RETHINKING PRAGMATICS, LANGUAGE AND COMMUNICATION
Yoshikata Shibuya
National Institute of Information and Communications Technology
Context
as
Other
Communication,
Minds:
by
Talmy
The
Pragmatics
Givón,
John
of
Sociality,
Benjamins
Cognition
Publishing
and
Company,
Amsterdam, 2005, xvi + 283pp.
Keywords: context, mental models, social interaction, communication.
1. Introduction
The book under review (Context as Other Minds: The Pragmatics of Sociality,
Cognition and Communication) was written by Talmy Givón (University of
Oregon), one of the finest linguists today, notably for his work on functionalism in
linguistics (e.g. Givón 1984, 1989, 1995). Givón is also among those with the
broadest perspectives in linguistic typology, having written numerous articles on
language
dealing
with
communicative,
cognitive,
cultural,
and
biological
constraints. In this book, he suggests re-casting pragmatics (or more specifically,
the pragmatics of sociality and communication) from a neuro-cognitive,
bio-adaptive, and evolutionary perspective. It has been well known since Aristotle,
Kant and Peirce that context is a mental construct (i.e. framing operation) that is
undertaken on the fly by taking into account relevance (i.e. through judgment of
relevance). In this book, the author proposes to put forth the traditional view so far
as to argue that the (construed) context relevant to sociality, culture and
communication is in fact the mental representation of other minds. That is, the
context most relevant for social interaction and communication is suggested to be
the mental model of the interlocutor’s current rapidly shifting belief-and-intention
states.
2. Synopsis
2.1. Theoretical orientation
The book consists of ten chapters. Chapter 1 (Perspective, pp. 1-37) provides
a condensed intellectual history of pragmatics. Givón starts the chapter by
discussing the conundrum of context. He notes that the core action of pragmatics
(i.e. selecting the relevant frame) is the “source of its ancient conundrum” (p. 1).
He writes that “[t]he challenge facing sentient organisms is how to, somehow,
cobble the right frame around the picture, set the figure in its proper ground,
choose an apt point-of-view for a description, zoom onto the relevant perspective”
(p. 1) (note that throughout this paper those words originally written in italics in
the literature have been underlined instead). The contextual judgments involved in
the act of framing are, he continues, “adaptively indispensable”, although they may
be “logically arbitrary” (pp. 1-2). He then moves on to discuss briefly “Russell’s
(1908) paradox” (e.g. the celebrated Epimenides), “objectivism” (e.g. Carnap
(1963)), “relativism” (direct descent from Kant, Peirce and Wittgenstein), and
“other minds” (or more specifically, the mental construal of the others’ minds). He
then turns to discuss the notion of context and context-dependency on the basis of
recurrent themes of pragmatics. The issues discussed in the rest of the chapter
include those of “relevance and importance”, “similarity, analogy and metaphor”,
“categories and classification”, “abductive inference and analogical reasoning”,
“explanation
and
understanding”,
“teleology,
purpose
and
function”,
“figure/ground”, “gradation, continuum and non-discreteness”, and “the semiotic
relation”. The chapter also contains a discussion on the early roots of pragmatics,
with an introduction of the insights of the important antecedents of modern
Pragmatism such as Plato/Socrates, Aristotle, Kant, Peirce, and Wittgenstein. The
historical overview is followed by an overview of the modern strands in pragmatics.
Recounted here include “cultural relativism” (e.g. Whorf 1956, Geertz 1973),
“early functionalism” (e.g. Bolinger (1977); Chafe (1970), (1994)), “speech-acts”
(e.g. Austin (1962); Grice (1968/1975); Searle (1970)), “logical presupposition”
(e.g. Keenan (1969)), “modal logic and possible worlds” (e.g. Montague (1970);
Lewis (1972)), “ethnography of speech” (e.g. Labov (1972); Gumperz (1982)),
“developmental pragmatics” (e.g. Bates (1976)), “pragmatics and the machine” (e.g.
Winograd (1970); Dreyfus (1972); Schank and Abelson (1977)), “cognitive
psychology” (e.g. Koffka (1935); Swinney (1979)), and “evolutionary biology”
(Darwinian). Givón ends the chapter by expressing his firm conviction that
pragmatics holds “the key to an integrated understanding of life, behavior,
cognition and communication, and thus ultimately to an understanding of the
biological constraints on the evolution of sentient social beings” (p. 36).
Chapter 2 (Categories as prototypes: The adaptive middle, pp. 39-64) provides
an investigation of the mechanism of how generic (lexical-semantic) mental
categories (called “semantic memory” in cognitive psychology) are constructed.
Chapter 1 discusses mental categories primarily in terms of their “source”, namely
whether they are “innate” (Plato) or “acquired by experience” (Aristotle) (section
1.7.4). In Chapter 2, the central focus is given on the “adaptive pragmatics” of
lexical-semantic categories. Givón first provides an outline of the two extreme
traditional approaches to categorization (i.e. “extreme discreteness” and “extreme
graduality” of mental categories), tracing their roots in philosophy (Platonic vs.
Wittgensteinean), linguistics (Chomsky’s (1961) generativity vs. Hopper’s (1987)
emergence), and psychology (the feature-based model of Smith et al. (1974) vs. the
semantic networks cum spreading activation model of Quillian (1968), Collins and
Quillian (1972), and Collins and Loftus (1975)). He argues that between the two
extremes there is Kant’s (Kemp (1968)) middle-ground epistemology, which Givón
calls “the pragmatic – interactive, constructivist – middle” (p. 39). He notes that
prototype-based categories (Rosch (1973), (1975)) are “a hybrid system, a
quintessential adaptive compromise (Posner 1986)” (p. 46). He formulates the
pragmatic middle as the “adaptive” middle, noting that the pragmatic middle has a
high adaptive value. It is suggested that “[t]he hybrid nature of mental categories –
partly Platonic, partly Wittgensteinean – is not a philosophical caprice but an
adaptive strategy, a compromise designed to accommodate two conflicting
demands
on
biologically-based
information
processing”
(pp.
47-48).
The
prototype-like nature of mental categories is an adaptive compromise between two
conflicting but equally valid adaptive imperatives, one of which is “rapid uniform
processing of the predictable bulk”, and the other “contextual flexibility in dealing
with exceptionally highly-relevant cases” (§2.5). Each of the two extreme
approaches to categorization can only take care of one of the demands. It is only
the hybrid (i.e. the pragmatic middle-ground approach) that can take care of both.
The issue of how generic (lexical-semantic) mental categories are constructed
is further pursued in Chapter 3 (Semantic networks and metaphoric language, pp.
65-89) with a special interest in the adaptive underpinnings of metaphoric language.
In this chapter, Givón first returns to take a closer look at the cognitive design of
lexical-semantic categories that are culturally shared with members of the relevant
social group. He outlines the general design of the human communication system,
suggesting that well-coded human communication can be divided into two
sub-systems of “the cognitive representation system” and “the communicative
codes”. The former is comprised of three levels: “the conceptual lexicon”,
“propositional
information”
and
“multi-propositional
discourse”.
The
communicative codes are comprised of two coding instruments: “the sensory-motor
codes” and “the grammatical code”. The sensory-motor codes are used to code the
conceptual lexicon (i.e. words) and also an important part of grammar such as
morphology. It is argued that the grammar code (or simply, “grammar”) is
primarily used to code “discourse coherence”, which in turn translates into the
coding of “communicative intent”, which translates into mental models of “the
interlocutor’s current states of belief and intention” (p. 69). Givón suggests
formulating communication as merely “a sub-species of cooperative transaction” (p.
69). He then turns to highlight the view where meaning (conceptual/semantic) is
represented in the mind/brain as a “network of nodes and connections” (e.g.
Quillian (1968); Collins and Quillian (1972); Collins and Loftus (1975)). He notes
that analogical-abductive reasoning is “the most natural means we have for
construing contexts in a novel way, and thus for reinterpreting erstwhile outlier
members of an entrenched category as central members of a new category” (p. 40).
It is suggested that a discussion of metaphoric meaning is thus essential for a
thorough account of mental categories.
To recapitulate the discussions so far, the main points made in the preceding
chapters are 1) that context is not an objective entity, but a mental construct, the
construed
“ground”
against
which
tokens
of
experience
attain
mental
representation that is relatively stable as salient “figures”, and 2) that it is not
possible for either social cooperation or interpersonal communication to proceed
meaningfully and efficiently without one taking it for granted that one’s “generic”
mental categories are shared mostly with those of one’s interlocutor.
2.2. An adaptive approach to grammar
Givón in Chapter 4 (Grammar and other minds: An evolutionary perspective,
pp. 91-123) goes deeper (i.e. from the generic to the specific) into the central topic
of the book (i.e. the notion of the other mind) by discussing in detail “mental
models of the mind of particular interlocutors at particular times during on-going
communication” (p. 92). This chapter provides a framework where grammar is
taken to be an essential instrument for automated, streamlined information
processing. It is suggested that the interlocutor’s mental models of his/her
epistemic and deontic states are constructed rapidly on-line in grammar-coded
human communication.
In the chapter, Givón first describes the three mental representation systems
of “the generic lexicon”, “the current text” and “the current speech situation” in
light of such systems in the human mind/brain study as “permanent semantic
memory”,
“episodic
memory”
and
“working
memory
and/or
attention”,
respectively. Then, arguing against a structuralist methodology where grammatical
structures are studied in isolation from their communicative context (Chomsky
(1965)), Givón proposes an adaptive approach to grammar where grammar is taken
to have adaptive function. He illustrates how the discourse-coherence functions
coded
by
grammar
are
re-interpreted
as
“perspective-shifting
operations”
(MacWhinney (1999), (2002)), which in turn can be further re-interpreted as
“systematic manipulation (in production) or anticipation (in comprehension) of the
interlocutor’s current states of belief and intention (Givón 2001)” (p. 96). It is
argued, for example, that a referent marked by a definite grammatical cue is
grounded to one (or more) of the representation systems. He explains that in using
definite grammatical cues (e.g. the English definite article the) the speaker assumes
that the hearer is mentally accessible to the referent, and that such accessibility
may be dependent upon one of the three cognitive systems (i.e. the shared context).
Another case Givón illustrates in the chapter is the grammar of speech-acts. In
considering this aspect of grammar, he attempts to show how one accesses other
minds, suggesting that while speakers seem to possess a shifting mental model of
the epistemic (knowledge) states of the hearer’s, they must also possess a shifting
mental model of the deontic (intention) states of the hearer’s.
Moving onto the second part of the chapter, Givón introduces the concepts of
“Theories of Mind” (Premack and Woodruff (1978)), discussing the issue of
consciousness by considering mainly the brain areas most likely involved in
consciousness and also the type of consciousness considered necessary for a
representation of other minds. He suggests that the most important adaptive
capacity for a social cooperating species is the ability to forecast one’s
conspecifics’ behavior, stating that “the systematic on-line construction of mental
models of the current epistemic and deontic states of one’s interlocutor is the
central adaptive motivation for the evolution of grammar” (p. 121). “Specific
grammatical constructions”, he continues to argue, “are used to code (in the
speaker’s mind) and cue (in the hearer’s mind) specific mental models of the
interlocutor’s current (and rapidly shifting) mental states” (p. 121).
2.3. Referential coherence, propositional modalities and discourse coherence
The adaptive approach to grammar laid out in Chapter 4 is fleshed out in the
three subsequent chapters with discussions on three major issues in grammatical
structure. Chapter 5 (Referential coherence, pp. 125-147) discusses the grammar of
referential coherence, probing mainly into the two mental representation systems
of “working memory/attention” and “early episodic memory” (“semantic memory”
is taken for granted as being involved in discourse coherence operations, and hence
here it is not discussed in detail). By “coherence”, Givón refers to “grounding” (the
concept to be discussed in §3 of this review article). Following Kintsch and van
Dijk (1978) and Kintsch (1994), for instance, Givón takes the mental text
represented in episodic memory as a sequential-hierarchic network structure. In
this view, coherent episodic representation is considered to guarantee rapid on-line
access and also retrieval of specific episodic-memory nodes in production and
comprehension of discourse. Givón suggests that such access is highly dependent
upon the nodes’ connectivity to other nodes in the relevant network. He suggests
that the speaker and the hearer are busy trying to connect (or grounding) incoming
lexical and propositional nodes to the episodic structure of the pre-existing current
text. In order to illustrate the use of grammar as a means of cueing the grounding of
incoming information into the episodic representation of the currently available
text, Givón considers “anaphoric (retrospective) grounding” and “cataphoric
(anticipatory) grounding”. He argues that the former grounds incoming information
into the mental text that exists already. That is, it plays the role of cueing the
hearer as to the way the current referent should be grounded onto its co-referent
node in the pre-existing mental representation. On the other hand, the latter (i.e.
cataphoric grounding), so Givón suggests, establishes the structural foundations of
the text that has arrived newly. That is, it is useful for the speaker to cue the hearer
to attentional activation of the referent in the hearer’s currently-assembling
episodic memory. He notes that a surprisingly large portion of the grammatical
machinery participates in the cueing of referential coherence. It is suggested that
grammatical devices that cue primarily cataphoric coherence include those such as
“indefinite articles”, “grammatical case-roles”, “existential-presentative clauses”
and “role-changing constructions”, and those that cue primarily anaphoric
coherence include “zero, pronouns, pronominal agreement” (p. 135).
Chapter 6 (Propositional modalities, pp. 149-177) discusses the grammar of
propositional modalities. It is considered in linguistics (e.g. Palmer (1986)) that
the propositional modalities are not logical properties of propositions. Rather, it is
considered that it codes the speaker’s attitude toward the proposition. In this
chapter, Givón further elaborates the traditionally held linguistics view by
suggesting that “the speaker’s attitude is, in turn, never just – not even primarily –
about the proposition itself, but rather about the hearer’s attitude towards the
proposition as well as toward the speaker” (p. 149). Throughout the chapter, he
makes a case for this suggestion, discussing topics such as epistemic and deontic
modalities, tense, aspect, NEG-assertions, and evidentiality. He concludes the
chapter by suggesting that the deployment of these grammar-coded propositional
modalities in natural communication shows “fine-tuned sensitivity on the part of
speakers to the informational and social reality around them, most conspicuously to
the constantly shifting epistemic and deontic states of their interlocutors” (p. 177).
He argues that the use of these propositional modalities is part of our evolved,
habituated skills (as a social species), and that the adaptive scope of such skills is
pervasive, pertaining to how we live, behave, interact and communicate with our
conspecifics.
In Chapter 7 (Discourse coherence and clause chaining, pp. 179-194), Givón
turns to discuss the grammar of clause chaining. This chapter ends his survey of
grammar as a conventionalized tool for representing the interlocutor’s mind in
communication. Givón defines the grammatical devices used during natural on-line
discourse production and comprehension as “coherence signals” (p. 180). He notes
that the most general features of clause-chaining in coherent discourse pertain to
the four most salient positions a clause can occupy within the chain: “pre-initial (or
grounding)”, “chain-initial”, “chain-medial” and “chain-final” (p. 180).
“Pre-initial” clauses include three grammatical devices that all share the same
general property of double grounding. Namely, they furnish “local cataphoric
links” to the following chain-initial clause and signal “global anaphoric links” to
the preceding discourse. The grammatical devices include “pre-posed adverbial
clauses”, “pre-posed adverbial phrases”, and “left-dislocation clauses”. Below are
examples of pre-posed adverbial clauses (taken from p. 182):
(1) Explicitly marked temporal links:
a.
Precedence:
After she entered, she saw him.
b. Subsequence: Before she entered, she saw him.
c.
Simultaneity: While she was entering, she saw him.
“Chain-initial” clauses launch a topical argument (a new chain) into the
discourse, an example of which includes the existential-presentative clause as
given in (2) (taken from p. 186):
(2) … There’s something I’ve been meaning to ask you… Thing is, I’m
not sure how to say it, it’s a bit embarrassing… Fact is, I’m not sure
how you’re going to take this… Well, heck, it’s been bothering me for
such a long time, I reckon I better tell you about it…
“Chain-medial” clauses are the most frequent and unmarked in coherent
discourse, examples of which include the case of aspectual change from
imperfective to perfective as given in (3) below (taken from p. 187):
(3) Maximally-coherent imperfective aspect chain:
a.
She was writing to her parents,
b.
telling them about her new flat,
c.
describing the furniture
d.
And poking fun at the neighbors.
Break in aspectual coherence:
e.
She also told them…
Unacceptable alternative following the break:
e.
*
, also told them…
“Chain-final” clauses terminate the thematic chain. The grounding properties
of these clauses are mostly anaphoric and only marginally cataphoric. An example
of chain-final clauses is given in (4) below, where it is shown that only the
chain-final clause is finite and is fully marked both for referent (she) and
tense-aspect (i.e. perfective-past) (example taken from p. 192):
(4) Coming into the room, looking around and finding no place to sit, she
finally perched herself on the window sill.
In the chapter, it is argued that discourse coherence (cross-clause and
cross-chain coherence) is established by the grammatical cues (those as discussed
in chapters 5 and 6). Givón maintains that what emerges with all coherence-cuing
devices taken together is “an elaborate system of cues that speakers give hearers
about highly-specific mental structures and operations, all directed at the three
major cognitive systems in which the current text is represented during on-line
communication: working-memory, attention, and early episodic memory” (p. 193).
2.4. Extending the scope of pragmatics beyond its traditional bounds
Givón, in the final three chapters of the book, extends the scope of pragmatics
somewhat beyond its traditional bounds, discussing the field’s interdisciplinary
implications for domains such as philosophy of science, theory of personality, and
social interaction. Chapter 8 (Community as other mind: The pragmatics of
organized science, pp. 195-220) discusses the close parallelism between the
pragmatics of individual cognition (i.e. epistemology) and the pragmatics of
organized inquiry (i.e. philosophy of science). Givón claims that epistemology and
philosophy of science have in common the dynamics of “being always in the midst
of the endless process of accretion of knowledge” and “having always a dialogic
interaction with some relevant interlocutor whose beliefs and intentions must be
reckoned with” (p. 196). It is suggested that the scientist’s relevant interlocutor
whose mind is to be anticipated is “the community of scholars” (p. 196).
Discussing two reductionist extremes: “deductivism” (Rationalist, e.g. Popper
(1934/1959)) and “inductivism” (Empiricist, e.g. Carnap (1963)), he argues that
pragmatic/abductive inference is employed not just at one particular phase but
actually at a number of other phases during empirical investigation. He
recapitulates the Peirce-Hanson rendition of the low-level cycle of empirical
investigation as follows (cf. Hanson (1958), Peirce (1940)) (pp. 215-216) (here the
other details have been omitted due to lack of space):
(5) a.
Fact-driven initial impetus (‘the puzzle’)
b. Leaping to hypothesis (‘the mystery’)
c.
Abductive inference (‘gambler’s leap to faith’)
d. Deductive consequences (‘predictions’)
e.
Testability (‘ways and means’)
f.
Relevance (‘where to start’)
g. Inductive testing (‘roll of the dice’)
h. Inductive inference (‘validity’)
i.
Failure to falsify
j.
Falsification (‘modus tollens’)
k. Reconsideration and modification (‘back to square one’)
Givón argues that pragmatic judgments/inferences of various sorts are
intervened at a number of points during the cycle summarized in (5) (i.e. in 5a-c, e,
f, h, i, k). He concludes by stating that “the practice of scientific inquiry is
undertaken, at each phase of the empirical cycle, within the context of an
anticipated communal mind-cast”, and that “[t]he scientist, whether explicitly or
implicitly, is always engaged in a dialog with one or more putative interlocutors in
his/her relevant community of science” (p. 219). In Givón’s view, the scientist is
the social organism who is engaged in learning from his/her conspecifics through
social interaction and communication (a relevant issue to be raised again in §3).
Chapter 9 (The adaptive pragmatics of ‘self’, pp. 221-238) is concerned with
the concept of ‘self’ (or personality). It discusses context as the construed mind of
the other. When encountering a stranger, it is not uncommon for one to make a
quick judgment regarding what the stranger is really like (e.g. at job interviews). In
many cases, people only expose themselves to a limited range of the stranger’s rich
behavioral repertoire, and tend to make immediate judgments about the ‘essence’
of the person who they have just encountered. This popular theory of personality is
called in this book “the essentialist theory of the self” (p. 222). From an
evolutionary perspective, until recently, Givón argues, such an essentialist theory
of self was “highly predictive” and “adaptive” (p. 223). Givón contrasts the
essentialist theory of the self with a different theory called “the contextual theory
of the multiple self” (p. 224), which holds the proposition that “a person’s social
communication with his/her conspecifics, most conspicuously with strangers, is
nothing but an elaborate stage performance; and that people as a matter of course
tailor their self-presentation to fit the – perceived, construed – current social
context (‘setting’)”, namely “to fit what they perceive as their audience’s
expectations” (p. 225). Comparing the two theories, Givón argues that the twain
would never part, the one being “an ur-Platonic invariant essentialist, the other an
ur-Aristotelian context-adjusting empiricist” (p. 229).
In that chapter, he goes on to discuss two well-known personality disorders of
schizophrenia and autism, suggesting that in each case “one of the twin aspects of
the self – the context-adjusting multiple or the invariant essence – has taken sway
to the relative exclusion of the other” (p. 229). Discussing the extreme case of
schizophrenia and also the milder case of the so-called “borderline personality
disorder” (aka BPD), he argues that they are due to “a disruption of the central,
controlling, essentialist component of the self” (p. 231). As for autism, he makes
an observation that “[a]utistic-Asperger people appear to operate from a fixed,
rigid perspective, and have a great difficulty adjusting their perspective to fit the
vagaries of the rapidly-shifting context”, namely that “they have difficulty in
contextual construal, or re-framing” (p. 234). It is suggested that the two
personality disorders are caused by problems with the “controlling ‘self’” (p. 234).
The disorders are identified as the respective clinical expressions of the two
extreme poles of the self. The neurological basis for the two disturbances has been
reported to be found at two distinct loci within the “attentional networks” (p. 233;
Posner and Fan (2004)). It is noted that an unimpaired self must accommodate both
extremes (i.e. the anterior cingulate cortex and the posterior/dorsal parietal cortex).
Givón suggests that here evolution appears to have created a “classical complex,
hybrid … adaptive compromise” (p. 236). That is, “[t]hat our representation of the
mind of the other (3rd order) rebounds and eventually transforms our own
self-representation (2nd order) into a 4th-order construct is but an adaptive
consequence of being a social, cooperative, communicating species” (p. 236) .
In the final chapter of the book (Chapter 10: The pragmatics of martial arts,
pp. 239-254), Givón discusses the contextual pragmatics of the martial arts. More
specifically, he addresses the role of other minds in martial arts, discussing Tai Chi
Chuan as a stand-in for social interaction. Givón suggests that an important
difference between communication and martial arts is that the interlocutor in
martial arts is an adversary. He admits that one might find the inclusion of martial
arts in a book on pragmatics rather an odd choice. He, however, notes that a closer
examination reveals the fact that the inclusion of martial arts is really a natural fit
in the volume, because “[i]n both communication and warfare, one’s moves depend,
at any decision-making juncture, on the ever-present – explicit or implicit – mind
of the other, a mind crammed-full of currently-relevant but ever-shifting epistemic
and deontic states” (p. 239). He argues that whether in hostile or cooperative
interaction, one’s action is always motivated by the opponent’s action (or its
anticipation, to be more exact). One’s every move is, he argues, transacted in the
context of the adversary’s putative current states of belief and intention. He refers
to his late teacher Marshall Ho’o, who had faith in Tai Chi Chuan as a martial art
but would always revert to “Outer School” (Kung Fu, Judo) moves (not “Inner” Tai
Chi such as yoga) while demonstrating martial applications (conspicuously so
during sparring with an opponent).
3. Critical evaluation and conclusion
Having recapitulated the main points of the book, one thing would appear for
sure. That is, there is no doubt that Givón’s Context as Other Minds would attract
many students, not to mention professional scholars as well, who have an interest
in pragmatics, communication, language evolution, and the mind. The book
provides a wealth of necessary background knowledge about the topics with
detailed discussions of theory and methodology, making cases that apparently
support Givón’s suggested theory. Pragmatics is concerned with the meanings (e.g.
implicatures) that sentences have in particular contexts. It concerns how people
understand utterances (e.g. how people construe a context, how people choose a
perspective). Understanding is highly contextual. As Givón shows in the book,
pragmatics
has
communication.
an
The
inseparable
relationship
nature
pragmatics
of
with
thus
culture,
essentially
sociality,
calls
for
and
an
interdisciplinary approach, and Givón in this book provides a direction into it. He
aims at advocating a theory of context as other minds. Throughout the book, he
convincingly makes a case for such a theory. It seems thus that the aim of the book
has been attained on the whole, and also that the book seems appropriately titled.
There are, however, some critical points that I would like to make.
3.1. Necessity for more “concrete” discussions
There is first the problem that the book may leave an impression that it could
have been improved on if it included a more careful examination of the suggested
hypothesis on various levels. The main point of the book, as I understand it, is to
illustrate that the speaker constantly takes into consideration the interlocutor’s
mental models, and Givón provides an evolutionary/adaptive account for it. As
interesting as this claim might be, given the type of argumentation the book
provides, it is difficult to evaluate the validity of the claim for various reasons.
First, it appears that the book fails to provide a large enough number of
instances so that the reader would feel fully convinced by the discussions it offers.
Chapter 6 provides an exceptionally reasonable amount of data in the book, but for
the scale of the suggestions the author makes, it seems that more examples
could/should have been presented. In that chapter, for example, in discussing tense,
Givón, citing clause chains that are characterized by high continuity of reference,
notes that the same is true of the temporal continuity of the chain, arguing that this
is why once the chain has been temporally grounded by explicit tense-marking of
its initial clause, reduced marking (including zero) is used in the rest of the clauses
in the chain in most languages (as long as no further temporal re-orientation is
added). He illustrates this by citing some examples from Swahili, where the
so-called “consecutive tense” is used following initial grounding to certain
temporality (e.g. past, future, progressive). The following examples show the case
of past (taken from p. 154):
(6) a.
…wa-Ingereza
wa-li-wa-chukua wa-le
PL -British
3p- PAST -3p-take
maiti
2p- DEM corpses
‘… then the British took the corpses
b. wa-ka-wa-tia
Katika
bao
moja,
on
board
one
wa-ka-ya-telemesha maji-ni
kwa
utaratibu w-ote.
3p- CONS -them-lower water- LOC
of
in-order
3p- CONS -3p-put
put them on a flat board,
c.
3p-all
and lowered them steadily into the water…’
Givón simply notes that it is often the case in many languages that an
invariant marker is used to cue the hearer that the same temporality (or
aspectuality) remains as in the preceding clause. His discussion of this aspect of
grammar is thought-provoking. It seems to show a convincing case to argue that in
grammar-coded human communication, explicit tense-marking of the initial clause
temporally grounds the chain, and that an invariant marker cues the hearer that the
same temporality remains as in the preceding clause. Admitting the value of the
points Givón makes here, it seems, however, to me that the reader would not be left
fully convinced due to the fact that too little data has been provided in the
discussion. Here, only Swahili is referred to with a very limited number of
examples (see pp. 154-156), which makes a reader wonder if what he argues for is
really the case across languages in the world. Overall, it seems that the book
provides too small an amount of actual linguistic data for one to feel strongly that
the suggestions Givón makes are guaranteed empirically.
In addition to the lack of data, there is second the issue of how much one
should/could take at face value the type of explanation (i.e. evolutionary) which
Givón proposes in the book. Namely, there is the empirical issue as to whether the
claim that speakers constantly take into consideration the interlocutor’s mental
models is in fact true. Do speakers really build up representations of other minds?
And if so, then what do these representations consist of? What about the case
where speakers just cannot infer the interlocutors’ mental models on the basis of
their own (e.g. in the case of interaction with infants or people whose cultural
background is very different to the speakers’)? When do speakers make use of
others’ mental representations? In order to discuss if context does consist of
representations of other minds, all these questions need be addressed and some
evidence should be provided. Nevertheless, in the book none of these questions are
discussed squarely. It is indeed true that it is not easy to test the validity of the
suggestions Givón proposes in the book, but the suggested claim being so
important and thought-provoking, leaves the reader with the questions as noted
above.
Today, the issue of how people engage in conversation is attracting much
attention in psychology. An important concept in conversation studies is
“grounding” (e.g. Clark and Brennan (1991); Wilkes-Gibbs and Clark (1992)).
Clark and Krych (2004), for example, note that in conversation speakers try to
ground their communicative acts as they go along. The speakers’ goal in working
with their partners is, so they suggest, to reach the mutual belief that the partners
have understood them appropriately for the current purposes. Consider a
spontaneous exchange as given below (taken from Clark and Krych (2004:63);
pairs of asterisks mark overlapping speech):
(7) Alan
were you there when they erected the new signs? -
Beth
th- which new *signs*?
Alan
*litt*le notice boards, indicating where you had to go for
everything,
Beth
no,
Clark and Krych suggest that in (7) for Alan and Beth to ground Alan’s question
regarding “the new signs”, they need to deal with four levels of “joint action”
(Clark (1996)) as follows (Clark and Krych (2004:63)):
(8) Level 1.
Alan must get Beth to attend to his vocalization. They
would ordinarily try to establish this as common ground. If
she had missed it, she might say “What?” or “Pardon?”
and he would repeat it.
Level 2.
Alan must get Beth to identify the words, phrases, and
sentence he has presented. They would ordinarily try to
establish her identification as common ground. If she was
uncertain of “erected,” she might ask “Did what to the new
signs?” to which he would respond “erected.”
Level 3.
Alan must get Beth to understand what he means by those
words. What does he mean by “there,” and which signs is
he referring to? They would ordinarily try to establish this,
too, as common ground. In fact, Beth asks “Which new
signs?”
and
Alan
explains,
“Little
notice
boards,
indicating where you had to go for everything.”
Level 4.
Alan must get Beth to consider answering his question.
Should she reveal she was there or not? Does she
remember? They would ordinarily try to establish this as
common ground as well. She could reply “I don’t recall”
or “I’ll never tell.” In fact, she answers “no.”
Clark and Krych mention that there are a number of ways for people to ground at
these four levels. They argue that speaking is a bilateral process in the sense that
people do not only speak, but they also nod, smile, point, and gaze at each other
(moreover, also exhibit and place things) during communication. They suggest that
such gestural acts are often tied to what people are doing while talking. In the
kitchen, for example, people may do something like pointing at utensils, showing
the ingredients to each other, and handing each other pots and pans. At the dinner
table, on the other hand, people might point at salt shakers, pass food, and exhibit
empty plates. The important point made by Clark and Krych is that it is the vocal
and gestural acts together that comprise people’s talk, and that both of these
aspects must be put under scrutiny when studying how they speak. In the book
under review, Givón does discuss the concept of “grounding” when he considers
the grammar of referential coherence (Chapter 5), but unfortunately the importance
of studying both the vocal and gestural acts is not emphasized as much as it should
be.
Today, in addition to these psychological studies on grounding, there are
psycholinguistic studies on how people interact with each other in conversation, in
which issues such as the effects of speaker’s knowledge on addressees’
interpretations are addressed (e.g. Metzing and Brennan (2003); Schober and
Brennan (2003)). It seems that the book could have been improved on if it included
more “concrete” discussions by referring to these recent psychological and
psycholinguistic studies on communication. Givón advocates an adaptive (or
evolutionary) approach to explaining communicative contexts. His adaptive
explanation does seem interesting indeed, but it appears that taking an “adaptive”
approach without referring to any of the psychological and psycholinguistic
literature as introduced above unfortunately resulted in making the issue (i.e. the
nature of pragmatics and contexts) more highly abstract than necessary. It is true,
as Comrie (1989) rightly points out, that “any explanation necessarily pushes the
problem back one stage further, since the explanation itself then becomes an object
requiring explanation” (p. 25), but amongst the various types of explanations, one
that appeals to adaptive motivations as hard as Givón does in the book is among the
most abstract type of explanations. After all, it is probably not such an
unreasonable idea to argue that adaptive motivations underlie communication, but
it is also true that it is very hard to empirically test the validity of the adaptive
claim which Givón makes in the book. This book would have been less abstract and
more convincing if the author had included discussions of recent psychological and
psycholinguistic studies along with his suggested adaptive approach.
In
addition
to
the
way
Givón
advocates
an
adaptive
approach
to
communication, there is another abstract argumentation in the way he illustrates
grammar. He holds the view that grammar has the function of anticipating or
influencing others’ minds. He suggests that grammar has evolved as an adaptation
to our need for inducing others to comprehend what we have in our mind (i.e.,
grammar is taken to have an adaptive function). A series of attempts are made to
provide evidence for the adaptive view of grammar (Chapters 4-7). His claim is
very suggestive, but it is again difficult to test the suggested adaptive view of
grammar due to the fact that the explanation only appeals to the concept “adaptive”
without providing a large enough amount of actual linguistic data (as noted above).
In discussing grammar theoretically, one might expect a more concrete
argumentation on grammatical theories than just an adaptive view. On a personal
note, I wonder what the implication of Givón’s adaptive approach to grammar has
for other syntactic frameworks, in particular for “construction grammar” (e.g.
Fillmore and Kay (1993); Goldberg (1995); Croft (2001)). Construction grammar is
a cognitive-functional approach that studies semantic and discourse functional
properties of constructions (broadly taken) without assuming such formal
theoretical constructs as those found in generative grammar, for example (e.g.
Chomsky (1957), (1965), (1981), (1995)). Goldberg (2003) compares construction
grammar and generative grammar as follows (p. 219):
[C]onstructionist approaches contrast sharply with the mainstream
generative approach. The latter has held that the nature of language can
best be revealed by studying formal structures independently of their
semantic or discourse functions. Ever increasing layers of abstractness
have characterized the formal representations. Meaning is claimed to
derive from the mental dictionary of words, with functional differences
between formal patterns being largely ignored. Semiregular patterns and
unusual patterns are viewed as ‘peripheral,’ with a narrow band of data
seen as relevant to the ‘core’ of language. Mainstream generative theory
argues further that the complexity of core language cannot be learned
inductively by general cognitive mechanisms and therefore learners must
be hard-wired with principles that are specific to language (‘universal
grammar’).
In construction grammar, constructions are defined as pairings of form and
(semantic or discourse) function. There are a number of empirical reasons for one
to follow construction grammar. For example, today a number of researchers in the
construction grammar framework hold that constructions are learned pairings of
form and function. This is the usage-based model view of grammar (e.g. Barlow
and Kemmer (2000); Langacker (1988), (2000)). The usage-based view is
empirically supported by language acquisition research by Tomasello and his
collaborators (see e.g. Tomasello and Brooks (1999); Diessel and Tomasello
(2001); Tomasello (2003)). Another solid support for construction grammar is
provided by Croft’s (2001) Radical Construction Grammar, where he presents a
number of pieces of empirical evidence for this approach from a typological
perspective. Construction grammar takes language use seriously, and so does
Givón’s approach to grammar. It is thus naturally expected that the reader
interested in construction grammar would wonder what Givón’s adaptive approach
to grammar and a construction grammar approach would suggest to each other. In
the book, however, unfortunately no remark on construction grammar is found, and
the discussions on grammar remain abstract.
3.2. Some “incomplete” discussions
The second problem I address concerns the fact that some parts of the book
appear not as thoroughly written as they should have been. That is, there is the
problem that the book sometimes fails to refer to some very important works
available in the existent literature which are relevant to the discussions it offers.
The second problem is related, but still discrete to the first one addressed in the
preceding section, in that the second one is not due to the “abstractness” of the
argumentation but simply due to the “incompleteness” of it.
In Chapter 3, for example, utilizing a network model, Givón discusses
metaphoric meaning, focusing on “the process of abductive-analogical reasoning
by which senses are extended” (p. 72). He argues that the on-line use of metaphor
(or metaphorical senses) is marked by “a certain measure of serendipity”, because
“a context is not there objectively, waiting to be noticed” (p. 72). A context is
instead, he argues, “construed on the fly, for the occasion” (p. 72). As for the fact
that there are some analogies or similarities that are more likely to be construed
than others during live communication, he explains that they are more “cognitively
transparent” and thus more “adaptively valid” (p. 73). He suggests thus a
contextual-adaptive basis for metaphoric language use.
Givón discusses critically Lakoff et al.’s notion of “conceptual metaphors”
(e.g. ‘learning is eating’, ‘understanding is perceiving’) (e.g. Lakoff and Johnson
(1980), Lakoff (1987)). He makes a critique that conceptual metaphors are
identified out of context when the felicity of metaphors crucially does depend on
the serendipity of the context. He goes so far as to claim that the analytic method
employed in Lakoff et al.’s framework is that of the logician-philosopher, stating
that “[t]he vast collection of out-of-context metaphors, together with their
classifiers, are obtained through the study of competence rather than of
performance” (p. 79). The alternative approach Givón suggests is a network model
account, where senses (both literal and metaphoric) are co-activated in discourse
(the former sense by the expression itself, and the latter by the discourse context).
In his model, specific activation of conceptual metaphors is not necessary.
Givón’s discussion of how one should analyze metaphors is insightful. Yet,
there seem to be further points that should be addressed for a more detailed study
of metaphors. First, he does not discuss a motivational foundation for metaphors,
but it seems very important to address such an issue in metaphor research. Nozawa
and Shibuya (in press) study metaphors such as He is a wolf, and argue for a
social-behavioral motivation for metaphors. They suggest that communication that
makes use of a certain type of metaphor is a type of strategy whereby the speaker
evokes the source concept in the hearer’s mind in the way the speaker could
perform illocutionary acts and/or perlocutionary acts effectively.
In addition to the motivational foundation of metaphors, it is also important to
consider constructional properties in studying metaphors (and metonymies as well).
Through a corpus-based study of English adjectives, Shibuya (2005) makes a case
that the attributive construction (e.g. happy people, a loud explosion) allows more
metaphorical and metonymic senses to be available than the predicative
construction does (see also Shibuya (2006)). Take happy for instance. In Shibuya
(2005), distinguishing the senses of happy into “direct” (non-metonymic) and
“indirect” (metonymic) types, it is revealed in a corpus study that the indirect uses
(both literally and metaphorically) of the adjective are only found attributively (e.g.
happy faces, the happy sobs of the water, a happy place, happy years, a happy
marriage) (Shibuya (2005:210-212)). In Lakoff et al.’s theory, it is not clear why
some metonymies and metaphors are (or are not) available in a particular
construction. Shibuya (2005) emphasizes the importance of taking a constructional
approach to the study of metaphor and metonymy. He argues that the high
availability of metaphorical and metonymic senses in the English attributive
construction is due to the fact that this construction activates a relevant frame more
actively than the predicative construction, therefore allowing highly flexible
conceptualization of the referent (literally, metaphorically and metonymically).
That is, according to Shibuya (2005), if a construction does not have a certain
frame element within its frame activation range, then senses related to the element
will not be available in the construction. Metaphor and metonymy are not only
issues concerning concepts, but also crucially an issue of constructions. The
constructional approach to adjectival semantics as taken by Shibuya (2005)
provides an insight to the theory developed by Lakoff et al. and also Givón’s
network model account.
Turning now to another issue, there is also the issue of how one differentiates
between semantics and pragmatics. Consider the following examples (taken from p.
168):
(9) a.
There was once a man who didn’t have a head.
b. ? There was once a man who had a head.
c.
d.
? There was once a man who didn’t look like a frog.
There was once a man who looked like a frog.
Givón makes an observation, in the discussion on NEG-assertions (Chapter 6), that
(9b) and (9c) are “pragmatically” odd as they merely restate the norm and hence
are tautological. It depends on ones’ definition of pragmatics as to how one
analyzes the infelicity of (9b) and (9c). If one holds the view that semantics deals
with truth-conditional meanings while pragmatics deals with cultural background
knowledge (or world knowledge), then s/he would ascribe the infelicity of (9b) and
(9c) to pragmatics, which is what Givón does here. Yet, it is here that the
now-classic question arises immediately. How does one clearly differentiate
between “cultural background knowledge” and the so-called “truth-conditional
meanings” (or more precisely, “dictionary meanings”)? In cognitive linguistics,
one holds the theoretical assumption that in order for us to understand a concept
properly we need to call on our “encyclopedic” knowledge (for a discussion on the
dictionary view and the encyclopedic view, see Haiman (1980)). Given the
encyclopedic view, the infelicity of (9b) and (9c) is considered a problem of our
conceptual structure or knowledge structure, and is dealt with in relation to
theoretical concepts such as “frames” (e.g. Fillmore (1982), (1985), Fillmore and
Atkins (1992)), “domains” (e.g. Langacker (1987)), and “idealized cognitive
models” (e.g. Lakoff (1987)). Thus, from a cognitive linguistics perspective,
considering
the
inseparability
of
dictionary
knowledge
and
encyclopedic
knowledge, an encyclopedic view of concepts might appear preferable.
Finally, moving now onto the issue of “cycles of empirical investigation”,
Givón fails to include a discussion of David Hull’s (1988) work. As noted in §2.4,
Givón argues that the scientist is the social organism who is engaged in learning
from his/her conspecifics through social interaction and communication (Chapter
8). Hull (1988) proposes a selection model of conceptual change from the
perspective of the philosophy of science. He studies carefully the process of
science (or to be more precise, the social and conceptual development of science),
illustrating the social and intellectual dynamics of science taking an evolutionary
account (e.g. the ways how research is actually done by scientists, how science
develops). Hull’s model, in fact, provides such a general enough framework that
Croft (2000) applies the model to linguistics, bringing a new perspective to the
study of language change. It would have been interesting if Givón included Hull’s
(1988) work and also Croft’s (2000) in his discussions.
3.3. Typographical errors
In addition to the main problems that I raise about the content of the book,
there are also some typographical matters which I noticed while reading it. As is
usually the case with any literature, several typographical errors can be found in
the book (e.g. “metal” representation in the brain in stead of “mental” [p. 92], Once
grammar is “studies” in its natural adaptive context instead of “studied” [p. 96],
(20A-i) and (2A-i) should be (16A-i) [p. 105], “sort-term” working memory buffer
in stead of “short-term” [p. 107], … it would “seems” that … in stead of “seem” [p.
130], A “clauses” in this position performs … in stead of “clause” [p. 180], Schank
and Abelson (1977) is missing in the references).
3.4. Final remarks
Having made some critical points about the book, I would still like to
emphasize that the book is an extremely important work. The critical points that I
have made above should not detract from the fact that Context as Other Minds is a
very valuable work. As Givón notes in the preface of the book, the book is meant to
be “only an opening sketch” (p. xiv). The theoretical and methodological problems
that I raised above should not thus dismiss, by any means, the main points Givón
addresses in this book, as it is not reasonable at all to dismiss such an insightful
theory as Givón’s just because it cannot be tested empirically (not yet anyway).
Overall, throughout the book, Givón insightfully exemplifies and discusses the
issues, providing an apparently good argument in favor of his theory of context as
other minds. Context as Other Minds is thus destined to become one of the most
important works on the issues of language and communication in general for years
to come. The scope of the book is so far-reached that it would no doubt attract
attention from many students and professional scholars interested in not only
linguistics proper (e.g. semantics, pragmatics and syntax), but also areas such as
cognition and language, philosophy and sociology. I strongly agree with the point
Givón makes in the book that social factors need to be seriously taken into
consideration in language and communication research. In fact, today the
importance of taking a social view is increasingly emphasized by more and more
researchers (e.g. Clark (1996); Croft (2000), (2006); Tomasello (1995), (1999)). I
hope that the book will be read widely, and stimulate further discussions.
References
Austin, John L. (1962) How to Do Things with Words, Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, MA.
Barlow, Michael and Suzanne Kemmer, eds. (2000) Usage-Based Models of
Language. Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford.
Bates, Elizabeth (1976) Language in Context: The Acquisition of Pragmatics,
Academic Press, New York.
Bolinger, Dwight (1977) The Forms of Language, Longman, London.
Carnap, Rudolph (1963) The Philosophy of Rudolph Carnap, Open Court, La Sallre,
IL.
Chafe, Wallace L. (1970) Meaning and the Structure of Language, University of
Chicago Press, Chicago.
Chafe, Wallace L. (1994) Discourse, Consciousness and Time: Displacement of
Conscious Experience in Speaking and Writing, University of Chicago Press,
Chicago.
Chomsky, Noam (1957) Syntactic Structures, Mouton, The Hague.
Chomsky, Noam (1961) “On the Notion ‘Rule of Grammar’,” The Structure of
Language and its Mathematical Aspects, ed. by Roman Jakobson, 6-24,
American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI.
Chomsky, Noam (1965) Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, MIT Press, Cambridge,
MA.
Chomsky, Noam (1981) Lectures on Government and Binding, Foris, Dordrecht.
Chomsky, Noam (1995) The Minimalist Program, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Clark,
Herbert
H.
(1996)
Using
Language,
Cambridge
University
Press,
Cambridge.
Clark, Herbert H. and Meredyth A. Krych (2004) “Speaking While Monitoring
Addressees for Understanding,” Journal of Memory and Language 50, 62-81.
Clark, Herbert H. and Susan E. Brennan (1991) “Grounding in Communication,”
Perspectives on Socially Shared Cognition, eds. by Lauren B. Resnick, John
M. Levine, and Stephanie D. Teasley, 127-149, American Psychological
Association, Washington, DC.
Collins, Allan M. and Elizabeth F. Loftus (1975) “A Spreading Activation Theory
of Semantic Processing,” Psychological Review 82, 407-428.
Collins, Allan M. and M. Ross Quillian (1972) “How to Make a Language User,”
Organization of Memory, eds. by Endel Tulving and Wayne Donaldson,
310-351, Academic Press, New York.
Comrie, Bernard (1989) Language Universals and Linguistic Typology, 2nd ed.,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Croft, William (2000) Explaining Language Change: An Evolutionary Approach,
Longman, Harlow, Essex.
Croft, William (2001) Radical Construction Grammar: Syntactic Theory in
Typological Perspective, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Croft, William (2006) “Toward a Social Cognitive Linguistics,” paper presented at
symposium, Cognitive Patterns in Language, Institute of Language and
Communication, University of Southern Denmark, Odense.
Diessel, Holger and Michael Tomasello (2001) “The Acquisition of Finite
Complement
Clauses
in
English:
A
Usage
Based
Approach
to
the
Development of Grammatical Constructions,” Cognitive Linguistics 12,
97-141.
Dreyfus, Hubert L. (1972) What Computers Can’t Do, Harper and Row, New York.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1982) “Frame Semantics,” Linguistics in the Morning Calm,
ed. by the Linguistic Society of Korea, 111-137, Hanshin, Seoul, Korea.
Fillmore, Charles J. (1985) “Frames and the Semantics of Understanding,”
Quaderni di Semantica 6, 222-254.
Fillmore, Charles J. and Beryl T. S. Atkins (1992) “Towards a Frame-based
Lexicon: The Semantics of RISK and Its Neighbours,” Frames, Fields and
Contrasts, eds. by Adrienne Lehrer and Eva F. Kittay, 75-102, Lawrence
Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Fillmore, Charles J. and Paul Kay (1993) “Construction Grammar,” ms., University
of California, Berkeley
Geertz, Clifford (1973) The Interpretation of Cultures, Basic Books, New York.
Givón, Talmy (1984) Syntax: A Functional-Typological Introduction, John
Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Givón, Talmy (1989) Mind, Code and Context: Essays in Pragmatics, Lawrence
Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Givón, Talmy (1995) Functionalism and Grammar, John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Givón, Talmy (2001) “Toward a Neuro-cognitive Interpretation of ‘Context’,”
Pragmatics and Cognition 9, 175-201.
Goldberg, Adele E. (1995) Constructions: A Construction Grammar Approach to
Argument Structure, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Goldberg, Adele E. (2003) “Constructions: A New Theoretical Approach to
Language,” TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences 7, 219-224.
Grice, Paul (1968/1975) “Logic and Conversation”, Syntax and Semantics, Volume
3: Speech Acts, eds. by Peter Cole and Jerry L. Morgan, 41-58, Academic
Press, New York.
Gumperz, John J. (1982) Discourse Strategies, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Haiman, John (1980) “Dictionaries and Encyclopedias,” Lingua 50, 329-357.
Hanson, Russell N. (1958) Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual
Foundations of Science, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Hopper, Paul (1987) “Emergent Grammar,” BLS 13, 139-157.
Hull, David L. (1988) Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social
and Conceptual Development of Science, University of Chicago Press,
Chicago.
Keenan, Edward L. (1969) A Logical Base for a Transformational Grammar of
English, Doctoral dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.
Kemp, John (1968) The Philosophy of Kant, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Kintsch, Walter (1994) “The Psychology of Discourse Processing”, Handbook of
Psycholinguistics, ed. by Morton A. Gernsbacher, 721-739, Academic Press,
New York.
Kintsch, Walter and Teun A. van Dijk (1978) “Toward a Model of Text
Comprehension and Production”, Psychological Review 85, 363-394.
Koffka, Kurt (1935) Principles of Gestalt Psychology, Harcourt, Brace & World,
New York:
Labov, William (1972) Sociolinguistic Patterns, University of Pennsylvania Press,
Philadelphia.
Lakoff, George (1987) Women, Fire and Dangerous Things: What Categories
Reveal about the Mind, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Lakoff, George and Mark Johnson (1980) Metaphors We Live By, University of
Chicago Press, Chicago.
Langacker, Ronald W. (1987) Foundations of Cognitive Grammar: Theoretical
Prerequisites, Stanford University Press, Stanford.
Langacker, Ronald W. (1988) “A Usage-based Model,” Topics in Cognitive
Linguistics, ed. by Brygida Rudzka-Ostyn, 127-161, John Benjamins,
Amsterdam.
Langacker, Ronald W. (2000) “A Dynamic Usage-Based Model,” Usage-Based
Models of Language, eds. by Michael Barlow and Suzanne Kemmer, 1-63,
Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford.
Lewis, David (1972) “General Semantics,” Semantics of Natural Language, eds. by
Donald Davidson and Gilbert Harman, 169-218, Reidel, Dordrecht.
MacWhinney, Brian (1999) “The Emergence of Language from Embodiment,” The
Emergence of Language, ed. by Brian MacWhinney, 213-256, Lawrence
Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ.
MacWhinney, Brian (2002) “The Gradual Emergence of Language,” The Evolution
of Language out of Pre-language, eds. by Talmy Givón and Bertram F. Malle,
233-263. John Benjamins, Amsterdam.
Metzing, Charles and Susan E. Brennan (2003) “When Conceptual Pacts Are
Broken: Partner-specific Effects on the Comprehension of Referring
Expressions,” Journal of Memory and Language 49, 201–213.
Montague, Richard (1970) “Pragmatics and Intensional Logic,” Synthese 22,
68-94.
Nozawa, Hajime and Yoshikata Shibuya (in press) “Komyunikeshon kara Mita
Metafa: Sono Kiban to Doki (Metaphors from a Communicative Perspective:
Their Basis and Motivation),” Metafa Kenkyu no Saizensen (The forefront of
metaphor research), ed. by Takashi Kusumi, Hituzi Syobo, Tokyo.
Palmer, Frank R. (1986) Mood and Modality, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Peirce, Charles S. (1940) The Philosophy of Peirce: Selected Writings, by Justus
Buchler, Harcourt, Brace & World, New York.
Popper, Karl R. (1934/1959) The Logic of Scientific Discovery, revised edition,
1868, Harper and Row, New York.
Posner, Michael I. (1986) “Empirical Studies of Prototypes,” Categorization and
Noun
Classification,
ed.
by
Colette
Craig,
53-61,
John
Benjamins,
Amsterdam.
Posner, Michael I. and Jin Fan (2004) “Attention as an Organ System,” ms.,
University of Oregon.
Premack, David and Guy Woodruff (1978) “Does the Chimpanzee Have a Theory
of Mind?,” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 615-636.
Quillian, M. Ross (1968) “Semantic Memory”, Semantic Information Processing,
ed. by Marvin L. Minsky, 227-270, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Rosch, Eleanor (1973) “Natural Categories,” Cognitive Psychology 4, 328-350.
Rosch, Eleanor (1975) “Cognitive Representations of Semantic Categories,”
Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 104, 192-233.
Russell, Bertrand (1908) “Mathematical Logic as Based on a Theory of Types,”
American Journal of Mathematics 30, 222-262.
Schank,
Roger
and
Robert
Abelson
(1977)
Scripts,
Plans,
Goals,
and
Understanding: An Inquiry into Human Knowledge Structures, Lawrence
Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Schober, Michael F. and Susan E. Brennan (2003) “Processes of Interactive Spoken
Discourse: The Role of the Partner,” Handbook of Discourse Processes, eds.
by Arthur C. Graesser, Morton Ann Gernsbacher, and Susan R. Goldman,
123-164. Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Searle, John R. (1970) Speech Acts, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Shibuya, Yoshikata (2005) Concepts and Constructions: An Ecological Approach
to Adjectives, Doctoral dissertation, University of Manchester.
Shibuya,
Yoshikata
(2006)
“On
Transferred
Epithets:
A
Constructionist
Approach,” Proceedings of the 2006 Seoul International Conference on
Linguistics, 229-238.
Smith, Edward E., Lance J. Rips and Edward J. Shoben (1974) “Semantic Memory
and Psychological Semantics,” The Psychology of Learning and Motivation,
vol.8, ed. by Gordon Bowers, 1-45, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Swinney, David A. (1979) “Lexical Access during Sentence Comprehension:
(Re)consideration of Context Effects,” Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal
Behavior 18, 645-659.
Tomasello, Michael (1995) “Joint Attention as Social Cognition,” Joint Attention:
Its Origins and Role in Development, eds. by Chris Moore and Philip J.
Dunham, 103-130, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ.
Tomasello, Michael (1999) The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition, Harvard
University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Tomasello, Michael (2003) Constructing a Language: A Usage-based Theory of
Language Acquisition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Tomasello, Michel and Patricia J. Brooks (1999) “Early Syntactic Development: A
Construction Grammar Approach,” The Development of Language: Love,
Money and Daily Routines, ed. by Martyn Barrett, 161-190, Psychology Press,
East Sussex.
Whorf, Benjamin L. (1956) Language, Thought and Reality: Collected Writings, by
John B. Carroll, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Wilkes-Gibbs, Deanna and Herbert H. Clark (1992) “Coordinating Beliefs in
Conversation,” Journal of Memory and Cognition 31, 183-194.
Winograd, Terry (1970) A Computer Program for Understanding Natural Language,
Doctoral dissertation, MIT.
National Institute of Information and Communications Technology
3-5 Hikari-dai, Seika-cho
Soraku-gun
Kyoto 619-0289, Japan
e-mail:
[email protected]