Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2010
…
3 pages
1 file
The European Journal of Public Health, 2009
Modern technology has fostered a revolution in communication technologies. Individuals are on the receiving end of more information now than ever before. And that information is increasingly provided by partisan news sources and social media whose journalistic standards are less than optimal. Individuals are called upon to assess the trustworthiness of this information and now with A.I.-generated disinformation making inroads, discernment is more important than ever. Modern media affords consumers the ability to sort through an array of information choices, picking those that tell them what they want to hear. Many individuals respond to information that challenges their beliefs by using the various heuristics and psychological shortcuts (McRaney and Hagen 2011, 268) which are mentioned in this paper. This paper outlines the findings of the social sciences on the phenomenon of denial, in relation to important social policy decisions, such as those related to climate change, which may be made on the basis of politicized, less-than-factual information. The paper also discusses strategies for dealing with denial in its various forms.
Synthese, 2017
There is a robust scientific consensus concerning climate change and evolution. But many people reject these expert views, in favour of beliefs that are strongly at variance with the evidence. It is tempting to try to explain these beliefs by reference to ignorance or irrationality, but those who reject the expert view seem often to be no worse informed or any less rational than the majority of those who accept it. It is also tempting to try to explain these beliefs by reference to epistemic overconfidence. However, this kind of overconfidence is apparently ubiquitous, so by itself it cannot explain the difference between those who accept and those who reject expert views. Instead, I will suggest that the difference is in important part explained by differential patterns of epistemic deference, and these patterns, in turn, are explained by the cues that we use to filter testimony. We rely on cues of benevolence and competence to distinguish reliable from unreliable testifiers, but when debates become deeply politicized, asserting a claim may itself constitute signalling lack of reliability.
Trends in Microbiology, 2012
Evolution, climate change, and vaccination: in these cases and more, scientists, policymakers, and educators are confronted by organized campaigns to spread doubt, denial, and rejection of the scientific community's consensus on central scientific principles. To overcome these threats, scientists not only need to spread scientific knowledge, but must also address the social drivers of science denial.
Studies in history and philosophy of science, 2017
Science denialism poses a serious threat to human health and the long-term sustainability of human civilization. Although it has recently been rather extensively discussed, this discussion has rarely been connected to the extensive literature on pseudoscience and the science-pseudoscience demarcation. This contribution argues that science denialism should be seen as one of the two major forms of pseudoscience, alongside of pseudotheory promotion. A detailed comparison is made between three prominent forms of science denialism, namely relativity theory denialism, evolution denialism, and climate science denialism. Several characteristics are identified that distinguish science denialism from other forms of pseudoscience, in particular its persistent fabrication of fake controversies, the extraordinary male dominance among its activists, and its strong connection with various forms of right-wing politics. It is argued that the scientific response to science denialism has to be conceiv...
2014
Rhetorical patterns of history and science denial: The Holocaust, evolution, and climate change never happened The public sphere has been flooded with denialist arguments that no longer respond but simply deny certain realities, facts, and counter-arguments. The quintessential example of denialism is Holocaust denial, where the events of mass incarceration of Jews (among others) in concentration camps and the genocide committed against them is merely a fabrication. Despite
British Journal of Medical Psychology, 1998
This work is aimed at analysing the motivated reasoning underlying denial of some piece of information. Denial is first distinguished from both repression and biased interpretation; then an analysis is provided of the reasoning devices typical of denial. The rules on which reasoned denial is based are similar to those governing the individual's normal cognitive activity. Reasoned denial is here represented in the form of ifthen implications, where the to-be-denied belief plays the role of a consequence drawn from a given premise. So, in order to deny such a consequence one may either deny its premise, or search an alternative consequence, or search an alternative premise, or deny the very relation of implication, and so on. Each type of reasoning is logically biased, while at the same time psychologically plausible and convincing. A typical feature shared by all the reasoning strategies considered is the identification of 'unproven' with 'false'.
The Epistemology of Fake News (OUP), 2020
Science denialism is a widespread and worrying phenomenon. Rejection of standard scientific theories targets several areas of enquiry. For instance: flat-earth theorists deny basic assumptions of modern physics and astronomy; anti-vaccine supporters oppose compulsory vaccination by casting doubts on the efficacy of vaccines and, sometimes, by linking vaccines to severe pathologies like autism; HIV deniers put into question the very existence of HIV; climate-change deniers downplay the significance of the phenomenon and dispute its anthropogenic causes. The main thesis of this paper is that science denialism brings about an aberrant form of enquiry—that we shall call post-enquiry—in which the epistemic norms governing scientific enquiry are deviated in significant ways. Science denialism doesn’t involve just a rejection of a scientific theory; it also deeply challenges the practice, common within scientific enquiry, of continuously and, to a certain extent, impartially testing research methods, theories, and evidential sources with the aim of improving the accuracy of our theories. In this sense, science denialism brings about a radical deviation of the norms governing the practice of scientific enquiry—a deviation which gives rise to what we shall call a normative aberration. We will offer an in-depth analysis of the epistemic mechanisms underpinning the normative aberration brought about by science denialism. More specifically, we will develop a fine-grained framework to model a variety of normative deviances that can take place in enquiry. By analysing two case studies, we will argue that fake news contributes significantly to shape the epistemic norms operating within science denialism. They in fact play two pivotal roles: first, they are used to cast discredit on a variety of (institutional) sources of evidence in relation to a certain set of phenomena (e.g. whether vaccines are safe for the health); second, they also play a part in building the alternative explanation of the targeted phenomena.
Principia, 2024
In this article, we try to argue, against McIntyre's proposal in How to talk to a science denier, that there is a relevant difference between various forms of science denialism. Specifically, we contend that there is a significant distinction to be made between those forms of denialism which deny the existence of an expert consensus (the model of which is the strategy of the tobacco companies in the 1950s) and those which deny the probatory value of such expert consensus (on the basis, e.g., of conspiracy theories involving scientists). While McIntyre and others advocate for the value of communicating consensus as an effective and perfectly rational strategy against those forms of denialism which deceivingly deny the existence of scientific agreement, we argue that this approach becomes question-begging against those which deny its probatory value. Accordingly, then, we object to McIntyre's characterization that "all science denial is basically the same" and suggest a more nuanced understanding of the phenomenon.
Daimon, 2023
In recent years, several strategies have been proposed to tackle social controversies about topics in which science is settled, among which one of the most influential is that of Elizabeth Anderson, who argues that any lay person with access to the Internet and basic education can reliably assess the acceptability of various claims involving expert knowledge. In particular, the author shows that this procedure can be successfully applied to the case of anthropogenic global warming. In this article we will try to argue why, even if we concede that Anderson's proposal is satisfactory in that particular case, it fails to generalize when applied to other controversies. In this article, we illustrate it with the cases of flat-Eartherism and anti-vaxxerism.
“Daughter Zion.” Pp. 125-34 in Thus Says the LORD: Essays on the Former and Latter Prophets in Honor of Robert R Wilson. Eds. J. J. Ahn. and S. L. Cook. LHBOTS 502. London: T & T Clark, 2009.
Handbook of Social Justice Interventions in Education, 2021
Journal of Computational and Theoretical Nanoscience, 2020
Pertanika Journal of Social Sciences and Humanities
Journal of Gaming and Virtual Worlds, 2017
AGROSAINSTEK: Jurnal Ilmu dan Teknologi Pertanian, 2019
Agricultural Engineering International: The CIGR Journal, 2018
Catalysis Letters, 2019
European Scientific e-Journal, 2022
IOP Conference Series: Materials Science and Engineering, 2018
Work, Employment and Society, 2010
Clinical and Experimental Immunology, 2003