Ver en Español
Search Mises.org
MISES STORE
BLOG
MISES WIRE
BOOKS
PODCAST
VIDEO
EVENTS
BEGINNERS
MISES WIRE
✉
SUPPORT MISES
GRADUATE PROGRAM
GET NEWS AND ARTICLES
IN YOUR INBOX
A
A
GO
JOIN OR RENEW TODAY
WHAT IS MISES WIRE?
Mises Wire offers contemporary news and opinion
through the lens of Austrian economics and libertarian
political economy.
Home | Wire | Why Postmodernism Is Incompatible with a Politics of Li…
Submitting articles to Mises Wire
Why Postmodernism Is Incompatible with a Politics of Liberty
Reprints, Permissions & Copyrights
TAGS Philosophy and Methodology, Political Theory
The views expressed on Mises Wire and mises.org are
04/05/2021 • Michael Rectenwald
not necessarily those of the Mises Institute.
Several months ago, I debated Thaddeus Russell on The Tom Woods
Show. The proposition debated was “Postmodern philosophy is
compatible with a politics of individual liberty.” Thaddeus defended
the proposition and I opposed it. Here, I want to flesh out some of
the points I made in the debate, adding more context than I could
26 COMMENTS
LEE ESTO EN ESPAÑOL
MOST POPULAR WIRE ARTICLES
marshal under the constraints of the format. For better or worse, this requires a somewhat deep dive into
postmodern ideas.
Biden and Janet Yellen Are Pushing a Global
Postmodernism, I argue, is incompatible with liberty, first because it sees the individual as a mere product, as
constructed by language, social factors, and so on. As such, postmodernism effectively denies selfdetermination and individual agency. Second, the cultural obsession with social identity that is current today
derives from the social constructivism of postmodern philosophy. Such social constructivism further denies
Minimum Tax Rate. The EU Is Very Pleased.
Ryan McMaken
Globalists know that so long as sovereign states have
the ability to set their own tax rates, regimes are
tempted to engage in “tax competition” in order to
individual agency. The very concept of truth, meanwhile, is denied in favor of subjective belief. For reasons
attract capital. The cure to this “problem” is a global
discussed below, the denial of the concept of truth is anathema to liberty.
minimum tax rate.
Thaddeus Russell takes postmodernism’s “anything goes” epistemological subjectivism, skepticism, and
idealism for epistemic “humility.” That is, because postmodernism eschews or denies “truth” and suggests that
there are merely different “narratives” that pass for truth, it allows for people to escape from the truth claims
that others, like the state, would impose on them. Its rejection of metanarratives is liberational and Russell
takes this as an invocation of freedom.
Major League Baseball Punishes Georgians for
the Acts of a Handful of Politicians Antón
Chamberlin
Major League Baseball's boycott of Georgia only makes
any sense at all if we conflate every single Georgia
resident with the regime itself. But in the real world the
claim that "we are the government" has always been
But this is a mistake. As I argued in Springtime for Snowflakes:
nonsense.
Once beliefs are unconstrained by the object world … the possibility for assuming
The Economic Effects of Pandemics: An
Austrian Analysis Jesús Huerta de Soto
a pretense of infallibility becomes almost irresistible, especially when the requisite
How do recurrent cycles of boom and recession
power is available to support such beliefs. In fact, given its willy-nilly determination
compare to isolated crises caused by extraordinary
of truth and reality on the basis of beliefs alone, philosophical and social idealism
phenomena?
necessarily becomes dogmatic, authoritarian, anti-rational, and effectively
February Money-Supply Growth Hit Yet
Another All-Time High. Ryan McMaken
religious.
During February 2021, year-over-year growth in the
money supply was 39.1 percent. That makes February
the eleventh month of remarkably high growth in the
I mean that when coupled with the premium that Michel Foucault, Jean François Lyotard, and others place on
wake of unprecedented quantitative easing and
power, when everything is a power struggle, the lack of objective constraints, the lack of belief in “truth,” or
"stimulus."
any criteria for the judgment of facts, opens us up to the arbitrary imposition of beliefs—to authoritarianism.
Europe's Vaccine Programs Are about as
When “my truth” becomes as good or better than any objective truth, or any attempts to approach truth,
Successful as Their Lockdowns Ryan
when “lived experience” trumps facts, then, when one has the requisite power, one can impose one’s truth
McMaken
claims with apparent impunity. There is nothing to push back against belief. When objective criteria are
The EU has long claimed vaccine procurement is a top
eliminated, there is no court of appeal—other than authority. The ideal of objectivity, always asymptotically
priority. But even by Brussels's own standards,
approached, should be the court of appeal, but it is thrown out in advance by postmodernism. So,
Brussels's central-planning schemes have failed to
postmodernism resembles nothing more than it does the religious creeds that Russell apparently deplores.
deliver yet again.
We see this playing in the social justice movement. And, contrary to what Russell maintains—that social
justice has nothing to do with postmodernism—social justice ideology adopts the postmodern epistemology,
MEET THE WRITER
and this adoption has consequences. Take transgenderism for example. When belief is unmoored from
observation, and when such unmoored belief is institutionalized as it is today, it leads to the abolition of
others’ rights, including the right to make statements about observable facts. One is compelled to
Michael Rectenwald
acknowledge the self-described genders of believers and to use their self-assigned pronouns, or else. If one
Michael Rectenwald was a
denies the self-declared gender of one’s child, one may lose custody, or may even be thrown in jail. Similarly,
professor of liberal studies at New
critical race theory, which derives its epistemology from postmodernism, posits “lived experience” above all
York University (retired).
other criteria. Statistics, historical evidence, etc., are of no importance. “Stories” become the only valid
evidence, and such stories are unfalsifiable. When coupled with state and institutional power, such unmoored
The Great Reset, Part V: Woke Ideology
belief becomes dictatorial. Believe my lived experience, or else. You must take me at my word. You must
How would a reset of the mass mind come to pass that
accept my unfalsifiable stories.
would allow for the many elements of the Great Reset
to be put...
In Explaining Postmodernism, Stephen Hicks has a related but different explanation. He suggests that the
The Great Reset, Part II: Corporate Socialism
postmodern epistemology is a cover for the authoritarianism of postmodernism. With its extreme
The aims of the WEF are not to plan every aspect of
epistemological subjectivism and skepticism, the postmodern epistemology allows postmodernists to deny
production and thus to direct all individual activity.
socialism’s historical failures, while maintaining its ethos and goals. As Hicks puts it, “Postmodernism is the
Rather,...
academic far Left’s epistemological strategy for responding to the crisis caused by the failures of socialism in
theory and in practice.” This would account for the authoritarianism of such postmodernists as the literary
critic Stanley Fish, who in his most recent book, The First, argues for the curtailment of First Amendment
rights, including the elimination of religious expression in the public square and the elimination of speech
that others find offensive or harmful. If given power, Fish would no doubt impose such sanctions. Thus,
Camille Paglia is right in calling Fish a “totalitarian Tinkerbell.” While Hicks’s argument has merit, it doesn’t
explain the connection between the authoritarianism and the epistemology, except as an incidental
MEET OUR WIRE CONTRIBUTORS
relationship.
Robert Blumen
My explanation, as I have said, is that epistemological subjectivism, idealism, and relativism are intrinsically
connected to authoritarianism. Take the case of Lysenkoism in the Soviet Union, for example. Despite the
Robert Blumen is a software
claim that Marxism is materialist and objective, Lysenkoism was an example of philosophical idealism wielded
engineer and podcast editor. Send
by the state. The neo-Lamarckian creed became state policy and led to widespread famine and the death of
him email.
millions, as well as one of the worst witch hunts in the history of science. Lysenkoism underscores the danger
MORE
of denying our best science. There was a better biological science at the time—Mendelian genetics coupled
with the Darwinian model of natural selection. Agreement with this better science could have saved millions
of lives. The authoritarianism of unmoored belief led to famine and persecution.
In the debate, Russell suggested that I was antilibertarian because I referred to “objective constraints on
discourse.” But I did not refer to “objective constraints on discourse.” I referred to objective constraints, period. I
didn’t thereby suggest that states could impose constraints on discourse with impunity. I meant that the
material world imposes constraints on us. We deny these constraints at our own peril.
My second main point concerned Russell’s crediting postmodernism with the gains of liberation movements
like feminism, civil rights, etc. “Postmodernism allows people to escape the social constructs that contain
them,” Thaddeus’s story goes. But feminism, for one, doesn’t need postmodernism, and it never did. Further, it
would be much better off without it.
Feminism preceded postmodernism by decades, if not centuries. Mary Wollstonecraft, for example, argued
effectively for the expansion of women's rights in A Vindication of the Rights of Woman in 1792. And
Wollstonecraft wrote very much in the Enlightenment, modernist tradition, extending Enlightenment ideals
and ideas to the case of women. The suffragette movement preceded postmodernism by decades. The best
feminism, like the best movements for civil rights, have involved the extension of Enlightenment ideas and
ideals. So, feminism did not need postmodernism, and neither did civil rights.
In fact, postmodernism has done nothing for feminism, except to befuddle feminists with notions of social
constructivism and psychoanalytic theory—self-constructed boxes they’ve been trying to fight their way out
of ever since. For feminists, the social construction of gender does not mean that gender can be wished away.
Instead, escaping it is a never-ending struggle—to undo the supposed effects of “patriarchy,” or the phallus, in
the case of the psychoanalytic feminists who followed Jacques Lacan.
Yet even gender constructivism preceded postmodern theory. In the psychological literature, the word
“gender” was first applied to human sex difference in 1955, when the “sexologist” John Money introduced the
phrase “gender roles.” From there it became not only gender roles that were constructed but also gender
itself. Later, sex difference was deemed to be socially constructed as well. This is why I have called John
Money’s intervention “the gender jackpot.” Ever since Money, gender has multiplied and sought ever-new
pronouns, an absurd development that institutions have ludicrously attempted to keep pace with. The ironic
result of gender constructivism is that feminism is now being run by people with penises. If gender is a social
construct, then anyone can adopt the gender of their choice. Thus, males can be women. But that isn’t even
what feminists meant by the idea. They saw gender constructs as obdurate social categories that had been
established by long-standing conventions and enforced in multiple, almost inscrutable ways. For these
feminists, gender was no less real for being socially constructed. Undermining gender involved a long,
arduous social struggle. And gender-critical feminists figured sex and gender as tightly coupled. The attack of
second-wave feminists was not against biology but against socialization and social constraints based on
biology. They did not suggest that sex itself was socially constructed, only that roles based on sex were
socially constructed. Postmodernism, in third-wave feminism, suggests that sex itself is a social construct.
While our ideas about it surely are socially constructed, sex difference exists no matter what we think about it.
Gender difference and sex difference are very different things. Yes, sex roles, or gender roles, have changed
across time, but, to the best of our knowledge, sex difference itself has not, at least not appreciably. And thank
goodness for that—unless you believe, with some postmodern environmentalists, that human reproduction
is “evil.”
Furthermore, that postmodernists, according to Russell, don’t believe in biological determinism doesn’t make
biology any less determining. We are more or less biologically determined. I’ll say more about this below. But I
believe that the introduction of the concept of “gender constructivism” to describe human beings has been
pernicious, causing confusion and doing immeasurable harm to feminism and Western culture at large.
Meanwhile, the idea that gender is a social construct—determined by social factors—can be as deterministic
as biological determinism. This is especially the case in the hands of postmodern theory. That’s because,
under postmodern theory, the notion of the autonomous, preexisting self itself is denied. The self becomes
nothing but a mere aftereffect, a product of language and/or other social factors. Under postmodernism, the
self is “decentered,” that is, removed from the center of history and importance. And the agency of the self is
virtually denied. We can read this in the writing of the poststructuralists Roland Barthes and Michel Foucault,
for example, in “The Death of the Author” and “What Is an Author?,” respectively. Here, we find that authors do
not create texts. Texts produce their authors! Authors, and, by extension, the human subject itself, is the mere
product of text. Or, as described by Jean-François Lyotard in The Postmodern Condition (1979), the self is a
mere “node” in a communications circuit. Lyotard made his demotion of the self quite explicit: “And each of us
knows that our self does not amount to much…. A self does not amount to much.” This is hardly a formula for
self-determination, which requires individual agency, agency that postmodernism denies human beings.
Libertarianism requires the individual (the first form of property) and postmodernism denies the individual. To
the extent that Russell values the individual, I argued, he’s not a postmodernist. To the extent that he buys
into postmodernism’s denial of the self-determining individual agent, he’s not a libertarian.
Furthermore, postmodernism’s constant emphasis on social constructs suggests that they are all-determining.
This accounts for the social justice obsession with social identity categories and its denial of individual
identity and agency. Every outcome is determined by gender, race, or what have you. Everyone is reduced to
their social identity category. This obsession has led to the rabid identity politics of such groups as Black Lives
Matter, who see race as the sole determining factor for everything that happens to persons of color. Such
determinism denies their individual agency, reducing them to mere objects of history.
Meanwhile, there are different kinds of social constructivism. My epistemology may be called, following David
Hess, a “moderate constructivism.” Hess advanced the term in his An Advanced Introduction to Science
Studies (1997) to refer to a position that regards science as representing its natural object(s) and the social
and political orders, rather than either one exclusively. Martin J.S. Rudwick developed a similar standpoint
based on his detailed and remarkable study of the Devonian controversy in geology. Rudwick suggested that
“a consensual product of scientific debate can be regarded as both artifactual and natural, as a thoroughly
social construction that may nonetheless be a reliable representation of the natural world.” The point is that
there is a difference between the social construction of knowledge and the utter incommensurability of
knowledge and the object world. The latter implies that scientific knowledge is constructed, willy-nilly, and
even that the object world itself is socially constructed. Thaddeus Russell, like postmodern science studies
critics, confuses the two. The latter leads to an epistemological nihilism, because no one’s construction is any
better than anyone else’s.
Take Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts (1979) by Bruno Latour and Steve Woolgar, for
example. Laboratory Life is an anthropological examination of a scientific laboratory as a strange but not
altogether exotic culture. Almost “going native,” but not quite, the assumed strangeness effect allowed Latour
and Woolgar to see science’s final product in terms of what they called “literary inscription,” or writing. Despite
Latour’s subsequent break with the implications of “the social construction of scientific facts” arrived at in
Laboratory Life, this first book is constructivist through and through. The anthropologists aimed to show that
“the construction of scientific facts, in particular, is a process of generating texts whose fate (status, value,
utility, facticity) depends on their subsequent interpretation.” Latour and Woolgar thus reduced the objects of
scientific knowledge to “text,” just as Jacques Derrida had done with ontologies in philosophy. Of course, a
fallacy was at work. Latour and Woolgar’s sleight of hand demonstrated that scientific facts exist only within
texts—“there is no outside of text,” to quote Derrida. But as with all magic tricks, the deception had taken
place earlier, before we were looking. Latour and Woolgar stealthily conflated the knowledge of scientific facts
—established in the process of science and expressed in language—and the reality referred to by that
knowledge. Confusing knowledge and the objects of knowledge, our postmodern magicians seemed to make
the material world itself disappear into the text. The error is known as the fallacy of reification—or treating an
abstraction, like the knowledge of an object, as equivalent to a concrete object or thing, like the object to
which the knowledge refers. Russell makes the same mistake.
In Of Grammatology (1967), Derrida wrote that “[t]here is nothing outside of text.” So, some postmodernists
do in fact deny objective reality, contrary to Russell’s claim. Derrida’s Of Grammatology is a philosophical
excursus into the philosophy of language. It draws on Ferdinand de Saussure’s notion of the sign—the
signifier-signified-referent construction—to undermine any relationship between language and the object
world. The sign is the word, which has no necessary relationship to what it refers to. The signifier points to a
signified, or an idea, not to the referent, or something in the object world. Derrida goes further than Saussure
and breaks the connection between the signifier and the signified, arguing for the self-referentiality of the
signifier. The signifier points to itself and not to the signified. But Derrida also ends up conflating the signified
and the referent and thereby denying any relationship of language to the object world. This makes him an
epistemological nihilist. Knowledge becomes virtually impossible under such a sign system.
Language, however, is a tool. It allows us to connect particular words to particular objects, more or less
accurately defined, thus enhancing their use and manipulation. To pretend otherwise is sheer nonsense. (The
title Of Grammatology allows us to find Derrida’s ideas in said book by that title.) The point here is that by
denying a relationship between language and the object world, postmodernism abandons truth claims, as
does Russell himself. This epistemological nihilism would not be a problem if not for its likely consequences.
In “Transgressing the Boundaries: Towards a Transformative Hermeneutics of Quantum Gravity,” Alan Sokal
argued, parodically, that gravity itself is a social construct. The postmodernists at Social Text fell for the
parody. The Sokal Hoax pointed to the absurdity of the postmodern position inaugurated by Derrida as
applied to science.
Take the denial of biological determinism that Russell vaunts as a credit to postmodernism. Forget about
identity categories for a moment. We are more or less biologically determined and ignoring the extent of our
biological determination can be dangerous. The key is to find out just how biologically determined we are,
and in what ways. To investigate the extent and ways by which we are biologically determined is not
necessarily to cede authority to the state, as Russell suggested in the debate. Rather, it allows us to approach
an understanding of the scope of freedom itself. Liberty, if it is to be meaningful, depends on the
acknowledgement of constraints—those imposed by the object world, and those imposed by other people’s
rights. Without such an acknowledgement, liberty loses all meaning. We wouldn’t know what we are at liberty
to do.
Finally, as discussed above, the lack of an objective court of appeal leads to the possibility that others may
impose their unmoored beliefs on us, given the requisite power to do so. “Pseudo-realities,” as James Lindsay
notes in a recent installment of New Discourses, “being false and unreal, will always generate tragedy and evil
on a scale that is at least proportional to the reach of their grip on power … ”
Totalitarianism depends on the enforcement of false beliefs. Postmodernism admittedly and purposively
leaves us no way to adjudicate beliefs. Likewise, postmodernism lends itself to totalitarianism.
Author:
Contact Michael Rectenwald
Michael Rectenwald was a professor of liberal studies at New York University (retired).
Note: The views expressed on Mises.org are not necessarily those of the Mises Institute.
Image source: Getty
When commenting, please post a concise, civil, and informative comment. Full comment policy here
LOAD COMMENTS
TOPICS
AUSTRIAN SCHOOL
Anarchy
Legal System
Austrian Economics Overview
Money Supply
Anti-Politics
Liberalism
Business Cycles
Monopoly and Competition
Big Government
Libertarianism
Calculation and Knowledge
Other Schools of Thought
Biographies
Macroeconomics
Cantillon
Philosophy and Methodology
Bitcoin
Majority Rule
Capital and Interest Theory
Political Theory
Book Reviews
Media and Culture
Entrepreneurship
Praxeology
Booms and Busts
Minarchy
Fiscal Theory
Prices
Bureaucracy and Regulation
Monetary Policy
Gold Standard
Private Property
Capitalism
Money and Banks
History of the Austrian School of Economics
Production Theory
Central Banks
Old Right
Interventionism
Subjectivism
Coordination
Paternalism
Monetary Theory
Value and Exchange
Corporate Welfare
Philosophy
Money and Banking
Cronyism and Corporatism
Planning
Decentralization and Secession
Poverty
Democracy
Price Controls
Economic Freedom
Progressivism
Economic Policy
Property Rights
Education
Protectionism and Free Trade
Fed Watch
Rationalism
Financial Markets
Socialism
Free Markets
Strategy
From the Archives
Taxes and Spending
Global Economy
The Entrepreneur
Hayek
The Environment
Health
The Fed
Immigration
The Police State
Inflation
U.S. Economy
Interviews
U.S. History
Keynes
Unemployment
Labor and Wages
War and Foreign Policy
Law
World History
BROWSE LIBRARY
ABOUT THE MISES INSTITUTE
CONTACT US
Who is Ludwig von Mises?
Fellowships & Independent Research
What is the Austrian School of Economics?
What is the Mises Institute?
Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics
Driving Directions to the Institute
Mises Institute
518 West Magnolia Avenue
Auburn, Alabama 36832-4501
Journal of Libertarian Studies
Become a Member
PHONE 334.321.2100 | FAX 334.321.2119
The Austrian
Mises Events
Email Us
Mises Wire
Mises Bookstore
Human Action Podcast
Faculty & Staff
Homeschool Resources
Finances and Board
Order free copies of Economics in One Lesson
Subscribe to Email Lists
Support Mises
✉
GET NEWS AND ARTICLES IN YOUR INBOX
Tu ne cede malis,
sed contra audentior ito
STAY CONNECTED
Privacy Statement
Contact Us
Website powered by Mises Institute donors
Mises Institute is a tax-exempt 501(c)(3) nonprofit organization. Contributions are tax-deductible to the full extent the law allows. Tax ID# 52-1263436