QUAKER STUDIES 18/2 (2014) [151-169]
ISSN 1363-013X
CANDLESTICK MYSTERIES*
Laura Rediehs
St Lawrence University, USA
ABSTRACT
The Li£ht upon the Candlestick (1662) was written by a Dutch Collegiant, but was taken by the
Quakers to be a good account of their own theory of knowledge. Yet a contemporary scholar
of Dutch Collegiant thought interprets this same essay as showing the beginning of the
Col]egiants' moving away from a spiritualist interpretation of the Light Within and towards a
rationalist interpretation, influenced by the philosopher Spinoza. While the title page of this
essay indicates the influence of a Quaker, it seems that, until now, no one has examined this
cormection in detail. A recent translation of William Ames' Mysteries of the Kingdom of God 1661)
has now made this comparison possible. The comparison shows that the Quaker influence is
substantial, and that The Light upon the Candlestick is better interpreted as a point of convergence
between Quaker and Collegiant thought than as a rationalist turn in ColIegiant thought.
KEYÿORDS
Dutch CoUegiants, The tKeligious Society of Friends (Quakers), epistemology, William Ames,
Pieter Bailing, Spinoza.
INTP..ODUCTION: WHY SO MUCH INTEREST IN
THE LIGHT UPON THE CANDLESTICK?
I:
The Light won the Candlestick, written in 1662 by Pieter Balling, is said by
Collegiant scholar Andrew Fix to be the most discussed document written by a
Dutch Collegiant author (Fix 1991: 204). Not only is it of interest as a statement
of Collegiant thought, it has also long been of interest to Quakers as well. In 1663
it was translated into English by Benjamin Furly, an English Quaker merchant
living in Rotterdam. It was subsequently circulated among Quakers. The
pamphlet was included in its entirety as an appendix to William Sewel's 1722
history of Quakers. It is listed under the Quaker William Ames' name in Joseph
Smith's A Desc@tiue Catalogue of Friends Books, 1867, although Smith mentions
that it was probably not authored by.Ames, and cites Sewel in explaining why. It
was discussed again in 1914 by the Quaker Rufus Jones, and in 1992 by
contemporary Quaker Uuiversalists.ÿ
152
QUAKER STUDIES
As William Hull noted, The Light upon the Candlestick can be said to be a work
that has been 'claimed' by both Quakers and Collegiants (Hull 1938:215 n. 444),
although its significance within each of these movements is interpreted differently.
The Dutch Collegiants and Quakers who were connected to this document at the
time of its writing were also in close contact with the philosopher Baruch
Spinoza, and several scholars have concluded that it shows traces of a connection
with Spinoza. Its importance, then, is that of determining the nature of influences
among the Dutch Collegiants, the Quakers, and Spinoza.
The Light upon the CandIesti& presents a theory of knowledge centered on the
concept of the Light Within. The debate about this document is whether the
concept of the Light in this work is spiritualist2 or rationalist. If spiritualist, it
would represent an early phase in Collegiant thought, akin to the Quaker
understanding of the Light. If rationalist, it would suggest Spinoza's influence,
thus representing a shift to the later Collegiant view of the Light, when the
Collegiant interpretation diverged notably from the Quaker interpretation. Collegiant scholar Andrew Fix argues for the latter. This article argues for the former
based on comparing The Light upon the Candlestick, with William Ames' Mysteries
ofi the Kingdom of God.
WtkITTEN BY A DUTCH COLLEGIANT, BUT 'CLAIMED' BY QUAKEtkS TOO?
Richard Popkin noted that The Light upon the Candlestick was 'taken up immediately by the Quakers as a statement of their theory of knowledge' (Popkin 1985:
232). Earlier, Rufus Jones regarded this work as important for similar reasons.
Jones wrote that this work
R_EDIEHS CANDLESTICK 7ÿf YSTERJES
153
father'd it upon Adan: Boreel, because it is found printed in Latin among his Scripta
Posthuma... Besides he and some other of the Collegians, and among these also Dr.
Galenus Abrahamson, were so effectually convinced of the Doctrine preached by
William Ames, when he first came to Amsterdam, that they approved of it; tho'
afterwards from a Misapprehension they opposed it... (Sewel 1722: Preface).
Richard Popkin and Andrew Fix think that Pieter Bailing wrote The Light upon
the Candlestick, and that Adam Bored translated it into Latin (Popkin 1985: 232;
Fix t991:I99 n. 34). According to Popkin, it was probably written by Bailing
'right after he visited Spinoza in late 1661, when the latter had just completed
what exists as The Treatisd on the Emendation of the Understanding'. Popkin further
explains: 'Light on the Candlestick is an epistemological rationale for mysticism
based on Spinozistic terms and ideas. It could only be written by someone who
had access to Spinoza's unpublished Emendation', and also notes 'Spinoza's theory
as formulated in Emendation was still close enough to Quaker ideas to be taken up
by them' (Popkin 1985: 232).
Sally I<ickerman and Kingdon Swayne summarize some of the scholarship by
Richard Popkin, Michael Signer, and Rufus Jones on The Light upon the Candlestick, ending with these words: 'We may hope that some future scholar will solve
the major remaining puzzle presented by The Light upon the Candlestick: who
decided to put William Ames' name to Peter Balling's work, and why?' (Rickerman and Swayne 1992: 27). The answer to this question is now clear: it is not
that someone decided to put Ames' name to Bal]iag's work; rather, the title page
describes and acknowledges the influence of William Ames' work, Mysteries of the
Kit¢gdom of God on The Light upon the Candlestick. This influence is substantial, as
will be seen below.
was very quickly discovered by the Quakers, who inznediately recognized it as
'bone of their bone', and circulated it as a Quaker Tract. It was translated into
English in 1663 by B. F. (Benjamin Furley, a Quaker merchant of Colchester, then
living in tkotter&m), who published it with the curious title page: The Light upon
the Candlestick. Serving for Observation of the Principal things in the Book called,
77ze Mystery [sic] of the Kilgdom of God, &c. Agaitut several Professors, Treated of, and
ruritten by Wil! Ames. Printed in Low Dutch for the Author, 1662, and translated
into English by B. F. (Jones 1914: 128).
William Hull notes that both the content and the tide page even led some to
believe that 77w Light upon the Candlestick was itself authored by William Ames
because of the pronfinence dAmes' name in the layout of the original tide page
and the absence of reference to any other author (Hull 1938: 214-15). But a close
reading of the title page suggests that the anonymous author only claimed to have
been influenced by a separate work written by William Banes: The Mysteries of the
I(ilgdom of God. William Sewel, who had known Ames,3 discussed how others
had misread the title page, but himself noted
That he [Ames] approved the Contents of the Book I know; but I know also that it
never proceeded from his Pen. And many Years afterwards it was published under
the Name of one Peter Bailing, as the Author of it, tho' there were those who
HISTORICAL BACKGROUND: THE DUTCH COLLEGIANTS,
THE QUAKERS IN HOLLAND, AND SPINOZA
The Dutch Collegiant movement and Quakerism were both parts of the radical
branch of the second reformation. The Dutch Collegiant movement started
around 1620 in Holland, arising out of the Arminian controversy. Jacob Arminius
(1560-1609) did not agree with predestination. After his death, his supporters
formally requested toleration for their views in Holland, and were thus called
'Remonstrants'. When the P,.eformed Church suspended all Remonstrant
preachers, a congregation in Warmond, near Leiden, decided, under the advice of
former elder Gijsbert van der Kodde, to continue to meet even without a preacher
in a 'college' (informal gathering for religious education), to pray, read the Bible,
and freely discuss religious matters (Fix 1991: 37). This was the start of the Dutch
Collegiant movement. The Collegiants did not formally establish themselves as a
Church, and so were not a separate new denomination, as such, but formed as
groups of seekers from various religious traditions meeting separately from their
churches to discuss ideas. Collegiants typically maintained their memberships in
their churches even as they also participated in the colleges. Major colleges were
15 4
QUAKEK STUD IES
established in P,.ijnsburg, Amsterdam, and Rotterdam. The Collegiants had no
hired clergy. They advocated 'free prophecy', holding meetings in which any
man4 was free to speak. They believed in the Liglÿt Within although how they
interpreted this Light changed over time, as will be discussed later.
It is dear from this description why the Quakers would have been drawn to
make contact with the Dutch Collegiants. After Quakerism started around 1652
in England, some Friends soon went to Holiand both because Holland was more
tolerant of religious freedom than England was (although the Quakers still faced
persecution there), and because the Quakers found people receptive to their
message. The relative tolerance of diversity in religious thought created a seeking
culture that the Quakers regarded as ripe for converting seekers to Quakerisln and
founding more Quaker Meetings. They were also trying to convert Jews to
Christianity in anticipation of what they thought to be the coming Millennium.
While unsuccessful in converting Jews (Popkin 1987: 11-12), they did make
important connections with Mennonites and Collegiants.
In 1653 the first Quaker missionaries, William Caton and Jolm Stubbs, arrived
in Holland, visiting Middetburg and Vlissingen. A few years later, in 1656,
William Ames arrived in Amsterdaln and soon became recognised as an important
Quaker leader. William Ames was deeply involved in discussions and debates with
important Dutch Collegiant writers, and he also met Spinoza.
The Dutch Collegiants who are especially important to our story include Adam
Bored (who, along with Daniel De Breen, co-founded the Amsterdam College
in 1646), Galenus Abrahamsz (a Mennonite pastor who was inspired by Adam
Bored and joined the Amsterdam College in 1650, himself then becoming an
important Collegiant leader), and Pieter Bailing (who was himself influenced by
Galenus). Mysteries of the Kingdom of God was written by William Ames as a
response to earlier work by Galenus Abrahamsz.
The philosopher Baruch Spinoza was very much influenced by the rationalist
philosophy of 1Kenÿ Descartes. Spinoza was Jewish, but was excommunicated
from his synagogue for his radical views in 1656. Bored and BalIing were close to
Spinoza, even before Spinoza was excommunicated. After Spinoza's excommuni-
cation, he spent a lot of time in close contact with his Dutch Collegiant fi'iends
(Fix 1991: 200). Bailing translated Spinoza's Prin@les of Cartesian Philosophÿ, into
Dutch (1991: 193). In 1657 Spinoza met William Ames, and their meeting was a
good one. There are indications that Spinoza was planning to attend a Quaker
Meeting with Ames, but Ames unfortunately was arrested and imprisoned and
then temporarily exiled from Amsterdam before they were able to attend Meeting
together (Hull 1938: 205; Popkin 1987: 5). Meanwhile, Spinoza seems to have
been in contact with the Quaker Samuel Fisher. Margaret Fell had wanted Fisher
to translate into Hebrew wvo works that she had written to the Jewish people in
1658, but it was very likely Spinoza who actually translated Fell's writings (Popkin
1987). Another indication of Spinoza's contact with Fisher was that Spinoza's
Tractatus-Theologico-Politicus (1670) echoes many of the arguments of Fisher's 1660
Rlÿsticus Ad Academicos (1660) (Popkin 1985). Thus we see that the time of the
R.EDIEHS CANDLESTICK ]V[YSTERIES
155
writing of The Light upon the Candlesti& was a time in which Spinoza, the
Quakers, and the Dutch Collegiants were in significant contact with each other.
Galenus, Bailing, and Pieter Serrarius were initially attracted to Quakerism,s
but theological differences and controversial events created tensions between the
two groups. For example, in England in 1656 James Nayler's messianic ennT into
Bristol caused Quakers to rethink the discermnent of divine inspiration (Hull
1938: 237; Dandelion 2007: 38-43). In Amsterdam interest in Quakerism, both
positive and negative, was due ha part to the wide publicity this event received
(Hull 1938: 221). One of Nayler's followers, Ann Cargii1, went to Amsterdam and
created considerable corItroversy within the Quaker communities there (1938:
273). Galenus himself was the target of strange and unsettling Quaker behavior
when the Quaker Issac Fumier in 1656 scratched off 'Dr' from the nameplate on
Galenus' door. When Galenus confronted him on this, Fumier said he had been
divinely led. Galenus asked if Fumier would run him through with a knife if he
felt that God commanded him to do so, and Fumier responded 'yes', to which
Galenus reeled with horror (Fix 1991: 199).
It is perhaps because of incidents like these that others involved in or closely
connected to the Collegiants also had negative views of the Quakers. For example,
the author of Kort VerhaeI t, an Nieuw-Nededand (Brief Account of Neuÿ Nethedand), a
1662 proposal for a utopian community in the New World, banned 'stiff-headed
Quakers'.6 This work had been thought to be authored by Collegiant Pieter
Cornelisz Plockhoy (e.g., Harder and Harder 1952), who had in fact put forward
a proposal himself around the. same time. More recent scholarship indicates that
the actual author was Franciscus van den Enden (Looijesteijn 2009; Mertens
2009),7 who knew Plockhoy and was very likely influenced by him.s While Van
den Enden's words may seem to indicate a low opinion of Quakers, one scholar
has suggested he did not regard all Quakers as 'stiff-headed' but only meant to ban
those Quakers who were so (Mertens 2007). Another scholar notes that Plockhoy
hhnself was famiSar with the Quakers and was likely sympathetic with them, at
least for a time (Looijesteijn 2011:88).9
At any rate, the mixed reputation of the Quakers made the work of Quaker
missionaries difficult (Hull 1938: 278). The theological disputes between the
Quakers and Collegiants highlighted the question of how to understand the
nature of divine inspiration and also how to prioritise the Light and Scripture.
These points will be discussed in more detail below.
ANDREW FIX'S THESIS REGARDING SPINOZA AND THE COLLEGIANTS
Collegiant scholar Andrew FIX describes the Collegiant movement as going
through three stages: (1) spiritualism and miJtenarianism, (2) rational spiritualism,
and (3) secular philosophical rationalism. He claims that The Light upon the Candlestick demonstrates the shift from the first to the second stage, representing the
Collegiants' departure from Quaker influence, away from a spiritualistic intm-pretation of the Liglat and towards a rationahstic interpretation, influenced by
15 6
QUAKEt:k STUDIES
Balling's and Boreel's close contact with Spinoza. Fix appears unaware of the
Quaker interest in The Light upon the Candlestick, and seems not to have closely
compared the document to Ames' Mysteries of the Kingdoni of God.
Fix defines 'spiritualism' as the belief in Light as inspiration from God, providing religious knowledge that surpasses that provided by unaided human intellect.
The Light is both a source of divine truth and a means to salvation (FIX 1991:
187). In the early phase of the Collegiant movement, from 1620 to 1657, the
Collegiants thought that divine inspiration could be heertijkmahing (extraordinary);
that is, humans could be inspired in a way that gave them the power to convert
others and transform the Church. But Galenus Abrahamsz had a different view,
and when he became involved in the Collegiant movement, he influenced the
movement to adopt his view. He interpreted the heerIijkmaking gaft to have been
present only in the early days of Christianity, disappearing when the Christian
Church was corrupted by Constantine's alliance of Church and secular power
(Fix 1991: 102). He thought that another kind of divine inspiration was s6_li
available: the heiligmaking, gift; this is the view that divine inspiration can lead to
one's own salvation. Thus, he had little hope that churches themselves could be
cleansed from corruption. But like some of the earlier spiritualists as well, he
beEeved that there was a true, 'invisible' Church consisting of those who were
genuinely divinely inspired, and that they could support each other in their quests
for personal salvation.
Fix reads this shift in the interpretation of divine gift as starting to pave the way
towards a rationalising of the Light (FIX 1991: 192), the second stage in Collegiant
thought, which in turn led eventually to the third stage: the rejection of the Light
altogether in favor of secnlar rationalism. Secular rationalism is the view that
human reason is all that is required for knowledge--some special ÿ from God
above and beyond this is not necessary. While FIX classifies Galenus as a spiritualist, he places Balling in the stage of 'rational spiritualism', and thus interprets
Candlestick as beginning to equate the Light with reason)°
Balling's work was part of what FIX describes as a 'pamphlet war' between the
Quakers and Collegiants that arose follovd.ng the °final break' between the two
oups in 1660 (Fb: 1991: 196). Fix discusses tee debate as if Candlestick represented a decisive departure from Quaker views. The debate began with an
exchange between Galenus and Ames, with Ames' Mysteries of the Kingdom of God
appearing as a second response to Galenus. Although FIX mentions this work, he
translates the title as 'The hidden things of God's kingdom' and does not discuss
its content specifically, nor comments on the fact that it is mentioned on the title
page of The Light upon the Candlestick. He seems not to have noticed the
connection between this work and Candlestick, except to imply that Candlestick is
a critical response to Ames (1991: 196-97).
Other works by other authors also appeared in this pamphlet debate, but what
is interesting to note is that in both Fix's and Hull's accounts of the pamphlet
debate it seems that Galenus did not respond further to Ames. Fix's interpretation
of the results of this 'pamphlet war' is to say:
P,..EDLEHS CANDLESTICK MYSTERIES
157
[Some] Collegiants reacted to Quaker spiritualistic zeal by modifying traditional
Collegiant spiritualism in a rationalistic direction. By deveIoping a secular interpretation of the inner light these P, Sjnsburgers perhaps hoped to undercut the IeDtimacy of Quaker claims based on the inworking of the Holy Spirit. At the same time
the Collegiants attempted to move away from what they considered to be the bad
example provided by the Quakers by shifting Collegiant truth claims to an episte-
moloÿcal foundation not discredited by Quaker spiritualistic excess. Such a work
was Pieter Balling's [77ze Light upon the Candlestick] (Fb: 199!: 199).
THE UNEXAMINED LINK: WILLIAM AMES' MYSTERIES
OF THE KINGDOM OF GOD
Interpreting Candlestick as a critique of,aÿnes and a departure from Quaker views
is problematic. While it is clear that there are influences from Cartesian thought
and Spinoza (described below), it is hard to argue that Candlestick is a defense of
rationalistic thought in opposition to Quaker spiritualism. Before discussing and
responding to Fix's interpretation of Candlestick in detail, it is helpful to describe
Mysteries. Neither Jones, 1Klckenzaan, Swayne, nor Fix actually seem to have
directly compared Mysteries with Candlestick. Once this comparison is made, it is
clear that Bailing borrows heavily from Ames, and thus Candlestick is better interpreted as drawing k-ore and expanding on Ames' text rather than as refilting it.
Mysteries of the Kingdom of God, as mentioned above, is a response by William
Ames to Galenus Abrahamsz. This discussion centers on two closely related questions, one on human nature and the other on the primary source of religious
knowledge. The question on human nature concerns the origin of human
sinfulness, and the question on religious knowledge is related in that it focuses on
how to obtain the enlightenment that can free us from our sinful state.
GALENUS ABKAHAMSZ'S VIEWS AND AMES' R.ESPONSE
As we have seen, Galenus distinguished between the heerlijkmaking ÿ (the view
that divine inspiration carries the power to save others and purify the Church) and
the heiligmaking ÿft (the view that divine inspiration can only lead to one's own
salvation), and he preached that the heedO'kmaking g-ift was no longer available to
people during his time: the only remaining form of divine inspiration was the
heiligmaking gift.
Ames himself summarises Galenus' views as follows. He claims that Galenus
aÿgues that part of human nature is corrupt, and the path to salvation is to follow
Scripture as a role for life. Only after humans have made the choice to seek
redemption and have followed the Me of Scripture might Christ then come to
the person, bringing saving power. On Ames' interpretation, this theoW implies
two kinds of Light: the light of conscience by which people ol-iginally su-ive to be
flee from sin, and by which they follow Scripture (in a literal way), and the Light
of Christ which may then follow these initial human efforts. A strong implication
is that humans in their natural state are radically separated from God.
158
12,EDIEHS CANDLESTICK MYSTERIES
QUAKER STUDIES
This theory to Ames is puzzling and inconsistent. First, if we were created by
God, it is inconsistent to regard humans as having something evil inherent in their
nature and to regard humans as being radically cut off from God. Second, it is
hard to imagine how humans could long for a better state without something of
true goodness (hence, from God) residing already in their souls. It is this core of
goodness that sparks the longing for God, and is itself fivom God. Thus, Ames
does not want to separate two kinds of light, but argues for a single Light, present
in all humans by virtue of their having been created by God. His emphasis on the
Light he calls 'the first principle of true religion' (Ames, Third DifferenceU). It is
this Light that sparks the striving for release from sin. It means that Christ is
within us all along. The reason that this is not obvious in everyone is that sinful
nature can obscure it or hide it (but can never damage or destroy it). Where,
then, does sinful nature come from? It is not inherent in human nature in a
necessary way, but was inherited through Original Sin, which itself is a story of
infection from a source that exists radically outside of God (and in opposition to
God) that is capable of tempting human nature by appealing to individualism and
earthly desires in ways that set these against God, although not thereby creating
such a strong rift between humans and God as Galenus' view seems to imply.
Another reason that Ames disagrees with Galenus' views is because Galenus'
views suggest a religion that is outside of God: any religion which prescribes a path
to follow in darkness before connection with the Divine is possible is a religion
that does not need the Divine, and hence Ames regards it suspiciously as a
religion of darkness (Ames, Fourth Difference).
Much of the discussion in Mysteries concerns the role of Scripture. Galenus
believes it should be followed literally: that is the path to salvation. Anles believes
that it can be greatly misunderstood unless read under the illumination of the
Light Within. Furthermore, Ames points out passages in the Bible (especially
from the Gospel of John) that confm-n his view that the main point of Scriptures
is to lead people to this Light Within. His conclusion is that the Scriptures are
important, but not primary. What is primary is the Light Within. Only then can
one understand Scripture correctly. And so, in Ames' view, the Light is central
both to human nature and to religious knowledge.
COMPAKISON BETWEEN MYSTERIES AND CANDLESTICK
If we next compare Mysteries with Candlestick, we fred many shared themes,
including passages where Bailing dearly follows Ames and thus parts ways with
the points Galenus had made that Ames had argued against. But Balling is less
concerned with disputing prior arguments; the tone of this piece is to share more
directly this view of religious knowledge. Bailing, like Ames, emphasises the
notion of the Light Within, and pays more attention to its epistemological significance, developing the epistemology a bit more than Ames did. Bailing echoes
some of Aanes' arguments, sometimes strengthening them with appeals to Cartesian, but not rationalistic, thinking. That is, we heat-echoes of some of Descartes'
patterns of reasoning, but we never find Balling exalting the power of reasoning
!"
159
itself,, or equating the Light with the faculty of reason. The examples that follow
will illustrate this difference.
In both works, there is an emphasis on the Light, and on the priority of the
Light over a literal reading of Scripture. In both works, the priority of the Light is
said to be the first principle of religion. It is the Light that enables us to understand Scripture rightly. Without it, we cannot understand Scripture or any divine
truths correctly. In fact, without it even our knowledge of nature is inadequate.
Bailing also notes that we must stand squarely in the Light of truth to be able
to grasp truth and to judge it accurately: He furthermore labels this as the 'Rule'.
" The concept ofa 'mIe' may seem to echo Descartes' concern with method, that is,
rules of inquiry, by which to ensure that our extensions of our knowledge do not
lead us into error. Thus, invoking the notion of a 'rule' may signify a rationalist
turn. But Ames also discusses 'rules' in a similar manner (Ames, Seventh Difference); furthermore, if we exanaine Balling's use of the term in context, we see
that he articulates a point of view that does resemble the Quaker perspective:
This Light, Christ, &c. is the truth & word of God, as hath been already said, and in
every way appears by what we have hitherto laid down: For this is a living Word,
and transmiteth man from death to life, is powerful, & enableth a man to bear
witness of itself every where. This is also the true Kule according unto which all our
actions are to be squared. This hath the pre-eminence before any Writing, Scripture,
Doctrine, or anything else that we meet from without (Bailing 1992 [1663]: 19).1ÿ
This passage as well as others shows that the Light is not just interpreted
intellectually, but is something active and dynamic that can have an effect on a
person's entire being, a view that also calls into question the rationalisation of the
Light. Part of rationaSsing the Light is to emphasise its intellectual character and
de-emphasise or even deny that it has any non-intellectual powers. Both Ames
and Bailing emphasise the salvational powers of the Light: Light gives life (brings
us out of spiritual death). The Light shows us our true state, and helps us conquer
sin and find a happy state.
Both works express similar views on the origin of human sin. This Light is
available to all, even to those who have not heard of Scripture. It cannot be
destroyed. While people seem to have different measures of Light, it is really a
matter of how much the workings of the Light are obscured by sin.
And Ames seems to put forth a view defending heedijhmalein2 (extraordinary)
divine inspiration (though he does not use that word), near the beginning of
• Mysteries, where he discusses how the faithfifl today do have the same power that
the servants of the Lord long ago had to convert others; this view may be
somewhat echoed by Balling in his description of the Light as being what gives
people the power to do good (quoted below).
There are also places where Candlestick adds to the points and arguments made
in Mysteries. In some of these places, one can see Cartesian and Spinozistic
influences, and these are highlighted and discussed below.
160
QUAKEr< STUDIES
RESPONSE TO FIX'S THESIS
R_EDIEHS CANDLES TICK I-Vf YSTERIES
161
[Candlestick] can be recognized as an intermediate work of great importance. As a
writing representing the RJjnsburger religion of individual conscience in the midst
of a process of secularization, Balling's work gives the reader a rare ÿance into the
Fix bases his interpretation of The Light upon the Candlestick on both the known
contact between Bailing and Spinoza, and the clear Spinozistic influences in this
work. Yet he fails to take into account the fact that Spinoza was also in sympathetic contact with Quakers during this same time period, and that his views on
biblical interpretation seemed more compatible with the Quaker view of Scripture than the Collegiant view)3 Thus, regarding Balling's Candlestick as a refutation of Ames and a departure from Quakerly spiritualism in favor of rationalism is
questionable. Rather, it seems more likely that the conclusion of the 'pamphlet
wars' was a moment of convergence between the two groups, perhaps somewhat
mediated by Spinoza, who had not yet fully developed his later more specifically
rationalistic philosophy.
Clearly there were serious disagreements between the Quakers and the Collegiants, especially regarding the role of Scripture and how to understand the nature
of divine inspiration. Yet there .were also events that suggest a closeness that was
not entirely fraught with diÿculty and disagreement. George Fox reports in his
own Journal that two times he met Galenus. The fix'st, in 1677, did not go so well;
the second, in 1684, was much better (Jones 1914: 122-23). While these incidents
are later than the time period we are considering here, they indicate continuing
contact between Quakers and Collegiants which calls into question Fix's attribution of a 'final break' between the two groups in 1660. During the time that
Mysteries and Candlestick were written, it is entirely possible that Ames did
persuade at least some of the Collegiants.
Bailing himself may have intended Candlestick to mediate bevween Galenus and
Ames. In his third paragraph, he refers to the 'Sea of Confusion', emphasizing
throughout these opening paragraphs the great difficulties we have in understanding each other, even when using the same words, and even when not trying to be
deceptive or obscure. He may well have been thinking of the dispute between his
friends Galenus and Ames, trusting that both were sincere in their disputations
and himself looking for the means to resolve such debates, finally deciding (and
thus siding with Ames) that it was the Light Within that provided the only means
for resolution and reconciliation.
Fix himself notes that the language of the Light is prominent in Candlestick, and
admits that this language can be taken to suggest a spiritual interpretation. But he
further claims that the exact language used can permit either a rationalist or a
spiritualist interpretation (Fix 1991: 202). He states that 'because of its mixture of
spiritualistic and rationalistic elements, Balling's work has long been considered
puzzling by historians' (1991: 200), and lists the authors who offer each kind of
interpretation (1991: 204-205).
The division of scholarly opinion concerning Balling's thought is eloquent testimony to the fact that [Candlesgick] represented a truly transitional form between
spiritualism and rationalism. Viewed in its proper intellectual and historical context,
within a tradition of Collegiant thought evolving from spiritualism to rationalism,
anatomy of intellectual transition (Fix 199l : 205).
And yet Fix himself falls to fred convincing evidence that this work represents the
beginning of the rationalisation of the Light. Fix himself admits that the word
'reason' never appears in this work (FIX 1991: 200), but he takes the echoes of
Cartesian language that he finds in Candlestick to support his interpretation of an
emerging rationalist interpretation of the Light. He takes the language of the
" Light being 'a principle certain and infallible' to indicate a Cartesian influence,
and hence a rationalist interpretation of the Light (1991: 201). Also he quotes:
'The light...is a clear and distinct knowledge of truth in the understanding of
every man, by which he is so convinced of the being and quality of things, that
he cannot possibly doubt thereof', interpreting this passage as providing evidence
that 'Balling thus identified the light of truth with that fundamental and indubitable rational knowledge upon which Descartes built his new philosophy' (1991:
201-202).
While these passages do clearly show a Cartesian influence, in themselves they
do not clearly represent rationalism as such. That is, these passages do not equate
the Light with reason nor make the claim that human reason is an independent
means for coming to know religious truths in a way that does not necessitate
divine inspiration. While the language of a pnnciple that is 'certain and infallible'
echoes Descartes' quest for a method we can trust that would allow us to extend
our knowledge through careful, well-reasoned steps, Balling does not discuss the
reasoning process. Here is the same passage in a wider context:
We direct thee then to look within thyself, that is, that thou oughtest to turn into,
to mind and have regard unto that which is within thee, to wit, the Light of Troth,
the true Light which enlighten every man that cometh into the world. Here 'tis that
thou must be, and not without thee. Here thou shalt find a Principle certain and
infallible, and whereby increasing and going on therein, thou mayest at lenÿh arrive
unto a happy condition (Balling 1992 [1663]: !2-13).
Part of what is interesting about this larger passage is that the Cartesian phrase
closely follows a quotation from the Bible (Jn 1:9) that furthmvnore is quoted
repeatedly throughout Ames' l!/Iysteries. While it is possible that Bailing intends to
say that the Light referred to in the Bible is best understood as nothing more than
the principle of reason, he does not go on to say this or develop such an argument, and so such a reading of this passage is difficult to defend. The invocation
of the notion of 'Truth' here is more biblical than rationalist, a broader notion of
truth similar to that employed by the Quakers: one that is not just epistemological
but transforms a person, allowing him or her to 'arrive unto a happy condition'.
Now mining to the passage mentioning 'clear and distinct knowledge', we find
that it too shows a clear Cartesian influence but cannot be taken to be
rationalising the Light when we consider what BallLng says two sentences later:
i 62
QUAKER STUDIES
This Light then, Christ the Truth, &c. is that which makes mahifest and reproves
sin in man, shewing him how he has strayed from God, accuseth him of the evil
which he doth and hath con=nitted; yea this is it which judgeth and condemeth
him: Again, This is the preaching to every Creature under Heaven, though they
have never read or heard of the Scripture. This is it which leads man into truth, into
the way to God, which excuseth him in well-doing, giving him peace in his
Conscience, yea, brings him into union with God, wherein all happiness and
salvation doth consist (Bailing 1992 [1663]: 14).
Again we find a much broader function of the Light than simply rationally
ascertaining knowledge claims. The notion of troth invoked here again is the
broader Quaker conception of 'Truth', which involves not just a clarification of
knowledge but a transformation of one's whole being.
In another line of discussion, Fix himself notes that Billing 'was never ambiguous...in his insistence that the Light was an independent source of true ideas
superior in authority to all other sources, including Scripture' (Fix 1991: 202).
The Light was thus a som'ce of kalowledge available even to those who had never
heard of Scripture. Fix seems to regard this departure from the then-prevailing
Collegiant view of Scripture as evidence for rationalising the Light, because he
associates spiritualism with a strong emphasis on Scripture. But here FIX fails to
notice the Quaker influence: placing priority on the Light above Scripture was
one of the major points of both Mysteries and Fisher's Rustick Alamt. FIX himself
does go on to quote Balling saying 'the light is also the first principle of religion,
because there can be no true religion without knowledge of God, and no
knowledge of God without this light' (1991: 202), but interprets this passage
rationalistically because the notion of a 'first principle' sounds Cartesian. Fix goes
R_ED IEHS CANDLESTICK MYSTERIES
163
Fix interprets this passage rationalistically, especially because of the discussion of
cause and effect which echoes Descartes (Fix 1991: 203). The argument structure
here has similarities with Descartes' use of an argument from efficient causation
which functions as part of his rational proof for the existence of God in his
Meditations.14 Even though the reasoning pattern is similar to that of Descartes,
however, the point he is making cannot be said to be the claim that the Light is
equivalent to the principle of reason. The larger point here echoes Ames: the
arÿmnnent is that we perceive good and evil not merely because other people tell
us what is good or evil but because there is something within us that illuminates
good and evil, allowing {ts to perceive it. The passage is neutral on what this Light
is: it could be reason itself but it could equally be a quasi-perceptual faculty independent of reason. In addition, the language of the Light giving people the power
to do good suggests a stronger (heerIijhmakin2) version of divine inspiration than
Galenus had promoted.
Fix continues himself to express some anabivalence: 'Despite his inclination
toward rationalism, however, Bailing often returned to a traditional spiritualistic
interpretation of the inner light' (Fix 1991: 204). Again, he tries to justify his
rationalistic interpretation, this time by noting that Bailing concludes 'on a final
interesting philosophical note' (1991: 204): that the Ligllt was how people came
If Bailing had conceived of the inner light of truth in purely spiritualistic terms, his
elevation of the light above Scripture would have been clearly in the Quaker tradi-
to know God and preceded any external knowledge of God. Fix attributes this to
a Cartesian influence ('because Descartes used similar arguments ha discussing the
innate idea of God'), but, again, after comparing Ames and Bailing, it is clear that
this argument draws directly from a similar argument made by Ames (Fifth
Difference).
The passages discussed above show the best evidence of influences from
Descartes and Spinoza, but we now see that none of them can be said to support
the view that Candlestick represents a departure fi:om Quaker thought, reinterpreting the Light as nothing more than the human faculty of reason. Some of the
tion. As his usage of Cartesian phraseology suggests, however, Bailing thought of
passages that seem to use Cartesian language in fact echo Ames' langlaage in
on to say:
the light of truth also in terms of human reason... Seen in this perspective, Baÿng's
elevation of the inner light above Scripture takes on a meaning that sets [Candlestick]
dramatically apart from the spiritualistic tradition (FLx 1991: 203).
Here, FIX fails to notice the distinctive nature of Quaker spiritualism which Bailing
himself is acknowledging: Balling's phrasing is in fact taken directly from Ames'
Mysteries (Third Difference), where Ames is interpreting the Light as divine inspiration rather thai the light of reason. Fix then quotes a passage that again sounds
Cartesian:
Without this light man has no power or ability to do good. It must first awaken him
out of the death of sin and make him living. Darkness is only driven away by the
light, ignorance only by knowledge. It is folly to want something where there is
Mysteries.
Furthermore, there are even some passages in Candlesti& that reflect the
Quakerly caution against excessive reliance on human rationality. While Fix and
other anthors have characterised the Quaker view as being anti-rationalist, that
position is too strongly stated. It is not that the Quakers were wholly opposed to
human powers of reasoning; it is that they were cautious about thinking too
highly of it. As with the Bible, human reasoning must be employed only within
the guidance and illumination of the Light. We see Balling's own caution toward
human rationality in the following passage:
And if thou happenest to be one of those that wouldst know all things, before thou
dost begin, yea, even those things which are experienced in a condition to which
nothing. There is no effect without cause. If man does anything, something causes
thou art so much a stranger, that there's nothing in thee hath so much agreement
him to do it. And tlÿs cause must contain all that the effect contains. If there is the
effect of the light, the light alone must be the cause (Bailing, quoted by Fix 1991:
therewith, as to comprehend it according to truth: Know this, Thou dost (therein)
just as those that would learn to Kead, without knowing the Letters (Bailing 1992
203).
[1663]: 13).
164
QUAKER STUDIES
R.EDIEHS CANDLESTICK MYSTERIES
165
This passage cautions against a strong anti-empiricist rationalism, very much
reflecting the Quaker emphasis on experience. The first sentence can even be
read as a direct criticism of Descartes. A rationalism that is disconnected from
experience is like trying to read without bothering to learn the letters first. In
addition, in the next paragraph 13ailing goes on to discuss the limits of human
knowledge: 'To desire to know all thinÿ that we are capable of, is good and
laudable; but to go further, is folly. There will be alwayes something else to ask,
and our knowledge will ever be too short. He that will not adventure till he be
fully satisfied, shall never begin, much less finish it to his own salvation' (Balling
1992 [1663]: 13). This passage too suggests a critique of the Cartesian demand for
notes that Candlestick is 'indistinguishable in its body of ideas from Quaker teaching, and differs only in one point, that it reveals a more philosophically trained
mind in the writer than does any early Quaker book with the exception of
Barclay's Apology' (Jones 1914: 123). He goes on to discuss the Cartesian influence,
though what he emphasises is not his rationalism specifically but rather the
a priori certainty.
Thus we find that when Jones emphasises the influences of Descartes and
Spinoza on Candlestick, he is not referring to their rationalism as such but rather to
Spinoza's mysticism and to a subtle move in Descartes' thinking that, while it can
be interpreted rationalistically, may better described as subjectively experiential than
rationalistic:ÿ6 'That we are oppressed with oÿuc own littleness, that we "look
before and after and sigh for what is not", that we are conscious of finiteness,
means that we partake in some way of an infinite which reveals itself in us by an
inherent necessity of self-consciousness' (Jones 1914: 125).
The sentence that immediately follows this passage does look more rationalist:
'There are, then, some ideas within us--at least there is this one idea of an infinitely perfect reality--implanted in the very structure of our thinking self, which
could have come from no other source but from God' (Jones 1914: 125; emphasis
in original). This passage is in fact rationalist because it is part of Jones' general
description of Cartesian thougJÿt. But in Jones' later discussion of Candlestick
specifically, the connections he draws are to the mystical and experiential dimensions of Descartes' and Spinoza's thought--not to the specifically rationalist
Another passage that can be taken as critical of rationalism is:
So that if the Truth of God be presented to a man who stands not in the Light of
Truth, 'tis impossible he should understand it, although he hears and comprehends
the words after his manner, yet he is st2!l fenced off from its true sence and meaning
thereof Hence, therefore, it is, that amongst so many hearers there are so few that
have ears to hear (Bailing I992 [1663]: 19).
Here too is the Quakerly sense that human reason is not enough. One can hear
true words or hear well-constructed rational arguments, and yet not grasp the full
meaning if one is not standing in the Light.
A final passage suggesting a critique of rationalism is a discussion of the immediate (not mediated) nature of the Light, towards the end of Candlesti& (Balling
1992 [1663]: 21-22), a passage echoing the Quaker view that the Light operates
by its own direct apprehension of certain aspects of divqne reality, a view that
shows a dear distinction between the Light and the faculty of reason, tkeasoning
is a process that employs words for its functioning, but Bailing describes the limitations of words (which are finite) for grasping something that is infinite (God).
DID JONES' INTEKPtK.ETATION SUPPOKT FIX'S?
consciousness of God deep in the core of self-conscionsness itself, this conscious-
ness of God being indeed 'the condition of thinking anything at all' (1914: 125).
Then, in his discussion of Spinoza, he notes thatSpinoza adds to Descartes'
'mathematical and logical system' a 'warmth and fervor of mystical experience
that is wholly lacking in [Descartes]' (1914: 125).
elements. For example, Jones notes,
The point of contact between Spinoza and the spiritual movement which we are
studying is found in his central principles that God is the prius of all finite reality,
that to know thinÿ or to know one's own nind truly is to know God, and that a
A final point to consider is that Fix indicates that Rufus Jones backs him up on his
interpretation of Candlestick. In his discussion of the vaaTing interpretations of
Light upon the Candlestick, with some regarding it as mystical or spiritualistic, and
others as rationalistic (Fix 1991: 204-205), he put Jones on the rationalistic side:
'IKufns Jones also considered Bailing to be a Cartesian' (1991: 205). R_ickerman
and Swayne agree: 'The late-twentieth-century reader is left to speculate whether
Balling's tract was primaAly a product of his Descartes-Spinoza heritage, as Jones
believed, or the covert acknowledgment of his conversion by Ames, as Sewel
thought (IKickerman and Swayne 1992: 5).
Yet a closer look at Jones himself shows that his interpretation was more
mystical than rationalistic.ÿs While he acknowledges influences from Descartes and
Spinoza, it is not their rationalism that he points to, but other elements of their
thought, and those elements remain compatible with Quaker spiritualism. He
man who has formed a pure love for the eternal is above the variations of temporal
fortune, is not disturbed in spirit by changes in the object of his love, but loves with
a love which eternally feeds the son with joy (Jones 1914: 127).
It is important also to note that some of the passages of Candlestick that Jones
quotes and connects to Cartesian influences in fact are echoes of Ames' Mysteries.
J.ones notes that 'the Collegiant author, quite ha the spirit and style of Spinoza,
urges the importance of discovering a central love for "things which are durable
and incorruptible'" (Jones 1914: 128, quoting from Candlestick), which does
resonate with passages in Spinoza's Treatise on the Improvement of the Understanding.
But when Jones later in the same paragraph describes the conversion experience,
which is what leads people to this awareness, and discusses how this conversion
originates from the Light, the passages from Candlestick that he cites are really
echoes of Ames. Consider, for example:
166
QUAKER STUDIES
"Tis not far to seek. We direct thee to within thyself. Thou oughtest to turn into,
to mind and have regard unto, that which is within thee, to wit, the Light of Truth,
the true light which enlighteneth every man that cometh into the world' (Balling
quoted by Jones 1914: 129).
The central point of Ames' IVIysteries is the centrality and unity of this Light, and
the quotation from the Gospel of Jn 1:9, 'the true light which enlighteneth every
man that comes into the world', is repeated like a poetic refrain often throughout
Mysteries. Jones also says:
RAEDIEHS CANDLESTICK MYSTERIES
167
Benjamin Fixrly translated this work into English and circulated it anlong the
Quakers, and that Sewel printed it as an appendix to his history of Quakerisnl
further support the view that this work is highly compatible with Quaker
thought. Thus, rather than representing a criticism of Quaker thought and the
Collegiants' radical departure from Quaker influences, Candlestick is better interpreted as representing a moment of sympathetic convergence between Quaker
and Collegiant thought, synthesizing spiritualism with elements of Descartes' and
Spinoza's thought without yet rationalizing the Light Within.
In true Cartesian fashion, [Bailing] demonstrates why this Light must have its locus
NOTES
within the soul and not in some external means or medium. All knowledge that
God is being revealed in external signs, or through external means, already
presupposes a prior knowledge of God. We can judge no doctrine, no Book to be
Divine except by some inward and immediate knowledge of what really is Divine.
Without this Light the Scriptures are ouly Words and Letters (Jones 1914: 130).
While there is indeed a consistency with Descartes' reasoning here, again the
parallels with Ames are more staÿing: here Balling echoes and expands on an
argument offered in Mysteries (Fifth Difference).
Finally, Jones cites the language of the Light being the 'first Principle of all
religion', including this in his discussion of the 'Cartesian' influence on Candlesti&
(Jones 1914: 130-31). Yet this language too is actually a direct quotation from
Banes, where Ames argues, in familiar Quaker fashion, that it is the Light and not
the Bible that is central to religious faith (Ames, Third and Sixth Differences).
Therefore, despite Fix's and Rickerman and Swayne's claims that Jones reads
Candlestick as more Cartesian than Quaker, we see first of all that the aspects of
Descartes' and Spinoza's thought that Jones emphasises are the aspects that are
more mystical or spiritualistic than specifically rationalistic, as such, and, secondly,
that some of the passages he quotes in support of his Cartesian interpretation in
fact bear a much closer resemblance to Ames than to Descartes or Spinoza. Thus,
Jones' comparison of Candlestick to Descartes and Spinoza cannot in any case be
interpreted as supporting a rationalist reading of Candlestick that represents a radical
departure from Quaker thought. Instead, we have good reason to take Sewel's
interpretation seriously.
CONCLUSION: MORE SPIRITUALIST THAN RATIONALIST
While Candlestick shows Cartesian and Spinozistic influences, those influences are
limited to a few phrases and the employment of some rational argumentation ha
the s@e of Descartes. The actual discussion and description of the Light closely
resembles the Quaker view: the Light is not equivalent to reason but is a faculty
of divine inspiration. There is no evidence that the author equates the Light with
the faculty of reason; not only is the word 'reason' never used, but there are hints
of a critical attitude towards strong rationalism. The author is clearly indebted to
William Banes, drawing heavily from major points of discussion in Ames' Mysteries of the Kin2dom of God. The facts that Ames approved of The Li£ht upon the
Candlestick, that Mysteries is prominently mentioned on its title page, that Quaker
* The author wishes to thank Ann W. Upton, Special Collections Librarian and Quaker
BibIiographer at Haverford College, for providing me with a copy of Ames' De Verbor£elzflÿedell
uan her Rijcke Godts, and also wishes to thankJo Van Cauter, Phi) student at Ghent University,
for translating that document into English.
1. A Quaker Universalist Fellowship pamphlet reprinted an English version of The Light
upon tlze Candlestick, along with an excerpt from Jones' Spiritual Reformelx, and a Preface and an
Epilogue by Sally Pdckerman and Kingdon Swayne.
2. Note that 'spiritualism' in this paper does not refer to the nineteenth-century spiritualist
movement, but is either meant in a general sense to contrast with 'secularism' or is meant in the
more specific epistemological sense to refer to belief in the Light as inspiration from God, a
source of reliÿous knowledge surpassing the knowledge offered by unaided human inteilect.
3. Sewel's parents were converted to Quakerism by Ames in 1656.or 1657 (Hull 1938: 24).
4. Women did not normally speak in these meetings, although William Sewel's mother
requested permission to speak and apparently her message was well received (Sewel 1722: 442).
5. Hull notes that Galenus 'was almost persuaded by Ames to become a Quaker' (Hull
1938: 233).
6. The full quotation indicates that others were banned as well: 'stiff-headed Papists obligated to the Ron:dsh Chair, usurious Jews, English stiff-headed Quakers, Puritans and audacious
stupid Millennialists' (quoted in Looijesteijn 2009: 237).
7. Mertens (2009) points out that two other scholars, Wim K.lever and Marc Bedjai,
independently discovered this in the early 1990s.
8. Van den Enden's proposal was not accepted (Looijesteijn 2009: 236), but Plockhoy's
was, and Plockhoy in fact established a settlement in the New World, near present-day Lewes,
Delaware. After fourteen months, this settlement was destroyed when the English seized New
Netherland in 1664. Another note of interest about Van den Enden was that he had also been a
teacher of Spinoza (Looijesteijn 2009: 12).
9. A further intriguing note: when the English took over New Netherland, everything
Dutch was taken, including 'what belonged to the Quakin Society of P]ockhoy to a very naile"
(quoted in Looijesteijn 2009: 250-51). Looijesteijn takes this interesting phrasing as a further
indication that Plockhoy did not agree with Van den Enden's negative assessment of Quakers
(2009:251 n. 65, and see pp. 94-97 for more on the strong links between Piockhoy and the
Quakers).
10. Here and elsewhere interesting comparisons can be made to other arenas in which
Quakers and philosophers were in dialogue. For example, the Cambridge Platonists were also
interested in comparing or even equating the Light with reason, and one notable Cambridge
Platohist, Henry More, was frequently involved in philosophical conversations with Anne
Conway and her Quaker friends. See Hutton (2004) for details on Anne Conway, and see
Dudiak and Rediehs (2013) for more on connections between Quakers and philosophers.
V
168
QUAKER STUDIES
11. Because the English translation of Mysteries is not yet published, instead of using page
references I indicate the relevant section of the work.
12. Page references are from the version of Candlestick published in the pamphlet by the
Quaker Universalist Fellowship, except in cases where I quote Fix's quotations, as these seem to
P,._EDIEHS CANDLESTICK MYSTERIES
169
Fix, A.C., 1991. Prophecy and Reasom The Dutdz Collegiants in the Eady Enlightemltelzt, Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Harder, L., and Harder, M., 1952. Plockhoy feom Zurifi-zee: The Study of a Dutch Reformer in
Puritan England and Colonial America, Newton, KS: Board of Education mad Publicatiou,
be Fix's own translation of the wm'k.
13. Not only do many of Spinoza's 1670 arguments resemble Fisher's 1660 arguments, but
General Conference Mennonite Church.
they are also compatible with the views Ames discusses in Mysteries.
14. To identify the 'efficient cause' of something, according to Aristotle, is to identify what
Hull, W.I., 1938. The Rise of Quakefism in Amsterdam 1655-1665, Swarthmore College
brought it into being. Descartes makes use of efficient causation in his proof for the existence of
Hutton, S., 2004. Amw Cot*way: A Woman Philosopher, "Cambridge: Cambridge University
God. Having established that he himself exists, at least as a thinking thing 03/Ieditation II),
Descartes notices that among his thoughts is a concept of perfection, a concept he could not
have originated because he is not himself perfect. That concept of perfection, however, must
have an efficient cause. Therefore, there must be something eIse besides himself--something
perfect--that is the efficient cause of the concept of perfection. Thus, a perfect being must exist
(Meditation il!).
Monographs on Quaker History 4, Swarthmore, PA: Swazÿimore College.
Press.
" Jones, K., 1914. Spiritual Reforme1:ÿ in the I6th and 17th Centuries, London: McMillan & Co.
Looijesteijn, H., 2009. ' "Born to the Conunon Welfare": Pieter Plockhoy's Quest for a Chris-
tian Life (c. 1620-1664)', unpublished Phi) dissertation, European University Institute.
-- 2011. 'Between Sin and Salvation: The Seventeenth-Century Dutch Artisan Pieter
15. It should be noted that recent scholars have been re-assessing Jones' work. Elaine Pryce,
for example, re-evaluates Jones' understanding of mysticism, noting his de-emphasizing the uia
negatiua and favoring what can be called a more rationalistic version of mysticism, in that part of
Jones' agenda was to develop a version of mysticism that is harmonious with modem, progres-
sivist Protestantism (Pryce 2010: 523), which in tuna entails harmonising with the broad sense
of rationalism (that is, the version that includes sense perception, inductive reasoning, and
modern scientific reasoning). In my discussion that follows, I contrast Jones' understanding of
mysticism with the narrow version of rationalism. The narrow version of rationalism emphasizes both a Cartesian notion of innate ideas and the deductive reasoning process, in contrast to,
Plockhoy and his Ethics of Work', International Review of Sodal History 56, pp. 69-88.
Mertens, F., 2007. 'Franciscus van den Enden Works: The Brief Account of Ncw Nethedand',
http://users.telenet.be/fvde/Works4c.htm, accessed 1/8/2013.
-- 2009. 'Franciscus van den Enden Works: Introduction to the !<on' Verhael (Brief Account)',
http://users.telenet.be/fvde!Works4.htm, accessed 178/2013.
Popkin, R.H., 1985. 'Spinoza and Samuel Fisher', Philosophia: Philosophical Quarterly of Israel 15,
pp. 21%36.
-- 1987. 'Introduction', in Spinoza's Earliest Publication? The Hebrew Translation of Margaret Fell's
or even suspicious of, the experiential dimensions of human knowledge. Even those who
'A Louing Salutation to the Seed of Abraham among the [ews, whereuer they are scattered up and
accept Pryce's interpretation ofJones ÿ find that the distinction I draw still holds relevantly to
down upon the Face of the Earth', Assen: Van Gorcum, pp. 1-15.
the rest of my paper.
Pryce, E., 2010. '"Negative to a Marked Degree" or "An Intense and Glowing Faith": Rufus
16. This is not to say that Jones or I deny that Descartes was a rationalist. My own claim is
simply to say that some aspects of his views might better be described as experiential (what is
perceived or experienced within) than rational (what is deduced through a reasoning process).
P,.EFEP-.EN CES
Ames, W., 1661. The Mysteries of the Kingdom of God, trans. J. Van Cauter, in Van Cauter, J.,
and Kediehs, L., 2013 (forthcoming). 'Spiritualism and Kadonalism in Dutch Collegiant
Thought: New Evidence from William Ames's Mysteries of the Kingdom of God (1661),
with a Trandation', Lias 40, pp. 105-73. Original complete Dutch title: De Verbor2en-
Jones and Quaker Qnietism', Common Kawwledge 16, pp. 518-31.
Pdckemaan, S., and Swayne, K., 1992. 'Preface' and 'Epilogue', in The Light upon the
Candlestick, Quaker Universalist Fellowship, http://universaÿst£riends.org/pdUcandle.pdf,
accessed 5/12/2012, pp. 3-9, 24-27.
Sewel, W., 1722. The History of the Rise, Increase, and Progress of the Christian People called
Quakers, London: J. SoMe.
Smith, J., 1867. A Desc@tiue Catalogue of Friends Books, London: Joseph Smith.
AUTHOK DETAILS
theden van het Rid'dee Godts, ende de wer&inge leydinge en bestieringe tan Godts Geest verklaelr in
complete Dutch title: Her gi&t op den KandeIam; Dienende lot opmerckinge van de voomaamste
Laura Rediehs is associate professor of philosophy and coordinator of peace
studies at St. Lawrence University, in Canton, New York, USA. She joined the
St Lawrence faculty after completing a PllD in philosophy at the University of
Minnesota, specializing in philosophy of science. In her current research, she
investigates the theory of knowledge that emerges from Quaker thought, and
dingen in het boeckje genaamt De verbogentheden van het Ro'ke Ghodts tegens Galenus
how this theory of knowledge reconciles science and reliÿon.
tegenstellinge van de letterIijcke oeffeningen uootgestelt als de ware Godtsdienst door Galenus
Abrahamsz ende door sun aenhangers ende toestemmers gelo@, 1661.
[Bailing, P.], 1992 [1663]. The Light upon the Candlestick, trans. B. Furly, Quaker Universalist
Fellowship, http://universalist£dends.org/pdf/candle.pdf, accessed 05/12/2012. Original
Abrahamsz. en zO'n toestemmers verhandelt en besclzreven door William Ames, 1662.
Dandelion, P., 2007. An Introduction to Quakerism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dudiak, J., and P-,ediehs, L., 2013. 'Quakers, Philosophy, and Truth', in B. Dandelion and S.
AngelI (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Quaker Studies, O.-cford: Oxford University Press, pp.
507-19.
Mailing address: Department of Philosophy, St Lawrence University, Canton, NY
13617, USA. Emaih
[email protected].