JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL
HISTORY 2 (2019) 3–12
brill.com/saih
Introduction: Framing Bedil,
Arguing the Indo-Persian Self
Sajjad Rizvi
University of Exeter, Exeter, UK
[email protected]
Prashant Keshavmurthy
Institute of Islamic Studies, McGill University, Montreal, Quebec, Canada
[email protected]
What is the self? How does it emerge? What are its constituents? To what extent are our conceptions of the self, our construction of selfhood and personhood tied to specifically culturally conditioned notions of agency, modernity,
literature and politics that arise in Europe? Can there ever be a truly global
approach to the history of the self? It is precisely these questions that animate our endeavour in this volume, to draw upon a specific case study within
a Persianate context—of Bedil Dihlavī—to inform our globalizing discourse
on the self.
There is little doubt that we live in self-obsessed times in which the desire
to live authentically, to be concerned with our particular existence, to consider
ourselves to be good moral agents, to tell our story and recognize ourselves in
other more communally constructed and inclusive stories, seems to be central to live metropolitan lives, perhaps peculiarly in the West. As argued by
Charles Guignon and more famously Charles Taylor, the rise of this self from
the 18th century is tied to some of the values of the Enlightenment and the
bold assertion of the independence of the human self, unfettered by the authorities of God and other political-theological institutions.1 From the need
to find the authentic self in ‘your absolute core’, as self-help works will often
argue in rather emotivist ways—that deliberately violate the notion of the self
that is embedded in a tradition and a community of interpretation as Alasdair
MacIntyre would have it2—to the idea of the possession of the self and the
1 Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of Modern Identity (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1989); Charles Guignon, On Being Authentic (London: Routledge, 2004).
2 Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (London: Duckworth, 1981).
© Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2020 | doi:10.1163/25425552-12340013
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access
4
Rizvi and Keshavmurthy
rejection of any other’s possession over one’s self, the modern worldview of
the self that privileges its desires, wants, experiences and futures over that of
any other, whether individual or a collectivity; modern identity in that sense is
dialogical and conflictual.
Modern selfhood thus is constituted by two elements, the first an introspective turn inward and consequently a need to act in a way that is true to
oneself—consistent with an earlier askesis of the self that reflected the intimate link between will and action or the knowledge of the self and the need
to act accordingly, but distinct in its diagnosis of that self that is the ground
for action. When some individuals and cultures articulate critiques of such a
Western model of the individual, they reflect a sense of a loss of tradition, of a
notion of a fully rounded self whose embodiment is also an expression of its
acculturation and socially embedded reality. The rise of this Enlightenment
self is very much the victory of a thorough-going naturalism in which no
claims to enchantment or that which is beyond the tangible or material can
be countenanced. The liberated self, as Guignon points out, may well lead to
new and more confined forms of control—indeed as Foucault showed through
his notions of governmentality and the apparatus—that are no less pernicious
and reductive than earlier forms of restricting the self through the dictates of
heaven or some other external authority.3
The story of the rise of the self in western cultures takes on three masks
and modes of fashioning. The first concerns the ontology of the self. Is there
such a thing as a self that is a ground for experiences, thoughts and the agencies? Is that self some substantive being that emerges as part of a duality that
is the human, as famously argued by Descartes and more recently by Galen
Strawson?4 Or is it a mere first person perspective and a bundle of experiences that seems to link the phenomenal self, as articulated by Parfit, Gallaher
and others, to some Buddhist notions of no-self?5 Is our self discrete or are
our experiences, awareness, consciousness and mental states part of a wider
stream in a panpsychist world in which, as it were, other minds do not obtain?6
3 Guignon, On Being Authentic, 157–67.
4 Galen Strawson originally in Mental Reality (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1994), and more recently
in Selves (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).
5 Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986); Dan Zahavi,
Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective (Cambridge: MIT Press,
2005); Mark Siderits et al (eds), Self, No Self? Perspectives from Analytical, Phenomenological
& Indian Traditions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).
6 David Chalmers, The Conscious Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996); Barry Dainton,
The Phenomenal Self (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008); Philip Goff, Consciousness and
Fundamental Reality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), although he defends a version
that is named Russellian monism which one might argue is more a form of quasi-physicalist
panpsychism.
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL
HISTORY 2 (2019) 3–12
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access
Introduction: Framing Bedil, Arguing the Indo-Persian Self
5
Where does this self come from? Alain de Libera in his recent major study of
the emergence of the self in Western philosophy ties its origins to the notion
of the persons within the Trinity, especially as enunciated by Augustine and in
subsequent commentators.7 This, of course, makes this history of the self particular to a Christian (and post-Christian) tradition—just as most other philosophers do for slightly different reasons. For such an eminent medievalist who
has engaged with Avicennian and Avveroist ideas on the nature of the human
rational soul—one thinks of Avicenna’s famous suspended person thought experiment (and one need not even stretch to its determining influence upon
Descartes) and Averroes’ monopsychism—this myopia is quite astounding. Or
perhaps it is the need to pick other types of fights, not least against the thorough anti-humanism of much postwar post-structuralist French thought?8
Richard Sorabji’s intellectual history of the self locates its emergence from the
older notion of the soul and the life of the soul, its origins, identity and faculties and its afterlife; the Greek origins of the self are thus quite clear in this
account although at least he engages with some Buddhist notions of the self
and also with Avicenna’s famous thought experiment.9 Nevertheless, what one
notices in the philosophical account of the self in Western philosophy is both
at times a universalizing claim about the category of the human as well as a
culturally embedded and specific set of intellectual trajectories particular to
Europe.
The second mask, that follows from the ontological, is the moral. Once
God was displaced and the moral code given by revelation set aside, the main
question was how to reconstruct morality in the absence of external authority. The old Euthyphro dilemma of deciding whether the source of value lay
in independent human reason or in revelation was decisively answered in favour of the former. Acts could be intrinsically good or bad. While the concern
with moral psychology and character persisted, there was a shift to actions as
expressions of the self and less concern with the self as such. This shift was
7 Alain de Libera, L’invention du sujet moderne (Paris: Vrin, 2015); idem, Archéologie du sujet,
3 volumes (Paris: Vrin, 2010–2014).
8 On this anti-humanism, see the excellent study of Stefanos Geroulanos, An Atheism that is
Not Humanist Emerges in French Thought (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2010).
9 Richard Sorabji, Self: Ancient and Modern Insights about Individuality, Life, and Death
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), especially 222–229, 278–297. Even on the related
idea of human rights—rights that pertain to the category of the human—there is a similar debate that locates its origins either in Christian debates or in the understanding of the
Enlightenment’s category of the person—for the former, see Samuel Moyn, The Last Utopia:
Human Rights in History (Cambridge: The Belknap Press, Harvard, 2010) and for the latter
Lynn Hunt, Inventing Human Rights (New York: Norton, 2007). In either case, human rights
discourse is given an exclusively European pedigree.
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY 2 (2019)
3–12
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access
6
Rizvi and Keshavmurthy
then tied to the emergence of the liberal, atomistic, Enlightenment self with
political values, negative liberty and notions of contractual relationships in
inter-subjective public ethics. The cruder version of this moral self was Francis
Fukuyama’s The End of History and the Last Man published as an opinion piece
in 1989 and then as a book, genuflecting to the Hegelian tradition and Kojève.10
The liberal self was the perfected self at the culmination of history; liberalism is a set of hard fought values against impositions of external authority
and the most perfect form of morality and political theory that the world has
known and hence ought to be universalized. This was not an agonistic liberalism that concerned itself with its internal discontents, its history of violence,
nor with its proximate others such as Islam.11 Nor was it willing to consider
non-Hellenic origins for our practices of liberal democracy. Larry Siedentrop’s
history of the liberal self—the individual—with its hard won values of equality and individual liberty and democracy is concerned with the history of the
West, indeed of Christendom, and is conscious of the fact that not only is the
West and its individuality a unique historical process but Islam, represented in
the hordes invading Europe, represents the very antithesis of the West.12 This
is the Enlightenment as a Graeco-Christian event, a process that culminates
in the liberalism and Protestantism of the present. It could have been called
‘How the West was won’. But there is no problematization of the notion of the
West.13 Andrew Gamble in a recent article argues how the very notion of the
West and its values denotes a universalization of neo-liberalism and of a narrow definition of Anglo-American values, policies and institutions.14 If this was
a truly liberal Western self, it would be more tolerant of dissident selves within
the West as well.
10
11
12
13
14
Francis Fukuyama, ‘The End of History?’ The National Interest 16 (1989): 3–18; idem, The
End of History and the Last Man (New York: Free Press, 1992). Cruder still is Steven Pinker’s
recent Enlightenment Now: The Case for Science, Reason, Humanism and Progress (New
York: Viking, 2018), which has the added advantage of being thin on philosophical and
historical expertise and thick on the dismissal of the agonistic and critical nature of the
humanities.
John Gray, Enlightenment’s Wake (London: Routledge, 1995), and Two Faces of Liberalism
(Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000); Domenico Losurdo, Liberalism: A Counter-History
(London: Verso, 2014); Joseph Massad, Islam in Liberalism (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 2016).
Larry Siedentrop, Inventing the Individual: The Origins of Western Liberalism (London:
Penguin, 2015).
For this, one might look at Georgios Varouxakis, ‘The godfather of occidentality: Auguste
Comte and the idea of the West’, Modern Intellectual History (2017): 1–31, and Rolf Petri, A
Short History of Western Ideology (London: Bloomsbury, 2018).
Andrew Gamble, “The Western Ideology”, Government and Opposition, Volume 44, Issue 1,
2009, 1–19.
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL
HISTORY 2 (2019) 3–12
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access
Introduction: Framing Bedil, Arguing the Indo-Persian Self
7
The third mask is the literary one that concerns the emergence of the self
and the individual in European literatures. Jerrold Seigel ties the idea of the self
in Western Europe since the seventeenth century to processes of literary narration and philosophical introspection.15 As classic ‘intellectual history’, it takes
ideas and expressions seriously and argues for the coherence, consistency and
persistence of the self as a narrative. It is therefore not surprising that the most
narrated and consciously introspective literary form—the novel—might be
tied to the rise of this modern self. This argument is made more categorically
by both Harold Bloom and Stephen Greenblatt, the former through the identification of Shakespeare and the early modern period for the invention of the
individual (indeed the category of the ‘human’) and the latter’s notion of the
revival of classicism and naturalism in the early modern period.16 That intellectual shift then bore literary fruit. A feature of that modern literary self is the
desire to narrate the nation through the self. The rise of national languages and
literatures—as Benedict Anderson argues—is directly connected to the imagined community of the nation and demonstrates not only the construction of
European nations and literatures but also those peoples affected by the colonial experience in which nationalism emerged as a set of elite discourses about
political identity.17 Even there one could point to the secondary and devolved
sense of the novel as expression of self in those non-European contexts, and
Frederic Jameson famously dismissed most such works as thin allegories of the
nation.18 Nevertheless, does this mean that we seek the modern non-Western
self in these ‘national allegories’? Where can we look for global discourses?
The current vogue for the label ‘global’ requires that we not only provincialize some of these discourses of the rise of the modern self in their European
intellectual history but also look for other trajectories of self-narration. It is
precisely in this context that we wish to interrogate the notions of the self and
indeed the modern that can be applied to a pivotal Persian poet of the late
Mughal period, ʿAbd al-Qādir Bedil, whose influence on the modern literary
15
16
17
18
Jerrold Siegel, The Idea of the Self: Thought and Experience in Western Europe since the
Seventeenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).
Harold Bloom, Shakespeare: The Invention of the Human (London: Fourth Estate, 1998),
and Stephen Greenblatt, The Swerve: How the Renaissance Began (Oxford: Bodley Head,
2011).
Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of
Nationalism (London: Verso, 1983).
Frederic Jameson, ‘Third-World literature in the ear of multinational capitalism’, Social
Text 15 (1986): 65–88. For incisive critiques, see Aijaz Ahmad, “Jameson’s rhetoric of otherness and the national allegory”, Social Text 16 (1987): 3–25. Imre Szeman, in fact, argues that Jameson has been misread—see ‘Who’s afraid of national allegory?’ The South
Atlantic Quarterly, 100 (2001): 803–827.
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY 2 (2019)
3–12
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access
8
Rizvi and Keshavmurthy
canon and modalities of literary expression can be gauged through his influence on the literary giants of the modern period such as Ghālib, Iqbāl and
others. Can we engage in global intellectual history and find a multi-layered
approach to modernities and selfhood beyond the West? In the Persianate context, there are already some important precursors. Mohamad Tavakoli-Targhi
has made an argument for Persian modernity and selfhood that is tied to texts
but also histories that differ from the standard trajectory of the Greeks to the
Christians to the Renaissance to the Enlightenment to the present.19 Similarly,
more recently both Rajeev Kinra and Sunil Sharma have considered Mughal
literary practices in India and their modern turn through the narration and
expression of the literary self.20 The search for the self in the intersection of
the Indian and the Persianate is also timely given the recent interventions of
Jonardon Ganeri in Indian philosophy and the centrality of the care of the
self and the art of the self in Indian philosophies across the traditional Vedic
schools and beyond.21 That notion of selfhood was linked to the ‘new reason’
of the early modern period, a new style and discourse of philosophizing.22 It is
therefore the coming together of the Persianate and the Indian in the thought
of Bedil that demands our attention, his narrating of a self that is at once comfortable with Vedic ideas and epics and also at home with the philosophical
thought of Avicenna and the mystical insights of Ibn ʿArabī. But why pick a
poet, even one as philosophically astute as Bedil?
The modernisation of poetic practice across Asia and Africa from the early
twentieth century onward was its increasingly exclusive identification with
lyric understood, as in Europe of the time, as the verbal expression of the
inner states of a biographically particular individual. This identification was
also a conflation—perhaps confusion—of poetic meter with “dated diction
and subject matter”.23 The ghazal is one of only two pre-modern Persianate
poetic forms—the other being the rubāʿī or quatrain—to have survived
this early twentieth century revolution of free verse. It survived (in Persian,
Urdu, Turkish, Pashto and other Persianate languages) because certain of its
practitioners and readers recognized in its poetics elements of what could
19
20
21
22
23
Mohamad Tavakoli-Targhi, Refashioning Iran: Orientalism, Occidentalism and
Historiography (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2001).
Rajeev Kinra, Writing Self, Writing Empire (Oakland: University of California Press, 2015),
and Sunil Sharma, Mughal Arcadia (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2017).
Jonardon Ganeri, The Concealed Art of the Soul (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007),
and Identity as Reasoned Choice (London: Bloomsbury, 2012).
Jonardon Ganeri, The Lost Age of Reason (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).
Timothy Steele, Missing Measures: Modern Poetry and the Revolt Against Meter (University
of Arkansas Press, 1990), 55.
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL
HISTORY 2 (2019) 3–12
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access
Introduction: Framing Bedil, Arguing the Indo-Persian Self
9
be recombined to meet the requirements of the preeminent modern poetic
form—the lyric.
However, it was not the Romantic Wordsworthian model of the lyric that
allowed this survival but the modernist one. Modernism, understood here as
a set of literary and aesthetic practices that foregrounded their own devices
in anti-illusionistic ways, discovered a predecessor in the ghazal. Rather than
the ghazal of the earliest phases of Persian literary history, it was the ghazal
from the sixteenth to eighteenth centuries that formed an aesthetic resource
for Persianate modernism.24 This was because the ghazal of this late phase, as
practiced by poets who identified with the style they called Speaking Anew
(tāza-gūyī, shīva-yi tāza, tarz-i tāza, tarz-i now), foregrounded its inherited conventions in just the sort of playful, exploratory ways that modernism did with
the many pasts it appropriated.
The ghazals of Sāʾeb Tabrīzī (d. 1676) and Bedil Dihlavī (d. 1720) were conspicuous models for such modernist appropriation and were considered stylistic thresholds even in the lifetimes of the two poets. Their poetry and that
of scores of other poets in this style radicalized the reflexivity of early modern
Persian literary culture. That is, it tested and took to new limits the tendency
beginning in the early 1500s to survey and synthesise inherited ghazal conventions in metaphor, syntax and figures of speech.25 As the examples below will
show, poetry in this style folded language upon itself, seldom allowing realist and indexical modes of reference to the world. For this very reason, the
nationalist literary canons of Iran, Afghanistan, Tajikistan, India and Pakistan
took shape over the twentieth century by either repudiating Bedil for his stylistic distance from the Romantic lyric or by appropriating him for his Sufi and
thus, on this interpretation, non-elite and progressive credentials. Modernism,
when it arose in these literary communities, often took the form of iterations
of pre-modern non-realist aesthetics. To study selfhood in Bedil today is, in this
sense, to study poetry made newly legible by various Asian-African modernisms inspired by it; and to return indirectly to the very question of modernist
lyric subjectivity in the postcolonial world.
There is another stake to studying selfhood in Bedil today—that of intellectual history. As his student Ārzū remarked, Bedil’s vast and variegated oeuvre
was put in the service of a single imperative: Sufism.26 Specifically, Bedil be24
25
26
For a survey of the poetics of the ghazal of this period, see Shamsur Rahman Faruqi, Early
Urdu Literary Culture and History (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2001), 145–84.
Paul E. Losensky, Welcoming Fighani: Imitation and Poetic Individuality in the
Safavid-Mughal Ghazal (Costa Mesa: Mazda, 1998).
Sirāj al-Dīn Khān Ārzū, Majmaʿ al-nafāyis: bakhsh-i muʿāṣirān (Tehrān: Anjuman-i āsār-i
mafākhir-i farhangī, 1384/2006), 54.
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY 2 (2019)
3–12
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access
10
Rizvi and Keshavmurthy
longed to one of the many traditions of reading and reformulating Ibn ʿArabī’s
(d. 1240) theist monism. His oeuvre reveals few philosophical-theological ideas
that are original, few that were not already in Ibn ʿArabī or his major glossators.
But this is precisely what allows us to assert the autonomy of poetry as a kind
of thinking from discursive genres of writing in Islamic intellectual history.
Bedil put his innovative poetics in the service, not of new ideas, but of new
ways in which to alert his reader to old ideas from Ibn ʿArabī’s long reception.
In this sense, studying his rhetoric of selfhood presents us with innovations in
the ethical practice by which ideas already familiar from Ibn ʿArabī might be
recognized and realised.
Finally, a third stake impels our interest in selfhood in Bedil. His oeuvre is
culturally bisemic, constituting an acme of around two centuries of efforts in
Persian literary culture to think certain Hindu and Islamic traditions of ethical self-transformation together. This is explicit in his masnavis in which he
embeds tales from the Yogavāsiṣṭha, a popular Sanskrit philosophical text
composed sometime between the 5th and 12th centuries. By the Mughal
period it had become a teaching text for the Advaita Vedānta philosophical
tradition and its ninth century abbreviation, Laghuyogavāsiṣṭha (“Shorter
Yogavāsiṣṭha”), was rendered into Persian multiple times. We know that Bedil
drew two of the tales in his earliest masnavī Muḥīṭ-i aʿẓam and several cosmogonic elements and plot devices in his last masnavi ʿIrfān from one of these
Persian adaptations that was made in 1656 by the Mughal prince Dārā Shukūh,
in both cases extending Dārā’s interest in reading this Sanskrit text in ways that
were amenable to both Vedantic and Akbarian (i.e. Ibn ʿArabī’s) readings.27 But
implicitly and more challengingly, such a bisemic poetics also characterizes
his ghazals. Consider this distich, one of around ten in his ghazal corpus that
uses the metaphor of the peacock’s egg to convey the emergence of a sensorily
rich phenomenal Many from the single and abstract greater reality of the One.
tīghat chih afsūn dāsht kih chun bayża-yi ṭāvūs
gul mīkunad az khāk-i shahīd-i tu shafaq-hā28
A translation conveying only the salient senses of the lexemes might be:
27
28
ʿAbd al-Qādir Bedil, ʿIrfān (9–395) and Muḥīt-i aʿẓam (704–19) in Kulliyāt-i Bedil: jild-i
sevvum (Tehran: Chāpkhānah-yi Payām, 1386/2008). For a study of Bedil’s adaptation of
tales from the Yogavāsiṣṭha, see Hajnalka Kovacs, “The Tavern of the Manifestation of
Realities: the Masnavi Muḥīt-i aʿẓam by Mirzā ʿAbd al-Qādir Bedil (1644–1720)” (University
of Chicago: PhD dissertation, 2013), 112–72.
ʿAbd al-Qādir Bedil, Kulliyāt-i Bedil: Jild-i avval (Tehrān: Chāpkhānah-yi Payām, 1386/
2008), 430.
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL
HISTORY 2 (2019) 3–12
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access
Introduction: Framing Bedil, Arguing the Indo-Persian Self
11
What wonders did your sword work that, like the peacock’s egg,
The horizon’s flush rises from your martyr’s dust?
A translation attentive to the non-salient senses might go:
What wonders did your sunray work that, like the peacock’s egg,
Mercy blossoms from your martyr’s dust?
But the verbal compound gul kardan also means ‘to snuff out’, yielding yet another translation:
What wonders did your sword work that, like the peacock’s egg,
Mercy was snuffed out by your martyr’s dust?
Addressing the divine beloved who is by poetic convention cruel to the loverspeaker, the distich invokes the image of a peacock’s egg lanced by a sword or
a sunray (tīgh means both) and leaking a peacock’s iridescent colours, here
implied in the pluralisation of shafaq which means both “the reddish flush at
dawn or dusk” as well as “affection and mercy”. The shahīd, meaning witness
and martyr at once, witnesses God’s multifarious world only at his martyrdom.
Across his oeuvre, Bedil emphasizes the sensory richness of the phenomenal
world as an aspect of its unreality. Here, creation’s horizon-flush is also God’s
love or mercy for His creation. But equally, it is the end of such mercy for birth
itself, as Bedil often says elsewhere in his oeuvre, is an affliction; and the beloved’s sword was a trimming of creation’s candle till it flared into darkness.
The conspicuous images of this distich cite multiple traditions at once: the
Neoplatonic Illuminationist metaphysics of light that was appropriated by the
Mughals as a political theology; Bhartṛhari’s (6th century CE) Sanskrit philosophical grammar that famously uses the metaphor of the peacock’s egg to
account for how the “word, which in itself has no parts and no sequence, unfolds itself so as to give rise to something that appears to have both, just as the
vital essence (rasa) of a peacock’s egg, which does not possess the variety of
colours of a peacock, unfolds itself so as to give rise to a peacock that does”;29
Khāqānī’s mention of the golden egg of “dawn’s peacock” in one of his qasidahs; and Sāʾeb’s ghazal image of the peacock’s bloody tulip-bright birth from
a steel egg lanced by the blade-like mountaintop. What distinguishes Bedil’s
re-use of this compound metaphor from Khāqānī and Sāʾeb’s is the Akbarian
29
Johannes Bronkhorst, “The Peacock’s Egg: Bhartṛhari on Language and Reality”, Philosophy
East and West, 51. 4 (2001): 474–91.
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY 2 (2019)
3–12
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access
12
Rizvi and Keshavmurthy
topos (mażmūn) of phenomenal multiplicity issuing from a single, greater and
abstract or transcendent reality—the “dust” of Bedil’s distich. That he is consistent in his uses of this compound metaphor for this topos across his ghazals
strengthens the probability that he derived this image from a Persian and possibly Vedantic recension, oral or written, of Bhartṛhari’s vision of unpartitioned
language giving rise to a partitioned reality.
These, then, are three sets of reasons for why we should take an interest
today in questions of selfhood in Bedil’s oeuvre: to revisit the question of nonWestern poetic modernisms by considering their pre-colonial models; to revisit
the place of poetry in Islamic intellectual history; and to study the integration
into the poetics of a single author of long standing Islamicate-Persianate interest in Sanskrit and other Indic language philosophy. But further, we want to
place this interrogation of Bedil into the wider frame of asking the question
about the nature of selfhood and alternative trajectories of the modern self
in non-European contexts that may contribute to a more nuanced and rich
understanding of the history of selfhood, subjectivity, and modern poetics in
intellectual history.
JOURNAL OF SOUTH ASIAN INTELLECTUAL
HISTORY 2 (2019) 3–12
Downloaded from Brill.com10/23/2020 05:11:00PM
via free access