky’s Liars and Narrative Explorers, “In mobilizing
shame as a narrative strategy, Dostoevsky adds shame’s affective and cognitive synergy to the recursive relations among author, reader, and text. The
activity of writing exposes characters to readers’ views; the activity of reading positions readers as witnesses.”51 In other words, Dostoevsky doesn’t
merely want his characters to be aware of their own or others’ shame,
but he also wants his readers to be ashamed—and to know that they are
ashamed—on behalf of those ashamed characters.
Martinsen sees Dostoevsky as prefiguring insights of the later-day philosophers of shame, such as Emmanuel Levinas and Jean-Paul Sartre, who
wrote about the “reflected assessment of the self” involved in shame.52 From
the cognitive literary perspective, what I find particularly fascinating about
the dynamic that Martinsen describes is that Dostoevsky exploited one
of the most powerful social emotions known to humans to expand the repertoire of fictional embedments beyond what may be familiar to us from
our daily life. His characters wallow in layers of embarrassment and selfexposure until no one around them is able to take it anymore, and then they
add more to make it yet worse.
Think of this original cringe factor as yet another case of a writer’s
experimentation with the reader’s social brain—experimentation, that is,
as opposed to a faithful reproduction of any “real-life” dynamics. Can we
process these emotionally gripping complex embedments of mental states?
Yes, we can. Are they “realistic”? If your answer is, “Well, not in my personal experience, but I wouldn’t put it past those crazy Russians,” I suggest
checking in with a Russian of your acquaintance.
As far as this Russian remembers, the ever-widening and ever-deepening
circles of mortifying self-awareness that Dostoevsky cultivates in his novels
is not something that I have encountered in reality. But, of course, now,
thanks to Dostoevsky, I can imagine surfing those dark waters and suspect
that one day a conversation with friends and family may yet veer in that
direction. As the literary critic Lidiya Ginzburg puts it, “Dostoevskian sensibility [Достоевщина] as a moral and ideological phenomenon is highly
Literary History
161
repugnant to me, and not because it is alien, but because, it is, to a degree,
inherent in me.”53
I think I understand the reason why we may treat Dostoevskian sensibility as, “to a degree, inherent” in us. On some level, our mindreading adaptations do not differentiate between attributing mental states to real people
and to fictional characters.54 Having processed those complex embedments
in a novel—that is, having experienced ourselves as being capable of such
deep, involved, yet coherently articulated mental states—we may now,
indeed, believe that a day may yet come when we will find ourselves luxuriating, with a sickening abandon, in the embarrassment caused to others
and ourselves by our self-exposure. That the day keeps being indefinitely
postponed does not contradict the reality of having had those feelings one
fine afternoon while reading The Idiot or The Brothers Karamazov.
Reenter lying. Here is a passage from The Idiot (this one happens to be
relatively low on the cringe factor), in which the protagonist, Prince Myshkin, is reflecting on the conversation he has just had with the old General Ivolgin. The General, a drunkard and inveterate liar, has left the house
thinking that Myshkin, a naïve young man, believed his tall tale about the
General’s former tender friendship with the Emperor Napoleon: “He also
understood that the old man left the house intoxicated by his success, yet
he also had a presentiment that he was one of those liars who, though lying
up to the point of voluptuousness and even self-oblivion, at the very peak
of their euphoria, still suspect deep inside that others do not believe them
and cannot possibly believe. In his present state, the old man could come
to his senses, be extremely ashamed, surmise that [Prince Myshkin] was
boundlessly compassionate toward him, and become affronted.”55
I won’t bother spelling out the obvious complex embedments of mental
states that structure this passage. The reason I quoted it (following Martinsen’s lead) is that I wanted to illustrate the new role that lying, once it joins
forces with shame, begins to play in the Russian novel.
In medieval Russian literature, lying was instrumental, antagonistic,
and private: it helped protagonists to survive or gain an upper hand over
their enemies. In contrast, in nineteenth-century literature, shame-driven
lying becomes, paradoxically, prosocial, occurring, as Martinsen points
out, largely “in the public sphere.” Dostoevsky’s liars, such as the old Ivolgin, “lie because they are ashamed of themselves. They do not intend to
162
Chapter 5
[defraud] others but to create a public persona that will be accepted and
admired. They lie to affirm their own self-worth and thus their social worthiness.”56 There is a performative aspect to their lying, which implicates
others as (more or less) appreciative spectators.
Other Russian writers, such as Turgenev, Tolstoy, and Chekhov will
take shame and self-deception—already brimming with embedded mental
states—and add something else to the mix: imperfect introspection. Their
characters will not quite trust their own emotional reactions. Their torturous vitality will often come from querying their motives when they feel
ashamed of themselves or on behalf of others, from being aware of their
double consciousness (i.e., aware of seeing themselves through the eyes of
imagined others), and from suspecting that they deceive themselves.
Such, then, is one story one can tell about the early history of Russian
literature if one focuses squarely on the role of embedded mental states in
the development of literary imagination. We start out, in the sixteenth and
seventeenth centuries, with complex embedment driven mainly by antagonistic lying. Then, in the 1760s, the influx of western European novels significantly expands the range of representational strategies for embedment.
The expansion continues in the 1790s–1830s with new embedments arising
from interactions between various idiosyncratic narrators and their implied
readers, as well as from the fictional exploration of hypocrisy, shame, and
self-deception. Then Dostoevsky perfects the cringe factor and recasts lying
as a public performance, and later yet, Tolstoy and Chekhov experiment
with nuances of self-deception and imperfect introspection. To sum it up,
while lying as the engine of complex embedment in literature never goes
out of fashion, it gets continuously reinvented, now by being layered with
the author’s ironic self-reflection, now by being integrated with a variety of
complex social emotions.
5.8 What Happened in China
Let us now turn to another national literary tradition, one that has developed,
until relatively recently, independently from European influences and can,
as such, be particularly illuminating as a test case for our working hypothesis
about lying and literary history. Can we say that the further back one goes in
time, the likelier it is that third-level embedments of mental states in Chinese
fiction arise mostly from situations in which characters intentionally deceive
Literary History
163
other characters? And can we also say that after a certain point in time, more
and more complex embedments are created by social contexts other than
lying, as well as the ones that reimagine lying, integrating it with a variety of
social emotions and with nuances of authorial self-consciousness?
Broadly speaking, yes, it seems that we can make such an argument,
but with some qualifications. For instance, as we have just seen, in Russian
literature, the breakthrough increase of embedment techniques in the late
eighteenth century owed to the introduction of French and English models in the 1760s. Chinese literary history developed along a very different
path. One way to trace its patterns of complex embedment is to look at the
experimentation with literary forms that took place within the “literati”
(i.e., scholar-official) culture in the Tang dynasty (618–907 AD) and to compare its patterns of embedment with those that we find in the fiction of the
preceding and following centuries.
One factor that makes this comparison challenging is the lack “of general agreement on criteria by which to identify [the] earliest examples” of
Chinese fiction.57 While some critics believe that the first examples of texts
that “ceased to be classed as history” and were instead “considered as fiction” appeared only toward the end of the Tang period,58 others trace it
further back, for instance, to the third century, that is, the early years of the
Six Dynasties era,59 or even “to the list of works labeled hsiao-shuo in . . .
The History of the Western Han Dynasty, completed shortly after A.D. 92.”60
Another complication arises from the expectation of the linear development that seems to be implied by my working hypothesis. Especially given
the variety of genres that fed into literature, the fictional status of which
remains contestable, we cannot expect to see a “gradual straight evolution”
from embedment arising almost exclusively from lying to embedment arising from a broader variety of contexts.61 The process is more complicated
and allows for returns to the earlier forms of embedment, especially in various hybrid genres, including historical fiction (as we will see shortly).
With these caveats in mind, let us compare patterns of embedment in
some of the earliest stories that can be arguably identified as fiction, with
those in the later Tang period and beyond, and speculate about circumstances that may have triggered the Tang authors’ experimentation with
contexts for embedment.
Cao Pi’s “Scholar T’an” (談生) is dated to the late second–early third cen-
tury. It tells a story of an old bachelor suddenly blessed with a beautiful
164
Chapter 5
wife, who, however, asks him not to “shine any lights” on her at night for
three years. They live together and have a son, but when the child is two
years old, T’an’s curiosity gets the better of him: “One night, lurking and
waiting after his wife had gone to bed, he stealthily shone a light on her.
From the waist up she was just like any human being, but from that point
downward there was no flesh, only dried-out bones.”62
T’an will lose his wife but, eventually, gain riches and palace employment,
for the woman turns out to have been the late daughter of a local prince. The
story is very short—about one-third of a page—and T’an’s preparing to disobey his wife’s injunction is, it seems, its only instance of third-level embedment. T’an doesn’t want his wife to know that he intends to find out who she
really is—hence all the “lurking” and “waiting after she had gone to bed”
and shining a light “stealthily.”
Niu Seng-ju’s “Scholar Ts’ui” (崔書生), another very short story, is dated to
the early ninth century. Its protagonist falls in love with a beautiful woman
and marries her without informing his mother. That leads to a deception
that will have fatal consequences. Ts’ui doesn’t want his mother to think that
he married without her knowledge, so he tells her that he had merely “taken
a concubine.”63 The mother eventually breaks up the couple, as neither she
nor her son know that the young woman is a daughter of a goddess and
that staying married to her for at least a year could bestow immortality on
Ts’ui and his family.
Yuan Zhen’s “Ying-ying’s Story” (鶯鶯傳), also from the early ninth cen-
tury, is a longer piece, centrally preoccupied with its characters’ tangled
motivations. It tells about the seduction and subsequent abandonment of
a beautiful girl from a good family by a young scholar, although the questions of who seduced whom and whether the abandonment was justified
remain open. There is no shortage of lies. For instance, Ying-ying doesn’t
want her mother to know that she loves student Zhang; Ying-Ying may
be deceiving either herself or Zhang when she wants him to think that
she only summoned him to their initial rendezvous because she wanted to
chide him for his improper advances; Zhang may be deceiving himself and
his friends when he claims that he decided to abandon Ying-ying in order
to guard his virtue against her “bewitching beauty,” and so forth.64
Yet interweaved with the complex embedments driven by deception and
self-deception are those arising from the interaction between the implied
reader and the implied author. As Pauline Yu puts it, “Ying-ying” is “a
Literary History
165
consummate writerly text, one that seems to be talking self-referentially as
much about what it is doing as text as about what it as text contains.”65 By
having student Zhang explain to the narrator why he “hardened [his] heart”
against his mistress (an explanation that may come across as feeble and selfserving); by including a long manipulative letter from Ying-ying; and by
having Zhang, Ying-ying, and the narrator write stylized poems reflecting
on the romance, the text draws the readers’ attention to the “arbitrariness
of what it is doing.” There are plenty of “behavioral motivations” to choose
from, and none is really adequate.66 As a result, “Ying-ying” becomes a narrative about constructing a narrative—rather than about why the characters did what they did—which presupposes an ongoing mutual awareness
between the implied author and the implied reader.
That the protagonist and his friends write poems about the affair firmly
situates “Ying-ying’s Story” within the literati culture. Yet this may not be the
most important sign of the narrative’s indebtedness to the mid-Tang poetic
tradition. A key feature of that tradition, as Stephen Owens explains, was the
poets’ insistence on shifting their readers’ attention from what is being interpreted to the act of interpretation. Thus, Du Fu (712–770), Han Yu (768–824),
Jia Dao (779–843), Bai Juyi (772–846), and Xue Neng (ca. 817–880), while
contemplating something pointedly insignificant, such as a miniature pond,
a porch in need of repair, or a tiny patch of bamboo plants, conjured up
observers—now disapproving, now sympathetic—even when claiming that
those observers’ responses do not matter to them. Hence Du Fu in “Deck by
the Water” (764), thinking of his intention to fix a sagging porch:
I suspect I’ll be laughed at by those who know it.
........................................
But people are moved by familiar things,
and I am overwhelmed by grief.”67
And hence Han Yu in “Pond in Basin”:
I mean it, this old man
is acting just like a kid,
he buried a basin and drew some water
to make a little pond.
...................
Don’t tell me my pond in a basin
is not completely done,
I began planting slips of lotus root
and now they are growing evenly.68
166
Chapter 5
Owen sees this “version of the ‘private,’ with its constant attention to being
observed from the outside, [as] ultimately a form of social display, depending on the amused approval of others who are playfully excluded.”69 What
I want you to notice is that this social display depends on complex embedment of mental states. The poet invites us to watch him as he watches
other people as they watch him. He wants us to know that he is aware of
their perspective, perhaps even encouraging us to side with him against
that communally sanctioned perspective.70
One may speculate that the interest in conflicting interpretations cultivated by the mid-Tang poets found further expression in ninth-century
tales of romance, such as “Ying-ying’s Story.” As Owen argues, the “rise
of romance [was] closely related to the development of individual acts of
interpretation or valuation” in poetry. Thus, “Ying-ying’s Story” “begs us
to pass judgment” on its protagonists; yet, “in the end, the disputants are
deadlocked,” and so, instead of siding with either, readers are left arguing
about the validity of those conflicting perspectives and even the possibility
that the author may have been personally invested in the situation.71 This
focus on the process of interpretation is what marks “Ying-ying’s Story” as
an early example of “a fully developed fictional form.”72
But “Ying-ying” also seemed to go beyond the interest in the act of
interpretation cultivated in mid-Tang poetry. It expanded that interest
in a direction that was not available to contemporary poets. According
to Owen, working in prose allowed Yuan Zhen to delve into minutiae of
motivation that might not be amenable to poetic treatment. Looking at
“verse renditions of romantic stories, both in quatrains and long ballads,”
including a poem that Yuan Zhen’s friend Yang Juyuan (755–?) wrote about
Ying-ying, Owen observes that “prose narratives often give complicated
and nuanced accounts of human behavior, [while poetry] for all its undeniable virtues, . . . flattens these complications into purified roles.”73 Thus,
in Yuan Zhen’s quatrain, the complications of Ying-ying’s manipulative
letter—in which “the Ying-ying who wants to show the self-effacing concern of a model wife is in conflict with another Ying-ying who is both
desperate and enraged”74—“are reduced” to such stock description as “her
broken heart.”75
Were we now to construct a straightforward narrative of a gradual
expansion of strategies for complex embedment of mental states in Chinese literature, this narrative might go like this: The exploration of readers’
Literary History
167
consciousness in mid-Tang poetry led to the opening up of new social contexts for complex embedment in ninth-century tales of romance. One of
them, “Ying-ying’s Story,” depends on a much broader range of complex
embedments—particularly those driven by the give-and-take between the
implied reader and the implied author—than we have encountered in, for
instance, “Scholar T’an” and “Scholar Ts’ui,” in which embedment was
driven exclusively by lying.
Then there is also a long tradition of Chinese drama, in which complex embedments arise from the embodied presence of actors onstage, for
instance, from comic disjunctions between the sentiments conveyed by the
characters’ words and their body language. To see how these three contexts for complex embedments (that is, lying, the give-and-take between
the implied author and the implied reader, and the disjunction between
words and body language) come together, think of Wang Shifu’s thirteenthcentury comedy The Story of the Western Wing (西廂記). Based on “Ying-ying’s
Story,” the Western Wing replicates some of “Ying-ying’s” plot-based lies,
and it also continues to cultivate the awareness between the implied author
and the implied reader through its steady stream of references to classical
texts, including poetry.
We would turn next to The Plum in the Golden Vase: more intricate lies
and references to poetry and philosophy. And then we would inevitably
end up with Cao Xueqin’s Dream of the Red Chamber (ca. 1750–1760), which
features lies and classical references, foregrounds its characters’ body language, and also talks obsessively about their thoughts and feelings. Voilà!
Behold the steadfast movement toward increasingly diverse ways to embed
complex mental states in Chinese literature.
I believe that this narrative has merits as long as we also acknowledge
fictional texts that disrupt its seemingly smooth course by continuing to
rely almost exclusively on lying to generate complex embedment. Consider
Luo Guanzhong’s Romance of the Three Kingdoms (三國演義). Written in the
fourteenth century—that is, after “Ying-ying’s Story” and The Story of the
Western Wing had demonstrated the possibilities of the expanded repertoire
of contexts for complex embedment—this eight-hundred-thousand-word
novel features complex embedments relatively infrequently,76 and when it
does, they are mostly driven by lies. Specifically, they are driven by stratagems and manipulations perpetuated by various warring factions, which
necessarily involve lying.77
168
Chapter 5
To give you a flavor of those stratagems, here is one of The Three Kingdoms’ frequently retold episodes. Wang Yun, a high-level official in the Han
government, gives his adopted daughter, Diaochan, to the evil warlord
Dong Zhuo as a concubine, in order to sow discord between Dong Zhuo
and his adopted son, Lu Bu. Once Dong Zhuo and Lu Bu are both besotted
with Diaochan, she takes turns lying to both of them in order to manipulate
them: “One day Lu Bu went to inquire after his father’s health. Dong Zhuo
was asleep, and Diaochan was sitting at the head of his couch. Leaning forward she gazed at the young man, with her hand pointing first at her heart,
then at the sleeping old man, and her tears fell. Lu Bu felt heartbroken.”78
Diaochan wants Lu Bu to think that she loves him and not Dong Zhuo.
Later on, when Dong Zhuo accuses her of consorting with Lu Bu, she pretends to want to commit suicide to prove her devotion to Dong Zhuo. That
is, now she wants him to think that she loves him and not Lu Bu. And so it
goes on, until, driven by anxiety and jealousy and secretly aided by Wang
Yun, Lu Bu kills his foster father.
Why did The Three Kingdoms rely on the “old” form of embedment
instead of building on the new forms compellingly explored by such works
as “Ying-ying’s Story” and The Story of the Western Wing? One possible
explanation is that, in contrast to both of them,79 The Three Kingdoms had
stronger roots in historical chronicles and folk literature.80 In fact, notwithstanding its iconic status as one of China’s “Four Classic Novels,” when
critics talk about The Three Kingdoms, they often qualify its status as novel,
referring to it now as “historical fiction,”81 now as “China’s first successful
historical novel,”82 or even as (note the extra quotation marks!) a “historical ‘novel.’”83
From the cognitive literary perspective, such qualifications are fascinating. They may reflect, among other things, our intuitive awareness that
texts that we call novels today embed mental states at a higher frequency
and by a greater variety of means than The Three Kingdoms does. Perhaps
one reason that The Three Kingdoms is considered a novel, and not, say, a fictionalized warfare chronicle, is that it often enters the cultural imagination
through other works of fiction and thus through a much more variegated
repertoire of contexts for complex embedment. For instance, the story of
the beauteous and devious Diaochan has been retold in opera, plays, films,
and manga series.84 (One of such intermedial incarnations, DiaoChan: The Rise
of the Courtesan, was performed on the London stage in 2016 and described
Literary History
169
by critics as soaring “to the heights of Shakespearean tragedy . . . and never
more so than when each character reveals his inner thoughts through soliloquy”).”85 I will revisit this point in chapter 6, with an even more drastic
example, showing how being reimagined through other media may lead to
a text being considered a novel in the absence of any complex embedments
(even those driven by deception).
And, meanwhile, we return to our narrative about the gradual expansion
of literary contexts for complex embedment. We do so by revisiting The
Plum in the Golden Vase. Written in the last decades of the sixteenth century
and building on touchstones of literati culture for its numerous classical references, it emerged as “the first Chinese novel that was wholly the creation
of one author and had no antecedent in the oral tradition.”86
5.9 Golden Lotus Drives a Servant to Suicide
As it so happens, this famous or, rather, notorious candidate for the role of
“first” Chinese novel has a very special relationship with lying. The Plum
tells the story of an upwardly mobile merchant, Hsi-men Ch’ing,87 and his
six wives and concubines, whose lives are steeped in “deception, bribery,
blackmail, profligacy, flamboyant sex, and even murder.”88 Among those
familial pastimes, lying occupies a pride of place. Every couple of chapters,
a new intrigue blossoms, often starting with a sexual transgression and then
snowballing as the characters keep eavesdropping on and framing each other.
What do scholars of Chinese literature make of those swarms of lies?
Some view them as integral to the author’s larger project of critiquing the
corruption of the contemporary imperial court. For, while the story “is
set during the reign of Emperor Huizong of Song (1101–1126 CE),” as a
political allegory, it “points clearly to contemporary Ming rulers as well.”89
Others consider the characters’ eager intriguing as a warped expression
of “competing claims of individual feeling and the constraints of conventional morality.”90 Yet others, such as the seventeenth-century commentator Chang Chu-p’o, appreciate the elaborate architectonics of the
three-thousand-page novel, in which every little detail becomes a “structural device” used by the author “to accomplish his aims without leaving a
trace.”91 For instance, as Chang explains, the “author needs [one character
to be driven to suicide after having been framed] in order to bring out as
completely as possible the viciousness of [another character],” for it is this
170
Chapter 5
second character’s “double-tongued troublemaking” that precipitates that
“needless suicide.”92
All of these are compelling arguments, and my “cognitive” perspective by no means invalidates them. Instead, it complements them. For it
makes sense to assume that in a complex artifact (such as a novel), a recurrent feature (such as a plot of deception) would end up serving multiple
cultural and structural purposes. Let us, then, take a closer look at “the
double-tongued troublemaking” that Chang refers to and see how this subplot allows the anonymous author to continuously embed complex mental
states and engage in a multilevel critique of the parties involved.
In chapter 25, when Hsi-men Ch’ing’s purchasing agent, Lai-wang,
comes back from a business trip, he learns that while he was away, Hsimen Ch’ing started an affair with his wife, Sung Hui-lien. The person who
informs Lai-wang of his wife’s infidelity is one of Hsi-men Ch’ing’s concubines, Sun Hsüeh-o. Lai-wang confronts his wife, but she claims that her
enemies “made up this tale.”93 This seems to placate him. It may help that
by now he has started his own affair with Sun Hsüeh-o.
Another of Hsi-men Ch’ing’s retainers, Kan Lai-hsing, has a grudge
against Lai-wang. He has a chance to act on his grudge when he overhears
Lai-wang, in his cups, railing angrily against Hsi-men Ch’ing and one of his
wives, P’an Chin-lien, who (as Lai-wang has been told by Sun Hsüeh-o) has
provided cover for the affair between Sung Hui-lien and Hsi-men Ch’ing.
Lai-hsing goes to P’an Chin-lien, tells her (falsely) that Lai-wang tried to pick
a fight with him, and gives her an exaggerated account of Lai-wang’s threats.
The incensed P’an Chin-lien reports Lai-wang’s (presumed) threats to
Hsi-men Ch’ing. Hsi-men Ch’ing questions Sung Hui-lien, but she swears
that Lai-wang “never said any such thing” and that Lai-hsing has “made up
this story out of whole cloth.”94 Hsi-men Ch’ing believes her and promises
to send her husband off on another long-term business trip. Sung Hui-lien
and Hsi-men Ch’ing then agree on a lie that she will tell when others notice
a new gift that Hsi-men Ch’ing is about to give her.
When P’an Chin-lien learns that instead of punishing Lai-wang, Hsimen Ch’ing plans to trust him with another prestigious errand, she convinces him that Sung Hui-lien lied to him about her husband’s intentions
and that, sooner or later, Lai-wang will take revenge on his master. Hsi-men
Ch’ing decides to drive Lai-wang away. He frames him and has him imprisoned. What follows is a long series of lies aimed at making Sung Hui-lien
Literary History
171
believe that her husband is doing fine, when, in fact, he is being severely
beaten in jail.
Sung Hui-lien eventually learns the truth and kills herself. To avoid an
official investigation of her death, Hsi-men Ch’ing bribes the court magistrate and concocts a story of Sung Hui-lien being put in charge of the
household’s silver utensils and hanging herself in fear of retribution when
a cup goes missing.
You can see, based on just one episode, what an important role deception
plays in The Plum. Now let us take a look at how the characters’ shenanigans generate complex embedments. I will keep this part of my argument
very brief because, at this point, what I have to say here may already be
self-explanatory.
When Lai-wang first confronts Sung Hui-lien about her affair with their
employer, she wants him to believe that her enemies wanted him to think
that she has been unfaithful (“some backbiting . . . person . . . must have
put you up to abusing your old lady”).95 Later, Lai-hsing wants P’an Chinlien to think that Lai-wang intends to kill her, and then P’an Chin-lien, in
her turn, wants Hsi-men Ch’ing to think that Lai-wang is keen on revenge.
Then, when Lai-wang is in jail, Hsi-men Ch’ing doesn’t want Sung Hui-lien
to know that he intends to force Lai-wang to run away by making his life
unbearable. Finally, after Sung Hui-lien kills herself, Hsi-men Ch’ing wants
the magistrates to think that the young woman was afraid of being punished for misplacing a silver cup.
Note that although I speak of Hsi-men Ch’ing’s wanting to shape the
magistrates’ thinking about the reason a young woman in his household
would want to kill herself, it falls to the reader to reconstruct those and
other mental states in this fashion. The novel itself offers almost no explicit
references to characters’ thoughts and feelings. Instead, as Tina Lu observes,
in The Plum, “bodies are depicted from the outside, and there is very little
internal monologue.” What we have, instead, are implied embedments.
That is, characters’ interiorities emerge from the “matrix of negotiation, of
motivation perceived through the prism of other peoples’ motivations.”96
Earlier I listed only a few such implied embedments. There are many
more, both in Sung Hui-lien’s story and elsewhere in the text. At every turn
of the plot, another one springs to life. To make sense of what is going on,
readers have to constantly keep in mind what one character wants another
character to think about their own or someone else’s intentions.
172
Chapter 5
Once we notice this pattern, we can speak of various ways in which
it is put to use in The Plum. We can say, along with the other scholars
quoted earlier, that it serves to present Hsi-men Ch’ing’s household as rotten to the core and thus deserving the awful retribution that awaits them;
that it critiques the corruption of contemporary rulers; and that it shows
what twisted forms individual initiative can assume when (as in the case
of women in the patriarchy) it has no better outlet than selfish intriguing.
We would do well, however, even as we commit to any of those interpretations, to acknowledge the role of the “cognitive” factor in structuring our
response to the story. For, while lying in fiction does not always call for
moral condemnation,97 it invariably opens the door to complex embedment
of mental states and, with it, to a very pointed and energetic engagement
with readers’ theory of mind. Thus, I do not think that it is a coincidence
that the text, which is considered to be an important milestone in Chinese
literary history, experiments with this kind of intense engagement. Lying is
a serious cognitive business, which is why the relentless massive lying that
we encounter in The Plum is a serious cognitive literary business.
5.10 Lies and “Face”
We have seen, with Russian literary history, how representation of complex
social emotions, such as shame, can transform a cognitive literary landscape. Again, Chinese literature developed along a very different trajectory. Still, it is worth noting how often the concern with one’s dignity, that
is, “face”—which is structurally similar in its effects to shame—motivates
characters in The Plum and is implicated with their lying.
As Haiyan Lee has shown, the notion of “face” is in and of itself an effective generator of complex embedment in fiction because it conjures the
perspective of a character thinking about how they would be perceived by
an imagined observer.98 In The Plum, given Hsi-men Ch’ing’s social ambitions, the worry about face is ever present. Consider, for instance, a debacle in chapter 12, when P’an Chin-lien first fools around with a page boy
and then claims that it never happened and that her enemies cooked up
the whole story. P’an Chin-lien’s lie works because her loyal servant, P’ang
Ch’un-mei, exploits Hsi-men Ch’ing’s fear of losing face with his neighbors
if he would punish P’an Chin-lien on (as she claims) false premises.
Literary History
173
As Ch’un-mei puts it, “This is all something fabricated by someone who
is jealous of [P’an Chin-lien] and me. [Hsi-men Ch’ing], you ought to think
what you’re doing, or you’ll only make an ugly reputation for yourself,
which won’t sound any too good when it gets abroad.”99 Ch’un-mei wants
Hsi-men Ch’ing to imagine what other people will think when they find out
about his rash behavior.100 Her manipulative invocation of those judgmental others bolsters a lie—for, in the same breath, she also wants Hsi-men
Ch’ing to believe that the reason P’an Chin-lien was accused of adultery is
that other wives want to bring her down.
A lie, thus, can gain in persuasiveness when paired with a reminder of
one’s social vulnerability (i.e., dependence on other people’s opinions).
This is what happens in chapter 25, that is, the story of the banishment
of Lai-wang and suicide of his wife, which I discussed earlier. When P’an
Chin-lien wants Hsi-men Ch’ing to believe that Lai-wang considers him
his enemy, she makes Hsi-men Ch’ing worry about what other people will
think about him. Thus, she refers to “allegations” that Lai-wang makes “in
front of people” and assures him that “such allegations would not redound
to [Hsi-men Ch’ing’s] credit.”101
Similarly, when P’an Chin-lien wants Hsi-men Ch’ing to think that Sung
Hui-lien conceals from Hsi-men Ch’ing the true extent of the enmity that
Lai-wang bears him (“Whatever that woman has had to say for some time
now has only been spoken on behalf of that slave of yours”), she, once
again, brings in public opinion. If Lai-wang defrauds Hsi-men Ch’ing of
his money (something that, P’an Chin-lien implies, he surely intends to
do), Hsi-men Ch’ing will be too embarrassed to “accuse him of anything,”
because everybody will have known that he has stolen Lai-wang’s wife.102
And, again, when Lai-wang is already in jail, tortured for a crime he
didn’t commit, and P’an Chin-lien learns that Hsi-men Ch’ing is writing
a note to the judge asking for his release, she lobbies for “[polishing] off
this slave once and for all” by planting an image of jeering neighbors in
Hsi-men Ch’ing’s mind. Lai-wang, she claims, shall always hold a grudge
against his master, even if Hsi-men Ch’ing will go as far as marrying him to
someone else, to make up for having taken Sung Hui-lien from him.
For instance, if Lai-wang comes to “report something” to Hsi-men Ch’ing
and sees him together with Sung Hui-lien, wouldn’t Lai-wang get “angry”?
And would Sung Hui-lien then have “to stand up” to greet her ex-husband?
174
Chapter 5
Wouldn’t that be embarrassing for Hsi-men Ch’ing? As P’an Chin-lien puts
it, “Just to start out with, this alone wouldn’t look right. If it got around,
not only would your neighbors and relatives laugh at you, but even the
members of your own household, high and low, would not be able to take
you seriously.”103
Finally, P’an Chin-lien uses the appeal to face to finish off the poor Sung
Hui-lien. She does it by making Sung Hui-lien imagine that other people will
never believe her side of the story. Here is how this is set up by the text: After
Lai-wang is driven away, just as P’an Chin-lien hoped he would be, she goes
between Sun Hsüeh-o and Sung Hui-lien, reporting lies that can’t fail to stir
up a “sense of grievance and desire for revenge.” First, she wants Sun Hsüeho to think that Sung Hui-lien knows that Sun Hsüeh-o told Lai-wang about
Sung Hui-lien’s affair with Hsi-men Ch’ing (which is not true) and that she
blames Sun Hsüeh-o for making Hsi-men Ch’ing angry and for making him
want to get rid of Lai-wang. Then she goes to Sung Hui-lien, whom she wants
to believe that people in the compound think that she has never cared about
her husband. So she reports to Sung Hui-lien—falsely—that Sun Hsüeh-o
tells everyone that Sung Hui-lien is an “old hand at inveigling” her masters
“into adultery” and that the tears that she sheds about her husband “are
only crocodile tears.”104 These lies precipitate an ugly standoff between Sung
Hui-lien and Sun Hsüeh-o, which pushes Sung Hui-lien over the brink and
leads to her second, and this time successful, suicide attempt.
5.11 Beyond Lies and Shame
Some comparisons between the early Chinese and the early Russian novel
are worth highlighting here. For instance, both The Plum and Eugene Onegin (Pushkin’s “novel in verse”) feature continuous embedment of complex
mental states. Both cultivate such embedment by having their characters
behave deceitfully (“How early he was able to dissemble”) and by motivating them through complex social emotions, such as shame. (Onegin kills
his best friend in a meaningless duel because he is afraid that others will
consider him a coward if he attempts to seek peace.) One important difference between the two texts is that Pushkin talks about mental states—those
of his characters, his readers, and his poetic persona—incessantly, while the
anonymous author of The Plum leaves it to the reader to infer thoughts and
feelings behind behavior.
Literary History
175
Another point of comparison, as far as the construction of complex
embedments is concerned, is the role played in both novels by references
to other texts. Eugene Onegin is deeply entrenched in the European literary
tradition.105 The conversation about French, English, and German prose and
poetry that the implied author is having with the reader supplies its own
steady stream of complex embedments. For instance, the narrator wants his
reader to consider the ironic implications of the fact that the main female
protagonist, Tatiana, imagines Onegin as the hero of the last novel by Samuel
Richardson, The History of Sir Charles Grandison, a man who is not motivated
by shame and is opposed to dueling in principle. As the narrator assures us
coolly, “our hero, whoever he might be, / quite surely was no Grandison.”106
A similar conversation is taking place in The Plum. Its frequent evocations
of classic Chinese songs and poems presuppose ongoing mutual awareness
between the implied author and the implied reader. For instance, when
Sung Hui-lien wants to convince Hsi-men Ch’ing that her husband would
never curse and threaten Hsi-men Ch’ing behind his back, she asserts that,
were Lai-wang to do such a thing, he would effectively be biting the hand
that feeds him and he is not that stupid. As she puts it,
If he should:
Live off King Chou’s largesse,
And yet call King Chou a villain,
on whom could he depend to make a living?107
Sung Hui-lien’s mention of King Chou comes close on the heels of an ear-
lier reference to the ancient Book of Documents (Shu-ching, 書經). That ref-
erence, according to The Plum’s translator, David Tod Roy, tacitly likens
Hsi-men Ch’ing to King Chou, the “evil last ruler” of the Shang dynasty.108
So, here, while Sung Hui-lien seems to want to emphasize the implausibility of her husband’s bad-mouthing Hsi-men Ch’ing, she accomplishes
quite the opposite with her quote: she badmouths him herself. For, as Roy
explains, the “unmistakable implication” of what she says “is that Hsi-men
Ch’ing himself is an evil last ruler.”109
That neither Sung Hui-lien nor Hsi-men Ch’ing is aware of this implication makes their mutually pleasing exchange profoundly ironic. The
implied author wants the reader to know he considers Hsi-men Ch’ing evil,
but he also wants us to know that Hsi-men Ch’ing doesn’t realize that the
argument that he apparently finds convincing is a classical reference that
condemns him. Nor is he aware of the grave innuendo of being likened to
176
Chapter 5
a last ruler—something that the implied author wants the reader to keep
in mind as we follow the household’s rejoicing at the birth of Hsi-men
Ch’ing’s son, Kuan-ko. Finally, we know that Sung Hui-lien doesn’t know,
when she unwittingly calls her lover a villain, that he is about to behave
like one toward her and her husband—another nuance in the ongoing giveand-take between the author and the reader.
Earlier, in chapter 4 of this book, I pointed out the ambiguous position
of The Plum in Chinese literary canon—which some readers view as a work
of pornography and others treat as a literary masterpiece. I also showed
that scholars who consider it a masterpiece focus on the novel’s intentionality, arguing, for instance, that the text’s implied author seems to want
to remind “the reader of the presence of the narrator somewhere between
himself and the story.”110
That the “cognitive” perspective would strongly support these kinds of
hyperintentionalist interpretations of The Plum is not at all surprising. The
history of the novel as a genre involves two developments entwined in such
a way that it is difficult to say where one ends and the other begins. Perhaps
I may be allowed to call it a “coevolution” of readers and writers. On the
one hand, the novel may be said to constantly cast about for new compelling ways to embed complex mental states of its characters, implied author,
and the reader. On the other hand, at least some of its readers may be said
to constantly cast about for new ways to read complex mental states into
the text. Those are readers who have had significant exposure to literary
fiction and thus tend to find characters’ motivations not as clear as do less
experienced readers, which is to say that they are more comfortable with
ambiguity than are less experienced readers.111 They are also more eager to
look for intentionality cues in their social environment, which may translate into a greater awareness of the conversation that the implied author is
having with the reader.
It should be pointed out that the comparison between The Plum and
Eugene Onegin still holds when we think of these different types of readers.
For instance, Eugene Onegin was a staple of the high-school syllabus in Soviet
Russia, but the depth of its engagement with the European literary tradition
was not acknowledged. It took Vladimir Nabokov’s Commentary (1964) to
place Pushkin’s novel in a sustained conversation with its European predecessors and thus open up a new layer of mindreading involving the author
and his audience. That Nabokov was an émigré writer—unconstrained by
Literary History
177
Soviet nationalistic censorship112 and professionally trained (so to speak) in
the intricacies of literary mindreading—shows how the political and the
personal can get intertwined in the quest for new ways of reading complex
embedment into a text.
I am also certain that, today, plenty of readers of Eugene Onegin are happily unaware of the embedments arising from its implied author’s oblique
references to the European literary tradition, just as plenty of readers of The
Plum do not think twice of the significance of Sung Hui-lien’s mention of
King Chou. Although some of the mindreading practiced by literary scholars makes it to the cultural mainstream, plenty of it remains in a category
of its own.
So let us say that we belong to the group of readers who see The Plum as
“a model of the literati novel genre maturing in the sixteenth century” and
that we thus acknowledge its unprecedentedly innovative appeal to lateMing-dynasty readers’ theory of mind.113 We can further ask how different aspects of this novel’s mindreading profile—which include deception,
psychological manipulation of one character by another, and the implied
author’s ironic appeals to the implied audience—were amplified in such
mid-eighteenth-century classics as Wu Ching-Tzu’s The Scholars (Rulin waishi, 儒林外史) and Cao’s Dream of the Red Chamber. Let us take a quick look
at these two novels, focusing specifically on their potential to keep their
readers steadily embedding mental states on a high level.
5.12 “Lust of the Mind”
Lying continues to drive complex embedment both in The Scholars (1750)
and in Dream of the Red Chamber (ca. 1750–1760). Indeed, a separate study
can be written on how much these novels depend on lying and on the role
of social class and gender in the construction and consumption of lies.
Also, just like in The Plum, lying often goes hand in hand with a concern
about face. Yet both lying and fear of losing face are also treated now in
ways that make possible distinctly new forms of complex embedment. For
instance, in The Scholars, they can be combined with a nearly direct appeal
to the reader, while in Dream, they are used to highlight important features
of its characters’ psychology.
Let us start with The Scholars, a satirical novel about educated gentlemen
vying for plum positions in civil service. At one point, early in the story, a
178
Chapter 5
magistrate named Shih wants Wang Mien, a peasant who paints exquisite
pictures of flowers, to pay him a visit, so that one Mr. Wei, a distinguished
scholar and Shih’s superior, can meet this homespun prodigy. Wang Mien
turns down the magistrate’s invitation (which he correctly recognizes as a
thinly veiled order) because he is a man of independent spirit who doesn’t
want to curry favor with the high and mighty. His refusal, however, creates a problem for several people who now worry about the effect that
this insubordination may have on other people’s perception of their social
status.
One of those people is bailiff Chai, whom the magistrate employed as his
messenger. To help Chai save face, Wang’s friend and neighbor, Old Chin,
suggests that Chai lies to Magistrate Shih and tells him that Wang Mien
is ill. That is, Old Chin doesn’t want Shih to know that Wang Mien doesn’t
consider his invitation an honor. Instead he wants him to think that Wang
Mien would like to come and only his illness prevents him from doing so.
Magistrate Shih, however, does not believe the bailiff’s report:
When Magistrate Shih heard the bailiff’s report, he thought, “How can the fellow be ill? It’s all the fault of this rascal Chai. He goes down to the villages like
a donkey in a lion’s hide, and he must have scared this painter fellow out of his
wits. Wang Mien has never seen an official before in his life. He’s afraid to come.
But my patron charged me personally to get this man, and if I fail to produce him,
Mr. Wei will think me incompetent. I had better go to the village myself to call on
him. When he sees what an honour I’m doing him, he’ll realize nobody wants to
make trouble for him and won’t be afraid to see me. Then I’ll take him to call on
my patron, and my patron will appreciate the smart way I’ve handled it.”
Then, however, it occurred to him that his subordinates might laugh at the
idea of a county magistrate calling on a mere peasant. Yet Mr. Wei had spoken of
Wang Mien with the greatest respect. “If Mr. Wei respects him, I should respect
him ten times as much,” Magistrate Shih reflected. “And if I stoop in order to
show respect to talent, future compilers of the local chronicles will certainly
devote a chapter to my praise. Then my name will be remembered for hundreds
of years. Why shouldn’t I do it?”114
This passage is an avalanche of complex embedments. Magistrate Shih
thinks that Wang Mien only wants him to think that he is ill because he is,
in reality, afraid of government officials. This leads him to believe that if he
visits the humble rustic in his own august person, Wang Mien will realize
that nobody intends him any ill. Readers, of course, know that Shih is mistaken in his assessment of Wang Mien’s feelings—a bit of dramatic irony here.
Literary History
179
The real joke of the situation, however, comes with the sly conversation
that Wu Ching-Tzu is having with his readers. Shih fondly imagines that
“future compilers of local chronicles” will devote a whole chapter to his
praise. And, as a matter of fact, Wu does devote a couple of pages to him,
and these are the pages that we are reading. Wu wants us to be aware that
Shih imagines that future generations will think that he wanted to “show
respect to talent,” and he also wants us to suspect that Shih’s hopes may have
been disappointed. The magistrate is not an unsympathetic character, but
because we know that he wanted us to admire him for his respect for talent,
we are not sure anymore that he is worthy of our admiration. What has
started out as a series of complex embedments arising from the lies and the
characters’ concerns about “face” is gradually turned into an exploration of
the mutual awareness between the implied reader and the implied author.
The fear of losing face is also a powerful motivator for many characters
in Dream of the Red Chamber, which tells the story of two lovesick cousins, a
girl named Lin Dai-yu and a boy named Jia Bao-yu, kept apart by their karmic destiny and, more immediately, by their family’s ambitions. For Dai-yu,
however, the concern about face can take a peculiar form of neurotic overthinking of other people’s intentions. Such overthinking is, of course, Daiyu’s trademark psychological trait, something that has been known both to
exasperate and attract the novel’s readers. Let us consider some examples of
Dai-yu’s anxious social projections aimed, ostensibly, at saving face; driven,
at least partly, by self-deception; and embroiling the reader in guessing and
second-guessing of everyone’s intentions.
At one point, Dai-yu and Bao-yu go to visit their other cousin Xue Baochai, whom Dai-yu considers her rival for Bao-yu’s affections, not only
because of her beauty and sophistication but also because her mother, old
Mrs. Xue, is a rich widow, whose fortune would come in handy were Baoyu to marry Bao-chai. As they are sitting at Mrs. Xue’s house, chatting and
drinking tea and wine, Dai-yu’s maid, prompted by another maid, brings her
a hand warmer. Dai-yu then scolds her for it. Neither Bao-yu nor Bao-chai
says anything, though for different reasons. Bao-yu knows “perfectly well”
that Dai-yu’s carefully phrased rebuke was “really intended for him,” but
he makes “no reply, beyond laughing good-humoredly,” whereas Bao-chai,
“long accustomed to Dai-yu’s peculiar ways,” simply ignores her words.
Mrs. Xue, however, is deaf to such intricacies and takes Dai-yu’s complaint at its face value. She points out to Dai-yu that it was “nice” of Dai-yu’s
180
Chapter 5
maids to think of her, because she often feels chilly. Dai-yu responds thus:
“You don’t understand, Aunt. . . . It doesn’t matter here, with you; but
some people might be deeply offended at the sight of one of my maids
rushing in with a hand-warmer. It’s as though I thought my hosts couldn’t
supply one themselves if I needed it. Instead of saying how thoughtful the
maid was, they would put it down to my arrogance and lack of breeding.”115
Dai-yu claims to be imagining people who’d think that she thinks that her
hosts are not taking good care of her. Though presented as an attempt to
save face, her own and Mrs. Xue’s, this complex embedment is an expression of the exhausting self-monitoring carried on by the neurotic and powerless Dai-yu. Not surprisingly, instead of appreciating her sentiments, Mrs.
Xue can only respond with the head-scratching, “You are altogether too
sensitive, thinking of things like that. . . . Such a thought would never have
crossed my mind.”116
Here is another example of a face-saving enterprise devolving into an
anxious overattribution of intentions. At Bao-chai’s birthday party, while
the family is watching a play performed by a group of professional child
actors, her aunt, Wang Xi-feng, comments slyly on the resemblance
between “someone we know” and a beautifully made-up child who plays
the main heroine. Bao-chai and Bao-yu merely nod without responding
(once again, they know better), but another young relative, Xiang-yun,
is “tactless enough” to blurt out that the actor looks like Dai-yu. Bao-yu
shoots “a quick glance in [Xiang-yun’s] direction; but [it’s] too late,” for
now the other guests catch on to the resemblance and start laughing.117
Shortly after the party breaks up, the offended Xiang-yun orders her
maid to start packing. Bao-yu overhears it and attempts to make her change
her mind, explaining that the only reason he gave her that look is that
he “was worried for [her] sake.” He claims to have known that Xiang-yun
didn’t know how sensitive Dai-yu can be and to have been “afraid that [Daiyu] would be offended with [Xiang-yun].” Xiang-yun won’t have any of it.
She knows that Bao-yu is not being emotionally honest with her, though she
can’t, perhaps, identify the exact meaning of his maneuvers. The way she
reads it (or claims to read it) is that Bao-yu’s glance implied that everyone
thinks that she is “not in the same class” as Dai-yu and hence mustn’t make
fun of “the young lady of the house.”118
I condense their conversation here, but you can see even from this
condensed version that it consists of a series of complex embedments all
Literary History
181
involving Xiang-yun’s perception of Bao-yu’s intentions regarding Dai-yu’s
feelings and leaving it up to readers to decide which interpretation of those
intentions they would find most plausible.
But then it turns out that Dai-yu overheard Bao-yu’s conversation with
Xiang-yun, so the real fun begins. First, Dai-yu “coldly” explains to Bao-yu
that even though he didn’t compare her with the child actor and didn’t
laugh when others did, his secret thoughts, of which she’s apparently the
best judge, implicate him severely. In the quote that follows, the italics are
in the original:
“You would like to have made the comparison; you would like to have laughed,”
said Dai-yu. “To me your way of not comparing and not laughing was worse than
the others’ laughing and comparing!”
Bao-yu found this unanswerable.
“However,” Dai-yu went on, “that I could forgive. But what about that look
you gave Yun? Just what did you mean by that? I think I know what you meant.
You meant to warn her that she would cheapen herself by joking with me as an
equal. Because she’s an Honourable and her uncle’s a marquis and I’m only the
daughter of a commoner, she mustn’t risk joking with me, because it would be
so degrading for her if I were to answer back. That’s what you meant, isn’t it?
Oh yes, you had the kindest intentions. Only unfortunately she didn’t want your
kind intentions and got angry with you in spite of them. So you tried to make
it up with her at my expense, by telling her how touchy I am and how easily I
get upset. You were afraid she might offend me, were you? As if it were any business of yours whether she offended me or not, or whether or not I got angry with
her!”119
The reason that Bao-yu and Dai-yu often find themselves pulled into this
kind of labyrinthine social reasoning is that their psychological profiles—or,
shall we say, their mindreading profiles—are uniquely and tragically suited
to each other. While Dai-yu overthinks people’s intentions, Bao-yu overreads them, being afflicted with the condition described in the novel as
“lust of the mind” (yiyin, 意淫). This condition has been interpreted by
critics in a wide variety of ways, so the interpretation that I give you here
reflects specifically my “cognitive” perspective. From this perspective, “lust
of the mind” means that Bao-yu feels the need to know and share the emotions of girls, dozens of them, servants, cousins, and young aunts, populating the Jias’ sprawling aristocratic households—an empathetic drive hardly
compatible with his position as the heir on whom the family’s hopes of
future prosperity are pinned.120
182
Chapter 5
The male protagonist’s passionate desire to understand the feelings of
women is something that is hard to imagine in the universe of Hsi-men
Ch’ing (from The Plum in the Golden Vase). Indeed, the scenes of intense
mindreading and misreading that we get in Dream are something quite
unprecedented in the literary history of medieval China.121 I will conclude
this section with another one of such scenes, which starts, once again, as an
ostensible endeavor to save face, implies self-deception, and embroils the
reader in complex and ambiguous mindreading attributions.
Bao-yu, having spent his early childhood cosseted by his loving grandmother and other relatives, is finally forced to start his formal education.
On the first day of school, he decides to visit Dai-yu to say good-bye, for
he won’t see her now for most of the day. After chatting with her for a
while, he is ready to tear himself away, but Dai-yu stops him to ask if he’s
“going to say good-bye to [his] cousin Bao-chai” too. In response, Bao-yu
smiles but says nothing and goes “straight off to school with [his friend]
Qin Zhong.”122
How are readers to make sense of this exchange? While there are several
different ways to interpret Bao-yu’s smile, it’s important to note that all of
them seem to involve complex embedments, some reaching even to the
fourth and fifth level. For instance, we may say that Bao-yu smiles because
he thinks that he knows that Dai-yu doesn’t really want him to stop by Baochai’s room to say good-bye. That is, he thinks that he knows that Dai-yu
(sensitive as she always is to how her behavior may be perceived by others)
doesn’t want anyone to think that she thinks she has any right to usurp Baoyu’s attention on this particular morning.
Moreover, by telling us that Bao-yu goes straight to school instead of
indeed stopping by Bao-chai’s room first, Cao wants us to be aware not just
of the clear preference that Bao-yu has for Dai-yu but also of the tortuous
way in which the admission of this preference was extracted from him. Baoyu certainly hasn’t planned to play favorites this morning—it’s not likely
that he’d even been thinking about it when he stopped by Dai-yu’s room—
but Dai-yu’s self-conscious remark has made him express his feelings. Ironically, this is what Dai-yu would have wanted—even though she would
never admit that to anyone. Bao-yu’s smile thus can also be interpreted as
his realization that Dai-yu has just made him newly aware that he likes her
more than he likes Bao-chai—and that she did it without being implicated
in doing so and perhaps not even intending it.
Literary History
183
I expect that not every reader will agree with my interpretation of Baoyu’s smile. What’s important, however, is that even if you disagree with this
interpretation and propose your own, yours is still likely to feature a complex embedment of mental states. That is, to do justice to a nuanced psychological dynamic conjured up by Cao, we have to embed mental states
on at least the third level, even if their exact content and configuration
differ from one reader to another.
5.13 Conclusion: “Cheater Detection” or “Destruction
of the Subject-Matter by the Form”?
As we are nearing the end of our conversation about lying, here is the question that this long chapter has been begging for a while: Why is lying so
integral to representation of literary consciousness? One answer offers itself
immediately. As developmental psychologists put it, “lying, in essence, is
theory of mind in action.”123 Given the centrality of mindreading and misreading to human communication, it is not terribly surprising that writers
would exaggerate this aspect of human sociality to make their narratives
more engaging.
We can stop at this, or we can indulge our critical perversity and dig
deeper. Why, we may ask, should this particular aspect of sociality be of
such interest to readers? After all, literature can (and does) play with mindreading uncertainty in many other ways. Why keep returning to deception?
One way to respond to this question is to roll out a couple of heavy
guns. By that, I mean turning to cognitive adaptations—all connected with
mindreading—that evolved hundreds of thousands of years ago and still
underlie much of our social functioning today. We may start with the concept of cheater detection. According to the founders of cognitive evolutionary psychology, John Tooby and Leda Cosmides, detecting cheaters in
situations involving social exchange was an adaptive problem faced by our
ancestors, and the solution to this problem was the evolution of a “cheaterdetection mechanism.” This mechanism “looks for cheaters”; that is, “it
looks for people who have intentionally taken the benefit, specified in a
social exchange rule, without satisfying the requirement [of the cost].” The
appraisal of intentions is crucial: the mechanism “is not good at detecting violations caused by innocent mistakes, even if they result in someone
being cheated.”124
184
Chapter 5
Now remember that, on some level, our mindreading adaptations do
not distinguish between mental states of real people and those of fictional
characters. This means that once we attribute an intention to cheat to a
fictional character, this cognitive output feeds into the cheater-detection
mechanism. Evolved for detecting cheaters in real life, this mechanism now
has no choice but to start detecting them in made-up stories as well. So we
can say that one way in which works of fiction compel our attention is that
they keep our cheater-detection mechanisms up and running.125
Think of one of the earliest known examples of lying in literature. Gilgamesh promises to Utnapishtim to stay awake for six days and seven nights
in exchange for the secret of immortality; then he promptly falls asleep;
then, upon awakening, seven days later, he denies that he has slept at all.
Behold a cheater! Gilgamesh wants the benefit (i.e., immortality) without
having satisfied the requirement (i.e., not sleeping).
Of course, in spite of Utnapishtim’s grim observation that “all men are
deceivers,” The Epic of Gilgamesh doesn’t actually feature many instances
of cheating. So we should not overstate the role that our cheater-detection
mechanism may play in our interaction with this text. It is merely one
of numerous inducements to pay close attention that the story offers—
important (no question about that, in the case of the four-thousand-yearold artifact!)—but, still, one of many.
Here comes another heavy gun. Our species also evolved to pay attention to sexual deception. (Ancestors who didn’t do that aren’t our ancestors, because they didn’t leave descendants.)126 This means that, today, we
are attuned to a broad variety of mental states involved in sexual deception,
including mental states that we attribute to fictional characters. When we
are certain that Othello is wrong in thinking that Desdemona is in love
with Cassio, it is because we have been carefully checking Iago’s allegations
against what we know about Desdemona’s feelings, while also pondering
Iago’s motivations.
It may seem that just these types of cheating—seeking to get a benefit
without incurring a cost and sexual deception—would account for a lot of
lying that takes place in literature. Thus, we have another possible answer
to the question of just why lying is so integral to representation of fictional
consciousness. We can say that complex embedments of mental states still
often arise from plots of deception—even though other, more “sophisticated” contexts of embedment have long been available—because writers
Literary History
185
intuitively rely on social contexts that are guaranteed, by our evolutionary
history, to sustain their readers’ attention.
Then there is also the question of genre. Some genres, such as detective
and spy stories, suspense thrillers, and romances, derive most of their emotional punch from deception. This is to say that such stories are deemed
successful to the extent to which their readers are caught up emotionally in
the project of identifying liars, understanding their motivation, and assigning different moral values to different instances of lying. In contrast, other
genres (and here we are, once more, on the treacherous critical ground of
drawing a distinction between “popular” and “literary” fiction) may still
exploit lying for its capacity to generate complex embedments, but the
affective charge of those narratives is not tied to their plots of deception.
Let us look at a couple of such texts and see what kind of emotional
response they seem to be eliciting from their readers. For instance, in Shakespeare’s Sonnet 138, “When My Love Swears That She Is Made of Truth,”
lying repeatedly serves as a source of complex embedments, yet it also
appears that its readers are encouraged not to care about the grave sexual
and social repercussions of deception that the speaker and his beloved practice on each other:
When my love swears that she is made of truth,
I do believe her, though I know she lies,
That she might think me some untutored youth,
Unlearnèd in the world’s false subtleties.
Thus vainly thinking that she thinks me young,
Although she knows my days are past the best,
Simply I credit her false-speaking tongue:
On both sides thus is simple truth suppressed.
But wherefore says she not she is unjust?
And wherefore say not I that I am old?
Oh, love’s best habit is in seeming trust,
And age in love loves not to have years told.
Therefore I lie with her and she with me,
And in our faults by lies we flattered be.
What is going on in this sonnet? Or, to put it differently, what complex
embedments do we process in order to make sense of it? The speaker’s
beloved wants him to think that she doesn’t lie to him. He realizes that he
is willing to deceive himself by trusting her because he likes to think that
she thinks that he is young enough to believe her. But he also knows that
186
Chapter 5
she doesn’t really think that he is young, which means that perhaps she
knows that he has his own reasons for wanting to believe her even when
he knows that she is lying. Moreover, she knows that he wants her to think
that he trusts her (for “love’s best habit is in seeming trust”), and so forth.
Now let us look at the emotional value of the sonnet. One narrative generated by all those complex embedments is quite sad. The speaker’s beloved
is cheating on him, while he is meditating on his old age, her youth, and
the vagaries of self-deception. (Were we to go for a crude pseudoevolutionary reading, we’d even say that this is a downright tragedy: the guy is a
genetic dead end.) Yet the same poem also tells another story: that of a
poet enchanted by the pliability of the word “lie” and rounding it all off
triumphantly with a double entendre built around that word. Readers, too:
whatever negative emotions this account of sexual infidelity and powerlessness may be expected to elicit in us, the last two lines invite us to join the
fun that is to be had when strong emotions fade into delightful wordplay.
To see what Shakespeare is doing here—and why our reflexive interest in
keeping tabs on a cheater does not account for it—we may want to turn to
the German poet and philosopher J. C. Friedrich von Schiller and the Russian cognitive psychologist Lev S. Vygotsky.127 It takes a “true master,” wrote
Schiller in 1794, to know how to “destroy the subject-matter by the form.”128
Yes, agreed Vygotsky in 1925, and the way this destruction works is that the
reader is made to experience two opposing emotions, “developed together
and with equal force”: one elicited by the subject matter of the poem, another
“by the artistic form and the particular arrangement of the material.”129
A cognitive literary critic may add here that the destruction of subject matter by the form introduces more embedded mental states. For instance, the
embedments discussed earlier (e.g., “she knows that he wants her to think
that he trusts her”) all focus on the thoughts and feelings of the speaker and
his beloved. But the concluding double entendre involving the verb “lie”
shifts that pattern by orienting us toward mental states of the speaker and
the reader. The reason for this shift is that puns come with their own built-in
intentionality: they signal the punner’s desire to draw the reader’s attention
to the form of the word.
Let us now bring it all together: evolution, Schiller, Vygotsky, lies, and
embedment. Our evolutionarily conditioned interest in deception may
very well be integral to our interaction with Shakespeare’s sonnet, but it
Literary History
187
contributes little to the sonnet’s artistic value. That value is generated, at
least in part, by the clash of the two contradictory affects: one driven by the
content of the poem, another, by its form. The melancholy affect arising
from the content is entangled with the complex embedments associated
with the speaker, who reflects on various mutual deceptions that make the
relationship possible.
But the joy arising from the form is also entangled with complex embedments, and it starts developing even before we arrive to the final lines that
contain the double entendre. For, is not our awareness of the complexity of the speaker’s emotions in and of itself a source of positive affect, as
it reminds us that we are all interesting beings here, endowed with rich
inner lives, attuned to the intricacies of our social environment, apparently
with cognitive resources to spare? The concluding pun adds a nice nuance,
but do not overestimate its role! Most of the poem’s heavy lifting—that is,
of “destroying” the depressing subject matter by the delightful form—has
already been done by the time we read the pun.130
Have we seen this dynamic before? Yes, we have. Recall the stanza from
Pushkin’s Eugene Onegin that lists lies practiced by the main protagonist
as he seduces various ladies of his acquaintance. There, too, the “heavy”
subject matter of lying is undercut by the poetic form. For the stanza that
starts with “How early he was able to dissemble” contains not just multiple
instances of deception but also the narrator’s amused reflection on Eugene’s
amorous machinations—not to mention the sheer delight induced by its
pattern of sounds and rhymes in those who read this “novel in verse” in its
original language, for that, too, goes a long way toward destroying the negative affect that the protagonist’s treacherous, antisocial behavior could, in
principle, induce in us.
In fact, it seems that this dynamic—that is, the destruction of such critical a subject matter as cheater detection by a form—has been present in
literature for some time. Perhaps the best genre to illustrate this dynamic is
picaresque, for it is unequivocally built around deception. Since its earlier
days, from Lazarillo de Tormes (1554) and Mateo Alemán’s Guzmán de Alfarache (1599–1604) to Miguel de Cervantes’s Rinconete y Cortadillo (1613),
the picaresque novel focused on protagonists who cheated and lied their
way to economic survival. Yet the complex embedments arising from the
shenanigans of a resourceful picaro were often interlaced with complex
188
Chapter 5
embedments arising from the conversation that the narrator was having
with readers. Consider the opening paragraph of Guzmán de Alfarache:
I was so desirous, curious reader, to relate to you my own adventures, that I had
almost commenced speaking of myself without making any mention of my family, with which some sophist or other would not have failed to accuse me: “Be not
so hasty, friend Guzman,” would he have said, “let us begin, if you please, from
the definition, before we proceed to speak of the thing defined. Inform us, in the
first place, who were your parents; you can then relate to us at your pleasure those
exploits which you have so immoderate a desire to entertain us with.”131
There are many different ways to map out this paragraph in terms of its
embedded mental states. We can say, for instance, that the implied author
wants us to believe that the narrator is afraid of being censored by a pedant;
or that the narrator wants his ideal (i.e., “curious”) reader to feel superior to
an obtuse reader (a “sophist”) who is not quite aware of what kind of story he
or she is about to hear and thus demands a conventional opening; or that the
implied author wants to tease the reader as he defers the actual account of
his adventures (which is, presumably, something that the reader is impatient
to hear) and instead gives in to the convention of lengthy self-introduction
(which, he expects, or pretends to expect, the reader will find tedious).
Swamped by complex embedments, and we haven’t even gotten to the
story’s first official swindle! By the time we do, we will be frequently dealing with two parallel sets of embedments: those involving mental states of
liars and their victims and those involving mental states of the narrator, the
implied reader, and the various imagined onlookers who are similar in their
function to the “sophist” of the opening paragraph. The affect associated
with the act of deception as such—for example, with its negative communal
repercussions, with private sufferings experienced by the people immediately
involved—rubs against the affect arising from our awareness of the playful
conversation that we, as implied readers, are having with the narrator.
The presence of complex embedments involving mental states of the
critic, the narrator, and the reader may thus be the reason that the picaresque is considered “one of the earliest traditions (perhaps the earliest) in
the history of the novel.”132 For take those mental states out, and you will
end up with a mere trickster story. I use the word “mere” advisedly, not to
downplay this genre’s prominence in the world’s folklore. In fact, the trickster story often demonstrates the crucial role of complex embedment in the
construction of narrative, for the trickster wants his victims to think that his
Literary History
189
intentions are different from what they really are. Still, literature, as we know
it today, happens when authors move beyond straightforward accounts of
deception—that is, when they begin to “destroy” that particular “subjectmatter by the form”—even while still benefiting from the presence of lying
characters.
Let us conclude our conversation about writers simultaneously using
liars and moving beyond their lies with another “novel full of deception
and self-deception,”133 also set in Spain, albeit four hundred years later, and
written in English: Ben Lerner’s Leaving the Atocha Station (2011). Lerner’s
protagonist is an American poet on a fellowship in Madrid. Unlike a picaro,
he lies not so much to ensure his economic survival (although he is receiving money from a Madrid-based foundation for a “research-driven poem”
about the Spanish Civil War, which he has no intention of writing)134 but to
create and maintain a certain image of himself among his Spanish friends
and (prospective) lovers. He lies about his parents, about his feelings, about
what he is doing now, and about what he plans to do next. Those lies contribute their fair share of complex embedments, yet—a dynamic similar to
what we have seen in “When My Love Swears That She Is Made of Truth”—
they also don’t matter.
This is to say that Adam’s lies—even the ones that seem to be quite
atrocious—have no real social consequences. Neither his Spanish friends nor
his parents take them seriously. For instance, when Adam confesses on the
phone to his parents that he has been telling people in Spain that his “mom
was dead or gravely ill and that [his] dad was a fascist,” his mother and
father, both professional psychologists, are “confused, but not upset.” They
accept his explanation that he has been saying those things in order “to get
sympathy” and turn the conversation to other, more pressing, matters.135
In fact, it seems that Adam’s lying functions primarily as a trigger for selfreflexivity, and that self-reflexivity is what generates the majority of the novel’s complex embedments. For instance, when Adam feels disoriented in the
foreign social environment (as he does for most of the novel), he responds
by faking his emotional reactions and vividly describing involved mental
states that he would experience were he to actually have those reactions.
Thus, when one of his new acquaintances, Carlos (of whose exact stance
toward himself Adam is not sure but whom he is beginning to hate),
observes, in the presence of several other people, that it “must be an interesting time to be an American in Spain” and asks Adam what he thinks
190
Chapter 5
about “everything,” Adam adapts a series of postures that, he hopes, will be
read by the onlookers as signaling his sophistication and Carlos’s stupidity:
“I looked off in the distance as though I was making an effort to formulate
my complex reaction so simply even an idiot like him might understand.
Then, as if concluding this was an impossible task, I said I didn’t know.”136
Does the shaft hit the mark? Are Carlos’s friends now convinced that
no reasonably intelligent person would ask the kind of question that Carlos just asked, and do they appreciate Adam’s earnest, if ultimately futile,
attempt to tackle it? There is no telling. For all that we know, they may be
thinking of something else, completely unrelated to Adam’s hopeful performance of his emotional complexity.137
Yet Adam is not a deluded/unreliable narrator. He is open to revising his
perceptions if new evidence presents itself (e.g., if Carlos turns out to be less
hostile to Adam than he thought he was), and he can contemplate critically
his endeavors to shape other people’s impressions of him. This, of course,
supplies more grist for the mill of complex embedment.
Here, for instance, is a characteristically funny moment when Adam
reaches for his notebook to write down a potentially poetic observation
that has occurred to him, only to stop and blush at the realization that he
has apparently bought into his own lie (manufactured to impress a current girlfriend) about being the kind of person who writes down potentially
poetic observations that occur to him: “Why would I take notes when Isabel wasn’t around to see me take them? I’d never taken notes before: I carried around my bag because of my drugs, not because I intended to work on
my ‘translations,’ and the idea of actually being one of those poets who was
constantly subject to fits of inspiration repelled me; I was unashamed to
pretend to be inspired in front of Isabel, but that I had just believed myself
inspired shamed me.”138
Shame attendant on self-deception has long been a reliable source of
complex embedment in the novel. (Think, for instance, of another lonely
traveler in a strange land, Robinson Crusoe, who is ashamed when he
catches himself thanking God for bringing him to a desert island: “‘How
canst thou become such a hypocrite,’ said I, even audibly, ‘to pretend to be
thankful for a condition which, however thou mayest endeavour to be contented with, thou wouldst rather pray heartily to be delivered from?’”)139
Lerner’s “skeptically postmodern comedy” thus continues to work the rich
Literary History
191
territory staked by connoisseurs of abashed self-consciousness, from Defoe
to Dostoevsky, who used self-deception as a reliable jumping-off point for
other mindreading entanglements.140
Indeed, there seems to be a good-husbandry aspect to being a writer:
Why waste a perfectly expedient, time-tested way to embed complex mental states, such as lying, even if the majority of the text’s embedments now
come from other social contexts?
6
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
6.1 Mental States versus Embedded Mental States in Stories for Children
Children’s literature is a particularly fascinating area of study when it comes
to complex embedment of mental states. On the one hand, it seems to track
certain milestones in the development of children’s theory of mind. For
instance, as I show in this chapter, complex embedments are mostly absent
in stories targeting one- to two-year-olds; they are present, but in a limited
way, in those for three- to seven-year-olds; and they increase both in number and variety in literature for nine- to twelve-year-olds.
On the other hand, when it comes to novels written for children of this
latter age group, they can range widely, from featuring almost no complex
embedment (which is not something we would expect from a novel today!)
to displaying an intense “grown-up” pattern of embedment. To explain
this range, we have to look at specific historical factors that influence the
process of designating some texts as children’s literature and/or novels,
which reminds us, once again, how tightly cognition and history are bound
together in the case of any complex cultural artifact.
We start by revisiting research in developmental psychology that focuses
on depiction of thoughts and feelings in books for young children and then
see what can be added to this conversation by shifting the focus from mental states as such to embedded mental states. You may remember, from the
discussion in chapter 3, that the current view of theory of mind is that it
develops continuously and can already be studied in preverbal infants. For
a long time, psychologists have been especially interested in the changes
that occur around the age of four, when children seem to be able to clearly
demonstrate their understanding of false belief, that is, the understanding
that people may believe something that is not, in fact, the case. (Though
194
Chapter 6
see studies by ethnographers working with communities that subscribe to
the opacity model for useful qualification of this view).1 The understanding
of false belief may, in principle, be a key condition for appreciating stories
that feature embedded mental states, for example, stories whose readers are
led to realize that a given character does not know something crucial about
another character’s intentions.
Yet, to the best of my knowledge, although cognitive scientists have
looked at the frequency and types of mental states in children’s stories, they
have not looked specifically at embedded mental states. Thus, Jennifer Dyer
and her colleagues used a sample of ninety books to see if “the information about mental states” present in children’s storybooks differed in books
for younger preschoolers (three- to four-year-olds) and older preschoolers
(five- to six-year-olds), “either in quantity or kind.”2 What they found was
that “mental state information in storybooks for young children” doesn’t
simply increase “with the children’s sophistication from 3 [to] 6 years of
age”; instead, books for younger and older children are “notably similar in
the rates of types and tokens of mental state expressions and the richness of
mental state concepts, particularly those expressed by cognitive state terms
and situational irony.” Yet, at the same time, books for older children contain “more mental state terms [and] varied mental state vocabulary.” Additionally, a greater number of the books for older children feature a “variety
of references from more of the different categories of mental state.”3
The textual dynamic described by this study as “situational irony” comes
close to what I call “implied embedment.” Dyer et al. use this expression to
refer to moments when readers are aware of, say, a disjunction between two
characters’ perspectives, even if it is never explicitly spelled out. Observe,
however, the difference between the two terms. “Situational irony” is relatively abstract, while “implied embedment” calls for an articulation of the
relationship among the minds involved, which, in turn, allows us to calculate the level of embedment, as in, “the reader is aware that character A
doesn’t know what character B is thinking” (third level). Such a calculation
might not always be an easy task (though it may be more so in children’s
literature than in literature for grownups), but it would add an important
new dimension to the inquiries conducted by cognitive scientists.
Here is another study that also comes close to articulating the educational role of implied embedments in children’s literature. Joan Peskin and
Janet Wilde Astington wanted to explore further the connection between
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
195
the acquisition of vocabulary in young children and development of theory
of mind.4 It’s been shown that children attending schools in low-income
neighborhoods “demonstrate substantial lags in their theory-of-mind understanding” and also that at six years old, they know only half the number of
words as do children from higher socioeconomic groups: “Children whose
parents do not provide a rich lexicon for distinguishing language about perceiving, thinking, and evaluating might make important gains from hearing
and talking such talk in their everyday story reading. . . . A rich vocabulary,
more than any other measure, is related to school performance.”5
Peskin and Astington decided to test whether exposure to an explicit
discussion of mental states (they call it metalanguage) “will result in a
greater conceptual understanding of one’s own and other people’s beliefs
or whether this understanding develops more implicitly.”6 They rewrote
kindergartners’ picture books “specially for the study so that the texts were
rich in explicit metacognitive vocabulary, such as think, know, remember,
wonder, figure out, and guess, in both the texts and text questions.”7
Thus, Pat Hutchins’s classic Rosie’s Walk (1968)—which features a chicken
on her daily promenade, unaware that a hungry fox is right behind her—was
altered to include such descriptions of the chicken’s thoughts as, “Does Rosie
know that Fox has been following her? No, Rosie doesn’t know. She doesn’t
even guess.”8 The children in this “explicit metacognitive condition were
compared with a control group that received the identical picture books,
with a similar number of words and questions, but not a single instance of
metacognitive vocabulary.” (See figure 6.1 for snapshots of typical pages from
Hutchins’s book, which was what the control group was given.)
What Peskin and Astington found was that “hearing numerous metacognitive terms in stories is less important than having to actively construct
one’s own mentalistic interpretations from illustrations and text that implicitly draw attention to mental states.”9 Children exposed to explicit metacognitive terms did start using them more, but they used them incorrectly.
On the one hand, this study supports findings of psychologists who
argue that what parents say in their interactions with their children is less
important than how they say it. As Paul L. Harris et al. observe, “Parents
elucidate a variety of mental states in conversation with their children.
That elucidation is not tied to particular lexical terms or syntactic constructions. Instead it reflects a wide-ranging sensitivity to individual perspectives
and nurtures the same sensitivity in children.”10
196
Figure 6.1
Pat Hutchins, Rosie’s Walk.
Chapter 6
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
197
On the other hand, finding that explicit use of metacognitive vocabulary in stories doesn’t seem to benefit children’s theory of mind led Peskin
and Astington to take another look at the implicit mentalizing expected of
readers. In doing so, they were also prompted by an earlier study by Letitia
Naigles, who found that “children exposed to more metacognitive terms
of certainty (think, know, and guess) in a television show later displayed a
poorer understanding of certainty distinctions than those exposed to episodes containing fewer of these terms,” as well as by the (separate) studies
of Deepthi Kamawar and Elizabeth Richner and Ageliki Nicolopoulou, who
“compared children whose teachers used more metacognitive vocabulary
to those whose teachers used less” and “found superior performance on
theory-of-mind tasks for children whose teachers used fewer metacognitive
terms.”11
To explain such counterintuitive findings, Peskin and Astington suggest
that “the teaching of information does not automatically lead to learning.” What is required instead is a “constructive, effortful process where the
learner actively reorganizes perceptions and makes inferences. . . . These
inferences lead to an understanding that may be all the deeper because
the children had to strive to infer meaning. Ironically, the more direct,
explicit condition may have produced less conceptual development precisely because it was explicit.”12
Crucially for our present argument, Peskin and Astington’s main recommendation for fostering constructive learning in children was having them
read literature: “Dramatic tension in stories is created when the various
characters have disparate knowledge with regard to the action. This may be
through error: The reader knows that Romeo does not know that Juliet lies
drugged, not dead. Or it may be through deception: Pretending his assigned
chore is an adventure, Tom Sawyer tricks his friends into whitewashing the
fence.”13
The examples chosen by Peskin and Astington are prime examples of
implied third-level embedments. To stay just with the action that they
describe (and thus ignoring complex embedments created by the tone of
Twain’s narrator, which I discussed in chapter 1), Tom doesn’t want his
friends to realize that he hates whitewashing the fence. Just so, Romeo
doesn’t know that Juliet wants some people to think that she is dead. Neither
Shakespeare nor Twain spells out those mental states for his readers; we
have to deduce them ourselves in order to make sense of what we read.
198
Chapter 6
Think about it. Works of literature that do not spell out embedded mental states may enrich understanding of mental states,14 foster the ability for
constructive learning, and improve vocabulary in preschool and school-age
children. I wouldn’t claim that the effect is exactly the same for grown-ups.
After all, if theory of mind goes through some important developmental
milestones in young children and adolescents, the impact might be more
pronounced for those age groups. For older readers, we may want to speak
about a different kind of impact, for instance, the one suggested by Kidd
and Castano, which is that a long-term exposure to literary fiction may sensitize one to the presence of intentionality cues in one’s social environment
(including the social environment within a fictional world) and make one
more prone to considering ambiguous (rather than clear-cut) intentions.
In fact, we can bring the two kinds of impact together when we look at
the history of literary criticism. It appears to be the case, for instance, that
experienced readers of literature in the Ming and Qing dynasties (i.e., those
particularly eager to discern the less-than-obvious intentionality cues) praised
the pedagogical acumen of authors who made them work hard to figure
out characters’ mental states. As David Rolston puts it, although “use of
direct psychological description in fiction increased throughout the Ming
and Qing dynasties, it was never popular or influential.” One reason for this
was that “the main justification for reading [literature was] to develop the
ability to judge human character; easy access to the inner life of characters
would defeat this pedagogical purpose.”
As traditional commentators saw it, “the author who is presented as the
most subtle in his laying down of . . . clues that raise suspicions about a gap
between an inner state of the character’s mind and his or her actions or
words . . . becomes the author most worthy of praise.”15 Worthy of praise,
that is, by a very specific group of readers, ones whose long exposure to
literature may have made them seek out and appreciate texts that would
provide them with cues for “constructive, effortful [mindreading] where
the [reader] actively reorganizes perceptions and makes inferences.”
Note that what Peskin and Astington call “disparate knowledge with
regard to action” is similar to Dyer et al.’s “situational irony.” Once again,
we come close to the concept of “implied embedment,” particularly with
Peskin and Astington’s emphasis on texts “that implicitly draw attention
to mental states.” Let us see, however, if we can go further than simply
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
199
recognizing some moments in stories for children as instances of “situational irony,” or “disparate knowledge in regard to action,” if we inquire
more minutely into the configuration of mental states involved.
What follows is a preliminary assessment of patterns of embedment in
stories for children aged nine to twelve, three to seven, and one to two.
These age groupings are taken from the most recent editions of Judy Freeman’s, John Gillespie’s, and Eden Ross Lipson’s guides to children’s books
and cross-checked with scholastic.com. (Although scholastic.com is by no
means immune to the charge of being “primarily a marketing device,”16 it
is a resource widely used by parents and teachers. As long as one is aware of
its limitations, it is a good starting point for a conversation about reading
“interest levels.”)
6.2 Ages Nine to Twelve
Among the books recommended for children aged nine to twelve are
Twain’s Tom Sawyer, Frances Hodgson Burnett’s The Secret Garden, A. A.
Milne’s Winnie the Pooh, Laura Ingalls Wilder’s Little House in the Big Woods,
Tove Jansson’s graphic novel Moomin Falls in Love, Jeff Kinney’s “Diary of a
Wimpy Kid” series, Lewis Carroll’s Alice in Wonderland, P. L. Travers’s Mary
Poppins, and E. B. White’s Stuart Little. I list in what follows some examples
of third-level embedment more or less in their order of appearance in these
stories (with emphases added), leaving out for now Tom Sawyer and Little
House in the Big Woods.
We learn in the first paragraph of The Secret Garden that when Mary was
born, her nurse was made to understand that if she wanted to please her mistress, she should keep the child to herself. As the narrator explains, Mary’s
mother “had not wanted a little girl at all, and when Mary was born she
handed her over to the care of an Ayah, who was made to understand that
if she wished to please the Mem Sahib she must keep the child out of sight
as much as possible.”17
When Mary’s mother dies and the little girl is shipped to England, she
meets Mrs. Medlock, the housekeeper of her new guardian. Mary instantly
dislikes Mrs. Medlock and tries walking farther away from her because she
hates to think that people would assume that she belongs to her: “It would
have made her angry to think people imagined she was her little girl.”
200
Chapter 6
When Mrs. Medlock tells Mary about her new home, Mary listens “in spite
of herself,” but she doesn’t want Mrs. Medlock to think that she is interested:
she “did not intend to look as if she were interested.”18
In the first chapter of Winnie the Pooh, Pooh, in his quest for honey, floats
up to a bees’ nest on his balloon and hopes that the bees will think that
he is a small black cloud in the sky. But the honey is still out of reach, and,
moreover, he worries that the bees suspect something. So he asks Christopher Robin for help: “‘Christopher Robin!’ ‘Yes?’ ‘Have you an umbrella in
your house?’ ‘I think so.’ ‘I wish you would bring it out here, and walk up
and down with it, and look up at me every now and then, and say “Tut-tut,
it looks like rain.” I think, if you did that it would help the deception which
we are practising on these bees.’ Well, you laughed to yourself, ‘Silly old
Bear!’ but you didn’t say it out loud because you were so fond of him, and
you went home for your umbrella.”19
Short as it is, this passage contains several complex embedments: Pooh
doesn’t want the bees to know that he wants to steal their honey; Christopher
Robin doesn’t want Pooh to know that he thinks his plan won’t work; the
narrator knows that Christopher Robin doesn’t want to hurt Pooh’s feelings.20
In Diary of a Wimpy Kid: Rodrick Rules, the main protagonist, Greg, observes
his parents “acting all lovey in front of [their youngest son] Manny,”
because they don’t want Manny to think that their arguments mean that
they don’t love each other.21 (Does the implied author want his grown-up
readers to squirm in recognition as they think of the times when they
hoped to manipulate their own kids the same way? I leave it up to you to
decide if this particular embedment is part of our “mentalistic interpretation” of the action.) On another occasion, Greg reports thinking about his
father’s feelings about Greg’s older brother’s intentions: “I’m pretty sure Dad’s
worst fear is that . . . Rodrick will want to follow in Bill’s footsteps.”22
In Moomin Falls in Love, Moomintroll develops a crush on a circus performer, La Goona. His girlfriend, Snorkmaiden, is heartbroken and lonely.
As she confides to Mymble, “If you only knew how I have longed for a friend’s
understanding and advice.”23 Mymble suggests that Snorkmaiden pretend
that she doesn’t care for Moomin anymore, but when Snorkmaiden follows Mymble’s suggestion, she’s bitterly disappointed because Moomin’s
only too happy to learn that he can do anything he wants.24 Moreover, it
transpires that La Goona fancies a circus acrobat who can lift big stones.
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
201
Moomin tries to wrench a heavy boulder out of the ground and fails. Little
My, who observes his effort, tells him, “I guess you must think of an entirely
different way of impressing La Goona.”25
In Alice in Wonderland, Alice “[thinks that she] can remember feeling a little
different.”26 In Mary Poppins, Mrs. Banks wishes that Mary Poppins wouldn’t
“know so very much more about the best people” than she knows herself.27
(This is an explicitly spelled-out embedment, but an equally interesting
implied one is lurking just beneath the surface, involving a grown-up reader’s
awareness of Mary Poppins’s manipulation of her class-conscious employer.)
Furthermore, Jane and Michael can’t figure out if Mary Poppins only pretends
to get angry at them and not understand what they mean when they say that
her Uncle likes “rolling and bobbing on the ceiling”;28 and Jane “wonder[s] if
she would ever be able to remember what Mrs. Corry remembered.”29
In Stuart Little, we learn that Stuart’s father, “Mr. Little, was not at all sure
that he understood Stuart’s real feelings about a mousehole.”30 Later on, the
family cat wants everyone to think that Stuart ran down the mousehole
while he’s actually trapped in a window shade. Stuart knows what the cat
had in mind, yet when he is finally found and rescued, he decides not to
tell on the cat. Instead, he wants his family to “draw [their] own conclusions”
about who might have wanted them to think that he would run down the
mousehole and why.31
It appears that, in spite of obvious differences in subject matter, the
pattern of embedment that one encounters in books for this age group
is similar to the one encountered in fiction for “grown-ups.” Both feature
complex (that is, at least third-level) embedments of mental states, which
are either implied or explicitly spelled out and associated with characters,
narrators, readers, and authors.
One important difference—at least in this sample—seems to have to do
with the frequency of complex embedments. In story after story, from Alice
in Wonderland to Stuart Little, I had to actively search for third-level embedments, sometimes coming up empty for a whole page. This situation would
be difficult to imagine in literary fiction for grown-ups, in which the main
effort required to find an instance of complex embedment involves opening the book.32 (There, even when descriptions of mental states are intentionally omitted, to make it seem that characters lack what we may call
interiority, embedded mental states are still implied.)
202
Chapter 6
Let me complicate this narrative of difference, if only up to a point.
Books in this age bracket (nine to twelve) are sometimes characterized by
what Ulrich Knoepflmacher and Mitzi Myers call “cross-writing.” That is,
they activate a dialogue “between phases of life we persist in regarding as
opposites,” appealing in different ways to young and to adult readers.33 And
I don’t just mean implied embedments, as when adult readers are aware of
Travers’s intention to show that Mary Poppins knows how to tacitly exploit
Mrs. Banks’s class anxieties. I also mean subtle interactions between the
author and the reader that arise from the parodic feel of the text. As Sandra Beckett observes, to “appreciate parody [of, for instance, Carroll’s Alice
books] the reader must first recognize the intent to parody another work
and then have the ability to identify the appropriated work and interpret
its meaning in the new context.”34 This recognition of intent is already a
complex embedment—I realize that the author wants me to think of text A
as I am reading text B—even before we factor in mental states of characters
whose motivations we may have to interpret in light of this “new context.”
What does a reader’s potential awareness of an author’s intent do to my
present argument about a somewhat less frequent incidence of complex
embedment in literature for children aged nine to twelve as compared to
literature for adults? Should we say that at least in some of these books,
the frequency of complex embedments may approach that encountered
in books for grown-ups, but only for those readers who “possess all of the
codes necessary to understand all of the parodic allusions”?35
In principle, a version of this argument—which is that there are always
more implied embedments in a text than meet the casual eye—can be
made about many stories. One can say, for instance, that experienced readers bring to anything they read the “mastery of the codes of fiction” and
a heightened attunement to intentionality cues,36 while less experienced
readers do not. Literary critics, too, may find new ways to read implied
embedded mental states into a text by expanding the range of minds associated with it, as we have seen scholars of eighteenth-century literature have
done with Haywood’s Fantomina. Still, even if we allow that, with enough
effort, we can import more complex embedments into just about any work
of literature, some of them do clearly require less of this kind of effortful
importation than others, for example, Howards End less than Mary Poppins,
and Dream of the Red Chamber less than The Secret Garden.
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
203
6.3 Young Adult Fiction (Thirteen to Eighteen): Preliminary Notes
One category of books that I did not explore systematically for this study
but that may be an interesting one to watch is young adult fiction, or YA.
Were I to venture some general observations about YA novels, I would say
that they tend to combine features that we encounter in the nine-to-twelve
age bracket with those that we encounter in so-called popular fiction. That is,
they embed complex mental states somewhat less frequently (i.e., similarly
to books for nine- to twelve-year-old readers), and they also tend to associate their complex embedments with characters and spell those out (i.e., a
pattern similar to that we find in works of “popular” fiction). At the same
time—and this is why I want you to take what I just said with a grain of salt—
some YA books also experiment with forms of embedment that arise from the
interaction between the implied reader and the implied author and, as such,
develop a more complex and less predictable sociocognitive profile.
For instance, Mariama J. Lockington’s For Black Girls like Me (2019) features an eleven-year-old narrator, Makeda, who is missing one crucial bit
of information about her environment, namely, that her adopted mother
is bipolar and that while she is taking her daughters on an exciting crosscountry trip, she is actually having a manic episode. Once we figure out
that our first-person narrator is unreliable, we start communicating with
the implied author behind Makeda’s back, as it were. For instance, when
Makeda’s father (who is currently away, performing at a concert in Japan) is
talking to his family on the phone, making Makeda wonder why he is using
“that fake cheery voice again,”37 we know that Makeda doesn’t know that
her father is terribly worried that his wife’s life is in danger and that, even
though he does tell his daughters, when he gets a chance, to watch her, he
cannot communicate to them the full extent of his fear.
In another, richly suggestive episode, the father gets to talk to Makeda
on the phone in the middle of the night, while her mom can’t hear them,
and he asks her if she thinks that he should come home early. Again, we
know that Makeda doesn’t know how worried he really is and how worried
she, herself, should be. But then we also realize that Makeda is worried but
doesn’t want to acknowledge it and that she thus seems to be learning from
her mom—without being aware of it!—the habit of refusing to deal with
scary feelings:
204
Chapter 6
“Makeda. Wait. Do you think I should come home early? I think maybe this trip
is too long.”
“Honestly.” I hear myself saying. In what sounds like someone else’s voice. “We
don’t need you. We’re having fun. Just enjoy your tour. I gotta go. Talk tomorrow.”
Before he can say anything else I hit END CALL. I shake the dark of the bathroom
off me. I shut the front door and lock it. I slip into my bed. Then I keep my eyes
open until the sun comes up.38
It is not a given, moreover, that the novel’s primary audience will grasp
the extent of its narrator’s unreliability upon first reading. Thirteen-yearold readers may know something about the Bipolar II mental disorder (and,
arguably, they are more likely to know about it in the 2020s than their
counterparts a decade or two ago would have). But, then again, they may
not, in which case they will have to learn about it together with Makeda,
almost at the end of the book. If they then reread the story, armed with that
new knowledge, they may end up processing an additional set of implied
complex embedments. But if they do not reread it, it is hard to say how
many of the embedments arising from the unreliability of Lockington’s
narrator will have registered with them.
The potential fluidity of the audience for YA books—owing to their pronounced cross-writing tendencies—is what makes this category such a fascinating subject for cognitivist inquiry. Will their patterns of embedment
gradually come to replicate our present division between “literary” and
“popular” fiction, that is, with some of them featuring mostly explicitly
spelled-out mental states of their characters and others featuring mostly
implied as well as spelled-out mental states of narrators and implied readers
as well as those of characters? Or will YA books evolve their own distinct
profile, which may be characterized, for instance, by less frequent instances
of complex embedment than we encounter in adult literature yet also by
more active use of complex embedment associated with implied narrators
and implied readers than we encounter in popular literature?
6.4 History and Cognition: Case Study 1 (Tom Sawyer)
Here is the reason I set Tom Sawyer aside when dealing with literature for
nine- to twelve-year-olds. Although it is typically placed on the same reading level as Mary Poppins, Alice in Wonderland, and Stuart Little, its pattern
of embedment differs from that prevalent in those books. That is, even if
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
205
we take into account those books’ cross-writing tendencies and say that an
experienced/adult reader intuits more intentionality in them than does a
less experienced/child reader, they still do not live up to the furious rate
with which complex embedments (especially implied ones, involving the
narrator and the implied reader) present themselves in Tom Sawyer. When it
comes to the frequency of such embedments, Twain’s novel is on par with
unambiguously “grown-up” texts that which I have looked at throughout
this study (e.g., novels by Murasaki Shikibu, Cao Xueqin, Frances Burney,
Jane Austen, Alexander Pushkin, E. M. Forster, and Zadie Smith).
Why, then, is Tom Sawyer considered to be a book for children? Several
factors seem to have made it so. First, as Beverly Lyon Clark has shown in
her study of the history of children’s literature in America, Twain “himself notoriously vacillated about the intended audience for what are now
sometimes called his boy books.”39 In July 1875, he wrote to William Dean
Howells that Tom Sawyer was “not a boy’s book at all,” that it was “only
written for adults” and would “only be read by adults.”40 When Howells
suggested that it should rather be (to use our present term) a cross-writing
novel, Twain responded by “toning down [its] satire and strong language.”41
In January 1876, he was able to assure Howells that Tom Sawyer was now “for
boys and girls.”42 In the preface to the published novel, he evokes both audiences, hoping that, though “intended mainly for the entertainment of boys
and girls, . . . it will not be shunned by men and women on that account.”43
And nineteenth-century men and women did not shun Tom Sawyer. It
was said to “appeal to all ages,” reflecting, among other things, the perspective of a culture “in which the [grown-up and children] audiences were not
yet fully discrete.”44 In that culture, a review of books titled “For the Young”
could still appear in the Atlantic (a practice apparently discontinued after
1903), stating that, although a child “will devour tales like Tom Sawyer or
Huckleberry Finn, . . . he cannot understand their real merit. . . . The adult
intelligence is necessary to understand them.”45
But, although both “tales” were initially thought to demand the “adult
intelligence,” that perception did not last. Over the course of the twentieth century, Huckleberry Finn was gradually elevated to the “great American novel,” an elevation that depended, Clark argues, on the simultaneous
relegation of Tom Sawyer to “kiddie lit.” As she puts it, the construction of
Huckleberry Finn’s greatness “at the expense of Tom Sawyer” entailed erosion
“of a fundamental respect for childhood and children’s literature.”46
206
Chapter 6
Here is what a cognitivist perspective may contribute to this kind of historicist reconstruction. If we consider the difference between the two novels’ patterns of embedment, we can suggest that it was this difference that
may have made easier—though not necessarily determined!—the elevation
of one book at the expense of the other.
Let us take as our starting point James Phelan and Peter Rabinowitz’s
contrast between the respective implied authors of Tom Sawyer and Huckleberry Finn. As they put it, Twain of Tom Sawyer speaks in the “avuncular”
voice—“one that sold well in the public marketplace” but that may have
demanded less work from his readers than the voice behind Huckleberry Finn,
which is characterized by a “multilayered” ethical consciousness.47 Thus, in
one of the passages used by Phelan and Rabinowitz to illustrate their point,
Huck describes the widow Douglas’s response to his return to her home this way:
“The widow she cried over me, and called me a poor lost lamb, and she called
me a lot of other names, too, but she never meant no harm by it.” . . . Huck
misinterprets the widow’s joyous religious references as name-calling because he
doesn’t recognize the New Testament source—and that misinterpreting leads him
to undervalue the ethical quality of her response. Yet this comic failure of understanding simultaneously reveals a moral strength. Although Huck’s ignorance
means that he fails to grasp both the extent of the widow’s joy and her beliefs
about what his return means, Twain demonstrates that Huck’s ethical compass is
sufficiently sensitive for him to appreciate that she “never meant no harm.” . . .
The overall effects are to bring us affectively and ethically closer to Huck even as
we continue to register our interpretive difference from him.48
To translate Phelan and Rabinowitz’s analysis into our “cognitivist” one,
focusing on high-level embedments, the implied author wants us to know
that Huck doesn’t understand the widow’s motivations (i.e., he “undervalues
the ethical quality of her response”). At the same time, he wants us to know
that Huck understands the widow’s kind intentions. What I find particularly interesting is that it seems that to experience the full rhetorical and
emotional impact of the passage—which brings us “closer to Huck even as
we . . . register our interpretive difference from him”—we have to process
both of these complex embedments simultaneously.
I actually don’t know what this kind of dual ethical processing entails
in terms of mindreading. I strongly believe that it does not simply ratchet
up the overall level of embedment, adding up, say, to the seventh or eighth
level. Still, something peculiar is happening here, something that cognitive
scientists who study complex embedments in laboratory and in real-life social
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
207
interactions don’t tend to encounter.49 At the very least, it shows that, while
remaining inextricably bound with the social, literature has run away with
it, “having amassed a repertoire of extremely nuanced stylistic tools for
embedding mental states,”50 as well as having cultivated cultural niches in
which the capacity for this kind of somewhat “ecologically implausible”51
mindreading is prized and rewarded.
Thus Huckleberry Finn. I do not mean to say that Tom Sawyer never once
demands such dual ethical processing from our theory of mind but that such
demands are more frequent in Huckleberry Finn and central to the development
of its main character, that is, to “the wisdom and understanding [Huck gains]
during the trip down the River.”52 Huck’s reaction to the widow’s response
comes early and, as Phelan and Rabinowitz put it, is a “fairly simple” case of
split ethical evaluation. The “same kind of interplay,” only “with more subtlety and greater consequences,” will mark Huck’s “self-examination” later,
when he decides “to go to hell rather than inform” the owner of Jim (i.e., of
the runaway slave and Huck’s friend) of Jim’s whereabouts.53
In fact, so integral is this pattern of “multilayered communication” with
the reader to the voice of this novel that when, at one point (i.e., when Tom
plots to arrange Jim’s escape from Silas Phelps), Twain abandons it, lapsing
into the broad humor familiar to the readers of Tom Sawyer, the change
feels like “a serious come-down.”54 The story still gets told through a series
of complex embedments—what with all the lies that Tom is feeding the
Phelpses and with the implied author winking to the reader as he parodies
the chivalric romance—but the dual ethical processing is notably absent.
Where does it all leave us in the conversation about the twentieth-century
designation of Tom Sawyer as “kiddie lit”? Looking at the dual ethical processing expected from readers of Huckleberry Finn—which marks some of
its third- and fourth-level embedments as qualitatively different from the
third- and fourth-level embedments in Tom Sawyer—we may speculate that
had Twain never written Huckleberry Finn, the frequency of such embedments in Tom Sawyer would have made its relegation to children’s literature
less certain. But with Huckleberry Finn next to it, the intuitive awareness of a
different kind of sociocognitive complexity underlying the latter’s affective
charge may have contributed to this cultural phenomenon.
Still, the main payoff of factoring the cognitive perspective into the historicist explanation of this process offered by Clark may be a more nuanced
understanding of why the designation of Tom Sawyer as “kiddie lit” remains
208
Chapter 6
troubling enough for critics to keep wanting to account for it. The cascading frequency of complex embedments expected from the reader of Tom
Sawyer—a frequency that, though not inconceivable in a book for children,55 is nevertheless rare—may be the reason why this novel does not stay
meekly put in the category of kiddie lit. For as long as we place in that category texts that embed complex mental states of characters, narrators, and
implied readers, but not at the same high rate that we’ve come to expect
from a work of “grown-up” literature, Tom Sawyer shall remain an outlier.
6.5 History and Cognition: Case Study 2 (Little House in the Big Woods)
Tom Sawyer is not the only outlier that I found in the nine-to-twelve age
group. An even more striking case, though for the opposite reason, is Laura
Ingalls Wilder’s Little House in the Big Woods. It contains very few embedded
mental states and practically no third-level embedments. Though a highly
compelling narrative in its own right, it has, as its readers observe, “no
plot.”56 Instead, we learn details of life on the frontier: how bullets were
made, how butter was churned, and how meat was cured. The near-total
absence of social situations that would call for attribution of complex mental states is, one can safely say, extremely unusual for a text considered to
be a novel. To see how this classification came to pass, we have to inquire,
once again, into the circumstances of its writing and publication.
The original version of the “Little House” series was called Pioneer Girl.
It was an autobiographical account of Wilder’s “family pioneering experiences in the American West,” intended for adults. As Wilder’s biographer
Pamela Smith Hill puts it, it was “nonfiction, the truth . . . as only Wilder
remembered it.”57
What happened then was that Pioneer Girl could not find a publisher. A
typical rejection, from Country Home magazine, praised it for “some very
interesting pioneer reminiscences” yet explained that they had “no place
for non-fiction serials.”58 Wilder then turned her autobiographical manuscript into a book of fiction for children, with the assistance of her daughter, the established writer Rose Wilder Lane. As Hill puts it, “Lane not only
switched audiences, she switched genres—from nonfiction to fiction. When
she replaced Wilder’s intimate first-person voice, her ‘I’ narrator, with a
third-person narrative, the juvenile manuscript instantly became fiction.”59
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
209
Did it? If we think of fiction in a broader sense of the term, as something fabricated rather than factual, we can say that Wilder’s manuscript
“became fiction” even earlier, when, for instance, to make Pioneer Girl more
dramatic, Lane adjusted the timing of the Ingallses’ move to Wisconsin to
bring them into contact with a notorious family of Kansas mass murderers.60 Or we can say that the fictional status of the Little House books was
clinched when, as staunch opponents of the New Deal, Wilder and Lane
took “serious liberties with the facts of the Ingallses’ lives” to portray the US
government as “nothing but destructive to the enterprising individual.” Or
that it happened when they “entirely made up or altered in fundamental
ways” scenes that testified to Laura and her sisters’ schooling “in emotional
and physical stoicism” and to their family’s socioeconomic self-reliance.61
As far as historical accuracy goes, the series is certainly fiction: a heady
blend of libertarian ideology and emotional warmth, mythologizing life on
the frontier.
Yet we have also come to intuitively expect something else from fiction/
literature, particularly with the novel as its flagship genre. While the presence of complex embedments alone does not determine if a given text is
considered fiction, the near absence of such embedments in Little House in
the Big Woods makes one wonder just how those joint appellations—that of
fiction and that of novel—came to stick. To see how it happened, we retrain
our attention on its cultural reception.
And what we learn when we look at the history of that reception is
that readers have always seen Little House in the Big Woods in the context
of other books in the series, which are more “novelistic” in their outlook.
For, as Wilder continued to draw on Pioneer Girl for her subsequent volumes, she went further than merely substituting “I” with “Laura.” As Smith
Hill observes: “[As] Wilder transformed her original material into fiction for
young readers, she grew both as a writer and ultimately as an artist, creating
dynamic characters, building more suspenseful stories, and manipulating
her themes more masterfully.”62
From a cognitive literary perspective, we can see the evidence of this
transformation in a gradual increase of the number of situations calling
for third-level embedment. Take Little Town on the Prairie, “the best-selling
of the Little House books,” which serves for many readers as the gateway
into the series. It turns out to owe very little to the original manuscript: the
210
Chapter 6
“comparable segment” of Pioneer Girl is “only six and a half pages long.”
In this “product of . . . Wilder and Lane’s imaginations,” Laura feels shocked
when her sister Mary tells her that she knows why Laura used to want to
slap her and that she thinks she deserved being slapped.63 She also feels bad
about reading a poem in a fine book that she finds in a drawer because she
realizes that her mother wanted that book to be a surprise gift for her.64
Similarly, in These Happy Golden Years, older Laura is “furiously angry” at
her student Clarence and trying to conceal her anger, for “as her eyes met
his she knew that he expected her to be angry.”65 When Laura goes for a ride
with Almanzo and her potential rival, Nellie, Laura is thinking that her
acquaintance Mr. Boast knows that she intends to take Nellie down a road
that she won’t like: “His eyes laughed at Laura. She was sure he guessed what
was on her mind.” Later on, Laura is having a similar exchange of glances
with Almanzo: “She let her eyes twinkle at him. She didn’t care if he did
know that she had frightened the colts to scare Nellie, on purpose.”66
This is very different from the inaugural volume, which focuses on how
things are made as opposed to what people think and feel. Still, because
the Little House books are treated as one continuous narrative—a story of
Laura’s “transition from a tomboyish girl to a marriageable woman”67—it’s
possible that the sociocognitive complexity of the later volumes colors our
perception of the first. Had those later volumes been constructed similarly
to Little House in the Big Woods—that is, had they focused on objects and
processes to the exclusion of complex social dynamics—perhaps Little House
in the Big Woods wouldn’t have been considered a novel today. Instead, it
might have been viewed as an arresting description of a child’s experience
on the frontier—for remember that expository nonfiction does very well
with lower (i.e., first and second) levels of embedment!—perhaps something along the lines of Susan Sinnott et al.’s Welcome to Kirsten’s World,
1854: Growing Up in Pioneer America.
To see how the perception of the Little House books as one continuous
narrative has become entrenched in US popular culture, we can inquire
into the role of the 1974–1983 television series, which didn’t follow the
original’s division into volumes (indeed, didn’t follow the original at all).68
I prefer, however, to look at another, subtler factor, one that has to do with
Little House’s career as a mainstay of basal readers used by US elementary
school teachers from the 1930s until the 1990s. The original inclusion in
basal readers owed to the fact that Wilder’s book seemed to fit several diverse
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
211
criteria articulated by 1920 research studies, which called for more “adventure stories (boys) and home-and-school stories (girls)” as well as for more
“informational books.” The criteria changed by the 1970s—with stress on
the emotional security provided by family and on the child’s ability “to
master environment without adult help.”69 Once again, Little House books
met those criteria because they have long been perceived—and taught!—as
a story of Laura’s personal journey toward maturity and independence,
made possible by her warm, supportive family.
So here we have Tom Sawyer classed with “kiddie lit” even as the frequency of its complex embedments makes it stand out among other books
in its designated cohort and Little House in the Big Woods considered a novel
in the absence of any complex embedments. What these two outliers tell us
(besides illustrating the importance of historical inquiry for a cognitive literary analysis) is that patterns of embedment don’t always determine genre
designations even if, at present, our “grown-up” literature, and novels in
particular, are dominated by subjectivity arising from complex embedment
of mental states.
6.6 Ages Three to Seven
Three to seven is an extremely interesting age when it comes to embedment,
because this is when children are more consistently found to be aware of
first- and second-order false beliefs in themselves and others. Although the
boundary between books for seven-year-olds and nine-year-olds is porous,
here is one intriguing pattern found in stories signposted specifically for the
younger age group.
Some books marked for ages three to seven contain just one third-level
embedment, although it can be repeated several times either with different characters or in slightly different settings. This embedment is central
to the story, constituting, in effect, its punch line, its raison d’être. It is
typically structured as a dawning awareness, on the part of young readers, that they know something about one character’s thoughts that another
character doesn’t know. (Literary scholars may recognize this as a preschool
version of dramatic irony and thus talk of cultural scaffolding involved
in shaping children into future mature readers,70 while developmental
psychologists may note its similarity to their made-up scenarios used in
double-embedment false-belief tests with six-year-olds.)
212
Chapter 6
Thus, Jon Klassen’s This Is Not My Hat follows the path of a small fish who
has stolen a big fish’s hat. Young readers gradually realize—and presumably
delight in their realization71—that the small fish erroneously believes that
the big fish doesn’t know who has stolen his hat.72 Julia Donaldson’s Gruffalo
tells a story of a big scary monster who believes a mouse’s claims that the
mouse is the most powerful animal in the forest. Once more, preschoolers
are “in” on the joke: they know that the Gruffalo doesn’t realize that when
she73 is walking behind the mouse in the forest, other animals are scattering
because they are afraid of her and not of the tiny mouse.74
Similarly, reading Pat Hutchins’s Rosie’s Walk, children know that Rosie
the hen doesn’t know that the hungry fox wants to devour her and that she
has one lucky escape after another. In Gene Zion’s Harry the Dirty Dog, the
premise of the story is that Harry’s owners don’t recognize Harry, a white
dog with black spots, because running around the city and getting dirty has
turned him into a black dog with white spots. The young readers thus know
that Harry’s owners don’t suspect that the reason this strange dog brings
them a scrubbing brush (a hateful implement, which Harry earlier buried
in the backyard) is that he thinks that, once they wash him, they’ll recognize
him as their beloved pet.
The positive affect presumably elicited in young readers by such embedments is a fascinating phenomenon. One may argue that it derives from
identification with the characters,75 particularly those who get to have
their way, such as Rosie, Harry, the big fish, and the little mouse. I tend to
think that it comes from the perception of social mastery fostered by the
plot. Children know—and they know that they know!—that the small fish
doesn’t realize that the big fish has already figured out who has stolen his
hat and is on the way to catch the thief. So the big fish may end up eating
the little fish, but it’s the young reader who is having the satisfying experience of being on top of the epistemological food chain.
We may do well to remember here that contemporary writers for young
children didn’t invent the concept of a triply embedded punch line and
that it has been long present in “trickster” stories worldwide. Thus, the
premise of Gruffalo is based on a classic Chinese tale of a tiger and a fox.
(The fox wants the tiger to think that, when they walk together, the fox
slightly ahead, other animals run away because they are afraid of the fox.)
We find triply embedded mental states in West African folklore (e.g., Brer
Rabbit wants Brer Fox to think that he’s afraid of the briar patch); in Native
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
213
American legends (e.g., Badger knows that Coyote thinks that Badger is
lying to him when he says that there is no food in the sack that the Badger is
carrying on its back); in Bornean folktales (e.g., a mouse-deer wants a crocodile to think that the mouse-deer doesn’t know if the body in the water is
the crocodile or just a log); and in Russian fairy tales (e.g., an exhausted
old house cat wanders into the forest, where he meets a fox, who promptly
offers to marry him; once married, the fox has to figure out how to protect
and feed her new husband; she decides to make a bear and a wolf think that
the cat is an important government official who’ll be angry at them if they
come to see him without substantial gifts).
Of course, not all trickster tales feature triply embedded mental states.
Just so, not all are geared toward children. Still, if we only consider those
that do and are, it is an extremely suggestive sociocognitive phenomenon.
It seems that many cultural traditions offer young children stories centering around doubly embedded false beliefs just at the time when children
go through a developmental stage that makes them particularly attuned
to such beliefs.76 In this particular case, the “cultural” and the “cognitive”
appear to form a feedback loop, shaping and reinforcing each other.
6.7 Ages One to Two
Recall that in the study of children’s books by Dyer et al. (which found that
books for younger and older children are similar in their “richness of mental state concepts”), the youngest subjects were three years old. I wonder if,
at three, children are already too far advanced on the developmental trajectory that leads to awareness of (first-degree) false belief. For that awareness
is not achieved suddenly once the child turns four. It is being continuously
built up, in conjunction with other “maturational factors,” such as language ability.77
This is why I believe it’s worth our while to take a closer look at books
for toddlers.78 (This age group, as you remember, is now a subject of controversy: it used to be assumed that they have not yet reached the theory
of mind milestone of appreciating false beliefs, but now experimental evidence suggests that one may elicit such appreciation from them.) What
I found after a preliminary study of books in this group is that they do
demonstrate a significant drop in third-level embedment. This is not to say
that they don’t contain references, both explicit and implied, to mental
214
Chapter 6
states: they do. (This is a key difference between my approach and that of
developmental psychologists studying children’s theory of mind: they look
at mental states; I look at embedded mental states.) What they don’t seem
to contain—at least those that don’t function as crossovers that appeal both
to toddlers and to older readers—is third-level embedment.
In looking at books geared toward children aged one to two, I focus on
those that lay a claim to telling a story, as distinct, that is, from books of
colors, numbers, body parts, and so on, which don’t.79 There is, for instance,
Curious George at the Zoo: A Touch and Feel Book (not to be confused with the
original Margret and H. A. Rey’s “Curious George” stories and their more
recent versions: the touch and feel books do not reproduce any of their
plots; indeed, the only thing they seem have in common with the “real”
Curious George series are the two main characters.)
We learn on the first page that the “man with the yellow hat is taking George to the Zoo today. There are so many things to see and do and
touch.” Most of the pages that follow focus on the sensory: “Feel the black
and white penguin’s thick coat,” “Feel the smooth shiny water,” “Feel the
rhino’s rough skin.” The book does contain references to mental states (e.g.,
“Where has George gone? He would love to watch the pink flamingo standing on one leg”),80 but it has no complex embedments.
Note that Curious George currently has 175 reviews on Amazon, and 62
of them mention explicitly the age of the young reader (another 10 merely
say that the reader is a “toddler”). Out of these 62, 58 cluster between the
ages of four and twenty-four months. While we may not want to put too
much emphasis on this bit of digital data mining, it offers a useful glimpse
at the perspective of caregivers who actually buy these books and judge
their appropriateness for their young charges.
Here is another example: Disney’s Pooh’s Honey Trouble, based, loosely,
on the first chapter of Milne’s Winnie the Pooh. That’s the chapter in which
Pooh hopes to fool the bees into thinking that he is a black cloud and not a
honey-stealing bear floating on a balloon and in which Christopher Robin
doesn’t want to hurt Pooh’s feelings by telling him that his plan won’t
work. In Disney’s version, Pooh wakes up in the morning feeling hungry
and goes out in search of honey. He comes across several of his friends, busy
doing what they like to do. Then Christopher Robin finds out that Pooh
is hungry and gives him a balloon, with which he finally manages to get
some honey:
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
215
Winnie the Pooh awoke one morning with rumbly in his tumbly. “Oh, bother,”
he said, finding his honeypots not at all full. The trouble with empty honeypots,
thought Pooh, is that they’re so very empty. Pooh went to see Piglet who was busy
gathering haycorns. Pooh helped his friend for a bit, but picking haycorns didn’t
help to take his mind off his rumbly tummy, so he continued on. . . . “Hello,
Pooh Boy!” said Tigger, bouncing his way through the forest. “Tiggers love bouncing.” “And bears love honey,” Pooh replied in a rumbly voice. . . . When Christopher Robin heard of Pooh’s honey trouble, he gave him a balloon. The balloon
was very nice, in a balloonish sort of way, but Pooh was quite sure it wouldn’t
make his tummy any less rumbly. “Silly old bear,” said Christopher Robin, watching Pooh float up, up, up, up to the spot where the honey was. And, at last, Pooh’s
tummy wasn’t rumbly anymore.81
What kind of embedments do we have here? Most of them are first level,
such as “Pooh wants honey,” “Tiggers love bouncing,” “Rabbits like carrots,” “Piglet likes haycorns,” although there are also some implied secondlevel ones, such as “Pooh knows that Piglet likes haycorns” or “Christopher
Robin knows that Pooh doesn’t understand what the balloon is for.”
There are currently seventy-two reviews of this book available on Amazon,82 and twenty-nine of them explicitly mention the age of the child
for whom the book was bought. Out of these twenty-nine, twenty-eight
fall between the ages of eight and twenty-four months, making it, as one
reviewer puts it emphatically, a “book for toddlers.”83
The development of theory of mind is intertwined with the acquisition
of vocabulary, but it’s not a simple vocabulary that makes Pooh’s Honey
Trouble “a book for toddlers.” Take another look at Rosie’s Walk, mentioned earlier (a book targeting children aged three to seven). Rosie’s Walk
contains fewer words than either Curious George at the Zoo or Pooh’s Honey
Trouble does, and, unlike them, it has no explicit references to mental
states.84 Nevertheless, it does embed mental states on the third level—via
illustrations!—and the reviews on Amazon testify to its popularity with
parents of preschoolers, with kindergarten teachers, and with beginner
readers themselves.85
Still, although I am encouraged by early findings about the relative scarcity of third-level embedments in books for one- to two-year-olds, I would
be cautious about simply concluding that they signal intuitive awareness
on the part of authors and caregivers of the stages in the development of
theory of mind.86 For the excision of complex mental states from such
books must also have its own history, bound up with the emergence of
216
Chapter 6
what Alan Richardson calls “the children’s book industry,” which in England, for instance, goes back to at least 1744.87
Complicating the issue even further are recent experiments of cognitive scientists that demonstrate some awareness of false beliefs in fifteenmonth-olds. Given these experiments, one would think that it may be good
for one-year-olds, now and then, to hear a story that is “above their head”—
that is, a story that embeds mental states on the third level—especially
if their parents make a point of talking with them about the characters’
thoughts and feelings. Benefits of this practice are borne out by research of
the developmental psychologist Paul L. Harris and his colleagues, who have
shown that parents “who talk about psychological themes promote their
children’s mental state understanding,” especially when their elucidation
of mental states “is not tied to particular lexical terms or syntactic constructions, . . . [reflecting instead] a wide-ranging sensitivity to individual
perspectives and [nurturing] the same sensitivity in children.”88
Of course, to extrapolate from Peskin and Astington’s study, there may
be a delicate balance between letting toddlers infer implied mental states
of characters in a children’s book and talking to them about those mental
states. This, moreover, is the point at which our current state of knowledge makes me cautious about speculating any further, calling (predictably)
for more research into historical and cognitive-developmental aspects of
embedment in stories for toddlers.
Crossovers
It’s fitting to conclude this chapter with a discussion of crossovers: books
that appeal to toddlers and to their parents, such as Marla Frazee’s Hush,
Little Baby.89 The “story” told by this board book is an old folksong, “Hush
little baby, don’t say a word,” transcribed verbatim. There are no third-level
embedments in the song. In fact, there are no references to mental states at
all, although we may come up with a couple of implied embedments, such
as, papa and mama are willing to buy anything to make their baby happy (“If
that billy goat don’t pull, / Papa’s gonna buy you a cart and a bull”), and
papa and mama love the baby (“If that horse and cart fall down, / You’ll still
be the sweetest little baby in town”).
Frazee’s illustrations, however, tell a different story. Its protagonist is an
older sister, who is about eight and jealous of the attention that the new
Embedded Mental States in Children’s Literature
217
baby gets. So when the baby’s peacefully asleep and the parents are looking the other way, the girl pushes the cradle roughly. The baby wakes up
screaming, and the girl pretends to be concerned and eager to calm it down
(“Hush, little baby, don’t say a word”), while the startled and bleary-eyed
parents look on. The girl then convinces the father that they should go visit
a village peddler, because a mockingbird in a cage would surely console the
baby. Frazee’s drawings seem to imply that the girl has wanted the bird for
some time and that she is thrilled to get some time alone with her daddy.
And so it goes. The baby keeps crying, while the older sister keeps accumulating one treasure after another (a diamond ring, a looking glass, a puppy),
delighting in her important role in the common project of calming down
the baby and, in fact, gradually warming up to the little interloper.
There are numerous third-level embedments in the story told by the
pictures. At first, we are encouraged to think that the parents don’t suspect
that the girl is jealous, just as they don’t suspect that she only wants them
to think that these toys are for the baby while, in reality, they are for her.
But toward the end of the narrative, we begin to wonder if the parents
are indeed as clueless as the girl thinks they are. In fact, when she gets
the puppy, the father’s facial expression seems to imply that he has understood all along more than his daughter thought he did (figure 6.2). His
glance breaks the fourth wall and draws us in: he wants us to know that he
knows what’s going on. (Or, given that the narrative thus foregrounds the
Figure 6.2
“If that dog named Rover don’t bark.” (Marla Frazee, Hush, Little Baby: A Folk Song
with Pictures Board Book)
218
Chapter 6
relationship between the implied reader and the implied author, another
way to map out this scene would be to say that Frazee wants us to know that
the father knows what’s going on.)90
Eden Ross Lipson as well as Amazon put the age of the reader for Hush,
Little Baby at two to three years old, which is reasonable, given that the
original folksong has no third-level embedments.91 Freeman, Gillespie,
and Scholastic, however, estimate the age of the reader as pre-K to second
grade.92 The difference between two to three and pre-K to second grade
appears striking unless we assume that Freeman, Gillespie, and Scholastic
respond to the story told by the book’s illustrations. The level of embedment
in that story, indeed, makes it appropriate for readers who can appreciate
the first- and even second-order false beliefs, that is, for four- to seven-yearolds. Moreover, responses accumulated on Amazon show that parents and
grandparents are intuitively aware that Frazee’s book contains two stories
under one cover, one geared (we can say) toward a more mature theory of
mind, and another, toward a theory of mind early in development.93
What I have hoped to show throughout this chapter is that embedded
mental states are richly present not just in “grown-up” fiction but also in
children’s literature and that a critical inquiry into patterns of embedment
in children’s literature draws on close reading, cultural-historical analysis,
research in cognitive science, and even some occasional digital data mining. As such, it makes a practitioner of the cognitive approach to literary
criticism accountable to several different fields and, moreover, aware of the
provisional state of one’s conclusions. This may imply more uncertainty
than our discipline is used to, but, then, one doesn’t turn to interdisciplinary work seeking certainty and familiarity.
Conclusion: On the Future of the “Secret Life” of Literature
Then Ea opened his mouth and said to me, his servant, “Tell them this: I have
learnt that Enlil is wrathful against me, I dare no longer walk in his land nor live
in his city; I will go down to the Gulf to dwell with Ea my lord. But on you he
will rain down abundance, rare fish and shy wild-fowl, a rich harvest-tide. In the
evening the rider of the storm will bring you wheat in torrents.”
—The Epic of Gilgamesh, 2100 BC
It is interesting that we either fictionalize or become tongue-tied when it comes
to personal matters. We may have good reasons to hide from ourselves (at least
to hide certain aspects—which amounts to the same). But even if there is little
hope of an eventual self-acquittal, it would be enough to withstand the lure of
silence, of concealment.1
—Christa Wolf, Patterns of Childhood, 1976
There are four thousand years and several worlds of difference between the
promise of abundance that the god Ea dangles in front of the people of
Shurrupak, just before they are all swept to their death by a giant flood, and
the painful self-searching awareness of Wolf’s autobiographical novel about
growing up in Nazi Germany. Yet to make sense of either situation, we
engage in a very particular kind of social reasoning. We navigate, without
being consciously aware of it, the multilayered intentionality of the text.
That is, we recursively embed—mostly on the third level—thoughts, feelings, and wishes of its characters, as well as (if we are that kind of readers)
of its narrators and implied audiences.
Thus, we may recognize that Ea wants the citizens of Shurrupak to believe
that Enlil is angry at Utnapishtim. We may also surmise that, with all the talk
about “a rich harvest-tide,” Ea is enjoying his cruel joke, as befits a trickster
220
Conclusion
deity—which is to say that the narrator of Gilgamesh wants to draw his audience’s attention to Ea’s intention to mock the doomed Shurrupakians.
When it comes to Wolf, her narrator knows that she may not like much of
what she will learn about herself when she starts thinking about her childhood. Yet she also intuits that there is some hope that she may forgive her
past self. She thinks that her awareness of that hope, however small, should
help her to keep going even when it would feel so much easier to stop and
keep her memories hidden from herself and others.
Moreover—again, if we are that kind of readers—we may start reading
additional intentionality into the present juxtaposition of the two passages.
After all, the child protagonist of Wolf’s novel is no more aware of what
kind of deadly “harvest-tide” lies in wait for her and her countrymen than
are the people of Shurrupak. Although I did not intend any such conversation between the two passages when I selected them—indeed, my goal was
to use works of literature as distinct from each other as possible—I now
can’t help wondering if some of my readers will see the connection and think
that I meant for it to be there.
(Herein lies an object lesson in what happens when you put two random literary passages in front of a person who makes her living by reading
complex intentionality into cultural artifacts: “Hey, what do you mean ‘two
random passages’? I see a connection here!”)
And now I also wonder if you will take this emerging conversation
between Gilgamesh and Patterns of Childhood as me saying that nothing
much has changed in the depiction of literary subjectivity over the past
four thousand years. In fact, I am saying the opposite. I want you to see
how different literary subjectivity has become as it has moved from the
occasional reliance on complex embedment of mental states (e.g., in Gilgamesh) to the constant one. For, to find my Gilgamesh example, I had to
comb the text; to find my Patterns of Childhood one, I had to merely open
the book. The challenge of casting about for social situations conducive to
incessant complex embedment of mental states has been shaping literature
as we know it for several centuries. Without being consciously aware of
it (which is a good thing, too, as my experience in the writing workshop
confirms), authors keep inventing new and tweaking old ways of recursively embedding thoughts and feelings. To quote Lewis Carroll’s Through the
Looking-Glass, just to stay in place—here, on the third level of embedment—
they have to run as fast as they can.
On the Future of the “Secret Life” of Literature
221
It remains an open question whether literature will ever be able to break
free of this relentless gravitational pull of complex embedment. Writers
who seem to attempt such a break, driven by a wide variety of personal,
political, and aesthetic motivations (e.g., Evgeny Zamyatin in We, Alain
Robbe-Grillet in Jealousy, Muriel Spark in The Ballad of Peckham Rye, Cormac McCarthy in Blood Meridian, and Fedor Gladkov in Cement), manage it
only to a point. The odds are stacked against them. Reading complex intentionality into a literary text—which is to say, intuitively expecting literary
subjectivity to be constructed as a series of complex embedments, explicit
or implied—has become our standard experience of literature.
This expectation/experience is buttressed by several cultural factors.
First, there is a vast ocean of popular fiction that embeds complex mental
states of (mostly) characters. Though differing from literary fiction (which
embeds mental states of narrators and implied readers, as well as characters), such books nevertheless contribute to making their readers experience complex embedment as a default mode of engagement with fictional
imagination. Second, this “induction” into the association between fictional stories and complex embedment begins quite early—with books targeting three- to seven-year-olds. Third, cultural institutions—from college
literature departments to critical reviews—implicitly train their adepts to
think in terms of embedded motivations of characters, writers, and readers
and reward them for compellingly articulating such motivations.
Fourth, there is also the possible impact of moving images, which I
mention here only briefly, not having addressed it in this book. Feature
films and television series use medium-specific methods to generate complex embedments of mental states. Moreover, critics (as in my Susan Sontag example, in chapter 4) depend on complex embedments to talk about
films, which means that institutional structures that reward thinking about
moving images in terms of complex intentionality have been in place for
some time. Whether the experience of watching certain films and TV series
and reading reviews of such films/series sensitizes viewers to cues of intentionality in their social environment and whether such a sensitivity translates between media, influencing reading practices, are open and intriguing
questions.2
Finally, consider that we tend to view as ethical and prosocial the practice of rendering minds transparent—which is to say, of talking publicly
about one’s own and other people’s feelings, even when (in fact, sometimes
222
Conclusion
especially when) we think that we can articulate other people’s true motivations better than they themselves can articulate them. Though adapting the rhetoric of opacity when it is expedient, our culture inclines, on
the whole, toward the transparency end of the opacity-transparency spectrum. This means that representations of and conversations about complex
intentionality of fictional characters, their creators, and their audiences are
entrenched in our public discourse and, indeed, in our current cultural perception of how the social mind works.
Imagine, then, an author who is firmly committed to writing a novel
that will transcend the pull of embedded subjectivity. (Not that they themselves would put it that way; they may think of it as “antipsychological” or
“surface based,” or “a story without interiority”—you name it.) That writer
will face an uphill battle at every step of their interaction with their audience. Readers will come to that novel intuitively expecting to encounter
recursively embedded subjectivity either of characters or of characters, narrators, and implied readers. They will force-read as much of that kind of
subjectivity into the story as the text itself and their own past reading history will allow them. Critics, too, will find ways of talking about embedded thoughts and feelings, by speculating about the writer’s intentions and
describing their reactions. If the novel is adapted for screen, social situations and/or shots calling for complex embedment of mental states will be
introduced, and that will, in turn, influence the experience of readers who
will come (or return) to the original text after watching the film. Can our
experimental novel survive this onslaught of embedded mentalizing and
even start a new literary trend of embedment-free writing? Perhaps it still
can, but it won’t be easy.
This is not to say that complex embedment of mental states is an inevitable feature of the literary landscape of a mindreading species—merely
that it has been around for a while and is still going strong. Contributing
to its longevity is its integration with our ideology of mind: we believe that
mental states are knowable and can be discussed in public, and we have cultural institutions that reward elaborate forms of such discussions, be they
about real or fictional minds. But while there is no way of knowing what
the future holds either for such institutions or for the secret life of literature, we can follow, with new awareness, the remarkable current career of
this inconspicuous yet pervasive phenomenon: watch it as it adapts to new
media and reinvents itself in the old ones.
Notes
Preface
1. For an introduction to the field, see Zunshine, “Introduction to Cognitive Literary Studies.” For a representative bibliography, see Zunshine, “May 2020 Bibliography,” as well as its more frequently updated counterpart at my Academia page:
https://uky.academia.edu/LisaZunshine.
2. B. Schieffelin, “Found in Translation,” 143.
Chapter 1
1. Twain, Mississippi Writings, 20.
2. For a discussion, see Fernyhough, “Metaphors of Mind.” Note that plenty of cognitive scientists use “theory of mind,” “mindreading,” and “mental states” (or “internal
states”) in a literal sense. Indeed, for the purposes of studying the phenomena referred
to by these terms, it does not seem practicable to be always carefully foregrounding
their metaphoricity.
3. For a review of mindreading, see Apperly, Cognitive Basis of “Theory of Mind.”
4. See, for instance, Tomasello, Origins of Human Communication, 173, 189.
5. Of course, I can imagine a context in which this statement will contain mental
states. For instance, if I am standing in a long line and an authority figure comes over
and tells us that this is the line only for people whose last names begin with a Z and that
we should thus disperse, I may call out with some strong feelings, “My last name begins
with a Z!” This is to say that my present examples are synthetic constructs designed to
make a point rather than to represent accurately a range of real-life situations.
6. Mercier and Sperber, Enigma of Reason, 81. See also Martins and Fitch, “Do We
Represent Intentional Action as Recursively Embedded?”
7. Tomasello, Origins of Human Communication, 173.
224
Notes
8. Miller, Kessel, and Flavell, “Thinking about People Thinking,” 622.
9. On the difference between the effect on theory of mind of reading fiction and
expository nonfiction, see Mar et al., “Bookworms versus Nerds.”
10. In prose fiction, sentence- and paragraph-level complex embedments may be
particularly predominant. Compare to Auyoung’s observation that “the prosaic organization of text across sentences and paragraphs emerges as a crucial scale at which
narrative information can be strategically arranged” (When Fiction Feels Real, 63).
11. See Zunshine, “Commotion of Souls”; Whalen, Zunshine, and Holquist, “Increases
in Perspective Embedding.”
12. From this point on, I frequently omit the term “implied” as a modifier for reader/
audience. Although the narratologist in me would strongly prefer to speak of implied
readers as opposed to just readers, I find useful the distinction between the literarycritical (in my case, narratological) and empirical perspectives, recently outlined by
Andrew Elfenbein. As he puts it, “Literary scholars may at times strive to occupy a
position as close as possible to their understanding of the implied reader. . . . While
I am comfortable with the ‘implied reader’ as a literary critical construct, I have seen
no psychological evidence that actual readers envision an implied reader as they read
or use an implied reader to gauge their own performance” (Gist, 199).
13. Compare to arguments developed by narratologists, such as Henrik Skov Nielsen,
James Phelan, and Richard Walsh, who contend that “the rhetoric of fictionality is
founded upon a communicative intent” (“Ten Theses about Fictionality,” 64); by
philosophers, such as Gregory Currie, who observes that a “narrative is an artefact,
wherein the maker seeks to make manifest his or her communicative intentions”
(“Framing Narratives,” 18); by cognitive literary scholars, such as Andrei Ionescu,
who notes that the relationship between reader and writer can in itself be “a very
complex form of intersubjectivity” (“Manifesto,” 9); and by cognitive linguists, such
as Yanna Popova, who sees literature as “framing an interactive engagement with a
reader” (Stories, Meaning, and Experience, 71).
14. Phelan and Rabinowitz, “Authors, Narrators, Narration,” 37.
15. As Elfenbein puts it, “As soon as a reader can recognize that paradoxes, ambiguities, and uncertainties are intentional, at whatever level of agency intention is
understood, representation becomes coherent” (“Mental Representation,” 251).
16. See Bowes and Katz, “Metaphor Creates Intimacy.”
17. Twain, Mississippi Writings, 24 (emphasis added).
18. Twain, 25 (emphasis added).
19. Gavaler and Johnson, “Genre Effect,” 86, 91. For an analysis of the “interaction
effect between genre and mentalizing” in case of espionage stories as compared to
relationship stories, see also Carney, Wlodarski, and Dunbar, “Inference or Enaction?”
Notes
225
20. Ferrante, Story of the Lost Child, 250.
21. Rooney, Conversations with Friends, 242.
22. Cusk, Transit, 174.
23. Dangarembga, Nervous Conditions, 116.
24. Al Harthi, Celestial Bodies, 97.
25. Lerner, Leaving the Atocha Station, 84.
26. Williams, Ninety-Nine Stories of God, #61.
27. Gavaler and Johnson, “Genre Effect,” 79–108.
28. For a related critique of this stance, see Savarese’s See It Feelingly, in which he
objects to its “very narrow conception of the social, as if the social were something
that only human did with each other” (111).
29. Dick, Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep?, 4.
30. Savarese, See It Feelingly, 101.
31. Jackson, “Beautiful Stranger,” 79.
32. Forster, Howards End, 254.
33. Tolstoy, Anna Karenina, 413.
34. Austen, Pride and Prejudice, 180.
35. Cao, Story of the Stone, vol. 1, 438.
36. And if we agree with Elaine Scarry’s argument that Shakespeare’s “beautiful
young man” (Naming Thy Name, 4) was Henry Constable, then we have a poetic
rejoinder written by Constable, who casts about for illusory explanations that
may soothe his pain. The speaker of this sonnet (number 8 in Constable’s “Diana”
cycle) suspects that his beloved (i.e., Shakespeare) placed him in harm’s way—by
asking him to keep company with his mistress in his absence—on purpose. But
if that’s the case—and here comes the complex embedment—then the speaker
can make himself feel better by imagining that the beloved wanted him to feel this
pain:
So when this thought my sorrowes shall augment,
That mine owne folly did procure my paine;
Then shall I say, to give my selfe content,
Obedience only made me love in vaine:
It was your will, and not my want of wit;
I have the paine—beare you the blame of it.
Or, as Scarry explains in her own tour-de-force of complex embedment, “I am in
torment, says the speaker, a torment made worse by knowing my own folly brought
this about; the only explanation that would make me gladly accept my pain would
226
Notes
be to know you so take pleasure in my torment that you scripted the entire event; if
my pain gives you pleasure, I can accept my pain” (Naming Thy Name, 68).
37. Nizami, Story of Layla and Majnun, 10.
38. Anonymous, “The Wanderer,” n. p.
39. Petronius, Satyricon, 50.
40. Homer, The Odyssey, 219.
41. Anonymous, Epic of Gilgamesh, 108.
42. Furlanetto et al., “Through Your Eyes.” Note that in this case the word “actor” as
used by the authors of this essay refers not to an actor onstage but to a person whose
actions are observed by others.
43. Furlanetto et al.
44. See, for instance, Noel, “What Do We Actually See on Stage?”
45. Shakespeare, Measure for Measure, 5.1.
46. Hogan, Sexual Identities, 141.
47. Shakespeare, Twelfth Night, 3.4.97–98.
48. For a detailed discussion, see Zunshine, “Why Jane Austen Was Different.”
49. Nizami, Layla and Majnun, 10.
50. See Whalen et al., “Validating Judgments,” 293.
51. Chekhov, “Skripka Rotshil’da,” n.p., translation mine.
52. Lu, Madman’s Diary, 19. In the original: 我忍不住,便放聲大笑起來,十分快活。自己曉
得這笑聲裏面,有的是義勇 和正氣。老頭子和大哥,都失了色,被我這勇氣正氣鎮壓住了。
53. Pittard, Listen to Me, 2, 3.
54. Z. Smith. On Beauty, 3.
55. Forster, Howards End, 3.
56. Note the specific meaning of the word “intentionality” when used interchangeably with “mental state.” As Mauricio D. Martins and W. Tecumseh Fitch observe,
It is important before going further to identify a potential source of confusion concerning
“intention” and “intentional” stemming from the specialized interpretations of these terms
as traditionally used by philosophers, that differ considerably from their ordinary English
meanings. In ordinary English, “intentional” means “on purpose,” but philosophers use
“intentionality” to designate a particular characteristic of mental states. . . . In this sense,
intentionality is a pervasive and fundamental feature of mental states like beliefs or desires,
but including a wide range of other states including memories, hopes, knowledge, love—or
intentions (in the ordinary sense). Thus, from the philosophers perspective, intentions are
Notes
227
just one among many different forms of intentional state. . . . [Thus] it is important to note
that “intentionality” does not imply an “intention to do something.” (“Do We Represent
Intentional Action as Recursively Embedded?,”18)
57. Williams, Ninety-Nine Stories of God, #61.
58. Kulpa, “Review of Ninety-Nine Stories of God.”
59. Apuleius, Golden Ass, 112.
60. Ruden, “Translator’s Preface,” xv.
61. Peter Stockwell, MIT Press reader report, 2020.
62. Anonymous, Epic of Gilgamesh, 108.
63. Kidd and Castano, “Reading Literary Fiction and Theory of Mind,” 8. For a discussion of a controversy involved in the replication of the findings from the original
2013 study (i.e., Panero et al., “Does Reading a Single Passage of Literary Fiction
Really Improve Theory of Mind?”), see also Kidd and Castano, “Panero et al. (2016)”;
and van Kuijk et al., “Effect of Reading a Short Passage.” For a useful metastudy
that reviews recent research on fiction’s effects on social cognition, see Dodell-Feder
and Tamir, “Fiction Reading Has a Small Positive Impact.” As its authors summarize
(citations omitted throughout),
The effect of fiction on social cognition was larger when compared to no reading versus
nonfiction reading. Indeed, if fiction’s causal impact depends on the extent to which a text
provokes readers to consider mental states, then many forms of nonfiction (e.g., memoir)
may likewise improve social cognition. Individual difference factors may also moderate the
causal relation between fiction and social cognition. Given the same text, some readers
may be more likely to benefit from fiction than others. Reading is an active experience,
requiring willful participation by the reader. Thus, the benefits to social cognition may
depend on the quality of a reader’s engagement with a text and motivation to understand
the characters. For example, fiction’s impact may depend on a reader’s propensity to be
transported into narratives, generate imagery while reading, or to simulate other minds. In
the absence of this type of reader engagement, fiction is unlikely to effect any change at all.
Furthermore, one’s existing knowledge base, expertise, or age of exposure may determine
how likely one is to benefit from fiction reading. If so, prior social-cognitive ability would
also moderate fiction’s impact. While we were not able to test these factors here, we recommend that future studies measure the role that individual differences play in moderating
the effect of fiction reading on social cognition. While we show here that fiction effects a
small causal improvement of social cognition, it is also likely the reverse causal relation
exists. That is, fiction reading and social cognition might form a mutually facilitating and
reinforcing pathway, akin to a “Matthew Effect.” Socially skilled individuals may gravitate
toward fiction due to its social content more than less-skilled individuals. In doing so,
readers further differentiate their social-cognitive skills from nonreaders as part of a selfreinforcing cycle. In summary, we find that fiction reading leads to a small improvement
in social cognition. (1725)
64. As Phillips puts it, “We define close reading . . . as a style of focus—a mode of
noticing details about literary form—that serves as a springboard for later analysis,
writing, and criticism” (“Literary Neuroscience and History of Mind,” 58).
228
Notes
65. I have more to say about this in section 1.19.
66. See Zunshine, Why We Read Fiction.
67. Elfenbein, Gist, 59, 139.
68. Elfenbein, 58. Compare to H. Porter Abbott’s discussion in Real Mysteries, 10.
Also, for a related discussion of the “online/offline” experience of reading and
“promiscuous inference generation,” see, respectively, Elfenbein, Gist, 83–84 and
86. Finally, for a critique of “decoupling reading from interpretation, a linkage so
common in literary criticism that the claim ‘there is no reading without interpretation’ has become a truism, though it rests on a host of unexamined assumptions
about both,” see Elfenbein, Gist, 214.
69. Elfenbein, Gist, 19.
70. Elfenbein, 2. Compare to Anezka Kuzmičová’s argument that “trained readers’
minds may . . . take up various higher-order and formal aspects of the text in addition to the basic gist” (“Consciousness,” 272).
71. Elfenbein, Gist, 2.
72. See Zunshine, “Who Is He to Speak of My Sorrow?”; and Steven Feld, Sound and
Sentiment.
73. I have more to say about this in chapter 2, on mindreading and social status.
74. The full list of vignettes can be found here: https://yale.app.box.com/s/qvk12d3
vwrppimedrrdkkj5hgrdq5p76.
75. Whalen et al, “Validating Judgments,” 287.
76. Whalen et al., 288.
77. See Whalen, Zunshine, and Holquist, “Increases in Perspective”; Whalen, Zunshine, and Holquist, “Theory of Mind and Embedding of Perspective”; and Whalen
et al., “Validating Judgments.”
78. For details, see Zunshine, “Style Brings In Mental States.”
79. To quote Elfenbein again, such stylistic nuances “could create a heightened textural density in reading, a sensation that does not produce paraphrasable meaning
but a phenomenological feeling” (Gist, 35).
80. Hogan, Sexual Identities, 130.
81. While there are different ways to control for subjects’ level of expertise, one may
want to discuss with them beforehand situations that can lead to an overgenerous
counting of embedded mental states. For instance, in my tutorial sessions, I used sentences similar to those I offered to you earlier in this chapter , such as “My last name
begins with a Z” (no mental states), “I’m glad that my name begins with a Z because
Notes
229
the teacher may not get to the end of the list today” (two mental states), and so forth.
Were I to do it again now, I would also point out that some sentences may look like
complex (i.e., third- and fourth-level) embedments, when in fact they are just parallel
sets of low-level embedments. Thus, “I hope he doesn’t realize what I did last week
because I am scared that he would be angry at me” contains two sets of second-level
embedments connected by “because” and not one four-level embedment. Here is
what a four-level embedment may look like, based on the same material: “I hope that
he doesn’t realize that I am scared of him being angry at me if he finds out what I did
last week.” Note the very different emotional tenor of this second sentence. Before,
the speaker was afraid that “he” would be angry at her for what she did. Now she is
worried that he would realize that he holds quite a bit of emotional power over her.
It’s a rather more interesting feeling (perhaps there is even a whiff of a story to it).
82. This would bear out the findings of the social psychologist Raymond Mar and
his colleagues, who have shown that, contrary to the conventional belief that
“bookworms” must be antisocial, there is actually a positive correlation between
reading fiction and having good social skills (“Bookworms versus Nerds”), as well
as the historical perspective offered by Elfenbein, who observes that “although
reading is sometimes imagined as a withdrawal from social relationships, for many
[eighteenth-century English] readers, reading novels sustained friendship and occasioned new ones” (Gist, 145).
83. This, of course, supports the aforementioned finding of Kidd and Castano. A
similar argument has been made by social psychologists studying “attributional
complexity”—a construct that was “proposed as an integration of several perspectives on cognitive complexity and includes the motivation to understand human
behavior, along with the preference for complex explanations of it.” It has been suggested that people who are already “interested in explaining human behavior,” such
as students who decide to major in psychology, are likely, in the process of their
studies, to develop a “more complex explanatory schemata for human behavior as
compared with other groups of students, such as students majoring in the natural
sciences” (Fletcher et al., “Attributional Complexity,” 880).
84. Whalen et al, “Validating Judgments,” 293.
85. Whalen et al, 292, 294.
86. De Jaegher and Di Paolo, “Participatory Sense-Making,” 490.
87. Forster, Howards End, 254.
88. For a foundational work on free indirect discourse, see Pascal, Dual Voice. See
also Gunn, “Free Indirect Discourse.” For a recent discussion of FID from a cognitive
perspective, see Mäkelä, “Possible Minds.”
89. Forster, Howards End, 241.
90. Forster, 253.
230
Notes
91. For a discussion of “the disparity between to kinds of engagement with fiction—
the experience of the text and its interpretation,” see Abbott, Real Mysteries, 10.
92. The enactive perspective on the extent to which embedded mental states are
already in a work of fiction can be illustrated by the use of the classical example of a
sponge, i.e., an object that changes depending on how it is acted upon. To quote De
Jaegher and Di Paolo,
Traditional distinctions between action and perception arise only as the specialization of
phases in an act of sense-making. Several examples that illustrate this point have been discussed in the enaction literature, but perhaps the simplest and clearest one is that of perceiving the softness of a sponge. . . . The softness of a sponge is not to be found “in it” but in how
it responds to the active probing and squeezing of our appropriate bodily movements (e.g.,
with the fingers or the palms of the hand). It is the outcome of a particular kind of encounter
between a “questioning” agent with a particular body (sponges are solid ground for ants) and
a “responding” segment of the world. (“Participatory Sense-Making,” 489)
93. See also Troscianko, Kafka’s Cognitive Realism, 172.
94. De Jaegher and Di Paolo, “Participatory Sense-Making,” 502.
95. One may speak here of the guidance provided by the author or, even more specifically, of what Gregory Currie calls the “guided attention” cultivated by the text
(“Framing Narratives,” 25). For a discussion of how a reader may be made to share
“the dispositions, preferences and knowledge that make [one character’s] response
to [what is going on] a natural one,” see Currie, 22. Compare, also, to a recent compelling discussion, by Auyoung, of “postdictability” of Pride and Prejudice, that is, of
the availability of “locally surprising information” that makes readers experience as
“inevitable” certain emotional responses of the novel’s characters (When Fiction Feels
Real, 47). Finally, compare to the argument by Scarry, who suggests that texts offer
sets of “instructions” to their reader (Dreaming by the Book, 13).
96. Kuzmičová, “Consciousness,” 275.
97. Kuzmičová, 277. See also Kuzmičová and Bálint, “Personal Relevance in Story
Reading.”
98. Kuzmičová, 277.
99. Compare to Auyoung: “No two occasions of reading are ever exactly the same,
not just for different readers within the same interpretive community but even for
the same reader, who may approach a single text with a variety of reading goals,
fluctuating levels of motivation to pursue those goals, and newly acquired domains
of background knowledge, to say nothing of the reader’s variable moods, preferences, and physical surroundings” (When Fiction Feels Real, 6). See also Elfenbein,
Gist, 41–44; Graesser, Singer, and Trabasso, “Constructing Inferences”; and Cook,
“4E Cognition and the Humanities,” 879.
100. Kuzmičová, “Consciousness,” 275.
Notes
231
101. One way to talk about this process is to rely on yet another series of metaphors
and say that the secret life of literature is enactive, emergent, and embodied. There
is, currently, a rich body of criticism that applies the enactivist approach to literature. See, for instance, Kukkonen, 4E Cognition and Eighteenth-Century Fiction; Spolsky, Contracts of Fiction; Zunshine, “Embodied Social Cognition and Comparative
Literature”; Tribble and Sutton, “Cognitive Ecology”; Polvinen, “Sense-Making and
Wonder”; Polvinen, “Enactive Perception and Fictional Worlds”; Popova, Stories,
Meaning, and Experience; Troscianko, Kafka’s Cognitive Realism; and Garratt, Cognitive
Humanities.
102. M. Johnson, Embodied Mind, Meaning, and Reason, 34. But see also Nikola A.
Kompa’s useful critique of “embodied accounts of language comprehension,” 27.
103. De Jaegher and Di Paolo, “Participatory Sense-Making,” 495. Also: “Overemphasis on [explanation and prediction involved in mindreading] has led most of
the comparative social cognitive science to paint a picture of individuals who have
to work out each other’s minds much like they do with scientific problems” (De
Jaegher and Di Paolo, 486).
104. This description of the process of reading is explicitly modeled on De Jaegher
and Di Paolo’s definition of “social interaction as a regulated coupling between
at least two autonomous agents, where the regulation is aimed at aspects of the
coupling itself so that it constitutes an emergent autonomous organization in the
domain of relational dynamics, without destroying in the process the autonomy
of the agents involved (though the latter’s scope can be augmented or reduced)”
(“Participatory Sense-Making,” 493). Compare to Auyoung’s discussion of readers’
experience with fictional characters as “a form of social connection in which their
[i.e., readers’] autonomy is preserved” (When Fiction Feels Real, 120; see also 109).
105. For a discussion of challenges involved in this kind of study, see Elfenbein,
Gist, 101.
106. Natalie Phillips reports a similar experience when she writes about conducting
an interdisciplinary study involving cognitive scientists and literary scholars: “One of
my favorite moments in the process, however, was when our group—three humanists and two scientists—met one evening to discuss the project. Something happened:
the literary critics got excited about experimental variables; the scientists started
waxing poetic about Jane Austen’s style. Now, this kind of crosstalk has become part
of our everyday lives” (“Literary Neuroscience and History of Mind,” 57).
107. Elfenbein, Gist, 3–4.
108. If that is impossible, the next best thing to do is to “read actual articles rather
than overviews popularizing scientific findings” (Elfenbein, 6).
109. Jackson, “Beautiful Stranger,” 79.
232
Notes
110. As Ottessa Moshfegh sees it, the man in “The Beautiful Stranger” is “not quite
sly enough to convince his wife that he’s the same person he was before he left”
(foreword to Jackson, Dark Tales, viii).
111. Vapnyar, Still Here, 168–169.
112. To adapt Stanley Cavell’s term used to describe a particular Hollywood genre,
this would make Vika’s story a variation of “the comedy of remarriage” (Pursuits of
Happiness, 1).
113. Spark, Girls of Slender Means, 71.
114. Van Duijn, Sluiter, and Verhagen, “When Narrative Takes Over,” 148; italics in
the original.
115. Van Duijn, Sluiter, and Verhagen, 151. Note that Van Duijin et al. use the term
“multiple-order intentionality” (149) rather than “embedded mental states.”
116. Dunbar, How Many Friends Does One Person Need?, 180. See also Whalen, Zunshine, and Holquist, “Increases in Perspective Embedding” and Whalen et al., “Validating Judgments.”
117. Van Duijn, Sluiter, and Verhagen, “When Narrative Takes Over,” 149, 153.
Compare to Ralf Schneider’s useful description of various sources of information
involved in constructing a mental model of a character (“Cognitive Theory of Character Reception,” 122–123).
118. Quoted in Schenkar, Talented Miss Highsmith, 270.
119. Highsmith, Price of Salt, 363.
120. See Zunshine, Why We Read Fiction; Palmer, Social Minds in the Novel; and Vermeule, Why Do We Care about Literary Characters?
121. As Highsmith wrote later, the appeal of The Price of Salt “was that it had a
happy ending for its two main characters, or at least they were going to try to have
a future together. Prior to this book, homosexuals male and female in American
novels had had to pay for their deviation by cutting their wrists, drowning themselves in a swimming pool, or by switching to heterosexuality (so it was stated), or
by collapsing—alone and miserable and shunned—into a depression equal to hell”
(afterword to Selected Novels and Short Stories, 579).
122. Isabelle Johnson, MFA workshop, University of Kentucky, March 22, 2019.
123. Hagan Smith, MFA workshop, University of Kentucky, March 25, 2019.
124. Taylor Sarratt, MFA workshop, University of Kentucky, April 1, 2019.
125. Auyong, When Fiction Feels Real, 121.
Notes
233
126. Dunbar, “Why Are Good Writers So Rare?,” 7.
127. Dunbar, 17.
128. Miller, Kessel, and Flavell, “Thinking about People Thinking,” 622. See also my
argument in section 1.1.
129. Dunbar, “Why Are Good Writers So Rare?,” 18.
130. Dunbar, 18.
131. As Hogan puts it (citations omitted):
It is not only unnecessary for universals to apply to all works; they need not apply to all
traditions. Linguists use the term universal to refer to any property or relation that occurs
across (genetically and areally unrelated) languages with greater frequency than would be
predicted by chance alone. An absolute universal is merely a special case—a property or relation that occurs across traditions with a frequency of one. Universals with a frequency below
one are referred to as statistical universals. On the whole, we should expect to find a limited
number of hierarchies of statistically universal properties and relations, ordered according
to abstraction and thus according to frequency (again, as abstraction increases, frequency
can only increase or remain the same), with a few absolute universals at the apex of these
hierarchies.
This extension of “universal” to statistically unexpected properties may seem odd, even
misleading. However, it is perfectly in keeping with standard practices and definitions in all
sciences, and is inconsistent only with common prejudices about the nature of literary or,
more broadly, cultural universals. An example from the field of medicine may help to clarify
things. It is a universal principle of medicine that secondhand smoke causes lung cancer,
despite the fact that most people who have inhaled secondhand smoke never develop lung
cancer. It is a universal principle because there is a statistically significant correlation between
inhaling secondhand smoke and developing lung cancer (or, rather, there is a statistically
significant correlation that cannot be explained by other factors--obviously it is important to
distinguish between correlations that are primary or causal and those that are derivative or
noncausal). Statistical universals of literature, as well as linguistics, anthropology, etc., are no
different. (“Literary Universals,” 42–43)
132. Zamiatin, Мы, 7; translation mine. Original: “Все это без улыбки, я бы даже
сказал, с некоторой почтительностью (может быть, ей известно, что я—строитель
“Интеграла”). Но не знаю—в глазах или бровях—какой-то странный раздражающий
икс, и я никак не могу его поймать, дать ему цифровое выражение.”
133. McCarthy, Blood Meridian, 3.
134. Proust, Remembrance of Things Past, 34.
135. Isabelle Johnson, MFA workshop, University of Kentucky, March 22, 2019.
136. Defoe, Robinson Crusoe, 111.
137. Defoe, 148.
138. Wharton, “Xingu,” 25.
234
Notes
139. Defoe, Robinson Crusoe, 97.
140. Given the importance of embedded thinking for Defoe’s novel, we should not
hurry to conclude that, in contrast to twentieth-century introspective characters,
eighteenth-century “heroes like Robinson Crusoe . . . did things in the external
world that declared their beliefs and character” and that twentieth-century writers
“replaced these kinds of heroes with heroes like Mrs. Dalloway and Stephen Dedalus,
heroes whose reflective consciousness and inner lives supplied the novel’s action”
(Lantos, “Reconsidering Action,” 157; emphasis in the original).
141. Wordsworth, “Lines Composed a Few Miles above Tintern Abbey,” 1493, lines
58–65.
142. Herman, “Multimodal Storytelling,” 204.
143. Palmer, “Storyworlds and Groups.” For an important related analysis, see Palmer’s Social Minds in the Novel, in which he shows how a town such as Middlemarch
(2006) or Santa Dulcina delle Rocce of Evelyn Waugh’s Men at Arms can “actually
and literally does have a mind of its own” (74).
144. Defoe, Robinson Crusoe, 115.
145. As pointed out earlier, research by Dunbar and his colleagues strongly suggests
that fifth-level embedment of mental states represents “a real upper limit for most
people” (How Many Friends Does One Person Need?, 180). Moreover, in one of the
studies dealing with embedment of mental states that my colleagues and I conducted jointly with cognitive scientists, the question of how to process mental states
shared by several people came up. For instance, while counting levels of embedment, some experiment participants felt that when two people experience the same
doubly embedded mental states, the total number of embedments adds up to four.
To avoid ambiguity on this count, we felt that, for the purpose of future studies, it
would be useful to introduce subjects early on to Palmer’s concept of “intermental
unit” (Whalen et al., “Validating Judgments,” 291).
146. Eliot, Middlemarch, 506.
147. Eliot, 505.
148. Henry, Life of George Eliot, 38.
149. The Middlemarch crowd knows its mind because George Eliot knew hers. That
is, she knew where she stood on the subject of a rich landowner who dabbles in
politics without caring about progress. But consider a different scenario. In some
works of fiction, crowds don’t know what they want. As Monika Fludernik observes,
fictional crowds and, in particular, rioting mobs can be portrayed as dangerous precisely because they lack in consistency: the “monstrosity of the crowd consists in
its magnitude and its divisibility into constituent groups with their own agendas”
Notes
235
(“Collective Minds,” 702); see also Fludernik, “Many in Action and Thought.” And,
of course, the crowd’s dispersal “into many different viewpoints, [thwarts] the access
of the multitude to political impact.” Just as in Middlemarch, this outcome may be
a reflection of a particular ideology on the part of the author, and it is up to literary
critics to figure out what “ideological premises and rhetorical strategies of naturalization, defense, or resistance” may underlie such unflattering representations of
“collective minds” (Fludernik, “Collective Minds,” 710).
150. Apuleius, Golden Ass, 167.
151. Heliodorus, Ethiopian Romance, 73.
152. Murasaki, Tale of Genji (trans. Tyler), 8.
153. Murasaki, 8. Compare to other translations, e.g., Edward G. Seidensticker’s:
“Ashamed before the Takasago pines,/I would not have it known that I still live”
(Murasaki, Tale of Genji [trans. Seidensticker], 9; or Arthur Waley’s: “Though I know
that long life means only bitterness, I have stayed so long in the world that even
before the Pine Tree of Takasago I should hide my head in shame” (Murasaki, Tale of
Genji [trans. Waley], 9).
154. Irving, 158-Pound Marriage, 38.
155. Cao, Story of the Stone, vol. 1, 124. Original: “不想如今忽然來了一個薛寶釵,年歲雖大
不多,然品格端方,容貌豐美,人多謂黛玉所不及” (紅樓夢, 第五回).
156. Note that in the original, even that mental state is not present in this explicit
form. The word 謂 implies a verbal agreement rather than a mental state. 人多謂 is
“all said” rather than “all agreed”—although this is a situation in which the boundary between the two is blurry.
157. Castano, Martingano, and Perconti, “Effect of Exposure to Fiction.” The
authors consider this finding important for several reasons (citations are omitted):
“First, it contributes to the ongoing discourse surrounding the role of fiction in shaping social cognition . . . and is consistent with theory and research on the characteristics of literary fiction and how they may impact cognition and cognitive style. . . .
Second, understanding correlates and especially possible predictors of attributional
complexity is of importance and has far ranging potential consequences because
high attributional complexity attenuates racism . . . and plays a role in attitudes
about important policy-related opinions.” See also Kidd and Castano, “Reading
Literary Fiction and Theory of Mind”; and Wulandini, Kuntoro, and Handayani,
“Effect of Literary Fiction.”
158. See Fletcher et al., “Attributional Complexity,” 880.
159. As Castano et al. put it, “For one thing, the variables that are specifically associated with exposure to literary fiction may be desirable from one perspective, but
236
Notes
problematic from other perspectives. Literary fiction is associated with greater attributional complexity, which seems a valuable cognitive style from a societal perspective.
Yet, attributional complexity may also delay or derail decision-making and it has been
shown to be negatively related to mental health” (“Effect of Exposure to Fiction”).
160. See also Castano, “Art Films Foster Advanced Theory of Mind.”
161. van Kuijk et al., “Effect of Reading a Short Passage.”
162. See, for instance, the discussion by Ralph James Savarese, which complicates
the distinction between genres that involve “understanding characters” and those
“imagining different realities.” Specifically, Savarese objects to “the distinction
between literary and science fiction, as if the latter can’t be ‘literary,’” as well as to
“the claim that science fiction isn’t character-based” (See It Feelingly, 111).
163. Gavaler and Johnson, “Genre Effect,” 82. As they point out, citing Russian
Formalists’ analysis of Jonathan Swift’s Gulliver’s Travels and Laurence Sterne’s Life
and Opinions of Tristram Shandy, Gentleman, a text may straddle categories and also
migrate, in time, between them.
164. Peskin and Astington, “Effects of Adding Metacognitive Language.”
165. Culler, “Closeness of Close Reading,” 22.
166. Culler, 23.
167. B. Johnson, “Teaching Deconstructively,” 141. Quoted in Culler, “Closeness of
Close Reading,” 23.
168. For a discussion of translation as a form of close reading, see Culler, “Closeness
of Close Reading,” 24.
169. For a discussion of nuances of mindreading attributions that depend on the
translator’s understanding of the emotional and kinesic meaning of the scene, see
Bolens, Kinesic Humor, 95–105.
170. Zunshine, Getting Inside Your Head.
Chapter 2
1. De Jaegher and Di Paolo, “Participatory Sense-Making,” 498.
2. Mercier and Sperber, Enigma of Reason, 100. See also Andrew Ionescu on how
“folk psychology grounded in a folk sociology” may cause “erroneous interpretations of the others” in works of literature (“Manifesto,” 9).
3. Hirschfeld, “Myth of Mentalizing,” 101.
4. Sperber, Rethinking Symbolism, 115. What used to serve as a radical corrective
to the view that mental life is “for the most part . . . conscious, or at least open
Notes
237
to introspection”—that is, Freud’s notion of the “unconscious”—is now outdated
because it’s not radical enough: “Not some, but all mental processes, affective and
cognitive, are now seen as largely or even wholly unconscious” (Sperber, 114). On
the useful distinction between the cognitive and the traditional psychoanalytic
unconscious in the context of cognitive literary studies, see Crane, “Cognitive Historicism,” 18.
5. Hogan, Sexual Identities, 232.
6. Snodgrass, “Women’s Intuition,” 149; see also Vignemont, “Frames of Reference
in Social Cognition.” For a recent review, see Santos, Grossmann, and Varnum,
“Class, Cognition and Cultural Change.”
7. Miller, Losing It, 180–181.
8. See, for instance, Baum, Garofalo, and Yali, “Socioeconomic Status and Chronic
Stress.”
9. Simon Stern, email communication, March 8, 2018. For fascinating fictional
correlatives—for example, when characters refuse to read mental states of their
presumed social inferiors (e.g., as Nelly does Heathcliff’s, in Wuthering Heights) or
when the “unreadable character” is a “socially marginalized” colonial “other” (as in
Coetzee’s Waiting for the Barbarians), see Abbott, Real Mysteries, respectively, 125 and
143–144.
10. Sedgwick, “Privilege of Unknowing,” 23. I am grateful to Simon Stern for this
reference.
11. Solnit, “Nobody Knows,” 5. Compare, too, to Fritz Breithaupt’s comment that
“Nietzsche tells us that we should not expect rulers to have any capacity for selfobservation” (Dark Sides of Empathy, 150).
12. Note that this is still the same old me who, under different circumstances,
feels compelled to carefully parse the nuances of possible mental states of my dean
and who, under yet different circumstances (that is, in classroom, analyzing complex mental states of characters, readers, and other critics), may find the process
genuinely delightful. As Fletcher et al. observe, “The condition under which people
with complex schemata revert to the use of simple schemata or heuristics, or the
extent to which they do, are important questions for future research and theorizing”
(“Attributional Complexity,” 883).
13. Ochs, “Clarification and Culture,” 329.
14. Ochs, 333.
15. Tobar, “Assassin Next Door.” I thank Doug H. Whalen for bringing this passage
to my attention.
16. Vermeule, Why Do We Care about Literary Characters?, 86.
238
Notes
17. For a discussion, see Phillips, Distraction, 179–180; and Zunshine, “Bakhtin,”
118. See also Auyoung’s observation that if “even Mrs. Elton and Mr. Collins can
feel real to Austen’s readers [i.e., “capable of rotundity,” as E. M. Forster puts it], the
claim that fictional characters seem lifelike [i.e., not flat] is not necessarily a function of how much psychological depth they display” (When Fiction Feels Real, 40).
Compare to Vermuele, Why Do We Care about Literary Characters?, 83.
18. Tolstoy, Война и Мир, 331. Original: “Une ville occupée par l’ennemi ressemble
à une fille qui a perdu son honneur.”
19. Tolstoy, 279. Original (emphasis in the original):
Лицо Кутузова становилось все озабоченнее и печальнее. Из всех этих разговоров
Кутузов видел одно—защищать Москву не было никакой физической возможности, в
полном значении этих слов, то есть до такой степени не было возможности, что ежели
бы какой-нибудь безумный главнокомандующий отдал приказ о даче сражения, то
произошла бы путаница, и сражения все-т аки бы не было; не было бы потому, что все
высшие начальники не только признавали эту позицию невозможной, но в разговорах
своих обсуждали только то, что произойдет после несомненного оставления этой
позиции. Как же могли начальники вести свои войска на поле сражения, которое они
считали невозможным? Низшие начальники, даже солдаты (которые тоже рассуждают),
также признавали позицию невозможной и потому не могли одни драться с
уверенностью в поражении. Ежели Бенигсен настаивал на защите этой позиции и другие
еще обсуживали ее, то вопрос этот уже не имел значения сам по себе, а имел значение
только как предлог для ссоры и интриги. Это понимал Кутузов.
20. For an analysis of the difference between the complexity of Kutuzov’s thinking
as compared to Napoleon’s, see Allakhverdov, Psichologia Iskusstva, 76–78.
21. Austen, Mansfield Park, 197.
22. Austen, 310.
23. Austen, 113.
24. Zunshine, “From the Social to the Literary.”
25. Lee, “Measuring the Stomach of a Gentleman,” 205. For in-depth discussion of
“kinship sociality,” see Lee’s Stranger.
26. Lee, “Measuring the Stomach of a Gentleman,” 209. Compare, too, to Breithaupt’s analysis of Nietzsche’s view of women: “In the world of Nietzsche’s
thought, women are masters at manipulating the way they are seen by others. They
understand how they are observed but, unlike the objective person, they do not
comport themselves purely receptively and projectively in the face of observation.
Rather, they stake a claim to the observations of others by disguising, masking,
beautifying, or withholding themselves” (Dark Sides of Empathy, 160).
27. Lee, “Measuring the Stomach of a Gentleman,” 210.
28. Cao, Story of the Stone, vol. 1, 20.
Notes
239
29. For discussion, see Zunshine, “I Lie Therefore I Am.”
30. Zunshine, “Think What You’re Doing,” 47.
31. Tale of Frol Skobeev; translation mine. Original: “Смотри, мой друг,—говорит
Скобеев,—в каком она здравии: таков вот родительский гнев—они её за глаза
бранят и клянут, оттого она и при смерти лежит.”
32. Morris, Literature of Roguery, 51.
33. For a valuable cognitivist reading of the picaresque novel, see Simon, “Contextualizing Cognitive Approaches.” As he puts it,
The picaro, the hero of the genre, must live by his own wits to survive in a Spanish society
in which vast social inequalities exist, in spite of the enormous fortune plundered from its
American possessions. Throughout the story of his survival, the protagonist will rely on his
own ability to read others’ mental states and manipulate them. The resulting complexity of
the interplay of minds, between the picaro and the other characters (picaros or otherwise)
who are all trying to outsmart each other, is a central feature of this genre. In sum, as need
breeds ruse and craftiness, the social-economic disparities of early modern Spain are an essential component of the genre and serve as an important contextual factor in the rise of the
literary representation of intentionality. (19)
34. For a discussion of the master-manservant dialectic, see M. Gillespie, “From
Beau Brummell to Lady Bracknell,” 179.
35. Cusk, Saving Agnes, 157.
36. Ellison, introduction to Invisible Man, xxi.
37. Ellison, xix.
38. Ellison, xxii.
39. This applies not just to the Invisible Man’s position as a character but also to his
stance as a writer/narrator of his story. As John F. Callahan points out,
Invisible Man’s career as a failed orator teaches him that he must speak to us, his audience,
in order to speak for us. And he returns to that condition of eloquence in the profound rhetorical question with which he ends: “Who knows but that on the lower frequencies I speak
for you?” A writer’s communication with his audience—citizens, some of which may also be
other writers—may be an act of leadership. But, because of the nature of literature, narrative
leadership is a symbolic act. Invisible Man, having set himself free, encourages his readers to
take similar action. He does not attempt, as he has done presumptuously and blindly so many
times, to lead his audience but to make contact on an equal individual basis. (“Frequencies
of Eloquence,” 87)
40. Ellison, Invisible Man, 508.
41. Ellison, 559.
42. For an analysis of the trickster/picaro references in Invisible Man, see Nadel, Invisible Criticism. Nadel complicates Norton Frye’s comparison of Ellison’s protagonist
to such classic folklore and literary figures as Brer Bear, Brer Rabbit, and the “tricky
240
Notes
slave of Roman comedy,” emphasizing “the specific conditions that created the Brer
Bear and Brer Rabbit versions of the eiron,” conditions that also obtain in the case
of Invisible Man. For the latter “also manifest the specific marks of oppression and
consequent encoding created by the racial caste system deeply embedded in the
legal and extralegal institutions of the South. The slave in Roman comedy who wins
his freedom ceases to be in an ironic position; he is not merely ostensibly free, not
like the free black in the South, a slave without a master” (32–33).
43. As Valerie Smith observes, “Throughout the course of his life, the Invisible Man
learns that he can never quite learn to be deceptive enough. No matter how devious
he thinks he is, those who control him always manage to trick and betray him”
(“Meaning of Narration,” 209).
44. Ellison, Invisible Man, 257.
45. Ellison, 478.
46. Ellison, 477.
47. One wonders to what extent this dynamic is still at play in other literary contexts in which white characters are portrayed as not being able to appreciate the
complex subjectivity of Black characters. Consider, for instance, Jennifer Riddle Harding’s observation that in Charles Chesnutt’s short story “Dave’s Neckliss” (1889),
the narratees of the story within the story, John and Annie, see the narrator, an old
African American man named Julius, “largely as a childish, ham-loving old man who
tells whimsical stories about slavery” and that neither John nor Annie are capable of
appreciating “Julius’s metaphors and his humor” (“Mind Enslaved?,” 439).
48. Not only does Evelina signal to Mr. Smith her social superiority, but she also
manages to do so without offending her grandmother, Mme. Duval, who is present
and quite happy with Mr. Smith’s courtship of her granddaughter. Here, as on many
other occasions, Evelina’s speech manifests the quality of what the Burney scholar
Julia Epstein describes as “double-edgedness” (Iron Pen, 111), which is a particularly
fascinating term if we consider the embedments that underlie it.
49. Burney, Evelina, 220.
50. Bakhtin, “Discourse in the Novel,” 265.
51. Bakhtin, 308, 262.
52. Burney, Evelina, 327.
53. Burney, 330–331.
54. See Holquist, Dialogism, 154–155.
55. As Brian McCrea puts it, building on Michael McKeon’s concept of “status
inconsistency,” Burney’s “satire upon Mr. Smith doesn’t imply an endorsement of
characters like Coverley and Merton” (Frances Burney, 54).
Notes
241
56. Burney, Evelina, 221.
57. Burney, 146.
58. Burney, 177.
59. Burney, 188.
60. Burney, 206.
61. Burney, 275.
62. That Captain Mirvan seems to embed mental states on the second level more
consistently than, say, Mme. Duval or the Branghtons (who tend to stay around the
first level) may reflect his peculiar role in Evelina. As Ruth Bernard Yeazell observes,
“though there is scarcely a character in the novel who seems more distant from Evelina than this crude ex-sailor, he nonetheless has a remarkable tendency to aim his
practical jokes at targets whom she herself has strong motives to attack” (Fictions of
Modesty, 141).
63. Burney, 141. See Francesca Saggini for a discussion of Burney’s possible appropriation of the “long-established theatrical technique of employing particular
speech patterns for characterization” (Backstage in the Novel: Frances Burney and the
Theater Arts [University of Virginia Press, 2012], 78) in her representation of Captain
Mirvan and Mme Duval.
64. Burney, 13, 19, 227, 355, 257.
65. Jane Spencer concurs: “on the whole the novel shows remarkably little sympathy
for a grandmother deprived of her grandchild.” Spencer sees this as part of the general
pattern informing Burney’s narrative: “With its strong emotional investment in the
heroine’s relationship to her father and to father figures, Evelina honours the patriline
and is ambivalent about the matriline” (“Evelina and Cecilia,” 27). While I agree with
Spencer’s analysis, my focus here is on specific rhetorical strategies (such as low-level
emdedment of mental states associated with her) that make Mme. Duval a less sympathetic character than her personal losses might have entitled her to be. See also
Kristina Straub’s useful discussion of the novel’s divided consciousness when it comes
to the treatment of older women, such as Mme. Duval (Divided Fictions, 30).
66. Which may work, as it does more often than not, in Evelina’s case, as a heightened awareness of one’s own feelings (e.g., shame) in response to other people’s
perceptions of oneself, what Yeazell calls Evelina’s “obsession with watching herself
being watched” (Fictions of Modesty, 123).
67. As Epstein puts it, Mme. Duval’s “roughhewn sensibility makes it impossible for
her to empathize with others” (Iron Pen, 113).
68. At least this is what we encounter in Evelina. We can’t assume that this is a
general rule in fiction. Complexity does not imply moral goodness. High embedders
242
Notes
may come across as sensitive and intelligent people, or they may come across as
peculiarly misguided, betrayed as it were by their sociocognitive complexity into
ethically questionable or socially debilitating behavior. And do not forget about evil
masterminds, whose hubristic Machiavellianism may render them abhorrent in the
eyes of the reader. (Compare to Vermeule’s important discussion of masterminds in
Why Do We Care about Literary Characters?, 86.)
69. This happens when Tom Branghton uses his connection with Evelina to mooch
a free ride out of Lord Orville (Evelina, 248–249).
70. Santos, Grossmann, and Varnum, “Class, Cognition and Cultural Change.”
71. Santos, Grossmann, and Varnum.
72. Some literary critics feel very uncomfortable applying insights from contemporary psychology to the historical past. As Elfenbein explains,
Such investigations open themselves to an easy charge of anachronism: since most psychological findings derive from participants who postdate [the past centuries], we cannot know
if those findings apply to earlier periods. Yet literary scholars routinely apply approaches and
insights honed in the twentieth- and twenty-first century academy to works written in earlier
periods. Nervousness about the use of cognitive science is an arbitrary invocation of rigor that
misrecognizes the field’s enabling anachronisms. Also, there is no reason to decide a priori
that contemporary psychological findings are irrelevant to the past. If it is wrong to assume
that there is no difference between now and then, it is equally wrong to assume that there
are no continuities either; assertions of historical difference do not guarantee truth any more
than do ones of continuity. (Gist, 168)
73. Pocock, Virtue, Commerce, and History, 119. Of course, the dynamic of the relationship between social class and cognitive complexity can be reversed. For a compelling
example of such a reversal, see Ellen Bayuk Rosenman’s argument that the working
poor can be presented as having a more “layered consciousness of social interactions,” and thus “the most satisfying understanding” of a social situation, than their
middle-class “betters” do (“Rudeness, Slang, and Obscenity,” 58).
74. Doody, Frances Burney, 3.
75. Zunshine, “Why Jane Austen Was Different.”
76. Shakespeare, Measure for Measure, 4.3.110–114.
77. Zunshine, Getting Inside Your Head, chap. 3.
78. Vineberg, “Problem Plays,” 33.
79. For an important discussion of what it means for an author to display an intuitive awareness of various “cognitive” insights that couldn’t have been known to the
scientific (or natural-philosophic) thought of their day, see Hogan, Sexual Identities.
80. For a discussion of goals, methods, and the disciplinary trajectory of cognitive
historicism, see Crane, “Cognitive Historicism.”
Notes
243
81. Lee, “Measuring the Stomach of a Gentleman,” 219. See also Lee, “Society Must
Be Defended.”
82. See also Emmerich, “GDR and Its Literature,” 28.
83. For a recent discussion of functions of the unreliable narrator in the Russian
novel of the 1920s–1930s, see Zhilicheva, “Функции ‘Ненадежного.’”
84. For a discussion of a related dynamic in the GDR, i.e., when “some of the most
significant works of GDR literature were either never published or only published
years or even decades after the fact,” see Emmerich, GDR and Its Literature, 20.
85. Borden, “Leonid Dobychin’s The Town of N,” viii.
86. Morris, “Russia,” 213. See also Karin Leeder’s observation about the literature
produced in the GDR, which describes, to some extent, attitudes toward the official
literary output of the Soviet Union. As she writes, “it is undoubtedly the case that for
many years critical judgments in East and West were skewed more to political or moral
considerations than aesthetic ones” (introduction to Rereading East Germany, 2).
87. See Günther, “Soviet Literary Criticism,” 105. Elsewhere, Günther also points out
that, “just as in the Soviet Union, in Germany in the 1930s, struggle for classicism
meant the struggle against modernism” (“Zeleznaja Garmonija,” 38; translation mine).
88. As Nancy Easterlin observes, “the history of literary theoretical approaches
in the twentieth century . . . demonstrates the problem of assuming a correlation
between aesthetic practices and the ideological implications of artworks. The vagaries of Marxist criticism serve as the most prominent example.” In the three decades
subsequent to the Russian Revolution in 2017, “arguments that unusual and nonrepresentational techniques exposed class struggle kept pace with contrary arguments that mainstream realism served as the best mechanism for enlightenment”
(Biocultural Approach, 98).
89. Hake, “Political Affects,” 106–107. See also her discussion of “socialist modernism” (Hake, 108–109). See, however, Günther, “Zheleznaya Garmonia,” for a different perspective. As he puts it, “on the whole, totalitarian culture is an enemy
of modernism; it represents, rather, a form of enforced postmodernism. Everything
associated with the avant-garde is subjected to a strictest selection; what is selected is
useful from the point of view of the official ideology” (31; translation mine).
90. Compare to Günther: “In literature and in art, the danger arose above all from
ambiguity and lack of transparency, which—not without foundation—were seen
as the source of dissidence and the possibility of ‘ideological contraband’” (“Soviet
Literary Criticism,” 96). See also Emmerich’s discussion of GDR literature after 1965,
in which, as he observes, poets, in particular, became aware “of literature’s potential as subversive counter-discourse, in which they could practice diverse ways of
speaking—heteroglossia, dialogism and intertextuality—and thus undermine the
monosemy-affirming language environment” (“The GDR and Its Literature,” 25).
244
Notes
91. Günther, “Soviet Literary Criticism,” 106.
92. Günther, 97. See also David Brandenberger’s discussion of the resolution of the
Central Committee, of December 1928, “on state publishing,” which mandated,
among other things, that publishing industry provided “for mass literature’s maximal accessibility (in both form and content) in order to find the broadest swath of
readership” (Propaganda State in Crisis, 23).
93. Günther, 106.
94. Günther, “Zheleznaya Garmonia,” 40; translation mine.
95. For a discussion of the official GDR literature after 1965, see Emmerich, “The
GDR and Its Literature,” 22. Particularly, as he observes, in that time period, writers
“made use of unconventional, eccentric or dislocated narrative perspectives, which
reached the standards set by modernism decades earlier (self-reflexivity, discontinuity and lack of plot)” (24).
96. Ellison, introduction to Invisible Man, xix.
97. Ellison, xxi, xxii.
98. Günther, “Zheleznaya Garmonia,” 27; translation mine.
99. Lee, “Measuring the Stomach of a Gentleman,” 219.
100. Gladkov, Цемент, 241; translation mine. Original:
Глеб положил голову на колени Даши и увидел над собою ее лицо с огнистым пушком
на щеках и глаза—пристальные, большие, встревоженные и любящие.
—Здесь, под небом, чувствуешь себя другим, Дашок. Вот лежу у тебя на коленях . . .
Когда это было?.. И никогда я, кажется, не переживал ничего подобного. Я знаю только
одно, что твоя любовь была больше и глубже моей, и я тебя недостоин. Я и сотой доли
не пережил того, что пережила ты. Расскажи же мне сама о своих мытарствах . . . М
ожет
быть, я и себя тогда узнаю лучше.
Воздух внезапно вспыхнул молнией: везде большими и маленькими звездами
зароились огни. Волна восторга охватила Глеба; в волнении он поднялся на локоть.
—Даша, голубка, гляди . . . как хорошо бороться и строить свою судьбу!.. Ведь это—
все наше . . . мы!.. Наша сила и труд . . . Б
удто вздох чувствуешь . . . в здох перед первым
ударом . . . когда хочется размахнуться . . .
Даша опять положила руки на его грудь. Она сама волновалась, и Глеб слышал, как
глухими толчками билось ее сердце.
—Да, милый, хорошо бороться за свою судьбу . . . П
усть муки, пусть смерть . . .
Страшно это . . . и не всякий может вынести . . . Я вот вынесла, потому что люблю тебя
сильнее страха . . . А потом и другое поняла, другое полюбила . . . м
ожет, даже больше
тебя . . .
—Говори, Дашок . . . что бы ни было—г овори . . . Я уж научился не только слушать,
но и . . . бороться с собой . . .
101. Of course, the socialist realist protagonists’ tongue-tiedness also harks back to
the literary convention, already well in place by the end of the nineteenth century,
according to which a strong emotional experience “was thought to elude expression
in language” (Martens, “Corporeality,” 237).
Notes
245
102. Gladkov, Цемент, 236. Original: “Внутренние Прослойки.”
103. Gladkov, 220, 221, 222.
104. Emmerich, “The GDR and Its Literature,” 19.
105. Paul, “Gender in GDR Literature,” 108.
106. Claudius, Menschen an unserer Seite, 274–75; translated by and quoted in Paul,
“Gender in GDR Literature,” 109.
107. Claudius, 171–172; translated by and quoted in Paul, 108.
108. See also Lee’s suggestive exploration of Chinese socialist realism in “When
Nothing Is True.”
109. Wolf, They Divided the Sky, 34–35.
110. On Wolf’s subsequent commitment to “revise” socialist realism, expressed
“in her comments in various interviews and essays,” see Wiesehan, “Christa Wolf
Reconsidered,” 79.
111. “100 Must-Reads.”
112. See A. Richardson, Neural Sublime; Crane, Shakespeare’s Brain; Spolsky, Satisfying
Skepticism; Phillips, Distraction; and Keen, Thomas Hardy’s Brains.
Chapter 3
1. Over the years, literary scholars have suggested several other essential features.
See, for instance, Miall, “Science in the Perspective of Literariness”; and A. Richardson, “Studies in Literature and Cognition.”
2. As Nancy Easterlin puts it, some literary scholars
point to the youth of neuroscience and the inferential nature of experimental psychology
to confirm the prejudice that that science has nothing of interest to offer the student of
literature. But drawing such a hasty conclusion is unwarranted in the light of the pragmatic
process whereby ideas are tested, gain or lose force, and are rejected as invalid or accepted as
legitimate knowledge by communities of learning. The more intellectually defensible conclusion to draw, given the experimental and provisional nature of so many psychological
findings, is that our own uses of ideas from this new field will themselves be provisional and
experimental. (Biocultural Approach, 154)
3. B. Schieffelin, “Found in Translation,” 143.
4. Keane, Ethical Life, 131.
5. Consider, for instance, how easily Soviet writers ignored the long tradition of
whimsical narrators, under socialist realism.
6. Astuti, “Some After Dinner Thoughts.”
7. Astuti.
246
Notes
8. Duranti, “Further Reflections,” 492. In fact, the etymology of the word “intention” testifies to the boundedness of mind reading with embodiment. As Duranti
points out, “the contemporary understanding of intention comes from the Latin
intentio originally understood as an embodied movement or ‘tension’” (Anthropology of Intention, 72–73). But see also Gregory Hickok for an alternative explication of
the role of embodiment in mindreading (Myth of Mirror Neurons, 171–172).
9. Boyer, Minds Make Societies, 222.
10. As Karin Kukkonen observes, “It seems quite likely that thought does not coincide with language, but this does not mean that language would not have an effect
on the ways in which we think” (“Does Cognition Translate?,” 251). Specifically, as
Lisa Feldman Barrett proposes, “words invite the formation of emotion concepts,
and . . . these emotion concepts, by providing the kind of attention-guiding and
perception-shaping predictions mentioned above, then enable us to understand
inner bodily states in terms of meaningful emotions” (quoted in Kukkonen, 249).
11. Wolf, City of Angels, 19. As Elfenbein puts it, “we are . . . battling the linearity of
writing to capture the nonlinear, weblike experience of reading” (Gist, 36).
12. See Drucker, Graphesis, 64–137. For a related discussion of “pictorialism” and
cognition, see Troscianko, Kafka’s Cognitive Realism, 41–42, 54.
13. Sabbagh and Baldwin, “Understanding the Role,” 171.
14. M. Johnson, “Embodiment of Language,” 630. See also Martins and Fitch, “Do
We Represent Intentional Action as Recursively Embedded?” As they point out in
the conclusion of their essay, “the point is that models positing recursion are only
relevant for human cognition if humans actually represent and use implicit knowledge of recursion in their activities: a demonstration of which requires hard empirical work” (20). But see also Tomasello, Origins of Human Communication, 336. Finally,
for a discussion of enactivism as an alternative to representationalism (“according to
the enactivist view, there is no representation of the world inside the brain”) and
for a useful alternative view of “functional” representations, see Troscianko, Kafka’s
Cognitive Realism, 114, 73–75.
15. I owe this insight to the anonymous reader of my manuscript enlisted by the
MIT Press.
16. Mercier and Sperber, Enigma of Reason, 81.
17. Some cognitive literary scholars working with an enactive paradigm (e.g.,
Kukkonen, Polvinen, Caracciolo, and Troscianko) experiment with moving in
that direction. To appreciate challenges that they face—that is, to see how their
analyses may still depend on their awareness of the dynamic created by complex
embedments—consider Troscianko’s study of emotional appraisal as “an affective
and enactive cognitive act” in Kafka’s Metamorphosis. When Gregor Samsa overhears
Notes
247
his “mother worrying out loud to his sister that it would be a cruelty, not a kindness,
to empty his room of furniture,” he wonders about his response to her suggestion,
while Kafka’s readers are made aware that he may not fully realize what his response
entails. As Kafka (in Troscianko’s translation) puts it, “On hearing these words from
his mother Gregor realised that the lack of all direct human speech, along with the
monotony of life within the family, must have confused his mind over the past
two months, for he could not account otherwise for the fact that he could quite
earnestly have longed for his room to be emptied” (Kafka’s Cognitive Realism, 167).
As Troscianko explains,
After the fact, Gregor’s elaborative, experienced appraisal is that he’d longed for the room to
be emptied because he’d been confused by the lack of verbal contact with other people and
the monotony of family life. But the reader is also prompted here, precisely by the mention of
confusion, to interpret things differently from Gregor: the obvious alternative is to understand
what he glosses as confusion to be instead the natural cognitive changes resulting from his
transformation into an insect and the simultaneous changes in his behavioural preferences.
The antecedent appraisal would then be “this is a good thing, because I want to be able to
crawl over the walls and ceiling more easily,” making Gregor happily anticipatory. Then, by
the time of the realisation quoted here, he has reappraised events as “I thought this was a good
thing because I was confused by being so isolated and bored (so I am upset),” implicitly with
a new antecedent appraisal of “this is a bad thing, because I’m scared of becoming more fully
an animal.” By highlighting the discrepancies between possible emotional appraisals, the text
dramatises the ambivalences and fears involved in Gregor’s gradual transition to a more fully
insect state, as well as his attempts to deny them. . . . [The] potentially unsettling aspect of this
kind of evocation consists in the way that Gregor’s introspective capacities are so clearly yet
subtly flagged as flawed: his access to the causes of his own mental states is presented as confused even as he supposedly identifies prior confusion in himself. The possibility of introspective insight, and in particular the transparency of emotion to itself, are called into question by
the (somewhat messy) inseparability of thought and emotion in the form of appraisal. (167)
Note how Troscianko’s analysis of emotional reappraisals experienced by Gregor
directly depends on her (and our) processing of a series of complex embedments,
which involve her/our awareness of Gregor’s flawed understanding of the meaning of his introspective insights. For Troscianko, highlighting complex embedments
present in the text serves as a means toward a particular interpretive end: it is a
stepping stone toward her compelling exploration of antecedent and elaborative
appraisals. What I propose here is that we slow down and become aware of that
stepping stone as an underappreciated but crucial element of a critical analysis centering on enactive cognition.
18. For an overview of some alternatives to “cognitivism” (which provides the base
for the current, metaphor-laden concept of theory of mind), such as, for instance,
“antirepresentationalism” and “relationalism,” see Baggs, “Book Review,” 1947.
19. Vessel, Starr, and Rubin, “Brain on Art.” As Randy L. Buckner and Daniel Carroll
observe, “default modes of cognition are characterized by a shift from perceiving the
external world to internal modes of cognition that simulate worlds that are separate
from the one being directly experienced” (“Self-Projection and the Brain,” 53).
248
Notes
20. Buckner, Andrews-Hanna, and Schacter, “Brain’s Default Network,” 1, quoted in
Hickok, Myth of Mirror Neurons, 171.
21. Li, Mai, and Liu, “Default Mode Network.”
22. Frith, “Social Mind?”
23. Dunbar, How Many Friends Does One Person Need?, 180. See also Whalen, Zunshine, and Holquist, “Increases in Perspective Embedding”; and Whalen et al., “Validating Judgments of Perspective Embedding.”
24. Stiller and Dunbar, “Perspective-Taking and Memory Capacity,” 95, 100.
25. For further discussion, see Stiller, Nettle, and Dunbar, “Small World of Shakespeare’s Plays,” 401.
26. Kanske et al., “Dissecting the Social Brain,” 6.
27. For a review, see Apperly, Cognitive Basis, 11–34. See also Milligan, Astington,
and Dack, “Language and Theory of Mind.”
28. Astington, Pelletier, and Homer, “Theory of Mind and Epistemological Development,” 133, 142. See also Deena Skolnick and Paul Bloom’s study of children’s
perspective taking in the case of fictional characters. As they point out, there is
“considerable evidence that children have difficulty with conceptual perspective
taking before the age of five” (“What Does Batman Think about Sponge Bob?,” B13.
29. See, for instance, an important volume, Theory of Mind in the Pacific, edited by
Wassmann, Träuble, and Funke (2013). As Tanya Luhrmann summarizes in her
review of the collection,
[This] book presents a series of research projects in the Pacific by experimenters and ethnographers. That region has long been famous for its so-called opacity of mind—for the
strong sense that it is inappropriate to ask about someone else’s intentions, beliefs, and
desires, or presume that one knows what they are. In what way might this strong cultural
bias affect theory of mind? [What the researches found was that, although] theory of
mind abilities develop universally among all human populations, [the] onset of mental
state reasoning . . . varies across cultures as a consequence of different socialisation practices and ethnotheories concerning, for example, mental state talk. (“Theory of Mind in the
Pacific,” 443)
30. Astington, Pelletier, and Homer, “Theory of Mind and Epistemological Development,” 133.
31. Onishi and Baillargeon, “Do 15-Months-Old Infants Understand.” For a discussion, see Mercier and Sperber, Enigma of Reason, 94–96.
32. To quote Rebecca Saxe, there is the puzzling divergence between “recent
advances in developmental psychology [that] suggest that children have some
understanding of false beliefs much earlier than age 3 years, and initial neuroimaging studies of children’s brains [that] suggest that key maturational changes in the
Notes
249
[right temporo-parietal junction] occur much later than age 5 years” (“New Puzzle,”
108). To account for this divergence, some scientists now propose a two-system
theory of mindreading; that is, they suggest that infants’ theory of mind is housed
in a neural system distinct from that in which it will be housed later in development
(see Saxe, 110; and Apperly, Cognitive Basis, 108–181). The first system encompasses
“‘low-level’ processes that are cognitively efficient but inflexible, and the second,
‘high-level’ processes that are highly flexible but cognitively demanding.” In this
view, when we “make explicit judgments about what others think or want” (or
want us to think), we rely on the “high-level” processes, but what “gets us through
our social day” is a “combination of low-level mindreading processes and the rich
endowment of social knowledge that we gain through development” (Apperly, Cognitive Basis, 143, 155). For some responses to this proposal, see Mercier and Sperber,
Enigma of Reason, 341; and Carruthers, “Two Systems for Mindreading?”
33. Carruthers, “Two Systems for Mindreading?,” 159.
34. This may date to David G. Premack and Guy Woodruff’s “Does the Chimpanzee
Have a Theory of Mind?”
35. Miller, Kessel, and Flavell, “Thinking about People Thinking,” 623.
36. Saxe and Kanwisher, “People Thinking about Thinking People,” 1835.
37. See Saxe and Powell, “It’s the Thought That Counts.”
38. Skerry and Saxe, “Neural Representations of Emotion,” 1951.
39. Saxe and Kanwisher, “People Thinking about Thinking People,” 1841.
40. Kanske et al., “Dissecting the Social Brain,” 17.
41. See Keen, Empathy and the Novel; Savarese, See It Feelingly; and Breithaupt, Dark
Sides of Empathy. Also, see Joshua Landy for a witty critique of the view that good
literature “simply gives us no choice but to be improved by it” (How to Do Things
with Fictions, 30). For important studies of empathy and literature conducted by
social psychologists, see Mar, Tackett, and Moore, “Exposure to Media”; and Djikic,
Oatley, and Moldoveanu, “Reading Other Minds.”
42. As Elfenbein puts is, “Literary scholars assume that characters are not real people
and that the questions appropriate to ask about them are not the same ones that we
might ask about real people. Yet no matter how often we stress such a point, both
students in literature classes and many critics find that it never fully takes hold. For
all our efforts, readers persist in treating literary characters as if they were people
they had met” (Gist, 59).
43. Nettle, email communication, June 28, 2006. Also, see David Herman’s suggestive argument about “thinking about thinking—or intelligence about intelligence”
(Storytelling and the Sciences of the Mind, 278).
250
Notes
44. Boyer, Minds Make Societies, 131, 153. See also Tomasello, Origins of Human
Communication, chap. 5 (“Phylogenetic Origins”). As Tomasello puts it, “The combination of helpfulness and recursive mindreading led to mutual expectations of helpfulness and the Gricean communicative intention as a guide to relevance inferences,
which could then come under social norms created by still another uniquely human
propensity, in this case to be like and to be liked by others in this social group, as
opposed to those other social groups” (218).
45. Kanske et al., “Dissecting the Social Brain,” 17.
46. William James, The Principles of Psychology, quoted in Easterlin, Biocultural
Approach, 156.
47. Easterlin, Biocultural Approach, 156.
48. See Palmer, Fictional Minds, for an exploration of this point.
49. As Auyoung puts it, the “sustained experience of reading between the lines intensifies the reader’s consciousness of being uniquely able to comprehend the implied
author” (When Fiction Feels Real, 55). For a discussion of such “nonreciprocal sense
of intimacy” between the reader and the author, see Auyoung, 109; and Auyoung,
“Unspoken Intimacy.”
50. Compare to the religious studies scholar Paul C. Dilley’s critique of “strict universalism of . . . [a] proposal for a ‘cognitive historiography’ dedicated to discovering
universal historical ‘rules’ based on evolutionary trends.” In its stead, similarly to
literary scholars working with cognitive approaches to literature (e.g., see Crane,
“Cognitive Historicism”), Dilley proposes a “’cognitive historicism,’ on the model
of New Historicism, with its emphasis on understanding texts in their ideological
context, as well as uncovering the mechanisms of power in cultural representations”
(Monasteries and the Care of Souls, 12).
Chapter 4
1. Luhrmann, “Toward an Anthropological Theory of Mind,” 6.
2. Luhrmann, 7.
3. B. Schieffelin, “Speaking Only Your Own Mind,” 433.
4. Robbins and Rumsey, “Introduction,” 407–408.
5. Astuti, “Some After Dinner Thoughts.”
6. Luhrmann, “Toward an Anthropological Theory of Mind,” 11.
7. Luhrmann, 11.
8. Bambi Schieffelin, personal communication, March 1, 2019.
Notes
251
9. Steven Feld, email communication, March 1, 2019.
10. Luhrmann, “Toward an Anthropological Theory of Mind,” 7.
11. Throop, “Suffering,” 128.
12. Throop, 129.
13. Lepowsky, “Personhood,” 48.
14. For a useful related analysis of comparative “perceptions of mental state access
in the United States and Japan,” see Wice at al. As they observe, the overall “results
indicate that culturally variable norms specifying appropriate levels of mental state
access play an important role in how individuals estimate their knowledge of other
people’s minds in close relationships” (n.p.).
15. Ochs and Schieffelin, “Language Acquisition and Socialization,” 298.
16. B. Schieffelin, “Speaking Only Your Own Mind,” 434.
17. B. Schieffelin, 433.
18. B. Schieffelin, 438. See also Bambi Schieffelin’s more extensive treatment of this
topic in her book Give and Take of Everyday Life, in which she observes that Kaluli say
that “one cannot know what another thinks or feels” (72).
19. B. Schieffelin, Give and Take, 73. For a discussion, see Sabbagh and Baldwin,
“Understanding the Role,” 167. Also, compare to Ellen Dissanayake’s argument
about baby talk as a “proto-aesthetic device” (“Prelinguistic and Preliterate Substrates,” 63).
20. B. Schieffelin, Give and Take, 71.
21. B. Schieffelin, 72–73.
22. Steven Feld, email communication, March 1, 2019.
23. Consider, for instance, premodern China, which, as Haiyan Lee argues, may have
selectively drawn on the “opacity principle” in some of its “mainstream expressive
culture,” which prioritized “dramatic speech and action over interior monologues and
embedded mental states” (“Measuring the Stomach of a Gentleman,” 205).
24. Bambi Schieffelin, personal communication, March 1, 2019.
25. Caldwell-Harris, Kronrod, and Yang, “Do More, Say Less,” 53.
26. Oforlea, “Dilemma of the African American Detective.”
27. Ochs and Schieffelin, “Language Acquisition,” 303–304.
28. Keane, Ethical Life, 127.
29. B. Schieffelin, “Found in Translation,” 143.
252
Notes
30. Throop, “Suffering,” 133.
31. Ochs and Schieffelin, “Language Acquisition,” 299.
32. Throop, “Suffering,” 134.
33. Trawalter et al., “Attending to Threat,” 1325. See also Argyle and Cook, Gaze and
Mutual Gaze; and Mason, Tatkow, and Macrae, “Look of Love.”
34. As Lasse Hodne puts it, in studies of gaze orientation in Western portraits, conducted by experimental art historians, “the overall reaction” of subjects showed
that “frontal faces with direct gaze . . . were regarded to be more caring, trustworthy,
harmonic, inclusive and respectable than the corresponding images with averted gaze
and face” (“Memling’s Portraits of Christ,” 254). Compare to Kayo Muira and Motoko
Koike’s discussion of gaze orientation in Japanese Ukiyo-e pictures, in “Judgment,
Interpretation and Impression of Gaze Direction.” As they point out, an “averted”
gaze or an “ambiguous” gaze direction may give rise to “negative emotion,” even in
a culture known for “a tendency to avoid direct eye contact” (218). As they suggest,
one reason for this negative response may be that the avoidant figure (in this case, a
woman standing next to a young child) may be perceived as refusing to engage in a culturally “desirable” practice of “viewing together” or “side-by-side relation” (219, 220).
35. Landau, “11 Reasons a Child Cannot Look You in the Eyes.” As Landau puts it,
“Particularly [in] Asian cultures, eye contact can be seen as a sign of disrespect. To
look at someone directly can be considered bold or defiant, so it is avoided.”
36. Landau.
37. Bambi Schieffelin, personal communication, March 1, 2019.
38. Abbott, Real Mysteries, 146.
39. Abbott, 146–147.
40. See Savarese and Zunshine, “Critic as Neurocosmopolite,” 21–26.
41. Hickok, Myth, 208.
42. Hickok, 224.
43. Blackman, “Reflections on Language,” 149, 153. Quoted in Savarese and Zunshine, “Critic as Neurocosmopolite,” 23.
44. Ochs and Schieffelin, “Language Acquisition,” 299.
45. S. Richardson, Clarissa, 460.
46. Throop, “Suffering,” 133.
47. Of course, direct eye contact can be experienced as intrusive and frightening in
the context of the culture of transparency, too. See, for instance, Blakey Vermuele’s
Notes
253
discussion of Big Brother’s “enormous black staring eyes that seem to follow you
everywhere” (Why Do We Care about Literary Characters?, 53).
48. Dilley, Monasteries, 14–15.
49. Dilley, 234.
50. Dilley, 295.
51. Dilley, 295.
52. Asztalos, “Faculty of Theology,” 409.
53. Leff, “Trivium and the Three Philosophies,” 308.
54. Robbe-Grillet, Two Novels, 51.
55. David Richter, email communication, April 23, 2018.
56. I use the word “naturalize” here the same way that Abbott does when he
explains that “most readers of modernist texts . . . have learned to naturalize and
thus accept without strain” certain “unique, even disturbing” textual features (Real
Mysteries, 39; also 39n16). See also Monika Fludernik, Towards a “Natural” Narratology , 274.
57. Abbott, Real Mysteries, 145.
58. Lorant, Melville, 333. Quoted in Abbott, Real Mysteries, 129.
59. Abbott, Real Mysteries, 128–130.
60. Troscianko, Kafka’s Cognitive Realism, 199. For the full description of the experiment, see Troscianko, 217–218.
61. See Zunshine, Getting Inside Your Head, 150.
62. Abbott, Real Mysteries, 152.
63. B. Schieffelin, “Found in Translation,” 150.
64. Ochs and Schieffelin “Language Acquisition,” 294.
65. B. Schieffelin, “Found in Translation,” 150.
66. B. Schieffelin, “Two Dukula Sulo: & One Dog”; B. Schieffelin, email communication, January 23, 2019.
67. Rumsey, “Empathy and Anthropology,” 222.
68. Compare to Dissanayake’s argument that, although “literary scholars occasionally pay lip service to the existence of oral literature, it may not be fully realized that
a minute proportion of all humans throughout history have been readers or writers,
yet they nevertheless invented and responded to literary language” (“Prelinguistic
and Preliterate Substrates,” 70).
254
Notes
69. For a full discussion, see Zunshine, “Who Is He to Speak of My Sorrow?”
70. E. Schieffelin, Sorrow of the Lonely, 197.
71. E. Schieffelin, 184.
72. Feld, Sound and Sentiment, 223.
73. Duranti, “Further Reflections,” 493.
74. Aristotle, Poetics, 71.
75. Booth, “Control of Distance,” 574.
76. Spivak, “Women’s Texts,” 1095.
77. Sontag, “Against Interpretation,” 406.
78. If it’s indeed the case that readers who treat The Plum as pornography miss
complex embedments involving mental states of the implied reader and the implied
author, then it would be similar to the phenomenon described by Chris Gavaler and
Dan Johnson, who found that, when readers assume a priori that what they are reading has “lower literary merit” (such as science fiction) they “exert less inference effort”
in figuring out characters’ motivations (“Genre Effect,” 86, 91). Perhaps one can even
test this hypothesis, telling one group of the first-time readers of The Plum that it’s
a pornographic novel and another that it’s literary classic and seeing how deeply
these respective groups would delve into the text’s intentionality. Also, compare the
history of the critical analysis of The Plum to that of another classical Chinese novel,
Wu Cheng’en’s Journey to the West (ca. 1592), as highlighted by Yuanfei Wang. Read
as a religious text, Journey to the West offers up very different constellations of mental
states than when read as a humorous, even nonsensical story (“Fantastic Jokes”).
79. Plaks, The Four Masterworks of the Ming Novel, 122, 123, 128.
80. Ballaster, Seductive Forms, 35.
81. See, for example, Nussbaum, “Finely Aware”; Nussbaum, “Literary Imagination”;
and Bruner, Actual Minds. In general, as John Guillory points out, recent attacks on
the humanities “provoked a torrent of books, articles, reports, and blogs in [their]
defense . . . , all attesting to the value of critical thinking and other skills produced
by humanities study” (“Monuments and Documents,” 10).
82. See Guillory for a critique of the notion that the sciences do not foster critical
thinking (“Monuments and Documents,” 15).
83. According to Robbins and Rumsey, in “Pacific societies where the opacity
doctrine is present, . . . people tend to put little store in the veracity of what others
say about their own thoughts”—but it does mean that the further open discussion
would go against established daily practices and would be “regarded as extremely
invasive and unethical” (“Introduction,” 408, 416). When such a discussion does
Notes
255
ensue—when, for instance, others have good reasons to disbelieve the person’s
initial claim and are invested in bringing the matter to communal attention—they
still carefully refrain from openly articulating their versions of the person’s mental
states. Instead, a social context may be arranged in which the person would eventually revise their earlier statement. For a description of such a situation, see B. Schieffelin, “Speaking Only Your Own Mind,” 438.
84. Ochs, “Clarification and Culture,” 335. See also McNamara et al., who point
out in their study of how “cultural models of mind shape moral reasoning,” that in
“North American samples, judgments of wrongdoing are scaled almost exclusively
by the ‘did they mean to,’ intent-oriented mental state reasoning process, while
judgments about punish-worthiness are scaled by the degree of severity calculated
by the more mind-blind ‘whodunnit’ process (though scope of punishment can be
scaled by intent). Because these processes do not perfectly overlap, mis-matches in
intent and outcome (i.e., an accident that results in a bad outcome despite a positive
or neutral intent) can receive more severe reactions than would be expected in a
strictly intent-focused system” (96; in-text quotations omitted).
85. See Rosenberg, How History Gets Things Wrong.
86. Howard, First World War, 3; emphasis added.
87. Tro, Chemistry, 4.
88. Note that we can’t just say that the author added an extra bit of narrative to his
list of basic SI units and be content with this general explanation. For, while it may
be true that we now experience the text as having slightly more of a narrative arc to
it—as in, “first we do this, and then we do that”—what has made the actual specific
difference is the introduction of a mental state.
89. Charon, “Spoken Body,” 264.
90. Charon, 270.
91. See Columbia University School of Professional Studies, “Narrative Medicine.”
92. See Charon, Narrative Medicine; and Charon et al., Principles and Practice.
93. Hoekstra, “From Darwin to DNA,” 278.
Chapter 5
1. As Karin Kukkonen puts it eloquently in her discussion of the “curse of realism,” the “novel is the literary genre of realism. Its narratives are situated in a place
and time that are recognisably real, its characters are subject to coincidence and
contingencies that are conceivably every-day, and their feelings are expressed in a
language that gets progressively better at capturing the subtleties of experience” (4E
Cognition, 14).
256
Notes
2. See, for instance, Cravens, “Lyric and Narrative Consciousness.” See also Petrone’s
Life Has Become More Joyous for a discussion of the appropriation of Pushkin’s by
Stalinist ideology. Starting from the 1930s, the official Party line was that the “traits
of simplicity and realism linked Pushkin ot the prevailing literary style of the time,
socialist realism” (117).
3. Pushkin, Eugene Onegin, 99.
4. Compare to Mark Turner’s argument about compression in “Compression and
Representation.”
5. The general argument that art exaggerates familiar characteristics of reality
is, of course, quite old. As Roman Jakobson wrote in 1922, “Exaggeration in art is
unavoidable [according to] Dostoevskij; in order to show an object, it is necessary to
deform the shape it used to have; it must be tinted, just as slides to be viewed under
the microscope are tinted. You color your object in an original way and think that it
has become more palpable, clearer, more real” (“On Realism in Art,” 26).
6. For instance, when you listen to papers delivered by literary critics at scholarly
conferences, such papers tend to embed complex mental states at an unusually high
rate, for, after all, they often report and interpret complexly embedded mental states
of literary characters.
7. Compare to Troscianko’s observation that fiction “has the structural potential to
prompt more reflexive instances than may occur in real life, resulting in an experience which is compelling, as we enactively engage, but may also be unsettling as
moments of reflection accumulate, through perspectival shifts away from the primary focaliser” (Kafka’s Cognitive Realism, 179).
8. As Jakobson puts it, “classicists, sentimentalists, the romanticists to a certain
extent, even the ‘realists’ of the nineteenth century, the modernists to a large degree,
and, finally, the futurists, expressionists, and their like have more than once steadfastly proclaimed faithfulness to reality, maximum verisimilitude—in other words,
realism—as the guiding motto of their artistic program” (“On Realism in Art,” 20).
See also McHale, “Revisiting Realisms.”
9. Troscianko, Kafka’s Cognitive Realism, 213.
10. Plaks, “Full-Length Hsiao-shuo,” 173.
11. Plaks, 172.
12. On the “weighty seriousness” of Patterns of Childhood, see Olney, Memory and
Narrative, 255.
13. Iliopoulou, Because of You, 83.
14. Plaks, “Full-Length Hsiao-shuo,” 176; emphasis added.
Notes
257
15. Plaks, 175. This relation would also work, to some extent, for Russian literature;
see Munro, “Finance and Credit,” 552.
16. Japan of the Heian period (794 to 1185) did not experience anything comparable to the kind of economic development that could be associated, however
broadly, with the rise of the novel in the eighteenth-century western Europe,
China, or Russia. Moreover, to expand our range of historical contexts beyond
economics, we can look at Plaks’s argument about the incommensurable intellectual environments of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century China and eleventhcentury Japan. As he puts it, while in “terms of intellectual history, at any rate,
it does make some sense to see in the novel a manifestation of the need for some
kind of a synthesis, a comprehensive reevaluation of the sum total of past cultural
experience, in order to adapt that to the perception of emerging new directions,
[such] speculations, however, cannot satisfactorily account for a work such as the
Tale of Genii, which partakes of a number of the defining characteristics of the
novel form enumerated above, yet appeared in the vastly more restrictive social
and intellectual context of the Heian court in eleventh-century Japan” (“FullLength Hsiao-shuo,” 176).
17. Plaks, 176.
18. Keane, Ethical Life, 131.
19. See Feld, Sound and Sentiment; and Zunshine, “Who Is He to Speak of My
Sorrow?”
20. Such a refutation will still be grist for the mill of “cognitive historicism” and
thus a welcome addition to a cognitivist project.
21. There is a long tradition of critical publications on deception in ancient Greek
and Roman poetics. For an example of a specifically “cognitive” perspective, see
Minchin, “Cognition of Deception.”
22. Saussy, “Comparative Literature and Translation,” 79.
23. See Austin, New Testaments.
24. I say “one such shift” because it’s possible that Russian literature had undergone
another, earlier shift before the Mongol Yoke (1237–1480). This argument depends
on how one reads the late twelfth-century epic poem The Song of Igor’s Campaign.
If one is willing to see third-level embedments in such lines as, for instance, “Let
us, however, / begin this song / in keeping with the happenings / of these times /
and not with the contriving of / Boyan” (31), then one would say, first, that thirdlevel embedment of mental states not driven by deception was already available to
the anonymous author of The Song and, second, that the literary context in which
such an embedment had been possible must have been largely obliterated during
the Yoke. Alternatively, one can adopt the view that “most old Russian literature
258
Notes
[including The Song] was not what we would consider fictional, or at least it presented itself as dealing with fact and reality” (Børtnes, “Literature of Old Russia,”
1). This would mean that occasional third-level embedments encountered in such
works as The Song should be read the same way in which we read occasional thirdlevel embedments in contemporary literary nonfiction; that is, their presence does
not impact the overall status of the text.
25. Kuritzyn, Tale of Dracula; translation mine. Original:
И отправил царь к Дракуле посла, требуя от него дани. Дракула же воздал послу тому
пышные почести, и показал ему свое богатство, и сказал ему: «Я не только готов платить
дань царю, но со всем воинством своим и со всем богатством хочу идти к нему на службу,
и как повелит мне, так ему служить буду. И ты передай царю, что, когда пойду к нему,
пусть объявит он по всей своей земле, чтобы не чинили зла ни мне, ни людям моим, а я
вскоре вслед за тобою пойду к царю, и дань принесу, и сам к нему прибуду». Царь же,
услышав все это от посла своего, что хочет Дракула прийти к нему на службу, послу его
честь воздал и одарил его богато. И рад был царь, ибо в то время вел войну на востоке.
И тотчас послал объявить по всем городам и по всей земле, что, когда пойдет Дракула,
никакого зла ему не причинять, а, напротив, встречать его с почетом. Дракула же, собрав
все войско, двинулся в путь, и сопровождали его царские приставы, и воздавали ему
повсюду почести. Он же, углубившись в Турецкую землю на пять дневных переходов,
внезапно повернул назад, и начал разорять города и села, и людей множество пленили
перебил, одних—на колья сажал, других рассекал надвое или сжигал, не щадя и грудных
младенцев. Ничего не оставил на пути своем, всю землю в пустыню превратил, а всех,
что было там, христиан увел и расселил в своей земле. И возвратился восвояси, захватив
несметные богатства, а приставов царских отпустил с почестями, напутствуя: «Идите и
поведайте царю вашему обо всем, что видели. Сколько сил хватило, послужил ему. И
если люба ему моя служба, готов и еще ему так же служить, сколько сил моих станет».
Царь же ничего не смог с ним сделать, только себя опозорил.
26. Ermolay-Erazm, Povest’ o Petre and Fevronii; translation mine. Original: “Это,
брат, козни лукавого змея—тобою мне является, чтобы я не решился убить его,
думая, что это ты—мой брат.”
27. I am grateful to Denis Akhapkin for bringing this tale to my attention.
28. Zenkovsky, “Misery-Luckless-Plight,” 497. Original:
“Откажи ты, молодец, невесте своей любимой:
быть тебе от невесты истравлену,
еще быть тебе от тое жены удавлену,
из злата и сребра бысть убитому!
Ты пойди, молодец, на царев кабак,
не жали ты, пропивай свои животы,
а скинь ты платье гостиное,
надежи [*] ты на себя гунку кабацкую,—
кабаком то Горе избудетца,
да то злое Горе-злочастие останетца:
за нагим то Горе не погонитца,
да никто к нагому не привяжетца,
а нагому, босому шумить розбой!”
Тому сну молодець не поверовал (Tale of Misery)
Notes
259
29. Zenkovsky, “Misery-Luckless-Plight,” 497.
30. Morris, Literature of Roguery, 51.
31. Serman, “Eighteenth Century,” 69.
32. Emin, Letters of Ernest and Doravra; translation mine. Original: “Забудь вину мою
и знай, что пожирающая меня любовь наказания, но не презрения достойна. На
осужденного на смерть никто не гневается; все о нем сожалеют; и ты, небесная
красота, последуя светскому правосудию, сожалей о несчастном, от которого
последнее сие получаешь письмо, который тебя больше ничем огорчить не может
и который идет на вечное заточение, неся с собою лютейшую о твоих приятностях
память, коя бесконечно все его мысли, все чувства и всю природу мучить не
перестанет.”
33. Karamzin, “Bednaya Liza,” 607; translation mine.
34. Karamzin, 612; translation mine, emphasis in the original. Original:
Все жилки в ней забились, и, конечно, не от страха. Она встала, хотела идти, но не
могла. Эраст выскочил на берег, подошел к Лизе и—м
ечта ее отчасти исполнилась: ибо
он взглянул на нее с видом ласковым, взял ее за руку . . . Ах! Он поцеловал ее, поцеловал
с таким жаром, что вся вселенная показалась ей в огне горящею! «Милая Лиза!—с казал
Эраст.—Милая Лиза! Я люблю тебя!», и сии слова отозвались во глубине души ее, как
небесная, восхитительная музыка; она едва смела верить ушам своим и . . . Но я бросаю
кисть. Скажу только, что в сию минуту восторга исчезла Лизина робость—Э
раст узнал,
что он любим, любим страстно новым, чистым, открытым сердцем.
35. Being shaped by does not mean, of course, copying. As Boyer puts is, “creating
a tradition does not really consist in imitation but includes the constant reconstruction and correction of input” (Minds Make Societies, 253).
36. Note how thinking of literature as seeking new ways of representing fictional
consciousness shifts our focus from the subject of literary discourse to the effect this
discourse may have on the mind of the reader. According to Porter Abbott, this
shift relocates “the intention of the art to what it does to the mind of the reader or
viewer: from what art is about to what it cognitively is” (Real Mysteries, 82).
37. Pushkin, Novels, Tales, Journeys, 39.
38. Pushkin, 41.
39. Gogol, “Overcoat,” 394; emphasis in the original.
40. Nabokov, Lectures on Russian Literature, 60.
41. Nabokov, 54.
42. Wood, Fun Stuff, 233.
43. As Ann Gaylin puts it, “the eavesdropping scene [in Wuthering Heights] is crucial
to the very existence of the narrative” (Eavesdropping, 26).
260
Notes
44. Nabokov, “Translator’s Foreword,” x.
45. Lee, “Measuring the Stomach,” 205.
46. Note that this account focuses on the European novel and leaves out poetry,
particularly the Romantics. A complementary line of inquiry may look, for instance,
at the pattern of embedment of mental states in narrative poems that are known to
have influenced Pushkin, such as Byron’s Childe Harold’s Pilgrimage.
47. Compare to Fritz Breithaupt’s analysis of Nietzschean’s view of shame: that is,
the “awareness of being observed” (Dark Sides of Empathy, 43).
48. Pushkin, Novels, Tales, Journeys, 41.
49. Pushkin, 42.
50. Mersereau, “Nineteenth Century,” 173.
51. Martinsen, Surprised by Shame, 1.
52. Martinsen, xv.
53. Ginzburg, Записные Kнижки, 379; translation mine. Original: “Достоевщина
как явление моральное и идейное мне в высокой степени противна, не потому,
что чужда, но потому, что в какой-то мере свойственна.”
54. I have explored this topic more fully in Why We Read Fiction.
55. Dostoevsky, Idiot; translation mine. Original:
Он понимал также, что старик вышел в упоении от своего успеха но ему все-т аки
предчувствовалось, что это был один из того разряда лгунов, которые хотя и лгут до
сладострастия и даже до самозабвения, но и на самой высшей точке своего упоения
все-таки подозревают про себя, что ведь им не верят, да и не могут верить. В настоящем
положении своем старик мог опомниться, не в меру устыдиться, заподозрить князя в
безмерном сострадании к нему, оскорбиться.
56. Martinsen, Surprised by Shame, 31, 35. Also, as she reports, in “an 1873 Diary of
a Writer article titled “Something about Lying” (Nechto o vran’e), Dostoevsky’s narrative persona identifies shame as a critical motive for lying” (4).
57. Hegel, “Traditional Chinese Fiction,” 395.
58. Lu, Brief History, 4.
59. This is the perspective taken by Y. W. Ma and Joseph S. M. Lau, the editors
of Traditional Chinese Stories. Note that both their introductory notes (especially
“Explanations,” xx) and the subsequent reviews of this volume (see, for instance,
Mair, “Review of Traditional Chinese Stories,” 466; and DeWoskin, “Review of Traditional Chinese Stories,” 774) provide a good example of what Hegel characterizes
as the lack “of general agreement on criteria by which to identify” early Chinese
fiction (“Traditional Chinese Fiction,” 395).
Notes
261
60. Ma and Lau, “Explanations,” in Traditional Chinese Stories, xx. As Ma and Lau
observe,
Judging from fragments of these works that have survived, these writings can hardly be called
fiction in the modern sense of the word. Nor, in our opinion, can passages from early historical works be regarded as fiction, properly speaking. No matter how lively the portraits
of historical figures through the use of direct speech, they are nevertheless historical figures
meant to be eyewitnesses of history. Indeed, unless one draws a line between fiction and history, it might even be possible to find some of the earliest examples of Chinese story in the
markings on oracle bones. It would be a great irony if the ingenuity of a historian in recording
fact should be read as fiction. (xx)
61. I am lifting this phrase from Riftin, От Мифа к Роману, 78. Riftin uses it to describe
a different kind of evolution in Chinese literary history, but his critique of the expectations of the linear development when it comes to literary history is relevant here.
62. Ma and Lau, Traditional Chinese Stories, 387. Original: 不能忍,夜伺其寢後,盜照視之,
其腰已上生肉如人,腰下但有枯骨。
63. Ma and Lau, 414.
64. Owen, Anthology of Chinese Literature, 548.
65. Yu, “Story of Yingying,” 184.
66. Yu, 185.
67. Quoted in Owen, End of the Chinese “Middle Ages,” 92.
68. Quoted in Owen, 96.
69. Owen, 101–102.
70. Note that the poetic convention of invoking present or future observers had
preceded the poetry written in the Tang period. See, for instance, the ending of the
famous “Preface to the Poems Collected from the Orchid Pavilion” (“Lantingji Xu,”
“蘭亭集序,” fourth century AD) by Wang Xizhi, in which the speaker suggests that
the future readers will empathize with the feelings expressed by the collection: “For
the people who read this in future generations, perhaps you will likewise be moved
by these words” (“後之覽者,亦將有感於斯文。
”).
71. Owen, End of the Chinese “Middle Ages,” 150.
72. Owen, Anthology of Chinese Literature, 518.
73. Owen, End of the Chinese “Middle Ages,” 168.
74. Owen, Anthology of Chinese Literature, 540.
75. Owen, End of the Chinese “Middle Ages,” 168.
76. I make this claim advisedly, taking into a consideration that (1) an expert reader
of classical Chinese literature may see a broader variety of embedments in Romance
262
Notes
than I do and that (2) in principle, the subjective element unavoidably present in
such claims serves to invite further research and discussion (and disagreement)
rather than settling this question once and for all.
77. As Haiyan Lee puts it, “Martial tales are as much about the joust of brain as about
the joust of brawn; and swashbuckling warriors invariably have to share the spotlight
with shrewd strategists. In The Romance of the Three Kingdoms . . . , beloved warriors like
Guan Yu and Zhao Yun at times are little more than pawns in the elaborate schemes
cooked up by the master strategist Zhuge Liang—whose name is synonymous with
strategic wisdom in Chinese culture” (“Measuring the Stomach of a Gentleman,” 215).
78. Luo G., Three Kingdoms, 96. Original: “呂布入內問安,正值卓睡。貂蟬於床後探半身望
布,以手指心,又以手指董卓,揮淚不止。布心如碎。”
79. On The Western Wing and literati culture, see M. Luo, Literati Storytelling, 179.
80. See, respectively, Tillman, “Selected Historical Sources”; and Shen, “Studies of
Three Kingdoms,” 163.
81. Hayden, “Beginning of the End,” 43.
82. Shen, “Studies of Three Kingdoms,” 156.
83. Tillman, “Selected Historical Sources,” 53.
84. See Shen on “various artistic forms [that] aided in the dissemination of the story
cycle” (“Studies of Three Kingdoms,” 156).
85. Monaco, “Review of DiaoChan.”
86. Schonebaum, introduction to Approaches to Teaching, 63. Scholars of Chinese
literature have long been aware of the special role of The Plum for the course of
Chinese literary history. Chen Dakang, for instance, saw 1590 “as the date at which
the vernacular novel began to flourish” (Lu, Brief History, 101).
87. Please note that I use Wade-Giles in transcribing names of characters in The
Plum, while using pinyin to transcribe names of characters in several other classical
Chinese texts, such as Dream of the Red Chamber. For instance, I say Hsi-men Ch’ing
instead of Ximen Qing, and Li P’ing-erh instead of Li Ping’er. The reason for this,
potentially confusing, usage is that I want my English-speaking readers to be able
to refer to David Tod Roy’s translation of The Plum, which uses Wade-Giles, and
to David Hawkes’s translation of Dream (that is, The Story of the Stone), which uses
pinyin. Generally, throughout this book, I use whichever system of Romanization
the English translator of the cited text used.
88. Link, “Wonderfully Elusive Chinese Novel.”
89. Link.
90. Scott, “Story of the Stone and Its Antecedents,” 266.
Notes
263
91. Chang, “How to Read the Chin P’ing Mei,” 204, 206.
92. Chang, 211.
93. Roy, Plum in the Golden Vase, vol. 2, 87.
94. Roy, 96.
95. Roy, 87.
96. T. Lu, “Interiority in Jinpingmei cihua.” For a discussion of psychological interiority in classical Chinese texts, such as the Analects of Confucius, see Slingerland,
“Cognitive Science and Religious Thought.”
97. In fact, we can be made to feel sympathetic toward the liar. For instance, Utnapishtim does not judge Gilgamesh for attempting to deceive him: he sees that behavior
as only too human. As he puts it to his wife, “Since the human race is duplicitous,
he’ll endeavor to dupe you” (Foster, Epic of Gilgamesh, 92).
98. Lee, “Response to the Panel.”
99. Roy, Plum in the Golden Vase, 237. Original: “這個都是人氣不憤俺娘兒們,做作出這樣
(http://www.guoxue123
.com/xiaosuo/jd/jpmch/025.htm).
事來。爹,你也要個主張,好把醜名兒頂在頭上,傳出外邊去好聽?”
100. See Zunshine, “Think What You’re Doing.”
101. Roy, Plum in the Golden Vase, vol. 2, 95.
102. Roy, 99.
103. Roy, 111. Original: “先不先只這個就不雅相,傳出去休說六鄰親戚笑話,只家中大小,把
你也不著在意裡。”
104. Roy, 121.
105. See Nabokov’s commentary in Pushkin, Eugene Onegin.
106. “Но наш герой, кто б ни был он / Уж верно был не Грандисон” (Pushkin,
Eugene Onegin, 154).
107. Roy, Plum in the Golden Vase, vol. 2, 96.
108. Roy, 494.
109. Roy, 494. See also Plaks, The Four Masterworks of the Ming Novel, 163–164.
110. Plaks, The Four Masterworks of the Ming Novel, 122, 123, 128.
111. Kidd and Castano, “Reading Literary Fiction and Theory of Mind,” 8.
112. To appreciate how unwelcome a sustained argument about Pushkin’s engagement with Western literature would have been in Soviet Russia, see chapter 5 (“A
264
Notes
Double-Edged Discourse on Freedom: The Pushkin Centennial of 1937”) of Petrone’s
Life Has Become More Joyous (113–148).
113. Plaks, “The Four Masterworks of the Ming Novel, 121.
114. Wu, Scholars, 40. Original: “知縣心里想道:‘這小斯那里害什么病!想是翟家這奴 才,
走下鄉,狐假虎威,著實恐嚇了他一場;他從來不曾見過官府的人,害怕不 敢來了。老師既把這個人
托我,我若不把他就叫了來見老師,也惹得老師笑我 做事疲軟;我不如竟自己下鄉去拜他。他看見賞
他臉面,斷不是難為他的意思, 自然大著膽見我。我就順便帶了他來見老師,卻不是辦事勤敏?’ 又
想道:‘堂 堂一個縣令,屈尊去拜一個鄉民,惹得衙役們笑話。•••’又想到:‘老師前 日口气,甚是敬
他;老師敬他十分,我就該敬他一百分。況且屈尊敬賢,將來志 書上少不得稱贊一篇;這是万古千年
不朽的勾當,有甚么做不得?
”
115. Cao, Story of the Stone, vol. 1, 193. Original: “姨媽不知道。幸虧是姨媽這裏,倘或在別
人家,人家豈不惱?好說就看得人家連個手爐也沒有,巴巴的從家裏送個來。不說丫頭們太小心過餘,
還只當我素日是這等輕狂慣了呢。
”
116. Cao, 193.
117. Cao, 436.
118. Cao, 437.
119. Cao, 438.
120. See Zunshine, “From the Social to the Literary.”
121. Shang Wei points out that the literati novels “of the mid- and late Qianlong
era . . . had so little in common with the earlier novels that their emergence in the
mid-eighteenth century could well indicate the rise of a new narrative form” (“Literati Era,” 269). The profound influence of The Story of the Stone on the subsequent
development of Chinese literature is a well-explored topic in critical studies; see
Plaks, “Novel in Premodern China”; and Schonebaum, introduction to Approaches
to Teaching. We may further enrich our understanding of that influence if we retrace
its history by looking specifically at the patterns of embedment associated with it.
It would be interesting to see, for instance, to what extent numerous imitations and
revisions of this novel (see Wei, “Stone Phenomenon”) embed complex mental states
in the same ambiguous, open-ended manner.
122. Cao, Story of the Stone, vol. 1, 205. Original: “黛玉忙又叫住,問道:「你怎麼不去辭辭
你寶姐姐呢?」寶玉笑而不答,一逕同秦鐘上學去了.”
123. Talwar, Gordon, Lee, “Lying in the Elementary School Years,” 804.
124. Ermer, Cosmides, and Tooby, “Cheater Detection.”
125. Compare to William Flesch’s suggestive exploration of punishing cheaters in
fiction, in Comeuppance.
Notes
265
126. On the adaptive role of the emotion of sexual jealousy, see Cosmides and
Tooby, “Evolutionary Psychology and the Emotions”; Daly, Wilson, and Weghorst,
“Male Sexual Jealousy”; and Buss, Evolution of Desire.
127. Although the critical conversation about the relationship between form and
context, both within and outside cognitivist contexts, has been rich and variegated
(for some recent examples, see, for instance, Kramnick and Nersessian, “Form and
Explanation”; and Levine, Forms), I focus deliberately on the earliest cases, such as
Schiller and Vygotsky. For a recent engagement with Schiller’s “conception of the
liberating force of form,” specifically from a cognitive perspective (i.e., that of probability designs), see Kukkonen, Probability Designs, 187.
128. “Darin also besteht das eigentliche Kunstgeheimnis des Meisters, dass er den Stoff
durch die Form vertilgt” (Schiller, Schillers Sämmtliche Werke, 644; translation mine).
129. Vygotsky, Psichologia Iskusstva, 180, 186. Original:
С этой точки зрения становится совершенно ясным, что, если те два плана в басне, о
которых мы все время говорим, поддержаны и изображены всей силой поэтического
приема, т.е. существуют не только как противоречие логическое, но гораздо больше,
как противоречие аффективное,—переживание читателя басни есть в основе своей
переживание противоположных чувств, развивающихся с равной силой, но совершенно
вместе. . . . Разве не то же самое разумел Шиллер, когда говорил о трагедии, что
настоящий секрет художника заключается в том, чтобы формой уничтожить
содержание? И разве поэт в басне не уничтожает художественной формой, построением
своего материала того чувства, которое вызывает самым содержанием своей басни?
130. I speak of heavy lifting intentionally, building here on Vygotsky’s useful
metaphor of the airplane in Psichologia Iskussstva, 288; for translation, see Vygotsky,
Psychology of Art, 227.
131. Mateo Alemán, Life and Adventure (1823).
132. Garrido Ardila, “Origins and Definition,” 1.
133. Wood, “Reality Testing.”
134. Lerner, Leaving the Atocha Station, 23.
135. Lerner, 119.
136. Lerner, 133.
137. On egocentricity and mindreading, see Riva et al., “Emotional Egocentricity
Bias.”
138. Lerner, Leaving the Atocha Station, 57.
139. Defoe, Robinson Crusoe, 97.
140. Wood, “Reality Testing.”
266
Notes
Chapter 6
1. See Luhrmann, “Theory of Mind in the Pacific,” 443. See also McNamara et al.,
“Weighing Outcome,” who point out that (in-text citations omitted),
Developmentally, children living in more traditional and community-oriented groups often
pass psychological tests that require them to use others’ beliefs to predict their behavior (i.e.,
false belief measures) at later ages . . . This is particularly so for children from cultural contexts with Opacity of Mind norms . . . This suggests a weaker, more distant cognitive/semantic connection between thoughts and behaviors for children in these societies. Conversely,
exposure to a larger lexicon of mental state terms and more formal Western education predicts children will perform these tasks at younger ages . . . This suggests a tighter linkage
between mental states and behaviors, and further implies more emphasis on intention for
judging behavior. (96)
2. Dyer, Shatz, and Wellman, “Young Children’s Storybooks,” 19.
3. Dyer, Shatz, and Wellman, 34. See also Wulandini, Kuntoro, and Handayani,
“Effect of Literary Fiction.”
4. See, for instance, Astington and Baird, Why Language Matters.
5. Peskin and Astington, “Effects of Adding Metacognitive Language,” 256.
6. Peskin and Astington, 254.
7. Peskin and Astington, 255.
8. An earlier version of this section appeared in Zunshine, “From the Social to the
Literary,” under the heading “What Rosie Knew.”
9. Peskin and Astington, “Effects of Adding Metacognitive Language,” 253.
10. Harris, Rosnay, and Pons, “Language and Children’s Understanding,” 72.
11. Peskin and Astington, “Effects of Adding Metacognitive Language,” 265. See
also Zunshine, “Secret Life of Fiction.”
12. Peskin and Astington, “Effects of Adding Metacognitive Language,” 266.
13. Peskin and Astington, 267.
14. Of course, “the exact interpretation of [Peskin and Astington’s] results needs
more research” (Paul L. Harris, email communication, April 18, 2014). To begin
with, the emphasis on the importance of reading fictional stories that make children work hard at deducing mental states does not mean to downplay the crucial
role of talking to children about thoughts and feelings, and it may shed an interesting light on the underlying structure of those conversations. See, for instance, the
study by Harris and his colleagues, who looked at children’s attribution of emotions, attendant upon their attributions of false beliefs, and found that while the
four- to six-year-olds may judge correctly that Red Riding Hood doesn’t know that
Notes
267
the Wolf is waiting for her in her grandmother’s cottage, they may still say that
she is afraid rather than happy as she approaches the cottage. While thus positing a lag between “children’s understanding of a protagonist’s mistaken beliefs and
their grasp of the emotions that flow from such beliefs,” this study also found that
“children with mothers who use more mental-state language make more correct
attributions” of emotions (Harris, Rosnay, and Ronfard, “Mysterious Emotional
Life,” 107). Moreover, as Harris observes elsewhere, “a simple count of mentalstate terms [used by mothers] may not be the most sensitive measure of effective
maternal input even if it is a useful correlate. [It’s possible] that it is the mother’s
pragmatic intent, notably her efforts to introduce varying points of view into a
given conversation, that is the underlying and effective source of variation” (Harris,
“Conversation,” 77).
15. Rolston, Traditional Chinese Fiction, 217.
16. Dyer, Shatz, and Wellman, “Young Children’s Storybooks,” 22.
17. Burnett, Annotated Secret Garden,1.
18. Burnett, 6.
19. Milne, Winnie-the-Pooh, 14.
20. For a witty analysis of mindreading in the honey scene, see Cave, Thinking with
Literature, 42–45.
21. Kinney, Diary of a Wimpy Kid, 15.
22. Kinney, 35.
23. Jansson, Moomin Falls in Love, 17.
24. Jansson, 18.
25. Jansson, 19; my emphases throughout.
26. Carroll, Alice’s Adventures, 29.
27. Travers, Mary Poppins Omnibus, 26.
28. Travers, 56.
29. Travers, 133.
30. White, Stuart Little, 11.
31. White, 25.
32. Compare to Emer O’Sullivan’s suggestion that a study in “comparative poetics”
of children’s literature may concern itself with such a question as “how (and why)
the beginnings of the new, complex, literary children’s literature, which embraces
268
Notes
techniques common to the psychological novel, can be traced back to the end of the
1950s in England, the 1960s in Sweden, and around 1970 in Germany [Nikolajeva, Children’s Literature Comes of Age] and why this form has taken longer to be accepted and produced in other children’s literatures” (O’Sullivan, “Comparative Children’s Literature,”
192). It would be interesting to see if the frequency of complex embedments in the books
for children described by O’Sullivan as having embraced “techniques common to the
psychological novel” would indeed approach that of the psychological novel.
33. Knoepflmacher and Myers, “From the Editors,” viii.
34. Beckett, Crossover Picturebooks, 175.
35. Beckett, 176.
36. Zunshine, “Secret Life of Fiction,” 729.
37. Lockington, For Black Girls like Me, 221.
38. Lockington, 219–220.
39. Clark, Kiddie Lit, 80.
40. Clemens and Howells, Mark Twain–Howells Letters, 196.
41. Clark, Kiddie Lit, 80.
42. Clemens and Howells, Mark Twain–Howells Letters, 122.
43. Twain, Mississippi Writings, 3.
44. Clark, Kiddie Lit, 84, 81.
45. Quoted in Clark, 89.
46. Clark, 101.
47. Phelan and Rabinowitz. “Narrative Values,” 163.
48. Phelan and Rabinowitz, “Authors,” 35.
49. Compare to Hogan’s observation that literature can present us “with emotionally affective situations, where emotion systems interact in sometimes very subtle
ways—unlike the artificially limited situations that are necessary for the control of
variables in experimental research” (Sexual Identities, 20). Also, on the processing of
high-level embedments, see Dunbar, How Many Friends Does One Person Need?, 180.
50. Zunshine, “Commotion of Souls,” 139.
51. Miller, Kessel, and Flavell, “Thinking about People Thinking,” 622.
52. Phelan and Rabinowitz, “Narrative Values,” 163.
53. Phelan and Rabinowitz, “Authors,” 35.
54. Phelan and Rabinowitz, “Narrative Values,” 163.
Notes
269
55. Another fascinating outlier, similarly classed with children’s literature, yet
embedding complex mental states at a frequency we would associate with literature for adults, is J. M. Barrie’s Peter Pan. For a useful discussion of the “labyrinth
of subjectivities” of its various textual incarnations, see Butte, Suture and Narrative,
particularly chap. 4, “The Wounds of Peter Pan” (quote on 133). Although Butte
does not deal with embedded mental states per se, his analysis of Barrie’s texts as
speaking “to several audiences in several registers at the same time” (136) reveals
proliferation of complex embedments.
56. As one anonymous Amazon purchaser puts it, “Although there are wonderful little
snippets of family life, and a few hints of the conflicts between the feisty Laura and her
more reserved and perfect sister Mary, the truth is, there isn’t much of a plot here.” slowmamma, review of Little House in the Big Woods, Amazon, April 12, 2002, https://www
.amazon.com/Little-House-Woods-Ingalls-Wilder/dp/0060581808/ref=sr_1_1?s=books
&ie=UTF8&qid=1475604634&sr=1-1&keywords=little+house+in+the+big+woods.
57. Hill, “Introduction,” xvi.
58. Quoted in Hill, xliii
59. Hill, xxxvi.
60. Hill, xxx.
61. Fellman, Little House, 6–7, 106.
62. Hill, “Introduction,” lv.
63. Fellman, Little House, 85.
64. Wilder, Little Town, 12, 140.
65. Wilder, These Happy Golden Years, 49.
66. Wilder, 176, 184; my emphases throughout.
67. Fellman, Little House, 127.
68. For a broader discussion of “intermediality” of children’s literature—that is, “a
synergistic relation between stories and characters that originally appear in print and
the forms into which they are subsequently transformed across media boundaries:
film, video, DVD, audio adaptations,” etc.—see O’Sullivan, “Comparative Children’s
Literature,” 193. In one striking example she mentions, the Canadian classic Anne of
Green Gables, by L. M. Montgomery, was not translated into German until the mid1980s, and the translation was based on the film version” (O’Sullivan, 193).
69. Fellman, Little House, 123, 127–128.
70. Compare to Bettina Kümmerling-Meibauer’s classic argument that “most of the
key elements of sophisticated narratives are present in a simpler form in picture
books” (“Metalinguistic Awareness,” 177).
270
Notes
71. For a discussion of “pleasure” involved in children’s interaction with twist endings, see Bellorín and Silva-Díaz, “Surprised Readers,” 118.
72. On the gendering of the small fish and the big fish, see Drabble, “Jon Klassen.”
73. On the gendering of Gruffalo, see Nick Miller, “Gruffalo Creator.”
74. And, of course, as Alexandra Berlina helpfully reminds me, they also know that
the mouse is surprised that the Gruffalo, the monster that the mouse thinks it has
invented, turns out to exist!
75. For a valuable review of problems inherent in the issue of identification, see
Keen, Empathy and the Novel.
76. Talwar, Gordon, and Lee, “Lying in the Elementary School Years,” 804–810.
77. As Milligan et al. point out, age itself is not an “explanatory variable, but rather
a proxy for various maturational factors that may explain variation, an important
one of which is language ability” (“Language and Theory of Mind,” 638).
78. For a review, see Ahrens, “Picturebooks.”
79. See Kümmerling-Meibauer and Meibauer, “Early-Concept Books.”
80. Rey, Curious George at the Zoo, n.p.
81. Miller, Pooh’s Honey Trouble.
82. The number of reviews is growing, so by the time this book is in press, it will be
higher.
83. The full review reads, “There is pretty much no story here, but if your little
loves Winnie the Pooh, it’ll be a hit anyway. However, I must disagree with the
recommended age of 3 & up. This book is for toddlers” (Linklau, “Cute for Toddlers,” Amazon, September 2015, https://www.amazon.com/gp/customer-reviews
/R1YY7D6HAYZ6SX/ref=cm_cr_arp_d_rvw_ttl?ie=UTF8&ASIN=1423135792).
84. As Bettina Kümmerling-Meibauer observes, the “text in Hutchins’s book merely
informs the reader in a few words about Rosie’s walk and is supplemented only by
participial constructions with changing place names. . . . The completely dull [text
relates] events with almost no mention of the emotional reactions of those who
participate in them” (“Metalinguistic Awareness,” 170).
85. Amazon, reviews of Rosie’s Walk, https://www.amazon.com/Rosies-Walk-Pat
-Hutchins/dp/0020437501/ref=sr_1_1?s=books&ie=UTF8&qid=1477417845&sr=1-1
&keywords=rosie%27s+walk.
86. For a discussion of the role of adults in mediating children’s relationships with
books, see O’Sullivan, “Comparative Children’s Literature.” As she observes, “at
every stage of literary communication we find adults acting for children” (191).
Notes
271
87. Richardson, Literature, 109; cf. Deppner, “Parallel Receptions of the Fundamental,” 58–59. See also O’Sullivan, “Comparative Children’s Literature,” 190. Also, in my
book Strange Concepts (chap. 14), I have looked at an eighteenth-century text specifically geared toward three- to five-year-olds, Anna Laetitia Barbauld’s Hymns in Prose for
Children (1781), but I don’t want to conclude too much based on just one case study.
88. Harris, Rosnay, and Pons, “Language,” 71–72. See also Rosnay et al., “Lag
between Understanding”; and Hughes, White, and Ensor, “Talking about Thoughts.”
89. On the relationship between cross-writing and crossovers, see Falconer, “Children’s Literature.”
90. For a useful discussion of the role of illustrations in “metafictional picturebooks”
(355), see Lissi Athanasiou-Krikelis, “Mapping.”
91. Lipson, New York Times Parent’s Guide, 48; Amazon, Hush Little Baby page,
accessed 06/08/2021. https://www.amazon.com/Hush-Little-Baby-Folk-Pictures/dp
/0152058877/ref=sr_1_1?s=books&ie=UTF8&qid=1535232923&sr=1-1&keywords=h
ush+little+baby+marla+frazee.
92. J. Freeman, Books Kids Will Sit Still For 3, 236; Gillespie, Best Books for Children,
712; Scholastic, Hush Little Baby page, accessed 12/18/2018. As of 06/08/21, Scholastic doesn’t seem to feature Frazee’s Hush Little Baby anymore, so this reference more
accurately pertains to their former characterization. https://www.scholastic.com
/teachers/books/hush-little-baby-by-marla-frazee/.
93. Amazon, Hush Little Baby reviews, accessed 12/18/2018. https://www.amazon
. com / Hush - Little - Baby - Folk - Pictures / product - reviews / 0152058877 / ref=cm_cr_
getr_d_paging_btm_4 ? ie=UTF8 & reviewerType=all_reviews & showViewpoints=1
&sortBy=recent&pageNumber=4.
Conclusion
1. Wolf, Patterns of Childhood, 8. The translation is missing a part of one sentence.
The full original (with the missing part italicized) reads, “Auffallend ist, daß wir in
eigener Sache entweder romanhaft lügen oder stockend und mit belegter Stimme
sprechen. Wir mögen wohl Grund haben, von uns nichts wissen zu wollen (oder
doch nicht alles—was auf das gleiche hinausläuft). Aber selbst wenn die Hoffnung
gering ist, sich allmählich freizusprechen und so ein gewisses Recht auf den Gebrauch
jenes Materials zu erwerben, das unlösbar mit lebenden Personen verbunden ist—so wäre
es doch nur diese geringfügige Hoffnung, die, falls sie durchhält, der Verführung
zum Schweigen und Verschweigen trotzen könnte” (Wolf, Kindheitsmuster, 15).
2. See, for instance, Black and Barnes, “Fiction and Social Cognition.”
Bibliography
Abbott, H. Porter. Real Mysteries: Narrative and the Unknowable. Columbus: Ohio State
University Press, 2013.
Ahrens, Kathleen. “Picturebooks: Where Literature Appreciation Begins.” In Emergent Literary: Children’s Books from 0 to 3, edited by Bettina Kümmerling-Meibauer,
77–89. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2011.
Alemán, Mateo. The Life and Adventure of Guzman D’Alfarache, or the Spanish Rogue.
Vol. 1. Translated from the French Edition of Mons. Le Sage by John Henry Brady.
London: J. Nichols and Son, 1823. https://www.gutenberg.org/files/52806/52806-h
/52806-h.htm.
Alemán, Mateo. The Life and Adventures of Guzman D’Alfarache, or the Spanish Rogue.
Vol. 1. Translated by Alain-René Le Sage and John Henry Brady. London: Printed
for Longman, Hurst, Rees, Orme, Brown, and Green, Paternoster-Row, 1823. https://
www.gutenberg.org/files/52806/52806-h/52806-h.htm.
Al Harthi, Jokha. Celestial Bodies. Translated by Marilyn Booth. Croydon, UK: Sandstone, 2018.
Allakhverdov, Victor Michailovitch. Psychology of Art [Психология искусства]. St. Peterburg: Izdatelstvo DNK, 2001. http://mhp-journal.ru/upload/Library/Allakhverdov_VM
_(2001)_Psychology_of_Art.pdf.
Athanasiou-Krikelis, Lissi. “Mapping the Metafictional Picturebook.” Narrative 28
no. 3 (2020): 355–374.
Anonymous. The Epic of Gilgamesh. Translated by Nancy K. Sandars. Penguin, 1960.
Anonymous. “The Wanderer.” Translated by Sean Miller. Anglo-Saxons.net. http://
www.anglo-saxons.net/hwaet/?do=get&type=text&id=Wdr
Apperly, Ian. The Cognitive Basis of “Theory of Mind.” New York: Psychology Press,
2011.
Apuleius. The Golden Ass. Translated by Sarah Ruden. New Heaven, CT: Yale University Press, 2013.
274
Bibliography
Argyle, Michael, and Mark Cook. Gaze and Mutual Gaze. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1976.
Aristotle. Poetics. In The Critical Tradition: Classic Texts and Contemporary Trends,
edited by David H. Richter, 50–72. Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 2016.
Asimov, Isaac. The Bicentennial Man and Other Stories. New York: Doubleday, 1976.
Astington, Janet Wilde, and Jodie A. Baird, eds. Why Language Matters for Theory of
Mind. New York: Oxford University Press, 2005.
Astington, Janet Wilde, Janette Pelletier, and Bruce Homer. “Theory of Mind and
Epistemological Development: The Relation between Children’s Second-Order FalseBelief Understanding and Their Ability to Reason about Evidence.” New Ideas in
Psychology 20 (2002): 131–144.
Astuti, Rita. “Some After Dinner Thoughts on Theory of Mind.” Anthropology of This
Century 3 (2012): n.p. http://eprints.lse.ac.uk.
Asztalos, Monika. “The Faculty of Theology.” In A History of the University in Europe,
vol. 1, Universities in the Middle Ages, edited by Hilde de Ridder-Symoens, 409–441.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
Austen, Jane. Mansfield Park. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.
Austen, Jane. Pride and Prejudice. New York: Dover, 1995.
Austin, Michael. New Testaments: Cognition, Closure, and the Figural Logic of the Sequel,
1660–1740. Newark: University of Delaware Press, 2011.
Auyoung, Elaine. “The Unspoken Intimacy of Aesthetic Experience: Hardy and
Degas,” Poetics Today 41, no. 2 (2020): 301–314.
Auyoung, Elaine. When Fiction Feels Real: Representation and the Reading Mind. New
York: Oxford University Press, 2018.
Baggs, Ed. “Book Review: Evolving Enactivism: Basic Minds Meet Content.” Frontiers
in Psychology 8 (2017): 1947. doi: 10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01947.
Bakhtin, Mikhail. “Discourse in the Novel.” In The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays,
edited and translated by Michael Holquist and Caryl Emerson, 259–422. Austin:
University of Texas Press, 1982.
Ballaster, Ros. Seductive Forms: Women’s Amatory Fiction from 1684 to 1740. Oxford,
UK: Clarendon, 1992.
Barrie, J. M. Peter Pan: The Original Tale of Neverland. New York: Simon and Schuster,
2000.
Baum, Andrew, J. P. Garofalo, and Ann Marie Yali. “Socioeconomic Status and
Chronic Stress: Does Stress Account for SES Effects on Health?” Annals of the New
York Academy of Sciences 896, no. 1 (1999): 131–144.
Bibliography
275
Beckett, Sandra. Crossover Picturebooks: A Genre for All Ages. New York: Routledge,
2013.
Bellorín, Brenda, and Cecilia Silva-Díaz. “Surprised Readers: Twist Endings in Narrative Picturebooks.” In New Directions in Picturebook Research, edited by Teresa
Colomer, Bettina Kümmerling-Meibauer, and Cecilia Silva-Díaz, 113–127. New
York: Routledge, 2010.
Black, Jessica, and Jennifer L. Barnes. “Fiction and Social Cognition: The Effect of
Viewing Award-Winning Television Dramas on Theory of Mind.” Psychology of Aesthetics Creativity and the Arts 9, no. 4 (2015): 423–429. doi: 10.1037/aca0000031.
Blackman, Lucy. “Reflections on Language.” In Autism and the Myth of Person alone,
edited by Douglas Biklen with Richard Attfield, Larry Bissonnette, Lucy Blackman,
Jamie Burke, Alberto Frugone, Tito Rajarshi Mukhopadhyay, and Sue Rubin, 146–
167. New York: New York University Press, 2005.
Bloom, Paul. Against Empathy: The Case for Rational Compassion. New York: Harper
Collins, 2016.
Bolens, Guillemette. Kinesic Humor: Literature, Embodied Cognition, and the Dynamics
of Gesture. New York: Oxford University Press, 2021.
Booth, Wayne C. “Control of Distance in Jane Austen’s Emma.” In The Critical Tradition: Classic Texts and Contemporary Trends, edited by David H. Richter, 570–582.
Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 2016.
Borden, Richard C. “Leonid Dobychin’s The Town of N: Introduction.” In The Town
of N, by Leonid Dobychin, translated from Russian by Richard C. Borden with Natalia Belova, i–xi. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1998.
Børtnes, Jostein. “The Literature of Old Russia, 988–1730.” In The Cambridge History of Russian Literature, edited by Charles A. Moser, 1–44. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1989.
Bowes, Andrea, and Albert Katz. “Metaphor Creates Intimacy and Temporarily
Enhances Theory of Mind.” Memory and Cognition 43 (2015): 953–963. https://doi
.org/10.3758/s13421-015-0508-4.
Boyer, Pascal. Minds Make Societies: How Cognition Explains the World Humans Create.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2018.
Brandenberger, David. Propaganda State in Crisis: Soviet Ideology, Indoctrination, and
Terror under Stalin, 1927–1941. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2011.
Breithaupt, Fritz. The Dark Sides of Empathy. Translated from German by Andrew
B. B. Hamilton. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2019.
Bruner, Jerome S. Actual Minds, Possible Worlds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1986.
276
Bibliography
Buckner, Randy L., Jessica R. Andrews-Hanna, and Daniel L. Schacter. “The Brain’s
Default Network: Anatomy, Function, and Relevance to Disease.” Annals of the New
York Academy of Sciences 1124 (2008): 1–38.
Buckner, Randy L., and Daniel C. Carroll. “Self-Projection and the Brain.” Trends in
Cognitive Sciences 11, no. 2 (February 2007): 49–57.
Burnett, Frances Hodgson. The Annotated Secret Garden. Edited by Gretchen Holbrook
Gerzina. New York: Norton, 2007.
Burney, Frances. Evelina; or, The History of a Young Lady’s Entrance into the World.
Edited by Edward A. Bloom. Introduction and notes by Vivien Jones. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2002.
Buss, David M. The Evolution of Desire. New York: Basic Books, 1994.
Butte, George. Suture and Narrative: Deep Intersubjectivity in Fiction and Film. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 2017.
Caldwell-Harris, Catherine, Ann Kronrod, and Joyce Yang. “Do More, Say Less:
Saying ‘I Love You’ in Chinese and American Cultures.” Intercultural Pragmatics 10,
no. 1 (2013): 41–69.
Callahan, John F. “Frequencies of Eloquence: The Performance and Composition
of Invisible Man.” In New Essays on Invisible Man, edited by Robert O’Meally, 55–94.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
Cao Xueqin. The Story of the Stone. Vol. 1, The Golden Days. Translated by David
Hawkes. London: Penguin, 1973.
Cao Xueqin. The Story of the Stone. Vol. 2, The Crab-Flower Club. Translated by David
Hawkes. London: Penguin, 1977.
Carney, James, Rafael Wlodarski, and Robin Dunbar. “Inference or Enaction? The
Impact of Genre on the Narrative Processing of Other Minds.” PLoS ONE 9, no. 12
(2014): e114172. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0114172.
Carroll, Lewis. Alice’s Adventures in Wonderland. London: Usborne, 2013.
Carruthers, Peter. “Two Systems for Mindreading?” Review of Philosophy and Psychology 7, no. 1 (2016): 141–162. doi: 10.1007/s13164-015-0259-y.
Castano, Emanuele. “Art Films Foster Theory of Mind.” Humanities and Social Sciences Communications volume 8, Article number: 119 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1057
/s41599-021-00793-y
Castano, Emanuele, Alison Jane Martingano, and Pietro Perconti. “The Effect of
Exposure to Fiction on Attributional Complexity, Egocentric Bias and Accuracy in
Social Perception.” PLoS ONE 15, no. 5 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone
.0233378.
Bibliography
277
Cave, Terence. Thinking with Literature: Towards a Cognitive Criticism. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2016.
Cavell, Stanley. Pursuits of Happiness: The Hollywood Comedy of Remarriage. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981.
Chang Chu-p’o. “How to Read the Chin P’ing Mei.” Translated and annotated by
David T. Roy; additional annotation by David L. Rolston. In How to Read the Chinese Novel, edited by David L. Rolston, 202–243. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1990.
Charon, Rita. Narrative Medicine: Honoring the Stories of Illness. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Charon, Rita. “Spoken Body: An Infinite Jest of Life, Death, and the Medical Tongue,”
Poetics Today 41, no. 2 (2020): 261–280.
Charon, Rita. “To See the Suffering.” Academic Medicine 92, no. 12 (December 2017):
1668–1670.
Charon, Rita, Sayantani DasGupta, Nellie Hermann, Craig Irvine, Eric R. Marcus,
Edgar Rivera Colsn, Danielle Spencer, and Maura Spiegel. The Principles and Practice
of Narrative Medicine. New York: Oxford University Press, 2016.
Chekhov, Anton P. “Skripka Rotshil’da.” Polnoie Sobranie Sochinenii I Pisem v 30-ti
Tomach. Tom 8. Moscow: Nauka, 1986. https://ilibrary.ru/text/978/p.1/index.html.
Clark, Beverly Lyon. Kiddie Lit: The Cultural Construction of Children’s Literature in
America. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2003.
Claudius, Eduard. Menschen an unserer Seite. Berlin: Volk und Welt, 1951.
Clemens, Samuel L., and William D. Howells. Mark Twain–Howells Letters: The Correspondence of Samuel L. Clemens and William D. Howells, 1872–1910. Edited by Henry
Nash Smith and William M. Gibson. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1960.
Columbia University School of Professional Studies. “Narrative Medicine.” Accessed
06/08/21. http://sps.columbia.edu/narrative-medicine.
Cook, Amy. “4E Cognition and the Humanities.” In The Oxford Handbook of 4E
Cognition, edited by Albert Newen, Leon De Bruin, and Shaun Gallagher, 875–890.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020.
Cook, Amy. Shakespearean Neuroplay: Reinvigorating the Study of Dramatic Texts and
Performance through Cognitive Science. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010.
Cosmides, Leda, and John Tooby. “Evolutionary Psychology and the Emotions.” In
Handbook of Emotions, 2nd ed., edited by Michael Lewis and Jeannette M. HavilandJones. New York: Guilford, 2000. https://www.cep.ucsb.edu/emotion.html.
278
Bibliography
Crane, Mary Thomas. “Cognitive Historicism: Intuition in Early Modern Thought.”
In The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Literary Studies, edited by Lisa Zunshine, 18–33.
New York: Oxford University Press, 2015.
Crane, Mary Thomas. Shakespeare’s Brain: Reading with Cognitive Theory. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001.
Cravens, Craig. “Lyric and Narrative Consciousness in Eugene Onegin.” Slavic and
East European Journal 46, no. 4 (Winter 2002): 683–709. http://www.jstor.com/stable
/3219907.
Culler, Jonathan. “The Closeness of Close Reading.” ADE Bulletin 149 (2010): 20–25.
Currie, Gregory. “Framing Narratives,” Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 60
(2007): 17–42.
Cusk, Rachel. Saving Agnes. New York: Picador, 1994.
Cusk, Rachel. Transit. New York: Farrar Straus and Giroux, 2017.
Daly, Martin, Margo Wilson, and Suzanne J. Weghorst. “Male Sexual Jealousy.”
Ethology and Sociobiology 3 (1982): 11–27.
Dangarembga, Tsitsi. Nervous Conditions. London: Women’s Press, 1988.
Defoe, Daniel. Robinson Crusoe. New York: Oxford University Press, 2007.
De Jaegher, Hanne, and Ezequiel Di Paolo. “Participatory Sense-Making: An Enactive Approach to Social Cognition.” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6 (2007):
485–507.
Deppner, Martin Roman. “Parallel Receptions of the Fundamental: Basic Designs
in Picturebooks and Modern Art.” In Emergent Literary: Children’s Books from 0 to 3,
edited by Bettina Kümmerling-Meibauer, 55–74. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2011.
DeWoskin, Kenneth J. “Review of Traditional Chinese Stories: Themes and Variations, by
Y. W. Ma, Joseph S. M. Lau.” Journal of Asian Studies 38, no. 4 (August 1979): 773–775.
Dick, Philip K. Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep? New York: Ballantine Books, 1996.
Dilley, Paul C. Monasteries and the Care of Souls in the Late Antique Christianity: Cognition and Discipline. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017.
Dissanayake, Ellen. “Prelinguistic and Preliterate Substrates of Poetic Narrative.”
Poetics Today 32, no. 1 (2011): 55–79.
Djikic, Maja, Keith Oatley, and Mihnea C. Moldoveanu. “Reading Other Minds:
Effects of Literature on Empathy.” Scientific Study of Literature 3, no. 1 (2013): 28–47.
Dodell-Feder, David, and Diana I. Tamir. “Fiction Reading Has a Small Positive
Impact on Social Cognition: A Meta-Analysis.” Journal of Experimental Psychology
General 147, no. 11 (2018): 1713–1727.
Bibliography
279
Doody, Margaret Anne. Frances Burney: The Life in the Works. New Brunswick, NJ:
Rutgers University Press, 1988.
Drabble, Emily. “Jon Klassen: Kate Greenaway Medal Winner 2014 – in Pictures.”
The Guardian 23 June, 2014. https://www.theguardian.com/childrens-books-site
/gallery/2014/jun/23/jon-klassen-this-is-not-my-hat-kate-greenaway-in-pictures.
Dostoevsky, Fedor. The Idiot. Достоевский, Ф. М., Идиот. Том 2. Париж, YMCA-Press,
1900. https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=pst.000006918101&view=1up&seq=1F.
Drucker, Johanna. Graphesis: Visual Forms of Knowledge Production. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2014.
Dunbar, Robin I. M. How Many Friends Does One Person Need? Dunbar’s Number and
Other Evolutionary Quirks. London: Faber and Faber, 2010.
Dunbar, Robin I. M. “Why Are Good Writers So Rare? An Evolutionary Perspective
on Literature.” Journal of Cultural and Evolutionary Psychology 3, no. 1 (March 2005):
7–21. doi: 10.1556/JCEP.3.2005.1.1.
Duranti, Alessandro. The Anthropology of Intention: Language in a World of Others.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
Duranti, Alessandro. “Further Reflections on Reading Other Minds.” Anthropological
Quarterly 81, no. 2 (2008): 483–494.
Dyer, Jennifer R., Marilyn Shatz, and Henry M. Wellman. “Young Children’s Storybooks as a Source of Mental State Information,” Cognitive Development 15, no. 1
(January–March 2000): 17–37. doi: 10.1016/S0885-2014(00)00017-4.
Easterlin, Nancy. A Biocultural Approach to Literary Theory and Interpretation. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2012.
Easterlin, Nancy. “Voyages in the Verbal Universe: The Role of Speculation in Darwinian Literary Criticism.” Interdisciplinary Literary Studies 2, no. 2 (2001): 59–73.
Elfenbein, Andrew. The Gist of Reading. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2018.
Elfenbein, Andrew. “Mental Representation.” In Further Reading, edited by Matthew
Rubery and Leah Price, 246–256. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020.
Eliot, George. Middlemarch. Edited by Rosemary Ashton. New York: Penguin Classics,
2003.
Ellison, Ralph. Introduction to Invisible Man, vii–xxiii. New York, Vintage, 1989.
Ellison, Ralph. Invisible Man. New York: Vintage Books, 1989.
Emin, Fedor. Letters of Ernest and Doravra. [1769] In Русская литература XVIII века,
1770–1775. Хрестоматия, edited by В. А Западов. Москва: Просвещение, 1979.
http://az.lib.ru/e/emin_f_a/text_0020.shtml.
280
Bibliography
Emmerich, Wolfgang. “The GDR and Its Literature: An Overview.” In Rereading East
Germany: The Literature and Film of the GDR, edited by Karen Leeder, 8–34. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
Ender, Evelyne, and Deidre Shauna Lynch. “On ‘Learning to Read.’” PMLA 130, no.
3 (2015): 539–545.
Epstein, Julia. The Iron Pen: Frances Burney and the Politics of Women’s Writing. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1989.
Ermer, Elsa, Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby. “Cheater Detection.” Iresearchnet
.com: Psychology Research and Reference. Accessed 06/10/2021. http://psychology
.iresearchnet.com/social-psychology/antisocial-behavior/cheater-detection/.
Ermolay-Erazm. Повесть о Петре и Февронии [The Tale of Peter and Fevroniya].
1547. Translated by A. A. Alekseev. In Памятники литературы Древней Руси.
Выпуск 06: Конец XV - Первая Половина XVI века, edited by Лев Александрович
Дмитриев and Дмитрий Сергеевич Лихачев. Москва: Художественная Литература.,
1984. http://drevne-rus-lit.niv.ru/drevne-rus-lit/text/povest-o-petre-i-fevronii.htm.
Falconer, Rachel. “Children’s Literature: Part II. Forms and Genres. 43. Crossover
Literature.” Schoolbag. Accessed September 20, 2020. http://schoolbag.info/literature
/children/140.html.
Feld, Steven, Sound and Sentiment: Birds, Weeping, Poetics, and Song in Kaluli Expression. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1990.
Fellman, Anita Clair. Little House, Long Shadow: Laura Ingalls Wilder’s Impact on
American Culture. Columbia: University of Missouri Press, 2008.
Fernyhough, Charles. “Metaphors of Mind.” Psychologist 19 (2006): 356–358. https://
thepsychologist.bps.org.uk/volume-19/edition-6/metaphors-mind.
Ferrante, Elena. The Story of the Lost Child: Neapolitan Novels, Book Four. Translated by
Ann Goldstein. New York: Europa Editions, 2015.
Flesch, William. Comeuppance: Costly Signaling, Altruistic Punishment, and Other Biological Components of Fiction. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009.
Fletcher, Garth J. O., Paula Danilovics, Guadalupe Fernandez, Dena Peterson, and
Glenn D. Reeder. “Attributional Complexity: An Individual Differences Measure.”
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 51, no. 4 (1986): 875–884. https://doi.org/10
.1037/0022-3514.51.4.875.
Fludernik, Monika. “Collective Minds in Fact and Fiction: Intermental Thought and
Group Consciousness in Early Modern Narrative.” Poetics Today 35, no. 4 (Winter
2014): 689–730.
Fludernik, Monika. “The Many in Action and Thought: Towards a Poetics of the
Collective in Narrative.” Narrative 25, no. 2 (May 2017): 139–163.
Bibliography
281
Fludernik, Monika. Towards a “Natural” Narratology. New York: Routledge, 2010.
Forster, E. M. Howards End. New York: Vintage Books, 1954.
Frazee, Marla. Hush, Little Baby: A Folk Song with Pictures Board Book. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2007.
Freeman, Charles. The Greek Achievement: The Foundation of the Western World. New
York: Penguin, 1999.
Freeman, Judy. Books Kids Will Sit Still For 3: A Read-Aloud Guide. Children’s and
Young Adult Literature Reference Series 3. Westport, CT: Libraries Unlimited, 2006.
Frith, Christopher D. “The Social Mind?” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, April 29, 2007. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2006.2003 np.
Furlanetto, Tiziano, Andrea Cavallo, Valeria Manera, Barbara Tversky, and Cristina
Becchio. “Through Your Eyes: Incongruence of Gaze and Action Increases Spontaneous Perspective Taking.” Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, August 12, 2013. https://
doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2013.00455.
Garratt, Peter, ed. The Cognitive Humanities: Embodied Mind in Literature and Culture.
New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016.
Garrido Ardila, J. A. “Origins and Definition of the Picaresque Genre.” In The Picaresque Novel in Western Literature: From the Sixteenth Century to the Neopicaresque,
edited by Garrido Ardila, 1–23. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
Gavaler, Chris, and Dan Johnson. “The Genre Effect: A Science Fiction (vs. Realism)
Manipulation Decreases Inference Effort, Reading Comprehension, and Perceptions
of Literary Merit.” Scientific Study of Literature 7, no. 1 (2017): 79–108.
Gaylin, Ann. Eavesdropping in the Novel from Austen to Proust. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002.
Gillespie, John T. Best Books for Children: Preschool through Grade Six. Westport, CT:
Libraries Unlimited, 2002.
Gillespie, Michael Patrick. “From Beau Brummell to Lady Bracknell: Re-viewing
the Dandy in The Importance of Being Earnest.” In The Importance of Being Earnest, by
Oscar Wilde, edited by Michael Patrick Gillespie, 166–182. New York: Norton, 2006.
Ginzburg, Lidiya. Записные Kнижки, Bоспоминания, Эссе. Санкт-П
етербург:
Искусство-СПБ, 2011.
Gladkov, Fedor. Цемент. Москва: Художественная литература, 1925. https://www
.e-reading.club/book.php?book=150460.
Gladkov, Fedor. Cement. Edited and translated by A. S. Arthur and C. Ashleigh.
Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1994.
282
Bibliography
Gogol, Nikolai. “The Overcoat.” In The Collected Tales of Nikolai Gogol, translated by
Richard Pevear and Larissa Volokhonsky, 394–424. New York: Pantheon, 1998.
Graesser, Arthur C., Murray Singer, and Tom Trabasso. “Constructing Inferences
during Narrative Text Comprehension.” Psychological Review 101, no. 3 (1994): 371–
395. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.101.3.371.
Guillory, John. “Monuments and Documents: Panofsky on the Object of Study in
the Humanities.” History of Humanities 1, no. 1 (2016): 9–30. http://dx.doi.org/10
.1086/684635.
Gunn, Daniel P. “Free Indirect Discourse.” In Oxford Research Encyclopedias, June
2019. doi: 10.1093/acrefore/9780190201098.013.1020m.
Günther, Hans. “Soviet Literary Criticism and the Formulation of the Aesthetics of
Socialist Realism.” In A History of Russian Literary Theory and Criticism. The Soviet Age
and Beyond, edited by Evgeny Dobrenko and Galin Tihanov, 90–108. Pittsburgh:
University of Pittsburgh Press, 2011.
Günther, Hans. “Zeleznaja Garmonija (Gosudarstvo Kak Total´noe Proizvedenie
Iskusstva)” [“The Iron Harmony (a State as an All-encompassing Work of Art)”].
Voprosy Literatury 1 (1992): 27–41.
Hake, Sabina. “Political Affects: Antifascism and the Second World War in Frank
Beyer and Konrad Wolf.” In Screening War: Perspectives on German Suffering, edited
by Paul Cooke and Marc Silberman, 102–122. Rochester, NY: Camden House, 2010.
Harding, Jennifer Riddle. “A Mind Enslaved? The Interaction of Metaphor, Cognitive Distance, and Narrative Framing in Chesnutt’s ‘Dave’s Neckliss.’” Style 42, no. 4
(Winter 2008): 425–447.
Harris, Paul L. “Conversation, Pretense, and Theory of Mind.” In Why Language Matters for Theory of Mind, edited by Janet Wilde Astington and Jodie A. Baird, 70–83.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
Harris, Paul L., Marc de Rosnay, and Francisco Pons. “Language and Children’s
Understanding of Mental States.” Current Directions in Psychological Science 14, no. 2
(2005): 69–73.
Harris, Paul L., Marc de Rosnay, and Samuel Ronfard. “The Mysterious Emotional
Life of Little Red Riding Hood.” In Children and Emotion: New Insights into Developmental Affective Sciences, edited by Kristin H. Lagattuta, 106–118. Basel: Karger, 2014.
Hayden, George A. “The Beginning of the End: The Fall of the Han and the Opening
of Three Kingdoms.” In Three Kingdoms and Chinese Culture, edited by Kimberly Besio
and Constantine Tung, 43–51. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2007.
Hegel, Robert E. “Traditional Chinese Fiction—The State of the Field.” Journal of
Asian Studies 53, no. 2 (May 1994): 394–426.
Bibliography
283
Heliodorus. An Ethiopian Romance. Translated by Moses Hadas. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1957.
Henry, Nancy. The Life of George Eliot: A Critical Biography. Chichester, UK: WileyBlackwell, 2012.
Herman, David. “Multimodal Storytelling and Identity Construction in Graphic
Narratives.” In Telling Stories: Language, Narrative, and Social Life, edited by Deborah
Schiffrin, Anna de Fina, and Anastasia Nylund, 195–208. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2010.
Herman, David. Storytelling and the Sciences of the Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
2013.
Heyman, Gail D. “Children’s Reasoning about Deception.” In Trust and Skepticism:
Children’s Selective Learning from Testimony, edited by Elizabeth J. Robinson and Shiri
Einav, 83–94. New York: Psychology Press, 2014.
Hickok, Gregory. The Myth of Mirror Neurons: The Real Neuroscience of Communication
and Cognition. New York: Norton, 2014.
Highsmith, Patricia. Afterword to Selected Novels and Short Stories, edited by Joan
Schenkar, 577–580. New York: Norton, 1993.
Highsmith, Patricia. The Price of Salt. In Selected Novels and Short Stories, edited by
Joan Schenkar, 337–575. New York: Norton, 1993.
Hill, Pamela Smith. “Introduction: ‘Will It Come to Anything?’: The Story of Pioneer
Girl.” In Pioneer Girl: The Annotated Autobiography, edited by Pamela Smith Hill,
xv–lix. Pierre: South Dakota Historical Society Press, 2014.
Hirschfeld, Lawrence A. “The Myth of Mentalizing and the Primacy of Folk Sociology.” In Navigating the Social World: What Infants and Other Species Can Teach Us,
edited by Mahzarin Banaji and Susan A. Gelman, 101–106. New York: Oxford University Press, 2014. doi: 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199890712.003.0019.
Hodne, Lasse. “Memling’s Portraits of Christ: A Cognitive Approach.” Acta ad archaeologiam et artium historiam pertinentia 3, no. 17 (2019): 245–258. doi: 10.5617/acta.7810.
Hoekstra, Hopi E. “From Darwin to DNA: The Genetic Basis of Color Adaptation.” In
In the Light of Evolution: Essays from the Laboratory and the Field, edited by Jonathan B.
Losos, 277–295. Greenville Village, CO: Roberts, 2010.
Hogan, Patrick Colm. Sexual Identities. New York: Oxford University Press, 2019.
Hogan, Patrick Colm. “Literary Universals.” In Introduction to Cognitive Cultural Studies, edited by Lisa Zunshine, 37–60. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press,
2010.
Holquist, Michael. Dialogism: Bakhtin and his World. London: Routledge, 1990.
284
Bibliography
Homer. The Odyssey. Rendered into English Prose for the Use by Those Who Cannot Read
the Original by Samuel Butler. London, New York, and Bombay: Longmans, Green, and
Co, 1900.
Howard, Michael. The First World War: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2002.
Hughes, Claire, Naomi White, and Rosie Ensor. “How Does Talking about Thoughts,
Desires, and Feelings Foster Children’s Socio-cognitive Development? Mediators,
Moderators and Implications for Intervention.” In Children and Emotion: New Insights
into Developmental Affective Science, edited by Kristin Hansen Lagattuta, 94–105.
Basel: Karger, 2014.
Iliopoulou, Evgenia. Because of You: Understanding Second-Person Storytelling. Bielefeld,
Germany: Transcript-Verlag, 2019.
Ionescu, Andrei. “A Manifesto against Failures of Understanding: Ian McEwan’s
Atonement.” Critique: Studies in Contemporary Fiction, August 1, 2017, 1–19.
Irvine, Judith T. “Language Ideology.” Oxford Bibliographies. New York: Oxford University Press, 2012. Accessed March 27, 2019. http://www.oxfordbibliographies.com
/view/document/obo-9780199766567/obo-9780199766567-0012.xml.
Irving, John. The 158-Pound Marriage. New York: Ballantine, 1997.
Jackson, Shirley. “The Beautiful Stranger.” In Dark Tales, 73–80. New York: Penguin,
2017.
Jakobson, Roman. “On Realism in Art.” In Language and Literature, edited by Krystyna
Pomorska and Steven Rudy, 19–27. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987.
Jansson, Tove. Moomin Falls in Love. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2013.
Johnson, Barbara. “Teaching Deconstructively.” In Writing and Reading Differently,
edited by G. Douglas Atkins and Michael L. Johnson, 140–148. Lawrence: University
Press of Kansas, 1986.
Johnson, Mark. Embodied Mind, Meaning, and Reason: How Our Bodies Give Rise to
Understanding. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2017.
Johnson, Mark. “The Embodiment of Language.” In The Oxford Handbook of 4E
Cognition, edited by Albert Newen, Leon De Bruin, and Shaun Gallagher, 623–640.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020.
Kanske, Philipp, Anne Bockler, Fynn-Mathis Trautwein, and Tania Singer. “Dissecting the Social Brain: Introducing the EmpaToM to Reveal Distinct Neural Networks
and Brain–Behavior Relations for Empathy and Theory of Mind.” NeuroImage 122,
no. 15 (November 2015): 6–19.
Karamzin, N. M. “Bednaya Liza.” In Izbrannye Sochinenia, vol. 1, 605–621. Moscow:
Khudozhestvennaya Literatura, 1964.
Bibliography
285
Keane, Webb. Ethical Life: Its Natural and Social Histories. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2016.
Keane, Webb. “Others, Other Minds, and Others’ Theories of Other Minds: An Afterword on the Psychology and Politics of Opacity Claims.” Anthropological Quarterly
81, no. 2 (Spring 2008): 473–482.
Keen, Suzanne. Empathy and the Novel. New York: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Keen, Suzanne. Thomas Hardy’s Brains: Psychology, Neurology, and Hardy’s Imagination. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 2014.
Kidd, David Comer, and Emanuele Castano. “Panero et al. (2016): Failure to Replicate Methods Caused the Failure to Replicate Results.” Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology 112 (2017): e1–e4. doi:10.1037/pspa0000072.
Kidd, David Comer, and Emanuele Castano. “Reading Literary Fiction and Theory
of Mind: Three Preregistered Replications and Extensions of Kidd and Castano
(2013).” Social Psychological and Personality Science, June 20, 2018, 1–10. doi: 10.1177
/1948550618775410journals.sagepub.com/home/spp.
Kidd, David Comer, and Emanuele Castano. “Reading Literary Fiction Can Improve
Theory of Mind.” Nature Human Behaviour 2 (September 2018): 604. doi: https://doi
.org/10.1038/s41562-018-0408-2 .
Kinney, Jeff. Diary of a Wimpy Kid: Rodrick Rules. New York: Amulet Books, 2008.
Knoepflmacher, Ulrich C., and Mitzi Myers. “From the Editors: ‘Cross-Writing’ and
the Reconceptualizing of Children’s Literary Studies.” Children’s Literature 25 (1997):
vii–xvi.
Kompa, Nikola A. “Language and Embodiment—Or the Cognitive Benefits of Abstract
Representations.” Mind and Language 26 (2021): 27–47. doi: 10.1111/mila.12266
Kramnick, Jonathan, and Anahid Nersessian. “Form and Explanation.” Critical
Inquiry 43 (Spring 2017): 650–669.
Kukkonen, Karin. “Does Cognition Translate? Predictions, Plot, and World Literature.” Poetics Today 41, no. 2 (2020): 243–259.
Kukkonen, Karin. 4E Cognition and Eighteenth-Century Fiction: How the Novel Found Its
Feet. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019.
Kukkonen, Karin. Probability Designs: Literature and Predictive Processing. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2020.
Kulpa, Kathryn. Review of Ninety-Nine Stories of God, by Joy Williams. Cleaver: Philadelphia’s International Literary Magazine, September 22, 2016. https://www.cleavermagazine
.com/ninety-nine-stories-of-god-by-joy-williams-reviewed-by-kathryn-kulpa/.
Kümmerling-Meibauer, Bettina. “Emotional Connection: Representation of Emotions in Young Adult Literature.” In Contemporary Adolescent Literature and Culture:
286
Bibliography
The Emergent Adult, edited by Mary Hilton and Maria Nikolajeva, 127–138. Abingdon, UK: Ashgate, 2012.
Kümmerling-Meibauer, Bettina. “Metalinguistic Awareness and the Child’s Developing Concept of Irony: The Relationship between Pictures and Text in Ironic Picture
Books.” Lion and the Unicorn 23, no. 2 (April 1999): 157–183.
Kümmerling-Meibauer, Bettina, and Jörg Meibauer. “Early-Concept Books: Acquiring Nominal and Verbal Concepts.” In Emergent Literary: Children’s Books from 0 to 3,
edited by Bettina Kümmerling-Meibauer, 91–114. Amsterdam: John Benjamins, 2011.
Kuritzyn, Fedor. The Tale of Dracula. ca. 1490. http://old-ru.ru/06-7.html.
Kuzmičová, Anezka. “Consciousness.” In Further Reading, edited by Matthew Rubery
and Leah Price, 271–281. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020.
Kuzmičová, Anezka and Katalin Bálint. “Personal Relevance in Story Reading: A
Research Review.” Poetics Today 40 no. 3 (2019): 429–451
Landau, Bonnie. “11 Reasons a Child Cannot Look You in the Eyes.” Special Mom
Advocate, March 2, 2018. https://www.specialmomadvocate.com/11-reasons-child
-cannot-look-eyes/.
Landy, Joshua. How to Do Things with Fictions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012.
Lantos, John D. “Reconsidering Action: Day-to-Day Ethics in the Work of Medicine.” In Stories Matter: The Role of Narrative in Medical Ethics, edited by Rita Charon
and Martha Montello, 154–159. London: Routledge, 2002.
Lee, Haiyan. “Chinese Feelings: Notes on a Ritual Theory of Emotion.” Wenshan
Review of Literature and Culture 9, no. 2 (June 2016): 1–37.
Lee, Haiyan. “Measuring the Stomach of a Gentleman with the Heart-Mind of a Pipsqueak: On the Ubiquity and Utility of Theory of Mind in Literature, Mostly.” Poetics
Today 41, no. 2 (2020): 205–222.
Lee, Haiyan. “Response to the Panel on Cognitive Approaches to Chinese Literature.”
Paper presented at the Modern Language Association, New York, January 2018.
Lee, Haiyan. “Society Must Be Defended: Chinese Spy Thrillers and the Enchantment of Arcana Imperii.” Unpublished paper.
Lee, Haiyan. The Stranger and the Chinese Moral Imagination. Stanford, CA: Stanford
University Press, 2014.
Lee, Haiyan. “When Nothing Is True, Everything Is Possible: On Truth and Power by
Way of Socialist Realism.” PMLA 134, no. 5 (2019): 1157–1164.
Leeder, Karen. Introduction to Rereading East Germany: The Literature and Film of the
GDR, edited by Karen Leeder, 1–7. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
Bibliography
287
Leff, Gordon. “The Trivium and the Three Philosophies.” In A History of the University
in Europe, vol. 1, Universities in the Middle Ages, edited by Hilde de Ridder-Symoens,
307–336. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992.
Lepowsky, Maria. “Personhood, Empathy, and ‘the Native’s Point of View.’” In The
Anthropology of Empathy: Experiencing the Lives of Others in the Pacific Societies, edited
by Douglas W. Hollan and C. Jason Throop, 43–65. New York: Berghahn Books, 2011.
Lermontov, Mikhail. A Hero of Our Time. A Novel. translated by Vladimir Nabokov
and Dmitri Nabokov. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday, 1958.
Lerner, Ben. Leaving the Atocha Station. Minneapolis: Coffee House, 2011.
Levinas, Emmanuel. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Translated by
Alphonso Lingis. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1969.
Levine, Caroline. Forms: Whole, Rhythm, Hierarchy, Network. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2017.
Li, Wanqing, Xiaoqin Mai, and Chao Liu. “The Default Mode Network and Social
Understanding of Others: What Do Brain Connectivity Studies Tell Us.” Frontiers in
Human Neuroscience 8, no. 74 (2014). Published online February 24, 2014.
Link, Perry. “The Wonderfully Elusive Chinese Novel.” New York Review of Books,
April 23, 2015. https://www.nybooks.com/articles/2015/04/23/wonderfully-elusive
-chinese-novel/.
Lipson, Eden Ross. The New York Times Parent’s Guide to the Best Books for Children.
New York: Three Rivers, 2000.
Lockington, Mariama J. For Black Girls like Me. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux,
2019.
Lorant, Laurie Robertson. Melville: A Biography. New York: Clarkson Potter, 1996.
Lu, Tina. “Interiority in Jinpingmei cihua.” In Approaches to Teaching “The Plum in the
Golden Vase,” edited by Andrew Schonebaum. New York: MLA, 2022.
Lu Xun [Lu Hsun]. A Brief History of Chinese Fiction. 1959. Translated by Yang Hsien-Yi
and Gladys Yang. Introduction by Moss Roberts. Beijing: Foreign Language Press, 2014.
Lu Xun [Lu Hsun]. A Madman’s Diary: English and Chinese Bilingual Edition. Translated by Paul Meighan. CreateSpace, 2014.
Luhrmann, Tanya Marie. “Theory of Mind in the Pacific: Reasoning across Cultures,
edited by Jürg Wassmann, Birgit Träuble and Joachim Funke.” Anthropological Forum
25, no. 4 (2015): 442–444.
Luhrmann, Tanya Marie. “Toward an Anthropological Theory of Mind: Overview.”
Suomen Antropologi: Journal of the Finnish Anthropological Society 36, no. 4 (2011): 5–13.
288
Bibliography
Luo Guanzhong. The Three Kingdoms. Vol. 1, The Sacred Oath: The Epic Chinese Tale
of Loyalty and War in a Dynamic New Translation. Edited by Ronald C. Iverson. Translated by Yu Sumei. North Clarendon, VT: Tuttle, 2014.
Luo, Manling. Literati Storytelling in Late Medieval China. Seattle: University of Washington Press, 2015.
Ma, Y. W., and Joseph S. M. Lau, eds., Traditional Chinese Stories: Themes and Variations. New York: Columbia University Press, 1978.
Maiping, Chen. “The Intertextual Reading of Chinese Literature with Mo Yan’s
Works as Examples.” Chinese Literature Today 5, no. 1 (2015): 34–36.
Mäkelä, Maria. “Possible Minds. Constructing – and Reading – Another Consciousness as Fiction.” In FREE Language INDIRECT Translation DISCOURSE Narratology,
edited by Pekka Tammi and Hannu Tommola, 231–260. Tampere: Tampere University Press, 2006.
Mair, Victor H. “Review of Traditional Chinese Stories: Themes and Variations by Y. W.
Ma, Joseph S. M. Lau.” Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies 39, no. 2 (December 1979):
461–469.
Mar, Raymond A., Keith Oatley, Jacob Hirsh, Jennifer dela Paz, and Jordan B. Peterson. “Bookworms versus Nerds: Exposure to Fiction versus Non-fiction, Divergent
Associations with Social Ability, and the Simulation of Fictional Social Worlds.”
Journal of Research in Personality 40 (2006): 694–712.
Mar, Raymond A., Keith Oatley, and Jordan B. Peterson. “Exploring the Link between
Reading Fiction and Empathy: Ruling Out Individual Differences and Examining
Outcomes.” Communications 34, no. 4 (2009). doi: https://doi.org/10.1515/COMM
.2009.025.
Mar, Raymond A., Jennifer L. Tackett, and Chris Moore. “Exposure to Media and
Theory-of-Mind Development in Preschoolers.” Cognitive Development 25, no. 1
(January–March 2010): 69–78.
Martens, Lorna. “Corporeality, Materiality, and Unnamed Emotions in Rilke’s
Dinggedichte.” In Feelings Materialized: Emotions, Bodies, and Things in Germany,
1500–1950, edited by Heikki Lempa, Derek Hillard, and Russell Spinney, 235–251.
New York: Berghahn Books, 2020.
Martins, Mauricio D., and W. Tecumseh Fitch. “Do We Represent Intentional Action
as Recursively Embedded? The Answer Must Be Empirical. A Comment on Vicari
and Adenzato (2014).” Consciousness and Cognition 38 (December 15, 2015): 16–21.
Martinsen, Deborah A. Surprised by Shame: Dostoevsky’s Liars and Narrative Exposure.
Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 2003.
Bibliography
289
Mascaro, Olivier, and Olivier Molin. “Gullible’s Travel: How Honest and Trustful
Children Become Vigilant Communicators.” In Trust and Skepticism: Children’s
Selective Learning from Testimony, edited by Elizabeth L. Robinson Shir Einav, 69–82.
London: Psychology Press, 2014.
Mascaro, Olivier, and Dan Sperber. “The Moral, Epistemic, and Mindreading Components of Children’s Vigilance towards Deception.” Cognition 112 (2009): 367–380.
Mason, Malia F., Elizabeth P. Tatkow, and C. Neil Macrae. “The Look of Love: Gaze
Shifts and Person Perception.” Psychological Science 16 (2005): 236–239.
McCarthy, Cormac. Blood Meridian: Or the Evening Redness in the West. New York:
Vintage, 1985.
McCrea, Brian. Frances Burney and Narrative Prior to Ideology. Newark: University of
Delaware Press, 2013.
McHale, Brian. “Revisiting Realisms; or, WWJD (What Would Jakobson Do?)” Journal of the Midwest Modern Language Association 41, no. 2 (Fall 2008): 6–17. http://
www.jstor.com/stable/20464270.
McKinnon, Margaret C., and Morris Moscovitch. “Domain-General Contributions
to Social Reasoning: Theory of Mind and Deontic Reasoning Re-explored.” Cognition
102 (2007): 179–218.
McNamara, Rita Anne, Aiyana K.Willard, Ara Norenzayan, and Joseph Henrich.
“Weighing Outcome vs. Intent across Societies: How Cultural Models of Mind Shape
Moral Reasoning.” Cognition 182 (2019): 95–108. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition
.2018.09.008.
Mercier, Hugo, and Dan Sperber. The Enigma of Reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2017.
Mersereau, John, Jr. “The Nineteenth Century: Romanticism, 1820–40.” In The Cambridge History of Russian Literature, edited by Charles A. Moser, 136–188. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1989.
Miall, David S. “Science in the Perspective of Literariness.” Scientific Study of Literature 8 (2011): 8–14.
Miller, Nick. “Gruffalo Creator Finds Room for Girls—But They Don’t Have to be
Feisty.” The Sydney Morning Herald. February 16, 2020. https://www.smh.com.au
/culture/books/gruffalo-creator-finds-room-for-girls-but-they-don-t-have-to-be-feisty
-20200214-p5411n.html.
Miller, Patricia H., Frank S. Kessel, and John H. Flavell. “Thinking about People Thinking about People Thinking about . . . : A Study of Social Cognitive Development.”
Child Development 41, no. 3 (September 1970): 613–623. doi: 10.2307/1127211.
290
Bibliography
Miller, Sara F. Pooh’s Honey Trouble. Glendale, CA: Disney, 2012.
Miller, William Ian. Losing It. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2011.
Milligan, Karen, Janet Wilde Astington, and Lisa Ain Dack. “Language and Theory
of Mind: Meta-analysis of the Relation between Language Ability and False-Belief
Understanding.” Child Development, 78, no. 2 (2007): 622–646.
Milne, Alan Alexander. The Complete Tales of Winnie-the-Pooh. New York: Penguin,
1996.
Minchin, Elizabeth. “The Cognition of Deception: Falsehoods in Homer’s Odyssey
and Their Audiences.” In The Routledge Handbook of Classics and Cognitive Theory,
edited by Peter Meineck, William Michael Short, and Jennifer Devereaux, 109–138.
London: Routledge, 2018.
Monaco, Loretta. “Review of DiaoChan: The Rise of the Courtesan.” LondonTheatre1
May 12, 2016. https://www.londontheatre1.com/reviews/review-of-diaochan-the
-rise-of-the-courtesan/.
Morris, Marcia A. The Literature of Roguery in Seventeenth- and Early Eighteenth-Century
Russia. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2000.
Morris, Marcia A. “Russia: The Picaresque Repackaged.” In The Picaresque Novel in
Western Literature: From the Sixteenth Century to the Neopicaresque, edited by Garrido
Ardila, 200–223. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
Moshfegh, Ottessa. Foreword to Dark Tales, by Shirley Jackson, edited by Ottessa
Moshfegh, vii–x. New York: Penguin, 2016.
Muira, Kayo and Motoko Koike, “Judgment, Interpretation and Impression of Gaze
Direction in an Ukiyo-e Picture.” Japanese Psychological Research 45 no. 4 (2003): 209
– 220.
Munro, George E. “Finance and Credit in the Eighteenth-Century Russian Economy.” Jahrbücher für Geschichte Osteuropas 45, no. 4 (1997): 552–560.
Murasaki Shikibu. The Tale of Genji. Translated by Edward G. Seidensticker. Gardners Books, 1992.
Murasaki Shikibu. The Tale of Genji. Translated by Royall Tyler. New York: Penguin,
2002.
Murasaki Shikibu. The Tale of Genji. Translated by Arthur Waley. North Clarendon,
VT: Tuttle, 2010.
Nabokov, Vladimir. Lectures on Russian Literature. Edited by Fredson Bowers. New
York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1981.
Nabokov, Vladimir. “Translator’s Foreword.” In A Hero of Our Time, by Mihail Lermontov, v–xv. New York: Doubleday Anchor Books, 1958.
Bibliography
291
Nadel, Alan. Invisible Criticism: Ralph Ellison and the American Canon. Iowa City: University of Iowa Press, 1988.
Newen, Albert, Leon De Bruin, and Shaun Gallagher. “4E Cognition: Historical
Roots, Key Concepts, and Central Issues.” In The Oxford Handbook of 4E Cognition,
edited by Albert Newen, Leon De Bruin, and Shaun Gallagher, 3–15. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2020.
Nielsen, Henrik Skov, James Phelan, and Richard Walsh. “Ten Theses about Fictionality.” Narrative 23, no. 1 (2015): 61–73. doi: 10.1353/nar.2015.0005.
Nikolajeva, Maria. Children’s Literature Comes of Age: Toward a New Aesthetic. New
York: Garland, 1996.
Nikolajeva, Maria. “‘The Penguin Looked Sad’: Picturebooks, Empathy and Theory of
Mind.” In Picturebooks: Representation and Narration, edited by Bettina KümmerlingMeibauer, 121–137. New York: Routledge, 2011.
Nizami. The Story of Layla and Majnun. Translated by Rudolf Gelpke. 2nd ed. Medford, OR: Omega, 1996.
Noel, Anne-Sophie. “What Do We Actually See on Stage? A Cognitive Approach to
the Interaction of Visual and Aural Effects in the Performance of Greek Tragedy.”
In The Routledge Handbook of Classics and Cognitive Theory, edited by Peter Meineck,
William Michael Short, and Jennifer Devereaux, 297–309. London: Routledge, 2018.
Nussbaum, Martha C. “‘Finely Aware and Richly Responsible’: Moral Attention
and the Moral Task of Literature.” Journal of Philosophy 82 (1985): 516–529. doi:
10.2307/2026358.
Nussbaum, Martha C. “Literary Imagination in Public Life.” New Literary History 22
(1991): 877–910. doi: 10.2307/469070.
Ochs, Elinor. “Clarification and Culture.” In Meaning, Form, and Use in Context: Linguistic Applications, edited by Deborah Schiffrin, 325–341. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1984.
Ochs, Elinor, and Bambi B. Schieffelin. “Language Acquisition and Socialization:
Three Developmental Stories and Their Implications.” In Culture Theory: Essays on
Mind, Self, and Emotion, edited by Richard A. Shweder and Robert A. LeVine, 276–
320. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984.
Oforlea, Aaron Ngozi. “The Dilemma of the African American Detective in Walter
Mosley’s Devil in a Blue Dress.” Manuscript under review.
Olney, James. Memory and Narrative: The Weave of Life-Writing. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1998.
“100 Must-Reads.” DW. Accessed 06/09/2021. https://www.dw.com/en/top-stories
/100-must-reads/s-43415865.
292
Bibliography
Onishi, Kristine H., and Renée Baillargeon. “Do 15-Months-Old Infants Understand
False Beliefs?” Science 308 (2005): 255–258.
O’Sullivan, Emer. “Comparative Children’s Literature.” PMLA 126, no. 1 (2011):
189–196.
Owen, Stephen. An Anthology of Chinese Literature: Beginnings to 1911. New York:
Norton, 1996.
Owen, Stephen. The End of the Chinese “Middle Ages”: Essays in Mid-Tang Literary Culture. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1996.
Palmer, Alan. Fictional Minds. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 2004.
Palmer, Alan. Social Minds in the Novel. Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 2010.
Palmer, Alan. “Storyworlds and Groups.” In Introduction to Cognitive Cultural Studies,
edited by Lisa Zunshine, 176–192. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010.
Panero, Maria Eugenia, Deena Skolnick Weisberg, Jessica Black, Thalia R. Goldstein,
Jennifer L. Barnes, Hiram Brownell, and Ellen Winner. “Does Reading a Single Passage of Literary Fiction Really Improve Theory of Mind? An Attempt at Replication.”
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 111, no. 5 (November 2016): e46–e54.
Parker-Pope, Tara. “Behind the ‘Wimpy Kid’ Phenomenon.” New York Times, October 12, 2009. http://www.nytimes.com/2009/10/13/health/13well.html.
Pascal, Roy. The Dual Voice: Free Indirect Speech and Its Functioning in the NineteenthCentury European Novel. Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1977.
Paul, Georgina. “Gender in GDR Literature.” In Rereading East Germany: The Literature and Film of the GDR, edited by Karen Leeder, 106–125. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2015.
Peskin, Joan, and Janet Wilde Astington. “The Effects of Adding Metacognitive Language to Story Texts.” Cognitive Development 19 (2004): 253–273.
Petrone, Karen. Life Has Become More Joyous, Comrades: Celebrations in the Time of
Stalin. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2000.
Petronius, Arbiter. The Satyricon. Translated by John Malcolm Mitchell. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, 1923.
Phelan, James, and Peter J. Rabinowitz. “Authors, Narrators, Narration.” In Narrative
Theory: Core Concepts and Critical Debates, by David Herman, James Phelan, Peter
J. Rabinowitz, Brian Richardson, and Robyn Warhol, 29–38. Columbus: Ohio State
University Press, 2012.
Phelan, James, and Peter J. Rabinowitz. “Narrative Values, Aesthetic Values.” In Narrative Theory: Core Concepts and Critical Debates, by David Herman, James Phelan,
Bibliography
293
Peter J. Rabinowitz, Brian Richardson, and Robyn Warhol, 160–164. Columbus:
Ohio State University Press, 2012.
Phillips, Natalie M. Distraction: Problems of Attention in Eighteenth-Century Literature.
Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2016.
Phillips, Natalie M. “Literary Neuroscience and History of Mind: An Interdisciplinary
fMRI Study of Attention and Jane Austen.” In The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Literary
Studies, edited by Lisa Zunshine, 55–81. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015.
Pittard, Hannah. Listen to Me. New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2016.
Plaks, Andrew H. “Full-Length Hsiao-shuo and the Western Novel: A Generic Reappraisal.” New Asia Academic Bulletin 1 (1978): 163–176.
Plaks, Andrew H. “The Novel in Premodern China.” In The Novel, vol. 1, History,
Geography, and Culture, edited by Franco Moretti, 181–213. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 2006.
Plaks, Andrew H. The Four Masterworks of the Ming Novel: Ssu ta ch’i-shu. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 2016.
Pocock, J. G. A. Virtue, Commerce, and History: Essays on Political Thought and History,
Chiefly in the Eighteenth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.
Polvinen, Merja. “Enactive Perception and Fictional Worlds.” In The Cognitive
Humanities: Embodied Mind in Literature and Culture, edited by Peter Garratt, 19–34.
London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016.
Polvinen, Merja. “Sense-Making and Wonder: An Enactive Approach to Narrative
Form in Speculative Fiction.” In The Edinburgh Companion to Contemporary Narrative
Theories, edited by Zara Dinnen and Robyn Warhol, 67–80. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press, 2018.
Popova, Yanna B. Stories, Meaning, and Experience. New York: Routledge, 2015.
Premack, David G., and Guy Woodruff. “Does the Chimpanzee Have a Theory
of Mind?” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1, no. 4 (1978): 515–526. doi: 10.1017/
S0140525X00076512.
Proust, Marcel. Remembrance of Things Past. Vol. 1. Translated by C. K. Scott Moncrieff. Hertfordshire, UK: Wordsworth Editions, 2006.
Pushkin, Alexander. Eugene Onegin, Revised Edition: A Novel in Verse by Alexandr
Pushkin, Translated from Russian, with a Commentary, by Vladimir Nabokov. Vol. 1.
Bollingen Series 77. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975.
Pushkin, Alexander. Novels, Tales, Journeys: The Complete Prose of Alexander Pushkin.
Translated by Richard Pevear and Larissa Volokhonsky. New York: Knopf, 2016.
294
Bibliography
Rey, H. A. Curious George at the Zoo. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2007.
Richardson, Alan. Literature, Education, and Romanticism: Reading as Social Practice,
1780–1832. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Richardson, Alan. The Neural Sublime: Cognitive Theories and Romantic Texts. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010.
Richardson, Alan. “Studies in Literature and Cognition: A Field Map.” In The Work
of Fiction: Cognition, Culture, and Complexity, edited by Alan Richardson and Ellen
Spolsky, 1–29. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2004.
Richardson, Samuel. Clarissa; or, The History of a Young Lady. Edited by Angus Ross.
Penguin Books, 1985.
Riftin, Boris. От Мифа к Роману: Эволюция Изображения Рерсонажа в Китайской
Литературе [From myth to the serial novel: The evolution of the image of character in
Chinese literature]. Moscow: Наука, 1979.
Riva, Federica, Chantal Triscoli, Claus Lamm, Andrea Carnaghi, and Giorgia Silani
“Emotional Egocentricity Bias across the Life-Span.” Frontiers in Aging Neuroscience 8,
no. 74 (2016). doi: 10.3389/fnagi.2016.00074.
Robbe-Grillet, Alain. Two Novels by Robbe-Grillet: Jealousy and In the Labyrinth. Translated by Richard Howard. New York: Black Cat Books by Grove Press, 1965.
Robbins, Joel, and Alan Rumsey. “Introduction: Cultural and Linguistic Anthropology and the Opacity of Other Minds,” Anthropological Quarterly 81, no. 2 (2008):
407–420.
Rolston, David L. Traditional Chinese Fiction and Fiction Commentary: Reading and
Writing between the Lines. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1997.
Rooney, Sally. Conversations with Friends. London: Hogarth, 2017.
Rosenberg, Alex. How History Gets Things Wrong: The Neuroscience of Our Addiction to
Stories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2018.
Rosenman, Ellen Bayuk. “Rudeness, Slang, and Obscenity: Working-Class Politics in
London Labour and the London Poor.” In Victorian Vulgarity: Taste in Verbal and
Visual Culture, edited by Susan David Bernstein and Elsie B. Michie, 55–70. Farnham,
UK: Ashgate, 2009.
Rosnay, Marc de, Francisco Pons, Paul L. Harris, and Julian M. B. Morrell. “A Lag
between Understanding False Belief and Emotion Attribution in Young Children:
Relationships with Linguistic Ability and Mothers’ Mental State Language.” British
Journal of Developmental Psychology 22 (2004): 197–218.
Roy, David Tod, trans. The Plum in the Golden Vase, or, Chin P’ing Mei. Vol. 1, The
Gathering. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993.
Bibliography
295
Roy, David Tod, trans. The Plum in the Golden Vase, or, Chin P’ing Mei. Vol. 2, The
Rival. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001.
Ruden, Sarah. “Translator’s Preface.” In The Golden Ass, by Apuleius, translated by
Sarah Ruden, ix–xvi. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2013.
Rumsey, Alan, “Empathy and Anthropology: An Afterword.” In The Anthropology of
Empathy: Experiencing the Lives of Others in the Pacific Societies, edited by Douglas W.
Hollan and C. Jason Throop, 215–224. New York: Berghahn Books, 2011.
Sabbagh, Mark A., and Dare Baldwin. “Understanding the Role of Communicative
Intentions in Word Learning.” In Joint Attention: Communication and Other Minds,
edited by Naomi Eilan, Christoph Hoerl, Teresa McCormack, and Johannes Roessler,
165–184. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005.
Saggini, Francesca. Backstage in the Novel: Frances Burney and the Theater Arts. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 2012.
Santos, Henri Carlo, Igor Grossmann, and Michael E. W. Varnum. “Class, Cognition and Cultural Change in Social Class.” PsyArxiv Preprints, July 2, 2018. https://
psyarxiv.com/92smf/.
Sartre, Jean-Paul. Being and Nothingness. Translated by Hazel E. Barnes. New York:
Philosophical Library, 1956.
Saussy, Haun. “Comparative Literature and Translation.” In Introducing Comparative
Literature: New Trends and Applications, by Cesar Domingues, Haun Saussy, and Dario
Villanueva, 78–87. London: Routledge, 2015.
Savarese, Ralph James. See It Feelingly: Classic Novels, Autistic Readers, and the Schooling of a No-Good English Professor. Durham, NC: Durham University Press, 2018.
Savarese, Ralph James, and Lisa Zunshine. “The Critic as Neurocosmopolite; or, What
Cognitive Approaches to Literature Can Learn from Disability Studies: Lisa Zunshine
in Conversation with Ralph James Savarese.” Narrative 22, no. 1 (2014): 17–44.
Saxe, Rebecca. “The New Puzzle of Theory of Mind Development.” In Navigating
the Social World: What Infants, Children, and Other Species Can Teach Us, edited by
Mahzarin R. Banaji and Susan A. Gelman, 107–112. New York: Oxford University
Press, 2013.
Saxe, Rebecca. “The Right Temporo-Parietal Junction: A Specific Brain Region for
Thinking about Thoughts.” In Handbook of Theory of Mind, edited by Alan Leslie
and Tamsin German. London: Psychology Press, 2010. https://saxelab.mit.edu/sites
/default/files/publications/Saxe_RTPJChapter.pdf.
Saxe, Rebecca, and Nancy Kanwisher. “People Thinking about Thinking People: The
Role of the Temporo-parietal Junction in ‘Theory of Mind.’” NeuroImage 19 (2003):
1835–1842.
296
Bibliography
Saxe, Rebecca, and Lindsey J. Powell. “It’s the Thought That Counts: Specific Brain
Regions for One Component of Theory of Mind.” Psychology Science 17 (2006): 692–699.
Scarry, Elaine. Dreaming by the Book. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2013.
Scarry, Elaine. Naming Thy Name: Cross Talk in Shakespeare’s Sonnets. New York:
Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2016.
Schacter, Daniel L. Searching for Memory: The Brain, the Mind, and the Past. New York:
Basic Books, 1996.
Schenkar, Joan. The Talented Miss Highsmith: The Secret Life and Serious Art of Patricia
Highsmith. New York: St. Martin’s, 2009.
Schieffelin, Bambi B. “Found in Translation: Reflexive Language across Time and
Texts in Bosavi, Papua New Guinea.” In Consequences of Contact: Language Ideologies and Sociocultural Transformation in Pacific Societies, edited by Miki Makihara and
Bambi B. Schieffelin, 140–165. New York: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Schieffelin, Bambi B. The Give and Take of Everyday Life: Language Socialization of
Kaluli Children. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
Schieffelin, Bambi B. “Speaking Only Your Own Mind: Reflections on Confession,
Gossip, and Intentionality in Bosavi (PNG).” Anthropological Quarterly 81, no. 2 (2008):
431–441.
Schieffelin, Bambi B. “Two Dukula Sulo: & One Dog.” Told by Heina (Kaluli, Papua
New Guinea, 1984). Unpublished manuscript, 2019.
Schieffelin, Edward L. The Sorrow of the Lonely and the Burning of the Dancers. New
York: St. Martin, 1976.
Schiller, J. C. Friedrich von. Schillers Sämmtliche Werke: Vollständige Ausgabe in Zwei
Bänden. Vol. 2. Philadelphia: Ferlag von J. Robler, 1880.
Schneider, Ralf. “The Cognitive Theory of Character Reception: An Updated Proposal.” Anglistik 24, no. 2 (2013): 117–134.
Schonebaum, Andrew. Introduction to Approaches to Teaching “The Story of the Stone,”
edited by Andrew Schonebaum and Tina Lu, 5–69. New York: Modern Language
Association, 2012.
Scott, Mary. “The Story of the Stone and Its Antecedents.” In Approaches to Teaching
“The Story of the Stone,” edited by Andrew Schonebaum and Tina Lu, 266. New York:
Modern Language Association, 2012.
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky. “Privilege of Unknowing: Diderot’s The Nun.” In Tendencies,
23–56. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1993.
Serman, Ilya. “The Eighteenth Century: Neoclassicism and the Enlightenment,
1730–90.” In The Cambridge History of Russian Literature, edited by Charles A. Moser,
45–91. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.
Bibliography
297
Shakespeare, William. Measure for Measure. In The Complete Works, edited by G. B.
Harrison. Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt Brace, 1980.
Shakespeare, William. Twelfth Night. In The Complete Works, edited by G. B. Harrison. Fort Worth, TX: Harcourt Brace, 1980.
Shen, Bojun. “Studies of Three Kingdoms in the New Century.” In Three Kingdoms and
Chinese Culture, edited by Kimberly Besio and Constantine Tung, 153–165. Albany:
State University of New York Press, 2007.
Simon, Julien S., “Contextualizing Cognitive Approaches to Early Modern Spanish
Literature.” In Cognitive Approaches to Early Modern Spanish Literature, edited by Isabel
Jaén and Julien J. Simon, 13–33. New York: Oxford University Press, 2016.
Sinnott, Susan, Michelle Jones, Yvette Lapierre, Jodi Evert, Chris Duke (Illustrator), Connie Russell (Illustrator), and Jamie Young (Illustrator). Welcome to Kirsten’s
World, 1854: Growing Up in Pioneer America. American Girl Publishing, 1999.
Skerry, Amy E., and Rebecca Saxe. “Neural Representations of Emotion Are Organized around Abstract Event Features.” Current Biology 25, no. 15 (August 2015):
1945–1954.
Skolnick, Deena, and Paul Bloom. “What Does Batman Think about Sponge Bob?
Children’s Understanding of the Fantasy/Fantasy Distinction.” Cognition 101 (2006):
B9–B18.
Slingerland, Edward. “Cognitive Science and Religious Thought: The Case of Psychological Interiority in the Analects.” In Mental Culture: Towards a Cognitive Science of
Religion, edited by Dimitris Xygalatas and Lee McCorkle, 197–212. London: Acumen,
2013.
Smith, Valery. “The Meaning of Narration in Invisible Man.” In Ralph Ellison’s Invisible Man: A Casebook, edited by John F. Callahan, 189–220. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
Smith, Zadie. On Beauty. New York: Penguin, 2005.
Snodgrass, Sara E. “‘Women’s Intuition’: The Effect of Subordinate Role on Interpersonal Sensitivity.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 49 (1985): 146–155.
Solnit, Rebecca. “Nobody Knows.” Harper’s Magazine, March 2018. https://harpers
.org/archive/2018/03/nobody-knows-3/.
Song of Igor’s Campaign, The. Ca 1200 [Слово о Полку Игореве] Translated by Vladimir Nabokov. New York: Ardis Publishers, 2003.
Sontag, Susan. “Against Interpretation.” In The Critical Tradition: Classic Texts and
Contemporary Trends, edited by David H. Richter, 403–408. Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 2016.
Spark, Muriel. The Girls of Slender Means. New York: New Directions, 1998.
298
Bibliography
Spencer, Jane. “Evelina and Cecilia.” In The Cambridge Companion to Frances Burney,
edited by Peter Sabor, 23–38. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
Sperber, Dan. Rethinking Symbolism. Translated by Alice L. Morton. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975.
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. “The Women’s Texts and a Critique of Imperialism.”
In The Critical Tradition: Classic Texts and Contemporary Trends, edited by David H.
Richter, 1086–1099. Boston: Bedford/St. Martin’s, 2016.
Spolsky, Ellen. The Contracts of Fiction: Cognition, Culture, Community. New York:
Oxford University Press, 2015.
Spolsky, Ellen. Satisfying Skepticism: Embodied Knowledge in the Early Modern World.
Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, 2001.
Stiller, James, and Robin I. M. Dunbar. “Perspective-Taking and Memory Capacity
Predict Social Network Size.” Social Networks 29 (2007): 93–104.
Stiller, James, Daniel Nettle, and Robin I. M. Dunbar. “The Small World of Shakespeare’s Plays.” Human Nature 14 (2003): 397–408.
Straub, Kristina. Divided Fictions: Fanny Burney and Feminine Strategy. Lexington: University Press of Kentucky, 1987.
Tale of Frol Skobeev, The. 1680–1720. [Повесть о Фроле Скобееве] Древнерусская
Литература, при поддержке кафедры русской литературы и фольклора КемГУ
[Ancient Russian Literature: site supported by the Department of Russian Literature
and Folklore of Kemerovo State University (Kemerovo, Russia)], 2002–2003. Accessed
06/11/2021. http://www.drevne.ru/lib/frol.htm.
Tale of Misery-Luckless-Plight, The. 1600–1700. Повесть о Горе и Злочастии]
Древнерусская Литература, при поддержке кафедры русской литературы и
фольклора КемГУ [Ancient Russian Literature: site supported by the Department
of Russian Literature and Folklore of Kemerovo State University (Kemerovo, Russia)],
2002-2003. Accessed 06/11/2021.http://www.drevne.ru/lib/zlos.htm.
Talwar, Victoria, Heidi Gordon, and Kang Lee. “Lying in the Elementary School Years:
Verbal Deception and Its Relation to Second-Order Belief Understanding.” Developmental Psychology 43, no. 3 (2007): 804–810. doi: 10.1037/0012-1649.43.3.804.
Throop, C. Jason. “Suffering, Empathy, and Ethical Modalities of Being in Yap.” In
The Anthropology of Empathy: Experiencing the Lives of Others in the Pacific Societies,
edited by Douglas W. Hollan and C. Jason Throop, 119–149. New York: Berghahn
Books, 2011.
Tillman, Hoyt Cleveland. “Selected Historical Sources for Three Kingdoms.” In Three
Kingdoms and Chinese Culture, edited by Kimberly Besio and Constantine Tung, 53–
69. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2007.
Bibliography
299
Tobar, Héctor. “The Assassin Next Door.” New Yorker, July 29, 2019. https://www
.newyorker.com/magazine/2019/07/29/the-assassin-next-door.
Tolstoy, Lev. Anna Karenina. Translated by Richard Pevear and Larissa Volokhonsky.
New York: Viking, 2000.
Tolstoy, Lev. Война и Мир. 1869. [War and Peace]. Tom 3 [Volume 3] Moscow:
Molodaia Gvardia, 1978.
Tomasello, Michael. Origins of Human Communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
2008.
Travers, P. L. The Mary Poppins Omnibus. London: Lions, 1994.
Trawalter, Sophie, Andrew R. Todd, Abigail A. Baird, and Jennifer A. Richeson.
“Attending to Threat: Race-Based Patterns of Selective Attention.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 44, no. 5 (September 2008): 1322–1327. doi: 10.1016/j.jesp
.2008.03.006.
Tribble, Evelyn B. Cognition in the Globe: Attention and Memory in Shakespeare’s Theatre. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011.
Tribble, Evelyn B., and John Sutton. “Cognitive Ecology as a Framework for Shakespearean Studies.” Shakespeare Studies 39 (2011): 94–103.
Tro, Nivaldo J. Chemistry: Structure and Properties. Boston: Pearson, 2017.
Troscianko, Emily. Kafka’s Cognitive Realism. London: Routledge, 2014.
Turner, Mark. “Compression and Representation.” Language and Literature 15, no.1
(2006): 17–27. doi: 10.1177/0963947006060550.
Twain, Mark. Mississippi Writings: “Tom Sawyer,” “Life on the Mississippi,” “Huckleberry Finn,” “Pudd’nhead Wilson.” New York: Library of America, 1982.
Van Duijn, Max J., Ineke Sluiter, and Arie Verhagen. “When Narrative Takes Over:
The Representation of Embedded Mindstates in Shakespeare’s Othello.” Language and
Literature 24, no. 2 (2015): 148–166.
van Kuijk, Iris, Peter Verkoeijen, Katinka Dijkstra, and Rolf A. Zwaan. “The Effect of
Reading a Short Passage of Literary Fiction on Theory of Mind: A Replication of Kidd
and Castano (2013).” Collabra: Psychology 4, no. 7 (2018). doi: 10.1525/collabra.117.
Vapnyar, Lara. Still Here. New York: Hogarth, 2016.
Vermeule, Blakey. Why Do We Care about Literary Characters? Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010.
Vessel, Edward A., G. Gabrielle Starr, and Nava Rubin. “The Brain on Art: Intense
Aesthetic Experience Activates the Default Mode Network.” Frontiers in Human
Neuroscience 6, no. 66 (2012). Published online April 20, 2012. doi: 10.3389/
fnhum.2012.00066.
300
Bibliography
Vignemont, Frédérique de. “Frames of Reference in Social Cognition.” Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 2007, 1–27.
Vineberg, Steve. “Problem Plays.” Threepenny Review 52 (1993): 32–34.
Vygotsky, Lev S. Psichologia Iskusstva. Moscow: Iskusstvo, 1968.
Vygotsky, Lev S. The Psychology of Art. Translated by Scripta Technica, Inc. Introduction
by A. N. Leontiev. Commentary by V. V. Ivanov. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1974.
Wang, Xiaojue. “Stone in Modern China: Literature, Politics, and Culture.” In
Approaches to Teaching “The Story of the Stone,” edited by Andrew Schonebaum and
Tina Lu, 413–426. New York: Modern Language Association, 2012.
Wang Xizhi. “Preface to the Poems Composed at the Orchid Pavilion.” https://en
.wikisource.org/wiki/Translation:Preface_to_the_Poems_Composed_at_the_Orchid_
Pavilion.
Wang, Yuanfei. “Fantastic Jokes: Allegory, Humor, and Narrative in the Early
Modern Chinese Novel Journey to the West.” Paper presented at the Modern Language Association, New York, January 2018.
Wassmann, Jürg, Birgit Träuble, and Joachim Funke, eds. Theory of Mind in the Pacific:
Reasoning across Cultures. Heidelberg: Universitätsverlag Winter, 2013.
Wei, Shang. “The Literati Era and Its Demise (1723–1840).” In The Cambridge History of Chinese Literature, edited by Kang-o Sun Chang and Stephen Owen, 245–342.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
Wei, Shang. “The Stone Phenomenon and Its Transformation from 1791 to 1919.” In
Approaches to Teaching “The Story of the Stone,” edited by Andrew Schonebaum and
Tina Lu, 390–412. New York: Modern Language Association, 2012.
Whalen, Douglas H., Lisa Zunshine, Evelyne Ender, Jason Tougaw, Robert F. Barsky,
Peter Steiner, Eugenia Kelbert, and Michael Holquist. “Validating Judgments of
Perspective Embedding: Further Explorations of a New Tool for Literary Analysis.”
Scientific Study of Literature 6, no. 2 (2016): 278–298.
Whalen, Douglas H., Lisa Zunshine, and Michael Holquist. “Increases in Perspective
Embedding Increase Reading Time Even with Typical Text Presentation: Implications for the Reading of Literature.” Frontiers in Psychology, November 2015. doi:
10.3389/fpsyg.2015.01778.
Whalen, Douglas H., Lisa Zunshine, and Michael Holquist. “Theory of Mind and
Embedding of Perspective: A Psychological Test of a Literary ‘Sweet Spot.’” Scientific
Study of Literature 22, no. 2 (2012): 301–315.
Wharton, Edith. “Xingu.” In “Roman Fever” and Other Stories, ed. Cynthia Griffin
Wolff, 23–58. New York: Scribner, 1997.
Bibliography
301
White, E. B. Charlotte’s Web. New York: HarperCollins, 1952.
White, E. B. Stuart Little. New York: Harper and Row, 1945.
Wice, Matthew, Minoru Karasawa, Tomoko Matsui, and Joan G. Miller, “Knowing
Minds: Culture and Perceptions of Mental State Access.” Asian Journal of Social Psychology 31 March 2020. https://doi.org/10.1111/ajsp.12404.
Wiesehan, Gretchen. “Christa Wolf Reconsidered: National Stereotypes in ‘Kindheitsmuster.’” Germanic Review 68, no. 2 (Spring 1993): 79–87.
Wilder, Laura Ingalls. Little House in the Big Woods. New York: Scholastic, 1963.
Wilder, Laura Ingalls. Little House on the Prairie. New York: Scholastic, 1963.
Wilder, Laura Ingalls. Little Town on the Prairie. New York: Scholastic, 1941.
Wilder, Laura Ingalls. These Happy Golden Years. New York: Scholastic, 1943.
Williams, Joy. Ninety-Nine Stories of God. New York: Tin House Books, 2016.
Wolf, Christa. City of Angels; or, The Overcoat of Dr. Freud. Translated from German by
Damion Searls. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2013. Published in German in
2010.
Wolf, Christa. Kindheitsmuster. Berlin: Aufbau-Verlag, 1976.
Wolf, Christa. Patterns of Childhood. Translated by Ursule Molinaro and Hedwig Rappolt. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1980.
Wolf, Christa. They Divided the Sky. Translated by Luise von Flotow. Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press, 2013.
Wood, James. The Fun Stuff: And Other Essays. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux,
2012.
Wood, James. “Reality Testing: A First Novel about Poetry and Imposture in Spain.”
New Yorker, October 24, 2011. https://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2011/10/31
/reality-testing.
Wordsworth, William. “Lines Composed a Few Miles above Tintern Abbey, on Revisiting the Banks of the Wye during a Tour, July 13, 1798.” The Norton Anthology of
English Literature, Eighth Edition: The Major Authors, edited by Stephen Greenblatt and
M. H. Abrams, 1491–1495. New York and London: Norton, 1990.
Wu Ching-Tzu. The Scholars. Beijing: Foreign Languages Press, 2000.
Wulandini, Gouvara, I. A. Kuntoro, and E. Handayani. “The Effect of Literary Fiction
on School-Aged Children’s Theory of Mind (ToM).” In Diversity in Unity: Perspectives
from Psychology and Behavioral Sciences, edited by Amarina Ashar Ariyanto, Hamdi
Muluk, Peter Newcombe, Fred P. Piercy, Elizabeth Kristi Poerwandari, and Sri Hartati
R. Suradijono, 159–166. London: Taylor and Francis, 2018.
302
Bibliography
Yeazell, Ruth Bernard. Fictions of Modesty: Women and Courtship in the English Novel.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991.
Yu, Pauline. “The Story of Yingying.” In Ways with Words: Writing about Reading
Texts from Early China, edited by Pauline Yu, Peter Bol, Stephen Owen, and Willard
Peterson, 182–185. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2000.
Zamiatin, Evgenij. Мы [We]. Moscow: АСТ, 2008.
Zenkovsky, Serge A., ed. and trans. “Misery-Luckless-Plight.” In Medieval Russia’s
Epics, Chronicles, and Tales, 489–501. New York: Dutton, 1974.
Zhilicheva, G. A. “Функции «Ненадежного» Нарратора в Русском Романе 1920–
1930-х Годов” [Functions of “unreliable narrator” in the Russian novel of the
1920s–1930s]. Вестник ТГПУ [TSPU bulletin] 11, no. 139 (2013): 32–38.
Zunshine, Lisa. “Bakhtin, Theory of Mind, and Pedagogy: Cognitive Construction of
Social Class.” Eighteenth-Century Fiction 30, no. 1 (2017): 109–126.
Zunshine, Lisa. “The Commotion of Souls.” SubStance #140, 45, no. 2 (2016): 118–142.
Zunshine, Lisa. “Embodied Social Cognition and Comparative Literature: an Introduction.” Poetics Today 41, no. 2 (2020): 171–186.
Zunshine, Lisa. “From the Social to the Literary: Approaching Cao Xueqin’s The Story
of the Stone (Honglou meng) from a Cognitive Perspective.” In The Oxford Handbook
of Cognitive Literary Studies, edited by Lisa Zunshine, 176–196. New York: Oxford
University Press, 2015.
Zunshine, Lisa. Getting Inside Your Head: What Cognitive Science Can Tell Us about
Popular Culture. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2012.
Zunshine, Lisa. “I Lie Therefore I Am.” In Approaches to Teaching “The Plum in the
Golden Vase,” edited by Andrew Schonebaum. New York: MLA, forthcoming.
Zunshine, Lisa. “Introduction to Cognitive Literary Studies.” In The Oxford Handbook
of Cognitive Literary Studies, edited by Lisa Zunshine, 1–9. New York: Oxford University Press, 2015.
Zunshine, Lisa. “May 2020 Bibliography for Cognitive Literary Studies.” May 2020.
https://mla.hcommons.org/deposits/item/hc:30131/.
Zunshine, Lisa. “The Secret Life of Fiction.” PMLA 130, no. 3 (2015): 724–731.
Zunshine, Lisa. Strange Concepts and the Stories They Make Possible: Cognition, Culture,
Narrative. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 2008.
Zunshine, Lisa. “Style Brings in Mental States: A Response to Alan Palmer’s ‘Social
Minds.’” Style 45, no. 2 (2011): 349–356.
Bibliography
303
Zunshine, Lisa. “‘Think What You’re Doing, or You’ll Only Make an Ugly Reputation for Yourself’: Chin P’ing Mei (金瓶梅), Lying, and Literary History,” in 认知诗学
[Cognitive poetics] (December 2017): 44–62.
Zunshine, Lisa. “Who Is He to Speak of My Sorrow?” Poetics Today 41, no. 2 (2020):
223–241.
Zunshine, Lisa. “Why Jane Austen Was Different, and Why We May Need Cognitive
Science to See It.” Style 41, no. 3 (2007): 287–290.
Zunshine, Lisa. Why We Read Fiction: Theory of Mind and the Novel. Columbus: Ohio
State University Press, 2006.
Zwaan, Rolf A. “Effect of Genre Expectations on Text Comprehension.” Journal of
Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 20, no. 4 (1994): 920–933.
Index
Abbott, Porter, xii, 123–124, 128–129,
228n68, 230n91, 237n9, 253n56,
259n36
Aeschylus, 141–142
Aesthetics, 65, 90, 91, 93, 221, 243n86,
243n88, 251n19
Affect, 60, 187–188, 207, 212. See also
Emotions
Ahrens, Kathleen, 270n78
Akhapkin, Denis, xii, 258n27
Aldama, Frederick Luis, xii
Alemán, Mateo
Guzmán de Alfarache, 72, 187–188
Al Harthi, Jokha
Celestial Bodies, 9, 121
Allakhverdov, Victor M., 238n20
Anna Karenina (Tolstoy), 10–11, 145, 162
Apperly, Ian, 223n3, 248n27, 249n32
Apuleius, 36, 141, 142
The Golden Ass, 17–18
Aristotle, 132, 133
Astington, Janet Wilde, 194–197, 198,
216, 266n14
Astuti, Rita, 101, 114
Attributional complexity, 56, 229n83,
235n157, 236n159
Augustine
The City of God, 4
Austen, Jane, 205
Emma, 15, 65, 111, 133
Mansfield Park, 67–70, 76, 78
Persuasion, 133, 157
Pride and Prejudice, 11, 230n95
Austin, Mike, xii, 257n23
Autism, 124
Auyoung, Elaine, xii, 42, 224n10, 230n95,
230n99, 231n104, 238n17 250n49
Baggs, Ed, 247n18
Bai Juyi, 165
Baillargeon, Renée, 106
Bakhtin, Mikhail, x, 78, 80, 81
Baldwin, Dare, 102, 251n19
Ballaster, Ros, 134
Barnes, Jennifer L., 271n2
Barrett, Lisa Feldman, 246n10
Barrie, J. M.
Peter Pan, 269n55
Baum, Andrew, 237n8
Beckett, Sandra, 202
Berlina, Alexandra, xii, 270n74
Black, Jessica, 271n2
Blackman, Lucy, 124
Blair, Rhonda, xii
Bloom, Paul, 248n28
Bolens, Guillemette, xii, 236n169
Book of Documents, The, 175
Book of Exeter, The, 12
Booth, Wayne, 133
Bosavi, 114–115, 119–122, 125,
130–131, 135, 147. See also Kaluli
Boyer, Pascal, 101, 110, 259n35
306
Brandenberger, David, 244n92
Breithaupt, Fritz, xii, 109, 237n11,
238n26, 260n47
Brontë, Emily
Wuthering Heights, 157, 237n9, 259n43
Brown, Dan
Da Vinci Code, 56, 57
Bruner, Jerome S., 254n81
Buckner, Randy L., 247n19
Burnett, Frances Hodgson
The Secret Garden, 199–200, 202
Burney, Frances
Evelina, 78–84, 85, 93, 205, 240n48,
241n62, 241n65, 241n68
Butte, George, xii, 269n55
Caldwell-Harris, Catherine, 119
Cao Pi
“Scholar T’an,” 163–164
Cao Xueqin, 11, 36, 57, 142, 157, 205
Dream of the Red Chamber (The Story of
the Stone), 47, 55–56, 70–71, 78, 157,
167, 177, 179–183, 202
Caracciolo, Marco, 246n17
Carney, James, 224n19
Carroll, Lewis
Alice in Wonderland, 199, 201, 202, 204
Through the Looking-Glass, 220
Carruthers, Peter, 249n32
Castano, Emanuele, xii, 19–20, 56,
198, 229n83, 235n157, 235n159,
236n160
Cave, Terence, xii, 267n20
Cervantes, Miguel de
Don Quixote, 149
Rinconete y Cortadillo, 187
Chang Chu-p’o, 169, 170
Charon, Rita, xii, 137, 138
Chekhov, Anton, 162
“Rothschild’s Fiddle,” 15
Chesnutt, Charles
“Dave’s Neckliss,” 240n47
Cicero, 122
Index
Clarissa (Richardson), 125
Clark, Beverly Lyon, 205, 207
Claudius, Eduard
People at Our Side (Menschen an unserer
Seite), 92, 95–96
Close reading, 20, 57–58, 130, 218,
227n64, 236n168
Cognitive approaches to literature, 7,
92, 97, 147, 160, 170, 172, 176, 181,
186, 204, 218. See also Cognitive
literary criticism
Cognitive historicism, 87, 97, 237n4,
242n80, 250n50, 257n20
Cognitive literary criticism, ix, 157, 168,
206, 209
and heteroglossia, 80
and history, 39, 58, 66, 86, 87, 97, 89,
97, 109, 139, 145, 204–211, 216,
218, 229n82
Colonialism, 123–124, 237n9
Cook, Amy, xii, 230n99
Cosmides, Leda, 183, 265n126. See also
Tooby, John
Crane, Mary, xii, 237n4, 242n80,
245n112, 250n50
Culler, Jonathan, 58
“Curious George” (Margret and H. A.
Rey), 214
Curious George at the Zoo: A Touch and
Feel Book (H. A. Rey), 214, 215
Currie, Gregory, 224n13, 230n95
Cusk, Rachel
Saving Agnes, 73
Transit, 9
Damasio, Antonio, 111
Dangarembga, Tsitsi
Nervous Conditions, 9
Deception, xi
and ancient Greek and Roman poetics,
257n21
and genre, 195
and theory of mind, 183–184
Index
as a recurrent plot device, xi, 148–154,
158–159
in ancient Chinese literature, 164
in Dream of the Red Chamber, 167, 179,
182
in Eugene Onegin, 143, 187
in Gilgamesh, 13, 184
in Guzmán de Alfarache, 187–188
in Huckleberry Finn, 207
in The Idiot, 161–162
in Leaving the Atocha Station, 189–191
in Listen to Me, 16
in the medieval Russian literature,
150–152, 161
in Poor Liza, 154
in The Plum in the Golden Vase, 167,
169–174
in Romance of the Three Kingdoms,
167–168, 261n76
in Sonnet 138 (“When My Love
Swears”), 185–187
in Tales of Belkin, 159
in Tom Sawyer, 197
DEFA, 90
Default network, 104
Defoe, Daniel, 191
Moll Flanders, 72
Robinson Crusoe, 47, 48–49, 50, 153,
190, 234n140
De Jaegher, Hanne, 26, 29, 230n92,
231n104
Developmental psychology, 57, 102,
106–107, 109, 193–195, 198, 211,
213, 214, 215, 216, 218, 248n32
Dialogism, 81, 243n90
Dick, Philip K., Do Androids Dream of
Electric Sheep? 9–10
Didion, Joan, 4
Dilley, Paul, 125–126, 250n50
Di Paolo, Ezequiel, 26, 29, 230n92,
231n104
Dissanayake, Ellen, 251n19, 253n68
Distributed temporality, 49
307
Djikic, Maja, 249n41
Dobychin, Leonid
The Town of N, 89–90
Dodell-Feder, David, 227n63
Donaldson, Julia
Gruffalo, 72, 212, 270n73, 270n74
Doody, Margaret, 84
Dostoevsky, Fedor, 36, 142, 158, 160–
161, 162, 191
The Brothers Karamazov, 161
The Idiot, 161
Dramatic irony, 13, 16, 28, 178, 211
Drucker, Johanna, 246n12
Du Fu
“Deck by the Water,” 165–166
Dunbar, Robin, 36, 42–43, 105, 224n19,
234n145, 248n25, 268n49
Duranti, Alessandro, 101, 132, 246n8
Dyer, Jennifer R., 194, 198, 213
Easterlin, Nancy, xii, 111, 243n88, 245n2
Eavesdropping, xi, 154, 157, 169,
259n43
Egan, Jennifer
A Visit from the Goon Squad, 65
Ehrenburg, Ilya
Julio Jurenito, 89
Eisenstein, Sergei, 90
Elfenbein, Andrew, 20–22, 33, 224n12,
224n15, 228n68, 228n79, 229n82,
230n99, 231n105, 231n108, 242n72,
246n11, 249n42
Eliot, George
Middlemarch, 50–51, 234n143,
234n149
Ellison, Ralph, 74, 92
Invisible Man, 75–78, 93, 239n42
Embedded mental states, 2. See also
Secret life of literature
cultural institutions supporting, x, xi,
9, 58, 99, 125, 132, 135, 136, 141,
221, 222
distal and proximate causes of, 109–112
308
Embedded mental states (cont.)
downgrading levels of, 51–54
empirical studies of, 19–20, 23–26, 31,
32–33
explicitly spelled out, 5, 8–13, 17,
34–35, 38, 41–42, 46, 47
implied, 5, 13–19, 20, 22, 26, 33, 35,
38, 39, 41–42, 44, 47, 54–56, 57,
74, 95, 96, 104, 110–216, 133, 171,
175–176, 215
maps of, 3, 15, 18, 20–21, 27, 31,
35–39, 41, 55, 73, 76, 80, 81, 92, 95,
99–100, 104, 148–149, 156, 164–165,
188, 218
upper limits of, 105–106
ways of counting, 2, 29, 54, 228n81,
234n145
writers’ awareness of, 39–43
and acquisition of vocabulary, 195,
198, 215
and affect, 187–188, 212
and anthropology, 99, 101, 110
and attention, 21, 22, 111, 134, 137,
154, 165–166, 184–185, 186, 195,
230n95, 246n10
and “better” mindreading, 78
and cheater detection, 183–187
and close reading, 20, 57–58, 218
and cultural history of visualization,
102
and cultural shortcuts for describing,
13, 15, 28, 49
and cognitive neuroscience, 56, 99,
107–108
and the contested definition of
“fiction,” 163
and default network, 104
and developmental psychology,
56–57, 102–103, 106–107, 183, 211,
213, 214, 216
and difference between real life and
literature, 3–4, 42–43, 78, 83–84, 85,
86, 109, 145, 160–161, 207
Index
and dramatic irony, 13, 16, 22, 28,
178, 211
and evolutionary psychology, 110,
183–184
and embodiment, 3, 14, 36, 100, 101,
104, 167, 246n14
and ethics, 206–208
and ethnography, 99, 194
and expansion of literary contexts
for, 153, 155, 157, 160–162, 163,
166–167, 169, 177, 189, 191,
202
and false beliefs, 102, 106, 193, 194,
211, 213, 216, 218, 220, 248n32,
266n1, 267n14
and form, 186–187. See also Style
and free indirect discourse, 27–28
and gender, 8, 70–71, 177
and ideology, 78, 85, 93, 95, 97
and indigenous performance genres,
19, 130–132
and individual reading differences, 25,
29, 30–32, 183
and in-group cooperation, 110
and intermedial storytelling, 168–169,
269n68
and irony, 4, 155
and literary criticism, 198, 222,
225n36, 256n6
and literary subjectivity, 89, 91, 93,
96, 97, 107, 157, 211, 220–222,
249n42
and moving images, 210, 221, 222,
269n68
and the novel, 92, 145–148, 155,
168–169, 176, 208–211
and parody, 202
and political subversion, 89, 96
and practices of literary interpretation,
20, 21, 23, 25, 27, 28, 130, 135, 139,
165, 166, 181, 183, 228n68
and psychological realism, 142, 143,
144
Index
and race, 8, 74–78
and realism, 141–145, 243n88, 255n1
and representational (aka propositional) language, 3, 36, 38, 68,
101–104, 105, 108
and rereading, 10, 204
and rhetoric, 80, 206, 241n65
and “rise of the novel,” 146–147,
257n16
and self-reflection, 104–105, 189–190
and “situational irony,” 194, 198, 199
and social class, 8, 81–82, 84, 85,
87–89, 177
and social psychology, 56
and socialist realism, 43, 87–97
and style, 24–25, 38, 39, 141
and theater, 14, 141, 167
and unreliable narration, 90, 91, 155–
157, 203–204
as counted by a computer program,
54–57
as dialogic, 81
as a metaphor, 2, 100, 102, 104
as signaling complex consciousness in
literature, 74–75
in Bornean folktales, 213
in children’s literature, 193–218
in crossovers, 216–218
in crowd scenes, 49–51
in detective fiction, 71, 87–89, 185
in epic, 92, 96, 141, 146, 220
in expository non-fiction, 4, 210
in folklore, 92, 212, 213, 218
in historical fiction, 163, 168
in Huckleberry Finn, 205–207
in Little House in the Big Woods,
208–211
in memoirs/autobiographies, 49, 146,
219
in mid-Tang poetry, 166
in myth, 92
in narratives featuring solitary protagonists, 48–49
309
in Native American legends, 212–213
in ninth-century Chinese tales of
romance, 164–165, 166, 167
in picaresque novels, 72, 76, 187–189
in popular fiction as opposed to
literary fiction, 7, 54–57, 104, 185,
203, 204, 221
in “production novels,” 93–96
in Russian fairy tales, 213
in science fiction, 7, 9, 20
in Scholars, 179
in stories for one- to two-year-olds,
213–216
in stories for nine- to twelve-year-olds,
199–202
in stories for three- to seven-year-olds,
211–213, 221
in Tom Sawyer, 204–208, 211
in West African folklore, 212
in visual representations, 6, 216–218
in Young Adult fiction, 203–204
Embodiment, 36, 74, 100, 101, 104,
167, 231n101, 231n102, 246n8
Emin, Fedor
Letters of Ernest and Doravra, 153
Emmerich, Wolfgang, 243n82, 243n84,
244n95
Emotions, 101, 124, 154, 159, 162, 163,
174, 181, 185–186, 189, 209, 211,
246n10, 266n14
self-monitoring of, 17
and complex mental states, 40, 85,
107, 108, 153, 174, 185–186, 190,
206, 247n17
and mind-misreading, 60–61
and socialist realism, 93–95
as manipulable by others, 85–86
in science fiction, 9–10
Empathy, 109, 116
Emperor Huizong of Song, 169
Enactivism, 31–32, 230n92, 231n101,
246n14, 246n17, 256n7
Epic, 91–92, 220
310
Epic of Gilgamesh, The, 7, 8, 12–13, 18–19,
22, 92, 141, 148, 184, 220, 221
Epstein, Julia, 240n48, 241n67
Ermolay-Erazm
The Tale of Peter and Fevroniya,
150–151
Etherege, George
The Man of Mode, 15, 85
Ethics, 206–207
and mindreading, 19, 86, 132, 138,
139, 141
and the opacity model, 120–121
as independent from complex
embedment, 65
Evelina (Burney), 78–84, 85, 93, 205,
240n48, 241n62, 241n65, 241n68
Feld, Steven, 115, 228n72, 251n9,
251n22, 257n19
Fellman, Anita Clair, 269n61, 269n69
Fernyhough, Charles, 223n2
Ferrante, Elena
The Story of the Lost Child, 8
Fielding, Henry, 80, 144, 153
Tom Jones, 149
Fitch, W. Tecumseh, 226n56
Fitzgerald, Penelope, 36
Fiuza, Felipe de Oliveira, xii
Flesch, William, xii, 264n125
Fletcher, Garth J. O., 229n83, 235n158,
237n12
Fludernik, Monika, xii, 234n149, 253n56
Fontane, Theodor, 96
Forster, E. M., 238n17
Howards End, 10, 15, 16–17, 26–31, 33,
37, 57, 202, 205, 238n18
Frazee, Marla
Hush, Little Baby, 216–218, 271n91,
271n92, 271n93
Free indirect discourse, 27–28, 229n88
Freeman, Judy, 199, 218
Frith, Christopher, 248n22
Furlanetto, Tiziano, 14
Index
Garratt, Peter, 231n101
Gavaler, Chris, 224n19, 254n78,
236n163
Gaylin, Ann, 259n43
Gillespie, John, 199, 218
Ginzburg, Lidiya, 160
Gisalo, 131, 147
Gladkov, Fedor
Cement, 92, 93, 96, 221
Gogol, Nicolai, 155, 157
“The Overcoat,” 156
Goldstein, Thalia R., xii
Günther, Hans, 91, 92, 243n89, 243n90
Hake, Sabina, 90–91
Han Yu
“Pond in Basin,” 165–166
Harding, Jennifer Riddle, 240n47
Harris, Paul L., xii, 195, 216, 266n14
Hawkes, David, 55, 262n87
Haywood, Eliza
Fantomina, 134, 202
Hegel, Robert E., 260n59
Heliodorus, 36, 141, 142, 143, 144
An Ethiopian Romance (Aithiopika),
52–53, 145, 149
Henry, Nancy, 51
Herman, David, xii, 49, 249n43
Heteroglossia, 80, 82, 243n90
Hickok, Gregory, 124, 246n8, 248n20
Highsmith, Patricia, 37, 57
The Price of Salt, 37–39, 232n121
Hirschfeld, Lawrence A., 236n3
Hodne, Lasse, 252n34
Hoekstra, Hopi, 138
Hogan, Patrick Colm, xii, 25, 44, 60,
233n131, 242n79, 268n49
Holquist, Michael, xii, 23
Homer, 141, 142, 143
The Iliad, 149
The Odyssey, 12, 92
Howard, Michael
The First World War, 136–137
Index
Howells, William Dean, 205
Hutchins, Pat
Rosie’s Walk, 195–196, 212, 215,
270n84, 270n85
Ideologies of mind, 99, 100, 113–114,
121, 122, 124, 222
Ideology of transparency, 89, 96, 122,
123, 124, 125, 126, 136, 138,
221–22, 243n90
and academic learning, 126
and autism, 124
and colonialism, 123–124
and critical thinking, 135
and liberal democracy, 136
and “monastic theory of mind,”
126
and teaching of literature, 127–130
Implied mental states, 4–5, 15–19
and behavioral neuroscience, 110
and elements of style, 24–25
and dramatic irony, 13
and experienced readers, 20–22
and literary criticism, 133
and popular fiction as compared to literary fiction, 54–57, 104
and stage, 14, 167
in the absence of references to mental
states, 44–46, 127, 129
in “Bartleby the Scrivener,” 128–129
in Blood Meridian, 45–47, 96
in Dream of the Red Chamber, 55–56
in Evelina, 80–81
in Eugene Onegin, 142–143, 175,
177
in Guzmán de Alfarache, 187–188
in Howards End, 26–30
in Huckleberry Finn, 206–207
in Hush, Little Baby, 216–218
in Invisible Man, 76–77
in The Girls of Slender Means, 34–35
in Mansfield Park, 68–70
in The Price of Salt, 37–39
311
in The Plum in the Golden Vase,
133–134, 171, 175–176, 177
in The Scholars, 178–179
in We, 44–45, 95, 96
in “Ying-ying’s Story,” 164–165, 167
Intentionality, 5, 20, 21, 22, 36, 39, 42,
43, 64, 83, 95, 97, 102, 104, 105,
107, 128, 132, 135, 137, 138, 146,
176, 186, 198, 202, 205, 219, 220,
221, 222, 226n56
as used interchangeably with “mental
state,” 5, 226n56
Intermedial narratives, 168–169,
269n68
Intermental unit, 50, 234n145
Intersubjectivity, 3, 10, 103, 224n13
Invisible Man (Ellison), 74, 75–78, 93,
239n42
Ionescu, Andrei, 224n13
Irony, 4, 13, 19, 34, 144, 146, 194, 198,
199
Irving, John
The 158-Pound Marriage, 54–55, 56, 57
Ivanov, Vsevolod
U, 89
Jackson, Shirley
“The Beautiful Stranger,” 10, 33
Jackson, Tony, xii
Jaén-Portillo, Isabel, xii
James, Henry, 36, 74–75, 93, 142
James, William, 110–111
Jansson, Tove
Moomin Falls in Love, 199, 200–201
Jia Dao, 165
Johnson, Dan, 224n19, 254n78,
236n163
Johnson, Isabelle, 232n122, 233n135
Johnson, Mark, 103
Kafka, Franz
“Jackals and Arabs,” 129
Kaluli, 114, 116–118, 120, 131, 251n18
312
Kamawar, Deepthi, 197
Kanske, Philipp, 106
Kanwisher, Nancy, 107
Karamzin, Nikolai, M.
“Bednaya Liza,” 153–154
Kaverin, Veniamin
Two Captains, 88
The Open Book, 88
Keane, Webb, 99, 121, 130, 136, 147
Keen, Suzanne, xii, 109, 245n112,
270n75
Kidd, David Comer, xii, 19–20, 56, 198,
229n83
King, Martin Luther, Jr.
“I Have a Dream,” 4
Kinney, Jeff
Diary of a Wimpy Kid, 199, 200
Klassen, Jon
This Is Not My Hat, 212
Knoepflmacher, Ulrich C., 202
Koike, Motoko, 252n34
Kokin rokujo 3057, 53
Kompa, Nikola A., 231n102
Kosofsky Sedgwick, Eve, 69, 77, 237n10
Kramnick, Jonathan, 265n127
Kukkonen, Karin, xii, 231n101, 246n10,
246n17, 255n1, 265n127
Kümmerling-Meibauer, Bettina, 269n70,
270n79, 270n84
Kuritzyn, Fedor
The Tale of Dracula, 150
Ku Waru, 114, 131–132
Kuzmičová, Anezka, 30
Landy, Joshua, xii, 249n41
Lantos, John D., 234n140
Lazarillo de Tormes, 187
Lee, Haiyan, xii, 70–71, 88–89, 96, 158,
172, 245n108, 251n23, 262n77
Lee, Harper
To Kill a Mockingbird, 23, 24
Leeder, Karin, 243n86
Leff, Gordon, 253n53
Index
Lepowsky, Maria, 251n13
Lermontov, Mikhail, 155
A Hero of Our Time, 157
Lerner, Ben
Leaving the Atocha Station, 9, 189–191
Lesage, René, 153
Levinas, Emmanuel, 160
Lincoln, Abraham
“The Gettysburg Address,” 4
Lipson, Eden Ross, 199, 218
Literary subjectivity, 89, 91, 93, 96, 97,
107, 157, 211, 220–222
Literati culture, 163, 165, 169, 177,
264n121
Lockington, Mariama J.
For Black Girls like Me, 203–204
Lu, Tina, 171
Luhrmann, Tanya Marie, 113, 248n29
Luo Guanzhong
The Romance of the Three Kingdoms, 71,
167–168, 261n76, 262n77
“Lust of the mind” (in Dream of the Red
Chamber), 181–182
Lu Xun, 142, 144
“A Madman’s Diary,” 16
Lying. See also Deception
role of, in shaping the secret life of
literature, xi, 12, 148–149, 150–153,
157–158, 161–163, 164, 167–169,
172, 177, 183–186, 187, 189, 191
and cheater detection, 183–187
and sexual deception, 184, 185, 186,
265n126
and theory of mind, 148, 172, 183, 213
in trickster stories, 213
Machiavelli, Niccolò
The Prince, 4
Mäkelä, Maria, 229n88
Mann, Thomas, 96, 142
Mansing, Howard, xii
Mar, Raymond, 224n9, 229n82, 249n41
Marivaux, Pierre, 153
Index
Martens, Lorna, 244n101
Martins, Mauricio D., 226n56
Martinsen, Deborah A., 160, 161
Mary Poppins (P. L. Travers), 199, 201, 202
Mayakovski, Vladimir, 90
McCarthy, Cormac
Blood Meridian, 45–47, 57, 96, 221
McConachie, Bruce, xii
McHale, Brian, xii, 256n8
Melville, Herman
“Bartleby the Scrivener,” 128–129
Mercier, Hugo, 103, 249n32
Mersereau, John Jr., 159
Meyer, Stephenie
Twilight Saga, 56, 57
Miall, David S., 245n1
Miller, Nick, 270n73
Miller, Patricia, 107, 143
Miller, Sara
Pooh’s Honey Trouble, 214–215
Miller, William Ian, 61–62
Milligan, Karen, 248n27, 270n77
Milne, A.A.
Winnie the Pooh, 199, 200, 214
Mindreading, ix, 22, 23. See also Theory
of mind
culture-specific models of, 113, 114,
121, 124, 125, 147, 251n14
and academic disciplines, 126, 127,
128, 132, 135, 136–139
and heteroglossia, x, 80, 82
and intersectionality, 65
and language, x, 137, 95, 195, 197,
213, 215, 216, 231n102, 256n10,
248n27, 267n14
and literary scholarship, 123–135
and metacognitive language, 195–198
and mind misreading, 59–61, 75, 182
and narrative medicine, 138
and oppression/discrimination, 63–65,
87–97
and participatory sense-making,
290–30, 231n104
313
and power, 63–64, 69, 77, 78, 86
and race, x, 64–65, 74–78
and sadistic benefaction, 86, 87
and social status, x, 7–8, 61–65, 66–67,
72–73, 77, 78, 81–82, 84, 86, 87–89,
97, 145
and totalitarian regimes, x, 78, 87–97
and translation, 58
as embodied, 3, 36, 101, 104, 167,
231n101, 246n8
as multimodal, 101
as ontologically unstable, 138–139
as opposite of telepathy, 75
in liberal democracies, 62
in literature courses, 127–130
Mindreading ideology, x, xi. See also
Ideologies of mind
Mirror neurons, 84
Modernism, 45, 90–91, 243n89,
244n95, 253n56, 256n8
“Monastic theory of mind,” 125–126
Montaigne, de, Michel, 4
Moors, Agnes, 21
Morris, Marcia A., 239n32, 243n86
Moshfegh, Ottessa, 232n110
Muira, Kayo, 252n34
Murasaki Shikibu, 36, 142, 205
The Tale of Genji, 53–54, 257n16
Musil, Robert, 96
Myers, Mitzi, 202
Nabokov, Vladimir
Commentary on Eugene Onegin,
176–177
Lolita, 47
Speak, Memory, 49
Lectures on Russian Literature, 156
“Translator’s Foreword,” 157
Nadel, Alan, 239n42
Naigles, Letitia, 197
Nersessian, Anahid, 265n127
Nettle, Daniel, 110, 248n25
Nicklas, Pascal, xii
314
Nicolopoulou, Ageliki, 197
Nielsen, Henrik Skov, 224n13
Nikolajeva, Maria, 268n32
Niu Seng-ju
“Scholar Ts’ui,” 164
Nizami, 142, 143
The Story of Layla and Majnun, 11–12, 15
Noel, Anne-Sophie, 226n44
Nussbaum, Martha, 254n81
Oatley, Keith, xii, 249n41
Ochs, Elinor, 63, 116, 120, 135
Oforlea, Aaron Ngozi, xii, 119
Olesha, Yuri
Envy, 89
Olney, James, 256n12
Onishi, Kristine, 106
Opacity of mind model, 113–114, 125,
136, 138, 248n29, 266n1
public performance of, versus private
mindreading, 115, 116, 138
and conversations about performance,
132
and different cultural
models of parenting, 116–117, 118,
122, 123
and ethics, 120–121
and eye contact, 114, 115, 121–125
and interpreting toddlers’ babbling,
114, 116, 117
and interpreting other people’s mental
states, 114–115, 117, 121, 254n83
and literary production, 130–131, 147
as compared to the “transparency of
mind” model, 122–123, 125, 136, 222
as not an all-or-nothing phenomenon,
116, 118–120, 222
Ostrovski, Nicholai
How the Steel Was Tempered, 92
O’Sullivan, Emer, 267n32, 269n68,
270n86, 271n87
Otis, Laura, xii
Owen, Stephen, 165, 166
Index
Palmer, Alan, xii, 50, 232n120,
234n143, 234n145, 250n48
Panero, Maria Eugenia, 227n63
Pascal, Roy, 229n88
Peskin, Joan, 194–197, 198, 216,
266n14
Petrone, Karen, 256n2, 264n112
Petronius, Arbiter, 141
Satyricon, 12
Phelan, James, xii, 206–207, 224n13
Phillips, Natalie, xii, 20, 25, 227n64,
231n106, 238n17, 245n112
Picaresque, 72, 76, 78, 150, 158,
187–189, 189, 239n33, 239n42
Pittard, Hannah
Listen to Me, 16
Plaks, Andrew, 134, 145, 146, 257n16
Plantinga, Carl, xii
Pleistocene, 109, 111–112
Plum in the Golden Vase, The, 71,
133–134, 167–177, 182, 254n78,
262n86, 262n87
Plutarch
Lives of the Noble Greeks and Romans,
149
Polvinen, Merja, xii, 231n101, 246n17
Popova, Yanna, 224n13, 231n101
Postmodernism, 45, 190, 243n89
Premack, David G., 249n34
Prevost, Antoine
Adventures of Marquis G., Or, The Life
of a Nobleman Who Abandoned the
World, 153
English Philosopher, 153
Pride and Prejudice (Austen), 11, 230n95
Proust, Marcel, 45, 142
Remembrance of Things Past, 46, 47
Pushkin, Alexander, 36, 91, 92,
205
Eugene Onegin, 142–144, 148,
157–158, 174, 176, 187, 256n2,
260n46, 263n112
The Tales of Belkin, 155, 157, 158–159
Index
Rabinowitz, Peter, xii, 206–207, 224n13
Realism, 90–91, 101, 141–145, 160,
243n88, 255n1, 256n2, 256n5,
256n8
Restoration plays, 85, 158
Richardson, Alan, xii, 216, 245n112,
245n1
Richardson, Samuel
Clarissa, 125
History of Sir Charles Grandison, The,
175
Richner, Elizabeth, 197
Richter, David, xii, 128, 129
Riftin, Boris, 261n61
Riva, Federica, 265n137
Robbe-Grillet, Alain
Jealousy, 44, 95, 127–128, 129, 221
Robbins, Joel, 250n4, 254n83
Robinson Crusoe (Defoe), 47, 48–49, 50,
153, 190, 234n140
Rolston, David, 198
Rooney, Sally
Conversations with Friends, 8
Rosenman, Ellen Bayuk, 242n73
Roy, David Todd, 175, 262n87
Ruden, Sarah, 18
Rumsey, Alan, 250n4, 254n83
Sabbagh, Mark A., 102, 251n19
Sadistic benefaction, 86
Saggini, Francesca, 241n63
Santos, Henri Carlo, 237n6, 242n70
Sarratt, Taylor, 232n124
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 160
Saussy, Haun, 149
Savarese, Ralph James, xii, 10, 109,
225n28, 236n162
Saxe, Rebecca, 107, 248n32
Scarry, Elaine, 225n36, 230n95
Schieffelin, Bambi, xii, 113, 116–118,
120, 121, 126, 255n83
Schieffelin, Edward, 131
Schiller, von, J. C. Friedrich, 186, 265n127
315
Schneider, Ralf, 232n117
Schoenberger, Casey, xii
Schonebaum, Andrew, 262n86,
264n121
Science fiction, 7, 9, 20, 56, 236n162,
254n78
Secret life of literature, the, 4, 35
cognitive-evolutionary history of, 99,
100, 109, 110, 112, 141, 183, 185
cultural history of, 99, 100, 112, 141,
154
empirical testing of, xii, 19, 23–26, 31,
32–33, 67
future of, xi, 219–222
literary history of, 92, 99, 100, 112,
141, 148–155, 158, 162
and determinism, 146–147
and eavesdropping, xi, 154, 157, 169,
259n43
and enactivist approach to literature,
32, 231n101, 246n17
and “face,” 172–174, 177, 178, 179,
180, 182
and hypocrisy, 49, 158, 162
and intratextual references to other
works of literature, 175–177
and literary canon, 92, 134
and literary genres, 44, 67, 85, 89, 92,
100, 113, 130, 131, 132, 133, 139,
142, 145–148, 149, 163, 176, 177,
185, 187, 188, 208, 209, 211, 254n78
and literary universals, 43–44,
233n131
and lying, 157, 158–159, 161, 162,
167, 169–174
and shame, 53, 158–160, 161–162,
172–174, 190
and self-deception, 16, 158, 159, 162,
164, 179, 182, 186, 189, 190–191
and texts that lack or seem to lack it,
43–45, 92, 94–95, 96, 201, 208, 221
and writers’ awareness of, 39–43, 220
as invisible, 4, 8, 222
316
Sei Shonagon, 4
Shakespeare, William, 36
Measure for Measure, 86–87
Othello, 14, 36, 43, 184
Romeo and Juliet, 197
Sonnet 42 (“That thou hast her”), 11
Sonnet 138 (“When My Love
Swears”), 148, 185–187, 189
Twelfth Night, 14
Shame, xi, 53, 158–160, 161–162,
172–174, 175, 190, 241n66, 260n47,
260n56
Shen, Bojun, 262n80, 262n84
Simon, Julien S., xii, 237n9, 239n33
Sinnott, Susan
Welcome to Kirsten’s World, 1854:
Growing Up in Pioneer America, 210
Skolnick, Deena, 248n28
Slingerland, Edward, 263n96
Smith, Hagan, 232n123
Smith, Valerie, 240n43
Smith, Zadie, 57, 205
On Beauty, 16–17
Smollett, Tobias, 80
Snodgrass, Sara E., 237n6
Social cognition, 43, 58, 102, 227n63,
235n157
Socialist realism, 43, 87–97, 155,
243n89, 244n101, 245n108,
245n110
Social mind, 222
Social pleasure of mind-reading, 109,
111, 187, 212
Social status, x, 62, 70, 81–82, 84, 86–89
Sociocognitive complexity, 7, 66–67, 85,
87, 89, 93, 147, 158, 203, 207, 210,
213, 242n68
Solnit, Rebecca, 63
Song of Igor’s Campaign, The, 257n24
Sontag, Susan, 133, 221
Sophocles, 141–142
Soyinka, Wole, 4
Spark, Muriel, 36
Index
The Ballad of Peckham Rye, 95, 221
The Girls of Slender Means, 34–35
Spencer, Jane, 241n65
Sperber, Dan, 60, 103, 236n4, 248n31,
249n32
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty, 133
Spolsky, Ellen, xii, 231n101, 245n112
Starr, Gabrielle, xii, 247n19
Steel, Danielle
Against All Odds, 56, 57
Steen, Francis, xii
Stern, Simon, xii
Sterne, Laurence, 80, 142, 153, 154,
236n163
Stiller, James, 248n25
Stockwell, Peter, xii, 227n61
Story of the Western Wing, The (Wang),
15, 167, 168
Straub, Kristina, 241n65
Stuart Little (E. B. White), 199, 201, 204
Style, 24–25, 38, 39, 141
Sutton, John, xii, 231n101
Tale of Frol Skobeev, The, 71–72, 78, 150,
152, 158
Tale of Misery-Luckless-Plight, The, 150,
151
Tamir, Diana I., 227n63
Tang dynasty, 163, 165–166, 167,
261n70
Theory of mind, 2. See also Mindreading
cultural elaboration or suppression of,
23, 58, 90, 99, 106, 121, 124–125,
128, 147, 207, 221
and academia, 25, 126, 127–128,
136–139
and ethics, 120–121, 206–207
and fiction, 56–57, 109, 147, 161, 209,
224n9, 227n63, 235n157
and lying, 148, 172, 183, 207
and monasticism, 125–126, 130
and opacity of mind, 113, 248n29
and representation, 25, 38, 102–104
Index
and social status, 62, 70, 87–89
as a metaphor, 100–104, 223n2
as separate from empathy, 108
in children, 107, 193–198, 213–218
Thompson, Bradbury, 1, 6
Throop, C. Jason, 115, 122
Tobar, Héctor, 64
Tolstaya, Tatiana, 36, 57
Tolstoy, Lev, 91, 92, 96, 142, 162
Anna Karenina, 10–11, 145, 162;
War and Peace, 66–67
Tomasello, Michael, 102, 223n4,
246n14, 250n44
Tooby, John, 183, 265n126. See also
Cosmides, Leda
Travers, P. L.
Mary Poppins, 199, 201, 202
Tribble, Evelyn B., 231n101
Tricksters, 13, 19, 188, 212, 213, 219,
239n42
Troscianko, Emily, 129, 145, 231n101,
246n12, 246n14, 246n17, 247n17
Turgenev, Ivan, 162
Turner, Mark, xii, 256n4
Twain, Mark
Huckleberry Finn, 205–207
Tom Sawyer, 1, 4–6, 51, 197, 199, 204–
208, 211
Tyler, Royall, 53
Unreliable narration, 154–157, 190,
203–204, 243n83
and socialist realism, 89–91
Vaginov, Konstantin
Works and Days of Svistonov, 89
Van Duijn, Max J., 35–36
Van Kuijk, Iris, 56, 227n63
Vapnyar, Lara
Still Here, 33–34
Vermeule, Blakey, xii, 65, 232n120,
237n16, 238n17, 241n68, 252n47
Vignemont, Frédérique, de, 237n6
317
Vincent, J. Keith, xii
Vineberg, Steve, 86
Vygotsky, Lev, 186, 265n127, 265n130
Walsh, Richard, 224n13
“Wanderer, The,” 12
Wang, Shifu, 141
The Story of the Western Wing, 15,
167
Wang, Yuanfei, 254n78
Wang Xizhi
“Preface to the Poems Collected from
the Orchid Pavilion,” 261n70
Wei, Shang, 264n121
Whalen, Doug, xii, 23, 224n11, 228n77,
232n116, 234n145, 237n15, 248n23
Wharton, Edith
“Xingu,” 48
Wice, Matthew, 251n14
Wiesehan, Gretchen, 245n110
Wilde, Oscar
The Importance of Being Earnest, 72
Wilder, Laura Ingalls
Little House in the Big Woods, 199,
208–211, 269n56
Little House on the Prairie, 209
Little Town on the Prairie, 209
Pioneer Girl, 208–209, 210
These Happy Golden Years, 210
Wilder, Rose Lane, 208–209
Williams, Joy
“The Museum,” 9, 17
Winnie the Pooh (A. A. Milne), 199, 200,
214
Wodehouse, P. G., 72
Wolf, Christa
City of Angels, 101
Patterns of Childhood, 146, 220–221,
271n1
They Divided the Sky, 96
Wood, James, 157, 265n140
Woodruff, Guy, 249n34
Woolf, Virginia, 45, 142
318
Wordsworth, William, 46
“Lines Composed a Few Miles above
Tintern Abbey,” 49
Prelude, 49
Wu Cheng’en
Journey to the West, 254n78
Wu Ching-Tzu, The Scholars, 177–179
Wycherley, William
A Country Wife, 85
Xiong, Muqing, xii
Xue Neng, 165
Yap, 114, 115, 121, 122
Yeazell, Ruth Bernard, 241n62, 241n66
Yongchao, Wen xii
Yu, Pauline, 164
Yuan Zhen
“Ying-ying’s Story,” 164–167, 168
Zamyatin, Evgeny
We, 44–45, 95, 96, 221
Zion, Gene
Harry the Dirty Dog, 212
Zweig, Stefan, 96
Index