Viewpoint Convergence as a Philosophical Defect
Grace Helton
Draft of April 2024
Please cite official version where possible.
(Forthcoming), in S. Goldberg and M. Walker (eds)., Attitude in Philosophy, Oxford University Press.
ABSTRACT. What can we know? How should we live? What is there? Philosophers famously diverge in the answers they give to these
and other philosophical questions. It is widely presumed that a lack of convergence on these questions suggests that philosophy is not progressing at all, is not progressing fast enough, or is not progressing as fast as other disciplines, such as the
natural sciences. Call the view that ideal philosophical progress is marked by at least some degree of convergence on the core
philosophical questions the pro-convergence thesis. I will argue that there is reason to reject the pro-convergence thesis in favor of
the anti-convergence thesis, the view that significant viewpoint convergence is at odds with the aims of a philosophically ideal
community. Specifically, I will suggest that we must reject the pro-convergence thesis in order to escape the claim that our
current philosophical methods are so woefully inadequate to the task of philosophy that no employment of those methods,
no matter how extensive or rigorous, could possibly produce philosophical success. On this view, call it philosophical primitivism,
ours is a kind of pre-philosophical era, something akin to a pre-scientific era. The overall argument centers on a thought
experiment about two different philosophical communities.
WORD COUNT.
10,277 (incl. footnotes), 9,048 (excl. footnotes)
Key words. philosophical progress, disagreement, convergence, social epistemology, metaphilosophy
What can we know? How should we live? What is there? Philosophers famously diverge in the answers they give to these
and other philosophical questions, though it is somewhat controversial how extensive this disagreement is.1 In
recent metaphilosophy, many theorists treat the fact that philosophers persistently fail to converge on the answers
they give to these questions to be a matter of concern, even embarrassment. In particular, it is widely presumed
that a lack of convergence on answers to the central questions suggests that philosophy is not progressing at all,
is not progressing fast enough, or is not progressing as fast as other disciplines, such as the natural sciences. The
guiding presumption of this body of work is that, across philosophical domains, late stages of philosophical inquiry will ideally be marked by significant convergence on answers to the core philosophical questions.2 Call this
For the view that there is at least some significant divergence on the core questions, see: Van Inwagen (2004,
2006), Brennan (2010), Dietrich (2010), Lycan (2013), Chalmers (2015), Kelly (2016: 374, Cf. 386), Jackson (2017),
Jones (2017: 230), Kamber (2017), Shand (2017), Walker (2017), Williamson (2017), Slezak (2018), and Arroyo
(2019). Cf. Cappelen (2017) and Stoljar (2017a, 2017b).
2 Those who implicitly or explicitly accept something like this view include: Rescher (2014), Chalmers (2015),
Brock (2017), Kamber (2017), Norris (2017), Stoljar (2017a, 2017b), Shand (2017), Williamson (2017), and Žanic
(2020: 10). Cf. Green (2017: 207). Bright (2021) does not explicitly endorse the pro-convergence thesis, but he
1
the pro-convergence thesis. The pro-convergence thesis is a normative view about what a philosophically flourishing
community will look like in later or mature phases of inquiry. This thesis does not rule out that initial or intermediate phases of inquiry might, even ideally, feature significant divergence. This thesis is also silent on the descriptive question of whether our own community currently exhibits viewpoint convergence, or ever will.
In this paper, I will suggest we should reject the pro-convergence thesis in favor of the anti-convergence
thesis. This is the view that, for at least some philosophical domains and for mature stages of inquiry, significant
convergence in the answers philosophers give to philosophical questions is inconsistent with the aims of a philosophically ideal community.3 My argument exploits the following interim claim: Either, philosophical communities which evince, in late stages of inquiry, widespread, highly diachronically stable viewpoint convergence are
philosophically defective in at least some respect; or else, our current philosophical methods are so woefully
inadequate to the task for which they are intended that no employment of those methods, no matter how extensive
or rigorous, could possibly produce philosophical knowledge. On the latter view, call it philosophical primitivism, we
have never figured out, in even rough form, what kinds of tools we should use for the task at hand. On this view,
ours is a kind of pre-philosophical era, something akin to a pre-scientific era. I will further suggest that, given how
unappealing philosophical primitivism is, we should reject the view that the relevant form of convergence is a
condition on philosophical progress.
My argument centers on a thought experiment about two philosophical communities, one of which exhibits, at a late stage of inquiry, broad and diachronically stable convergence on the core philosophical questions,
and one of which exhibits, at a late stage of inquiry, broad and diachronically stable divergence on these questions.
I will suggest that it is natural to think that the convergent community must be philosophically defective in some
respect or other. Call this the convergence intuition. To be clear, the convergence intuition does not say that it is in
virtue of being convergent that the relevant community is defective; rather, the intuition says something far coarser-something like ‘philosophically speaking, there is something ‘off’ about this particular community.’ The intuition
leaves open what is ‘off’ about this community. I will also suggest that it is natural to think that the divergent
community might be a philosophically ideal one. Call this the divergence intuition. As with the convergence intuition,
the divergence intuition is coarse in grain. It ‘says’ that the relevant divergent community might, for all we know,
be a wholly flourishing one, but it doesn’t say in virtue of what features this community is potentially flourishing.
One strand of my argument is dedicated to considering what might best explain these intuitions. Either,
the intuitions track reality, or they do not track reality. I will first argue, by excluding other plausible explanations,
suggests that analytic philosophy’s lack of consensus has contributed to a lack of confidence amongst its practitioners. Blackford (2017: 11), Cappelen (2017), and Jones (2017) express sympathy with something like the anticonvergence thesis, as does Riggle (2021), in the context of aesthetic discourse. McGrath (2010) criticizes several
arguments in favor of the view that if moral realism is true, then reasoners will converge in their moral theories,
and Kelly and McGrath (2010) argue that neither reflective equilibrium nor Bayesian methods secure philosophical viewpoint convergence (but leave open that other methods might).
3 The pro-convergence thesis and the anti-convergence thesis do not exhaust logical options. On a view we might
dub convergence neutrality, it is neither the case that ideal philosophical progress will be marked by viewpoint convergence nor the case that viewpoint convergence is a sign of philosophical defect.
that we have some reason to take these intuitions at face value (§1). I will second consider a rival explanation, on
which these intuitions are false but nevertheless persist due to an imaginative failure on our part. I will argue that
this explanation would, if true, help support philosophical primitivism, the view that our own community’s methods
are wholly ill-suited for the task of philosophy. I will suggest that, in order to avoid primitivism, we should reject
the pro-convergence thesis (§2). I close by reflecting on some of the motivations for the pro-convergence thesis
(§3).
Some might suppose that to reject viewpoint convergence as a marker of ideal, late-stage philosophical
inquiry is to commit to certain, arguably radical broader views about the nature of philosophy. For, if ideal philosophical progress is not marked by viewpoint convergence, then there is some reason to think that philosophy
does not have collective knowledge as an aim.4 Building on this result, some might wonder whether this view in
turn entails that philosophy lacks an epistemic aim altogether; if this is so, perhaps philosophy is more like art,
cuisine, or athletics than it is like paradigmatically epistemic activities, such as science. As it turns out, and as I
further discuss in §3, the anti-convergence thesis does not require us to relinquish the presumption that philosophy is an epistemic activity. At the same time, it might turn out that the aim of philosophy, though epistemic, is
not knowledge of first-order philosophical facts, but is rather some other epistemic aim, such as: knowledge of
how certain views and commitments fit together; a kind of epistemically valuable grasping that is independent of
knowledge or justification; or something else.5 The point is merely that the anti-convergence thesis leaves much
open in the way of philosophy’s ultimate nature, including whether it is an epistemic enterprise.
In a similar vein, it might be tempting to suppose that the anti-convergence view all but implies that
philosophy forms a contrast with the natural sciences. For, it might be supposed that ideal scientific communities
will ideally exhibit convergence on central scientific questions. As it turns out, this question is much more fraught
than it would at first appear. In particular, it is not clear whether ideal scientific communities will ideally converge
on central scientific questions and thus not obvious whether philosophy is in this respect similar to or rather
different than the natural sciences.6 The present paper is simply neutral on this issue.
A few smaller comments before proceeding: First, as mentioned, the pro-convergence thesis is the view that,
in late stages of inquiry, and in suitably large communities, ideal philosophical progress will be marked by widespread, highly diachronically stable convergence on the core philosophical questions, whereas the anti-convergence thesis is the view that ideal philosophical progress is at odds with such convergence. For simplicity, I routinely use ‘convergence’ as short-hand for the relevant kind of convergence, but the reader should keep in mind
that it is widespread, diachronically stable convergence in a suitably large community at a late stage of inquiry that is at issue.
Second, one might think that the anti-convergence thesis shares much with—or indeed, is merely a special instance of—a much-discussed class of views in political science and feminist epistemology, on which
I explore this suggestion further in §3.
McSweeney (2023a, 2023b, this volume) champions this kind of ‘grasping’ approach.
6 For a helpful discussion, see Bird (2007).
4
5
viewpoint diversity is valuable in collective inquiry, either on epistemic grounds or on grounds of legitimizing
such inquiry. Call these ‘viewpoint diversity’ views.7 While the anti-convergence thesis is consistent with ‘viewpoint diversity’ views, it turns out to be distinct from at least many of them, namely those concerned with the
value of viewpoint divergence in early or intermediate stages of inquiry. This is because the anti-convergence thesis
strictly concerns the disvalue of convergence in late stages of inquiry. Moreover, a motive for some ‘viewpoint
diversity’ views relies on the thought that viewpoint diversity in earlier stages of inquiry can help contribute to the
univocity or collective accuracy of views formed in later stages of inquiry; these approaches presume ideal inquiry
will tend to converge over time. The anti-convergence view is at odds with this style of motivation, since it precisely denies that late stages of philosophical inquiry will ideally be marked by viewpoint convergence.
Finally, the pro-convergence thesis is the view that across philosophical domains, ideal philosophical progress
will be marked by convergence on the core philosophical questions, and the anti-convergence thesis is the view
that for at least some philosophical domains, viewpoint convergence is inconsistent with the aims of a philosophically ideal community. The anti-convergence thesis is thus consistent with the claim that late stages of inquiry into
some philosophical domains—formal semantics, perhaps, or philosophy of chemistry—will exhibit viewpoint convergence. In the paper, I tend to focus on examples from traditional metaphysics and epistemology, but I am
deliberately neutral on the question of which domains of philosophy are governed by the anti-convergence thesis.
The thesis should rather be read as the existential claim that there exist at least some domains in philosophy which
are such that suitably large philosophical communities inquiring into their questions should not, at late stages of
inquiry, demonstrate marked and diachronically stable convergence on answers to those questions.
1 Two Philosophical Communities
Consider two different philosophical communities.
Call the first community the convergent community. Let this community be extremely large and extremely
long-lived. Suppose, for instance, that this community contains thousands of members at a given time and spans
a tradition of several centuries, even millennia. This group of philosophers exhibits, over this period, broad convergence, though not strict consensus, on most or all of the most fundamental philosophical questions, such as:
What can we know? How should we live? What is there? And so on. This isn’t to say that these philosophers don’t diverge
in any of their views. On the contrary, they have sophisticated, well-argued positions, but these differences in
viewpoint contrast with a background agreement on the core questions. For instance, perhaps the vast majority
of these thinkers take a contextualist approach to the question of external world skepticism but disagree amongst
themselves about which version of the view to favor and why. Or perhaps the vast majority of these thinkers
7 I thank Josh Armstrong and Daniela Dover for discussion on this point. For work that emphasizes the value of
viewpoint divergence in science, see, e.g., Longino and Doell (1983), Longino (1990), Fehr (2011), and Muldoon
(2013, esp. §6). For work that emphasizes the value of viewpoint divergence in the political context, see, e.g.,
Gaus (2019), Muldoon et al. (2014), and Muldoon (2017). For feminist work that emphasizes the value of viewpoint divergence, see, e.g., Longino (2002) and Intemann (2011). For a helpful overview, see Grasswick (2018).
suppose free will is compatible with determinism about the laws of nature but disagree amongst themselves about
why this is the case. Or perhaps the vast majority of these thinkers accept that morality is wholly a matter of
optimizing pleasure but disagree about which variant of this view to adopt.
This community produces countless monographs, edited volumes, journals, conferences, seminars, email
exchanges, book symposia, lectures, and in-person conversations. In this much, this community is vibrant, generating what appear to be compelling reasons for myriad positions; it is just that there are few degrees of freedom
between these positions.
Call the second community the divergent community. Let this community be extremely large and extremely
long-lived. Suppose, for instance, that this community contains thousands of members at a given time and spans
a tradition of several centuries, even millennia. Members of the second community evince, over this period, widespread divergence on the central philosophical questions, struggling to come to anything like consensus on even
the most fundamental questions: What can we know? How should we live? What is there? And so on. To these and other
questions, these thinkers manage to provide a dizzying array of answers, seemingly staking out every logically
possible position—and then some.8 These philosophers do not shun strange views. For instance, some argue that
they themselves do not exist. 9 Others argue that roads, cups, mountains, and dabs of paint do not exist.10
The divergent community produces countless monographs, edited volumes, journals, conferences, seminars, email exchanges, book symposia, lectures, and in-person conversations. Still, this community’s approaches
to the important questions never stabilize, at least not for long. For short periods, it might seem that most of its
members have converged on one answer to an important question. But no sooner is this stability achieved than a
new cohort takes over, suggesting an altogether different tack, usually one which upturns the most precious assumptions of the previous generation. For instance, for a time, one of them managed to convince a large number
of the others that it would be a bad thing to live your whole life in a machine.11 But over time, that consensus
crumbled, as others stepped in to suggest that such a life might not be so bad.12
Might either of these communities, the convergent community or the divergent community, be a philosophically ideal one? To my mind, it is obvious that the convergent community is not a philosophically ideal
community, which isn’t to say that it is obvious what exactly makes this community deficient. Further, to suggest
that the convergent community lacks something isn’t to deny that the community enjoys many philosophical
I respectfully refer to Priest (2006).
Unger (1979).
10 Van Inwagen (1990).
11 Nozick (1974: 42–45)
12 Hewitt (2010), Weijers (2013, 2014); Cf. Lin (2016). Since some of these examples are from our community,
one might suppose that I’m taking our own philosophical community to be a kind of divergent community. In
fact, I think our own philosophical community has elements of both the convergent and divergent communities.
As Liam Kofi Bright has pointed out to me, the range of views taken seriously in our own community is severely
constrained, which suggests that it shares something with the convergent community. To use his helpful example,
one would be hard pressed to find an academic philosopher who defends the view that we ought to de-industrialize society and abolish large-scale technologies, even though this position—anarcho-primitivism—is coherent and
has something to be said for it.
8
9
virtues, even some important ones. For instance, the arguments produced by this community might be novel or
interesting in their own right. The kinds of considerations the theorists in this community collectively raise might
be rich and suasive. But insofar as this community exhibits highly chronic and pervasive convergence on the core
questions—what can we know? how should we live? and so on—the community seems somehow to have foundered in
at least some part of its philosophical mission. Indeed, insofar as this community’s convergence on important
questions resembles something like dogmatism, one might even wonder whether this community is a community
of philosophers at all, or whether it would be more apt to characterize the group as a religious community or some
other group organized primarily around doctrine.13 Insofar as we can imagine that this community is one of philosophers, it seems to have fallen short of some philosophical ideal or other.14
As mentioned, to claim that the convergent community is, philosophically speaking, less than ideal is not
to make any more specific claim about what makes this community philosophically non-ideal. In particular, it is
not to claim that the fact that this community is convergent is itself a defect. It might be that there is some trait
which co-varies with convergence which is the source of the community’s philosophical defectiveness. For instance, perhaps a kind of closed-mindedness on the part of this community’s members both causes this community to evince viewpoint convergence and is the source of this community’s philosophical defectiveness.
At this point, many readers will immediately have thought of several possible ways of explaining away
this intuition—specifically, of granting that we have the sense that the convergent community is ‘off’ in some way
but of positing that the community is ‘off’ in a way that doesn’t entail that it is philosophically defective. For instance,
perhaps we simply suspect something is wrong with the community because it is different than ours. Or, perhaps
we presume that there must be some inapt social limitations on free thought in this community. I will shortly
consider and defuse these and other routes of explaining away this intuition. For now, the point is just that we
have some kind of sense that the convergent community is ‘off,’ and its being ‘off’ is plausibly tied to the fact that
the community is a philosophical community and not merely (say) a social community or a community organized
overtly around doctrine.
What of the second, divergent community? Might it be an ideally philosophically flourishing one? To my
mind, this community is the only of the two which has any chance of being a philosophically ideal one. Without
more information about the kinds of activities this community engages in, we can’t be sure whether this community is a philosophically flourishing one, but the mere fact of its divergence does not give us reason to think it is
somehow philosophically defective. Call the intuition that the divergent community is not necessarily a philosophically defective one the divergence intuition.
Of course, many—and perhaps all—actual communities of philosophers have been organized around a shared
religion, culture, or other shared sets of values. My suggestion is that the group’s marked dogmatism might incline
us to wonder whether the group is merely a doctrinal group and not (also) a philosophical one.
14 Harvey Lederman has suggested that it’s not obvious that this community is sociologically possible. If this is
right, I would take the result to be grist for my ultimate aim, which is to suggest that the kind of viewpoint
convergence this community evinces cannot be a condition on ideal philosophical theorizing. If this kind of
community is not possible, it seems doubtful that it might serve as an exemplar for our own community.
13
Going forward, I will largely set the divergence intuition to one side, as the argument centers on how
best to explain the convergence intuition, with the divergence intuition playing a supporting role. Let us turn,
then, to possible routes of explaining away the convergence intuition. Might we admit that the convergent community is ‘off’ in some sense, without conceding that this sense concerns some kind of philosophically defect?
On one view, already mentioned, the convergence intuition derives from a kind of stereotype about what
our own community is like. We suppose that philosophers disagree; that’s just what they (that is, we ourselves)
do, and we therefore feel uneasy about any community which veers so dramatically from this familiar model.
Perhaps this unfamiliarity even stems from the a more general status quo bias, on which, very roughly, in at least
some contexts, subjects exhibit a preference that certain things remain the same, just for the sake of remaining
the same.15
Here is one reason I think the ‘status quo’ explanation should be regarded with suspicion. This bias does
not hold across domains, with the result that we should at least like to know why the philosophical case is special,
such that it does hold of it. Consider the scientific community before modern developments in aviation. Technology-enabled flight was a radical impossibility for scientists from previous eras, a mere fantasy. Nonetheless,
this fact did not prevent a great many of them from longing for its possibility. Think, for instance, of da Vinci
dreaming of machines which propelled humans through the air. Many theorists foresaw and hoped for this
change, even if they had no idea, even in very rough form, of how to go about it, even if they thought it practically
impossible, and even though a world in which humans traveled through the sky diverged dramatically from their
current state of affairs. Of course, the case of a convergent philosophical community is importantly different from
this example in many potentially significant ways. The point is merely that there are many domains in which ‘status
quo’ bias does not hold, so, before adopting this explanation of the convergence intuition, we might wish for more
reason to think that the philosophical case is a context in which this preference for the familiar does hold.
Here is a second, stronger reason to think that status quo bias does not explain the convergence intuition.
As mentioned previously, many theorists profess frustration and even embarrassment with philosophy’s current
state of seeming divergence on answers to the core questions. These theorists’ responses suggest a kind of discomfort with the status quo of our discipline; they openly long for the discipline to be different than they take it
currently to be. So, for at least many philosophers, a preference for the status quo simply does not hold when it
comes to judgments about philosophical communities.
Here is another way one might attempt to explain away the convergence intuition. Perhaps what is behind
the intuition is that, in imagining the convergent community, we implicitly suppose that it is a community in
which free thought is constricted. On this view, the convergence exhibited is the result of a kind of enforced
dogmatism, and we might reasonably repel from such thought policing.16 If this is right, then we might expect
For a classic overview, see Kahneman (1991). I thank Sarah McGrath for suggesting this point.
Blackford (2017: 11) expresses sympathy with the thought that a convergent community seems philosophically
untoward, suggesting that such a community ‘smells too much of past situations when certain doctrines were
15
16
that further describing the case so as to specify that the convergence in question is not the result of inapt social
limitations should dissolve the intuition. So, let us suppose that the views formed by those in the convergent
community are not coerced via political sanction or social threat. These opinions are ‘freely’ formed, or as freely
formed as any view can be. Would we still have the intuition that the convergence is somehow inapt?
For my part, the intuition stubbornly persists even when I imagine that the relevant philosophical community is an unstifled, intellectually liberated one. At most, this reimagining of the community slightly deepens
the puzzle about how exactly the community might come about, but it does not dissolve the core intuition that
philosophically speaking, there is something ‘off’ about this community.
Here is another way an opponent of the convergence intuition might attempt to explain it away. Suppose
that the members of this community do not themselves take questions such as what we can we know? and how should
we live? to be the most important questions for their community. Suppose rather that the members of this community take the points of dispute between them—for instance, about which version of anti-skeptical contextualism to endorse—to be the central questions of their discipline. If this is the case, then perhaps this community is
a philosophically ideal one, at least by its own lights, insofar as it evinces divergence on what its members take to
be the central questions.17 On this view, once we appreciate that the relevant questions are, by the community
member’s lights, the central ones, we can see that the community is a kind of divergent community.
I must confess to finding it difficult to imagine that a philosophically ideal community might, over a
period of centuries, even millennia, take the very central questions of its discipline to be questions such as which
version of anti-skeptical contextualism is correct? instead of questions such as what can we know? To my mind, such a
community has erred, insofar as it has ignored deeper questions to focus exclusively on some shallower ones.
This isn’t to say that the shallower ones aren’t philosophically valuable. But a community that treats these questions as paramount seems somehow to have aimed just to the left of what really matters and has, at least in this
much, failed in its philosophical mission. This isn’t to suggest that there can be no variance, across communities
of philosophers, about what the most pressing questions are—far from it. But it is to suggest that a philosophical
community which chronically focuses wholly on quibbles concerning broadly agreed on positions is not a fully
flourishing community.
Here is yet another way an opponent of the convergence intuition might attempt to dissolve the intuition.
Suppose that we stipulate that the members of the convergent community are open-minded when it comes to the
central questions: What can we know? how should we live? and so on. They do not pre-judge these questions. Nevertheless, they all come to agree through compelling reason that (say) contextualist approaches to skepticism are
orthodox and everything else was heretical.’ Jones (2017: 231-233) suggests that practically speaking, such convergence could only be accidental, and thus presumably not the result of suasive reasons.
17 One might be tempted to think that this is how the natural sciences proceed; they reach rough convergence on
certain, ‘starting’ core questions and then move on to disputes arising in light of that convergence, and these new
questions become the new core questions of the discipline.
best, moral action is wholly a matter of optimizing pleasure, and so on. Would we presume that this community
is necessarily philosophically defective in some way?
I find it plausible that a small or short-lived philosophical community whose members all come to converge, through compelling argument, on the answers to the core philosophical questions, isn’t necessarily a philosophically defective one. Indeed, this is what we might call a school of thought, and there is nothing intuitively
problematic about a philosophical community’s containing different schools of thought, where each school’s
members tend to converge on answers to the large questions. But importantly, the convergence intuition does
not concern a school of thought. The intuition concerns a community which spans (say) many centuries and, at
any given moment, thousands of theorists. Once we fix our sights on this very long-lived and large philosophical
community, it becomes hard to avoid the sense that there is something or other untoward about this community if
it consistently converges on the central questions, whether or not its members somehow reach this convergence
via compelling argument.
Here my opponent might stand firm. She might insist that even if we fix our sights on a very large and
long-lived community, there is nothing philosophically untoward about convergence, so long as its members reach
this convergence by a rational process. Indeed, if these theorists employ similar, normatively constrained processes of reasoning, perhaps we should expect them to ultimately converge in their viewpoints.18 And if this is
right, then we simultaneously have a reason to reject both the convergence intuition and the anti-convergence
thesis writ large.
The suggestion that philosophers who employ similar, normatively constrained reasoning processes will
ultimately converge in their viewpoints is a compelling one, and this thought merits far more in the way of a reply
than I can afford it here. But as a kind of starting point, I would point the reader to some arguments developed
by Sarah McGrath in the context of assessing whether we should expect that the method of reflective equilibrium
will lead reasoners to converge in their moral theories. McGrath suggests that, even if moral realism is true, reasoners who employ reflective equilibrium might not converge in their moral views. Among other things, McGrath
points to the fact that such reasoners might begin with different starting points and to the fact that these reasoners
might resolve inconsistencies via different strategies.19 In joint work, Thomas Kelly and Sarah McGrath extend
this thought to Bayesian strategies of belief revision. They note that, while in some cases, reasoners with different
starting points will, by employing Bayesian methods, ultimately come to converge in their viewpoints, in other
cases, reasoners with different starting points will never, through Bayesian methods, converge in their views.20 So,
even perfect employment of Bayesian methods does not invariably result in viewpoint convergence.
I take these considerations to at least cast doubt on the suggestion that rational reasoners who employ
Many theorists have presumed that realism in particular supports this kind of claim. See, e.g., Wright (1992).
Cf. McGrath (2010).
19 McGrath (2010: 81-4), Kelly and McGrath (2010).
20 Kelly and McGrath (2010: 339-340).
18
ideal revision methods will invariably converge in their philosophical viewpoints. For, when it comes to two
much-championed philosophical methods, it is far from obvious that reasoners employing those methods will
ultimately converge in their viewpoints.21
So far, I’ve argued that many of us, when considering the convergent community, will have a sense that
the convergent community is ‘off’ in some way. I’ve further considered some ways of defusing this intuition in
ways which do not require us to posit that the community is philosophically deficient. I’ve argued that none of
these routes is very compelling. Together, these arguments suggest some reason to take the convergence intuition
at face value: Philosophically speaking, there is something ‘off’ about the convergent community. While this community might be a partly virtuous philosophical community, it is not an ideal philosophical community.
So, if we accept these points, we will have some reason to accept the following claim:
THE ANTI-CONVERGENCE THESIS
Any suitably large and suitably long-lived philosophy community whose members converge on answers
to the core questions is philosophically deficient in at least some respect.
Not everyone will think the arguments I’ve offered are strong enough to endorse this claim. They might suggest
that the convergence intuition is not to be trusted, even if hard to explain away via the considered routes. On
one line of thought, the convergent community might be philosophically ideal despite our stubbornly persistent
intuition to the contrary, for the simple reason that we struggle to imagine how exactly this would be the case. But
the fact that we struggle to imagine how the convergent community might be ideal doesn’t suggest that the
community is in fact not ideal. While, on its face, this suggestion from the limitations of our own imagination
seems a reasonable one, I will next argue that this suggestion has unexpected costs.
2 The Imaginative Difficulty and Philosophical Primitivism
Let’s reflect: On the assumption that the convergent community might in fact be a philosophically ideal one, why
is it so difficult for us to imagine, even in rough form, how it might be so? Think once more of da Vinci’s detailed
rendering of machines which would permit humans to fly through the air. In da Vinci’s time, the technology for
such flight was not even remotely within reach and yet, this was no barrier to his being able to imagine, in at least
crude mechanical form, how such an accomplishment might come about. So, it is not as though, in general, we
cannot imagine some future state of more advanced achievement if our current level of achievement with respect
to the domain is extremely crude.
Perhaps it is merely difficult, and not impossible, for us to imagine how the convergent community might
Kelly and McGrath (2010: 353-54) ultimately suggest that we should focus on a kind of normatively-constrained
strategy and on ‘…what makes it the case that some starting points are more reasonable than others, and how we
manage to recognize or grasp such facts.’
21
be a philosophically flourishing one. Perhaps in conceiving the original case, we simply didn’t fill in the details of
the philosophers’ methods enough to make it intelligible how they might rationally converge on the central questions. On this view, were we to properly imagine a sufficiently extensive or adroit employment of some or all of
our current philosophical tools—such as the method of cases, reflective equilibrium, experimental philosophy,
formal methods, conceptual engineering, applied approaches, historical work, and comparative methods—we
would no longer suppose the convergent community to be philosophically deficient in some respect.22 On this
view, the intuition results from our imagining the case in an impoverished way, not from the fact that the convergent community is in fact defective.
One reason to doubt that the imaginative difficulty is explained merely by our own imaginative shortcomings is that it just does not seem that any amount of imagining ‘more’ of our current methods shifts the sense
that the convergent community is philosophically ‘off’ in some sense. You can test this for yourself. Try to imagine
as vividly as you can a philosophical community which employs our methods, any of them you like, in any combination you like. Imagine also that these methods are as sophisticated as they might possibly be. For instance,
you might imagine a community whose employment of the method of cases, conceptual analysis, experimental
philosophy, formal methods, comparative methods, conceptual engineering, and the like are immeasurably more
sophisticated than ours, but are still, at least in very rough outline, the same kinds of methods we employ. Does
this exercise lessen the strength of the intuition that the convergent community is defective in some respect? Or,
does it make it easier to imagine how a community might reach convergence via cogent reasons? In my own case,
I find the answer to both questions to be ‘no.’
Moreover, there is a ready explanation of why this imaginative exercise would not help to mitigate the
sense that there is something philosophically ‘off’ about the convergent community. This imagining is plausibly a
kind of extrapolation from our present empirical knowledge of the role these methods have played in our discipline. And arguably, increasing levels of sophistication of these methods has not led to convergence on the core
questions. If anything, they have led, in at least some cases, to the development of novel ways of disagreeing about
these questions.
Consider, for instance, the debate over the nature of truth. Classically, some philosophers have defended
a pragmatist view of truth, others a correspondence view, and still others an identity view.23 One might have
thought (perhaps naively) that the recent metaphilosophical turn in this dispute would somehow lead to greater
convergence amongst philosophers about the first-order question. For instance, one might have thought that
clarifying the metaphilosophical considerations in this case would have resulted in more philosophers moving to
one of the three mentioned first-order views, with a net result of greater first-order convergence.
Williamson (2010) is perhaps amenable to this suggestion. Cf. Cherry (2017: 23). Likewise, Rawls seems to
suggest that reflective equilibrium, ideally employed, will result in viewpoint convergence (1974: 290, 1999: 301).
Cf. Lewis (1983: x-xi) and Kelly and McGrath (2010: 334-341).
23 For an overview, see Glanzberg (2021).
22
As it turns out, a turn to metaphilosophical considerations has not contributed to any increase in firstorder convergence about the nature of truth. On the contrary, a self-consciously metaphilosophical stance has
merely helped philosophers generate new ways for philosophers to disagree about the core question. For instance,
it has made it possible for some theorists to develop and defend pluralism about truth, on which there are multiple
correct views of truth.24 Examples like this—not to mention the history of philosophy understood as a history
of persistent disagreement—plausibly underpin our difficulty in imagining how the convergent community might
in fact be a philosophically ideal one. We are attempting to extrapolate from our current methods to envision,
even in extremely dim form, how some extremely sophisticated version of those methods could result in significant convergence, but this extrapolation is impeded by empirically-grounded awareness that increasingly sophisticated methods have not, in our own community, resulted in greater convergence.
What I am proposing is that the suggestion that the convergent community might be philosophically
ideal, despite our difficulty in imagining how it could be so, leads us fairly naturally to a rather disturbing (defeasible) conclusion: If the convergent community is indeed ideal despite this imaginative difficulty, this is because
our own tools are so woefully ill-equipped for the task of philosophy, that we cannot imagine, even in dim form, how the employment
of any such tools could possibly result in a convergent, philosophically ideal community. In other words, ours is something like
a pre-philosophical state, much like a pre-scientific state. Our methods are not merely crude; they are entirely
misguided for the task of philosophy.
In this section and the last, I have considered two approaches to the convergence intuition. On the first,
the intuition tracks reality; the convergent community is less than philosophically ideal in some respect. This
explanation straightforwardly supports the anti-convergence thesis. On the second approach, the convergence
intuition does not track reality, and in particular, the convergent community might be philosophically ideal, even
though we cannot imagine, even in rough form, how this community might be philosophically ideal. I have argued
that a plausible explanation of this imaginative difficulty is that no employment of our current philosophical
methods, no matter how extensive or skillful, can be used to reach convergence. This explanation just is a form
of philosophical primitivism.25 I conclude that we have good (defeasible) reason to accept the paper’s disjunctive,
interim thesis, which says that exactly one of the following claims is true:
THE ANTI-CONVERGENCE THESIS
Any suitably large and suitably long-lived philosophical community whose members converge on the
core questions is philosophically deficient in at least some respect.
Lynch (e.g. 2001, 2009) and Wright (1992, 999). Indeed, Wright (2013) argues that there are different forms of
pluralism worth taking seriously, further proliferating available views.
25 I say that this explanation is a form of primitivism because, as characterized, primitivism is the view that our
current methods are unusable for the philosophical task whatever that may be. Primitivism thus does not suppose
the ideally successful performance of philosophy to require viewpoint convergence.
24
PHILOSOPHICAL PRIMITIVISM
We are in a kind of pre-philosophical state, in that our current methods are not even remotely suited for
the task of philosophy.
According to the first disjunct, the anti-convergence thesis, ideal philosophical progress is not marked by viewpoint convergence. On the contrary, only the divergent community stands any chance of being philosophically
ideal. The convergent community is at least partly philosophically deficient, either in virtue of its convergence or
in virtue of some trait that goes along with that convergence. If this is right, we needn’t fret over our own discipline’s apparent lack of convergence on the core questions. Whatever our failures as a philosophical community—
and these are no doubt many—the fact that we diverge on the core questions is not one of them.
The second horn of the disjunctive thesis is philosophical primitivism. On this view, our current tools
for doing philosophy are wholly inapt for the task at hand, such that no amount of employing them, no matter
how extensively or expertly, will result in philosophical success. On this view, we seek an enlightenment we will
not find, unless we are willing to charter a radically different path. Indeed, the path required is perhaps not even
fathomable from our current intellectual perspective. Notably, primitivism goes far beyond the view that our
current strategies have not yet helped us realize the aims of philosophy. Primitivism says that our methods won’t
work, no matter how extensively we employ them or how skillfully; they are altogether the wrong tools for the
project.
I am presuming that primitivism is an extremely unappealing approach, to the extent that, faced with the
choice between the anti-convergence thesis and primitivism, we should embrace the anti-convergence thesis.
Thus, I take the paper’s arguments to together suggest some (defeasible) reason to reject the pro-convergence
thesis. So, we can tentatively conclude that the ideal philosophical community will not demonstrate, in late stages
of inquiry, diachronically stable convergence on answers to the core philosophical questions. In the next and final
section, I draw out some further issues connected to this tentative conclusion.
3 Some Conclusions
So far, I have offered some reason in favor of the thought that the ideal philosophical community will not, in late
stages of inquiry, show marked convergence on the core questions. But this reason is arguably trump-able by
some of the motivations for the pro-convergence thesis, motivations I have not engaged with here. I will close
with a brief reflection on just one motivation for the pro-convergence thesis, in an attempt to suggest how it
might be disarmed.
Some philosophers view their discipline as aimed at collective knowledge of philosophical truths, and
they see rough viewpoint coherence as required in order for the attainment of such collective knowledge. One
motivation for this thought comes from a conciliationist approach to the epistemology of disagreement. If the mere
fact of disagreement between epistemic peers can alter one’s justification for one’s own beliefs, then, the worry
arises that facts from philosophical disagreement entail that philosophers are not justified in believing their views,
even if those views are true.26 So, arguably, some philosophers do not know their views, even if these views are
true. For the sake of argument, let’s take all these points on board. Still, we can ask, why think knowledge of firstorder philosophical truths is an aim of philosophy at all? Here is David Chalmers on this point:
I think a case can be made that attaining the truth is the primary aim at least of many parts of philosophy,
such as analytic philosophy. After all, most philosophy, or at least most analytic philosophy, consists in putting
forward theses as true and arguing for their truth. I suspect that for the majority of philosophers, the primary
motivation in doing philosophy is to figure out the truth about the relevant subject areas: What is the relation
between mind and body? What is the nature of reality and how can we know about it? Certainly this is the
primary motivation in my own case.27
While Chalmers refers to truth in this passage, in the broader context in which he argues, he makes clear that he
thinks knowledge, and not merely truth, is an aim of philosophy.28 In what follows, I will construe his argument
in terms of knowledge.
The first reason Chalmers gives for thinking philosophy aims at knowledge is that certain aspects of
philosophical work suggest that philosophers view their own project this way. Chalmers is of course correct that
philosophers routinely present claims as true and adduce arguments in favor of those claims. But it is worth noting
that running alongside these activities, we sometimes find commentary suggesting that the very authors engaging
in these activities do not see knowledge of philosophical truths as an aim. This fact considerably complicates the
picture. Consider, for instance, the way Robert Nozick describes the aim of his own book in the introduction to
Philosophical Explanations:
This book puts forward its explanations in a very tentative spirit; not only do I not ask you to believe they are
correct, I do not think it important for me to believe them correct, either.29
In a similar vein, here is Ward E. Jones’ perspective on how philosophers view their enterprise:
Of course, philosophers would like to have some of their colleagues agree with them, but they do not
See, e.g., Goldberg (2009, 2013a), Kornblith (2013), Barnett (2019), Brennan (2010), and Walker (2022).
Chalmers (2015: 14). Van Inwagen (2004: 339) similarly attributes to other philosophers the view that there can
be successful arguments, though he himself rejects this view. Cf. Nozick (1981: 13).
28 Chalmers (2015: 14-15).
29 Nozick (1981: 42). If we assume that knowledge requires belief, Nozick’s claim is that producing knowledge,
whether in himself or in his readers, is not the aim of his work. Similarly, Wilson (2017: 102) suggests philosophical
claims should be presented as ‘provisional.’ See also Jones (2017: 231).
26
27
expect community-wide agreement. The expectations of the individual philosopher are different from
those of scientists in a deep and revealing way. More important than agreement, to the philosopher, is
attention; she wishes to be read and discussed by her colleagues, to have her claims found interesting (Jones
2017: 231, emphases original).
Certainly, there are some domains within philosophy with respect to which the sentiments expressed by Nozick
and Jones do not seem apt. Think, for instance, of applied ethics. Surely, many applied ethicists do think it important that their readers agree with them and do hope for community-wide agreement (whether or not they
expect it).30 Here it is worth reminding the reader that the anti-convergence thesis is the claim that there are at least
some domains of philosophy which are such that convergence with respect to their question is inconsistent with
ideal philosophical flourishing. I take it that Nozick’s and Jones’ remarks will resonate, for at least some readers,
with respect to at least some provinces of philosophy, whether or not they seem equally apt for all of the discipline’s sub-fields.
The second reason Chalmers gives for thinking philosophy aims at knowledge is that many philosophers,
including—as he reports—himself, pursue philosophy in order to acquire philosophical knowledge. No doubt
Chalmers is correct that many philosophers share this motivation. But I suspect that many other philosophers
will find this motivation missing in themselves, even alien. In the very least, I suspect that many philosophers will
find that this motivation, if present, stands alongside others, some of which seemingly stand in tension with this
one.
For my own part, when I try to reflect honestly on why I have found philosophy worth pursuing, I think
it’s possible that I can identify—at least in some periods of my life—something of the view that philosophy is a
route to truth or knowledge.31 Haven’t I thought philosophy could help me learn important new things, and
perhaps even be able to share these things with others? And yet, I’m not entirely sure whether this has ever been
a central reason I found philosophy worth pursuing, or even any part of my reason at all. For no sooner did I
enter philosophy than I learned what every philosopher quickly learns: Every argument has an interesting rebuttal,
every objection a cogent rejoinder, every view a coherent and compelling rival. I learned that philosophy is never
done, that there is a kind of shocking endlessness to it, that as soon as one thinks one has made some progress,
it all falls apart. I suspect, in fact, that this is a large part of what I found so compelling about the discipline, the
fact that its questions were seemingly so urgent and yet seemingly unsettle-able.32
No doubt Chalmers is right that in pursuing philosophy, many philosophers have been driven by a desire
Thanks to Sarah McGrath for raising this point.
More particularly, the relevant question is why I or any other philosopher has thought the pursuit of philosophy
to have intrinsic value. The question of why philosophers are motivated to pursue their discipline isn’t the right
one because these motivations will often be instrumental; pursuing philosophy helps us forget other problems, is
absorbing and enjoyable, and so on.
32 For an ancient perspective on philosophy’s shocking endlessness, see Annas, J. and Barnes. J. (1985). For a
helpful overview, see Morison (2019).
30
31
for knowledge. But this datum, however significant, should be made to stand alongside this other one: that every
philosophical argument can seemingly be met with a suasive reply from the other side, that often this reply comes
from oneself against one’s very own work, that many philosophers are keenly aware of this aspect of their discipline, and that at least some of them see the unsettle-ability of philosophy as somehow linked to the value of the
discipline.33
Notably, if knowledge of philosophical truths is not an aim for at least some philosophers, this doesn’t
preclude that these philosophers might have some other epistemic motivation for pursuing philosophy. Likewise,
the field of philosophy as a whole might have some epistemic aim other than knowledge of first-order philosophical truths. For example, one such epistemic aim might be the acquisition of higher-order knowledge about how
first-order views are or are not supported by further considerations. Another such epistemic aim might be the
acquisition of a grasp of a kind which has epistemic value distinct from that of first-order knowledge.34 Another
such epistemic aim might concern non-doxastic, but nevertheless epistemically valuable, mental states concerning
first-order philosophical claims; 35 on some views, these epistemically valuable first-order mental states might help
constitute knowledge, but on others, they will not.
I leave it as a further question how these points should be made to hang together in an ultimate theory
of philosophy’s aims.36
REFERENCES
Annas, J. and Barnes, J. (1985), The Modes of Scepticism: Ancient Texts and Modern Interpretations (Cambridge University
Press).
Arroyo, G. (2019), ‘Philosophical Disagreement and the Value-Laden Nature of Philosophy,’ in Contemporary Pragmatism, 16/4: 396-413.
Ballantyne, N. (2014), ‘Knockdown Arguments,’ in Erkenntnis 79/3: 525-543.
Barnett, Z. (2019), ‘Philosophy without Belief,’ in Mind 128/509: 109-138.
Bird, A. (2007), ‘What is Scientific Progress?,’ in Noûs, 41(1): 64-89.
Blackford, R. (2017), ‘Introduction 1: Philosophy and the Perils of Progress,’ in R. Blackford and D. Broderick
For the view that there are no successful philosophical arguments concerning the core questions, see, e.g.,
Lewis (1983: x) and Van Inwagen (2009 :105, cf. 34). Cf. Ballantyne (2014) and Kelly and McGrath (2017).
34 McSweeney (2023a, 2023b, and this volume). See Nozick (1983: Introduction), Golding (2011), and Pigliucci
(2017) for discussion of views on which philosophy has some epistemic aim other than truth or knowledge. See
Ross (2021) for a framework that understands both philosophical and scientific progress in terms of dynamical
community inquiry.
35 See, for instance, Goldman’s (2013) claim that philosophers’ view are special kinds of speculations and Barnett’s (2019) claim that philosophers’ views are disagreement-insulated inclinations. Cf. Jackson (this volume).
36 For extremely helpful feedback on this paper, I am indebted to: Josh Armstrong, Liam Kofi Bright, Emmalon
Davis, Daniela Dover, Adam Elga, Will Fleischer, Sandy Goldberg, Liz Jackson, Sarah McGrath, Michaela
McSweeney, Ben Morison, Ram Neta, Gideon Rosen, Susanna Schellenberg, Matt Walker, Snow Zhang, participants of my 2018 graduate seminar at Princeton University, and audiences at: the Desert Metaphysics Workshop,
the Philosophy with Attitude Conference at New Mexico State University, and UNC-Chapel Hill.
33
(eds.), Philosophy's Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress. Wiley Blackwell.
Brennan, J. (2010), ‘Scepticism about Philosophy,’ in Ratio, 23/1: 1-16.
Bright, L. K. (2021), ‘The End of Analytic Philosophy,’ in The Sooty Empiric. <http://sootyem- piric.blogspot.com/2021/05/the-end-of-analytic-philosophy.html> Accessed June 8, 2021.
Brock, S. (2017), ‘Is Philosophy Progressing Fast Enough?’, in R. Blackford and D. Broderick (eds)., Philosophy’s
Future: The Problem of Philosophical progress, N.J.: Wiley Blackwell, 119-31.
Cappelen, H. (2017), ‘Disagreement in Philosophy: An Optimistic Perspective,’ in G. D'Oro and S. Overgaard
(eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Philosophical Methodology. Cambridge University Press.
Chalmers, D. J. (2015), ‘Why Isn't There More Progress in Philosophy?,’ in Philosophy: 3-31.
Cherry, M. (2017), ‘Coming out of the Shade,’ in R. Blackford and D. Broderick (eds.), Philosophy's Future: The
Problem of Philosophical Progress. Wiley Blackwell, 21-30.
Dietrich, E. (2010), ‘There is No Progress in Philosophy,’ in Essays in Philosophy 12/2010: 329-44
Fehr, C. (2011), ‘What Is in It For Me? The Benefits of Diversity in Scientific Communities,’ In H. Grasswick
(ed.)., Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, Springer, 133-155.
Gaus, G. (2019), The tyranny of the ideal: Justice in a diverse society (Princeton University Press).
Glanzberg, M. (2021), ‘Truth,’ in E. Zalta (ed)., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/ar- chives/sum2021/entries/truth/>. Accessed June 1, 2021.
Goldberg, S. (2009), ‘Reliabilism in Philosophy,’ in Philosophical Studies, 142: 105-117.
Goldberg, S. (2013), ‘Defending Philosophy in the Face of Systematic Disagreement,’ in D.E. Machua (ed)., Disagreement and Skepticism (Routledge), 277-294.
Golding, C. (2011), ‘A Conception of Philosophical Progress,’ in Essays in Philosophy, 12/2: 200-223.
Grasswick, H. (2018), ‘Feminist Social Epistemology,’ in N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2018/entries/femi- nist-social-epistemology/>. Accessed January 1, 2021.
Green, K. (2017), ‘Re-Imagining the Philosophical Conversation,’ in R. Blackford and D. Broderick (eds.), Philosophy's Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress, Wiley Blackwell, 201-12.
Intemann, K. (2011), ‘Diversity and dissent in science: Does democracy always serve feminist aims?,’ H. Grasswick (ed.), Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, Springer, 111-132.
Jackson, E. (this volume), ‘How Low Can You Go? A Defense of Believing Philosophical Theories,’ in S. Goldberg and M. Walker (eds.), Attitude in Philosophy, Oxford University Press.
Jones, W. E. (2017), ‘Philosophy, Progress, and Identity,’ in R. Blackford and D. Broderick (eds.), Philosophy's
Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress, Wiley Blackwell, 227-239.
Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., & Thaler, R. H. (1991), ‘Anomalies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion, and
Status Quo Bias,’ in Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5/1: 193-206.
Kamber, R. (2017), ‘Does Philosophical Progress Matter?,’ in R. Blackford and D. Broderick (eds.), Philosophy's
Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress, Wiley Blackwell, 133-43.
Kelly, T. (2016), ‘Disagreement in Philosophy: Its Epistemic Significance,’ in in H. Cappelen, T. Szabó Gendler,
and J. Hawthorne (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology, Oxfor University Press.
Kelly, T. and McGrath, S. (2010), ‘Is Reflective Equilibrium Enough?,’ in Philosophical Perspectives, 24: 325-59.
Kelly, T. and McGrath, S. (2017). Are There Any Successful Philosophical Arguments? in J. Keller (ed.), Being,
Freedom, and Method: Themes from the Philosophy of Peter Van Inwagen, Oxford University Press, 324-40.
Kornblith (2013), ‘Is Philosophical Knowledge Possible?’ in D. E. Machuca (ed.), Disagreement and Skepticism,
Routledge, 260–76.
Lewis, David (1983), Philosophical Papers, Volume I (Oxford University Press).
Lin, E. (2016), ‘How To Use The Experience Machine,’ in Utilitas, 28/3: 314-332.
Longino, H. (1990), Science as Social Knowledge (Princeton University Press).
Longino, H. (2002), The Fate of Knowledge (Princeton University Press).
Longino, H, and Doell, R. (1983), ‘Body, Bias and Behavior: A Comparative Analysis of Reasoning in Two Areas
of Biological Science,’ in Signs, 9/2: 206–227.
Lycan, W. G. (2013), ‘On Two Main Themes in Gutting’s What Philosophers Know,’ in The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 51: 112-120.
Lynch, M (2001), The Nature of Truth: Classical and Contemporary Perspectives (MIT Press).
Lynch, M (2009), Truth as One and Many (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
McSweeney, M. (2023a). ‘Why Mary Left Her Room’, in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (online first).
McSweeney, M. M. (2023b), ‘Metaphysics as Essentially Imaginative and Aiming at Understanding,’ in American
Philosophical Quarterly, 60/1: 83-97.
McSweeney, M. (this volume), ‘Understanding in Science and Philosophy,’ in S. Goldberg and M. Walker (eds.),
Attitude in Philosophy, Oxford University Press.
Morison, B., ‘Sextus Empiricus,’ in E.N. Zalta (ed)., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/sextus-empiricus/>.
Muldoon, R. (2013), ‘Diversity and the Division of Cognitive Labor,’ in Philosophy Compass, 8/2: 117- 125.
Muldoon, R. (2016). Social Contract Theory for a Diverse World: Beyond Tolerance (Taylor & Francis).
Muldoon, R., Lisciandra, C., Colyvan, M., Martini, C., Sillari, G., & Sprenger, J. (2014), ‘Disagreement Behind the
Veil of Ignorance,’ in Philosophical Studies, 170/3: 377-394.
Nozick, R. (1974), Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Basic Books).
Nozick, R. (1981), Philosophical Explanations (Harvard University Press).
Pigliucci, M. (2017), ‘Philosophy as the Evocation of Conceptual Landscapes,’ in R. Blackford and D. Broderick
(eds.), Philosophy's Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress. Wiley Blackwell, 75-90.
Priest, G. (2006), Contradiction (Oxford University Press).
Rawls, J. (1974), ‘The Independence of Moral Theory,’ in Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 48/1975: 5-22.
Rawls, J. (1999), Collected Papers (Harvard University Press).
Riggle, N. (2021), ‘Convergence, Community, and Force in Aesthetic Discourse,’ in Ergo: An Open Access Journal
of Philosophy, 8: 615-57.
Rescher, N. (2014), Philosophical Progress: And Other Philosophical Studies (Walter de Gruyter).
Ross, L. (2021), ‘How Intellectual Communities Progress,’ in Episteme. 18/4: 738-756.
Shand, J. (2017), ‘Philosophy Makes No Progress, So What Is The Point of It?,’ in Metaphilosophy, 48/3: 284-295.
Slezak, P. P. (2018), ‘Is there progress in philosophy? The case for taking history seriously,’ in Philosophy, 93/4:
529-555.
Stoljar, D. (2017a), ‘Is there Progress in Philosophy? A Brief Case for Optimism,’ in R. Blackford and D. Broderick
(eds.), Philosophy's Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress, Wiley Blackwell, 107-18.
Stoljar, D. (2017b), Philosophical Progress: In Defence of a Reasonable Optimism (Oxford University Press).
Unger, P. (1979), ‘I Do Not Exist,’ in G.F. MacDonald (ed.), Perception and Identity, Macmillan, 235-251.
van Inwagen, Peter. (1990), Material Beings (Cornell University Press).
van Inwagen, P. (2004), ‘Freedom to Break the Laws,’ in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 28/1: 334-350.
van Inwagen, P. (2006), The Problem of Evil (Oxford University Press.)
van Inwagen, P. (2009), Metaphysics, 3rd Edn. (Boulder, CO: Westview Press)
Walker, M. (2017), ‘Between Gods and Apes: On the Lack of Scientific and Philosophical Progress,’ in R. Blackford and D. Broderick (eds)., Philosophy's Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress, Wiley Blackwell, 14758.
Walker, M. (2022), ‘Epistemic Permissiveness and the Problem of Philosophical Disagreement,’ in Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review/Revue canadienne de philosophie, 61/2: 285-309.
Weijers, D. (2013), ‘Intuitive Biases in Judgments about Thought Experiments: The Experience Machine Revisited,’ in Philosophical Writings, 41/1: 17-31.
Weijers, D. (2014), ‘Nozick's Experience Machine Is Dead, Long Live the Experience Machine!,’ in Philosophical
Psychology, 27/4: 513-535.
Williamson, T. (2010), ‘Must Do Better,’ in P. Greenough & M. Lynch (eds.), Truth and Realism, Oxford University
Press, 177-81.
Wilson, J. (2017), ‘Three Barriers to Philosophical Progress,’ In R. Blackford and D. Broderick (eds.), in Philosophy’s
Future: The Problem of Philosophical Progress, Wiley Blackwell, 91-104.
Wright, C. (1992), Truth and Objectivity (Harvard University Press).
Wright, C. (1999), ‘Truth: A Traditional Debate Reviewed,’ in Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 24: 31–74.
Wright, C. (2013), ‘A Plurality of Pluralisms,’ in N. Pedersen and C.D. Wright (eds.), Truth and Pluralism: Current
Debates, Oxford University Press, 123-153.
Žanić, J. (2020), ‘On the Nature of Philosophy,’ Metaphilosophy, 51/1: 3-13.