9(1)/2021
Received: July 10, 2020. Accepted January 2, 2021
ISSN 2300-7648 (print) / ISSN 2353-5636 (online)
DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/SetF.2021.006
Transhumanist Immortality: Understanding the Dream as
a Nightmare
Transhumanist Immortality:
Understanding the Dream
as a Nightmare
PABLO GARCÍA- BARRANQUERO
Universidad de Málaga
[email protected]
ORCID: 0000-0001-6472-5703
Abstract. This paper offers new arguments to reject the alleged dream of immortality.
In order to do this, I firstly introduce an amendment to Michael Hauskeller’s approach
of the “immortalist fallacy”. I argue that the conclusion “we (normally) do not want
to live forever” does not follow from the premise “we (normally) do not want to die”.
Next, I propose the philosophical turn from “normally” to “under these circumstances”
to resolve this logical error. Then, I review strong philosophical critiques of this transhumanist purpose of immortality in the literature. There are two key questions related
to the possibility of fulfilling this goal: the hard problem of consciousness and the
personal identity dilemma. Finally, I defend a specific type of indefinite life and justify
that it is more desirable than our current limited life.
Keywords: Immortalist fallacy; immortality; indefinite life; transhumanism.
Introduction
An optimistic vision of future technology
Let me confess an almost daily concern: I do not want to die today. I am
confident that I will not want to die tomorrow either. My anxiety about
dying is based on my fear of the moment in which my conscious life will
9 ( 1 ) / 2 0 2 1 , 1 7 7–1 9 6
177
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
end. I cannot imagine what it would be like if I ceased to exist. This fear is
an emotion which invades my mind and I can hardly suppress. Once dead,
I will not be able to enjoy admiring the sunset in Oriental Bay, reading The
Divine Comedy, or watching Blade Runner 2049 again. This concern is not
mine alone: it drives the philosophy of existentialists, and much of both
Eastern and Western religious thought.1 My anxiety may have deep-seated
evolutionary origins, and it even seems to be shared by other animals. Will
there ever be a solution to this common fear?
The advancement of science and technology in the past half-century is
opening up unprecedented horizons. The world is transforming, everything
is changing—not only in terms of the way we live, but also in terms of how
long. With science and technology increasingly pushing back the frontier of
death, is it possible that the “death of death” will be fulfilled in the distant
future? (Wood 2016). There is a distinguished group of thinkers who proclaim
the advent of the Singularity, where the evolution of Homo sapiens will be
directed by ourselves. The Singularity refers to the point in time when all
the advances in science and technology will cause unimaginable biological,
cultural, and social changes, impossible to predict or understand before
this event. In the Singularity, there will be no distinction between humans
and machines, or between physical and virtual world. Raymond Kurzweil
(2005, Ch. 1) suggests that we think about the way in which technology has
evolved over the past 100 years and project it into the future: there will be
an exponential growth of diverse forms of technological progress after which
the meaning of human life will be radically different. In this future, we will
conquer the fear of an inevitable death by eliminating the inevitability of
death itself. Many of the defenders of the Singularity typically endorse some
version of transhumanism (H+).
1
I do not deny that this debate would be radically different for an atheist compared to
someone who believes in an afterlife. For the former, death is the end of our life. For the
latter, death is only the end of our biological and earthly life before entering another
plane of existence. My arguments hold for any rational person, regardless of their spiritual beliefs or lack thereof.
178
9(1)/2021
T R A N S H U M A N I S T I M M O RTA L I T Y: U N D E R S TA N D I N G T H E D R E A M A S A N I G H T M A R E
H+ is a philosophical, scientific-technological, and social way of thinking
about the transformation of human beings. It provides opportunities by
developing emerging technologies to extraordinarily enhance ourselves.2
H+ will enable our society to be healthier, longer-lived, and smarter, capable
of selecting from a wide range of enhanced attributes and new traits. Nick
Bostrom (2008) or Anders Sandberg (2014), among others, present possible
advantages and disadvantages—that is to say, benefits and risks—of these
emerging technologies that could overcome traditional conditions in
cognition, longevity, or physical performance. Their premise is that human
beings at present do not enjoy the best of all possible states of existence.
Thus, the human condition is questioned, it is no longer sacrosanct as some
essentialists have defended (Kass 2003; Sandel 2007). On the basis of their
optimistic vision of future technology, they want to free human beings from
our biological chains, including death. Transhumanists justify this vision
based on the assurance that technology is growing faster than we could
have ever imagined, and it offers a new range of infinite possibilities and
powers. In other words, today’s science-fiction is a glimpse at tomorrow’s
reality. But what kind of world does technology have in store for us?
Digital immortality: The transhumanist dream
In a philosophical paper on life extension, Larry Temkin (2008) wonders
whether living longer is inherently living better. In this work, I begin with
the claim that I want to live longer, regardless of whether that means living
better than I do now. This starting point raises a significantly different
question: “Does wanting to live longer entail wanting to live forever?” (Agar
2010, Ch. 6; Gems 2003; Williams 1973).
From the perspective of H+, living longer is the first step towards the
ultimate goal of conquering death. This perspective envisions no limits
to humanity’s ability for continuous enhancement. Furthermore, the de-
2
There is an extensive academic literature about the ideas defended by transhumanists
in which the arguments for and against are exhaustively reviewed (Agar 2010; Diéguez
2017). See more briefly, Asla (2019); Hauskeller (2019).
9(1)/2021
179
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
struction of the biosphere will not be an obstacle to our survival, if the
form of immortality that the Singularity offers is not biological. For some
transhumanists, while the body is simply “jelly” (Moravec 1989, 117), our
minds may be uploaded into a computer (which is eternally functional)
and, in this way, achieve digital immortality. Transhumanists claim that
our hardware, like the human body, will be disposable. What will remain
in perpetuity is our software, even enhanced by future technology. We will
be able to transfer our ideas or memories into virtual world in which we
will live better than we live now. David J. Chalmers explains (destructive)
mind uploading as follows:
One possible form involves serial sectioning. Here one freezes a brain, and
proceeds to analyze its structure layer-by-layer. In each layer one records the
distribution of neurons and other relevant components, along with the character
of their interconnections. One then loads all this information into a computer
model that includes an accurate simulation of neural behavior and dynamics.
The result might be an emulation of the original brain (2010, 42).
H+ (implicitly) defends (destructive) mind uploading because the biological
chains are entirety gone by this point. The idea of digital immortality is
a form of life extension in which we would live forever and never die. The
result might look like an avatar behaving, thinking, and reacting like a person
on the basis of that person’s digital archive. In this line, Kurzweil (2005, Ch.
7) considers that digital immortality is forever as long as someone takes
care of the information. In a very strict sense, even this immortality would
not be absolute. Some may claim that this transhumanist purpose of immortality would never be possible. Imagine that our digital selves are erased
by a computer virus or the heat-death of the universe. However, I approach
digital immortality as if it were a possibility for complete immortality: life
without an end, with “life” no longer being tied to biological limitations.
In contrast to digital immortality, indefinite life is a form of life extension
in which humans have already cured aging but they can die from external
causes, such as accidents, dehydration, or murder, among other possibilities
(Glannon 2002, 343–344). Life is (potentially) forever, in biological terms.
180
9(1)/2021
T R A N S H U M A N I S T I M M O RTA L I T Y: U N D E R S TA N D I N G T H E D R E A M A S A N I G H T M A R E
Even though life extension technology offers us the possibility to live and
longer, even forever, we would remain vulnerable to the possibility for life
to end, as “life” is tethered to biology.3
Immortality is a hypothetical scenario for which imagination is necessary because of the absolute lack of scientific-technological evidence.
Accordingly, immortality is neither an expected nor a realistic result of
treating aging. What is more, an extreme longevity, similar to Methuselah’s
life, does not imply that one can live forever. The goal of the rest of this
paper is to reject the alleged dream of immortality. My structure will be
as follows: in section 2, I will introduce an amendment to the immortalist
fallacy (IF), inspired by Michael Hauskeller’s approach (2013). In section 3,
I will review strong philosophical critiques of this transhumanist purpose
of immortality in the literature: the hard problem of consciousness and
the personal identity dilemma. Finally, in section 4, I will conclude the
paper by suggesting a specific type of indefinite life derived from section 1
and justified by section 2 that it could be more desirable than our current
limited life. Thus, I will argue that this does not only change our concept
of “death”, but also our concept of “life”.
1. The immortalist fallacy: An amendment
to Hauskeller’s approach
1.1. A logical error?
Everyone wants to enjoy as much time as possible with their loved ones, as
long as their cognitive and physical capacities are tolerable, broadly speaking.
3
Nicholas Agar makes this distinction between a zero and non-zero immortality: “There’s
actually a big difference between immortality and negligible senescence. Whereas a negligible senescence being is likely to have a longer life span than a senescing one, an immortal being is guaranteed to. Immortal beings have a zero probability of dying over any
future period of time. Negligible senescent beings have, in contrast, a nonzero probability
of dying with each year that passes. The difference between them and us as we are now
is that this probability does not increase” (2010, 113). Broadly speaking, we refer to the
same distinction. However, I prefer to call it “indefinite life” because I argue that death is
possible beyond the cure of aging.
9(1)/2021
181
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
Many of us want more time for other purposes as well, like reading classic
novels, visiting exotic countries, and watching cult movies, among other
things. From this perspective, living longer could be better for humans.4
Many transhumanists doubt that there is anyone who rejects the dream of
immortality (Bostrom 2008). Now, I discuss that most radical view of the
life extension possibilities: living forever and never die.
Transhumanists argue that any significant extension of life we would
turn us into better humans, in the sense that we would be better off than
we are now. They assume that we appreciate being alive (life is good) and
that we do not want to die (death is bad). Bostrom uses these premises to
construct his main argument: (1) people “normally” appreciate being alive;
(2) accordingly, they “normally” desire not to die; (3) they also have an
(implicit) desire to have their life spans indefinitely extended; and (4) thus,
they normally desire to live (potentially) forever (2008, 113–118). Bernard
Williams, in his famous seminar chapter on immortality, stated a similar
conclusion: “[W]anting something itself gives one a reason for avoiding
death” (2000: 59). I assume a moderate position in this debate, but in order
to establish it I first have to answer these two questions: (1) “Do we never
want to die?”; and (2) “Do we want to live forever?”. A useful starting point
is Hauskeller’s approach (2013), which argues that Bostrom (2008) commits
what the calls the IF in making his four-step arguments:
[T]his argument, plausible as it may seem at first sight, is misleading, because
it is based on the premise that we (normally) do not want to die, which is then
taken to imply that we do want live forever (i.e. have an implicit desire for
indefinite life extension). Yet this conclusion is in fact not warranted. If you ask
people whether they want to die, most of them will indeed deny it. However,
if you as, the same people whether they want to go on living forever, you may
find that most will deny this too (…). It is quite possible that a person does not
want to die and still does not want to live forever. On the face of it his seems
4
In this paper, I assume a welfarist concept of living better. This concept entails several
changes in anthropology, morality, or psychology, which “increase the chances of leading
a good life in the relevant set of circumstances” (Savulescu et al. 2011, 16). I do not believe
that the meaning of life can be considered by religious or traditional doctrines.
182
9(1)/2021
T R A N S H U M A N I S T I M M O RTA L I T Y: U N D E R S TA N D I N G T H E D R E A M A S A N I G H T M A R E
to be a blatant contradiction. How can we at the same time not want to die and
not want to live forever? Obviously, if you do not die you will live forever and
the only way to avoid living forever is to die (2013, 89–90).
Hauskeller uses his critique of Bostrom’s argument to reject the alleged
dream of immortality. He argues that there is no logical entailment between
the claim that “people (normally) do not want to die” and “people (normally)
want to live forever”. In my view, the key to dismantling Bostrom’s argument
is the qualifier of the premise: “normally”. My position does not only serve
as an amendment to Hauskeller’s approach, but also as a distinct framework
to reject the dream of immortality of transhumanists.
That a person does not “normally” want to die does not imply that
the same person does not ever want to die (i.e. in the future). To clarify
Hauskeller’s approach, I propose a philosophical turn from “normally” to
“under these circumstances”. What does “normal” mean for Bostrom or
Hauskeller in the IF? They do not clarify whether it is “ideally”, “generally”,
“most of the time”, or “most people”. There are many possible meanings
which would substantially change the argument. I understand “under these
circumstances” as the anthropological, historical, psychological, and social
context according to which every individual makes a claim about the IF. I do
not want to die “under these circumstances” perhaps something that we all
think by living a limited life now implies an implicit desire to live forever
under these circumstances. This implicit desire to live forever is conditioned
by two reasons: (1) I want to be alive today; (2) and I do not want to die
today. I respond to the IF in my present. I cannot know what I would say in
my future under other circumstances.5 The fear of death justifies my desire
to live indefinitely, more than anything else.
Hauskeller thinks about the IF as a mortal human being, like any of
us. Moreover, Bostrom and Kurzweil remain human beings, beyond their
optimistic vision of future technology. They remain locked in the chains
5
With other words, I can say that it is incoherent to have any opinion about the attractiveness of living forever, or even of living to 1000, or only 100, because it is axiomatic that
whether one wants to die now (or soon) depends on one’s perceived quality of life at the
time and in the subsequent future. I owe this comment to Aubrey de Grey.
9(1)/2021
183
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
of biology. Death is the “inevitable destiny” of transhumanists if their
dream does not come true. All of us are in the same scenario and we all
project a future world that spans beyond our current limited life. The
substantial difference between us is the new world that we want now.
Thus, this reflection depends strongly on the context of every individual.
I take a metaphysical step from Hauskeller’s approach since I consider two
possible scenarios in the IF: (a) the people being described are mortal;
(b) the people being described are already immortal. For me, Hauskeller’s
question: “How can we at the same time not want to die and not want to
live forever?” (2013, 90) should be substituted by the statement: “We can
under different circumstances not want to die and not want to live forever”.
I propose dissolving the contradiction by showing different responses in
these opposing scenarios. We can desire or reject the dream of immortality,
but we do it under current circumstances, according to which our life is
limited and death is possible.
In the first scenario, in which we are mortals, we are delaying the hands
of the clock. Time is against us and death will come eventually. In the second
scenario, in which we are already immortal, we would live without having
to look at the clock. The clock does not exist anymore. In the first scenario,
death is the “inevitable destiny” because mortal beings are all condemned
to die, no matter how long we are able to delay our end. In the second scenario, death could be a “salvation” if it were the only way to move beyond
our temporal existence. Otherwise, life would be a prison from which we
could never escape. According to Hauskeller’s approach, death would not
always be something bad.
1.2. Is death always bad?
I have amended Hauskeller’s approach to the IF to suggest that where he
qualifies his claims with “normally”, it would be better to say “under these
circumstances”. Now, I evaluate the concept of “death” from my previous
division between mortals and immortals. I follow Hauskeller’s approach.
As he says:
184
9(1)/2021
T R A N S H U M A N I S T I M M O RTA L I T Y: U N D E R S TA N D I N G T H E D R E A M A S A N I G H T M A R E
Yet even if we should decide that death is indeed an evil, non-death (or living
forever) need not be a good. From the fact that a person does not want to die
it follows neither that (a) death is an evil to them, nor that (b) living forever
is a good to them. If this were a valid argument, which it is not, then we could
just as easily conclude from the fact that a person does not want to live forever,
that, to them, (a) life is an evil and (b) dying is a good (2013, 99).
Like Hauskeller, I strongly argue that the desire to live forever does not the
imply desire not to die. The philosophical turn from “normally” to “under
these circumstances” also shows how death could be “bad” or “good”
depending on the context of every individual. For many people, the case
a persistent vegetative state is an example of a situation in which death
might be considered a “salvation” rather than an “inevitable destiny”. There
is nothing in the desire not to die that infers that living forever is an inherently desire. The question is conditioned by the type of life that we would
live.6 Following Hauskeller’s approach, but incorporating my amendment,
I present the concept of death in the IF:
1. That a person does not want to die does not imply that either (a) death is
bad to this person, or that (b) living forever is a good to this person. That
a person does not want to die implies that this person wants to avoid it
under a specific set of circumstances. That a person does not want to die
implies that this person to be alive under these circumstances, but not that
this person wishes to be immortal.
2. That a person does not want to live forever does not imply that either (a) life
is bad to this person, or that (b) death is a good to this person. That a person
does not want to live forever implies that this person wants to die under
a specific set of circumstances. That a person does not want to live forever
implies that this person to be alive today, but not forever.
6
In the previous case the decisive reason was health. There are examples where the most
influential factors are the culture and time. Hara-kiri, is the classic Japanese ritual suicide
by disembowelment. Samurai voluntarily stuck a dagger into their stomachs so as not to
fall into the hands of the enemy or to atone for dishonor, or for a failure.
9(1)/2021
185
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
Death is not essentially “bad” or “good”, “undesirable” or “desirable”—
and either is life. I have proposed that whether death is seen as an “inevitable destiny” or as a “salvation” depends entirely on the circumstances
of a person’s life. Someone who is happy with the good experiences that
life can provide may have compelling reasons to want to keep having those
experiences indefinitely—or at least until they no longer seem so good.
However, someone could say that death could be avoided is only if we
wished to (there would always be a way out). In this vein, I will explain
what I call the obligatory nature of immortality in H+. Taking this as
a baseline, I will defend my own concept of death related to the IF. Similarly,
I will present my concept of “life” according to this obligatory nature of
immortality in section 4. First, the Singularity is the point in time at which
all the advances in technology will change the world as we know it today.
This event will affect all humans without exception (Kurzweil 2005, Ch. 1).
In other words, transhumanists seem to assume that all these changes will
be universally accepted. Second, digital immortality through that the (destructive) mind uploading would guarantee one could live forever and never
die. Would technological suicide be possible? For these transhumanists, it
is rather strange to end life when we have conquered death technologically
after centuries. Kurzweil says that if we take care of the information, we
will never die. Could we totally cease to exist after our upload? Someone
could also consider that this possibility implies that the only true form of
immortality would be an indefinite life. According to the above, I justify
what I have introduced previously in relation to the IF: (1) death is the
“inevitable destiny” in our current limited life; and (2) death would be the
“salvation” in immortality only if it were possible. And transhumanists seem
to disagree with one scenario in which death could be optional.
I have started my discussion with this question: “Do you never want to
die?”. Rather, we should ask: “Do you never want to die under the current
circumstances?”. Along this line, John Harris says: “Most people fear death,
and the prospect of personal extended life-span is likely to be welcomed”
(2000: 59). Absolutely. Transhumanists promise to live forever because
they know that the fear of death would entail the acceptance of any type
186
9(1)/2021
T R A N S H U M A N I S T I M M O RTA L I T Y: U N D E R S TA N D I N G T H E D R E A M A S A N I G H T M A R E
of life. Anything would be better than nothing for them. These authors
consider that the IF to be meaningless, and conceptualize only a single
scenario in which they conquer death and live forever. Thereby, I have
already presented a possible solution to the first question at the beginning
of this section: “Do we not want to die?”. No. Broadly speaking, and under
tolerable circumstances, today we want to be alive. Tomorrow life itself
might show us a world that we may prefer to escape through death. One of
the most difficulties is to predict how events in our lives will unfold from
one day to the next.
Having shown the logical error from the perspective of individual desire,
I take one metaphysical step. If wanting to live forever were our desire,
would (destructive) mind uploading be possible? Would future technology
solve all the challenges of digital immortality?
2. Serious arguments to reject digital immortality
2.1. Strong philosophical critiques
I have presented my amendment to Hauskeller’s approach to the IF (section 2). Now, I consider it useful to review the critiques that of the dream of
immortality that are raised in the literature. Transhumanists have already
shown all the (possible) benefits that (destructive) mind uploading would
have—and how it would improve people’s lives in all their aspects. For instance: (1) people could create multiple avatars of themselves to accomplish
their goals; (2) people could enjoy unimaginable pleasures for our senses;
or (3) people could save an emergency copy of their profiles. However,
I point out different problems that this type of “life” could pose for us in
the distant future. Everything is speculative, but I also think a scenario not
as desirable as the one proposed by transhumanists. From this perspective,
it is not only about the individual desire to want to live forever but also
about whether this desire can be fulfilled technologically. Transhumanists
imagine what they would like to happen. Where there is a will, there is
(not always) a way. Perhaps this (great) difficulty is what really concerns
9(1)/2021
187
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
transhumanists. Hence, I argue that there are strong reasons to show that
the transhumanist goal is not an easy one.
By “strong” critiques, I understand those that directly undermine the very
concept of digital immortality. Not surprisingly, there are serious difficulties
in meeting this goal from a technological perspective. Here, I follow the
ideas of Chalmers (2010) who argues that there are two key issues in the
(destructive) mind uploading debate: the hard problem of consciousness and
the personal identity dilemma. Therefore, my rejection of digital immortality
is related to these two questions: (1) “Will an uploaded version of me be
conscious?”; and (2) “Will I, upon uploading, still be me?”. The concept of
mind that Bostrom (2008) or Kurzweil (2005) defend is quite widely discussed
in neuroscience and philosophy. They assume that the mind is something
analogous to software, to an information pattern that can be transferred
to different hardware and function correctly. Consciousness would be one
of those functions, such as the ability of my laptop to monitor its own
functionality, to distinguish self from non-self by identifying computer
viruses, and to understand voice commands. However, many thinkers show
that this is a reduced version of who we are and that we hardly know what
consciousness is—besides, we are not certain at all that it is everything that
makes us who we are. Even supposing that consciousness were not a problem,
the personal identity dilemma would still be present. For instance, if I could
make copies of my mind, or I could transfer it to a silicon device, nothing
would guarantee me that “he”, “she”, or “that” is myself (Hopkins 2012;
Pigliucci 2014). Agar shows this dilemma in relation to different possible
scenarios after the uploading. In short:
There are two possible consequences of uploading. The advocates of strong AI
think that the computers we are uploaded into are capable of conscious thought.
If Kurzweil is right, you will not only survive, but your powers of thought will
be radically enhanced. If the doubters are right, then uploading is a nothing
more than a novel way to commit suicide (2010, 63).
We would try to avoid death by uploading our minds into a machine, but
we could die in the process. If this is the case, then (destructive) mind
188
9(1)/2021
T R A N S H U M A N I S T I M M O RTA L I T Y: U N D E R S TA N D I N G T H E D R E A M A S A N I G H T M A R E
uploading would just be a sophisticated way to end our lives. Even more,
I suggest that we are afraid of death but we are not aware that we could face an
even more fearful future. The most frightening monsters are not dragons or
witches; they are those that we cannot yet imagine. There is a third possible
scenario besides mind uploading way to end our lives or the transhumanist
success: we have survived but neither us nor the world around us is what
we really wanted. In this vein, João Pedro de Magalhães proposes a similar
idea when he says that:
Due to the both creative and destructive nature of the human mind, the dilemma
is whether the technological singularity will be a bridge to wonderland or if it
will mean the end of human civilization (2004, 85).
This nightmare of immortality characterizes the possible scenario triggered
resulting from H+ in which we would be obliged to accept not only all the
technological changes of the Singularity, but also the impossibility of ceasing
to exist. After the Singularity, the type of life that we would live would be
radically different from our current ones, and according to H+, these new
lives would be much better than anything that we can dream of. Now, we
imagine our lives projected towards a vague, abstract idea of finality, knowing
we are mortal (cf. Kitcher 2014, 99–100). A serious for everyone to consider
would be: “Do you know what mind uploading would be to say yes to the
transhumanist dream?”.
Typically, only the two extreme options of the debate are presented
for consideration by the wider society: essentialist mortality (Kass 2003)
and digital immortality (Kurzweil 2005). However, it is possible that most
people unknowingly hold a moderate position like the one that Hauskeller
and I have described previously. Based on my amendment to the IF, they
would want to keep living indefinitely as long as they can live under their
current circumstances. They would not want to live forever because they
can imagine themselves under other circumstances in which they would
rather die. The probability of seeing paradise on Earth is the same as that
of seeing hell. What is more, they are not two sides of a coin since we do
not even know whether there are two or more options.
9(1)/2021
189
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
Hauskeller (2013, 100) thinks that many people want to live forever simply because they imagine a radically different future. From my perspective,
there is an assumption that in the future we will live better than now. H+
seems to consider only the success of (destructive) mind uploading, but it is
also possible that life in the future could be more unbearable anything we
could ever imagine. I would like to live a life in which I recognized myself.
Kurzweil (2005) states that life will be better than now after the Singularity.
We will have a brain and body beyond the limits of biology. He wants our
existence to be as we need it and want it at any time. We will be the ones to
create ourselves. Some human beings would want to have a different avatar
every day; others would reject being able to imagine that they are angels and
that they were born with feathered wings on their backs. Transhumanists
want immortality, but they are mortal. They, and all of us, will be released
from their biological chains after the explosion of the Singularity. They just
need to be patient.7 However, what type of life we would live without death?
3. The defense of a specific type of indefinite life
3.1. Changing the concepts of “death” and “life”
In section 3, I have presented strong critiques to reject the dream of
immortality. Now, I will defend my own approach. One of the question
which started my argumentation was: “Do you want to live forever?”. In the
literature, this question has also appeared as follows: “Is more life always
better?” (Gems 2003).
I say that it depends on many factors. Following my argument that
the desire for ongoing life is context-dependent, most people will want
to keep living if the set of circumstances is ideal for them; for instance, if
they can continue to live with their loves ones, and under cognitively and
7
The transhumanist perspective actually claims to want this vision of the future, rather
than merely starting that “this is the inevitable future towards which we are headed”. The
prediction of a certain future does not necessarily imply that this is what one wants. For
many others, there is a very large gap between the future that may lie ahead and what
they would really want.
190
9(1)/2021
T R A N S H U M A N I S T I M M O RTA L I T Y: U N D E R S TA N D I N G T H E D R E A M A S A N I G H T M A R E
physically tolerable conditions. Upon assessing my current circumstances,
today I would answer: yes, more life is indeed better. Nevertheless, I am sure
that there could be a time when my circumstances change so much that
I would not want to continue to endure them. If a digital immortal existence
were ultimately boring or oppressive, I might desire to end it rather than
endure it forever. I defend that the answer to the question will always be
both personal and temporary. And it is difficult, if not impossible, for the
person who wants to live to understand the perspective of a person for whom
death is desirable. At the same time, no one knows for sure whether they
will ever change their desire to live, or to die. The only question that I can
possible answer is whether I myself would prefer to keep living rather die
under the current circumstances. From my view, absolutely. I do not want
to die today. I probably will not want to die tomorrow either. The fear of
death is present in my current limited life. Does this imply my desire to live
forever? Not really, as I will explain below.
The question is not only about the value of changing the concept of
“death” but also the concept of “life”. Not being able to die, one of the
greatest milestones that humans dream of, implies a radical modification
of what we understand by our existence as humans. H+ promises to evade
the “inevitable destiny” of death through an optimistic vision of future
technology. However, what would be the price? According to my amendment
to Hauskeller’s approach, we think about overcoming death from our finitude,
but we also project the type of life we would like to live in the future. Now,
if we were immortal would we want a similar life to the current limited one,
in terms of our interests and values? It seems that, in one way or another,
we would like to prolong a state of joy to infinity. We do not want what we
do not know, what is beyond the limits of our mind, although this may be
better. Our concept of “life” depends on who we are—it is the view from
where we stand, so to speak. In other words, if we were not Homo sapiens, or
even something similar, it is entirely possible that the concept of “life” would
not exist—or at least, not in its current form. Enjoying certain activities or
dreaming of a better future is specifically human. One question this raise is
whether as a transhuman we would retain the same desire for immortality
9(1)/2021
191
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
that we have as humans. H+ takes one metaphysical step further by detaching
itself from the biological body. If we cannot achieve the desired digital
immortality, there is no reason to be uploaded. We would like to admire the
sunset at Oriental Bay, read The Divine Comedy, or, watch Blade Runner 2049
once again. In this dystopian movie, Ryan Gosling walks through a desolate
and demolished planet Earth where all our omens have come true. However,
this very pessimistic future is imaginable for us. Thus far, we project a life
that is similar to the one that we live today. All of these activities would be
possible in a virtual world as long as the upload is a success of H+.
I argue that it is impossible to know whether I would carry out all of these
activities in a way that is similar to what I want under current circumstances.
I would like to keep living if and only if the type of life that I would lead
were not radically different from the current limited life that I enjoy today.
Now, would I want my mind to be in a virtual world or something like that?
Kurzweil (2005, Ch. 7) considers that the meaning of life is to appreciate
and create a kind of knowledge which improves itself to direct us towards
a higher “order”. Therefore, death is a tragedy if a person’s information is
lost in time. True immortality would only be possible if we uploaded our
mind into a computer. I do not claim that meaning of the life as envisioned
by H+ is the desire of all humans. Where they say “we”, they should say “I”,
or “my colleagues”.
I defend a change in the concepts of “death” and “life” as follows: if X
is death and Y is life, humans only worry about X without thinking that
Y changes when X disappears. The interdependence between X and Y is
so strong that we cannot imagine a world without X in which Y is still Y.
A world without X in which Y is still Y is impossible because X does not exist
anymore. Therefore, a world without X forces us to think of a world where
Y becomes Y’. Transhumanists promise us a world without X in which Y’
will be radically different from Y. From the TH perspective, we should not
fear Y’ for two reasons: (1) we would accept Y’ since it is the consequence
of the conquest of X; and (2) we would accept that Y’ is not simply the
consequence of the conquest of X, but also the possibility of living better
than our current limited Y. However, if Y’ does not practically resemble Y at
192
9(1)/2021
T R A N S H U M A N I S T I M M O RTA L I T Y: U N D E R S TA N D I N G T H E D R E A M A S A N I G H T M A R E
all, is it worth conquering X? Most of society might want Y without X, but
is it known that Y’ will in no way resemble our Y? Is it possible to imagine
a life without death? Answering David Gems’ question, one could say that
a longer life is not always a better life.
3.2. What do I want now?
Now, let me confess what my dream is. I imagine a life free of aging and
other diseases that limit my activities, plans, projects, and time with my
loved ones; a life in which I would (potentially) live forever because I want
to keep living indefinitely. However, I cannot give an answer as to how many
years I would like to live. 10 more years? 100 more years? Maybe, I would
say, a little more for now. There are open horizons of possibilities which
I would still like to explore. If you ask me in a distant future, in which the
transhumanist purpose has come true, my answer would surely be different.
I am afraid to close my eyes and not be able to open them once again, but
what if, in a dystopian scenario, I was afraid of never being able to close
them and always having to continue looking at a terrifying world? I imagine
that nobody finds it desirable to die for what is known as external causes:
accidents, dehydration, or murder, among other possibilities. I, under current
circumstances, would not want to die from any of the above. I convert into
a virtue what for H+ is a sign of weakness: the biological body. The fact of
having it gives us the possibility to die both when we do not want and when
we want to. One could desire life extension without desiring the immortality.
On some occasions, one must sacrifice something to obtain something else.
Following my previous reflection, I fear X but I am aware that without
X, I could not keep Y, at least as I know Y today. I do not defend a static Y
because my circumstances are changing day after day. It is a Y recognized
by me and those around me. I do not accept an unknown Y’ just to avoid
X. What is more, I do not give up X to have an “eternal” Y’. Therefore, I do
not accept what H+ defends: the desirability of uploading our minds into
a computer. First, this desire is quite improbable to achieve in the future.
Second, if it were real, this type of existence implies something unknown
9(1)/2021
193
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
that many people would not necessarily want. It is not, in other words, an
inherent desirability.
This specific type of indefinite life that I think humans should seek lies
between our current limited life and the dream of immortality: we would
be assuming that it would be optional to want to keep living, that death
would be avoidable for a certain time, and that it would be reversible, since
we would have a “salvation”. We could continue adding years of life, but, on
the other hand, we would be unless there are external causes the ones who
we decide if we want to die. It seems to me, that this might indeed be the
central point of the argument: what does one want, to live forever? No. To
die? Also no. What is desired is the ability to decide to end.
My current concern is not wanting to die. Death is the end of my life.
My desire is not to face the moment in which I will lose everything. I do not
want to live forever and I reject the transhumanist dream. How can I accept
what I can hardly imagine? If it were possible, I would want to live better
as long as my life had a very similar meaning as it has today. These are my
conditions, my set of circumstances, under which I accept the idea of an
unending life. Everything would change under other circumstances. This
is what I have called the specific type of indefinite life.
I believe that I have answered the IF discussed by Hauskeller. Nevertheless, I need some more time to think about it.
Concluding remarks
In this paper, I have analyzed and discussed the transhumanist dream of
immortality. First, I have suggested an amendment to Hauskeller’s approach
of the IF. The key to disambiguating the IF is the imprecise premise “normally”. I propose a philosophical turn towards context-dependency, so that the
desire to live is considered to be dependent on the circumstances of every
individual. The value of death is related to these circumstances. Second,
I have reviewed strong critiques against mind uploading in the literature.
Two great challenges about mind uploading were presented by Chalmers
(2010): the problem of consciousness and the personal identity dilemma.
194
9(1)/2021
T R A N S H U M A N I S T I M M O RTA L I T Y: U N D E R S TA N D I N G T H E D R E A M A S A N I G H T M A R E
According to the above, digital immortality could be a nightmare for humans.
Death would be a “salvation” when we do not want to live forever, if and only
if this were possible. Otherwise, the immortality will no longer be so much
of a dream. Finally, I have argued in favor of a specific indefinite life which
is more desirable than our current limited life. I would like to enjoy a life in
which I would recognize myself, my loved ones, and the world where I live.
Would there be anything better than deciding when is a good time to die?
Once those things are no longer possible, my current fear of death should
fade into acceptance and I would be released from this fear.
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Nicholas Agar, Suzanne Day, Aubrey de Grey, Antonio
Diéguez, Walter Glannon, Alejandro González Jiménez-Peña, Eric Juengst,
Alfredo Marcos, Andrés Moya, Andrés Ortigosa, and Jon Rueda, who read
previous versions of this paper and made helpful suggestions. I owe Antonio
Yuste-Ginel the idea of modifying the qualifier “normally”. This idea was
the catalyst for the rest of the paper. Additionally, I thank two anonymous
reviewers of Scientia et Fides and the editor for their comments on earlier
drafts. The research activity of Pablo García-Barranquero was supported by
MECD-FPU 2014/02041 and Contrato Puente para Doctores de la Universidad
de Málaga.
References
Agar, Nicholas. 2010. Humanity’s End: Why We Should Reject Radical Enhancement.
Cambridge, MA: MIT University Press.
Asla, Mariano. 2019. “On the limits, imperfections and evils of the human condition.
Biological improvement from a thomistic perspective.” Scientia et Fides 7(2):
77–95. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/SetF.2019.017
Bostrom, Nick. 2008. “Why I want to be a posthuman when I grow up.” In Medical
Enhancement and Posthumanity, edited by Berth Gordijn., and Ruth Chadwick,
107–136. Dordrecht: Springer.
Chalmers, David J. 2010. “The singularity: A philosophical analysis.” Journal of
Consciousness Studies 17: 7–65.
9(1)/2021
195
PA B LO G A RC Í A- B A R R A N Q U E RO
de Magalhães, João P. 2004. “Alice’s dilemma.” Futures 36(1): 85–89.
Diéguez, Antonio. 2017. Transhumanismo: La búsqueda tecnológica del mejoramiento
humano. Barcelona: Herder Editorial.
Gems, David. 2003. “Is more life always better?: The new biology of aging and the
meaning of life.” Hastings Center Report 33(4): 31–39.
Glannon, Walter. 2002. “Extending the human life span.” The Journal of Medicine
and Philosophy 27(3): 339–354.
Harris, John. 2000. “Intimations of immortality.” Science 288(5463): 59.
Hauskeller, Michael. 2013. Better Humans?: Understanding the Enhancement Project.
Durham, NC: Routledge.
Hauskeller, Michael. 2019. “Ephemeroi-human vulnerability, transhumanism, and
the meaning of life.” Scientia et Fides 7(2): 9–21. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/
SetF.2019.013
Hopkins, Patrick D. 2012. “Why uploading will not work, or, the ghosts haunting
transhumanism.” International Journal of Machine Consciousness 4(01): 229–243.
Kass, Leon. 2003. Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness. New
York: Harper Collins.
Kitcher, Philip. 2014. Life after Faith. The Case for Secular Humanism. New Haven:
Yale University Press.
Kurzweil, Raymond. 2005. The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology.
New York: Penguin.
Moravec, Hans. 1989. Mind Children. Harvard: Harvard University Press.
Pigliucci, Massimo. 2014. “Mind Uploading: A philosophical counter-analysis”. In
Intelligence Unbound: Future of Uploaded and Machine Minds, edited by Russel
Blackford., and Damien Broderick, 119–130. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Sandberg, Anders. 2014. “Transhumanism and the meaning of life.” In Religion and
Transhumanism: The Unknown Future of Human Enhancement, edited by Tracy
Trothen., and Calvin Mercer, 3–22. Oxford: Praeger.
Sandel, Michael J. 2007. The Case against Perfection. Harvard: Harvard University Press.
Savulescu, Julian., Anders Sandberg, and Guy Kahane. 2011. “Enhancement and
well-being.” In Enhancing Human Capacities, edited by Julian Savulescu., Ruud
ter Meulen, and Guy Kahane, 3–18. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
Temkin, Larry. 2008. “Is living longer living better?” Journal of Applied Philosophy,
25(3): 193–210.
Williams, Bernard. 1973. “The Makropoulos Case: Reflections on the Tedium of
Immortality.” Problems of the Self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wood, David. 2016. The Abolition of Aging. The Forthcoming Radical Extension of
Healthy Human Longevity. London: Delta Wisdom.
196
9(1)/2021