Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
4 pages
1 file
Ingold's ideas frighten with those of cognitive sciences, which presuppose machines that they process information, store and manipulate symbolic representations in a language of thought on the basis of a program that constitutes its syntactic rules. Cognitive psychology concerns the theory of complementarity, which sees man as the sum of body, mind and culture. Ingold instead emphasizes that the individual is rooted in the environment through local practices, as concrete matrixes of a set of specific abilities (skills), understood as a knowing to be silent and incorporated. Shortly, the systems that concretely generate expert activity are not circled as in a hardware but are assembled in a flexible way. According to the author, the genotype understood as a specific model independent of the context does not exist. This means that the forms and the capacities of human beings and other organisms are ultimately attributable not to inheritance genetics but to the generative potentialities of the evolutionary system, that is the whole system of relationships constituted by the presence of the organism, including its genes, in a particular environment. Every generation, the apprentice learns by means of his being situated in his contexts in which the what to do and what to pay attention to when dealing with certain tasks is shown. But nevertheless, this is he who
Lo Sguardo - Rivista di filosofia, 2023
This article aims to propose a new look on the distinction between mind, environment and culture. While the first of these has mostly been understood as an interior and individual dimension of experience both by common sense and modern philosophy, an evolutionary and ecological standpoint could help us rethink the practices, information and technologies forming the niches of Homo sapiens societies both as the ecological horizon of our actions and as collective and shared minds possessing an external and partially detached existence. Every human being participates in these collective 'exteriorities', extends his body through tools, organizes his behaviour with respect to others and absorbs the social context of his technologies, languages, institutions, values in a partial and unique standpoint, that is an individual 'interiority'.
Oxford University Press eBooks, 2007
ABSTRAKT Předmětem studie je analýza současného stavu konceptu kultury v antropologii, a to v kontextu konstatované krize jak antropologie jako holistické vědy o člověku, tak konceptu kultury jako klíčového epistemologického nástroje v antropologii. Zvláštní pozornost je věnována analýze evolučních teorií kultury, které jsou formulovány v tzv. evolučních sociálních vědách. Autor diskutuje biokulturologii jako výzkumnou strategii, která umožní dialog mezi společenskými a přírodními vědami, a to zejména s ohledem na evoluční teorie kultury, které jsou stále předmětem diskuzí a sporů. V závěru studie věnuje autor pozornost původu pojmů příroda a kultura a formuluje tezi, že spor o evoluční teorie kultury má kořeny právě v historických kořenech uvedených pojmů.
1. Attempts to develop evolutionary models of social processes have been the testing ground for many proposals as to how understand the relation between the social sciences and biology. One important discussion that goes back to Darwin and his contemporaries concerns the extent to which we can give an evolutionary model of culture. 1 Nowadays we are familiar with a wide variety of such models. There are models that start with a paradigmatic example of how biological models, relying on specific mechanisms of biological inheritance, can explain what is considered a paradigmatically socially structured behavior, and then the solution is extrapolated to other modes of social organization. The sociobiology of E.O. Wilson is a well-known example of this sort of approach. Other approaches identify what is considered the main mechanism for the social transmission of beliefs. Memetics, for example, refers usually to approaches based on the assumption that imitation is the main mechanism of transmission. And Boyd and Richerson have developed a theory based on the explanatory resources of Darwinian "population thinking" (Boyd and . As in the case of Memetics, Boyd and Richerson assume that an evolutionary model of culture requires the identification of units of cultural replication that are units of information stored in human brains. It follows that an explanation of the way this storage takes place (and changes) is sufficient to explain culture.
Palgrave Macmillan US eBooks, 2005
Earth is the planet where the most complex creativity of which we are aware has taken place; and on this Earth, the most complex creative thing known to us is the human mind. John Maynard Smith and Eörs Szathmáry analyze "the major transitions in evolution" with the resulting complexity, asking, "how and why this complexity has increased in the course of evolution." "Our thesis is that the increase has depended on a small number of major transitions in the way in which genetic information is transmitted between generations." Critical innovations have included "the origin of the genetic code itself," "the origin of eukaryotes from prokaryotes," "meiotic sex," "multicellular life," "animal societies," and especially "the emergence of human language with a universal grammar and unlimited semantic representation," this last innovation making possible human culture (1995, pp. 3, 14). Maynard Smith, the dean of theoretical biologists, finds that each of these innovative levels is surprising, not scientifically predictable on the basis of the biological precedents. He and his colleague are deeply impressed with the cybernetic and, eventually, cognitive character of what has taken place in natural history, expressed so strikingly in the human mind. What makes the critical difference in evolutionary history is increase in the information possibility space, which is not something inherent in the precursor materials, nor in the evolutionary system, nor something for which biology has an evident explanation, although all these events, when they happen, are retrospectively interpretable in biological categories-at least all except perhaps culture are. The biological explanation is modestly incomplete, recognizing the importance of the genesis of new information channels. Since we humans find ourselves at the apex of these complex events, it becomes us ? as far as we can, to figure out what to make of ourselves, both who we are and where we are. We proceed with an analysis of nature and culture, adapted versus adaptable minds, genes making human brains, human minds making brains, and the spirited human self and our self-transcendence, THE HUMAN COMPLEX 11 At such levels of complexity, we will often be in "over our heads"; but one conclusion is inescapable: what is in our heads is as startling as anything else yet known in the universe. We will be left wondering how far what is going on in our heads is a key, at cosmological and metaphysical levels, to what is going on over our heads. Nature and Culture _________________ Both "nature" and "culture" have multiple layers of meaning. If one is a metaphysical naturalist, nature is all that there is, and so all things in culturecomputers, artificial limbs, or presidential elections-are natural. Nature has no contrast class. At another level, however, culture contrasts with nature; and we need to be adequately discriminating about the real differences between them. Animals, much less plants, do not form cumulative transmissible cultures. Information in wild nature travels intergenerationally largely on genes; information in human culture travels neurally as persons are educated into transmissible cultures. The determinants of animal and plant behavior are never anthropological, political, economic, technological, scientific, philosophical, ethical, or religious. The intellectual and social heritage of past generations, lived out in the present, reformed and transmitted to the next generation, is regularly decisive in culture. Culture, by Margaret Mead's account, is "the systematic body of learned behavior which is transmitted from parents to children" (1989, p. 11). 1 Culture, according to Edward B. Tyler's classic definition, is "that complex whole which includes knowledge, belief, art, morals, law, custom, and any other capabilities and habits acquired by man as a member of society" (1903, p. 1). Animal ethologists have complained that such accounts of culture are too anthropocentric (indeed chauvinistic!) and need to be more inclusive of animals (de Waal, 1999). Partly because of new animal behaviors observed, but mostly by enlarging (or, if you like, shrinking) the definition, it has become fashionable to claim that animals have culture. Robert Boyd and Peter J. Richerson revise the definition: "Culture is information capable of affecting individuals' phenotypes which they acquire from other conspecifics by teaching or imitation" (1985, p, 33). The addition of "imitation" greatly expands and simultaneously dilutes what counts as culture. By this account, there is culture when apes "ape" each other, but also culture in horses and dogs, beavers, rats-wherever animals imitate the behaviors of parents and conspecifics. Geese, with a genetic tendency to migrate, learn the route by following others; warblers, with a tendency to sing, learn to sing better when they hear others. Whales and dolphins communicate by copying the noises they hear from others; this vocal imitation constitutes culture at sea (Rendell and Whitehead 2001). But with culture extending from people to warblers, it has become a nondiscriminating category for the concerns we wish to analyze here.
… of the Cognitive …
Most work in the cognitive sciences focuses on the manner in which an individual device -- be it a mind, a brain, or a computer -- processes various kinds of information. Cognitive psychology in particular is primarily concerned with individual thought and behavior. Individuals ...
2008
Le Laboratoire d'ANalyse Cognitive de l'Information (LANCI) effectue des recherches sur le traitement cognitif de l'information. La recherche fondamentale porte sur les multiples conceptions de l'information. Elle s'intéresse plus particulièrement aux modèles cognitifs de la classification et de la catégorisation, tant dans une perspective symbolique que connexionniste. La recherche appliquée explore les technologies informatiques qui manipulent l'information. Le territoire privilégié est celui du texte. La recherche est de nature interdisciplinaire. Elle en appelle à la philosophie, à l'informatique, à la linguistique et à la psychologie.
Cuadernos de Neuropsicología / Panamerican Journal of Neuropsychology, 2021
The psychobiological mechanisms by which the genus Homo developed its cognitive abilities have focused on evolutionary genetics and the action of its particular social and cultural environment, but their concrete articulation is still far from being known. This study analyses how the culture of human niches takes on an especially important role in the cognitive development of human populations. The cultural and social mechanisms used to achieve the development of their cognitive capacities and even the beginning of new ones would be exaptation, co-evolution, and emergence. As an example of this evolutionary form, an analysis of causal cognition is proposed.
Empires and Gods: The Role of Religions in Imperial History, 2024
Cadernos do CEOM, 2023
Business Coaching, 2020
Congress proceedings, ICEB 6, 2022
Baroque Belgrade - Transformation 1717-1739; Institute of Archaeology-Belgrade City Museum, Belgrade, 2019
Marine Ecology in a Changing World, 2013
Best Evid Chin Edu, 2020
Ataturk Universitesi Sosyal Bilimler Dergisi, 2003
SOCIUS, 2018
KONA Powder and Particle Journal, 2011
Journal of Clinical Medicine
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 1992
The Journal of neuroscience : the official journal of the Society for Neuroscience, 2017
Journal of Visualized Experiments, 2014