PAUL W E I R I C H
T H E ST. P E T E R S B U R G
GAMBLE
AND RISK
ABSTRACT. Pursuing a line of thought initiated by Maurice AUais (1979), I consider
whether the mean-risk method of decision making introduced by Harry Markowitz
(1959) and other resolves Karl Menger's (1934) version of the St. Petersburg paradox.
I provide a conditional answer to this question. I demonstrate that given certain plausible
assumption about attitudes toward risk, a certain plausible development of the mean-risk
method does resolve the paradox. My chief premiss is roughly that in the St. Petersburg
gamble the small chances for large prizes create big risks.
The St. Petersburg gamble poses a long standing problem for decision rules
that utilize expected valuesJ Here I will investigate the possibility of resolving
the St. Petersburg paradox by adopting the so-called mean-risk method of
evaluating options, espoused, for example, by Harry Markowitz (1959,
Chapter XIII). First I will briefly review the St. Petersburg gamble. Then I
will advance a version of the mean-risk method that evaluates an option using
both the expected or mean utility of the causal consequences of the option
and the utility o f the risk involved in the option. Finally 1 will show that
given certain assumptions about attitudes toward risk, our mean-risk method
of evaluation does indeed resolve the St. Petersburg paradox.
I do not claim to provide a complete resolution of the St. Petersburg
paradox. For my version o f the mean-risk method and my assumptions
about attitudes toward risk are somewhat controversial. My purpose is mainly
to show that the mean-risk method has good prospects for resolving the
paradox. 1 think that my approach to the paradox is sufficiently plausible
and suggestive to do this.
I. THE ST. P E T E R S B U R G GAMBLE
The St. Petersburg gamble awards cash prizes of various amounts depending
on the outcome of a series of tosses of a fair coin. Letting the prizes be
amounts of dollars, the gamble pays 2*n dollars if the first heads of the series
Theory and Decision 17 (1984) 193-202.
9 1984 D. Reidel Publishing Company.
0040-5833/84/0172-0193~01.00.
194
PAUL WEIRICH
occurs on the nth toss. (2*n is 2 raised to the nth power.) The expected
payoff of the gamble is therefore 2;n--~n=l(1/2*n x 2*n), or 2;n=1 1, which is
infinite. However it would be irrational to pay more than a modest sum of
money for the gamble. Evidently, the expected payoff of the gamble is not a
good measure of the value of the gamble.
In order to bring out what I take to be the main problem raised by the
gamble, I assume some additional background conditions. First, I suppose that
there are no obstacles to offering the gamble. In particular, there is a limitless
supply of money for payoffs and a limitless amount of time for coin tosses.
Second, I suppose that there is no barrier to enjoying the large prizes that are
possible. More specifically, the utility of money is unbounded. 2 Third, I
suppose that conditions are ideal for evaluating the gamble. For example,
there are no cognitive limitations that justify neglecting small probabilities.
And fourth, I suppose that the gamble is offered to an individual, not a
group, and that it is offered just one time, not repeatedly. Given these background conditions, the St. Petersburg gamble challenges the method of using
expected payoffs to evaluate options, and not just the application of this
method to real life cases. Thus attempts to resolve the paradox by appealing
to realism - such as the attempts of Leonard Savage (1954), Richard Jeffrey
(1965), Maurice Allais (1979), and Samuel Gorovitz (1979) - are not effective here.
The best known attempts to resolve the St. Petersburg paradox, taken as a
methodological problem, is due to Daniel Bernoulli (1738). He claims that
the expected payoff of the gamble is the wrong quantity to use to evaluate
the gamble. He recommends using the expected utility of the payoff, and
observes that given his law of the diminishing marginal utility of money, the
expected utility of the payoff is finite. However, BernouUi's attempt to
resolve the paradox is ultimately unsatisfactory. As Karl Menger (1934)
points out, if the cash prizes are adjusted for the diminishing marginal utility
of money so that the utility of the prize for no heads until the nth toss
is 2*n, the expected utility of the payoff is infinite. But the value of the
gamble is still not very large. Apparently, the failure to use expected
utilities is not the main source of trouble in evaluating the St. Petersburg
gamble.
The main problem seems to be that the probabilities of the prizes make
the value of the St. Petersburg gamble finite no matter what (finite) values
THE ST. P E T E R S B U R G GAMBLE AND RISK
195
the prizes have. To resolve the problem, one has to find a method of evaluating options that shows why the probabilities have this effect.
II. MEAN-RISK EVALUATION
Maurice AUais has long argued that the expected value of (causal) consequences misevaluates an option because it neglects attitudes toward the risk
involved in the option. Recently he has argued, in particular, that the
expected value of consequences misevaluates the St. Petersburg gamble
because it neglects attitudes toward the risk involved in the gamble (1979,
p. 502). His arguments suggest that we might resolve the St. Petersburg paradox by adopting a method of evaluating options that is more sensitive to
attitudes toward risk than using expected values of consequences of options.
In this section I will advance such a method, and in the next section I will
show that it does indeed correctly evaluate the St. Petersburg gamble given
some plausible assumptions about attitudes toward risk.
The best known risk sensitive method of evaluating options is the meanrisk method of Markowitz (1959) and others. This method takes the value
of an option to be a function of the expected or mean value of its (causal)
consequences and one's attitude toward the risk it involves. I will advance a
version of this mean-risk method of evaluation.
Let us begin by saying a bit about risk. In the mean-risk school risk is
taken broadly so that a risky option is any option that involves an element
of chance, even an option that involves no chance of a loss. Given this broad
sense of risk, which we adopt, aversion to risk is equivalent to aversion to
chance.
Three factors are generally acknowledged to influence the size of the risk
involved in an option. First, there is the dispersion of the values of the
possible consequences of the option. The greater the dispersion, the greater
the risk. (See Allais (1953).) 3 Second, there is the weight of the evidence for
one's assignment of probabilities to the possible states of the world that
determine the consequences of the option. The greater the weight of the
evidence, the smaller the risk. (See Daniel Eilsberg (1961).)And third, there
is one's wealth, or more accurately, one's utility level. The greater one's
utility level, the smaller the risk. (See Ralph Keeney and Howard Raiffa
(1976, Chapter 4).)
196
PAUL WEIRICH
The main task in developing our mean-risk method of evaluating an option
is to find a way of calculating the value of an option from the expected
value of its consequences and an assessment of the risk it involves. I will not
argue in detail for the method that I advance. I hope that it has enough
native plausibility to arouse interest in the kind of resolution of the St.
Petersburg paradox to which it leads.
Our first step is to adopt a uniform criterion of value for assessing possible
consequences and risks. It is convenient to choose utility since one can assign
utilities to both possible consequences and risks. Second, for simplicity, we
restrict our method of evaluation to options where the only factors that
matter are the expected utility of consequences and the utility of the risk
involved. Since satisfaction of the restriction is standardly presumed in discussions of gambles such as the St. Petersburg gamble, the restriction is not
an impediment from our point of view. Third, we assume that the expected
utility of the consequences of an option does not reflect the utility of the
risk involved in the option. This is plausible since the risk involved in the
option is part of the option itself and not a (causal) consequence of the
option. Given the assumption, we do not have to worry about double
counting risk when we combine the expected utility of consequences with
the utility of the risk involved. And fourth, we assume the independence
of the utility of the risk involved in an option and the utilities of the possible
consequences of the option. This assumption is plausible since once the
consequences of an option are obtained, the risk taken in realizing the option
seems to be so much water under the bridge. Given the assumption, we
can obtain the utility of an option by simply adding the expected utility of
its consequences and the utility of the risk it involves.
In virtue of the foregoing, we formulate our mean-risk rule as follows.
Let P stand for probability, U stand for utility, C stand for consequences,
and R stand for risk. Then if sl, s2, 9 9 are mutually exclusive and exhaustive
states of the world that are independent of an option o,
U(o) = ~., P(sn)U(C[o, snl) + U(R[ol). 4
In the St. Petersburg gamble (spg) the dispersion of the utilities of the
possible consequences is large. Given some standard measures of the dispersion, such as the standard deviation, the dispersion is infinite. This large
THE ST. P E T E R S B U R G GAMBLE AND RISK
197
dispersion makes the risk involved in the gamble large. It seems possible
that aversion to the large risk is the cause of the gamble's finite utility. In
particular, although ~ P(Sn)U(C[spg, Sn]) is infinite in Menger's version of the
St. Petersburg gamble, if U(R [spg]) is negatively infinite, then U(spg) may
be finite. To investigate this possibility using our mean-risk method, we will
have to rearrange the mean-risk equation for the St. Petersburg gamble to
avoid addition of infinite factors.
We can do this in the following way. Consider a series of gambles involving
a limited number of coin tosses. For the ruth gamble of the series a fair coin is
tossed exactly rn times. If the first heads comes up on the nth toss, the
gamble pays 2*n dollars. If heads never comes up, the gamble pays nothing.
The St. Petersburg gamble is the limit of this series of gambles. The increase
in risk as one moves from gamble m -- 1 to gamble m can be thought of as
part of the risk involved in the St. Petersburg gamble. One can think of it
as the risk added by the possibility that the first heads will be on the ruth
toss. Let us call it Rm(spg). Analogously, the difference in the utility of the
risk involved in gamble m and gamble m -- 1 can be though of as part of the
utility of the risk involved in the St. Petersburg gamble. One can think of it
as the utility of Rm(spg), i.e., U(Rm[spg]). According to these conventions,
U(R [spg]) = 2; U(Rn [spg]). Hence, associating U(Rn [spg]) with U(C[spg, sn ]),
the mean-risk equation for the St. Petersburg gamble becomes
U(spg) = ~ [1/2*n x U(C[spg, Sn]) +
U(Rn [spg])].
Given aversion to risk, U(Rn [spg]) is negative for eachn. And asn increases,
aversion to risk makes U(Rn[spg]) decrease. If the decrease is very rapid,
1/2*n x U(C[spg, sn])+ U(Rn[spg]) may approach 0 as n increases. And if
it approaches 0 very fast, 2; [1/2*n x U(C[spg, Sn]) + U(Rn[spg])] may be
finite. In this way it is possible for U(spg) to be finite.
IIl. ASSUMPTIONS ABOUT RISK
As we saw in Section I, the problem raised by the St. Petersburg gamble is to
show that the gamble has finite value regardless of the values of possible consequences. Given the mean-risk method of evaluation of Section II, the problem is, more specifically, to show that 2; [1/2*n x U(C[spg, s~ ]) + U(Rn [spg])l
198
PAUL WEIRICH
is finite regardless of the values of U(C[sgp, sad for n = 1, 2 . . . . . I will now
introduce some plausible assumptions about attitudes to risk that lead to
the desired result. Since my goal is just to present a program for resolving the
St. Petersburg paradox, I will not argue for the assumptions in detail.
Let us begin by extending our terminology a little. Consider again the
series of gambles introduced above. The difference between the utility of
gamble m and the utility of gamble rn -- 1 can be though of as part of the
utility of the St. Petersburg gamble. One can think of it as the utility added
by the possibility that the first heads will be on the ruth toss. Let us call it
Um(spg). According to this definition, U(spg) = ~ Un(spg ).
Now let us focus on the relationship for each n between increases in
U(C[spg, Sn]) and increases in Un(spg). As U(C[spg, sn ]) increases, the rate of
increase in Un(spg) for further increases in U(C[spg, Sn]) changes. The instantaneous rate of increase in Un(spg) for a given value of U(C[spg, sn]) is the
sum of the instantaneous rate of increase in 1/2*n x U(C[spg, sn]), or 1/2*n,
and the instantaneous rate of increase in U(Rn[spg]). Because greater stakes
create greater risk, the instantaneous rate of increase in U(Rn [spg]) is negative
given aversion to risk. s So the instantaneous rate of increase in Un(spg) is
less than 1/2*n. Our special assumptions about attitudes to risk take the form
of assumptions about other features of the instantaneous rate of increase
in U.(spg).
The firstassumption is motivated by three considerations. First, it seems
that the greater the stakes, the greater the rate of increase in risk for subsequent increases in the stakes. Hence as U(C[spg, Sn]) increases, the rate
of increase in U(Rn[spg]) drops, and, as a result, the rate of increase in
Un(spg) drops as well. s Second, the inverse of the rate of increase for
1/2*n x U(C[spg, Sn]), viz., -- 1/2*n, is a lower bound for the rate of increase
for U(Rn[spg]). And it seems that it is the least lower bound. That is, it
seems that the rate of increase in U(Rn[spg]) approaches - 1 / 2 * n as
U(C[spg, sn ]) approaches infinity so that decreases in U(Rn [spg]) eventually
come close to cancelling increases in U(C[spg, Sn]). Hence it seems that the
rate of increase in Un(spg) approaches 0 as U(C[spg, sn ]) approaches infinity.
Third, it seems that aversion to risk puts a limit on the attractiveness of
gambles. That is, more picturesquely, there is some number of birds in hand
worth more than any number of birds in the bush. Hence it seems that
after a point, not matter how much U(C[spg, sn]) increases, there is no
THE ST. PETERSBURG GAMBLE AND RISK
199
appreciable increase in Un(spg). In other words, it seems that after a point,
the area under the rate curve from 0 to U(C[spg, Sn]) is not appreciably
greater as U(C[spg, sn ]) increases.
The rate of
increase in
Un (spg)
1/2"n
0
~-Z'- U(C [spg, Sn ])
Put more precisely, it seems that the integral of the rate function is finite.
Now functions of U(C[spg, Sn]) of the form 1/2*n x k* -- U(C[spg, sn]),
where k > 1, decrease from 1/2*n to 0 and have finite integrals. So bearing
the foregoing in mind, some such function will provide an upper bound for
the rate function. This leads us to our first assumption.
(1)
For each n there is a k > 1 such that the rate of increase in
Un(spg) with respect to U(C[spg, Sn]) is less than 1/2*n x k*-U(C[spg, s, ]).
Our second assumption is motivated by two considerations. First, it seems
that as n increases and the probability that the first heads will be on the
nth toss decreases, the drop in the rate of increase in U(Rn [spg]) from 0 to
-- I/2*n will be more rapid. Next, since smaller probabilities of success make
ventures riskier, it seems that as n gets very large, and the probability that the
first heads will be on the nth toss gets very small, the rate of increase in
U(R, [spg]) will approach --1/2*n almost immediately. This leads to the
following assumption.
(2)
As n increases, the smallest k satisfying the condition in assumption (1) increases without limit.
From our two assumptions we obtain the desired result about the St.
Petersburg gamble straightforwardly. By (1), Un(spg ) is less than the integral
of 1/2*n x k*-- U(C[spg, Sn]) with respect to U(C[spg, Sn]). Hence by
200
PAUL W E I R I C H
calculus, Un(spg)< 1/2*n x 1~Ink. By (2), there is some N such that for
n > N , k > e , where e is the base of natural logarithms. Hence, for n > N ,
Un(spg)< 1/2*n. It follows by numerical analysis that Z~=~ Un(spg)<
zn=~n=N1/2*n < 1. This entails that Z Un(spg) is finite. Therefore, U(spg) is
finite regardless of the values for all n of U(C[spg, sn] ). In this way our
assumptions provide a resolution of the St. Petersburg paradox.
IV. C O N C L U D I N G R E M A R K S
The assumptions of the preceding section are similar to ones that other
authors have made in attempting to resolve the St. Petersburg paradox.
Assumption (1), that the rate of increase in Un(spg) is bounded by an
exponential function, is similar to Savage's (1954) assumption that the
utility of prizes is bounded. However assumption (1) is more plausible
since aversion to risk provides a reasonable explanation of assumption (1),
whereas the assumption that the utility of prizes is bounded seems ad hoc.
Assumption (2), that the rate of increase in Un(spg) becomes negligible
almost immediately for large values of n, is similar to Gorovitz's (1979)
assumption that small probabilities do not count. However assumption (2)
is more plausible since it seems that small probabilities cannot be discounted
entirely.
In the light of such comparisons, I conclude that we have made progress with the St. Petersburg paradox, even if our assumptions have not
been sufficiently supported for us to claim to have completely resolved
the paradox.
NOTES
i Recently, the problem has been one of the foci of discussions about rationality
triggered by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky (1974 and 1979). Contra Kahneman
and Tversky, Lola Lopes (1982) and Henry Kyburg (1983), for example, defend the
rationality of people who offer versions of the St Petersburg gamble in violation of
the canon to decide according to the expected values of (causal) consequences.
2 Given standard utility theory in the tradition of John Von Neumann and Oscar
Morgenstern (1944), typical preferences concerning the St. Petersburg gamble entail
that the utility of money is bounded. Hence this supposition requires some revision of
standard utility theory. There are many revisions that would suffice. For the sake of
definiteness, I will assume the revision proposed by Maurice Allais (1953).
T H E ST. P E T E R S B U R G
GAMBLE AND RISK
201
3 This assumes that there is a natural way of partitioning the possible consequences, and
that the dispersion is measured with respect to the natural partition of consequences.
Characterizing the natural partition of consequences is, of course, a difficult task. But we
need not undertake it here since it is clear what the natural partition is for the St.
Petersburg gamble.
4 One might conjecture that the sum on the right hand side of the equation is equal to
the expected value of some utility encompassing both the utility of the consequences of
o and the utility of the risk involved in o, perhaps the expected value of the utility o f o
itself, i.e., E P(sn)U(o,sn). If this conjecture were correct, our mean-risk method of
evaluation would be compatible with an expected utility method of evaluation. I will
not explore this issue here, however.
s I am ignoring some local aberrations that occur when U(C[spg, sn]) is close to
U(C[spg, Sm]) for some m not equal to n. These local abberrations do not affect the
plausibility of the assumptions introduced in this section.
REFERENCES
Allais, Maurice: 1953, 'Fondements d'une th~orie positive des choix comportant un
risque et critique des postulats et axioms de l'~cole Am~ricalne', t~conom~trie,
CNRS, Paris, vol. 40, translated in Maurlce AUais and Ole Hagen (eds.), Expected
Utility Hypothesis and the Allais Paradox, Reidel, D ordrecht, 1979.
Allals, Maurice: 1979. 'The So-Called Allals Paradox and Rational Decisions Under
Uncertainty', Expected Utility Hypothesis and the Allais Paradox.
Bernoulli, Daniel: 1738, 'Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk',
translated by Louise Sommer in Econometrica 22 (1954), 22-36.
Ellsberg, Daniel: 1961, 'Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms', Quarterly Journal
of Economics 7 5 , 6 4 3 - 6 6 9 .
Gorovitz, Samuel: 1979, 'The St. Petersburg Puzzle', Expected Utility Hypothesis and
the Allais Paradox.
Jeffrey, Richard: 1965, The Logic of Decision, McGraw-Hill, New York.
Kahneman, Daniel and Tversky, Amos: 1979, 'Prospect Theory', Econometrica 47~
263-291.
Keeney, Ralph and Ralffa, Howard: 1976, Decisions with Multiple Ob/ectives, Wiley,
New York.
Kyberg, Henry: 1983, 'Rational Belief', The Behavorial and Brain Sciences 6~ 2 3 1 245.
Lopes, Lola: 1982, 'Decision Making in the Short Run', Journal of Experimental
Psychology 7 , 3 7 7 - 3 8 5 .
Markowitz, Harry: 1959, Portfolio Theory, Yale UP, New Haven.
Menger, Karl: 1934, 'Das Unsicherheitsmoment in der Wertlehre', Zeitschrift far
National6konomie.
Savage, Leonard: 1954, The Foundations of Statistics, Wiley, New York; 2rid edn,
Dover, New York, 1972.
Tversky, Amos and Kahneman, Daniel: 1974, 'Judgment Under Uncertainty', Science
185, 1124-1131.
202
PAUL WEIRICH
Von Neumann, John and Morgenstern, Oscar: 1944, Theory of Games and Economic
Behavior, Princeton UP, Princeton; 2rid ed., 1947.
Department of Philosophy,
The University of Rochester,
River Campus Station,
Rochester, N Y 1462 7,
U.S.A.