Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
r
Fo
!
"
&
# $
'$
#
#
pe
!
%
er
& (# )
# *
+ #
,
)
# *+ / #!) 0
*
#(
/
)
# *+ 3
#
/ (
)4
*
#
"
#
#
re
4
'! "
1
"
" ) #
(
-
#
#
'
#
)
"'
(8 /
' 1 (' " !
" "
# 1
"
#
"
!
#
#
)
'7
!
! !
ew
8
5
# 7
(
#
# 1 (
#
"
"
'
) #
)#
vi
$
!
+ -
) 5
# 6
'
# )
"
'.
),
+ ) #
'$ 1
") 2
7
!
( ) -
( #
'
(
" "
! #
(
7
8 .#
8
'
-
ly
on
Page 1 of 10
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
:
Michael Loughlin PhD, Professor of Applied Philosophy, Department of Interdisciplinary
Studies, MMU Cheshire, Crewe, UK
Jonathan Fuller, MD/PhD student, Faculty of Medicine, University of Toronto, Ontario, Canada
Robyn Bluhm PhD, Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Michigan State University,
East Lancing, Michigan, USA
r
Fo
Stephen Buetow PhD, Associate Professor, Department of General Practice, University of
Auckland, Auckland, New Zealand
Kirstin Borgerson MA PhD, Associate Professor, Department of Philosophy, Dalhousie
University, Halifax, Nova Scotia, Canada
: Professor Michael Loughlin, MMU Cheshire, Crewe CW1 5DU,
[email protected]
er
pe
! "
: Medicine, healthcare, philosophy, epistemology, ethics, metaphysics, ontology,
disease, health, classification, clinical reasoning, value, evidence6based medicine, patient6
centred, person6centred
ew
vi
re
Despite its potential hazards, the activity of questioning theoretical frameworks and proposing
solutions is necessary if progress is even to be possible. Intellectual history has by no means
ended, so we cannot expect to have all the answers, and from time to time the activity of
critical questioning will be frustrating. But intellectual progress requires us to continue the
process of asking fundamental questions. The alternative to thinking in this way is indeed
unthinkable.
ly
on
It is easy for those of us who work in education to see the value of thinking, including explicit
theorising about questions of fundamental importance. In previous thematic editions of this
journal, we have argued that the practice of critical thinking is of fundamental importance if
virtue, progress and more enlightened practices are to be possible. [163] Without populations
– in the workplace and in society generally – able to expose underlying assumptions that
frequently frame popular debate, we are at the mercy of the spin6doctors and opinion6
managers who have made the control of human behaviour their explicit goal. [467] In
populations governed by the principle of 'moderate anti6intellectualism' [1] people are
encouraged to think about 'how6to' questions – how to accomplish certain tasks, to apply
established rules, guidelines and theoretical frameworks in particular situations and to
achieve pre6determined goals. But underlying, 'why' questions – about the justification for the
goals, the intellectual basis for the rules and guidelines as opposed to possible alternatives –
are dismissed as impractical. In a world in which we are constantly bombarded with bad
arguments, inadequate rationalisations and rhetorical ploys to make us conform to
unquestioned norms, [7] it makes very little sense to talk of such a population as containing
autonomous people – meaning persons who think for themselves and are in full, rational
control of their own actions.[6,7]
However, there are also serious concerns about the potential damage theorising can do. If
employed in the wrong ways, theorising can either serve to undermine the common6sense
knowledge of practitioners and patients, deny truths that would otherwise be intuitively
obvious or cause us to be sceptical in situations where in fact trust would be the more
beneficial, more human reaction.[6,8610] The view that theory should,
be
'grounded in' experience would command very broad support, as would the claim that a key
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
Page 2 of 10
goal of theory is to produce conclusions that facilitate more effective practice. But these broad
claims would be supported by defenders of radically different views about the proper basis of
practice,[3] from authors with a 'positivist' approach to evidence and clinical reasoning [11614]
to defenders of phenomenological approaches to reasoning in practice. [15,16] Even the view
that medicine should be more 'person6centred' can be conceptualised and justified in a variety
of – potentially incompatible – ways [17], as some of the contributions to this edition strikingly
demonstrate.
r
Fo
In this thematic edition of the
, we present a range of
papers that raise questions or problems about not only the intellectual basis for practice, but
also about the dangers inherent in theorising about practice – the sense that the wrong sort of
theorising can actually be harmful. Such questions are sometimes characterised as matters of
'philosophical methodology' in that they express concerns about how we go about addressing
important, underlying questions if we are to say something actually helpful to practitioners and
patients. Contributors present different views about the
of thinking we need when
discussing questions of ethics, knowledge and reasoning in clinical practice – reflecting
radically different views of what it means to have a basis for practice, and why one should
need such a thing in the first place.
# $
"
%
$ $
%
$
&
&
er
pe
The edition begins with a debate about the assumptions not only of medical ethics but of the
very activity of theorising about morality, at least as such theorising has typically been
conducted for much of our intellectual history. [18620] Joel Backström and Hannes Nykänen
[18] note that, from the development of the Hippocratic Oath to current debates about
bioethics and values6based practice, [21,22] a “dominant conception that morality is a matter
of values and valuation” is typically treated as self6evident. The authors claim that this
conception encourages us to ignore a fundamental truth about the nature of moral
experience. It effectively represses conscience, the fundamental importance of what they
characterise as the “I6you” relationship. They argue that all moral theories – including Kantian
and utilitarian theories and even approaches based on the concept of virtue – serve to codify
and reinforce dominant ideas in society, encouraging us to ignore our moral experience and
internalise collective values or dispositions. Moral relativism and moral particularism are seen
as responses to this dominant conception that fail to escape its underlying assumptions.
vi
re
ew
In his response, [19] Stephen Buetow tries to work out the implications of this critique of moral
theorising for practical debates about healthcare, developing implications of Backström and
Nykänen's argument and interrogating the meaning of some of their key claims. He applauds
their defence of conscience and notes their warnings about “non6reflectively identifying with
the collective values of society” at a time when concern is growing that, “rather than relate to
themselves and patients as persons, clinicians embrace anonymized, normative demands of
group values.” He welcomes the analysis because it helps to explain what he regards as the
“rising depersonalization in health care, lack of resistance to this development and a need to
revitalize person6centred health care.” However, he rejects what he sees as a false
dichotomy in their work between 'conscience' on the one hand and both 'value' and 'virtue' on
the other. For Buetow, commitment to conscience is still compatible with “constructing person6
centred care as a virtue ethic nourishing authenticity and reciprocated caring”. We should not
so much be jettisoning such concepts as 'virtue' and 'value' (he is not sure how we could) as
noting the possible dangers in their (mis)use.
ly
on
In their counter6response,[20] the authors reiterate their fundamental points that “conscience
is a concern for people, in the sense of an ‘I’ to a ‘you’, not for values, beliefs, norms,
principles, etc” and that dominant, “value‐based ethics is a repression (ie self‐deceptive
denial and evasion) of conscience”. Referring to examples and the history of moral
philosophy, they note that: “The problems in different versions of value‐ethics are legion,”
and “proponents of various positions – Kantians, consequentialists, virtue‐ethicists, etc. –
have managed to shoot their opponents full of holes, so that no man remains standing.” They
regard their critique as a major challenge to theoretical arguments that have shaped our
conception not only of medical ethics but of moral thinking more generally for centuries, so
they expect Buetow – and perhaps many others – to struggle in getting to grips with its
implications.
Page 3 of 10
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
Certainly such a broad critique of moral theories will lead some to wonder what role, if any,
moral theory can have in informing practice. Backström and Nykänen seem to ascribe all
ideas about value, virtue and principle to the role of 'repression', while Buetow wants to stress
that these ideas can form part of more defensible conceptions of ethics – though he agrees
with them that all such ideas, like their own favoured idea of 'conscience', can in fact be
abused to form rationalisations for clearly immoral acts. While value6theory
function
simply to reinforce non6rational norms/consensus, for him this is not an essential
characteristic of such theories. The history of philosophical debate in this area has not ended
with all the major approaches effectively refuting each other. Rather, it is on6going, and the
major traditions, precisely through their radical differences, have all brought out important
aspects of moral thinking – and part of the exercise of good conscience is in weighing the
significance of these aspects in making decisions in particular cases.
r
Fo
The section continues with a paper whose subject matter and methodology are strikingly
different from the approaches of those papers already mentioned, and yet whose conclusions
resonate with that debate. Focussing specifically on medical decision6making, Michael
Morreau and Aidan Lyon use a multi6agent computer simulation of groups of physicians to test
the assumption that common standards lead to better decision6making. [23] The standards, in
this case, are epistemic and concern deliberation in groups and the use of scores and grades
in evaluation. The authors note that: “One might expect individual differences in members’
grading standards to reduce the capacity of the group to discover the facts on which well6
informed decisions depend.” However, their observations of the simulated groups suggest
that: “on the contrary... this kind of diversity can in fact be conducive to epistemic
performance. Sometimes, it is adopting common standards that may be expected to result in
poor decisions.” This conclusion resonates with recent arguments in support of social and
cognitive diversity, [24] and explanatory pluralism. [25]
er
pe
ew
'
vi
re
Utilsing Longino's arguments about the centrality of diversity and public critique within a
community of scientists, [26] Emily Bingeman applies Longino’s criteria for assessing the
objectivity of a knowledge6productive community to assess Evidence6based Medicine (EBM)
against a casuistic framework for medical knowledge. [27] She argues that “EBM’s strict
adherence to a hierarchical organization of knowledge can reasonably be expected to block it
from fulfilling a high level of objectivity.” In contrast, she claims that a casuistic framework
“could be expected to better facilitate a more optimal epistemic community,” because it
emphasizes critical evaluation in conjunction with the flexibility of a case6based approach.
ly
on
Does involvement in the practice of medicine commit us to any particular set of philosophical
assumptions about the world and our place within it? If so, are those assumptions open to
criticism and what implications for practice might such criticisms have? Anna Louise
Kirkengen and colleagues [28] argue that contemporary medicine's perception of reality is
theoretically loaded in ways that may once have served the interests of progress in specific
areas, but which now stand in its way. Current medical knowledge, they maintain, ignores
central tenets of human existence, notably the physiological impact of subjective experience,
relationships, history, and sociocultural contexts. While the “materialistic shift of enlightenment
philosophy” was at one point crucial to progress in medicine and “yielded astonishing results”,
contemporary medicine now faces problems that cannot be solved (or indeed properly
, let alone understood) by “more of the same”. They conclude that the
biomedical framework now needs radical revision: “we must acknowledge that health,
sickness and bodily functioning are interwoven with human meaning6production,
fundamentally personal and biographical.”
In contrast, Seth Joshua Thomas [29] sets out to defend evidence6based healthcare against
the claim that it it is committed to a particular, 'reductionist' world view and to question the
philosophical commitments of some of its critics. Focussing on the claim that an “emphasis on
the hierarchy of evidence, grounded in the use of randomized controlled trials” embodies a
philosophical commitment to a “modernist” conception of reality, Thomas disputes the
apparent implication that the approaches to healthcare he identifies as “evidence6based”
inevitably “fail to recognize the patient as the complex self she is, treating her instead as
merely a quantifiable, medical6scientific object.” For Thomas, a purely scientific method is “in
principle neutral with regard to questions of selfhood”, so there can simply be no question of a
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
Page 4 of 10
philosophical tension between evidence6based and person6centred approaches, and no need
for the sort of 'philosophical overhaul' called for by other contributors to this edition.
r
Fo
The view that scientific reasoning can indeed embody significant philosophical commitment is
taken seriously by Daniele Chiffi and Renzo Zanotti. [30] Presenting examples from clinical
reasoning, these authors explore the epistemological and metaphysical commitments in
perspectives on clinical possibility. They note that modal concepts are widely used in clinical
reasoning, but philosophical debate on such notions is still at an initial stage. Opening up
what they regard as an important new line of research in the philosophy of healthcare, they
argue that almost all clinical possibilities are potentialities: “that is, possibilities that may be
actualised by effective, appropriate and feasible interventions” and they introduce “some
basic views on the nature of possibility, showing their validity and limitations when applied to
the concept of clinical possibility.” Their discussion is followed by a contribution from Matthew
Mercuri and Brian Baigrie, [31] which examines the use of epidemiological risk information as
evidence of causation in medical court cases. They illustrate various standards of evidence –
including statistical significance, relative risks (RRs) that are greater than 2, and biological
plausibility – through the case of Goodman v. Viljoen, a medical malpractice suit. They find
that multiple kinds of evidence were brought to bear in establishing individual causation, and
find analogies as well as disanalogies between the legal context and the clinical context when
using risk information to make causal attributions or predictions.
er
pe
In addition to philosophical commitments concerning the nature of possibility and causation,
medical reasoning also raises questions of ontological commitment with regard to the nature
of disease. [32] Such questions are particularly pressing in the area of psychiatry. As Sam
Fellows notes: “Validity of psychiatric syndromes is typically associated with questions over
their reality.” [33] Fellows argues that Kendell and Jablensky’s account of validity – which links
the validity of a syndrome to its causation by a specific biological mechanism not present in
other syndromes – is overly restrictive. He argues that: “Scientific phenomena are the product
of a multiplicity of unstable overlapping causes but this does not mean our descriptions of
scientific phenomena are automatically arbitrary.” Rather, he claims, science deals with
multiple unstable causes by producing idealised models that can be “approximately true”.
re
ew
vi
Returning to the crucial questions about contemporary medical ontology raised by Kirkengen
et al [28], and building on her important discussion of 'metaphysical care' and the ontology of
disease in the previous philosophy thematic edition of this journal, [32] Alexandra Parvan
attempts to lay philosophical foundations for person6centred healthcare. [34] While Parvan
would clearly agree with Kirkengen and colleagues that contemporary biomedicine needs to
rethink its theoretical basis, her own analysis of current medical thinking is somewhat different
from theirs, as is her own recipe for a genuinely humanistic, person6centred approach to care.
Going back to ancient philosophical views of disease as ‘bounded entity’ or as ‘relation',
Parvan proposes a way to think ontologically about disease “that places it in necessary
connection with the patient as person”, drawing on Augustine’s views on disease, bodily
integrity, and the human person as mind6body unit.
on
ly
Ramesh Prasad [35] asks what determines the 'ownership' of human body parts, looking in
particular at cases of transplantation where the biological integrity of the whole person is
disrupted. He makes the distinction between “internal” and “external property” and claims that
“Poor outcomes in some types of kidney donors may be due not only to a failure in their
proper selection by standard medical testing or post6donation care, but may also be a
manifestation of differing effects on sense of self resulting from transfer of their internal
property.” In contrast to dopamine levels that altruistic behaviour increases, commercial
donation may produce cortisol or adrenergic6based responses because the brain interprets
the donation as traumatic in the absence of a concurrent feeling of reward. Thus, there may
be a cognitive basis to society’s antipathy to commercial kidney transplantation. If screening
rules that treat a kidney as external property are inadvertently harming some living donors, a
property transfer approach, informed by a careful cognitive assessment, could help to
regulate harm associated with neurocognitive changes in the donors.
The section concludes with David Misselbrook's insightful and engaging discussion of the
ontology of health and the goals of medicine. [36] Utilising ideas taken from the very different
philosophies of Aristotle and Hume, Misselbrook presents an analysis of contemporary
debates about naturalist, biostatistical and normative accounts of health and disease and
defends an Aristotelian conception of 'human flourishing' as a key goal for medical practice.
Page 5 of 10
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
Like all good examples of applied philosophy, his paper makes underlying philosophical
questions highly accessible and uses the problems of practice to raise questions that
challenge distinctions operating in mainstream academic philosophical debate.
'
$
$
r
Fo
Theoretical questions about the nature of knowledge seem inescapable for defenders of any
approach to clinical reasoning and practice, be they exponents of EBM, or indeed of patient6
or person6centred care. In the context of continued debates about the future of EBM, [37,38]
Rudolfo Gaeta and Nelida Gentile [39] use epistemology and Kuhn's philosophy of science to
present a conception of EBM as a 'meta6methodology”. Insofar as the development of EBM
as a movement represented a genuinely new alternative in the field of medicine, showing a
way in which the discipline would henceforth endure, the authors show that it could not have
been what Kuhn meant by a 'paradigm', but this potentially reflects the problems with Kuhn's
philosophy as much as it reflects any identity6crisis in EBM.
er
pe
Motivated in the first instance by the problem that gave rise to Parvan's analysis, [32,34] that
of patient non6adherence to physicians' recommendations, Mary6Clair Yelovich [40] develops
a thesis on the nature and limits of expertise that provides “a new epistemological framework
that recognizes legitimate knowledge offered by the patient as well as the physician.” By
treating the clinical encounter not only as “an encounter between persons” [41] but as a
meeting of experts, Yelovich develops a “patient expertise framework within the paradigm of
patient6centred medicine”. Assuming the goal of medical treatment to be alleviation of
suffering, patient expertise becomes centralized as a means of determining the nature of
patient suffering. Drawing on ideas clearly at work in the paper by Kirkengen et al, [28]
Yelovich identifies two aspects of the patient’s tacit knowledge: the body aspect and the
meaning aspect, both of which, she notes, are context6dependent and directly accessible only
to the patient. She notes that both are “recognised as essential to the success of the
interaction”, and clearly distinguished from the equally essential expertise of the clinician. She
argues in detail the practical advantages of this approach for the problem she set out to
address.
re
ew
vi
In stark contrast, the contribution by Anthony Fry and Tania Gergel [42] looks at the need for
paternalism in clinical practice, when the conditions for the sort of patient6centred approach
Yelovich outlines do not obtain. In a paper presented to the workshop on Paternalism and
Trust at Kings College London, reported in the previous philosophy thematic edition of JECP,
[43] the authors discuss a case where paternalism seems appropriate. Factitious Disorder
(FD) is usually classified as a mental disorder involving deliberate and hidden feigning or
inducement of illness, in order to achieve patient status. (In such a case, it is hard to know
what to make of the concept of patient expertise.) Looking at case histories, the authors argue
that there are no compelling reasons for rejecting the use of paternalistic interventions for FD,
but that further investigation of FD and frameworks for psychiatric paternalism, in relation to
FD and other mental disorders, are urgently needed.
on
ly
Noting that diagnosis is “arguably the cornerstone of medicine”, Ashley Kennedy attempts to
to “extend the work that Worrall and Cartwright have done on the evaluation of medical
treatments to the topic of medical diagnosis.” [44] Much has been written on the role of
randomized controlled trials and mechanistic reasoning in the evaluation of therapeutic
treatments, but the question of how diagnostic tests and procedures should be evaluated is
surprisingly under6theorised. Kennedy begins by addressing a series of questions about
accuracy, effectiveness and value, noting that diagnostic value extends beyond patient
outcomes.
Wendy Rogers and Yishai Mintztker [45] look at the problem of overdiagnosis, when
diagnosis does not benefit the patient because the condition diagnosed is not a harmful
disease in those patients. Looking at a range of examples, from cancer screening to attention
deficit hyperactivity disorder, they classify two different types of overdiagnosis.
Misclassification overdiagnosis arises because the diagnostic threshold for the disease (they
give the illustration of chronic kidney disease) has been set at a level where many people
without harmful disease are nonetheless diagnosed. Maldetection overdiagnosis arises
because, at the time the diagnosis is made and despite the presence of a ‘gold standard’
diagnostic test, it is not possible to discriminate between harmful and non6harmful cases of
the index disease – they give the example of thyroid cancer. Like the paper by Fry and
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
Page 6 of 10
Gergel, this one proposes that the first stage for addressing the problem is to develop an
adequate conceptual analysis.
Donald Stanley and Daniel Campos [46] investigate logical strategies for narrowing the list of
diagnostic hypotheses during the diagnostic process, including Bayesian confirmation theory,
frequentist statistics and inference to the best explanation. They discuss these strategies in
the context of six realistic clinical cases, showing how informal clinical reasoning can be
understood as instances of these confirmation theories that are familiar to philosophers of
science. Stanley and Campos ultimately argue for using the full range of inferential strategies
available rather than limiting diagnostic reasoning to just one approach.
r
Fo
Matthew Maddocks and colleagues [47] discuss problems in ‘placebo6controlled’
physiotherapy trials and how the use of inadequate placebos can lead to systematic bias,
sometimes underestimating and sometimes overestimating the treatment effect. They adopt
Grűnbaum’s classic definition of a placebo, which has: all of the incidental features of the
treatment, none of the characteristic features, and nothing more. They use three published
physiotherapy trials that may have suffered from bias due to an inadequate placebo control to
illustrate how failure to satisfy Grűnbaum’s criteria might account for biased estimation of the
treatment effect, and argue that because of the difficulty of constructing placebos in
physiotherapy trials it is often necessary to use other trial designs.
pe
$
er
As noted in our opening comments, for many authors the only adequate 'base' for theorising
about practice is in lived experience: we do not understand health and illness, or the purpose
and nature of healthcare, unless we ground that understanding in the everyday experience of
those who have to live with the problems we aim to address. [15,16] This section includes
papers that attempt to illustrate the uses of phenomenology in the discussion of healthcare.
ew
vi
re
Juan Borda [48] discusses the relationship between Bipolar Disorder (BD) and Borderline
Personality Disorder (BPD). Despite intense debate for two decades, current diagnostic
classifications approach this complex phenomenon using syndromatic definitions based on
presence or absence of a restricted set of signs or symptoms which have demonstrated low
specificity. Borda argues that the phenomenological method in psychiatry can complement
other approaches, helping identify differences between two separated clinical syndromes.
Borda sets out to explore one particular clinical difference between these two conditions: the
experience of self6continuity and time perception. While BPD patients tend to experience only
the present, BD patients are constantly worried about the contradictions in their past
experiences, and the latent risk of losing control of themselves in future episodes of their
disease. This contrast needs to be corroborated in future research comparing directly the two
groups in terms of the continuity of the self and their temporal structures.
ly
on
Ines Hipolito [49] discusses the phenomenology of intersubjective impairment, in a paper that
attempts to show that “the second6person perspective” can be used to point out particular
features of social cognition and its related psychopathology. Characterising the second6
person perspective as “the congruence point between an objective process and the subjective
experience,” Hipolito tries to explain schizophrenia as a self6related deficit, first in the light of
the first6 and the third6person perspective; and afterward, in the light of the currently less
understood second6person perspective.
Drawing on psychiatric literature and philosophical work on self6knowledge, Jordi Fernandez
and Suzanne Blis [50] discuss how schizophrenia affects a subject’s sense of self. They
consider experience of alienation of mental states and actions and propose that the
experience of thoughts, feelings, impulses and actions as not being one’s own is the
experience of not being able to find reasons in support of occupying those states. To make
sense of these phenomena they propose two components to our normal sense of self,
understanding schizophrenia with reference to the dissociation of these components.
(
This year's debates section contains two responses to previously published articles in this
journal. Responding to Alexandra Parvan's paper in the previous philosophy thematic [32] on
patients' “substantialisation of disease” and metaphysical care, Thor Erik Eriksen and Anna
Luise Kirkengen [51] begin by providing their own reflection on the epistemological and
Page 7 of 10
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
r
Fo
ontological questions raised by the phenomenon of medically unexplained symptoms or
syndromes(MUS). They argue that “such health challenges can serve as the basis for an
exploration of how the suffering person as well as the medical caretaker come to grips with
disease, incapacitation or suffering.” While they broadly welcome and support Parvan's efforts
“to provide a renewed language as regards human suffering”, they fear she has given too
much ground to biomedical ontology and epistemology: “when, for example, she perpetuates
the prevailing biomedical concepts of the doctors’ role as knowers and the patients’ role as
adaptors.” In support of this point they cite her language of “non6adherence” 6 matched with
the idea of clinicians being the suppliers of “metaphysical care”. Their own account of the
phenomenon Parvan terms “substantialisation” (for which they prefer the term “thingification”)
describes “a process wherein patients reify their suffering in order to meet their doctors on
equal terms, which carries a potential for alienation.” Whether we are patients or practitioners,
we need a new philosophical framework if we are to avoid the problems Parvan's paper
highlighted.
pe
Reading both this commentary and Parvan's contribution to this thematic, [34] we feel these
authors' differences are less significant than their similarities, and we look forward to further
productive exchanges on these vital underlying questions: about how we conceptualise
health, illness, suffering and ultimately ourselves. As noted in our opening comments, the
wrong theoretical assumptions can indeed stand in the way of progress, and these authors
are to be praised for questioning underlying conceptions that may strike many as “sheer
common sense”, given our current, dominant conceptions of the world and our place within it.
er
The edition concludes with a commentary by Michael Loughlin, Peter Wyer & Sandy
Tanenbaum, [52] in reply to an article by Milos Jenicek [53] in last year's EBM6thematic
edition of this journal. Responding to the 'crisis' for EBM identified by prominent contributors
to the debate, [37,38] Jenicek proposed a “new medical cognitive science” that would
“supplement” EBM with certain “gnostic or epistemological processes” to address what he
sees as a deficit in EBM's approach to clinical reasoning.[53] While Loughlin and colleagues
find Jenicek's paper fundamentally confused, they nonetheless regard it as an extremely
helpful contribution. They explain this apparently paradoxical assessment by noting there are
fundamental epistemological questions regarding EBM that remain unaddressed. While some
commentators seem happy to brush over vital questions about EBM's intellectual heritage,
taking little note of the distinction between empiricist and rationalist approaches to medical
epistemology, [29] Loughlin et al regard an accurate account of this heritage as vital to
understanding the current EBM debate and to the possibility of making serious intellectual
progress in this area. They argue that Jenicek effectively attempts to 'supplement' an
empiricist framework with a rationalist conception of reasoning, and this amounts to a
philosophically untenable project. However, the attempt to reconcile these opposed epistemic
traditions, to find something worthwhile in each of them, (much like the effort to reconcile
opposing ethical traditions discussed in our opening sections) may well turn out to be the way
forward for medical epistemology:
ew
vi
re
on
ly
“the failure of [Jenicek's] identified ‘approaches’ to ‘interconnect’ requires us to give more
explicit attention to the underlying epistemological assumptions that frame the EBM debate.
While we think he fails to solve the problem he identifies, that failure can, in itself, teach us
something about its fundamental nature. There are times when proposing a confused solution
to a problem is a better way to move a debate forward than simply insisting that there is
nothing to feel confused about.”
This point seems pertinent with regard to our opening comments about the activity of
theorising. Despite its potential hazards, the activity of questioning theoretical frameworks and
and proposing solutions is necessary if progress is even to be possible. Intellectual history
has by no means ended [54,55] so we cannot expect to have all the answers, and from time
to time the activity of critical questioning will be frustrating. But intellectual progress requires
us to continue the process of asking fundamental questions. The alternative to thinking in this
way is indeed unthinkable.
) %
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
Page 8 of 10
[1] Loughlin, M, Upshur, R, Goldenberg, M, Bluhm, R, & Borgerson, K (2010) Editorial
introduction and commentary: ‘Philosophy, Ethics, Medicine and Health Care: the urgent need
for critical practice’,
16 (2) 249659
[2] Loughlin, M, Bluhm, R, Buetow, S, Goldenberg, MJ, Upshur, R, Borgerson, K & Entwistle,
V (2011) Virtue, Progress and Practice,
, 17:5, 8396
846
[3] Loughlin, M, Bluhm, R, Buetow, S, Goldenberg, M, Upshur, R, Borgerson, K, Entwistle, V
& Kingma, E (2012) Reason and Value: making reasoning fit for practice,
, 18:5, 929639
[4] Orwell, G 'Politics and the English Language' in Carey,J (ed.) (2002)
Everyman's Librarly, London, 954667
Little, Brown. London
[6] Loughlin, M (2002)
!
r
Fo
[5] Poole, S (2006)
. Radcliffe Medical Press, Oxon
!
[7] Loughlin M. (2010) Argument, platitude, caricature & ridicule in the EBM debate [Talk
delivered 13April 2010 at Manchester Metropolitan University, UK] Available at
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=KhI7P0gCneY [Accessed 1 April 2016]
#
, Cambridge University Press,
$
pe
[8] O’Neill, O (2002) "
Cambridge
er
[9] Pellegrino, E. D., R. M. Veatch and J. P. Langan (eds.) (1991
#
"
, Washington, DC: Georgetown University
Press
[10] Moore, GE (2014) 'A Defence of Common Sense' in
Abingdon
%
. Oxon: Routledge.
re
[11] Carnap, R. (2011) #
, Routledge,
[12] Schlick, M. (1979) Moritz Schlick: Philosophical Papers, Volume II (1925–1936).
Amsterdam, Netherlands: Springer
vi
[13] White, K. & Willis, E. (2002) Positivism resurgent: the epistemological foundations of
evidence6based medicine. Health Sociology Review,11, 5–15.
ew
[14] Djulbegovic, B., Guyatt, G. H. & Ashcroft, R. E. (2009) Epistemologic inquiries in
evidence6based medicine. Cancer Control, 16, 158–168
[15] Carel, H. (2008) &
, Acummen, Durham
, Cambridge Scholars Publishing, Newcastle
on
[16] Mitchell, D (2012)
upon Tyne
[17] Loughlin, M. (2014) What person6centered medicine is and isn’t: Temptations for the
‘soul’ of PCM.
'
, 2(1), 16621
ly
[18] Backström, J. and Nykänen, H. (2016), Collectivity, evil and the dynamics of moral value.
22:4
[19] Buetow, S. (2016), Morality about values and character. A commentary on Backström
and Nykänen (2016). Collectivity, evil and the dynamics of moral value.
22:4
[20] Backström, J., & Nykänen, H (2016) Ethics: the perfect mix? Response to Buetow.
22:4
[21] Fulford, K. W. M. (2011) The value of evidence and evidence of values: bringing together
values6based and evidence6based practice in policy and service development in mental
health.
, 17 (5), 976–987.
[22] Loughlin, M (ed.) (2014) ( )
*
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
+$
"
,
[23] Morreau, M & Lyon, A (2016) How common standards can diminish collective
intelligence: a computational study
22:4
"
,
Page 9 of 10
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
[24] Page, S (2008) #
(
. Princeton University Press
[25] Longino, H (2013) Studying human behaviour: How scientists investigate aggression and
sexuality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
[26] Longino, H. (1998) Values and Objectivity. In M. Curd, J.A. Cover & C. Pincock (Eds.)
Philosophy of Science: The Central Issues (2nd ed.)(p.p. 1446164). New York, NY:W.W.
Norton & Company
[27] Bingeman, E.(2016) Evaluating normative epistemic frameworks in medicine: EBM and
casuistic medicine.
22:4
r
Fo
[28] Kirkengen, A. L., Ekeland, T.6J., Getz, L., Hetlevik, I., Schei, E., Ulvestad, E. and
Vetlesen, A. J. (2016) Medicine's perception of reality – a split picture: critical reflections on
apparent anomalies within the biomedical theory of science.
22:4
[29] Thomas, S (2016) Does Evidence6Based Health Care Have Room for the Self?
22:4
[30] Chiffi, D. and Zanotti, R. (2016), Perspectives on clinical possibility: elements of analysis.
22:4
pe
[31] Mercuri,M & Baigrie,B (2016) Interpreting Risk as Evidence of Causality: lessons learned
from a legal case to determine medical malpractice.
22:4
er
[32] Parvan, A. (2014) Patients’ substantialization of disease, the hybrid symptom and
metaphysical care.
, 21:3, 380688
[33] Fellowes, S (2016) A reappraisal of Kendell and Jablensky's account of validity.
, 22:4
re
[34] Parvan, A (2016) Monistic Dualism and the body electric: an ontology of disease, patient
and clinician for person6centred healthcare.
, 22:4
vi
[35] Prasad,R (2016) Distinguishing Internal Property from External Property in Kidney
Transplantation.
, 22:4
ew
[36] Misselbrook, D. (2016), Aristotle, Hume and the goals of medicine.
22:4
[37] Greenhalgh, T., Howick, J. & Maskrey, N. (2014) Evidence based medicine: a movement
in crisis? $
!
, 348 (g3725), 1–7.
on
[38] Every6Palmer, S & Howick, J (2014) How evidence6based medicine is failing due to
biased trials and selective publication,
, 20:6, 9086
914
[39] Gaeta, R. and Gentile, N. (2016), Evidence, discovery and justification: the case of
evidence6based medicine.
. 22:4
ly
[40 ] Yelovich, M6C. (2016) The patient–physician interaction as a meeting of experts: one
solution to the problem of patient non6adherence.
,
22:4
[41] Henry, S.G. (2006) Recognizing Tacit Knowledgein Medical Epistemology. #
!
$
, 27(3), 1876213
[42] Fry, A. and Gergel, T. L. (2016), Paternalism and factitious disorder: medical treatment in
illness deception.
, 22:4
[43] Bullock, E, Gergel, T & Kingma, E (2015) Interdisciplinary workshop in the philosophy of
medicine: Parentalism and Trust,
, 21:3, 54268
[44] Kennedy, A. G. (2016) Evaluating diagnostic tests.
, 22:4
[45] Rogers, W. A., and Mintzker, Y. (2016) Getting clearer on overdiagnosis.
, 22:4
Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice
Page 10 of 10
[46] Stanley, D. E. and Campos, D. G. (2016) Selecting clinical diagnoses: logical strategies
informed by experience.
, 22:4
[47] Maddocks,M, Kerry,R, Turner, A & Howick,J (2016) Problematic placebos in physical
therapy trials.
, 22:4
[48] Borda, J. P. (2016) Self over time: another difference between borderline personality
disorder and bipolar disorder.
, 22:4
[49] Hipólito, I (2016) The phenomenology of intersubjective impairment.
, 22:4
[50] Fernández, J and Blis, S (2016) Schizophrenia and the Estranged Self
, 22:4
r
Fo
[51] 2. Eriksen, T. E. and Kirkengen, A. L. (2016) Patients' ‘thingification’, unexplained
symptoms and response6ability in the clinical context: in response to ‘Patients'
substantialization of disease, the hybrid symptom and the metaphysical care’, by Alexandra
Parvan.
, 22:4
[52] Loughlin,M, Wyer,P & Tanenbaum, S (2016) Teaching by (bad) example – commentary
on Jenicek's 'Do we need another discipline in medicine?'
, 22:4
pe
[53] Jenicek, M. (2015). Do we need another discipline in medicine? From epidemiology and
evidence6based medicine to cognitive medicine and medical thinking.
, 21:6, 102861034
er
[54]Loughlin, M., Lewith, G. & Falkenberg, T. (2013) Science, practice and mythology: a
definition and examination of the implications of scientism in medicine. Healthcare Analysis,
21, 130–145.
[55] Nagel, T. (1986) The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
ew
vi
re
ly
on