Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
The Routledge Handbook of Libertarianism
…
20 pages
1 file
AI-generated Abstract
This chapter examines the complexities surrounding the classification of classical liberalism and its distinction from contemporary understandings of liberalism. It critiques the traditional views that associate classical liberalism primarily with laissez-faire economics and explores Hayek's theoretical framework, which emphasizes the evolutionary and social processes underpinning the Open Society. The discussion highlights the limitations of moral theory in evaluating the Open Society and advances the notion that ethical perspectives are products of social evolution rather than external standards. Ultimately, the text defends the Hayekian conception of classical liberalism as a sophisticated approach that challenges standard normative evaluations of social orders.
Tradition & discovery, 1999
An extended discussion of Richard Allen's Beyond Liberalism: The Political Thought of F. A. Hayek & Michael Polanyi in which the book's prominent themes and arguments are described, and certain inaccuracies and shortcomings noted.
iv This edition is published in cooperation with the
Palgrave Studies in Classical Liberalism, 2023
In this chapter classical liberalism, and different liberal predicaments and potentials to fight back against populism, are explored. Liberals cannot resort to the same methods as the populists without abandoning liberalism itself. But the three dimensions of classical liberalism, about institutions, economics and society, and the liberal spirit reinforce each other and provide the potential for fighting back against populist threats. Keyword Classical liberalism • Liberal predicaments • Liberal potentials • Liberal institutions • Liberal economy and society • the liberal spirit
Socrates: Disagreement about what is the cause of the hatred and anger, my good man? Let's look at it this way. If we disagree, you and I, about quantity, over which of two groups is greater, would our disagreement over this make us enemies and angry with each other, or wouldn't we quickly resolve the issue by resorting to counting?... Euthyphro: How else? Socrates: Then what topic, exactly, would divide us and what decision would we be unable to reach such that we would be enemies and angry with one another? Perhaps you don't have an answer at hand, so see while I'm talking whether it's the just and the unjust, and the noble and shameful, and the good and the bad. Isn't it these things that divide us and about which we're not able to come to a satisfactory decision and so become enemies of one another, whenever that happens, whether it's me and you, or any other men? Euthyphro: It is indeed this disagreement, Socrates, and over these things.-Plato, Euthyphro7b-d.
Liberalism is a term employed in a dizzying variety of ways across the humanities and social sciences. This essay seeks to reframe how the liberal tradition is understood. I start by delineating different types of response – prescriptive, comprehensive, explanatory – that are frequently conflated in answering the question “what is liberalism?” I then discuss assorted methodological strategies employed in the existing literature: after rejecting “stipulative” and “canonical” approaches, I outline a contextualist alternative. On this (comprehensive) account, liberalism is best characterised as the sum of the arguments that have been classified as liberal, and recognised as such by other self-proclaimed liberals, over time. In the remainder of the article I present an historical analysis of shifts in the meaning of liberalism in Anglo-American political thought between 1850 and 1950, focusing in particular on how John Locke came to be seen as a liberal. I also explore the emergence of the category of "liberal democracy". I argue that the scope of the liberal tradition was massively expanded during the middle decades of the twentieth century, such that it came to be seen by many as the constitutive ideology of the West. This capacious (and deeply confusing) understanding of liberalism was produced by a conjunction of the ideological wars fought against “totalitarianism” and assorted developments in the social sciences. Today we both inherit and inhabit it.
SSRN Electronic Journal, 2016
It is widely considered that minorities' rights and dignity are protected in liberal societies particularly in western liberal countries up to a level humanly possible. However, in this article I show that it's not as much heroic a theory as we conceive specifically when the liberal society is committed to accommodate plurality of ideas and lifestyles. After briefly explaining principal tenets of classical liberalism I claim that some fundamental weakness of the theory makes it untenable in liberal plural society let alone non-western society of diversity.
A Great Transformation?: Global Perspectives on Contemporary Capitalisms, 2017
There is an apparent paradox at the core of the study of neoliberalism. Although a growing research literature in recent decades have documented how neoliberal ideas about free markets and privatization has been increasingly dominant in universities, government agencies and international organizations, this neoliberal dominance have not in meant any meaningful sense meant rollback of state power. Among the more sophisticated works of the neoliberalism, we have seen an analysis stating that the goal of neoliberalism is not a simple realization of minimal state in which state power is rolled back in favour of market forces. Instead, researchers such as Michel Foucault, Philip Mirowski and Jamie Peck see neoliberalism as a project that is aiming towards a redefinition of the relationship between state and market. The goal is not only to deregulate, but also to use state power to actively reshape the economy. This nuanced understanding of the relationship between state and market in neoliberalism, however is often made by contrasting it with a distorted version of the classic liberalism of the nineteenth century 1 , which is being portrayed as a simple realization of the principle of laissez-faire 2 and the minimal state. This idea of a sharp contrast between neoliberalism and classical laissez-faire liberalism can be traced back to the early neoliberal such as Hayek, who in the period after the Great Depression formulated neoliberalism, as a stated contrast to what they perceived as the dogmatism and simplicity 1 Liberalism purposes for the purposes of this article, us delimited as the self-identifying political liberal movement in line with Fawcett, (2015). "Liberals" from the period before the term was first used in Spain from the 18010s are therefore only touched upon sporadically 2 The term laissez-faire originated from the physiocratic school in 1700s France (Viner, 1960), but in this article will be used to denote the period of the doctrines dominance within liberal economic thinking in the first part of the nineteenth century.
3
hayekian "Classical" liberalism
Gerald Gaus
� is TheRe a "classical libeRal" View?
Political theories are structures of conceptual, normative and empirical commitments (Chapman 1965;Freeden 1996: part I;Gaus 2000: ch. 3). We seek to understand them by classifying instances according to families or allied approaches-socialism, conservatism, liberalism, feminism, libertarianism, and so on. These classificatory schemes are critical to understanding, but at the same time they run the danger of distorting a specific political view by stressing some features over others and perhaps employing categories that it abjures. These are unavoidable dangers of classification; we should be aware of them and always inquire whether our classificatory schemes are interfering with understanding a theory on its own terms and appreciating its insights. I believe that attempts at classification have been particularly distorting with respect to "classical liberalism. " To be sure, some political philosophers describe their view as "classical liberal" (e.g., von Mises 2005Mises [1927), yet the label is most often employed-perhaps originally devised-as a contrast class, designating liberal theories that are not "new, " "high, " or "egalitarian" forms of liberalism (Freeman 2011;Brennan and Tomasi 2012). 1 The "new liberalism" of the early twentieth century, which sought to reconcile elements of liberalism with socialism (Hobhouse 1911;Dewey 1931;1935) was especially keen to distinguish its "renewed" and "progressive" version of liberalism from the "earlier" (Hobhouse 1911: 54) or "old" version (Dewey 1931), which was almost always equated with "laissez-faire" economics (Hobhouse 1911;ch. IV). Because throughout the twentieth century the classical political economists (including Smith, Ricardo, and John Stuart Mill) were widely thought to be advocates of "laissez-faire, " this classical system of political economy was often assumed to be the heart of "classical liberalism, " a perception that continues to this day (Rawls 2001: 137). The confusions that these associations have engendered are legion. The classical economists were not advocates, but indeed usually critics, of laissez-faire Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 17:48 27 Nov 2021;For: 9781315709727, chapter3, 10.4324/9781317486794.ch3 (Robbins 1952: 34ff.;O'Brien 2004;Gray 1986: ch. 4); in fact, the only significant "classical liberal political economist" who sought to defend a weak version of laissez-faire was John Stuart Mill, and he is usually credited at being a paradoxical, transitional figure, bridging the "classical" and "modern" liberal views (Kors 2011;Gaus 2017).
The tendency to distort a sophisticated political theory by slotting it into a common view of "classical liberalism" is especially manifest with respect to the work of F. A. Hayek, who ultimately concluded that his view was best classified as "Old Whiggism" (Hayek 1960: 409). Samuel Freeman, holding that classical liberalism is intimately bound up with modern economic models, depicts Hayek as basing his liberalism on the pursuit of efficiency, yet he admits that Hayek was skeptical that we could know much about efficiency and equilibrium (Freeman 2011: 23n;compare Hayek 1978a). Freeman's, as have other attempts at classification, also depicts Hayek and the classical liberal tradition as essentially "indirect" or "rule-" utilitarian (Freeman 2011: 23n;Gray 1984: 59-60), yet utilitarianism is Hayek's bête noire, manifesting a constructivist delusion that we can have adequate knowledge of the overall consequences of our actions and so can design systems to optimize good consequences (Hayek 1973;1978b). 2 Hayek is a far deeper and more original thinker than these familiar efforts at categorization indicate. Indeed, in my estimation, he points the way forward to the most sophisticated and compelling account of the Open Society on offer-a line of analysis that is, I think, barely recognized in current political philosophy. Because it does not fit neatly into familiar classification systems, its distinctive character is largely ignored. My aim in this chapter is not simply to demonstrate the originality and power of Hayek's theory but also to extend and develop it in the light of more recent work. The present essay might well be described as a "Hayekian" analysis, not an explication of Hayek (compare Rawls 1999: 221-7). Rather than seeking to articulate a general account of classical liberalism, I shall outline an essentially Hayekian view of the Open Society.
Section 2 introduces the contrast between small, closed orders of cooperation and the extended rule-based "order of action, " which Hayek calls the Great, or Open, Society. Section 3 sketches the "twin ideas" at the heart of Hayekian political theory: self-organization and social evolution. Section 4 then summarizes the idea of the Open Society and why Hayek thinks central themes in modern political thought are hostile to it. Section 5 takes up the question of normative justification. Given Hayek's stress on complexity and ignorance, is there any room left for normative evaluation in Hayekian liberalism?
� exTended complex oRdeRs
�.� Systems of Rules
Traditionally-to many, by definition-political philosophy focuses on political and legal institutions, their functioning, and their moral evaluation. On this orthodox understanding, the essence of a classical liberalism would be a theory about moral requirements regarding state institutions and their limits. Given the strong associations of classical liberalism with economic theory that we have noted, we also would expect it to be a theory that provides arguments in favor of market over political arrangements in a wide array of contexts. Thus we might expect a classical liberal view to be one that, say, upholds the values of economic liberty and private property (Brennan and Tomasi 2012;Freeman 2011). geRald gaus While, of course, Hayek considers formal political institutions, constitutions, and legislation (1979)-and he certainly insists on the importance of liberty and propertyhis core concern is the basis of social order, especially the moral framework of society (1973; 1988). 3 In a Hayekian-inspired analysis, "classical liberalism" is first and foremost a theory about the basis of social order and its complicated dependence on systems of rules.
�.� Complex Orders
Consider a small society such as that described by Russell Hardin: Axel Leijonhufvud … characterizes the village society of eleventh century France in which the villager Bodo lived. We have detailed knowledge of that society from the parish records of the church of St. Germaine. Today one would say that that church is in the center of Paris, but in Bodo's time it was a rural parish distant enough from Paris that many of its inhabitants may never have seen Paris. Virtually everything Bodo consumed was produced by about eighty people, all of whom he knew well. Indeed, most of what he consumed was most likely produced by his own family. If anyone other than these eighty people touched anything he consumed, it was salt, which would have come from the ocean and would have passed through many hands on the way to St. Germaine, or it was spices, which would have traveled enormous distances and passed through even more hands. (Hardin 1999: 401-2) Bodo's village was comprised of a small number of fairly homogeneous agents-their preferences were not radically diverse. Moreover, they tended to share a common, accepted set of act-types: They categorized the available actions (being religious, being a father, trading) in similar ways (Hardin 2003: 98-99). Such a society still needs a system of social rules, 4 but the small number of rules, homogenous preferences, and shared categorizations implies that the rule system will be simple and the effects of changes predictable. Because there are only a small number of rules, there will not be complicated interactions among them; because individual preferences are homogenous, it is relatively easy to predict how people will respond to rules; and because they share similar, and rather limited, categorizations, they will understand their option sets in similar ways and so the rules can be relatively exhaustive in identifying what is permitted (Gaus and Nichols 2017). As Hayek stressed, such groups share a thick set of "aims and perceptions, " and this sharing guides social coordination and allows participants to agree on acceptable outcomes (Hayek 1988: 12). Moreover, predicting the social consequences of changes in the rules of cooperation is a relatively tractable problem. The rules of such an order can be understood as rules of regulation, designed to achieve certain common ends or values (Hayek 1973: 48-52).
Let us add more individuals, extending to hundreds of thousands. If the individuals share a rich set of common goals (say they are all devoted to living in accordance with the same principles of justice) and so have relatively homogeneous preferences (they have some different goals but share overarching regulative values), they could still be Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 17:48 27 Nov 2021;For: 9781315709727, chapter3, 10.4324/9781317486794.ch3 organized by rules of regulation that have a reasonable chance of securing their shared ends and common normative commitments (cf. Cohen 2008: 283ff.). Now, however, let us introduce a high level of heterogeneity of preferences (or aims) and ways of classifying actions and options. Depending far less on shared aims and goals to secure cooperation, this group will require a far more extensive system of rules. Hayek recognized that such rule systems-composed of a large number of highly heterogeneous individuals guided by a number of rules-quickly give rise to complex systems (Hayek 1967b;1978a: 26-27;Saari 1995;Mitchell 2009: 12). In perhaps the earliest analysis of such systems, John Stuart Mill (2006[1872: 370-3, 438-40; Auyang 1998: 173-4) considered a system S composed of elements {e 1 …e n } and an overall resulting outcome O. In his System of Logic, Mill proposes three features of property O:
1. O is not the sum of {e 1 …e n }; 2. O is of an entirely different character than {e 1 …e n }; 3. O cannot not be predicted or deduced from the behavior of the members of {e 1 …e n } considered independently (i.e., apart from their interactions in S).
This is the idea of an emergent property recognized by Hayek.
The "emergence" of "new" patterns that develop as a result in the number of elements between which simple relations exist means that this larger structure as a whole will possess certain general or abstract features that will recur independently of the particular values of the individual data, so long as the general structure (as described, e.g., by an algebraic equation) is preserved. Such "wholes, " defined in terms of certain general properties of their structure, will constitute distinctive objects of explanation for a theory, even though such a theory may be merely a particular way of fitting together statements about the relation between individual elements. (1967b: 267; see also Vaughn 1999: 248) Thus it is said that waves are an emergent property of H 2 O. The properties studied by hydrology are not the sum of the properties of hydrogen and oxygen (as opposed to a mechanical force, which may be seen as the sum of its causes); waves have a very different character than a chemical compound, and the properties of an individual water molecule do not allow us to deduce the relevant laws concerning waves. Emergent properties are distinguished from mere "resultant" properties on the grounds that, while a resultant property is the expected outcome of S, an emergent property is novel and, given our understanding of {e 1 …e n }, often unexpected or surprising (Auyang 1999: 177). The scientific study of complex orders cannot, Hayek insisted, aim at the prediction of the "specific" future states or values of the individual elements. To be sure, just how specific a specific prediction must be is context dependent; his claim, though, was that in many natural sciences (such as parts of physics), "it will generally be possible to specify all those aspects of the phenomenon in which we are interested with any degree of precision we may need for our purposes" (Hayek 1967a: 8). In contrast, when dealing with complex phenomena we are simply unable to specify the values (in contemporary terms, the system is modeled in nonlinear equations; Vaughn 1999: 245;Holland 2014: 4;Mitchell 2009: 22ff.); we can only predict the "range of phenomena to expect" (Hayek 1967a: 11;1967b). We can understand the general principles on which the system operates, and with this knowledge we can predict the parameters within which the system will settle. This is, as Hayek says, an idea of "great importance for the understanding of the theoretical methods of the social sciences" (Hayek 1955: 43). It is the failure to understand the limits of social prediction that leads to the ill-fated attempt to employ social science to engineer society.
�.� The Order of Actions
Readers in political philosophy may perhaps already be dismayed; what can all this highly theoretical social science have to do with the case for "classical liberalism" and the Open Society? It is, however, absolutely central to Hayek's understanding of the rule-based extended orders, for his fundamental claim is that the "order of actions" that characterizes an extended society is a property that emerges from its underlying moral and social rules and the way heterogeneous agents act under them (see Mack 2006). Not only does Hayek insist on the basic importance of rules and institutions ( §2.1), but he also stresses that an extended order of diverse agents cannot be identified with, or reduced to, these rules and institutions or its "basic structure." Our ultimate concern in social and political philosophy, Hayek stresses, is the sort of social order characteristic of a society. In an extended order composed of diverse agents guided by a large set of rules, this order is inherently complex-it emerges from the system of rules, yet it is neither equivalent to them nor can be it be predicted as a simple resultant of those rules.
�.� How Complex?
Hayek was manifestly correct that the social order of a large and diverse society will display characteristics of a complex system (Page 2011). This in itself was a tremendous insight. As he recognized (1955; 1973), political philosophers often take up an engineering perspective on society, supposing that a society can construct a basic structure that will reach the social and moral goals set for it. Some seek a basic structure that will apportion holdings according to desert or that yields the greatest happiness for the greatest number. This is plausible if societies are simple orders like the village in which Bodo lived; the social rules can be understood simply as effective instruments to secure posited goals. However, complex systems are characterized by constant novelty. Their elements are coupled, so that a change in one variable can reverberate throughout the system (Hayek 1967b). Because of this, the emergent outcomes generated by their rules can be deeply surprising.
However, Hayek seldom took up the question of just how complex extended societies are, and we shall see in section 5 that a good deal turns on this issue. The strong Hayekian thesis is that diverse, extended, social orders are maximally complex. An order is maximally complex-indeed, chaotic-if any change in its underlying structure of social rules moves the system to a new state that is entirely uncorrelated with the present system state (Kauffman 1993: ch. 2;Gaus 2016: 61-74). Somewhat more formally, we can say that in such systems, emergent property O (an order of actions, a system state) emerges Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 17:48 27 Nov 2021; For: 9781315709727, chapter3, 10.4324/9781317486794.ch3 on rules {r 1 …r n }; any change in a rule r i to its closest variant r i * (i.e. a slight change in r i ) produces an order O* that is entirely uncorrelated with O-knowing state O does not provide one with any evidence as to what O* would be like. In Stuart A. Kauffman's terms, such systems manifest "complexity catastrophe" (1993: 52). Such maximally complex systems occur in a large set of rules wherein each is interconnected with all others. That is, a change in any one rule, r i , affects the functioning of all other rules, so that one change affects everything, and so O* may be entirely unlike O. 5 In more familiar philosophic terms, such systems are characterized by "holism. " For example, in thoroughly holistic theories of justification, the justification of every element of a system of values or beliefs is dependent on all others-such systems are often depicted as "webs, " indicating a very high degree of interdependence among many variables. It is precisely such systems that give rise to complexity catastrophes; a small variation in one value can jump the system to a radically different state.
Hayek certainly embraced some form of holism: "systems of rules of conduct will develop as a whole" (1967c: 71). But systems can be holistic-the functioning and consequences of one rule can be dependent on others-without being maximally so. In a system that is moderately complex, the functioning and consequences of some rules will be dependent on others; in such systems, it still remains the case that a small variation in one rule from, say, r i to r i * can move the system from O to O*, where O* differs far more greatly from O that r i * does from r i . Still, in such moderately complex systems, the values of O and O* will be correlated: knowing O is indicative of what O* will be (Gaus 2016: 73-4). As we shall see, it matters a great deal whether we interpret Hayek's complexity analysis in the strong or moderate sense.
It is important to emphasize that the difficulty of predicting what the emergent property-in this case, the order of actions-will be does not mean that we are ignorant of the way the heterogeneous rule-based systems behave. It is sometimes claimed that Hayek's thought is, at bottom, contradictory: he insists on our ignorance of social processes but, out of his analysis of ignorance, he generates prescriptions about what we should do (Hodgson 1993: 183). If we know enough to say why, for example, socialism will not work, then we must have good enough insights into the economic order to intervene to promote social goals. This, though, is wrong. As we have seen, on a complex systems analysis, we can know quite a lot about the principles on which complex orders operate, and this theoretical knowledge allows us to say that some system states cannot be achieved and that some ways of organizing social cooperation are more efficient than others; 6 we also know that we are unable to predict the course of, or control, the complex order itself. As we shall see ( §4), the analysis of complexity provides sound reasons against planning that seeks to control the emergent order. There is nothing contradictory about a mix of knowledge of principle and ignorance of what is a good plan or optimal policy.
� The Twin ideas
�.� Self-Organization
If we cannot organize such systems according to a deliberate plan-if they cannot be engineered-then how are they organized? Hayek repeatedly refers to "the twin ideas of evolution and spontaneous order. " 7 Some commentators question whether these ideas are related (Hodgson 1993: 177ff.); however, more recent analyses have modeled relations between self-organization and evolution (Kauffman 1993;Mitchell 2009: ch.1; Holland 2014: ch. 3).
A system is self-organizing when its elements behave in such a way as to accommodate their behavior to each other so as to achieve a stable pattern of relatively dense interactions. In a physical system, the state space may exhibit basins of attractions in which elements gravitate over time to equilibria; it may be in principle impossible to predict on which equilibrium the system will settle, but it may well be extremely likely that the self-organizing system will gravitate to one of them (Kauffman 1993: 175ff.;Smith 1998). Complexity and self-organization are indeed intimately related ideas (Waldrop 1992: 300ff.). The Hayekian analysis is inspired by Hume's observation that coordination of a group on a social rule arises through "a slow progression, and by our repeated experience of the inconveniences of transgressing" it (Hume 1978: 490;Kukathas 1989: 88ff.;Hardin 2007: ch. 4). Over long series of iterated interactions, individuals adjust their actions to each other to secure stable patterns of interactions.
Yet not all self-organizing patterns are especially fruitful for the network of individuals. Although the pattern of interactions cannot be so dire that the constituent individuals expire, systems can get stuck at poor "local optima"-there are no marginal changes in their social rules that will produce better outcomes, yet overall, the individuals are not doing well in the system. (We can measure "doing well" in different ways-how well the diverse individuals satisfy their aims, their health, longevity, incidence of violence, wealth, and so on.) It is here that the second-and I think even less well understood-of the twin ideas, social evolution, enters.
�.� Social Evolution: Macro and Micro
Hayek insisted that social evolution did not rely on Darwinian natural selection. Cultural evolution, says Hayek, "simulates" Lamarckian evolution because acquired characteristics-rules and institutions-are transmitted from earlier to later generations (1988: 25; cf. Mesoudi 2011: 43-4). This is accomplished, he argued, through individual-toindividual transmission of social-moral rules, crucially through imitation (1967c: 67; 1979: 156-7). The more recent, and much more sophisticated, work of scholars such as Peter Richerson and Robert Boyd (2005: ch. 3) has greatly added to our understanding of cultural transmission, distinguishing conformity bias (doing as most others do), prestige bias (copying high-status individuals), unbiased transmission, and various content biased transmissions (e.g., a bias toward rules that accord well with our sentiments; Gaus 2015). It is important to appreciate that the teaching and preaching of social-moral rules is an important form of transmission.
An evolutionary analysis requires, in addition to a transmission mechanism, sources of variation and selection. In cultural evolution, variation in social-moral rules can come from random changes, errors in transmission, drift, or explicit revision (Mesoudi 2011: ch.3;Richerson and Boyd 2005: 68ff). This last is especially important. There is no reason why a theory of cultural evolution cannot appeal to explicit efforts to improve socialmoral rules; in this sense, cultural evolution is by no means simply "blind" (see §5). Some might decide that a current moral rule is objectionable and so, say, start preaching an alternative. Although Hayek's evolutionary account is often criticized as having no room for conscious attempts at innovation, an evolutionary analysis requires variation, and Hayek certainly accepts that rules can be consciously altered.
It would seem that what cannot be consciously determined on Hayek's social evolutionary account is whether a cultural innovation is adaptive. That requires competitive selection mechanisms. Hayek's account of selection is complicated, indeed more so than he often suggests. Selection occurs at both the macro and micro levels. At the macro level, "the selection process of evolution will operate on the order as a whole"; what is selected, Hayek (1967c: 71) argues, is the order of actions that arises from numerous interacting rules, other elements of the social system, and the wider environment. At the macro level, selection pressures operate directly on "the order of actions of a group" (1967c: 72). The distinction between a set of rules and the order of actions to which it gives rise ( §2.3) allows Hayek to distinguish the focus of selective pressure (the order of actions) and the underlying rules, which are transmitted from generation to generation ( §2.1). Recall that on Hayek's analysis, a group of individuals living under a set of social rules, {r 1 …r n }, will give rise to a certain emergent order of social interactions, O; it is this order on which macro selection operates (Hayek 1967b: 23-4).
On Hayek's analysis, macro social evolution is based on a form of group selection. "The rules of conduct have … evolved because the groups who practiced them were more successful and displaced others" (1973: 18, 1988: 25). Just what is meant by "group selection" is a vexed issue; models with very different dynamics are often categorized under this rather vague term. 8 Leaving nomenclature aside, a crucial claim is that if society S 1 , characterized by order of actions O 1 , is more productive than S 2 based on O 2 , society S 1 will tend to win conflicts with S 2 , a mechanism akin to natural selection (cf. Bowles and Gintis 2011). But perhaps more importantly, the members of S 2 , seeing the better-off participants in S 1 characterized by O 1 , may either immigrate to S 1 or seek to copy its underlying rules, thus inducing differential rates of reproduction between the two sets of underling rules (Hayek 1979: 26;1973: 3, 17-18;1988: 6, 25, 43).
Although in some statements, Hayek seems to suggest that all selection occurs at this macro level, his more nuanced view is that, while the macro level is the primary locus of selection, rule selection also takes place in the form of competition between rules within a society (1988: 23). For a rule r to be selected, it must be contributory to a selected order, O, but it must also attract allegiance within the group of individuals who coordinate via r. Individuals are constantly testing rules to determine whether conformity suits their overall concerns. We see here an especially intimate tie between self-organization and social evolution: The process by which self-organization occurs (individuals searching for rules that satisfy their aims) is also a process of evolutionary selection. Although in his discussions of social evolution, Hayek himself disparaged rule selection based on how well a rule conformed to one's social or moral ideals, 9 any plausible account of the selection of moral rules within a group must accord weight to how well those rules conform to the moral sense and judgment of different individuals. One of the factors that determine the within-group fitness of a moral rule is its ability to secure allegiance and be taught to the next generation. This is a case of content bias; rules that accord with people's moral sensibilities are more apt to be learned and transmitted. geRald gaus � The open socieTy and iTs enemies
�.� The Evolution of the Extended, Open Society
Over the last 300-400 years, a self-organizing network of moral rules and institutions has evolved that has provided the basis for worldwide cooperation. As Hayek stresses, to say that this order has evolved is not to deny that large parts of it were deliberatively constructed (1988: 37), but the emergent order of actions was not itself so constructed. This network secures wide-scale cooperation under conditions of wide and deep diversity; indeed, not only does it allow cooperation in the face of diversity (itself no mean feat) but also draws on deep heterogeneity as a pillar of cooperation (Friedman 2008). It is hard to overestimate the revolutionary character of this development. Throughout human history, cooperative schemes were largely based on some form of homogeneity-some way in which "we, " who were a distinct people who shared characteristics, engaged in a rich network of cooperation that, if not hostile to others, certainly was less concerned with maintaining relations of trust and beneficial interchange with them (Greene 2013: part I; Haidt 2012: part III). The tremendous scaling up of this order of cooperation, based on a moral order that extends trust and notions of fairness to massively extended networks of cooperative interactions (Rose 2011;Gaus 2015), leads to what Hayek called the Great, or Open, Society.
It is critical to stress that this order is not only distinctive because of its extent but also for the way it draws on deep and wide diversity of preferences, goals, and values (Gaus 2016: ch.4). It is because of this, perhaps, that some see a utilitarian idea lurking-the order of actions maximizes the satisfaction of diverse preferences. We can safely say that hitherto no human order of actions has been able to draw on, and in so doing satisfy, the diverse aims of so many people, but we cannot say that the satisfaction of preferences is maximized, assuming some sense can be made of that idea. More importantly, should we identify some way in which overall preference satisfaction is less than we wish or can imagine, this would not indicate a flaw in the order, for there is no engineering aim to successfully maximize.
�.� Property, Markets and Order
As we have seen, networks with a large number of heterogeneous elements can be highly complex-in the extreme case, they are chaotic. Although we cannot eliminate complexity from networks of heterogeneous interactions, we have powerful reasons to seek to reduce complexity and secure a social order that provides a more predictable pattern of interactions. This can be done by partially decoupling the decisions of agents, lessening the complexity of the system, so that changes in one's agent's action do not automatically induce changes throughout. What I have elsewhere called "jurisdictional rights" serve this function (Gaus 2011: 199ff.). Rather than seeking to construct "a system of assessment that enables diverse interests to be brought together in a field of calculation, " this method aims "to keep them apart, in order to simplify the basis for decision making" (D' Agostino 2003: 104).
In effect, we say that in a society with n individual members, there are n separate spheres in which an answer … may be sought, each of which is, in theory, inviolable and particular to the individual who occupies it. A decides for himself what Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 17:48 27 Nov 2021; For: 9781315709727, chapter3, 10.4324/9781317486794.ch3 he should believe; B decides for herself; and so on.… In other words, we don't approach the matter of "basic belief " as one which … requires that individuals' judgments about this matter be aggregated…. We see it, rather, as one which is devolved to individuals whose rights to decide the matter for themselves are scrupulously protected. (D' Agostino 2003: 105) Property rights and markets function in this way. As John Gray (1993: 314) once noted, "The importance of several [i.e., private] property for civil society is that it acts as an enabling device whereby rival and possibly incommensurable conceptions of the good may be implemented and realized without any recourse to any collective decision-procedure. " Private-property rights are quintessentially jurisdictional. To own property is to have a sphere in which one is free to act on, and explore, one's own purposes, plans, and beliefs and yet, given markets, one is able to collaborate with others as one thinks best (Hayek 1988: 35). Because the very foundation of an extended order is to allocate firm jurisdictions to each participant, so that each has a socially recognized basis for planning and acting, it is no exaggeration to say that justice is the recognition of jurisdictions in such a society (Hayek 1988: 33). Jurisdictional rights-most especially property rights-are critical because they provide a basis for each person to act on her or his heterogeneous preferences. We must always remember that diversity and heterogeneity are at the core of the complex Open Society. It is possible to organize on the basis of shared aims, but such organization is always homogenizing, taking us back toward simple orders. Any complex order must provide a basis for each person to undertake action based on her own goals. Marketsself-organizing systems of heterogeneous interactions-are the lynchpin, providing a way for innumerable heterogeneous agents to coordinate plans and share information (Hayek 1945).
�.� Socialist Planning
A traditional aspiration of socialism was a large-scale social order guided by a collective plan, allocating resources and activities to secure the greatest collective benefit. As some communists put it, under socialism, "society will be transformed into a huge working organization for cooperative production. There will then be neither disintegration of production nor anarchy of production [i.e., competition and markets]. In such a social order, production will be organized" (Bukharin and Preobrazhensky 1969: ch. 3, §19). Society was to become one huge factory. To Hayek, this is perhaps the fundamental error of social theory-to treat a complex system as if it were an organization (1973: 36ff.). An organization may be complicated, but it is not complex; its aims are set by its global controller, and plans are designed to achieve them. As Hayek recognized, complex systems have no global controller (Rosser 1999: 176). Any attempt to treat them as organizations will spur an iteration of ad hoc interventions as the complex system responds in unexpected ways, leading to a decrease in the freedom of agents in the system to decide their own courses of actions. In the end, the system may become dysfunctional, failing to secure even the most basic ends of its participants (Hayek 1944). In contrast, systems based on property and markets allow each individual to adjust her plans to revisions in the plans of others, acting and reacting as she sees fit (and sometimes not reacting as all, say to the way a person chooses to use her property to worship her God), yet all these constant changes at the micro level are consistent with an order of actions.
�.� Social Justice
Hayek (1976) famously insists that social justice is a mirage. In order to appreciate both the power and the limits of this claim, consider first what has been called a "patterned" theory of social justice, according to which a social state is just only if the holdings in that state correspond to a pattern such as "to each according to his deserts" (Nozick 1974: ch. 7). Hayek's argument against treating complex orders as organizations applies here. The particular array of outcomes produced by complex orders (person A receives x, person B receives y, person C receives z, and so on) is unpredictable: Holdings ultimately depend on an innumerable and unknowable range of factors. Thus Hayek (1976: ch. 7) insists that any government devoted to such a strong conception of social justice must constantly violate the rules (whatever they are) on which the complex order of actions depends, since the overall array of outcomes produced by any system of rules cannot be predicted. This is why "rule utilitarianism" is ultimately oxymoronic in a complex system: The system of rules cannot be designed to ensure the "correct outcome, " and so devotion to producing this outcome must involve constant violation of the underlying rules. Recall that the ultimate order of actions is an emergent property on a set of rules, so no matter how much we refine a set of rules, we cannot ensure that it secures the desired outcome. So any theory that is devoted to an overall outcome must necessarily be one that constantly interferes with the operation of the rules on which the overall order depends.
Note that this analysis would not apply to a theory of justice that adopts institutions and then defines as justice whatever outcomes this scheme produces. This helps explain a remark of Hayek's that has so puzzled commentators. In the preface of a book dismissing social justice as a mirage (1976: xiii), he asserts that he has no deep objection to the most important work on social justice in the history of political philosophy-John Rawls's A Theory of Justice. Hayek's (1976: 100) point is that Rawls's proposal does not seek to select specific distributive outcomes but rather articulates principles that might ground complaints against a set of rules; if the rules withstand such complaints, then the distribution, whatever it might be, is just. Because Hayek reads Rawls's theory as insisting on a refinement of the rules underlying the order of actions and not one seeking to specify the overall outcome, he insists that it is consistent with the complex order of the Open Society.
� The paRadox of moRal inquiRy
�.� Complexity and Moral Reform
The least developed aspect of the Hayekian project is the justification of the rules of the Open Society and the possibility of deliberate reform and justification. We have just observed that he seems friendly to (his understanding of) the Rawlsian project as one Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 17:48 27 Nov 2021;For: 9781315709727, chapter3, 10.4324/9781317486794.ch3 that seeks to determine whether free and equal citizens might have bona fide complaints against the rules of the Open Society. It would seem, though, that if a complaint is to make any sense, it must be possible to reform the order of actions in a way that mitigates the complaint by reforming and improving the nature of our cooperative arrangements. But given the complex nature of the order of actions, can we even make sense of this?
The distinction between high and moderate complexity ( §2.4) is critical in answering this query. If the system is maximally complex, every feature of the overall order of actions emerges on the interactions of every rule. Change any one rule, and the order of actions can be entirely transformed. If so, it is quite useless to evaluate whether any specific rule is functioning adequately, for all rules are, as it were, implicated in everything. Moreover, attempts at experimental or incremental change are quite hopeless. Any change can take the system to any system state. Suppose we make a change in rule r i and the system radically changes. Suppose further that everyone approves of the new system. Another small additional change in r i can again move the system anywhere, so even the smallest additional change will undo our previous one. Essentially, we would only be able to move randomly and observe results. Under these conditions, interpreting Hayekian analysis as conservative has much to recommend it (Freeden 1996: 373ff.;cf. Hayek 1960: 397ff.). Given the utter unpredictability of change, we might as well try to stay where we are, where we might have some modicum of reasonable expectations.
However, even under extreme complexity, Hayek is not best understood as a conservative. Hayek avoids conservatism by placing great weight on principles that he deems to be the bedrock of the Open Society, such as personal liberty (1973: ch. 3); the right thing to do might be to simply demand the satisfaction of certain principles and live with the consequences. Thus, he chides the conservative for accepting whatever outcome has been produced by the latest intervention (1960: 397ff.) and so failing to stand up for the core principles (liberty, jurisdictions, and markets) on which the Open Society depends. "A commitment to principles presupposes an understanding of the general forces by which the efforts of society are co-ordinated, but it is such a theory of society and especially of the economic mechanism that conservatism conspicuously lacks" (1960: 401).
Things look different under moderate complexity, where the rule system is not so tightly coupled. Here, reform of the rules to improve the order of actions seems entirely possible. Small changes in the underlying rules will produce significant changes in the order of actions, but we have seen that these changes are correlated: the overall features of S*, the state after the change, will have significant similarity to the previous system, S. While we can by no means predict the precise outcome of a change in the underlying rules, we will have reasonable confidence that-to put the matter roughly-they will be in the same neighborhood of the current order. 10 So incremental social experimentation looks plausible. Given this, we may interrogate rules with a prospect of improvement. A rule might strike us unfair or needlessly restrictive of freedom. In a maximally complex system, we would be most reluctant to experiment by altering it-the change would lead us to an entirely unpredictable outcome. But in a more moderately complex system, while global control is still out of the question, it is not reckless to incrementally alter rules with the aim of improvement. The society that results will not be radically different from our present one.
Reform of a moderately complex system thus seems feasible. But while it is feasible to reform, decisions to reform presuppose that we have rationally examined our order of actions and have determined that it comes up short, and we have an idea what to do about this. Hayek (1988: 68ff.), though, is understandably skeptical of the very idea of rationally evaluating our order of actions and demanding a justification or coming to the conclusion that some rule r is unjustified. Given the essence of complexity, we do not understand the outcomes produced by r. In a complex system, r interacts with a large set of other rules to produce an order of actions, the features of which simply cannot be wholly known from the characteristics of the individual rules. This, as we have seen, is a fundamental feature of complex systems. Thus it would seem that Hayek is quite right to reject any demand for justification according to which "our morality is justified just to the extent, say, that it is directed towards the production of, or striving after, some specific goal such as happiness" (1988: 69). If we do not know the consequences of our rules, it is hard to see how we can evaluate their outcomes. Of course, insofar as the overall system supports the Open Society and there is no alternative structure for coordinating multitudes of heterogeneous agents for large-scale mutual benefit, we might think that is all the justification we need.
Hayek insists that individuals do not learn the moral rules of their society through reasoned inquiry but through cultural imitation (1988: 21ff.). Because we cannot really know the purposes or consequences of any given rule r, morality is learned by observing the behavior of others and imitating it. This converges with recent analysis of the evolution of culture, which put imitation and conformity bias at the very heart of cultural transmission (Richerson and Boyd 2005: 86ff.;Henrich and Henrich 2007: 22ff.). Because culture has evolved complex adaptive practices, humans typically do well by imitating the behavior of others around them. We often do not understand precisely the benefits of our cultural practices, but because culture is largely transmitted via imitation, people often do not have to know why something is done, only that it is the done thing around here. Whereas intelligent primates such as chimps tend to figure out problems for themselves, human infants have a much stronger tendency to simply copy what they observe being done, copying "stupid" acts that the chimp sees as pointless (Horner and Whitten 2005).
Hayek, once again running against the current, insists that this general feature of culture applies to morality. Because the rules of morality are complex cultural adaptations, we do not really understand their functions or effects on the order of actions, and so simply imitating the rule-following behavior of others is not only sensible but also necessary (1988: ch. 5).
�.� The Necessity of Reasoned Moral Inquiry
Yet cultural and moral innovation depends on innovators who employ their reasoning to question current rules and seek better alternatives. If cultural transmission requires conformity, improvement and adaptation require reasoned innovation (Boyd and Richerson 2005: ch. 2). New problems arise; experience points to possible flaws in current rules. As in culture, the spread of new moral ideas is often based on the innovator's or trendsetter's reasoning (Bicchieri 2016). Innovators provide reasons for endorsing the new rule and seek to persuade others to come on board. Nevertheless, given the complexity of the order of action, no innovator's reasoned inquiry will capture the full function or consequences of any rule.
Thus the paradox of moral inquiry: In some ways, it is bound to fail in its quest for understanding and evaluation, yet it is an ineliminable feature of morality. Because all reasoned investigation is incomplete, the process of moral reform should draw on the largest possible pool of information, as diverse individuals throughout society observe changes in moral rules and the new state of affairs that results. It must be stressed that not even the entire collectivity can fully appreciate all the effects of changes in the system of moral rules, but the wider the population participating in the process of change, the greater the chance that important changes in the order of actions will be observed, and this information will affect the process of change.
Hayek thus envisages a decentralized testing of current rules by diverse individuals: "it is, in fact, desirable that the rules should be observed only in most instances and that the individual should be able to transgress them when it seems to him worthwhile to incur the odium this will cause.… It is this flexibility of voluntary rules which in the field of morals makes gradual evolution and spontaneous growth possible, which allows further modifications and improvements" (1960: 63).
We should distinguish rule abolition from rule replacement. Individual decisions to flout a moral rule can be very effective in undermining it. In many cases, as increasing numbers of individuals violate a current rule and others observe their behavior and approve of the results, the general expectation that the rule will be followed is undermined, and so the rule is apt to fade away. Such trendsetters can have great impact in undermining rules they see as morally objectionable, as they take the first steps, followed by others (Bicchieri 2016: ch. 5). Instituting new rules is more difficult; an innovator can do significant damage to an existing moral rule by flouting it and encouraging her network to follow her-it is more difficult to get groups to adopt and follow new rules. But here too, change can be from the bottom up. As small networks of people come to adopt a new rule, through persuasion or example, others may begin to adopt the new rule, first in neighboring networks; then, the new behavior can spread more widely. Changes in many rules about gender equality appear to have demonstrated this dynamic over the last 40 years: what were the norms of distinct subpopulations spread to the entire society, and they came to be endorsed by increasingly large social networks. And people often adopt new norms on the grounds of their reasons for them (Bicchieri and Mercier 2014). Yet Hayek is surely correct that too a great a faith in our ability to judge-insisting that our rules must be verified from the bar of reason in the sense that they must be fully understood and comprehensively evaluated-means that we cannot benefit from the evolution of our self-organizing order of actions. Morality requires conformity without full understanding while also requiring reason-giving and reasonedinnovation/reform. A paradox indeed.
�.� Macro Justification of the Open Society?
Hayek's account of social evolution, I have argued, integrates micro-selection of social rules by the participants ( §3.2); this opens up a path for content-based moral evaluation of social rules by diverse individuals to affect the evolution of the order of actions. This integration of moral evaluation into social evolution is a critical, and often overlooked, feature of his analysis. It is not simply that we can make moral evaluations (of course we do that); Hayekian analysis shows how these help shape a complex self-organizing adaptive system. For the Hayekian, that is the critical idea. Still, an orthodox political philosopher may press a demand for global justification. Thus, for example, G. A. Cohen (2009) presents a tale of a communal camping trip as a model of social relations and asks "Why not Socialism?" rather than the Open Society? Can a Hayekian-inspired analysis say anything in response?
The response most true to Hayek is, perhaps, the least satisfying to the orthodox political philosopher: There is no longer a viable alternative. The option of planning modern large-scale societies is an illusion. When sketching out their visions, political philosophers do not invent societies, they invent blueprints-or rather vague sketches of possible blueprints. Any attempt at implementation would, at best, yield totally surprising results-and probably disaster. Almost all utopian societies-be they socialist, environmentalist, or libertarian-imagined by philosophers are simply impossible under conditions of diversity and complexity, for they assume the very simplicity and predictability that complex orders of actions do not possess. To secure them would require a simplifying of human organization, a decreasing of diversity, and a controlling of innovation that would require…well, a cultural revolution and all that it involves.
As I said, this will be unsatisfying to most political philosophers, as it may simply be a cause for lamentation: justice is beyond the horizon of modern humans. We are too corrupt. And if the philosopher does view the Open Society as corrupt, constant disruption may even seem attractive-a sort of endless guerilla war with the diversity and complexity of the Open Society. A second response moves toward what, hopefully, the moral philosopher will see as normatively relevant: that the Open Society has provided the basis for tremendously more people to achieve freer, more interesting, less arduous, longer, healthier, and more enriched lives, recognizing a larger diversity of aims and ends-of both men and women-than was imaginable even 100 years ago. As Deirdre Nansen McCloskey (2016) demonstrates in her wonderful encyclopedic analysis of human betterment over the last 200 years, at its core has been the openness and creativity characteristic of the Open Society. Without openness and dense interactions among the mass of people and heterogeneous ideas, this astounding human betterment would not have occurred (McCloskey 2016: 40); but these are the very sources of Hayekian complexity.
Yet, the philosopher demanding the global justification may continue to press, what does this have to do with the justice of such a society? The Open Society, he may insist, is still unfair: it does not give us "true" equality or "fair" equality of opportunity; it does not undo the "accidents of birth" or track merit; it does not maximize utility, community, or liberty. Perhaps justice requires humans have less wealth, opportunities, and comforts but live in much fairer and very different ways. After all, says John Rawls, beyond some point, wealth "is more likely to be a positive hindrance, a meaningless distraction at best if not a temptation to indulgence and emptiness" (1999: 258). The Hayekian has one last response, drawing on a Millian idea. As I have recently tried to demonstrate (Gaus 2016), a highly diverse society, in which people have and develop deeply different views about ideal justice, provides the framework in which we stand the best chance of learning what ideal justice truly is. Let us admit that even for the political philosopher, knowing the ideally just social state is not easy, and even when we think we have a good idea of it, we always have something to learn. Scott has stressed the ways in which a wide diversity of perspectives is critical in helping a group solve its most Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 17:48 27 Nov 2021;For: 9781315709727, chapter3, 10.4324/9781317486794.ch3 pressing problems-over a large range of circumstances diverse groups and societies solve problems better than homogenous ones. And, the philosopher should acknowledge, one of our critical problems is figuring out what justice is. John Stuart Mill (1965Mill ( [1859) was right; if we wish to progress in our understanding of justice, we need the diversity and complexity of the Open Society.
� an eVolVed complex oRdeR
Hayekian "classical liberalism" remains obscure to most political philosophers, as it denies most of their basic assumptions and rejects their methods. First and foremost, it is not a "moral theory, " which formulates normative standards that are then used to evaluate and propose reforms of social orders. The Hayekian approach does not justify the Open Society in terms of efficiency, productivity, utility, utility-based rules, "evolutionary utilitarianism, " social welfare, desert, merit, natural rights, autonomy, economic liberty, respect for persons, or progress. This is not to say that it is skeptical whether the Open Society has been a tremendous boon to humanity; having experienced it, the resulting human betterment is manifest to all who truly look. But it was not designed to produce that betterment, nor can it be controlled to secure it in ways that may seem most desirable to us. We know the general features of the Open Society, such as its endless inquiry and innovation, but it has no "maximand"-a value to be maximized, by which our version is to be rated. Hayek presents us with a comprehensive theory of the Open Society-how its complex order comes about, the type of morality that it engenders, the types of social relations it makes possible, and why our failure to understand it leads both friends and foes to treat it as a simple order that can be evaluated by ethics and controlled by politics. Ethics is not an Archimedean point that allows a person to stand outside a moral system and evaluate it, dictating the correct way to live together (cf. Gauthier 1986: 233); our ethical views are a product of the very social evolutionary process we are seeking to understand and improve. noTes 1. Both Freeman and Brennan and Tomasi contrast classical liberalism with the "high liberalism" of Rawls, but whereas Freeman (2001; insists on sharply distinguishing classical liberalism and libertarianism, Brennan and Tomasi propose a more complex classification of classical liberalism that includes libertarianism. 2. Because Hayek appeals to social evolution (see section 3 of this chapter), some seek to save the "utilitarian" designation by deeming him an "evolutionary utilitarian"-the outcome of social evolution somehow indicates what is, from the utilitarian point of view, best.
Hayek was too sophisticated an evolutionary theorist to believe that social adaptation is a proxy for maximizing utility, much less that we could have any test of this claim. See further Kukathas 1989: 198ff. 3. Hayek (1973 is also critically concerned with common law, which shares much with informal social morality. 4. While direct reciprocity (for example, "tit-for-tat") can be effective in accounting for cooperation in very small groups (dyads, triads) its capacity to sustain cooperation dramatically decreases as group size increases (Henrich and Henrich 2007: 51). Bodo's group of 80 would be far too large for direct reciprocity to sustain cooperation (see Bowles and Gintis 2007: 64-8). 5. This is sometimes called "tight coupling. " See Tanner 1996: 16.