Educating the secular citizen in English schools, 1897–1938
Susannah Wright
None of the major English secularist organisations 1 in the early twentieth century could boast
about membership figures as an indicator of their strength and influence. Compared with most
Christian churches, and as a proportion of the general population, they were small. They did,
however, claim to have achieved a diffuse impact on wider societal thinking and debate. National
Secular Society (NSS) leaders, for example, asserted that the ideals and ideas that they stood for
had gained “a hold on the public mind”. Oxford classicist Professor Gilbert Murray stated that
the “spirit” of Positivism had “got abroad” at a time when only remnants of Positivist
organisations remained. 2 These were outcomes that secularists strove, actively, to achieve.
Energetic and canny publicists, they disseminated their ideas in letters and personal conversation,
on the platform, and in print. Their influence in scientific, literary and left-leaning political circles
has been noted; by the early twentieth century, a growing scientific and social-scientific elite,
influential in governance and welfare movements, might not have joined secularist bodies, but
sympathised with some of their arguments. 3 Secularists also targeted the captive audience of
young people who were compelled to spend five days a week, over much of the year, in schools.
Through pressure groups, they lobbied educational authorities, and produced teaching aids,
aiming to shape the teaching in schools in ways that would promote their interests. Not least
among these interests was the desire to instil the knowledge, values and behaviours that would
prepare pupils for their future lives as adult citizens, but outside of a Christian framework. This
desire sat within a broad discourse about the purposes of schooling in England, one of longstanding which pre-and post-dates the timeframe of the analysis here. As well as imparting
academic knowledge, schools, it was argued, should develop in pupils the knowledge, values, and
behaviours that they would require as adult citizens. These were concerns which appear to have
taken on a particular urgency in the early twentieth century, owing to widespread perceptions of
intense, and unprecedented, social, cultural, political, and ideological change. 4 Secularists sought
to shape the civic morality that would be taught in schools in their own image. Through
influencing policy-makers, teachers and pupils, secularist campaigners, some of whom were or
had been teachers or inspectors themselves, challenged assumptions that England was
inherently, and inevitably, Christian. 5 But the process of shaping a non-Christian civic morality
was a complex one, involving shifting alliances, dialogue, and compromises between different
secularists, and between secularists and Christians. 6
1
Citizenship, by the turn of the twentieth century, was frequently understood as an
individual’s membership of the nation state community. Membership was defined by legal and
political frameworks linking the individual with the state, and also a diffuse set of qualities and
identifiers of national identity which could relate to any or all of empire, countryside, Protestant
Christianity, and the Anglo-Saxon race. 7 Local and international dimensions of citizenship, also,
had significant purchase in this period; the international community of the “world citizen” of the
inter-war years is important for my purposes here. 8 Secularist campaigners’ primary concern was
the extent to which Christianity was perceived as a marker of English citizenship among
contemporaries, within and beyond schools: empire and race mattered to them too, but to a
lesser degree. They were aware that religious instruction lessons were commonly valued for their
contribution to individuals’ moral development and a virtuous and cohesive society, 9 and
Christian figures were held up as role models in teaching texts. 10 Secularists promoted as an
alternative teaching on a purely “social” or “humanist” basis. I will consider, as interconnected
case studies, two attempts to promote such teaching. An Ethical Movement-dominated pressure
group, the Moral Instruction League (MIL) (1897–c.1924) campaigned for what it termed “nontheological” moral teaching in English schools as the most effective approach to forming
citizens. And Frederick James Gould worked within the League of Nations Union (LNU) (1919–
38) to publicise his Positivist-flavoured version of world citizenship. 11 I will examine the
educational proposals that the MIL and Gould within the LNU offered, and the institutional and
intellectual resources that they drew on. I will analyse the responses that their efforts elicited
from educators, and a wider public of Christian and secularist commentators.
The MIL’s and LNU’s educational activities have been scrutinised in previous studies. 12
The new contribution offered here lies in examining these groups’ campaigns as a strand of
secularists’ evangelism, their efforts to reach beyond the relatively small membership of their
organisations and seek influence over questions of wide social import. Such an approach to the
MIL and LNU requires consideration not only of these organisations’ records and publications,
but of the records and publications of secularist groups too. Secularists aimed to act as “agents
of secularisation”, to adopt a concept long-used in historical, sociological, and anthropological
research. 13 They wanted to entice new recruits to their organisations, and to reshape English
culture and institutions in their image. An emphasis on these attempts at evangelism, outreach
and attempts at wider cultural influence challenges older theories of secularist organisational
decline after the nineteenth century. 14 There is novelty also in considering two campaigns
together over 41 years, and evaluating continuity and change. Activists worked within a shifting
educational and religious context, starting with a period of interdenominational contest, but
2
witnessing a rise in ecumenical efforts in the interwar years. This was also a period of change
within secularist bodies. The Ethical Movement reached a peak of organisational activity and
membership in the Edwardian era. It provided networks, publications, personnel and even an
educational programme, all of which proved central to the MIL’s campaigns. F. J. Gould, within
the LNU, drew relatively little on formal Positivist organisational channels, which were limited
by the interwar years. But he found in his own version of Positivist thought inspiration for his
educational activity. These campaigns constitute an ongoing form of secularist activity which
could take varying forms, but which resonates with the campaigns of secularist bodies today.
Examining these educational crusades, therefore, contributes to a growing historiography
of secularism. A spotlight on this aspect of secularist designs on English institutions, ideas, and
culture offers new insights into secularist organisations and the ways in which their ideas and
ideals “got abroad”. I also add to a historiography of educating the young for citizenship within,
and beyond, schools. Historians have been alert to the frequently Christian foundations of such
an education, while also paying considerable attention to themes of empire and nation. 15
Secularists’ campaigns for education for citizenship in schools have received considerably less
attention. The combining of case studies here adds to the studies that do exist by highlighting the
ongoing nature of secularists’ ongoing contributions to a broader discourse about the civic
purposes of education, and by revealing elements of long-term secular influence in English
schools.
Yet any influence attained was limited, and could operate in complex, sometimes
unintended ways. Secularists combined behind common goals, but disagreed with one another
on ideals and strategies. They sought out Christian allies to help them create and promote
educational schemes that were intended to include all. But they also critiqued widespread
Christian educational practices, either by explicit challenges to the prominence of religious
instruction as a tool for developing citizens (as with the MIL), or by providing what they deemed
a superior alternative (as with the LNU). Activists might not have been able to “secularise”
citizenship in English schools to the extent that they desired; they failed to achieve all they set
out to. But secularist bodies achieved some influence over educational authorities, local and
national, and their publications reached many thousands of teachers and pupils in schools. The
available primary sources, unfortunately, tell us very little about how far their proposals had a
direct impact on teachers’ day to day educational practice or views about civic morality, or on
pupils. I argue, also, for an influence on wider educational and public debates, though not always
the sort of influence that campaigners intended. In response to secularist proposals, Christian
perspectives were re-examined, reframed, improved, and restated. Secularist claims could be
3
accommodated (perhaps partially), resisted, or ignored. And responses among secularists, too,
were similarly varied. Ultimately, a minority perspective was unable to win over a majority in a
nation that, notwithstanding elements of religious weakness or decline, remained in many
respects a Christian one.
Religion, secularism and education
Early twentieth century commentators painted a mixed picture of the vitality of Christianity
within English culture and society. Christians described a national community, with common
positive characteristics, such as a sense of duty, based on shared Christian traditions. But they
were also concerned about the un-churched slum child and a hedonistic and overly-commercial
“secular age”. 16 Secularists were no less ambivalent. The Positivist Malcolm Quin proclaimed the
“death of Christianity”, while the NSS argued that public avowal of secularist views would, in all
but a very few schools, preclude promotion to a headship. 17 These commentators were not
disinterested observers. Claims about the significance of Christianity could, for Christians,
reassure believers, and, for secularists, galvanise efforts to promote change. Claims about
Christian decline could, conversely, provide a rallying cry for Christians and solace for the
secularist minority.
Historians in recent years have tended to side with those commentators who noted
Christian vitality in this period. The significance of Christian ideals and practices in domestic,
community and national life, even among those who did not attend church, has been
emphasised. 18 Church attendance and membership, at an aggregate level, declined only gradually
during the first half of the twentieth century, and participation in Christian rites of passage
remained high; regularity of church attendance, did, perhaps, decline more rapidly. 19 Such
findings have challenged older theories of secularisation, which had it as an inevitable side-effect
of modernisation and urbanisation and a process well underway by the early twentieth century.
This is not to ignore indications of religious doubt; the oft-noted Victorian and Edwardian
middle-class “crisis of faith”, and the respectable agnosticism among public intellectuals in the
interwar years. 20 Nonetheless, beyond these particular groups, there is evidence to suggest that
significant decline in Christian observance or professed belief did not occur until the 1960s.
Whether this change in the 1960s was a “religious crisis”, a sudden “death” of Christian Britain,
or the culmination of a more gradual process of the “passing” of protestant England is the
subject of debate. 21 A differentiated analysis of religious institutions has been proposed,
distinguishing between influence on social and educational policy, membership and attendance,
and cultural impact, allowing, simultaneously, for elements of strength and weakness. 22 Some
4
have questioned the very existence of a uni-directional pattern of religious decline, emphasising
instead the variety of religious experience and constant religious change. 23
Secularism has, only very recently, been taken seriously as part of these debates. Yet a
plethora of organisations offered non-Christians an alternative associational, intellectual and in
some cases spiritual life to that provided by the Christian churches. 24 These organisations were
united by the assumption that supernatural belief was erroneous, and also by the conviction that
men (to use the language of the time) possessed the power to shape their world and determine
their futures without recourse to a deity. 25 But they differed in their clientele and their ideas
about how best to engage with Christian organisations and religious belief.
The largest and most prominent groups, Secularists, Positivists and the Ethical
Movement are central to my narrative. Secularism was the first to emerge on British soil, in the
1840s. Organisationally and ideologically rooted in Owenite radicalism, Secularists sought to
expose the intellectual faults of Christianity, and fought against the exclusion of non-Christians
from full political and social rights. Membership of the NSS, dominated by skilled artisans,
reached about 4000 in the mid-1880s at the height of Charles Bradlaugh’s attempts to enter
parliament without swearing a biblical oath. Numbers declined steadily to an estimated 700 in
1948. 26 The Positivist Political and Social Union, with its ideals and political programme firmly
rooted in the philosophy of Auguste Comte, was established in London in 1867. Dominated by
middle-class professionals, membership peaked at less than 300 in the 1890s. But through
prominent sympathisers among the late nineteenth and early twentieth century progressive
intellectual elite, including George Eliot, Thomas Hardy, and George Gissing, and sympathetic
academics like Patrick Geddes and Gilbert Murray, Positivism gained, T. R. Wright suggests, a
wide, if diffuse, cultural influence. 27 The Ethical Movement, which emerged in England in the
1880s, also attracted an educated middle-class clientele, predominantly left-leaning in its politics.
Elements of philosophical idealism, the transcendentalism of Ralph Waldo Emerson, and social
activism, were combined in an eclectic and somewhat loosely defined programme. Membership
of the Union of Ethical Societies reached 2000 in 1912, but then fell. 28 All these bodies retained
some organisational presence through the interwar years, notwithstanding numerical decline.
And, beyond formal secularist organisational channels, adherents continued to seek a wider
influence of secularist ideals through their publications, and activism within a range of other
organisations, including pressure groups working in schools.
The main secularist bodies differed in their attitudes to Christianity, and, consequently, in
how they interacted with Christians. Positivists and ethicists, along with other contemporary
groups such as the theosophists, aimed to build on the best of Christian beliefs and practices
5
(and those of other world faiths). They offered spiritual alternatives, in the form of the Religion
of Humanity for Positivists and for ethicists the Ethical Ideal, and devised rudimentary forms of
worship. Without the trappings of “theology” (the belief in a supernatural being of older faiths),
religion would support and help individuals, and be a unifying social force. 29 “Religion” thus
conceived, emphasising emotional impact, common experience, unity of purpose, and shared
moral values, not necessarily tied to theological beliefs, would help create civic ideals and
practices that would include all, whether they believed in a God or not. Their notions of religion,
indeed, resonated with contemporary ideological and organisational developments including the
religion of socialism, Socialist Sunday Schools and the Labour Church. 30 And, in order to
promote religion as they defined it, ethicists and Positivists would work with sympathetic, usually
liberal, Christians. But, as J. H. Muirhead, founder of London Ethical Society in 1886, and, later,
professor of philosophy and political economy at Birmingham, acknowledged, many Christian
contemporaries continued to see religion as implying a God. 31 Most NSS members, however,
perceived no value in Christianity and drew attention to its limitations. They sought no spiritual
equivalent, seeking a secular future without religious influences of any sort. Attempts to develop
a religion without theology were “useless or misleading”. 32 These different understandings of
religion and its place (or otherwise) in the broader civic sphere form an important context for
understanding the arguments and choices of secularist activists campaigning to influence
teaching in schools.
The Moral Instruction League
On 7 December 1897, members of the Social Democratic Federation, the Independent Labour
Party, trade unions, the Union of Ethical Societies, the NSS, and other “progressive bodies” met
at St Martin’s Town Hall in London. 33 At this meeting, the Moral Instruction League (MIL) was
formed. The MIL promoted “systematic” moral instruction in state schools, its pedagogy of
direct moral teaching (“lessons or talks dedicated to the subject” 34) contrasting with more
popular indirect approaches whereby good citizenship was to be absorbed as a by-product of the
school ethos, curriculum content or extra-curricular activities. 35 Early campaigns were Londonfocused, but the MIL became a nationally-oriented body that canvassed school boards and local
education authorities (LEAs), the Board of Education at Whitehall, and teacher training colleges.
It created syllabuses and teachers’ handbooks for use in schools, and offered rudimentary
professional development for teachers through demonstration lessons. 36 References to moral
instruction in the Board of Education’s 1904 and 1906 Codes of Regulations for Elementary Schools
and 1905 Suggestions for the Consideration of Teachers were thought at the time to reveal the MIL’s
6
influence; the existence of an intellectual elite who advocated a civic morality with secular
components might be relevant here. 37 Individual LEAs, however, were to decide how moral
instruction would be delivered; 60 out of 327 opted for “more or less systematic moral
instruction” along MIL lines. 38 Devolving decision making to the local level enabled the Board of
Education to avoid alienating powerful church lobbies, the MIL noted, somewhat bitterly. 39 In
1909 a change of title to the Moral Education League signalled less parliamentary lobbying and
more curriculum development, and F. J. Gould was employed from 1910 to 1915 as paid
demonstrator to promote the MIL’s work among teachers on the ground. Attention was, from
1914, increasingly focused on civics, adult education, and regional surveys; further name changes
to the Civic and Moral Education League in 1914 and the Civic Education League in 1919
captured this shift in emphasis. After 1920, the MIL moved its offices to LePlay House, home of
the Sociological Society and kindred bodies. In 1925 its school-oriented activities, by then
subsumed into LePlay House’s civics teaching department, merited only a sentence in publicity
material. 40
Although other groups were involved in the League, the Ethical Movement was
dominant, offering ideological and organisational resources. The MIL’s key officers, including
Gould, Harrold Johnson (Secretary from 1902 to 1913), and Gustav Spiller, were all paid Ethical
Movement workers around the turn of the twentieth century. 41 Prominent supporters had strong
Ethical Movement credentials. G. P. Gooch, for example, historian and Liberal MP for Bristol
1906 to 1910, who spoke on behalf of the MIL in parliament and before the Board of
Education, was an early member of the West London Ethical Society and President of the
Ethical Union from 1933 to 1935. The MIL’s educational approach of direct moral instruction,
also, had Ethical Movement roots. Felix Adler, founder of the first ethical culture society in New
York in 1876, introduced a graduated programme of moral lessons in his ethical culture school in
that city which he published in book form in 1892. His book was, for the MIL, the “the pioneer
work from which our modern moral education movement has sprung”. 42 The moral instruction
circle organised by the Union of Ethical Societies for London-based teachers was an immediate
precursor to the MIL’s activities, and the Sunday Schools of local ethical societies provided a
“field of experiment” that activists would draw on in their MIL work. 43 Earlier, smaller scale,
efforts to introduce secular moral instruction in England by liberal Christians and socialists
wanting to end interdenominational battles over schooling were not acknowledged in the same
way. The same was true of contemporary international developments, such as the morale laïque in
French schools and a growing interest, beyond the Ethical Movement, in civic education in the
USA. 44
7
From its inception, the MIL associated moral instruction with creating citizens. An early
pamphlet was entitled Our Future Citizens. Other publications explained the nature of this
association in detail. Writing on behalf of the MIL, Gould defined citizenship not as a “general
sentiment of fraternity towards all mankind” but “the feeling of responsibility and the habit of
service” within “a definitely organized community”. The “modern state” had “developed a
highly complex demand upon the citizen’s devotion”, and therefore needed to work through its
schools to “[form] the habits, and [construct] the ideals, of the citizenship on which its very
existence depends”. 45 The MIL also referenced a wider “humanity” beyond the nation state,
presaging the world citizen of the interwar years. 46 Preparing pupils for citizenship so defined
would, for the MIL, best be achieved through systematic moral instruction in schools; “the
formation of personal good character” was “the condition … of good citizenship”. 47
The MIL’s linking of individual character and a unified community of citizens was
uncontroversial. It echoed the broadly idealist conceptions of citizenship so popular in socialpolicy discourse at the time, as well as older versions of Christian civic morality, and republican
traditions of moral virtue. 48 Basing moral instruction lessons only on “the strictly human reasons
for right conduct”, however, was less typical. Forming citizens of the state in schools, the MIL
claimed, required a core of moral sanctions acceptable to all members of that state, “people of all
theologies or none”. Sanctions deriving from a Christian God were not acceptable to all
members of the state. Religious instruction lessons were, therefore, an inappropriate vehicle for
teaching citizenship in schools. Moreover, these lessons failed to address important moral
subjects relevant to early twentieth century social life, including hygiene, industry, and civic life in
a modern democracy. 49 And interdenominational conflicts over religious instruction, for the
MIL, absorbed the churches’ attention; busy fighting over “shadowy religious questions”, they
neglected to teach “the duties of citizenship”. 50
Yet the universal moral code that the MIL proposed as an alternative, outlined in its
Graduated Syllabus and recommended moral instruction texts, did not deviate far from standard
Judaeo-Christian morality. Desirable moral qualities were expressed as a series of abstract nouns.
Teaching for Infants to Standard II was to address personal traits, such as kindliness,
truthfulness, and self-control, but framed so as to embody the notion of duty towards others,
these traits could form the basis of civic virtue. Social themes like justice, humanity and
patriotism were to be covered by children in Standards III to V. Complex and potentially
controversial subjects – for example, cooperation, peace and war, ownership, and ideals – was
reserved for pupils in Standards VI and VII; it is in relation to these themes that the left-leaning
and (sometimes) pacifist views of MIL activists are revealed. 51 Much of the content for younger
8
students was uncontentious, and in keeping with other teaching texts of the period. Under the
heading of patriotism, for example, students were encouraged to recognise positive national
characteristics (freedom of thought and action, democracy) and to serve their country.
Exemplars of patriotic virtue, nearly all men, included English historical and military leaders,
alongside a few international figures: Wellington, Nelson, Alfred the Great, General Gordon,
Joan of Arc, and Washington. But references to Irish and Indian claims for self-rule as a form of
patriotic expression are less typical and embody wider secularist ambivalence about imperial
expansion. 52
Commentary of the time endorsed the MIL’s emphasis on moral education and character
training. There was also support for addressing “the relations of the individual to the State and to
society”, and for basing teaching on “an ideal of personal and civic obligation”. 53 The MIL’s
purely human morality, however, proved controversial. It attracted favourable comment from
some teachers, 54 and a cross-section of Christians, who identified themselves as “modern” or
“inclusive”, and deemed inter-denominational rivalry in education inimical to the interests of
their faith. 55 However, a wider educational and general public were, more frequently, sceptical.
For a core of Christians that crossed denominational boundaries, the MIL’s association with
organised secularism rendered it “anti-religious”, 56 and its proposals were incomplete and
inadequate. Children needed to learn not only duties towards other people, which the Graduated
Syllabus covered, but also duties towards God. Only Christianity, with its promise of future
reward and threat of future punishment, would motivate pupils to be good. The MIL’s “virtuous
men and women”, Randall Davidson, Archbishop of Canterbury, claimed in 1903, were no
substitute for the ultimate moral exemplar, Jesus Christ. 57 Reference was also made to a national
community with shared Christian origins. For Mr Robert Duncan, Conservative MP for
Glasgow, speaking in a House of Commons debate on moral instruction in 1909, it was only by
the Bible that a “Christian nation” would “proceed to prosperity in the future”. 58 The MIL’s
proposals, he argued, would not suffice.
The MIL was willing to cooperate with and accommodate Christians, to an extent. The
MIL’s object, as stated at its first business meeting on 26 January 1898, was “to substitute
systematic non-theological moral instruction for the present religious teaching in all State
schools, and to make character the chief aim of all school life”. By 1902 the demand that
religious teaching should be removed had gone. 59 MIL activists, and commentators outside the
organisation, deemed this change responsible for a growing following outside organised
freethought, particularly among liberal Nonconformists and broad church Anglicans. Unitarian
minister Charles Peace promoted the MIL’s cause through the correspondence columns of the
9
Manchester Guardian. 60 Reverend Hugh Chapman was a prominent Anglican advocate who invited
Gould to give demonstration lessons in his chapel at the Savoy. 61 The MIL also sought Christian
allies in its parliamentary activity, courting Nonconformist support when seeking to influence the
Liberal Party’s 1908 Education Bill, and appreciating the patronage of a few Anglican and
Roman Catholic MPs in its campaigns to influence the 1906 Code. 62 Sophisticated schemes
encompassing both religious and moral instruction emerged as a direct response to the MIL’s
educational proposals and materials. Canon E. R. Bernard’s 56-page Scheme of Moral Instruction,
devised for Salisbury Diocesan Board of Education in 1907, referenced the MIL’s efforts, and
aimed to facilitate “systematic moral teaching”. This teaching was to be illustrated by the Bible
alone, and the scheme had as its foundations “God … the power of prayer … and judgment to
come”. 63 Bernard’s syllabus, the MIL noted, demonstrated that Christian educators could learn
from secularists and adopt some of their suggestions. 64 But in so doing, Bernard and others
offered a competitor model likely to appeal to many Christian teachers.
Christian critics might have been surprised at how deeply matters of religion divided
secularists within the MIL itself. Ethical Movement activists frequently wanted to align their
promotion of moral instruction with their understanding of religion (as distinct from
“theology”). Moral instruction, one claimed, would create a “religious spirit” in schools which
could “spring as holy and undefiled from lay and secular sources as from priests and
Churches”. 65 The Bible was valued as a source of illustration for moral instruction lessons which
contained valuable historical and ethical content; its “theological” elements could be ignored. 66
Harrold Johnson went further than others, experiencing a “crisis of doubt” and returning to the
Christian fold. 67 Johnson had trained as a Unitarian minister before he joined the Ethical
Movement. Over time he came to question the efficacy of moral instruction without a Christian
foundation. In 1913, “developments in his religious views” led him to resign as Secretary of the
MIL, and he resumed his Unitarian ministry. 68 NSS members, on the other hand, rejecting ideas
of an equivalent religion, argued that all instruction in schools should be “secular”, dealing only
with “the demonstrable facts of life”. 69 The MIL’s emerging stance on the Bible was objected to
as an Ethical Movement formulation which failed to satisfy other secularists. Any use of the
Bible in schools was “opposed to the principle of secular education”, the NSS Executive argued
in 1899, and on these grounds it terminated its formal organisational affiliation with the MIL. 70
There is truth in a contemporary critic’s assessment that the MIL’s influence on
educational policy and public debate was “out of all proportion with [its] modest resources”. Yet
it failed to achieve all that it set out to. 71 Its favoured pedagogical method of direct moral
instruction was, as already noted, at odds with more fashionable “indirect” approaches. Some
10
might, potentially, also have been troubled by radical views on empire in some of its teaching
materials, though this attracted scant comment. It was the MIL’s attitude to and relationships
with religion, and specifically Christianity, that proved most controversial. For critics, a Christian
rather than a “human” morality should be taught in schools. Secularists, on the other hand, could
not agree among themselves over the appropriateness of “religious” texts or concepts. The MIL
stimulated debate and curriculum development, and gained some support, but many politicians
and teachers, and even some secularists, remained unconvinced that its approach was the right
one. A unifying civic morality proved elusive.
F. J. Gould and the world citizen
After 1919, concepts of citizenship permeated educational discourse, perhaps to an even greater
extent than before, but were to take on new forms. 72 The First World War had revealed the
dangers of excessive military aggression and nationalism. Commitments to nation state and
Empire were still expressed, but with a greater emphasis than previously on benevolence and
moral duty, 73 and these commitments were supplemented by an emphasis on a broader
international sphere. Schools, according to many interwar-years educators, should produce
citizens not only of the nation state, but also of the world. Internationalist interests were
expressed through efforts to include more international content in existing subjects, notably
history and geography. 74 Outside the formal curriculum, new, internationally-oriented, youth
movements, such as the Junior Red Cross, were often attached to schools, and a greater
international focus became evident in the activities of existing events (Empire Day) and
movements (Boy Scouts and Girl Guides). 75 Particularly ambitious initiatives were devised in
connection with the League of Nations. The League of Nations Union was established in
November 1918. It aimed to promote the newly-formed League of Nations among politicians
and the general public, and, more broadly, to “foster mutual understanding … and habits of cooperation ... between the peoples of different countries”. 76 From late 1919 an Education
Committee campaigned for what contemporaries called “League teaching” in English schools. It
lobbied central and local educational authorities, school governing bodies, training colleges and
educational associations, produced curriculum materials and teaching aids, organised events for
teachers, and co-ordinated a range of extra-curricular activities. League teaching was intended to
develop knowledge about the aims, structure, and activities of the League of Nations, and to
create in pupils a sense of “world citizenship”. The Board of Education reported in 1932 that all
but a very few LEAs provided League teaching of some form. International events from the
mid-1930s, however, led to a decline in public support for the League of Nations and the LNU’s
11
pressure group tactics, and the Education Committee was reconstituted as the semi-autonomous
Council for Education in World Citizenship in 1939. 77
World citizenship proved difficult to define precisely, lacking the familiar legal and
political frameworks, patriotic sentiments and cultural markers associated with the nation state.
The LNU emphasised less than the MIL the development of personal moral attributes. Its
proposals for world citizenship, however, would develop in pupils “a positive desire for
international justice and a sense of world loyalty”, and the recognition of “a moral obligation
towards every other being in the world, irrespective of colour, race or creed”. 78 For many within
the LNU, an organisation with a predominantly Christian “spiritual core”, 79 it was assumed that
the ideological foundation of such attributes would be Christian. The LNU’s Christian
Organisations Committee targeted the church hierarchy and worshippers on the ground. The
League of Nations, it was argued, enabled the world to come closer to ideals of the Christian
faith, namely world peace and a universal brotherhood of man; English commitment to the
League, therefore, should rest on Christian foundations. 80 A Christian moral framework is
similarly evident in Education Committee publications. In 1938 William Temple, then
Archbishop of York, was commissioned to write the annual Armistice Day message. There are
brief, but telling, references in other texts. “The children of our Father in Heaven”, wrote Lillian
Dalton in her League of Nations Stories in 1924, should “[learn] to know and love each other
better”. 81 The Education Committee, it appears, thought it acceptable and appropriate to convey
explicitly Christian messages through material issued to schools.
Some provision, also, was made within the LNU for other faiths, and for secularist
bodies. The LNU’s Religion and Ethics Committee, never particularly active or powerful,
included, alongside Christians, representatives of different world faiths, spiritualism, theosophy,
and the Ethical Movement (but not the NSS or Positivists). 82 Indeed, the Ethical Movement was,
out of the major freethought organisation, the most consistently supportive of the League of
Nations project. But individual NSS members joined in local LNU branch activity, whilst
criticising local branches’ prayers and church services. 83 And Gould, his MIL demonstration
work having been terminated in 1915, worked during the interwar years, through the LNU’s
Education Committee, to promote his Positivist-flavoured version of world citizenship. Gould’s
primary secularist allegiance by this point was with Positivism. He ran a small Positivist group in
Leicester from 1908 to 1910, and after moving to London in 1910 lectured and produced
pamphlets for the Positivists there. He resigned from London Positivist Society in 1926, a body
by then in terminal numerical and organisational decline, but continued to elaborate his version
of the Positivist creed in his writings until his death in 1938. Gould’s approach to Positivism
12
involved adapting the teachings of Comte to the changing needs of the age, and working through
existing institutions to realise the advance of the Religion of Humanity. 84 The League of Nations,
for Gould, was an ideal institution for these purposes. With its emphasis on “cooperation and
conciliation” it had an affinity with Positivist aims. 85
Gould was not one of the well-connected educational intellectuals, administrators, and
representatives of teachers’ organisations who made up the mainstream of the Education
Committee; indeed, he was never a full Education Committee member. It is not clear how he
first became involved with the LNU. A possible scenario is that fellow Positivist F. S. Marvin,
Inspector of Schools from 1890 to 1924 and Education Committee member 1919 to 1939,
brought him to the notice of others. Marvin’s school and college friend, the Oxford classicist
Gilbert Murray (vice chairman then chairman of the LNU 1923-38), could, presumably, have
pulled strings if necessary. 86 Through the 1920s, Gould toured the country giving “League storytalk[s]” to pupils, and wrote pamphlets on the League for use in schools. 87 And from 1924 till
shortly before his death in 1938, he edited, and wrote much of, League News, a newsletter for
pupils published three times a year. 88
The moral basis of the League, for Gould, rested in the “ethical consciousness of all
mankind”, which included people of “all types of faith” and those who had “no theological
beliefs”. An undue emphasis on Christianity in common LNU local branch practices, including
church services, he suggested, might encourage “habits of intellectual divergence”, in turn
creating a “spirit of war”. Against this backdrop, he aimed to create in League News an “all
humanist” alternative which “[treated] World Faiths and Moral Movements with equal
respect”. 89 Gould described his LNU work as “within the circle, liberally interpreted, of Moral
and Civic instruction”. 90 His narrative approach to League teaching was an extension of the
methods that he developed in his earlier moral instruction work. The machinery and activities of
the League of Nations, he suggested, should be embedded in a deep knowledge of the
“environment, traditions, and ideals” of each country; this would reveal “the essential likeness in
the souls of men all the world over”. 91 League News contained information about the League and
its member states, illustrated with photographs, pictures and maps. Gould wrote about historical
figures, and linked their activities with the current work of the League. He noted the humble
background of William Randall Cremer (1828-1908) of the International Arbitration League.
Elizabeth Fry’s (1780-1845) efforts to improve conditions in prison were linked to women’s
involvement in the League of Nations penal reform committee. 92 He devoted considerable space
to non-Christian and non-European League members. In 1932, for example, he described
Afghanistan’s entry into the League of Nations and the joyful response of other Arab members.
13
This commentary on current League affairs was preceded by a moral tale (about a tribal Afghan
boy’s kindness when returning a stray mule to its owners at an English army base) and discussion
of the country’s geographical features, industries, social conditions, and religious beliefs. 93 Whilst
retaining distinctions between primitive and civilised peoples common among his
contemporaries, Gould’s inclusion of all countries and all religious traditions challenged, albeit
implicitly, what he deemed an undue Western and Christian emphasis within the LNU at large.
With his talks, pamphlets, and League News’ regular circulation of up to 35,000, Gould’s
views reached a not insignificant audience. 94 But it is difficult to gauge the response to what he
proposed. In contrast with what Gould experienced within the MIL, there is no clear evidence of
disapproval of his stance on religion from within the LNU or from League News readers. What
this lack of evidence signifies is hard to interpret. His position might have been accepted, or
partially accommodated. Or, conversely, maybe his perspective was tolerated as a harmless
minority one from an ageing educator on the fringes of the Education Committee who could be
quietly ignored.
Conclusion: educating the secular citizen
Through these educational campaigns, secularists aimed to challenge prevailing orthodoxies
about the foundations of citizenship and to influence young people in English schools. Theirs
was a field of activism which reached beyond their admittedly small organisational limits.
Secularists’ interventions ensured that alternatives to the dominant narrative of a Christian
version of English citizenship were presented to a wide audience. In response, Christian
narratives were re-shaped, sometimes in subtle ways, or re-stated, with claims of business as
usual. Existing secularist narratives were, similarly, affected in different ways. Not only was there
a contest between religious and secular conceptions of citizenship, but Christians and secularists
were divided among themselves. The intended secularising of English citizenship proved to be a
complex, partial, and fragmented process. Yet campaigners had some, albeit limited, influence
on policy and practice; why this was the case is a matter for debate. Was it the tenacious and
skilful activism of secularists? Or was it more that their proposals chimed, partially, with currents
of popular thought (idealism and internationalism), or, alternatively, that some within influential
intellectual and governmental elites were disposed to countenance some secular morality in
schools? Beyond the scope of this article, questions remain. We can ascertain campaigners’
intentions and, particularly for the MIL, responses to their suggestions on the part of the
minority of teachers whose views were published. But the extent to which campaigns influenced
a wider cross-section of teachers and pupils in schools remains impossible to determine.
14
The MIL and F. J. Gould, through the LNU, intended to use schools to impart in the
rising generation a form of national and international citizenship which was founded on
secularist principles but which was accessible and appropriate for all, including Christians. By
emphasising so strongly this one form of citizenship, albeit an inclusive one, secularist educators
over 41 years rejected the possibility that different models of citizenship might coexist. And in
this they were more like the Christian educators they criticised than they might have cared to
admit. Secularism, moreover, like Christianity for other educators, provided organisational
resources that enabled the development and dissemination of educational proposals. But it was
also a component of wider cultural currents – to use Gilbert Murray’s words it “got abroad”. Yet
differences over time should also be recognised. The MIL condemned, explicitly, during a period
of intense interdenominational rivalry, a purely Christian basis for the teaching of citizenship. It
drew an equally explicit critical response from many, but its proposals for including all faiths and
none attracted some moderate Christians. Gould’s “all-humanist” version of world citizenship
was offered as an alternative to the LNU’s predominantly Christian offer. Any challenge was
implicit rather than explicit, and responses are equally unclear. The role of secularist
organisations and ideas in activists’ thinking and activities also changed. The Ethical Movement
offered an organisational framework and field of educational experiment which the MIL could
draw on. Gould, within the LNU, drew on Positivism less for organisational support than for
ideas and personal spiritual inspiration.
Like other secularists at the time, the MIL, and Gould within the LNU, perhaps
underestimated, or at least downplayed, the extent to which Christianity remained a significant
cultural and ideological force in educational and other spheres. They were, ultimately, unable to
overturn the apparently widespread conviction that citizenship for the English, whether of the
country or the world, had Christian foundations. This was not to change, in the short term at
least, after 1939. During the Second World War, Churchmen and politicians alike suggested that
only a Christian country could withstand secular Nazi aggression, and a lobby of Christian
educators proposed that this could only happen through religious education in all schools. The
1944 Education Act, with its provision for compulsory religious instruction and a daily act of
worship, affirmed within government policy a Christian vision of English citizenship. Secularist
educators, and individual teachers beyond the secularist organisational fold, criticised such
developments. But there was not a sustained pressure group campaign, wartime exigencies
hindering the Secular Education League’s efforts in this direction. 95
Yet the triumph of a Christian education for citizenship was not assured. Mass
Observation’s Puzzled People, published in 1947, noted confusion over personal religious beliefs
15
and limited understanding of Christian doctrine and tradition. Christian teaching in schools was
favoured, it was suggested, simply because few people had experienced alternative approaches to
moral and civic education. This observation might suggest that, despite reaching a wide audience
and stimulating debate, secularist campaigns between 1897 and 1939 had limited long-term
impact. Since the 1960s, the British Humanist Association (BHA), the organisational descendant
of the Ethical Movement, and the NSS have campaigned for a school curriculum which
adequately represents secular perspectives, and does not privilege Christianity or other faiths.
They have achieved some recognition among educators and politicians, but have been, and,
arguably, remain, less influential than the Christian churches and the representatives of other
religions. 96 English schools remain a site of contest between religious and secular conceptions of
citizenship. But, with recent surveys suggesting that those professing no faith outnumber those
who define themselves as Christian, the secular conceptions which were a minority perspective
might now reflect the views of a larger proportion of the population. The BHA proposes, on
lines recognisable from its predecessor’s suggestions, a “moral education of pupils across the
curriculum” based on “shared human values” that will prepare pupils for adult life in a pluralist
society. It notes the need to challenge the “still widespread assumption that morality depends on
religious belief”. 97 Elements of continuity and change discussed in this article can be traced
through to the present.
REFERENCES
* Acknowledgments: I would like to thank David Aldridge, Mark Freeman, Bill Gibson, Annie
Haight, Anne-Marie Kilday, John Stewart and Lucy Vickers for their invaluable comments on
earlier drafts.
1
Connection with the National Secular Society is indicated by capitalisation (Secularist), whilst
‘secularist’ (lower-case) denotes those attached to a range of freethought organisations (this
article is particularly concerned with the Ethical Movement, Positivists, and the National Secular
Society) and agnostic or atheist ideological positions.
2
“NSS Executive Annual Report,” The Freethinker, June 3, 1927, 357–8; G. Murray to F. S.
Marvin, January 24, 1936, MS.Eng.Lett.c.268, fol. 95, Papers of Francis Sydney Marvin, Special
Collections, Bodleian Library.
3
For example, Michael Rectenwald, Nineteenth Century British Secularism (Basingstoke: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2016); Liz Lutgendorff, “Agents of Secularisation in the 20th Century”. Paper
presented at the International Society for Historians of Atheism, Secularism and Humanism
16
Inaugural Conference, Conway Hall, London, June 4-5 2016; T. R. Wright, The Religion of
Humanity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986).
4
B. Beaven and J. Griffiths “Creating the Exemplary Citizens: The Changing Notion of
Citizenship in Britain 1870–1939,” Contemporary British History 22:2 (2008): 203–25; J. Romein, The
Watershed of Two Eras. Europe in 1900, trans. A. J. Pomerans (Middletown, CT: Wesleyan
University Press, 1978).
5
Callum Brown, The Death of Christian Britain, 2nd edn (London: Routledge, 2009) argues for an
essentially ‘Christian’ nation during this period.
6
For a parallel emphasis on dialogue between the religious and the secular, and shifting alliances,
see David Nash, Christian Ideals in British Culture: Stories of Belief (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan,
2013); Rectenwald, Nineteenth Century British Secularism; John Seed, “‘Secular’ and ‘Religious’:
Historical Perspectives,” Social History 39:1 (2014): 3–13.
7
Benjamin Lammers, “‘The Citizens of the Future’: Educating the Children of the Jewish East
End, c.1885–1939,” Twentieth Century British History 19:4 (2008): 395–6; Stephen Heathorn (1995)
“‘Let us Remember that we, too, are English’: Constructions of Citizenship and National Identity
in English Elementary School Reading Books, 1880–1914,” Victorian Studies 38:3 (1995): 313;
Alun Howkins, “The Discovery of Rural England,” in Englishness: Politics and Culture, 1880–1920,
ed. Robert Colls and Philip Dodd (London: Croom Helm, 1980), 62–88.
8
Tom Hulme, “Putting the City Back into Citizenship: Civics Education and Local Government
in Britain, 1918–45,” Twentieth Century British History 26:1 (2015): 26–51; Helen McCarthy. The
British People and the League of Nations (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2011).
9
Charmain Cannon, “The Influence of Religion on Educational Policy, 1902–1944,” British
Journal of Educational Studies 12:2 (1964): 150–2; Rob Freathy, “The Triumph of Religious
Education for Citizenship in English Schools, 1935–1949,” History of Education 37:2 (2008): 295–
316; Stephen Platten, “The Conflict over the Control of Elementary Education 1870–1902 and
its Effect upon the Life and Influence of the Church,” British Journal of Educational Studies 23:3
(1975): 286–93.
10
For example, P. Yeandle, Citizenship, Nation, Empire: The Politics of History Teaching in England,
1870–1930 (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 2015), 83–7.
This organisation changed its name three times. For clarity, Moral Instruction League is used
11
throughout this paper. An emphasis on England rather than Britain, arises from the chief focus
of MIL and LNU activities, and the Anglo-centrism of contemporary citizenship debates (on the
latter see Matthew Grimley, “The Religion of Englishness: Puritanism, Providentialism and
National Character,” Journal of British Studies 46:4 (2007): 891–2).
17
12
Robert Nicholas Bérard, “The Movement for Moral Instruction in Great Britain: the Moral
Instruction League and its Successors,” Fides et Historia 16:2 (1984): 55–73; F. H. Hilliard, “The
Moral Instruction League 1879–1919,” Durham Research Review 12 (1961): 53–63; R. J. W. Selleck,
The New Education, 1870–1914 (London: Pitman, 1968), 299–328; B. J. Elliott, “The League of
Nations Union and History Teaching in England: a Study in Benevolent Bias,” History of
Education 6:2 (1977): 131–41; McCarthy, British People, chapter 4.
13
Space only allows for a couple of examples to indicate the use of this term, across disciplinary
and geographical boundaries, and from the 1970s to the present. See, for example, E. S. Miller,
“The Christian Missionary: Agent of Secularisation,” Anthropological Quarterly 43:1 (1970): 14–22;
Matthew Grimley, “Law, Morality and Secularisation: The Church of England and the
Wolfenden Report, 1954–1967,” Journal of Ecclesiastical History 60:4 (2009): 725–41 (at 740). Use
of “agents of secularisation” with particular reference to secularists is more recent, see
Lutgendorff, “Agents of Secularisation”.
14
John Eros, “The Rise of Organized Freethought in Mid-Victorian Britain,” Sociological Review
(1964) 2:1: 98–120 exemplifies an older narrative of secularist decline. Rectenwald, Nineteenth
Century British Secularism, chapter 2, argues for an emphasis on cultural and ideological rather than
organisational dimensions of secularism.
15
For example, see D. Cannadine, J. Keating and N. Sheldon, The Right Kind of History
(Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011); Cannon, “The Influence of Religion on Educational
Policy, 1902–1944”; V. Chancellor, History for their Masters (Bath: Adams & Dart, 1970); Freathy,
“The Triumph of Religious Education for Citizenship in English Schools”; Heathorn, “‘Let us
Remember’”; J. A. Mangan (ed.) Benefits Bestowed? Education and British Imperialism (Manchester:
Manchester University Press, 1989); W. E. Marsden, The School Textbook: Geography, History and
Social Studies (London: Woburn Press, 2001), 77–81, 149–55; S. Olsen, Juvenile Nation: Youth,
Emotions and the Making of the Modern British Citizen, 1880–1914 (London: Bloomsbury, 2014); S.
Platten, “The Conflict over the Control of Elementary Education”; Yeandle, Citizenship, Nation,
Empire.
16
Rev. Dymott, “Letter to the Editor,” School Guardian, September 20, 1902, 744–5; Birmingham
Daily Gazette, March 30, 1901; Maurice Leonard Jacks, God in Education (London: Rich & Cowan,
1939), 5–7.
17
Malcolm Quin, “The Death of Christianity,” Positivist Review, October 1924, 186–90; “NSS
Executive Annual Report,” The Freethinker, June 15, 1930, 372–5.
18
Brown, Death of Christian Britain; S. J. D. Green, The Passing of Protestant England (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2011); H. McLeod, The Religious Crisis of the 1960s (Oxford: Oxford
18
University Press, 2007); S. Williams, Religious Belief and Popular Culture in Southwark, c.1880–1939
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 87–104. A few defend secularisation in this period (see
Steve Bruce, God is Dead (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002) and Secularization: In Defence of
an Unfashionable Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 2011)).
19
Peter Brierley, “Religion,” in Twentieth Century British Social Trends, ed. Albert Henry Halsey and
Josephine Webb (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 2000), 650–74; Brown, Death of Christian Britain, 161–
9; C. Field, “Gradualist or Revolutionary Secularization? A Case Study of Religious Belonging in
Inter-War Britain, 1918-1939,” Church History & Religious Culture 43:1 (2013): 57–93. Aggregate
data illustrating long term trends inevitably masks inter-denominational, social class, gender and
geographical distinctions, and shorter-term peaks and troughs.
20
On the ‘crisis of faith’ see Owen Chadwick, The Secularization of the European Mind in the
Nineteenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975); on overt agnosticism and
atheism in the 1920s see Andrew Hastings, A History of English Christianity, 1920–2000 (London:
SCM Press, 2001), 221–39.
21
McLeod, Religious Crisis; Brown, Death of Christian Britain; Green, Passing of Protestant England.
22
Jeremy Morris, “The Strange Death of Christian Britain: Another Look at the Secularisation
Debate,” Historical Journal 46:4 (2003): 963–76.
23
For example, J. C. D. Clark, “Secularization and Modernization: The Failure of a ‘Grand
Narrative’,” Historical Journal 55:1 (2012): 161–94; J. Morris, “Secularization and Religious
Experience: Arguments in the Historiography of Modern British Religion,” Historical Journal 55:1
(2012): 195–219; David Nash, “Reconnecting Religion with Social and Cultural History:
Secularization’s Failure as a Master Narrative,” Cultural and Social History 1:3 (2004): 302–25;
Nash, Christian Ideals.
24
W. S. Smith, The London Heretics, 1870–1914 (London: Constable, 1967).
25
Susan Budd, Varieties of Unbelief (London: Heinemann, 1977), 8–9.
26
Budd, Varieties of Unbelief, 10–123; Edward Royle, Radicals, Secularists and Republicans
(Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1980); Edward Royle, Victorian Infidels (Manchester:
Manchester University Press, 1974).
27
Budd, Varieties of Unbelief, 190–99; R. Harrison, Before the Socialists: Studies in Labour and Politics
1861–81 (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1964), chapter 6; Wright, The Religion of Humanity.
28
Budd, Varieties of Unbelief, 188–90, 199–264; I. D. MacKillop, The British Ethical Societies
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986); Gustav Spiller, The Ethical Movement in Great
Britain (London: Farleigh Press, c.1934).
19
29
For example, H. G. Jones, “The Sociological Value of Christianity,” Positivist Review, January
1913: 21; Harry Snell, “The Religion of To-day and To-morrow,” in The Fiftieth Anniversary of the
Ethical Movement, 1876–1926 (New York; London: D. Appleton & Company, 1936), 205–9.
30
F. Reid, “Socialist Sunday Schools in Britain, 1892–1939,” International Review of Social History
11:1 (1966), 18–47; K. S. Inglis, “The Labour Church Movement,” International Review of Social
History 3:3 (1958): 445–60; Mark Bevir, “The Labour Church Movement, 1891–1902,” Journal of
British Studies 38 (1999): 217–45; Stephen Yeo, “A New Life: The Religion of Socialism in Britain,
1883–1896,” History Workshop Journal 4:1 (1977): 5–56.
31
J. H. Muirhead, “The Relation of Religion to Moral Teaching,” in Papers on Moral Education, ed.
G. Spiller (London: David Nutt, 1908), 171.
32
S. Gimson, Random Recollections of the Leicester Secular Society, Part 2 (n.p., 1935), 24–25, Record
Office for Leicester, Leicestershire and Rutland, Leicester Secular Society Papers (hereafter
LSSP), 10D68/19.
33
F. J. Gould, Moral Education. A Chapter from the Story of Schools in England and Wales (London:
Watts & Co., 1929), 2; Freethinker, December 12, 1897, 793.
34
Michael Sadler, ‘‘Introduction,’’ Vol. 1 of Moral Instruction and Training in Schools: Report of an
International Inquiry, ed. Michael Sadler (London: Longmans, Green & Co.), xxxix–xl.
35
Examples from a large historiography include Cannadine, Keating and Sheldon, The Right Kind
of History, 44–47, 72–96; Jim English, “Empire Day in Britain, 1904–1956,” Historical Journal 49:1
(2006): 248–52; Heathorn, “Let us Remember,” 413–21; Nathan Roberts, “Character in the
Mind. Citizenship, Education and Psychology in Britain,” History of Education 33:2 (2004): 177–
97; John Springhall, “Lord Meath, Youth and Empire,” Journal of Contemporary History 5:4 (1970):
97–111; Yeandle, Citizenship, Nation, Empire.
36
Spiller, Ethical Movement, 124–46.
37
Bérard, “Movement for Moral Instruction”, 59–60.
38
Harrold Johnson, Moral Instruction in Elementary Schools in England and Wales (London: David
Nutt, 1908), xi–xii.
39
Ethical World, September 15, 1909, 141.
40
Spiller, Ethical Movement, 152; LePlay House Programme, Spring 1925, p. 6, LePlay House
Meetings and Flyers, 1922–29 GB172/LP/5/3/7, Civic Education League Papers, The
Sociological Review Archive, Special Collections & Archives, University of Keele.
41
Gould, Life Story, 78; Spiller, Ethical Movement, 116.
42
Felix Adler, The Moral Instruction of Children (London: Edward Arnold, 1892); Moral Education
League Quarterly (MELQ) 24, April 1, 1911, 5.
20
43
Spiller, Ethical Movement, 111–13.
44
Susannah Wright, “The Struggle for Moral Education in English Schools 1879-1918” (PhD
thesis: Oxford Brookes University, 2006), 48–50; see chapters on France and America in Vol 2
of Moral Instruction and Training in Schools.
45
MIL, Our Future Citizens (London: MIL, 1900); F. J. Gould, A National Need. The Civic Spirit in
Education (London: MIL, 1913), 3–4, 7–9.
46
MIL, Moral Instruction. What it is not and What it is (London: MIL, n.d.), 1.
47
Gould, National Need, 10.
48
José Harris, “Political Thought and the Welfare State 1870–1940: An Intellectual Framework
for British Social Policy,” Past and Present 135:1 (1992): 116–41; José Harris, “From Richard
Hooker to Harold Laski: Changing Perceptions of Civil Society in British Political Thought, Late
Sixteenth to Early Twentieth Centuries,” in Civil Society in British History ed. José Harris (Oxford:
Oxford University Press), 13–37; J. T. Smith, “The Beginnings of Citizenship Education in
England,” History of Education Society Bulletin 69 (2002): 6–16.
49
MIL, Our Future Citizens, 10, 13.
50
C. Warren, “Moral Training in Public Elementary Schools,” Journal of Education, May 1907, 356.
51
MIL, A Graduated Syllabus for Moral Instruction and Training in Citizenship for Elementary Schools
(London: MIL, 1902). Elementary school standards were not age-bound, but most pupils in
Infants to Standard II would have been 4 to 8 or 9 years old, in Standards III to V 9 to 12, and in
Standards VI to VII 12 to 14.
52
Susannah Wright, “‘Our Future Citizens’: Values in Late Nineteenth and Early Twentieth
Century Moral Instruction Books,” History of Education and Children’s Literature 4 (2009): 157–77.
On secularist attitudes to empire see Bernard Porter, Critics of Empire (London, New York:
Macmillan, St Martin’s Press, 1968), 156–206 and David S. Nash “Taming the God of Battles:
Secular and Moral Critiques of the South African War,” in Writing a Wider War ed. G.
Cuthbertson, A. Grundling and M-L. Suttie (Athens, Cape Town: Ohio University Press, David
Philip, c. 2002), 266–86.
53
Head Teacher, July 15, 1907, 54; Sadler, “Introduction,” xxix.
54
A Teacher, “Letter to the Editor,” Yorkshire Post, October 28, 1905, Bridlington, “Letter to the
Editor,” Yorkshire Post, November 4, 1905, in Scrapbook of Newspaper Cuttings 1903–06, LSSP,
10D68/10.
55
For example, C. Heap, “Letter to the Editor,” Manchester Guardian, March 26, 1906, 4;
Twentieth-Century Christian, “Letter to the Editor,” Manchester Guardian, March 24, 1906, 14.
56
MIL, The Future of the Civic and Moral Education League, Circular M.30 (London: MIL, 1919).
21
57
“Moral Education and its Foundations,” School Guardian, April 20, 1907, 355–56; Sydney Smith,
“A Further Danger for our Schools,” The Month, December 1906, 613; “Annual Meeting of the
National Society,” School Guardian, June 13, 1903, 500.
58
Hansard, House of Commons, Series V, Volume 2, March 16, 1909, col. 1013.
59
Spiller, Ethical Movement, 152–3.
60
Manchester Guardian, November 18, 1903, 8.
61
MELQ 19, January 1, 1910, 1–2; 21, July 1, 1910, 2–4; 27, January 1, 1912, 4–5.
62
Harrold Johnson, “Moral Instruction and the Education Bill,” November 21, 1908, Social
Pamphlets R188675, John Rylands Library, Manchester; Moral Instruction League Quarterly
(henceforward MILQ) 15, January 1, 1909, 3; 8, January 1, 1907, 6.
63
E. R. Bernard, A Scheme of Moral Instruction for Teachers in Public Elementary Schools (London: John
Davis, 1907), 3–4, 6, Wiltshire and Swindon History Centre, 1585/313.
64
MILQ 11, October 1, 1907, 3–4.
65
MILQ 11, October 1, 1907, 3–5.
66
MIL, Moral Instruction, 3.
67
Timothy Larsen, Crisis of Doubt: Honest Faith in Nineteenth-Century England (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2006).
68
MELQ 33, July 1, 1913, 6; Gould, Moral Education, 4.
69
The Freethinker, November 28, 1897, 765.
70
The Freethinker, May 28, 1899, 347; July 9, 1899, 445.
71
Smith, “Further Danger”, 606.
72
Lammers, “Citizens of the Future”, 403.
73
English, “‘Empire Day,” 260–62.
74
Cannadine, Keating, Sheldon, Right Kind of History, 70–96; McCarthy, British People, 105–08.
75
McCarthy, British People, 103–04; Tammy Proctor, On my Honour (Philadelphia: American
Philosophical Society, 2002), 131–54; Scott Johnston, “Courting Public Favour: the Boy Scout
Movement and the Accident of Internationalism, 1907–29,” Historical Research 88:241 (2015):
508–29.
76
LNU, Annual Report for 1925 (London, LNU: 1926), 3.
77
Elliott, “League of Nations Union”; McCarthy, British People, chapter 4; Board of Education,
Report on the Instruction of the Young in the Aims and Achievements of the League of Nations (London:
HMSO, 1932), 7; Derek Heater, Peace through Education (Lewes: Falmer Press, 1984), 41–6.
22
78
LNU, League of Nations Union Year Book for 1933 (London: LNU, 1933), 25; LNU, League of
Nations Union Year Book for 1937 (London: LNU, 1937), 29–30; LNU, Junior Branches of the League
of Nations Union (London: LNU, 1936), 14.
79
McCarthy, British People, 94.
80
D. S. Birn, The League of Nations Union, 1918–1945 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), 135–8;
McCarthy, British People, 79–102; LNU, The Church, the League and the Union (London: LNU, 1929),
7–8.
81
LNU, Armistice Day Message (London: LNU, 1938); Lillian Dalton, League of Nations Stories
(London: George G. Harrap, 1924), 16.
82
McCarthy, British People, 92.
83
J. Reeves, “Religion and the League of Nations Union,” The Freethinker, June 3, 1934, 342–3.
84
F. J. Gould, The Life Story of a Humanist (London: Watts & Co., 1923), 77–80, 83–113; F. H.
Hayward and E. M. White, The Last Years of a Great Educationist (Bungay: R. Clay & Co., c.1942),
48–51; Wright, Religion of Humanity, 246–7.
85
F. J. Gould in Middlesex County Times, April 25, 1936, in Hayward and White, Last Years, 134.
86
Gould, Moral Education, 17–20; Wright, Religion of Humanity, 270–2.
87
Gould, Moral Education, 19; Hayward and White, Last Years, 136–7.
88
Hayward and White, Last Years, 264.
89
Hayward and White, Last Years, 140–1.
90
Gould, Moral Education, 21.
91
F. J. Gould, The League of Nations Spirit in the Schools (London: LNU, 1927), 1–2, 10–11.
92
League News, June 1932, 6; February 1937, 1–2.
93
League News, February 1935, 1–2.
94
Hayward and White, Last Years, 264.
95
Keith Robbins, History, Religion and Identity in Modern Britain (London: Bloomsbury, 1993),
chapter 14; Freathy, “The Triumph of Religious Education for Citizenship in English Schools”;
S. Wright, Morality and Citizenship in English Schools. Secular Approaches 1897-1944 (Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2017), 192–9.
96
Mass Observation, Puzzled People (London: Faber & Faber, 2009 – originally London: Gollancz,
1949), 86–8; Budd, Varieties of Unbelief, 177–9, 258–62; Rob Freathy and Stephen Parker,
“Secularists, Humanists and Religious Education: Religious Crisis and Curriculum Change in
England, 1963–1975,” History of Education 42:2 (2013): 222–56; Wright, Morality and Citizenship in
English Schools, 214–18.
23
97
British Humanist Association (BHA), “BHA Education Policy – A Summary,”
https://humanism.org.uk/education/education-policy/, date accessed 14 May 2016.
24