Engels @ 200
Frank Jacob (Ed.)
Engels @ 200
Reading Friedrich Engels in the 21st Century
Frank Jacob (Ed.)
Engels @ 200
Reading Friedrich Engels in the 21st Century
ISBN (Print) 978-3-96317-225-0
ISBN (ePDF) 978-3-96317-762-0
DOI 10.14631/978-3-96317-762-0
Erschienen 2020 bei: Büchner-Verlag eG, Marburg
Satz: SatzHerstellung Verlagsdienstleistungen Heike Amthor, Fernwald
Umschlaggestaltung: DeinSatz Marburg | lf
Bildnachweis Umschlag: Porträt Friedrich Engels, 1879;
Wikimedia Commons: https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/
File:Friedrich_Engels_portrait.jpg (bearbeitet)
Dieses Werk erscheint unter der Creative-Commons-Lizenz
CC BY-NC 4.0: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/.
Die Bedingungen der Creative-Commons-Lizenz gelten nur für
Originalmaterial. Die Wiederverwendung von Material aus anderen
Quellen (gekennzeichnet mit Quellenangabe) wie z. B. Schaubilder,
Abbildungen, Fotos und Textauszüge erfordert ggf. weitere
Nutzungsgenehmigungen durch den jeweiligen Rechteinhaber.
Bibliografische Informationen der Deutschen Nationalbibliothek
Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet diese Publikation in der
Deutschen Nationalbibliografie, detaillierte bibliografische Angaben sind
im Internet über http://dnb.de abrufbar.
www.buechner-verlag.de
Inhalt
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
Frank Jacob . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
7
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
25
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory:
The Legacy of a Revolutionary Life
Frank Jacob . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
49
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation
of the Manchu State: Understanding the Pre-State
Manchu Society from an Engelsian Perspective
(1550 – 1651)
Jia Feng . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
91
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique
of Political Economy
Renildo Souza . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 127
The Psychology of Friedrich Engels:
From Materialistic Theories of Manual Labor
to Criticism of Empiricism and Ideology
David Pavón-Cuéllar . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 157
6
Inhalt
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
Maria Rosário de Carvalho . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 173
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature.
An Interpretation of the Concept
of the Dialectics of Nature
Gottfried Schweiger . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 199
The Relationship between Art and Politics:
On the Letter of Friedrich Engels
to Margaret Harkness
Henrique Wellen . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 223
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹
to Social Reproduction Theory
Vincent Streichhahn . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 235
In the Shadow of Karl Marx: Perception and Reception
of Friedrich Engels in the Digital Age
Riccardo Altieri . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 271
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak:
Engels’s Perspective
Nuruddin Al Akbar . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 289
Engels as Course Reading in the 21st Century
History Classroom
Alexander Maxwell . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 335
Contributors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 353
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
Frank Jacob
I would always say »Engels and Marx.« The big rabbit was … Engels.1
Paul Frölich (1884 – 1953),2 a founding member of the German Communist Party, recognized the importance of Friedrich Engels in this
quote, which he sent as a remark related to a manuscript3 by the
Ukrainian Marxist Roman Rosdolsky (1898 – 1967).4 In contrast to
Frölich’s view, however, Engels continued to be seen as the second
fiddle5 and is often neglected with regard to his role and influence
on the course of the history in general and Marxism in particular.
Engels, as German historian Jürgen Herres put it, was a »republi-
1
2
3
4
5
Letter by Paul Frölich to Roman Rosdolsky, Kew Gardens, New York, October
26, 1948, International Institute of Social History, Amsterdam, Rosdolsky Papers
6, Correspondence with Paul and Rosi Frölich 1948 to 1950, 3. I would like to
thank Riccardo Altieri for pointing me towards this source.
Riccardo Altieri, »Paul Frölich, American Exile, and Communist Discourse
about the Russian Revolution,« American Communist History 17, no. 2 (2018):
S. 220 – 231.
The manuscript was eventually not published before both, Frölich and Rosdolsky,
were already dead. Roman Rosdolsky, Zur Entstehungsgeschichte des Marxschen
Kapital (Frankfurt am Main / Vienna, 1968).
Janusz Radziejowski, »Roman Rosdolsky: Man, Activist and Scholar,« Science &
Society 42, no. 2 (1978): 198 – 210.
Georges Labica, »Friedrich Engels — Wissenschaftler und Revolutionär,« in
Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker« nach 100 Jahren,
eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer (Hamburg:
VSA, 1996), 18. Engels called himself a »second violine« in a letter to Johann
Philipp Becker, October 15, 1884, in: Marx-Engels-Werke (Berlin: Dietz, 1956-,
henceforth MEW), 36: 218.
8
Frank Jacob
can communist and a European social critic.«6 Thomas Kuczynski
in addition called him a »young genius of social science.«7 A quarter
century after his death, an article in Der Wahre Jacob claimed Engels
to be the »creator of eternal intellectual works« and, at the same
time, a »pioneer of German and international socialism.«8 Engels
indeed was an intellectual giant, whose personality was so colorful
and multifaceted that it is not easy to describe it accurately.9 Regardless of this fact, the number of biographies and works about Engels
never became legion, as it did in the case of his friend Karl Marx
(1818 – 1883).10 At the same time, however, Engels’s work was much
more diverse than the writings of Marx.11 He was, to name just one
example here, not only a philosopher and a social scientist, but also
a military historian, one who realized the importance of the techno-
6
7
8
9
10
11
Jürgen Herres, »Friedrich Engels: Republikanischer Kommunist und europäischer Gesellschaftskritiker,« in Friedrich Engels: Ein Gespenst geht um in
Europa — Begleitband zur Engelsausstellung 2020, ed. Lars Bluma (Wuppertal:
Historisches Zentrum Wuppertal, 2020), 16 – 29.
Thomas Kuczynski, »Die zweite Violine,« in »Die Natur ist die Probe auf die
Dialektik«: Friedrich Engels kennenlernen, eds. Elmar Altvater et al. (Hamburg:
VSA Verlag, 2020), 27.
A. Conrady, »Friedrich Engels,« Beilage zum Wahren Jacob, No. 887, July 30,
1920: 10027.
Theodor Bergmann, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer, »Einleitung,«
in Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker« nach 100 Jahren,
eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer (Hamburg:
VSA, 1996), 9; Michael Krätke, »Friedrich Engels, der erste Marxist,« in Friedrich
Engels oder: Wie ein »Cotton-Lord« den Marxismus erfand, ed. Michael Krätke
(Berlin: Dietz, 2020), 58.
Some important biographies are Gustav Mayer, Friedrich Engels: Eine Biographie,
2 vols. (Berlin: Springer, 1920 – 1933); Hans Peter Bleuel, Friedrich Engels: Bürger
und Revolutionär (Bern / Munich: Scherz, 1981); Tristram Hunt, Friedrich Engels:
Der Mann, der den Marxismus erfand, transl. by Klaus-Dieter Schmidt, third
edition (Berlin: List, 2020).
Bergmann, et al. »Einleitung,« 11; Conrady, »Friedrich Engels,« 10027 – 10028;
Marcel van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft und Lebensleistung: Eine
biografische Skizze,« in »Die Natur ist die Probe auf die Dialektik«: Friedrich
Engels kennenlernen, eds. Elmar Altvater et al. (Hamburg: VSA Verlag, 2020), 19.
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
logical development and identified the industrial-military context.12
Engels was consequently called a »pioneer of the revolutionary-socialist military theory«13 as well, and one of his writings, »Po and
Rhine« (1859),14 was initially considered to have been written by a
member of the Prussian General Staff.15 What already becomes clear
from this short introduction here is that there is more to Engels than
just his friendship with Marx that makes him an important intellectual of the 19th century. Since he intellectually represented »a materialism of conditions and complex mediation, which determined
the problems of scientific research for him,«16 is it not surprising that
Engels got interested in other scientific fields during his life as well?
While diving into all kinds of knowledge, he developed what Epifanio San Juan, Jr. called a »genius that was organized strategically.«
Engels’s intelligence »aimed for practice« and therefore influenced
all his research.17 It was, at the same time, very much influenced by
his personal life, which is essential to understanding how the young
Engels turned into a radical communist.
The German historian Gustav Mayer (1871 – 1948), in his »groundbreaking work«18 on Engels’s life, emphasized that no biography of
any other important leaders of the political workers‹ movement initially pointed so little to such a historical course.19 Born on 28 November 1820 in Barmen, nowadays part of Wuppertal, Engels was
the eldest son of a cotton manufacturer by the same name and grew
up in »a family of culture« in which »nothing pointed to his later
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
Bergmann, et al. »Einleitung,« 11.
van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 17.
MEW 13 : 225 – 268. Online at http://www.mlwerke.de/me/me13/me13_225.htm.
Accessed August 20, 2020.
Kuczynski, »Die zweite Violine,« 30.
Epifanio San Juan, Jr., »Was wir aus Engels’s revolutionärer Ästhetik lernen können,« in Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker« nach 100
Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer
(Hamburg: VSA, 1996), 69.
Ibid., 70.
Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 13.
Mayer, Friedrich Engels, 4.
9
10
Frank Jacob
revolutionary interest.«20 His early years were determined by »industry, trade, bourgeois duties, and loyalty to the family,«21 and while
Engels did not face any sorrows and was surrounded by »loving parents [and] indulgent grandparents,«22 the boy would eventually suffer
from »the pressure of religious, political, and social conventions.«23 In
1837, Engels had to leave school, as his father wanted him to become
part of the family business, especially since the latter had decided
to expand and invest in a joint venture with the Ermen brothers‹
factory in Manchester.24 Following this decision, the young Engels’s
life changed, and from then onwards, he had to subordinate his own
interests to the family business.25
After a year in the Barmen factory and a first trip to England with
his father in the summer of 1838, Engels was sent to Bremen, where he
was supposed to continue his business education in a company where
he oversaw exports and was responsible for international correspondence. Regardless of the fact that he had to work in a field he very
much disliked, Engels, in contrast to Marx, was never melancholic or
discouraged.26 He was rather »a radical romantic damned to a life in a
trading post.«27 After his time in Bremen, Engels served as a volunteer
in the Prussian Guard Artillery Brigade in Berlin.28 While officially
serving in the military, the young intellectual used his time in the
metropolis to intensify his studies and visited lectures at the univer20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 19.
Ibid., 22.
Ibid., 19.
Narihiko Ito, »Realismus und Utopismus,« in Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker« nach 100 Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario
Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer (Hamburg: VSA, 1996), 23. On Engels’s
early years in Wuppertal see Reiner Rhefus, Friedrich Engels im Wuppertal: Auf
den Spuren des Denkers, Machers und Revolutionärs im »deutschen Manchester«
(Hamburg: VSA, 2020).
Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 38; van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 8.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 15.
Ibid., 19.
Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 47.
Ibid., 64; van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 10.
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
sity, where he got particularly interested in philosophy, especially the
works of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770 – 1831).29 The latter,
although he had already been dead for a decade, would always remain
an »authority of the history of science«30 for Engels, who considered
philosophy to be the root of German communism.
The young intellectual was consequently further radicalized in
Berlin. In 1842, when he visited the editorial staff of the Rheinische
Zeitung in Cologne, he met Marx for the first time. However, the
beginning of their more intense cooperation had not yet developed.31
Instead, Engels spent time in England again — between November 1842 and August 1844 — where, working as an assistant for the
management at Ermen & Engels, he began to understand the rules
of modern capitalism. In his writings, which resemble those of an »elegant novelist,«32 especially since Engels wrote much more lightly and
clearly than Marx,33 he criticized capitalism and its consequences for
the working class early on. Already in 1839, Engels had anonymously
published some »Letters from Wuppertal«34 in which he had criticized
pietism, Calvinism, and authentically described the bad condition
of the workers in his home region.35 His time in England and his
relationship with Mary Burns (1821 – 1863), a factory worker, however,
further radicalized Engels, and when he returned, he was dedicated
to changing the fate of the working class.36 In 1845 he published his
first major work, The Condition of the Working Class in England,37 in
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 66; Ito, »Realismus und Utopismus,« 23.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 38.
van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 11.
Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 50.
Kuczynski, »Die zweite Violine,« 32.
Telegraph für Deutschland, nos. 49, 50, 51, 52, 57 and 59 in March and April 1839.
Online at https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1839/03/telegraph.htm.
Accessed Augsut 20, 2020.
Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 54; van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 9.
Bergmann, et al. »Einleitung,« 10; van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,«
12.
For a more detailed discussion of the work see Regina Roth, »›Die Lage der arbeitenden Klasse in England‹ von Engels im Spiegel ihrer Zeit (1845 – 1892),« in
11
12
Frank Jacob
which he not only prophetically announced a near revolution38 but
also provided an early study of empirical social research. The study is
still considered today to be a »pioneer work«39 in this field and »classic
of urban sociology.«40
In August 1844, after his time in England, he met Marx again
for ten days in Paris, where both intensively discussed their views
and laid the foundation for their following and intensive cooperation.41 In Marx, Engels had finally found somebody who understood
him and did not have a problem with him being a »private scholar,«
having previously been criticized by academics and confronted with
their classist views.42 Both intellectuals would be further influenced
by historical events. While Engels had predicted a revolution in the
early 1840s that would happen in accordance with a theoretical model in relation to the French Revolution of 1789,43 the reality would be
a disappointment and demand some reflections about revolutionary
processes as such.44 Engels had been actively involved in the revolution, first as a journalist and then as a barricade fighter, but he
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
Friedrich Engels: Ein Gespenst geht um in Europa — Begleitband zur Engelsausstellung 2020, ed. Lars Bluma (Wuppertal: Historisches Zentrum Wuppertal, 2020),
84 – 99.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 30.
van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 16.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 32.
van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 13.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 19 and 23. That classism is still a problem in academia
is discussed in some recent publications: Riccardo Altieri and Bernd Hüttner,
eds. Klassismus und Wissenschaft. Erfahrungsberichte und Bewältigungsstrategien
(Marburg: BdWi-Verlag, 2020) and Julia Reuter, Markus Gamper, Christina
Möller and Frerk Blome, eds. Vom Arbeiterkind zur Professur: Sozialer Aufstieg
in der Wissenschaft. Autobiographische Notizen und soziobiographische Analysen
(Bielefeld: Transcript Verlag, 2020).
Ito, »Realismus und Utopismus,« 25.
For Engels’s evaluation of the Revolution of 1848, see Friedrich Engels, »Das Jahr
1848 war das Jahr der Enttäuschung, 17.III.[1849],« IISH, Karl Marx / Friedrich
Engels Papers, ARCH00860, H_8.
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
could not change its historical course and had to witness its failure.45
The experience would, however, influence the further work of Marx
and Engels, who tried to scientifically prepare another revolution in
the future while their politics were determined by a »revolutionary
reservation« (Revolutionsvorbehalt).46 Both consequently conceptualized the process of a revolution of the 19th century in their work,
and they made it clear that it would be important to have access to
the full power of a purposeful party and an enlightened mass of the
people to really secure the success of a future revolution.47 Engels,
who considered history to be a process without any final or absolute
truth, emphasized the role of crises in awakening the revolutionary
potential of a particular time.48 Engels’s and Marx’s reflections about
revolutions, nevertheless, were consequently products of their own
experiences of the 1840s and must be considered as such when taken
into consideration today.49
What is important to understand is that Engels already realized in
the 1840s that a revolution was like an inevitable natural event, forced
into being by pressure from suppressed people who demanded change.
It could therefore not be made or planned by a small minority — as
such revolutions would fail like the revolutions of 1848 / 49 — but was
the expression of a popular demand by the masses.50 The failure of the
revolution also meant an end for Engels’s dream to leave the business
world and to help with creating a new, better world.51 Due to his
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
Kuczynski, »Die zweite Violine,« 28; van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 16.
Georg Fülberth, Friedrich Engels (Cologne: PapyRossa, 2018), 68.
Ibid., 69.
Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 73; Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 28.
Marjan Britovšek, »Die slawischen Nationalbewegungen und die Perspektiven
der Revolution,« in Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker«
nach 100 Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert
Schäfer (Hamburg: VSA, 1996), 140.
Conrady, »Friedrich Engels,« 10028.
Kuczynski, »Die zweite Violine,« 28; Detlef Vonde, Auf den Barrikaden: Friedrich
Engels und die »gescheiterte Revolution« von 1848 / 49 (Wuppertal: Köndgen, 2019),
7 – 8.
13
14
Frank Jacob
active role, he was forced into exile, »expatriated by the bourgeois
revolution.«52 In the following years, Engels tried to better understand
what had happened in 1848 and therefore studied historical cases as
well. His work on The Peasant War in Germany (1850)53 was »a small
but nice attempt to interpret the central European peasant rebellions
of the 16th century in a materialist way.«54 Regardless of these approaches and the wish to understand revolutions much better, Engels,
like Marx as well, was not in favor of so-called revolutionaries by profession.55 In their works, the two men rather addressed questions of
their times, which is why German political scientist Georg Fülberth
correctly called them »operative intellectuals.«56 Regardless of his
many works, while in exile, Engels also had to work for the company
of his father, which he could not leave before 1869 due to financial
necessities; consequently, until then, he had to live a double life as a
businessman and an intellectual.57 However, between 1870 and 1895,
he could focus on the latter.58 Regardless of his personal condition,
Engels worked relentlessly to develop a socialist science, although he
remained a passionate utopian at the same time.59 He remained a believer in revolution as the only way to achieve the final liberation of
mankind, and in 1892 assumed that the socialist party would be in
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
Ibid., 8.
Friedrich Engels, »The Peasant War in Germany« (1850). Accessed August 20,
2020. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1850/peasant-war-germany/
index.htm.
van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 18.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 59.
Fülberth, Friedrich Engels, 12.
Paul Lafargue, »Persönliche Erinnerungen,« in Friedrich Engels oder: Wie ein
»Cotton-Lord« den Marxismus erfand, ed. Michael Krätke (Berlin: Dietz, 2020),
185; van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 18. Engels had saved sufficient money for his later life, and when he died his fortune still counted for more
than 30,000 Pounds (approximately more than 4 million Euro today).
Georg Fülberth, »Endlich angekommen: Friedrich Engels’s Londoner Jahre
1870 – 1895,« in Friedrich Engels: Ein Gespenst geht um in Europa — Begleitband
zur Engelsausstellung 2020, ed. Lars Bluma (Wuppertal: Historisches Zentrum
Wuppertal, 2020), 182 – 195.
Ito, »Realismus und Utopismus,« 32.
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
power in the next decade.60 At the same time, however, he declared a
year later that this was not the final goal for German socialism, as one
would rather have to consider the socialists to be revolutionaries who
were not intending to dictate the future of human society but wanted
to achieve freedom for the masses so that they could decide this for
themselves.61
The impact of the political ideas of Friedrich Engels is, at the same
time, important to understand the development of his friend Karl
Marx,62 as it was their friendship63 and intellectual cooperation that
would be responsible for a new interpretation of human history and
progress alike. The lives and works of the two friends eventually became so interwoven that it is quite challenging to separate them.64
However, Engels not only supported Marx intellectually, he also supported the latter and his family financially, and in 1851 even accepted
fatherhood for the child Marx had had with Helene Demuth, the
family’s maid, and thereby saved Marx’s marriage.65 With regard to
their intellectual cooperation,66 Engels played an equally important
role, as both only seemed to accept each other as critics of their own
60
Friedrich Engels, »Interview mit dem Korrespondenten der Zeitung L’Éclair am
1. April 1892,« in Friedrich Engels oder: Wie ein »Cotton-Lord« den Marxismus
erfand, ed. Michael Krätke (Berlin: Dietz, 2020), 158.
61 Friedrich Engels, »Interview mit dem Korrespondenten der Zeitung Le Figaro
am 8. Mai 1893,« in Friedrich Engels oder: Wie ein »Cotton-Lord« den Marxismus
erfand, ed. Michael Krätke (Berlin: Dietz, 2020), 164.
62 Eike Kopf, »Marx ohne Engels — das wäre kaum eine halbe Sache geworden,«
in »Die Natur ist die Probe auf die Dialektik«: Friedrich Engels kennenlernen, eds.
Elmar Altvater et al. (Hamburg: VSA Verlag, 2020), 69 – 89.
63 On the friendship of the two men see Jürgen Herres, Marx und Engels: Porträt
einer intellektuellen Freundschaft (Stuttgart: Reclam, 2018).
64 Lafargue, »Persönliche Erinnerungen,« 187.
65 Kuczynski, »Die zweite Violine,« 29; van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 17.
66 Georg Fülberth, »Wie zwei ein Compagniegeschäft betrieben: Friedrich Engels’s
Beitrag zum Werk von Karl Marx,« in »Die Natur ist die Probe auf die Dialektik«:
Friedrich Engels kennenlernen, eds. Elmar Altvater et al. (Hamburg: VSA Verlag,
2020), 54 – 68.
15
16
Frank Jacob
works,67 and as German political scientist Michael Krätke emphasized, »Both were arrogant, each in his own way, but together they
could be obnoxious.«68 Regardless of Engels’s intellectual capacity and
expertise in many different fields,69 which often even surpassed Marx,
the former would never achieve similar authority.70 In the early 1850s,
Engels wrote all of their works on military issues and foreign affairs,
including the English articles Marx would publish under his own
name in the New York Daily Tribune.71
It is safe to say, to quote Michael Krätke once more, »that there
would not have been Marxism without Engels,«72 as the latter was the
first who sought, especially after his friend’s death, to make Marx’s writings known to a wider public. It was probably the humbleness of Engels—who always would refer to himself as the second fiddle, a talent,
and to Marx as a genius—that made the rise of Marx and his legacy
possible. The two men might have appeared like an »inseparable duo,«73
yet Engels, often intentionally, tended to stand in the shadow of his
friend.74 Regardless of his humbleness, Engels was important for Marx
in many ways. He, according to Krätke, was a »guide, stimulator, a
source of ideas, a thought leader and a critic«75 alike and pretty heavily
influenced the latter’s economic works.76 It was also Engels who actually
repeatedly insisted that Marx publish his works while providing his
friend with the necessary time and financial security to do so.77 Engels
would help Marx, according to the latter’s own statement, at any time
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
Lafargue, »Persönliche Erinnerungen,« 189.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 13.
Lafargue, »Persönliche Erinnerungen,« 191.
Ibid., 187 – 188.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 9.
Ibid., 10.
Ibid., 11.
Ibid., 12.
Ibid., 25.
Conrady, »Friedrich Engels,« 10027; Herres, Marx und Engels, 46; Krätke,
»Friedrich Engels,« 29.
Conrady, »Friedrich Engels,« 10027; Fülberth, Friedrich Engels, 69.
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
and in any condition.78 This support was essential for Marx’s works and,
therefore, one cannot omit the Engelsian influence when talking about
these important writings of the 19th century. In addition, in the years
after Marx’s death, Engels worked relentlessly for the Marxian legacy
and, after 1883, he became the spiritual head of international socialism.79
He edited volumes 2 and 3 of Capital, an undertaking for which he was
criticized because some people argued that he had not only changed
but falsified parts of the work.80 Engels had attempted to make the
work more appealing to the masses, although he could not complete it
either, and Capital remained »an incomplete masterpiece.«81 He might
have therefore been the »first Marxist,« although he did not consider
it to be an orthodoxy but rather a work in progress that needed to be
reframed according to the historical and existent circumstances.82
Marxism was not a doctrine for Marx and Engels, but rather
1. a historical-materialist analysis of economy and class relations,
2. a political theory based on this analysis, and
3. a political practice that demands the end of a capitalist society.83
It is hard to understand this by a divided analysis of the works of Marx
and Engels, which must rather be seen as a compendium in which the
single works relate to each other. This, however, should also not deny
some kind of intellectual individualism, especially since too often the
two men were pressed into an almost religious duality.84 There were
also attempts to divide them, even to antagonize them. Marx was
considered the universal thinker, and Engels the one responsible for
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
MEW 28 : 596.
Labica, »Friedrich Engels,« 17 – 19.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 39 – 41; van der Linden, »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft,« 23 – 24.
Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 43.
Bergmann, et al. »Einleitung,« 12; Fülberth, Friedrich Engels, 8; Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 54 – 56.
Fülberth, Friedrich Engels, 9.
Bergmann, et al. »Einleitung,« 9; Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 13.
17
18
Frank Jacob
the flattening of his friend’s ideas that could then be corrupted by
totalitarian systems, e. g. Stalinism.85
In contrast to such arguments, it is important to understand Engels as an intellectual who tried to practically apply his thoughts to
change society.86 His experiences in English factories, his participation
in the Revolution of 1848, and his almost endless hunger for knowledge helped to forge his and Marx’s intellectual work. He must therefore be considered an equal to Marx, and nothing less. The negative
or anti-Engelsian attitude does not take into account that Engels, despite being in steady contact with the SPD leadership since the 1880s,
i. e. August Bebel (1840 – 1913) or Eduard Bernstein (1850 – 1932), never
gave up his belief in a better future, which could only be achieved by a
revolution of the masses.87 It is this belief, next to his many works that
seem to have never lost their actuality, that makes Engels important
for the 21st century as well.
While Marx is — also academically — en vogue again since criticisms of global hyper-capitalism have gained ground,88 especially
during the COVID-19 crisis, which due to its impact threatens the
further existence of capitalism as such, Engels has still not received
the necessary attention. Those in circles on the left, especially those
who call themselves Marxists today, still tend to make him responsible for the failures of regimes that used supposedly Marxist doctrines
to legitimize their rule89 and use Engelsism as a derogative term.90
Nevertheless, the 200th birthday of Engels stimulated some interest,
85
86
87
Bergmann, et al. »Einleitung,« 10.
Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 16.
Fülberth, Friedrich Engels, 72. For Engels's relation with and impact on German
Social Democracy also see Detlef Lehnert and Christina Morina, eds. Friedrich
Engels und die Sozialdemokratie: Werke und Wirkungen eines Europäers (Berlin:
Metropol, 2020).
88 Especially the 200th birthday of Marx in 2018 stimulated some public and academic interest again. For one of the recent surveys on problems and thoughts
related to his legacy see Martin Endreß and Christian Jansen, eds. Karl Marx im
21. Jahrhundert: Bilanz und Perspektiven (Frakfurt am Main: Campus, 2020).
89 Hunt, Friedrich Engels, 8; Labica, »Friedrich Engels,« 20.
90 Krätke, »Friedrich Engels,« 58.
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
especially in Wuppertal, where many events commemorated his legacy.91 Regardless of such events, it is more than timely to bring Engels
back into the spotlight and to re-read his writings, especially since
they offer so many insights into a variety of problems our society
still struggles with and will have to deal with in the 21st century. It
is time to draw him out of Marx’s shadow92 and to emphasize his
actuality, e. g. with regard to questions of housing,93 family theory,94
or gender-related discussions.95 As was already argued 25 years after
his death, Engels »must not be a simple name for the current generation,« but must become a »role model and teacher«96 instead. Engels
never feared to learn something new or to be critical with regard to
his own views either.97 We should be as critical and try to learn from
Engels’s experiences in the 19th century for our own benefit in the 21st
century. There is much to learn, and, if applied, the knowledge Engels
provides us with might be decisive for formulating our own revolutionary dream that can become a reality if the global masses share it.
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
Rainer Lucas, Reinhard Pfriem and Hans-Dieter Westhoff, »Einleitung der Herausgeber,« in Arbeiten am Widerspruch: Friedrich Engels zum 200. Geburtstag, eds.
Rainer Lucas, Reinhard Pfriem and Hans-Dieter Westhoff (Marburg: Metropolis-Verlag, 2020), 13.
Ibid., 14.
Burghard Flieger, »Engels’s Stellungnahme zur Wohnungsfrage: Anstöße für
zukunftsfähige wohnungsbaugenossenschaftliche Konzepte?« in Arbeiten am
Widerspruch: Friedrich Engels zum 200. Geburtstag, eds. Rainer Lucas, Reinhard
Pfriem and Hans-Dieter Westhoff (Marburg: Metropolis-Verlag, 2020), 335.
An essential text by Engels related to this question is Friedrich Engels, »Zur
Wohnungsfrage,« in MEW 18, 5: 209 – 287.
Gisela Notz, »Auseinandersetzung mit Friedrich Engels’s ›Ursprung der Familie …‹: … und was er uns heute noch zu sagen hat,« in Arbeiten am Widerspruch:
Friedrich Engels zum 200. Geburtstag, eds. Rainer Lucas, Reinhard Pfriem and
Hans-Dieter Westhoff (Marburg: Metropolis-Verlag, 2020), 398 – 404.
Adelheid Biesecker, Frigga Haug und Uta von Winterfeld, »Nachdenken mit
Friedrich Engels: Über Geschlechterverhältnisse und gesellschaftliche Naturverhältnisse,« in Arbeiten am Widerspruch: Friedrich Engels zum 200. Geburtstag, eds.
Rainer Lucas, Reinhard Pfriem and Hans-Dieter Westhoff (Marburg: Metropolis-Verlag, 2020), 417 – 438.
Conrady, »Friedrich Engels,« 10027.
Labica, »Friedrich Engels,« 21.
19
20
Frank Jacob
The present volume must consequently be understood as an attempt
to give a survey of questions and topics to which Engels’s thoughts and
writings can be applied, or at least taken into consideration. It offers
an insight into Engels’s broad variety of ideas and experiences, and it
hopes to stimulate further research on the man who was so important
for the intellectual lives of so many who tried to follow in his footsteps.
The first three chapters—by Vitor Bartoletti Sartori, Frank Jacob and
Jia Feng—will describe Engels’s view of dialectics and history. They will
not only analyze the role of dialectics in his historical worldview, but
will also show how Engels understood revolutions as historical processes that are linked to a specific space-time continuum and what we can
make of Engels’s theoretical concepts when they are applied to a concrete analysis of a historical case study. In the following contributions,
Renildo Souza, David Pavón-Cuéllar, Maria Rosario and Gottfried
Schweiger will shed light on some fields Engels was also interested in
when they discuss his works in the field of political economy, his psychology and his reflections on empirism and ideology, and his thoughts
about both evolutionist ethnology as well as the philosophy of nature.
That Engels intellectually offers much more than reflections about
historical materialism is also shown by Henrique Wellen’s analysis of
Engels’s understanding of the relationship between art and politics
and Vincent Streichhahn’s chapter on the ›woman question‹ and social reproduction theory from an Engelsian perspective. The existence
of Engels’s minor role, at least with regard to his perception in the
digital age, is analyzed by Riccardo Altieri, before Nuruddin Al Akbar
discusses a critical reading of Engels’s perspective in a time that is currently so heavily determined by the COVID-19 pandemic. Last but
not least, Alexander Maxwell provides a practical insight and shows
why Engels provides a course reading for history classes in the 21st
century that will not only engage students much better than Marx’s
Capital but also open the eyes of those who might be in steady contact
with global capitalism yet do not understand its functionality.
All in all, the editor and the authors hope that Engels will receive
more attention from activists and scholars alike because his works
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
and legacy remain timely and relevant in a century that faces many
crises. If a revolution of the masses can eventually change the world
and, through the abolishment of capitalism, turn it into a better place,
this might rely on a revival of Friedrich Engels, whose works provide
at least a theoretical map to solve the problems of humanity during
our century.
Works Cited
Altieri, Riccardo and Bernd Hüttner, eds. Klassismus und Wissenschaft. Erfahrungsberichte und Bewältigungsstrategien. Marburg: BdWi-Verlag, 2020.
—. »Paul Frölich, American Exile, and Communist Discourse about the
Russian Revolution.« American Communist History 17, no. 2 (2018):
S. 220 – 231.
Bergmann, Theodor, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer. »Einleitung.« In Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker«
nach 100 Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and
Gert Schäfer, 9 – 13. Hamburg: VSA, 1996.
Biesecker, Adelheid, Frigga Haug und Uta von Winterfeld. »Nachdenken
mit Friedrich Engels: Über Geschlechterverhältnisse und gesellschaftliche Naturverhältnisse.« In Arbeiten am Widerspruch: Friedrich Engels zum
200. Geburtstag, eds. Rainer Lucas, Reinhard Pfriem and Hans-Dieter
Westhoff, 417 – 438. Marburg: Metropolis-Verlag, 2020.
Bleuel, Hans Peter. Friedrich Engels: Bürger und Revolutionär. Bern / Munich:
Scherz, 1981.
Britovšek, Marjan. »Die slawischen Nationalbewegungen und die Perspektiven der Revolution.« In Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker« nach 100 Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario
Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer, 140 – 156. Hamburg: VSA, 1996.
Conrady, A. »Friedrich Engels.« Beilage zum Wahren Jacob, No. 887, July 30,
1920: 10027 – 10028.
Endreß, Martin and Christian Jansen, eds. Karl Marx im 21. Jahrhundert:
Bilanz und Perspektiven. Frakfurt am Main: Campus, 2020.
Engels, Friedrich. »Das Jahr 1848 war das Jahr der Enttäuschung,« 17.III.
[1849] IISH, Karl Marx / Friedrich Engels Papers, ARCH00860, H_8.
21
22
Frank Jacob
—. »Interview mit dem Korrespondenten der Zeitung L’Éclair am 1. April
1892.« In Friedrich Engels oder: Wie ein »Cotton-Lord« den Marxismus erfand, ed. Michael Krätke, 153 – 158. Berlin: Dietz, 2020.
—. »Interview mit dem Korrespondenten der Zeitung Le Figaro am 8. Mai
1893.« In Friedrich Engels oder: Wie ein »Cotton-Lord« den Marxismus erfand, ed. Michael Krätke, 159 – 165. Berlin: Dietz, 2020.
—. »The Peasant War in Germany« (1850). Accessed August 20, 2020. https://
www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1850/peasant-war-germany/
index.htm.
Flieger, Burghard. »Engels’s Stellungnahme zur Wohnungsfrage: Anstöße für
zukunftsfähige wohnungsbaugenossenschaftliche Konzepte?« In Arbeiten
am Widerspruch: Friedrich Engels zum 200. Geburtstag, eds. Rainer Lucas,
Reinhard Pfriem and Hans-Dieter Westhoff, 335 – 363. Marburg: Metropolis-Verlag, 2020.
Fülberth, Georg. »Endlich angekommen: Friedrich Engels’s Londoner Jahre
1870 – 1895.« In Friedrich Engels: Ein Gespenst geht um in Europa — Begleitband zur Engelsausstellung 2020, ed. Lars Bluma, 182 – 195. Wuppertal:
Historisches Zentrum Wuppertal, 2020.
—. Friedrich Engels. Cologne: PapyRossa, 2018.
—. »Wie zwei ein Compagniegeschäft betrieben: Friedrich Engels’s Beitrag
zum Werk von Karl Marx.« In »Die Natur ist die Probe auf die Dialektik«:
Friedrich Engels kennenlernen, eds. Elmar Altvater et al., 54 – 68. Hamburg: VSA Verlag, 2020.
Herres, Jürgen. »Friedrich Engels: Republikanischer Kommunist und europäischer Gesellschaftskritiker.« In Friedrich Engels: Ein Gespenst geht
um in Europa — Begleitband zur Engelsausstellung 2020, ed. Lars Bluma,
16 – 29. Wuppertal: Historisches Zentrum Wuppertal, 2020.
—. Marx und Engels: Porträt einer intellektuellen Freundschaft. Stuttgart: Reclam, 2018.
Hunt, Tristram. Friedrich Engels: Der Mann, der den Marxismus erfand, transl.
by Klaus-Dieter Schmidt, third edition. Berlin: List, 2020.
Ito, Narihiko. »Realismus und Utopismus.« In Zwischen Utopie und Kritik:
Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker« nach 100 Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer, 23 – 33. Hamburg:
VSA, 1996.
Kopf, Eike. »Marx ohne Engels — das wäre kaum eine halbe Sache geworden.«
In »Die Natur ist die Probe auf die Dialektik«: Friedrich Engels kennenlernen, eds. Elmar Altvater et al., 69 – 89. Hamburg: VSA Verlag, 2020.
Engels @ 200: An Introduction
Krätke, Michael. »Friedrich Engels, der erste Marxist.« In Friedrich Engels
oder: Wie ein »Cotton-Lord« den Marxismus erfand, ed. Michael Krätke,
9 – 68. Berlin: Dietz, 2020.
Kuczynski, Thomas. »Die zweite Violine.« In »Die Natur ist die Probe auf
die Dialektik«: Friedrich Engels kennenlernen, eds. Elmar Altvater et al..
27 – 34. Hamburg: VSA Verlag, 2020.
Labica, Georges. »Friedrich Engels — Wissenschaftler und Revolutionär.« in
Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker« nach 100
Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert
Schäfer, 17 – 22. Hamburg: VSA, 1996.
Lafargue, Paul. »Persönliche Erinnerungen.« In Friedrich Engels oder: Wie ein
»Cotton-Lord« den Marxismus erfand, ed. Michael Krätke, 185 – 194. Berlin: Dietz, 2020.
Lehnert, Detlef and Christina Morina, eds. Friedrich Engels und die Sozialdemokratie: Werke und Wirkungen eines Europäers. Berlin: Metropol,
2020.
Lucas, Rainer, Reinhard Pfriem and Hans-Dieter Westhoff. »Einleitung der
Herausgeber.« In Arbeiten am Widerspruch: Friedrich Engels zum 200.
Geburtstag, eds. Rainer Lucas, Reinhard Pfriem and Hans-Dieter Westhoff, 13 – 23. Marburg: Metropolis-Verlag, 2020.
Mayer, Gustav. Friedrich Engels: Eine Biographie, Bd. 1: Friedrich Engels in
seiner Frühzeit, 1820 bis 1851. Berlin: Julius Springer, 1920.
Notz, Gisela. »Auseinandersetzung mit Friedrich Engels’s ›Ursprung der
Familie …‹: … und was er uns heute noch zu sagen hat.« In Arbeiten
am Widerspruch: Friedrich Engels zum 200. Geburtstag, eds. Rainer Lucas,
Reinhard Pfriem and Hans-Dieter Westhoff, 397 – 416. Marburg: Metropolis-Verlag, 2020.
Radziejowski, Janusz. »Roman Rosdolsky: Man, Activist and Scholar.« Science & Society 42, no. 2 (1978): 198 – 210.
Reuter, Julia, Markus Gamper, Christina Möller and Frerk Blome, eds. Vom
Arbeiterkind zur Professur: Sozialer Aufstieg in der Wissenschaft. Autobiographische Notizen und soziobiographische Analysen. Bielefeld: Transcript
Verlag, 2020.
Rhefus, Reiner. Friedrich Engels im Wuppertal: Auf den Spuren des Denkers,
Machers und Revolutionärs im »deutschen Manchester«. Hamburg: VSA,
2020.
Rosdolsky, Roman. Zur Entstehungsgeschichte des Marxschen Kapital. Frankfurt am Main / Vienna, 1968.
23
24
Frank Jacob
Roth, Regina. »›Die Lage der arbeitenden Klasse in England‹ von Engels
im Spiegel ihrer Zeit (1845 – 1892).« In Friedrich Engels: Ein Gespenst geht
um in Europa — Begleitband zur Engelsausstellung 2020, ed. Lars Bluma,
84 – 99. Wuppertal: Historisches Zentrum Wuppertal, 2020.
San Juan, Jr., Epifanio. »Was wir aus Engels’s revolutionärer Ästhetik lernen
können.« In Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker«
nach 100 Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and
Gert Schäfer, 68 – 91. Hamburg: VSA, 1996.
van der Linden, Marcel. »Friedrich Engels’s Herkunft und Lebensleistung:
Eine biografische Skizze.« In »Die Natur ist die Probe auf die Dialektik«:
Friedrich Engels kennenlernen, eds. Elmar Altvater et al., 7 – 26. Hamburg:
VSA Verlag, 2020.
Vonde, Detlef. Auf den Barrikaden: Friedrich Engels und die »gescheiterte Revolution« von 1848 / 49. Wuppertal: Köndgen, 2019.
Notes on Dialectics and History
in Friedrich Engels1
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
Engels was certainly the closest collaborator of Marx. And that — for
those who, with the help of Marxist thought, aim to understand and
effectively criticize bourgeois society — is not a minor thing. It is
worth stressing the issue in a double sense in relation to the two authors in order to formulate an effective critique of capital: first, Engels
was the author of The Condition of the Working Class in England, and
was the person who brought many of the works of Marx (books II
and III of Das Kapital were organized by Engels!) to the wider public;
secondly, it is important to state that special attention must be given
to the »second fiddle« insofar as Engels contributed significantly in
his dialogues with Marx, which is evident in their letters, in the books
they wrote together, and in the close friendship that the two socialists
developed. It is important to note then that when we read Marx, to a
certain extent, we also read Engels. Conversely, when we read Engels,
we also read his friend Marx. For Marxists, there is no possibility of
treating Engels as a secondary figure. At the same time, it is important to point out that in spite of the similitude between both authors‹
ideas and positions (Standpunkt), there are significant differences that
in some crucial topics (such as the question of the organization of the
State and the right to suppress (Aushebung) bourgeois society) can be
decisive for those who embrace Marxism as their frame of reference.
Here we try to delineate an Engelsian treatment of dialectics and
history, mainly taking into consideration his work after The Paris
1
This chapter is a translation of »Apontamentos sobre dialética e história em Friedrich Engels,« Verinotio revista online 20 (2014) ISSN 1981 – 061X. We thank the
author and the journal for the permission to publish this translation.
26
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
Commune, an event impeccably treated by Marx in his The Civil War
in France. This approach is justified in that it is a collaboration between the author of Anti-Dühring and those who later became prominent leaders of the commune and gained prominence in the socialist
camp in Germany, Kautsky and Bernstein. We cannot deal in detail
here with how Engels was appropriated (many times erroneously) by
these authors, who became responsible for the vulgarization of Marxism. Nor can we deal with all the differences between Marx and Engels. We will only approach the topic to the extent that it deals with
the methodological foundation of a critique of capitalist society. We
will demonstrate the way in which Engels’s position fits in this field
without neglecting Marx. In this way, we will show the existence of
certain points of tension in Engels’s work.
The author of Anti-Dühring was explicit in what he wrote about
the necessary critique of common sense: »common sense, a very
respectable character, behind closed doors, between the four walls
of a house, lives truly marvelous adventures, when it dares to enter
the wide field of research.«2 This means that it is necessary to apply
special care when dealing with complex issues such as the State or
history. Without this care, our reasoning could be tainted with a
metaphysical appeal rather than a dialectic one. There would be
a tendency to hypothesize social relations on a daily basis, giving
them a ghostly appearance and reifying them in such a way that it
would be »a unilateral method, limited, abstract« that »gets lost in
unresolvable contradictions since, absorbed by concrete objects, it
cannot see its relationships.«3 The »reflexive determinations« (Reflexionsgestimmungen) of the effective reality (Wirklichkeit) will be
eclipsed by common sense, which makes it necessary to break away
from a linear thought that is too attached to a shallow conception of
the causality of social reality, a conception in which »cause and effect
take the shape of a rigid anti-thesis.«4 In this way, Engels attacked
2
3
4
Friedrich Engels, Anti-Dühring (Rio de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1990), 20.
Ibid.
Ibid.
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
two twin aspects of a »metaphysical« vision. On the one hand, he
criticized the reification of social relationships marked, among other
things, by the loss of a rational and effectively concrete dimension
of the effective reality. On the other hand, he points out that the
highlighted relationship is not simply antithetical or marked by unsolvable antinomies. It is necessary to overcome these antinomies
with a type of thought that »reflects its genesis and its lapse«5 in such
a manner that it is understood as something inseparable from forms
of being (Daseinformen), determinations of existence (Existenzbestimmungen) that are constituted by effectiveness itself. Contrary to
this position, there is »the metaphysical individual« who »thinks in
a whole series of disconnected anti-theses: for him there is only a
simple yes or no, and when he gets out of these molds, he finds only
disorder and confusion.«6
Therefore, we must recognize that there is a critique of the way
in which the quotidian takes form. To the extent that the »speculative method seems to us extremely plausible, because of the so-called
common sense,«7 it is clear that what is opposed to common sense
is not »speculation,« which is nothing more than the other face of
knowledge tied to immediacy. Thus, it would be necessary to question common sense as well as the »speculative method« in a decisive
manner. And this, Engels intended, would be accomplished with the
dialectical method, which had been inherited from Hegel but had
been superseded (aufgehoben) by Marx when he took into account the
contradictions present in the Hegelian system.
This occurred in the exact measure in which the »method« was
centralized, opposing, in Hegel, the »system.«8 The author of Phenomenology of Spirit, then, at the same time that he brought up
something already different from »metaphysics,« did not stop pay-
5
6
7
8
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid.
See Engels, Anti-Dühring.
27
28
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
ing homage to it, even when he tried to supersede it.9 In the words
of Marx, there was a situation in which, »in its mystified form, the
dialectic was a German fashion because it seemed to turn the existent into the sublime,«10 which is linked to the way in which Hegel
equated reconciliation (Vörsonung) and the rationality of the real.11 If
we follow Engels’s reasoning, then in Hegel there was the inability to
follow the very »method« in which, according to the author of AntiDühring, just as would happen with Marx, »movement is a mode of
material existence.«12 That is to say, dialectics would oppose a view
in which concepts »are isolated objects of research, fixed objects, immutable, one observed after the other, each one per se, like something
determined and perennial.«13 Indeed, Hegel himself, according to Engels, would not have been consistent with this:
Indeed, his philosophy still suffered from a great incurable contradiction since, on the one hand, he considered it essential to the historical conception, according to which human history is a process
of development that cannot, by its very nature, find an intellectual
solution to the discovery of what are called absolute truths. On the
other hand, it presents itself as a summary or compendium of those
9
10
11
12
13
According to Salgado, a Hegelian, there is a new form of metaphysics in Hegel:
»There remains the possibility of a metaphysics of reason to replace the metaphysics of understanding« (Joaquim Carlos Salgado, A ideia de justiça em Hegel
(Petrópolis: Loyola, 1996), 56).
Karl Marx, O capital bk. 1, vol. I, transl. by Régis Barbosa and Flávio R. Kothe
(São Paulo: Nova Cultural, 1988), 27.
To a certain extent, according to Engels’s comments, Lukács states: »This reconciliation is, on the one hand, an idealist mystification of unresolvable contradictions, but on the other hand, it expresses at the same time the realist sense
of Hegel, its proximity to the concrete social reality of his time, his profound
knowledge of the real life of human society, his efforts to discover the contradictions of progress in its true battlefield, which is in the economic life of man.«
György Lukács, El joven Hegel y los problemas de la sociedad capitalista, transl. by
Manuel Sacristán (México: Grijalbo, 1963), 413.
Engels, Anti-Dühring, 51.
Ibid., 20.
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
absolute truths. A universal and compact system, definitively shaped,
which is intended to frame both natural science and history, is incompatible with the laws of dialectics.14
The »laws of dialectics« would be incompatible with the Hegelian process, marked, at the same time, by an emphasis on becoming — which
comes from the dialectic between being (Sein) and nothing (Nichts),
according to the author of The Science of Logic — , on movement, and
on a systematic philosophy (»a universal and compact system«) that
conforms to a »summary and compendium« of »absolute truths.«
In other words, the problem of Hegelian dialectics is twofold:
while it would have been a »lesser« dialectic in seeking a systematic
philosophy in which effective reality would be viewed as a certain
closure, it would at the same time have been — in the wake of Shelling — a »greater« dialectic in seeking to frame »natural science and
history« in a universal system with the necessary mediations. On the
one hand, then, the author of Phenomenology of Spirit would have
been inconsistent with his own assumptions; on the other hand, however, with these very assumptions, he would have been taken to a
systematic and universal »application« of the dialectic, which would
require greater care — if we were to follow Engels’s observations.15 And
with that, Hegel was criticized while his merits were recognized, including, by the way, by Marx.
Nevertheless, at this point, some caution is necessary. It must be
noted how the author of Anti-Dühring put himself above the dialectic.
There were »fundamental laws of dialectical thought,« which »do not
exclude but rather imply that the systematic knowledge of the external world in its totality could progress with giant steps generation
after generation.«16 At this point, Engels seems to oppose the system14
15
16
Ibid., 22 – 23.
See Friedrich Engels, Dialética da natureza (Rio de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1979).
Friedrich Engels, Do socialismo utópico ao socialismo científico & Ludwig Feuerbach e o fim da filosofia clássica alemã, transl. by José Severo de C. Pereira (São
Paulo: Fulgor, 1962), 60.
29
30
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
atic character of Hegelian thought with another form of »systematic
knowledge,« a form that would be more open. It is clear that with
this the author wanted to say that we are talking about knowledge of
»the exterior world in its totality« and, in this sense (the separation
between subject and object is already being assumed in the notion of
the »outside world,« essential for any materialist position), he demonstrates a decisive distancing from Hegel, who considers the identical
subject-object of speculative idealism as something essential.17 However, we must recognize that it is still uncomfortable for those who
know the work of Marx, which is marked by the immanence of the
objectivity and historicity of being18 — a diction that intimately links
a »system« (evidently distinct from that of Hegel) to the »fundamental laws of dialectical thought.«
With this intonation, one could, at times, fall into the temptation
of believing that it would be a matter of »correctly applying« a »method« in order to reach a way of apprehending effectiveness that would
be real and effectively dialectical.19 In this sense, contrary to what we
see in Marx20, the »method,« in Engels, could provide an opportunity (if one were not to deal carefully with effectiveness [Wirklichtkeit]) with an epistemological apparatus and not with the real fabric
of reality. Thus, we cannot dismiss a reading according to which there
would be a certain impetus that is simultaneously gnoseological and
logical in its way of apprehending Engels; this is precisely the thesis of
17
18
19
20
It is important to note that certain Marxists tend to disagree with Engels with
regard to the closed character of the Hegelian system. See Paulo Arantes, Hegel e
a ordem do tempo (São Paulo: Hucitec, 1982).
See Vitor Bartoletti Sartori, »De Hegel a Marx: da inflexão ontológica à antítese
direta,« Kriterion 55, no. 130 (2014): 691 – 713.
Marx was clear when he said »the materialist method becomes its own anti-thesis
when it is utilized not as a thread conducting historical research but rather as a
finished model to which one must adapt historical facts« (Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Cultura, arte e literatura: textos escolhidos, transl. by José Paulo Netto
(São Paulo: Expressão Popular, 2010), 119.
See José Chasin, Marx: estatuto ontológico e resolução metodológica (São Paulo:
Boitempo, 2009).
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
an important theoretician like György Lukàcs,21 reinforced by the fact
that Marx’s main collaborator, at the end of his life, tried to develop a
»dialectic of nature,« a theme that, unfortunately, we cannot deal with
in this article but is highly polemical in the Marxist literature.
We should note that it is not that nature ought to be considered
in a static way, or that there is a tight opposition between the spirit
sciences and the natural sciences, as Löwy22 seems to point out in the
footsteps of Dilthey. It happens, however, that its movement could
not, as Engels sometimes implied,23 be quasi-deduced from the »laws
of dialectics.« Engels had a very peculiar way of dealing with dialectics, searching for the »laws of dialectics« (»interdependency of opposites,« »quantitative leap,« and »negation of negation«) at the same
time as he criticized a way of thinking marked by »the intellectual
solution in the discovery« of »what are called absolute truths,« which
shelter a »compact universal system.« In other words, as much as the
»spirit« of the author’s text could diametrically oppose a Hegelian »intellectual solution,« it merges with a certain way of thinking in which
the »method,« at times, seems to be taken as dissociated and dissociable from the object (Gegenstand) and from objectivity itself. In Marx,
there is no being (Wessen) lacking determinations and marked, logically, by the becoming of movement, but there is an understanding
of categories as ways of being driven by historicity that break with a
state of being »concentrated in its static condition«24 only insofar as
it deals with the complex mediations between man and nature, and
among humans themselves (to the extent that human praxis, realized
under conditions linked by the past,25 is focused more on its own immanence of »sensitive human activity« [sinnlich menchliche Tätigkeit]).
21
22
23
24
25
See György Lukács, Prolegômenos para uma ontologia do ser social, transl. by Lya
Luft and Rodnei Nascimento (São Paulo: Boitempo, 2010).
See Michel Löwy, As aventuras de Karl Marx contra o Barão de Münchhausen (São
Paulo: Cortez, 1994).
Engels, Dialética.
Engels, Anti-Dühring, 20.
As Marx says, »men make their own history, but they do not make it according
to their free will; they do not make it under circumstances that they choose
31
32
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
In this specific sense, as Lukács has already suggested in The History of Class Consciousness26 — although with a different prism in his
critique of Engels — , it may be possible to say that the author of
Anti-Dühring stopped focusing on decisive aspects of the praxis inasmuch as he brought to light the »laws of dialectics.« In a way, the
position according to which it would not be a question of opposing
the preceding idealism would be eclipsed by a contemplative materialistic position in which »the object [objekts], reality [Wirklichtkeit],
the sensitive [Sinnlichtkeit] is apprehended in the form of the object
or contemplation [Anschauung] but not as sensitive human activity,
as a practice [praxis], not subjectively.«27 Engels, in this sense, would
bring with him a limited conception of dialectics.
At the same time that he approached Hegel, Engels criticized
him based on the opposition of »system« and »method«; he came to
stress the autarchy of effective reality, breaking with the conception of
Hegelian science (related to the systematic treatment of all knowledge
and reality). We also should take into consideration this aspect of the
tensions within the thought of the author of Anti-Dühring:
From the moment that each science has to account for its position in
the Universal framework of things and the knowledge of those things,
there is no longer room for a science especially dedicated to the study
of universal concatenations. From the previous philosophy, with its
own existence, there only remains afoot the theory of thinking and its
laws: formal logic and dialectics. The rest is dissolved in the positive
science of nature and history.28
26
27
28
but under those that they face directly, linked and transmitted by the past. The
tradition of all dead generations oppresses, like a nightmare, the brains of those
who are alive.« Karl Marx, O 18 Brumário de Luís Bonaparte, transl. by Leandro
Konder and Renato Guimarães (Rio de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1997), 21.
György Lukács, História e consciência de classe, transl. by Rodnei Nascimento
(São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2003).
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, A ideologia alemã, transl. by Rubens Enderle
(São Paulo: Boitempo, 2007), 533.
Engels, Socialismo utópico, 60 – 61.
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
Engels was clear about what came to be known as »the end of classical
German philosophy,«29 concatenated to the extent that the task of
philosophy would no longer refer to a posture that would not be, in
itself, a taken position and would refer to praxis, »sensitive human
activity« being something that would not accept the rigid dichotomy
between reason and sensitivity, nor the dissolution of the sensitive
into a form of Aufhebung in reason. Thus, according to the appreciation of the immanence of effective reality, Engels was consistent in
valuing science. He also emphasized the impossibility of any form
of hypostasis of universality30 (which, at times, seemed to happen in
Hegel’s own Science and Logic, and in Plato before him), with reason. However, maybe Engels was in a rush to deal with philosophy
as something that remains only a »theory of thinking and its law,«
something that refers to a conception as a bias that can, in some circumstances, acquire a memorable gnoseological tonality in which it is
a matter of »applying« a »method« marked by the valorization of the
»dialectical laws« — which did not arrive, in the author, at a »compendium« of »absolute truths,« given that there was a clear valorization
of the correct apprehension of effective reality when it recognized the
importance of the »positive science of history.« Nevertheless, the issue
can become complex if we consider that there seems to be a certain
separation between »formal logic and dialectics« on the one hand and
»the positive science of nature and of history« on the other. That is
to say, there seems to be the possibility of thinking in terms of categories without considering »forms of being, determinations of existence«; thus, there is a certain counter-position to Marxist thought on
this specific point. The »science of history« mentioned earlier brings
with it the immanence of dialectics, considered the very movement
29
30
Ibid.
This a risk that could not be taken: as Marx had already stated in 1842, the best
hypothesis runs the risk of falling into the trap of Hegelian dialectic, which,
»as a universal in itself, I turned into something independent; it is immediately
mistaken with empirical existence and then the finite is tuned in an uncritical
manner into the expression of an idea.« Marx and Engels, A ideologia alemã, 77.
33
34
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
of the real, and now the question emerges in a somewhat different
way, breaking apart — at least when it comes to exposition (Darstellung) — the unity between »method« and effective reality.
It is clear that Engels did not create a simple apology for the partial
sciences, being consistent with a position that he, along with Marx,
defended in German Ideology.31 He placed them in a position to be
criticized in that he highlighted only the »positive science of nature
and history.« However, it is impossible not to notice a certain opposition between »the laws of dialectics,« present in what was left of
the philosophy of yore, and the apprehension of historical objectivity
itself, since Marx explicitly said that the »materialist method« presents itself »as a conducting thread of historical investigation« and is
inseparable from it, from the apprehension of its own effective reality.
Marx emphasized in Capital that »it is, without doubt, necessary
to distinguish the method of presentation [Darstellungsweise], formally, from the method of research [Forsuchungweise].«32 In this sense, we
can understand Engels’s note as him being careful not to juxtapose
both moments of the apprehension of the real. However, it is important to note that Engels seems to open the door to misunderstandings,
since his diction is more accessible to those who have not been initiated into the thought that Marx and the author criticized (»speculative
method«) — or who are unconcerned with the themes that permeated
the »previous philosophy« — and more obscure for those who seek
to see the way in which the conception developed by the author of
German Ideology differentiates itself from the conception of Hegel. In
other words, Engels is didactic when he seeks to offer a systematic
treatment of the themes of both dialectics and history (and at this
point he has perhaps come too close to the language of »common
sense«), and it seems confusing since he ends by leaving the possibility for the belief that it would be possible to depart from certain
31
32
In that work, the authors said: »There is no history of politics, of right, of science,
of art, of religion, etc.« Marx and Engels, A ideologia alemã, 77.
Marx, O capital I, 26.
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
epistemic dissociations between the »laws of dialectics,« »method,«
and effective reality.
When we say »leaving the possibility,« an important caveat is necessary: it seems to us that the intention of Engels was not to draw a
wall between the above-mentioned aspects, quite the contrary. However, maybe it is possible to find in this field of Engelsian theory the
germs of the notorious distinction — divulged by the Stalinist vulgate — between »materialist dialectics« and »historical materialism,«
which, verbally, sought to overcome the opposition between the
present position in the partial sciences and the »speculation« marked
by a certain hypostasis of the »laws of dialectics.« That is to say, the
Engelsian critique of common sense and the speculative method was
powerful, so powerful that it went so far as to be able to oppose even
those who would follow its author.
Sometimes, therefore, the »mode of exposition« used by Engels
was not the best, oscillating between the systematically exposed »laws
of dialectics« and the apprehension of effective reality itself, created
as a beacon of the »laws of dialectics« and carried out as a »positive
science of history.« It is necessary to realize, however, that in no way
did the author seek, ontologically, to distinguish that which — in exposition — he separated dialectically.
Reason itself could not be considered except in connection with
effectiveness in the following sense:
The French philosophers of the eighteenth century that paved the way
for the Revolution appealed to reason as the only judge of everything
that exists. They intended to establish a rational state, and anything
that contradicted eternal reason was to be buried without pity. (…)
Indeed, that eternal reason was nothing but the idealized intelligence
of the middle-class men of that period, the class from which the
bourgeoisie would emerge.33
33
Engels, Anti-Dühring, 223.
35
36
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
When trying to understand history, reason was seen by Engels, as by
Marx, as a unitary process in which we cannot separate the »totality
of relationships of production,« »the economic structure of society,«
the »political and judicial superstructure,« and »determined forms of
consciousness,« in short, every »process of intellectual, political and
social life.«34 For Engels, the notion of reason was, therefore, something inseparable from the contradictory development of the social
process as a whole, being effective not to the extent that »the rational
is real and the real is rational«35 but rather insofar as it is a matter
of seeing history as something made by man himself in the midst
of objective social conflicts and with the mediation of »ideological
forms, under which men acquire consciousness of those conflicts and
confront them [ideologischen Formen, worin sich die Menchen dieses
Konflikts bewusst werden und inh ausfechten].«36 The notion of reason,
then, although it may contain within itself certain gnoseological detours, is essentially considered when, in the same way that it tried
to mark itself as an »eternal reason,« it is defined by the finitude of
the bourgeois society emerging at the time. The notion is inseparable
from its ontological basis.
If Engels said that the French philosophers played an essential role
in preparing the ground for the French Revolution, then it is obvious
that he did not consider history as something produced by philosophers; however, at the same time, he could not fail to emphasize that
the influence of »ideological forms« could be left aside when dealing
with the »consciousness« of social conflicts, a consciousness that, in
the midst of determined material conditions, could be decisive.
34
35
36
Karl Marx, Contribuição à crítica da economia política, transl. by Florestan Fernandes (São Paulo: Expressão Popular, 2009), 47.
Georg Hegel, Princípios da filosofia do direito, transl. by Orlando Vittorino (São
Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2003), xxxvi.
Marx, Contribuição, 46. For a detailed treatment of this ideology, see Ester Vaisman, »A ideologia e sua determinação ontological,« Verinotio — Revista on-line de
Filosofia e Ciências Humanas 12 (2010): 40 – 64.
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
Consciousness or unconsciousness of the way in which effective
reality is actually and effectively conformed is not a »scholastic matter«; at the same time, however, it is not the criterion for dealing with
»ideological forms,« not least because, as Marx pointed out, men often operate through determinations of existence of which they are not
fully aware — »they do not know it, but they do it [Sie wissen das nicht,
aber sie tun es].«37 Thus, in the case brought up by Engels, even if the
French philosophers had used a concept of reason that would be, in
the midst of the social process of the development of capitalist society,
ineluctably reconciled with the vicissitudes of the emerging bourgeois
society, it would not be, on the part of these philosophers, an act of
simple bad faith, of mere deception. Before, there was a prevalence of
objective determinations that made »eternal reason,« in fact, operate
amid the irrationality of capitalist effectiveness. Bearing this in mind,
post festum, it was possible for Engels to say that »eternal reason was
nothing but the idealized intelligence of middle-class man of those
times, from which the bourgeoisie would emerge.«
To the same extent that reason was placed as timeless and eternal,
therefore, temporality and finitude left their indelible marks, and thus
there did not exist a watertight separation between the immanence of
objective determinations of the real and a method conceived, to a certain extent, in a gnoseological manner in the treatment of the author
of Anti-Dühring. For him, the »Rational State« was not, then, simply
gnoseologically mistaken (to the extent that it would not be possible for it to become effective); the effective reality that came from
the process that culminated in the French Revolution carried with
it the role that this ideal — this »ideological form« — played in men’s
acquisition of consciousness of their own time in such a way that,
even though this consciousness might have been mistaken from the
gnoseological point of view, it fulfilled its function. In other words,
we can see a certain tension in the Engelsian text here too.
37
Karl Marx, O capital bk. 1, vol. II, transl. by Régis Barbosa and Flávio R. Kothe
(São Paulo: Nova Cultural, 1996), 200.
37
38
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
Thus, at this moment, we can see that, at times, Engels’s manner of
exposition seems to go against the very thing that the author wants to
say. This happens, however, to the extent that the mode of exposition
and the mode of research need to gain greater relevance; we will focus
on this aspect in the next part of this text, in which the question of
history appears with special emphasis.
From what we have discussed, Engels’s exposition was not always
favorable for a better understanding of his work and the work of
Marx. This happened because, in Engels, the concept of dialectics
developed in a systematic manner in opposition to Marx’s procedure,
in which the immanent approach is more prominent. Evidently, there
are statements of a general character in the Marxist work, but they
were always related to a careful analysis of effective reality, with the
categories always being presented as »forms of being, determinations
of existence.« In Engels, the issue is more nuanced.
Maybe the problem is expressed more penetratingly when we take
into account the conception that that spoke of »laws of dialectics«
and, at the same time, when it is pointed out categorically that, »according to the materialist conception, the decisive factor in history
is, ultimately, the production and reproduction of immediate life.«38
Sometimes, when dealing with history, the author of Anti-Dühring
presented generalizations that were interpreted in an erroneous
manner by the self-styled Marxist vulgate (i. e., by Stalinism). The
reference to the »last resort« — placed alongside the »laws of dialectics« — resulted in its long and infamous career, leading to the most
diverse scholarly and economic resources, even in some authors held
in high regard, such as Bukharin, criticized by Lukács39 and Gramsci.40
It should be noted that it is not that the Engelsian passage is abso38
39
40
Friedrich Engels, Origem da família, da propriedade privada e do estado, transl. by
Ruth M. Klaus (São Paulo: Centauro, 2002), 10.
Lukács, História e consciência.
Antonio Gramsci, Maquiavel: notas sobre o estado e a política. Cadernos do
cárcere, vol. 3, transl. by Carlos Nelson Coutinho (Rio de Janeiro: Civilização
Brasileira, 2002).
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
lutely incompatible with the Marxist conception. However, there is
a considerable difference between the emphasis on the »real basis«41
and speaking of a »decisive factor in history.« The passage by Engels
made it seem as if the »ideological forms under which men acquire
consciousness« are, »in the last resort,« no more than epiphenomena.
From what has been stated above, even in Engels, this is not true.
If »the French philosophers of the eighteenth century … paved the
way to the Revolution,« this happened to the extent that the »decisive
factor« derived from human activity itself, an activity mediated by the
relationships of production, by the »judicial and political superstructure,« and certainly by ideology. This activity is »sensitive human activity,« praxis, which implies the highly important role of consciousness. It is true that »it is not consciousness that determines life, but
life that determines consciousness«42; however, it is equally the case
that it is through ideology that, oftentimes, men acquire consciousness of social conflicts and seek to act upon them. Let us synthesize:
in Engel’s exposition, the way in which the different spheres of the
social being take shape as reflective determinations was sometimes
obscured, giving the impression of it being a social process that possesses a kind of hidden engine that exercises unilateral determination.
This, in turn, occurred while the »last resort« was a much less precise
image than the one used by Marx, that of the »preponderant moment« (übergreifendes Moment) placed in social production, which is
»the effective starting point … the point at which the whole process
takes place again.«43 Thus, once again, the exposition hinders the understanding of the Engelsian text.
It happens, however, that the objective concatenations of history
are effectively seen in a somewhat automatic manner in Engels: when
dealing with the first Bonaparte and the historical situation of France,
for example, Engels — faced with historical necessity and the »laws
of dialectics« — tended to eclipse the role of consciousness, and even
41
42
43
Marx and Engels, A ideologia alemã; Marx, Contribuição.
Marx and Engels, A ideologia alemã, 94.
Karl Marx, Grundrisse, transl. by Mário Duayer (São Paulo: Boitempo, 2011), 49.
39
40
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
that of individual differences, stating that if it had not been Napoleon,
another individual would have taken his place. In a century like the
nineteenth century, strongly influenced by the specter of the Little
Corporal, the position of the author of Anti-Dühring undoubtedly
deserves criticism. First, Engels dealt with Napoleon’s shadow, a phenomenon that certainly had deep social roots (from which he could
not be dissociated), but he also depended on the personality of the
Emperor. Amidst the »laws of dialectics,« we can see the failure of the
republican model of the French Revolution44 as well as the contradictory way in which this failure took place in 18 Brumaire as something
necessary and in such a way that there seems to be a certain logical
necessity directing history in the way conceived by Engels.45
That is to say that even though Hegel is strongly criticized, his
influence can be sensed in Engels. While Marx had already remarked
that »the philosophical moment is not the logic of the thing, but
the thing of logic,«46 the main collaborator of Marx seems, at times,
to go against Marx in some specific points. There is an important
point to be considered here: the mode of research. Engels made a very
correct point about the development of bourgeois society when he
said that »by turning things into commodities, capitalist production
destroyed all the old traditional relationships and replaced inherited
customs and historical rights with buying and selling, with the ›free
contract‹«47. This passage can be supported by many references in
44
Felipe Ramos Musseti, »Marx e a constituição da república francesa de 1848,«
Verinotio — Revista on-line de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas 19 (2015).
45 Engels stated that »it was a coincidence that Napoleon Bonaparte, precisely a
Corsican, became a Military Dictator that the French Republic needed, exhausted by war. It can be demonstrated that without Napoleon, another man would
have fulfilled that function given the fact that the person in question was always
found as soon as it became necessary. Behold also the cases of Caesar, Augustus,
Cromwell, etc.« Friedrich Engels, »Brief an Walther Borgius in Breslau (Heinz
Starkenburg) (Carta a W. Borgius em Bratislava — Heinz Starkenburg de 25 de
Janeiro de 1894),« in MEW 39: 206.
46 Karl Marx, »Introdução,« in Crítica à filosofia do direito de Hegel, transl. by
Rubens Enderle and Leonardo de Deus (São Paulo, Boitempo, 2005), 39.
47 Engels, Origem da família, 93.
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
Marx. However, when it comes to understanding the different ways
in which »traditional relationships« are destroyed, we must highlight
certain points.
The first point concerns the fact that the »traditional relations«
Engels mentions still existed in various countries when he wrote the
sentence cited above, and Engels was, obviously, aware of this. The
second point is related to the specificity of the way in which the said
process could take place under different social and historical conditions. With this point in mind, Engels said the following about the
social commune and the possibility of the social development of socialism in Russia: »From India to Russia, the form of society in which
this isolation predominated always found in it its complement. The
Russian state, not only in general terms but in its specific form, the
Czarist despotism, instead of hanging in the air, is a necessary and
logical consequence of the social conditions of Russia.«48
The first issue that stands out is the consideration of Russia and India together. When dealing with the particularity of capitalist development, Engels did not fail to consider the concrete manner in which
bourgeois society developed under different conditions and historical
contradictions. When dealing with the peculiarities of the countries,
therefore, Engels believed that he could place India and Russia in the
same field. In this way, just as the complement of the rural commune
(with its relative isolation) was a manifestation in India of »oriental
despotism,« the same situation would take place in the Russian context. This would happen to the extent that there would be a certain
confluence between »oriental despotism« and »czarist despotism.« In
other words, there seems to be a solid analysis of the immanence of
the effective reality behind Engels’s position, which would be focused
on the fact that there would be »a necessary and logical consequence
to the Russian social conditions.« And here the problems reemerge.
48
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Lutas de classes na Rússia (São Paulo: Boitempo
Editorial, 2013), 51.
41
42
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
A certain theological and logicizing tone of a Hegelian nature
seems to be present in Engels’s position, as he saw the Russian process
as having a »necessary and logical« direction, that is, with an objective
form of conformation that would not bring in any other possibilities
than the development of a modern capitalist society. Later, the author
would say that »the way things were, there was no alternative.«49 In
other words, in view of the »laws of dialectics,« Engels may not have
gone deep enough in terms of his research, and it is important to say
that, against the challenges from Russian militants about the possibility to achieve socialism, Marx began to study this issue. It is also
important to understand how this happened.
For us to be fair to Engels, it is necessary to say that Marx also
spoke of something similar to the »laws of dialectics.« Marx made reference, in perhaps one of his most problematic texts on the situation
of India in the face of British colonization, to an »immutable law of
history.« In other words, we cannot blame Engels for a certain slip
in his exposition. When dealing with India, a country that has been
invaded several times by different peoples, Marx pointed out that
»according to the immutable law of history, barbaric conquerors are
conquered by the superior civilization of the peoples conquered by
them.«50 The Indian situation, until the British invasion, would not
have changed substantially since the Indian civilization was superior
to that of those who had invaded the country previously. British domination, thus, despite being atrocious, would bring with it progress by
making possible a rupture with a form of domination based precisely
on what Engels called a combination of isolation and despotism, providing, in the late development, the foundations for the demise of
British — and capitalist — domination in the Indian territory. Marx,
therefore, does not seem to simply »apply« the »laws of dialectics.«
Even if his diction is problematic, we can see that immanence already
appears insofar as »history« and »dialectics« are not separated, tak49
50
Ibid., 139.
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Acerca del colonialismo (Buenos Aires: Editorial
Utopia Libertaria, 2009), 48.
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
ing into account the specificity of the Indian case, as opposed to the
advance of capitalism in a typical form, as happened in England. In
other words, historical development is uneven, and we always have
to take into account the objectivity and historicity of the social being
himself, with praxis being the criterion for obtaining them, so much
so that Marx clearly highlighted the following with regard to primitive accumulation:51
The chapter on primitive accumulation aims exclusively at delineating a route through which, in Western Europe, the capitalistic order
emerged from the bowels of the feudal economic order. Therefore,
it accompanies the movement that divorced the producer from his
means of production, transforming the former into a wage earner
(a proletarian in the modern sense of the word) and the latter into
capital.52
At the same time that Marx mentioned the »immutable law of history,« he stressed that the way in which bourgeois society placed itself
in Capital only took Western Europe into account and, therefore, not
India or Russia. In this sense, in order to deal with these two countries, careful research was necessary before a judgment could be made
about the peculiarity of the historical development of each one.53
Thus, there is an intimate relationship between that which is placed
in a quite large degree of generality and the particular cases; however,
we can never ignore any of these aspects. According to the German
author, in some cases they could be
51
52
53
Primitive accumulation got underway in India through colonialism, and it was
a possibility in Russia in the face of the disintegrating tendencies that tried to
impose themselves upon the Russian commune.
Marx and Engels, Lutas de classes, 66
On this point, the use of quotation marks is essential: »The ›historical fatalism‹
of this movement is restricted to the countries of Western Europe.« Ibid., 89.
43
44
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
[e]vents of a striking analogy but which take place in different historical environments leading to totally different results. When you
study each one of these developments separately, we can easily figure
out the key to this phenomenon. However, we will never arrive at
this with a historical-philosophical master key whose supreme virtue
consists of being supra-historical.54
Sometimes there would be »different historical environments leading to totally different results,« and in these cases, it must be said,
Marx disagreed with Engels on this point about Russia: while Engels
took India and Russia together, that is not what Marx did in Capital,
which was emphatic about the prospect of a distinct development of
Russia, which had the possibility of a direct transition to socialism
from the rural commune.55
The Russian situation would be different in that the peasantry itself
would not be marked by private ownership of the means of production. In England, »in the final analysis, there is a transformation of one
form of private property into another form of private property. The
land in the hands of Russian peasants has never been their property.«56
There would also be the permanence of the rural commune in the middle of the capitalist development that would be inseparable from Russia, and thus, for reasons that we cannot go into here, Marx said that
»it can, therefore, become the direct starting point of the economic
system towards which modern society drifts and sheds its skin without
having to commit suicide.«57 In other words, in view of the uneven development of the history of capitalist society, not only would it be impossible to homogenize solutions to the problems of bourgeois society,
54
55
56
57
Ibid., 69.
After much study, Marx pointed out that »the conclusion at which I arrived is
the following: If Russia continues to pursue the path she has followed since 1861,
she will lose the finest chance ever offered by history to a nation, in order to
undergo all the fatal vicissitudes of the capitalist regime.« Ibid., 66.
Ibid., 89.
Ibid., 100.
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
it would also be a matter of apprehending the real and effective fabric
and particularity of each social formation, thus making it necessary to
be very careful in one’s research, which would imply the impossibility
of predictions of or narrative concatenations that did not have solid
support in the historicity and the objectivity of the social being. With
this, Marx again distinguished himself from Engels by bringing greater
care to these issues: in the face of this uneven development, he tried
to delineate the difference between India and Russia in a rigorous and
cautious way. First, he highlighted the »contemporaneity of the capitalist production: it is precisely thanks to the contemporary nature
of capitalist production that it can appropriate all positive achievements, and this without going through its unpleasant vicissitudes.«
Subsequently, he emphasized how this had implications, pointing out
that »Russia does not live isolated from the modern world, nor was it
the victim of a foreign conqueror, as were the East Indies.«58 In this
sense, there is very special care with regard to research, something that,
of course, Engels always had in mind but could not always put into
practice with the necessary diligence (it is perhaps possible to point out
some slightly hurried generalizations even in the classic The Origin of
the Family, Private Property and the State).
In this short contribution, we have made some notes about the theorizing of Engels on »methodological« aspects. These aspects, apparently irrelevant when dealing with analyses of conjecture or political
positions, proved decisive in the end. Even when it comes to one of the
greatest confluences in the history of social thought (the one between
Marx and Engels), the question arose in a strident manner. To the extent that the authors shared substantive positions, it was possible to see
how a conception of dialectics and history that barely differs in some
points can effectively bring forth different concrete positions to the
surface. In view of these positions, we notice that, in Marx, research
was essential, and the exposition was realized with difficulty, seeking
to express in the best possible way that which was obtained through
58
Ibid., 90.
45
46
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
careful research. In Engels, of course, there was never any deliberate
neglect with regard to research or seeking objective concatenations
present in the effective reality itself; nevertheless, using a certain tone,
sometimes logical, and supported by the »laws of dialectics,« the German philosopher may have stumbled at times. This happened with
regard to the mode of exposition, which tends to be too systematic in
some of its essential points (and this may have given rise to no less than
a century of vulgar »Marxism«), as well as with regard to the method
of research that, in the face of certain previous systematic treatments,
may have been neglected at times. Such tension, from what we have
seen, is the concrete expression of a certain Engelsian treatment that
brings with it a conflicting relationship between an exposition that, at
certain moments, borders on the gnoseological understanding of the
method and a concrete position that seeks, with care, to deal with the
real fabric of the effective reality. Thus, if Engels pointed out in Hegel a
»contradiction between system and method,« certain »contradictions«
can perhaps be pointed out in the author of Anti-Dühring. This does
not diminish his merits in the least; it only gives a necessary warning to
all those who look at Marx’s and Engels’s texts as sources of assistance
in the determined critique of capitalist society. Even if Engels was
rushed at times, for us, self-criticism is, and always will be, essential.
Translated by Gilmar Visoni-Alonzo
Works Cited
Arantes, Paulo. Hegel e a ordem do tempo. São Paulo: Hucitec, 1982.
Chasin, José. Marx: estatuto ontológico e resolução metodológica. São Paulo:
Boitempo, 2009.
Engels, Friedrich. Do socialismo utópico ao socialismo científico & Ludwig
Feuerbach e o fim da filosofia clássica alemã. Translated by José Severo de
C. Pereira. São Paulo: Fulgor, 1962.
Notes on Dialectics and History in Friedrich Engels
—. »Brief an Walther Borgius in Breslau (Heinz Starkenburg) (Carta a W.
Borgius em Bratislava — Heinz Starkenburg de 25 de Janeiro de 1894).« In
Marx / Engels Werke Vol. 39. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1968.
—. Dialética da natureza. Rio de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1979.
—. Anti-Dühring. Rio de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1990.
—. Origem da família, da propriedade privada e do estado. Translated by Ruth
M. Klaus. São Paulo: Centauro, 2002.
Engels, Friedrich and Karl Kautsky. O socialismo jurídico. Translated by Márcio Naves and Lívia Cotrim. São Paulo: Boitempo, 2012.
Gramsci, Antonio. Maquiavel: notas sobre o estado e a política. Cadernos do
cárcere vol. III. Translated by Carlos Nelson Coutinho. Rio de Janeiro:
Civilização Brasileira, 2002.
Hegel, Georg. Princípios da filosofia do direito. Translated by Orlando Vittorino. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2003.
Löwy, Michel. As aventuras de Karl Marx contra o Barão de Münchhausen. São
Paulo: Cortez, 1994.
Lukács, György. El joven Hegel y los problemas de la sociedad capitalista. Translated by Manuel Sacristán. México: Grijalbo, 1963.
—. História e consciência de classe. Translated by Rodnei Nascimento. São
Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2003.
—. Prolegômenos para uma ontologia do ser social. Translated by Lya Luft and
Rodnei Nascimento. São Paulo: Boitempo, 2010.
Marx, Karl. Grundrisse der Kritik der politichen ökonomie. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1953.
—. »Kritik des Goethaer Programms.« In Marx / Engels Werke Vol. 19. Berlin:
Dietz Verlag, 1962.
—. O capital bk. 1, vol. I. Translated by Régis Barbosa and Flávio R. Kothe.
São Paulo: Nova Cultural, 1988.
—. Grundrisse. Translated by Martin Nicolaus. London: Penguin Books, 1993.
—. O capital bk. 1, vol. II. Translated by Régis Barbosa and Flávio R. Kothe.
São Paulo: Nova Cultural, 1996.
—. O 18 Brumário de Luís Bonaparte. Translated by Leandro Konder and
Renato Guimarães. Rio de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1997.
—. »Introdução.« In Crítica à filosofia do direito de Hegel. Translated by
Rubens Enderle and Leonardo de Deus. São Paulo, Boitempo, 2005.
47
48
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori
—. Contribuição à crítica da economia política. Translated by Florestan Fernandes. São Paulo: Expressão Popular, 2009.
—. Grundrisse. Translated by Mário Duayer. São Paulo: Boitempo, 2011.
—. O capital. Translated by Rubens Enderle. São Paulo: Boitempo, 2013.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. »Die deutsche Ideologie.« In Marx / Engels
Werke Vol. 3. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1968.
—. A ideologia alemã. Translated by Luís Cláudio de Castro e Costa. São
Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2001.
—. A ideologia alemã. Translated by Rubens Enderle. São Paulo: Boitempo,
2007.
—. Acerca del colonialismo. Buenos Aires: Editorial Utopia Libertaria, 2009.
—. Cultura, arte e literatura: textos escolhidos. Translated by José Paulo Netto.
São Paulo: Expressão Popular, 2010.
—. Lutas de classes na Rússia. São Paulo: Boitempo Editorial, 2013.
Musseti, Felipe Ramos. »Marx e a constituição da república francesa de 1848.«
Verinotio — Revista on-line de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas 19 (2015):
144 – 159.
Salgado, Joaquim Carlos. A ideia de justiça em Hegel. Petrópolis: Loyola, 1996.
Sartori, Vitor Bartoletti. »De Hegel a Marx: da inflexão ontológica à antítese
direta.« Kriterion 55, no. 130 (2014): 691 – 713.
Vaisman, Ester. »A ideologia e sua determinação ontológica.« Verinotio — Revista on-line de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas 12 (2010): 40 – 64.
Friedrich Engels
and Revolution Theory
The Legacy of a Revolutionary Life
Frank Jacob
Introduction
Friedrich Engels was a revolutionary by heart, who never, although
having witnessed failed revolutions in 1848 and 1871, gave up believing
in its final success. He might have considered himself as second fiddle
to Karl Marx,1 but when it comes to the study and the attempt to theoretically explain revolutions as a phenomenon of modernity and the final aim of the communist movement, he was as important as his friend,
and together, these »revolutionary twins«2 were actively involved in
finding an explanation for the course of revolutionary processes. Their
contemporaries considered Engels to be Marx’s alter ego,3 and it is true
that both of them shared many thoughts, although the latter would remain the more important, at least with regard to the consciousness of
the masses. Nevertheless, Engels not only played an important role in
the intellectual development of Marx, he can and also should be taken
seriously as an intellectual of great ability.4 The rise of Marx as one of
1
2
3
4
Sigmund Neumann and Mark von Hagen, »Engels and Marx on Revolution,
War, and the Army in Society,« in Makers of Modern Strategy from Machiavelli to
the Nuclear Age, ed. Peter Paret (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1986),
264.
Oscar J. Hammen, »Alienation, Communism, and Revolution in the Marx-Engels
Briefwechsel,« Journal of the History of Ideas 33, no. 1 (1972): 80.
J. D. Hunley, Life and Thought of Friedrich Engels: A Reinterpretation of His Life
and Thought (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991), 47.
Samuel Hollander, Friedrich Engels and Marxian Political Economy (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2011), 279 – 313.
50
Frank Jacob
the most well-known intellectuals of the 19th century was without any
doubt only possible due to the support of Engels, who, as the economist Samuel Hollander emphasizes, was »more royalist than the king«5
and promoted and even finished important parts of Marx’s own work.
Many of the latter’s texts would not have existed without Engel’s influence, and the textual production of Marx and Engels was a cooperative
venture most of the time. When Marx was invited to write articles for
the New York Daily Tribune, Putnam’s Monthly, and The New American
Cyclopaedia, Engels translated some of his friend’s texts and also gave
him material that was eventually published under the former’s name.6
And Capital, especially volumes 2 and 3, would never have seen the
light of day without the hard work of Engels.7
Whenever Marx needed advice, he would consult Engels, who
also supported his friend financially for many years.8 The former was
thankful for this support, as he highlighted in a letter to Engels on 7
May 1867: »Without you, l would never have been able to bring the
work to completion, and I assure you, it has always weighed on my
conscience like an Alp that you have dissipated your splendid energy
and let it rust on commercial matters, principally on my account, and
into the bargain, still had to participate vicariously in all my minor
troubles.«9 It is ironic that Engels was accused by many scholars, and
Marxists in particular, for having revised Marx’s intentional ideas and
therefore paved the way for all the misery that has been caused by
dogmatic Marxism in the years ever since.10 Hence, and regardless of
such criticism, Engels, especially 200 years after his birth, needs to be
reconsidered and deserves to be treated as equally important as Marx.
Considering the number of works this »open-minded, experimental,
5
6
7
8
9
10
Ibid., 279.
Hunley, Life and Thought, 127.
Ibid., 137.
Ibid., 134.
Cited in ibid., 138.
Ibid., 96.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
heretical thinker«11 has left, it is very much worthwhile to have a closer
look at his thoughts, especially since the historical interpretations of
»Marxian theory« are related to his ideas and attempts to better understand the world and the forces that created it.12
It should be taken into account that Gustav Mayer’s biography
is still one of the best about Friedrich Engels;13 however, his life and
work have unfortunately not attracted as much attention as those
of Marx. Of course, most of these writings »were carried out as part
of a mutual collaboration with Marx,«14 but there are »increasing
attempts to view and treat Engels as separate and apart from Marx.«
Although Indian politician and intellectual Rustam Singh argued
that »[t]here may be some merit in these attempts, but, in our view,
the separation creates more problems than it solves,«15 it seems to be
valuable to take a closer look at Engels, especially when one dives
into revolution theory in relation to Marxism. Naturally, and due
to the mentioned working process the two intellectuals applied, »to
study Engels separately … represents a very difficult task.«16 Martin Berger also remarked with regard to the overlap of ideas in the
collected works of Marx and Engels that »[i]n the background of
most studies of Marx and Marxism lurks the pale figure of Fried11
12
13
14
15
16
Gert Schäfer, »Friedrich Engels: Builder of Closed Systems?« Science & Society 62,
no. 1 (1998), Friedrich Engels: A Critical Centenary Appreciation: 35.
Eric R. Wolf, »The Peasant War in Germany: Friedrich Engels as Social Historian,« Science & Society 51, no. 1 (1987): 82.
Gustav Mayer, Friedrich Engels: Eine Biographie, 2 vols. (Berlin: Springer,
1920 – 1933). For an early review of vol. 1 see Hermann Oncken, »Friedrich Engels
und die Anfänge des deutschen Kommunismus,« Historische Zeitschrift 123, no. 2
(1921): 241 – 242.
Elvira Concheiro, »A Century after His Death: Friedrich Engels and the Concept of Political Parties,« Science & Society 62, no. 1 (1998), Friedrich Engels: A
Critical Centenary Appreciation: 164.
Rustam Singh, »Status of Violence in Marx’s Theory of Revolution,« Economic
and Political Weekly 24, no. 4 (1989): 9. A similar view is expressed in Edmund
Silberner, The Problem of War in Nineteenth Century Economic Thought (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1946), 251.
Concheiro, »A Century after His Death,« 164.
51
52
Frank Jacob
rich Engels. When a suitable Marx quotation fails to come to hand
to illustrate a point, Engels can always fill in; thus most works on
Marx and his Ism are really studies of Marxandengels. So close was
the partnership of the two that it is virtually impossible to do Marx
without including Engels.«17
However, considering that both men remained individuals and
worked in their own fields of interest as well, one cannot simply declare all of Engels’s work to be based on Marx’s ideas and vice versa.18
Engels also remained the first and probably most important critic of
his friend, and as Oscar J. Hammen put it, »Engels frequently enough
was critical of Marx’s findings, but there is no evidence of a disturbing
conflict of views. Marx, in turn, never hesitated to alter or reject the
draft of an article by Engels — on one occasion even because the item
was not written in the customary ›easygoing‹ (sic) style, when a question of popularization was in the picture.«19 All in all, the two men
lived and worked as equal partners, who still had their own ideas and
projects, which they, however, would share and discuss with each other. They also profited from each other, not only financially, but first
and foremost intellectually, a fact that made their »company-business« so successful and productive for so many years.20 In contrast to
Marx, whose economic work is that of a genius, Engels did not limit
himself to one field of study, and, just as his intellectual sources may
17
18
19
20
Martin Berger, »Disentangling Engels from Marxandengels,« International Labor and Working-Class History 12 (1977): 41.
Hans Peter Bleuel, Friedrich Engels: Bürger und Revolutionär (Bern / Munich:
Scherz, 1981), William O. Henderson, The Life of Friedrich Engels, 2 vols. (London: Frank Cass, 1976), Tristram Hunt, Friedrich Engels: Der Mann, der den
Marxismus erfand, transl. by Klaus-Dieter Schmidt, third edition (Berlin: List,
2020), and Norman Levine, The Tragic Deception: Marx contra Engels (Santa
Barbara / Oxford, Clio Books, 1975) tried to provide a more separated view of
Engels’s life.
Hammen, »Alienation, Communism, and Revolution,« 79. Also see Erhard
Lucas, »Marx‹ und Engels’s Auseinandersetzung mit Darwin: Zur Differenz zwischen Marx und Engels,« International Review of Social History 9, no. 3 (1964):
433 – 434.
Hammen, »Alienation, Communism, and Revolution,« 79 and 82.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
have been diverse,21 so too were his writings with regard to the topics
he covered.22 The two men were, however, not static in their thinking,
but, as American historian Leonard Krieger (1918 – 1990) remarked,
»it has been recognized that the passion for the comprehension of
facts which drove Marx and Engels from the Hegelian dialectic to
dialectical materialism drove them at the same time to a search for
a command over historical and social knowledge.«23 Their result was
a new way to explain and understand historical processes, a method
that went away from the great men who determined human history
and important events that changed the course of the world. They explained history as being related to class and class conflict, and therefore to the masses of the people.24
When we talk about a Marxist-Engelsian approach towards history, we talk about revolutionary history, something especially Engels
outlined in his many works.25 Because communism, as Marx and Engels understood it, »sought to stand up for and with all the world’s
oppressed peoples, especially its workers, who were being crushed
under the wheels of industrialization, privatized greed, and a ruling
elite’s attempt to monopolize wealth,«26 it is not surprising that they
looked at the history of the people’s struggle against exploitation as
well. According to their interpretation, i. e. historical materialism, »[t]
hese two men believed that all human history was leading inevitably
to a class-based warfare that would result in the violent overthrow of
the upper classes by the working class.«27 Engels, due to the existent
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
Karl A. Wittfogel, »The Marxist View of Russian Society and Revolution,« World
Politics 12, no. 4 (1960): 487.
Martin Berger, »Engel’s Theory of the Vanishing Army: A Key to the Development of Marxist Revolutionary Tactics,« The Historian 37, no. 3 (1975): 422.
Leonard Krieger, »Marx and Engels as Historians,« Journal of the History of Ideas
14, no. 3 (1953): 382.
Jonathan Joseph, Social Theory: Conflict, Cohesion and Consent (Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, 2003), 6 and 9 – 15.
Krieger, »Marx and Engels as Historians,« 383.
John Murphy, ed. Socialism and Communism (New York: Britannica Educational
Publishing, 2015), x.
Ibid., xi-xii.
53
54
Frank Jacob
situation in the late 1840s, also focused on social groups rather than
political organizations when he considered the form and course of
the revolutionary process that would supposedly follow in the near
future.28 However, Engels was also aware that the existent conditions
would play an important role in any revolution and therefore, not surprisingly, changed his ideas about the revolution to come, although
not his belief that it would eventually change the world. He considered revolutionary processes to act according to natural law, and in a
letter to Marx in February 1851, Engels wrote: »A revolution is a pure
phenomenon of nature, which is led more according to physical laws
than according to the rules which in ordinary times determine the
development of society. Or rather, these rules take on a much more
physical character in revolution; material power emerges much more
violently.«29
Since Marx and Engels, as historians, included their own experiences in relation to the revolutionary events of the 19th century when
they discussed the revolution of the future, they also pointed out the
social and political shortcomings of a century in which the masses
began to demand more power from those who had determined the
latter’s fate for so long.30 The evaluation of bourgeois and proletarian
revolution, as well as the interrelationship between the two, was a
process for Marx and Engels, in which they changed their opinion
multiple times, as they could observe failed revolutionary attempts
over a long period of time. The two revolutionaries could look back
on the events of 1848 / 49, and they also knew about the Great French
Revolution. Therefore, they could base their theoretical assumptions
on actual historical knowledge, although the failures of the past did
not limit their revolutionary enthusiasm for the future.31 Like Marx
28
29
30
31
Krieger, »Marx and Engels as Historians,« 388.
Cited in ibid., 392.
David Leopold, »The Structure of Marx and Engels’s Considered Account of
Utopian Socialism,« History of Political Thought 26, no. 3 (2005): 466.
Martin Hundt, »Zur Entwicklung der marxistischen Revolutionstheorie nach
der Revolution von 1848 / 49,« Marx-Engels-Jahrbuch 10 (1986): 31.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
and Engels, we have to be careful when we discuss revolutions in
retrospect and consequently have to analyze them in their historical
context.32 In the case of the two famous revolutionaries, this means
that their ideas were the scientific condensation of actual experiences
related to the revolutionary process of 1848 / 49. The witnessing of the
failed revolution would determine the scientific condensation of their
thoughts about future revolutions,33 a process not only Marx and Engels went through. While theoretical works about the formation of
Marxist revolution theory were legion in an East German context,34 a
detailed analysis of Engels’s works and his thoughts on revolution as
a phenomenon of modernity has not really been of interest since the
end of the Cold War, although some reflections were provided by historian Martin Hundt in 1986. Hundt also argues that Engels’s revolution theory could not ignore his actual experience of the revolution
in 1848 / 49 and, like other revolution theories, was the consequence
of historical developments witnessed by the author of such theoretical
reflections.35 The Communist Manifesto (1848) was consequently the
attempt to provide a solid revolution theory for the first time; however, it would have to be proven by historical developments,36 and due
to the many failed revolutions that would follow in the 19th and 20th
centuries, it was redefined and reconfigured by other revolutionaries
32
33
34
35
36
Manfred Kossok, »Revolution und Weltgeschichte im Werk von Walter Markov,« in Walter Markov, Weltgeschichte im Revolutionsquadrat, ed. and introduced
by Manfred Kossok (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1982), ix.
Hundt, »Zur Entwicklung,« 31.
Wolfgang Eichhorn, »Gesetzmäßigkeit von Revolutionen,« Sitzungsberichte der
Akademie der Wissenschaften der DDR. Gesellschaftswissenschaften 11 (1984); Ernst
Engelberg and Wolfgang Küttler, eds. Formationstheorie und Geschichte: Studien
zur historischen Untersuchung von Gesellschaftsformationen Werk von Marx, Engels und Lenin (Berlin: Akademie-Verlagm 1978); Manfred Kossok, ed. Studien
über die Revolution (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1969); Manfred Kossok and Walter
Markov, eds. Studien zur vergleichenden Revolutionsgeschichte 1500 – 1917 (Berlin:
Akademie-Verlag, 1974).
Hundt, »Zur Entwicklung,« 33 – 34.
Ibid., 34.
55
56
Frank Jacob
who turned Marxism into a new form of historical interpretation, e. g.
Leninism or Maoism.
Regardless of such later changes, the present chapter intends to
take a closer look at Friedrich Engels’s writings and ideas about revolution. First, however, a look at his life as a revolutionary shall be
taken in order to explain where his ideas originated from. In the
second part, the chapter will then pay close attention to some texts
by Engels in which he develops his ideas in relation to a revolution
he believed would soon change the world. It is important to understand that Engels did not create a static revolution theory, but rather
tried to adjust his thoughts over a long period of time to match the
existent preconditions. He nevertheless was a true believer in revolution and never gave up on preparing himself and society for a tremendous transformation that would soon take place. Unfortunately,
Engels and his ideas were often used as a scapegoat to explain the
failures of revolutionary processes in the 20th century when Marxist
ideas about revolution and decontextualized quotes from Marx and
Engels were used to make arguments on behalf of corrupted revolutionary governments, whose leaders claimed to rule only in the
sense of Marx and Engels and at the same time promised a new and
better world.37 This was probably also possible due to the fact that
Engels in particular had written about the revolution in different
tones at different times. His revolution theory was a work in process
and therefore must be understood as something that might have
fitted into the 19th century but could not be applied to the events
of the 20th century without further processing. Regardless of this
fact, however, Engels’s writings about revolution are important to
understand this global phenomenon of modernity a bit better, and
those interested in revolution theory and its application in the 21st
century should be encouraged to pay close attention to these writings to better understand revolutionary processes, and especially the
dangers related to them.
37
Frank Jacob, 1917: Die korrumpierte Revolution (Marburg: Büchner, 2020).
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
The Revolutionary Life of Friedrich Engels
Engels was interested in philosophy from early on,38 which probably
revolutionized his mind and made him aware of the problems of his
time.39 When he first arrived in England in 1842 to work in the cotton
business of his father, Engels already, to quote British historian Gregory Claeys, »considered himself as something of a revolutionary,« and
when considering his early writings, including The Condition of the
Working Class in England (1845), it seems clear »that he expected and
desired a revolution to take place there.«40 When he met Marx for the
first time at the Rheinische Zeitung in 1842, Engels had probably been
more revolutionary than his future friend and companion, and it is
not surprising that his revolutionary ambitions were even intensified
by his experiences in Manchester between 1842 and 1844.41 It was the
British industrial center that offered Engels a deeper insight into the
functioning of industrial capitalism, and the exploitation and poverty
of the working class he observed there would turn the young capitalist
into a socialist revolutionary. In August 1844 he met Marx again, this
time in Paris, where the latter worked on the Deutsch-Französische
Jahrbücher, and the two men eventually forged their friendship while
discussing their theoretical ideas for ten days.42 Engels would become
one of the few people Marx accepted as intellectually equal, and the
38
Georges Labica, »Engels and Marxist Philosophy,« Science & Society 62, no. 1
(1998), Friedrich Engels: A Critical Centenary Appreciation: 13 – 34.
39 Narihiko Ito, »Realismus und Utopismus,« in Zwischen Utopie und Kritik: Friedrich Engels — ein »Klassiker« nach 100 Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann, Mario
Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer (Hamburg: VSA, 1996), 23 – 33.
40 Gregory Claeys, »The Political Ideas of the Young Engels, 1842 – 1845: Owenism,
Chartism, and the Question of Violent Revolution in the Transition from ›Utopian‹ to ›Scientific‹ Socialism,« History of Political Thought 6, no. 3 (1985): 457.
41 Philip Erbentraut and Torben Lütjen, »Eine Welt zu gewinnen: Entstehungskontext, Wirkungsweise undNarrationsstruktur des ›Kommunistischen Manifests‹,«
in Manifeste: Geschichte und Gegenwart des politischen Appells, eds. Johanna Klatt
and Robert Lorenz (Bielefeld: Transcript Verlag, 2010), 77.
42 Friedich Engels, »Zur Geschichte des Bundes der Kommunisten,« in Marx-EngelsWerke (Berlin: Dietz, 1956-, henceforth MEW), 21: 212.
57
58
Frank Jacob
following years would show that the two were quite good at working
as a productive joint venture. On the other hand, Engels worshipped
Marx and often agreed to work for his friend instead of following his
own interests to a larger extent.43
In his spare time, however, Engels worked extensively on many
other things than just economic questions. One field he was particularly interested in was military matters,44 and he not only studied
military history but also strategy and tactics, although Engels would
also set his knowledge about military affairs in the context of his revolutionary ambitions and reflections about the revolution he hoped
to witness soon, despite the failure of that of 1848 / 49.45 In military
science, it was therefore Engels who »was the dominant member of
the Marx-Engels partnership,« and it was not only there but in many
other relevant fields of his expertise that »he was the originator, not
merely a popularizer or vulgarizer of Marx’s ideas.«46 The famous German revolutionary also steadily combined his knowledge in military
affairs with his revolution theory, e. g. his Theory of the Vanishing
Army, and was therefore able to understand revolutionary processes in
their full complexity. His studies in relation to different military matters consequently »shaped the classical Marxist approach to the timing and tactics of revolution.«47 This also becomes obvious due to the
fact that Engels had had some experiences during the Revolution of
1848 when he was actively involved in the fight against the European
reaction, which he would later reflect upon in his writings about revolution: »Revolutions, Engels said, produced confusion, and confusion
43
44
45
46
47
Erbentraut and Lütjen, »Eine Welt zu gewinnen,« 78.
For a detailed discussion see Jehuda L. Wallach, Die Kriegslehre von Friedrich Engels (Frankfurt am Main: Europäische Verlagsanstalt, 1968); Gerhard Zirke, Der
General: Friedrich Engels, der erste Militârtheoretiker der Arbeiterklasse (Leipzig:
Urania-Verlag, 1967).
Berger, »Engel’s Theory of the Vanishing Army,« 421 – 422; Martin Kitchen, »Friedrich Engels’s Theory of War,« Military Affairs 41, no. 3 (1977): 119; Wittfogel,
»The Marxist View,« 489.
Berger, »Engel’s Theory of the Vanishing Army,« 422.
Ibid.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
did not promote military efficiency. Unorganized enthusiasm would
not win battles.«48 With regard to the growing militarism in Europe,
Engels also predicted that this would lead to revolution,49 although, in
contrast to his assumptions, such revolutions, e. g. in Russia in 1917
or Germany in 1918, would not change the world and end capitalism.
Due to his experience of the failed Revolution of 1848, it seemed
clear that the revolution of the future needed to be better prepared,
and tactical considerations, including those about the military and
its role during such a revolutionary process, were quite prominent
in Marx’s and Engels’s writings of later years.50 Engels, in particular,
»expressed increasing revulsion at the prospect of a future world war,
which threatened to destroy all the advances made not only by the
working class and by socialist movements, but by Western civilization
itself.«51 He also emphasized the role of a crisis in stimulating the
increase in revolutionary potential in the late 1850s. In 1857 he wrote
to Marx that »[a] continuing economic depression could be used by
astute revolutionary strategy as a useful weapon for a chronic pressure … in order to warm up the people … just as a cavalry attack has
greater elan if the horses trot five hundred paces before coming within
charging distance of the enemy.«52 Engels consequently included his
own observations in his reflections about the future revolution. This
also highlights that Engels’s revolution theory was a process based
on his everyday life experience since the 1840s. The theory, therefore,
cannot be considered as absolute, but rather a work in progress. In
the 21st century, this means that Engels’s assumptions can be accepted
as a theoretical base or framework, which, nevertheless, needs to be
adjusted to the present-day context.
48
49
50
51
52
Ibid., 425.
See for example Engels’s preface to The Capital (1886) or Friedrich Engels, Herr
Eugen Dühring’s Revolution in Science (Anti-Dühring) (New York: International
Publishers, 1939), 189 – 190.
Neumann and von Hagen, »Engels and Marx on Revolution,« 262.
Ibid.
Cited in ibid., 263.
59
60
Frank Jacob
Marx and Engels understood that their theoretical approach to
understand the world and to prepare the revolution of the future
needed to include multiple aspects, e. g. economic development, foreign policy, military affairs, etc. In addition, they realized, to quote
Sigmund Neumann and Mark von Hagen once more, »that the future of the European revolution would not be determined by the efforts of one country alone. This realization directed their attention to
a serious consideration of the relationships between socialism, military policy, and foreign affairs, because without an understanding
of these relationships a realistic revolutionary strategy could not be
possible.«53 At the same time, both tried to criticize the existent order
for its shortcomings and the existent stumbling blocks that prevented
people from realizing the necessity of revolution.54 Regardless of such
criticism, Marx and Engels were in favor of nationalism as well, as
long as it was directed towards their favored goals, e. g. the unification
of Germany and Italy or Polish independence from Russia.55
Regardless of such aspects related to the revolutionary thoughts of
the two men, it was the experience of 1848 / 49 that first and foremost
defined the theoretical reflections of Marx and Engels, who, due to
the outcomes of the European revolution in these years, accepted the
lessons and necessities for a new and inevitable revolutionary attempt
in the near future: »Equally inevitable [as another revolution] was the
violent nature of this revolution. This inevitability of the revolution
and its violent nature was determined by the very structures of the
bourgeois system. Marx and Engels concluded this on the basis of
their analysis of the historical forces and the then existing social relations, and of the nature of private property.«56 For Marx and Engels,
53
54
55
56
Ibid., 264.
For Engels’s views on religion see Michael Löwy, »Friedrich Engels on Religion
and Class Struggle,« Science & Society 62, no. 1 (1998), Friedrich Engels: A Critical
Centenary Appreciation: 81.
Horace B. Davis, »Nations, Colonies and Social Classes: The Position of Marx
and Engels,« Science & Society 29, no. 1 (1965): 27; Iring Fetscher, »Friedrich Engels, Polen und der Russische Imperialismus,« Osteuropa 7, no. 6 (1957): 431.
Singh, »Status of Violence,« 9.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
it was clear that »[t]he revolution is necessary … not only because the
ruling class cannot be overthrown in any other way, but also because
the class overthrowing it can only in a revolution succeed in ridding
itself of all the muck of ages and become fitted to found society anew.«57 Further studies and experiences, however, made the two men
rethink their attitude towards violence. In some political systems, a
peaceful change, i. e. the working masses gaining the popular vote in
the elections and the popular vote, seemed at least possible, although
the ›revolutionary twins‹ emphasized »that the working class should
not forego its right to use violent methods even at such places because
the ruling classes could not be expected to give up their power, even
here, without an armed resistance.«58
In February 1848, Engels was more than enthusiastic about the
revolution and was sure that it would bring the anticipated changes
with it in no time.59 Well aware of the history of the French Revolution, however, Marx and Engels had to witness how the Revolution
of 1848 was corrupted similarly to the French Revolution of 1789 and
ended with a Bonaparte ruling France again. Marx, in The Eighteenth
Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (1852), commented on this fact as follows:
»Hegel remarks somewhere that all great world-historic facts and personages appear, so to speak, twice. He forgot to add: the first time as
tragedy, the second time as farce.«60 The revolutionary process seemed
to have repeated the doomed course of that of 1789.61 As participants,
nevertheless, Marx and Engels had tried to influence the course of the
57
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology (Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1976), 60, cited in ibid.
58 Ibid., 18.
59 Christopher Andrew, Secret World: A History of Intelligence (New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press, 2018), 386.
60 Karl Marx, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (1852). Accessed August
20, 2020. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1852/18th-brumaire/.
61 Bernard H. Moss, »Marx and Engels on French Social Democracy: Historians or
Revolutionaries?« Journal of the History of Ideas 46, no. 4 (1985): 541. For a discussion of generic revolutionary processes and the danger of them being corrupted
see Jacob, 1917.
61
62
Frank Jacob
revolution and lead it to a positive outcome. Marx left Paris for Cologne, where he worked as the editor of the Neue Rheinische Zeitung
that was launched on 1 June 1848. Engels later emphasized that the
journal was led by his friend like a dictator, but he was able to achieve
a circulation of 5,000 issues of the paper, which was quite impressive
for the time.62 Despite their involvement, their attempt to radicalize
the revolutionary process, and their hopes for a real change as a consequence, the revolution lost its dynamic, and it seemed impossible
to achieve the changes that had been demanded by the representatives
of the international proletariat.63 The revolution remained unfulfilled,
a half one, and the revolutionaries failed to overthrow the bourgeois
elites who continued to determine the fate of the single nation states.
For the moment, it seemed clear that the hopes and aims of Marx
and Engels would remain long-term goals, while the former coined
the idea of a revolution in permanence (Revolution in Permanenz) in
March 1850.64 This concept would be essential for the further study
of and discussions about revolutions, and it was particularly necessary
because the revolution of 1848 had unexpectedly strengthened the
counter-revolutionary forces across Europe. Very soon after its appearance, »[t]he revolutionary momentum faded away without visible result,«65 although the many military struggles had turned Europe
into the battlefield of a civil war-like conflict about the future and a
vision for modernity. It was the eventual failure of this revolutionary attempt that demanded an explanation and therefore stimulated
the further development of a scientific form of socialism. Marx and
Engels would work on this specific issue in their post-revolutionary
exile. One of their assumptions in relation to their studies was the fact
62
63
Andrew, Secret World, 387.
Peter Stadler, »Wirtschaftskrise und Revolution bei Marx und Engels: Zur Entwicklung ihres Denkens inden 1850er Jahren,« Historische Zeitschrift 199, no. 1
(1964): 113.
64 Ibid., 114; Erik van Ree, »Marxism as Permanent Revolution,« History of Political
Thought 34, no. 3 (2013): 540.
65 Neumann and von Hagen, »Engels and Marx on Revolution,« 266.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
that a crisis was considered to be a necessary trigger66 for every future
revolution to begin, and when the European economies seemed to be
under pressure in 1857, they had hopes that »the European reaction
would give way to a new revolutionary situation. Engels was delighted by the thought that he might soon be able to leave business for
the battlefield and his office stool for a horse.«67 In addition to their
scientific approach to the study of revolutions, Marx and Engels, as a
consequence of their experiences of 1848, interpreted history as such
as a permanent class struggle.68 Alongside this conclusion, Engels
also realized the important interrelation between war and revolution.
While the latter could be triggered by the former, revolutions could
also cause wars, especially civil wars in the course of the events related to a revolutionary process. Due to this insight, Engels remained
interested in the military developments and the wars of his time, be
it the Crimean War, the US Civil War, or the Franco-Prussian War.69
Maybe he was observing these historical events so closely because he
hoped that they would unleash another, this time maybe successful,
revolutionary process. He would also do so as Engels, like Marx, continued to believe that only a revolution would be able to create a new
social order and therefore must have been considered the conditio sine
qua non for a better world.70
The revolutionary events of 1848 / 49 consequently forced the
two revolutionaries to formulate a concise theory that incorporated
the history of revolutions, one that Marx and Engels had witnessed
themselves. The failure, therefore, must have had an impact on the
understanding of revolutions and the future political course of the
proletariat, whose representatives had again not been successful in
involving the masses at a level that was perceived as essential for the
66
67
68
69
70
MEW 7: 440. For a detailed analysis see Stadler, »Wirtschaftskrise und Revolution,« 113 – 144.
Neumann and von Hagen, »Engels and Marx on Revolution,« 268.
Ibid., 269.
Ibid., 270.
Hunley, Life and Thought of Friedrich Engels, 97.
63
64
Frank Jacob
success of revolutionary change for the future. They intensified their
study of revolutions to come up with a more sophisticated revolution
theory, one that would pay tribute to history and the failures of the
past.71 It was at this time that the terms »locomotives of history« and
»dictatorship of the proletariat« first appeared in Marx’s and Engels’s
works, although the two intellectuals never really accurately defined
what the latter actually meant.72 Their works between 1849 and 1852
predominantly deal with the question of why the revolution had
failed, although capitalist structures were well developed at the time,
and why it had been unable to have the impact of the Great French
Revolution some decades before, especially in the sense that it did not
provide a chance for the communists to drive the revolutionary process any further.73 This would, with regard to the further theoretical
considerations of Marx and Engels, be one of their main questions:
How could the bourgeois-democratic revolution be driven forward to
reach the proletarian revolution as some kind of second step in the
overall process?74 The historical example of the French Revolution
could therefore no longer be used as an ultimate example, although
their experience of 1848 / 49 was often reflected and framed according
to their historical knowledge about the events in France between 1789
and 1799.75
The events Marx and Engels witnessed during the Revolution of
1848 would nevertheless function as a theoretical filter for a reconsideration of the French Revolution.76 This means that every revolu71
72
73
74
75
76
Hundt, »Zur Entwicklung,« 34.
Ibid. On the »dictatorship of the proletariat« see Mike Schmeitzner, »Lenin und
die Diktatur des Proletariats — Begriff, Konzeption, Ermöglichung,« Totalitarismus und Demokratie 14 (2017): 17 – 69.
Hundt, »Zur Entwicklung,« 35.
Ibid., 38.
Manfred Kossok, »Karl Marx und die Grundlegung wissenschaftlicher Revolutionsauffassung,« Zeitschrift für Geschichtswissenschaft 28, no. 2 (1980): 99 – 118.
Lenin would continue to emphasize such an interpretation, when he named the
proletarians to be the »Jacobins of the 20th century.« Wladimir I. Lenin, »Über
die Volksfeinde,« in Werke (Berlin: Dietz, 1972), 25: 45. For Marx’s view on the
French Revolution see: Dan Edelstein, »Revolution in Permanence and the Fall
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
tionary theory needs to be updated according to the course of history,
which is why the two intellectuals did not understand their own theoretical reflections as something that was written in stone, but rather
as something that needed to be adjusted depending on the actual
historical course of the future. This is one important aspect that we
have to include in our understanding of revolutions as well. They are
flexible processes that can hardly be predicted, and there will never
be absolute knowledge about the next step within such a process, especially since revolutions are driven forward by human beings, who
might not even act or understand themselves as conscious revolutionaries. Revolutions, and this was understood by Marx and Engels, had
to be seen within their specific space-time continuum,77 and although
we can identify some generic developments and possible steps, a revolutionary process can evolve; accordingly, every revolution must be
studied in its specific space-time continuum to fully understand its
nature, history, and very often its failure as well.
Nevertheless, for Marx and Engels, the working class, i. e. the proletariat, would play the important role within a successful revolution of
the future. Hundt identified three constant aspects of Marxist revolution theory that had their origin in the experiences of 1848/49, namely
1. the working class is already an essential part of the bourgeois-democratic revolution,
2. the determination, bravery, and energy of a revolutionary class, on
the one hand, and reason and scientific consciousness on the other
are decisive elements in times of a revolutionary crisis, and
3. the revolution has to be kept energetic or alive to guarantee success in the end.78
77
78
of Popular Sovereignty,« in The Scaffolding of Sovereignty: Global and Aesthetic Perspectives on the History of a Concept, eds. Zvi Ben-Dor Benite, Stefanos
Geroulanos and Nicole Jerr (New York: Columbia University Press, 2017),
378 – 384.
Hundt, »Zur Entwicklung,« 46.
Ibid., 49.
65
66
Frank Jacob
Marx and Engels had, according to these principles, identified four
main aspects related to the Revolution of 1848. These are:
1. the proletariat needs to be self-organized and led by a revolutionary fighting party,
2. the proletariat can only apply its power if it becomes the head and
heart of a popular revolution, i. e. leading the masses during the
revolutionary process to ultimately achieve a social change as well,
3. the proletariat has to break with and destroy the old political system to establish a classless order, and
4. the revolutionary workers‹ movement is not only limited by historical materialism and economically determined conditions, but
has more than one option for its course of action.79
The course of history could consequently only be changed by a revolution if the latter did not act according to non-existent preconditions, which is why each revolutionary process had to deal with
specific conditions that could not yet be taken into consideration.
This also makes comparative studies of revolutions necessary to really
understand the generic aspects that exist and determine revolutionary
processes, while differences can highlight specific factors that need to
be taken into consideration while reflecting upon a historical revolution.80
Regardless of these theoretical reflections, »Marx and Engels persistently repeated the same essential points, independently of circumstance, medium and audience. The conception of a two-stage
but uninterrupted revolution belonged to their stable core beliefs,
from which they did not back away.«81 They, however, reformulated
their revolution theory and relevant political strategies between 1843
and 1850 based on their actual experiences, which means that they
attempted to use their own experiences to establish a scientific rev79
80
81
Ibid., 50 – 51.
Ibid., 52.
van Ree, »Marxism as Permanent Revolution,« 544.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
olution model that would also apply the idea of historical materialism while still being flexible enough to be useful for revolutionaries
in different contexts. That implies that they did not have a static
model in mind that should be applied for all revolutions. They rather thought of a collection of thoughts that might be used to better
understand revolutionary processes as such, including their diversity
with regard to time and place. At the same time, as US scholar Dan
Edelstein highlighted, »[h]istory itself thus allowed Marx to update
the revolutionary theory he and Engels had laid out previously in
the Communist Manifesto. In defeat, the proletarians had come out
of the shadows of the bourgeoisie and assumed their own identity as
a revolutionary class.«82 In their works of the 1840s and 1850s, Marx
and Engels tried to find the answer to their revolutionary hopes and,
during that process, were eager to establish a set of rules or almost
natural laws that could be applied to revolutions and taken into consideration by future revolutionaries.83 As representatives of »an international community of revolutionary exiles,«84 it seemed almost natural that they would pay attention to the events that had caused their
exile and the future revolutionary events, which could end it again.
How Engels addressed these pressing questions with regard to
revolution, its meaning, its history, and its future shall be taken
into closer consideration in the following section, which will provide a close reading of the early writings of the famous German
intellectual.
82
83
Edelstein, »Revolution in Permanence,« 374.
Samuel Hollander, »Marx and Engels on Constitutional Reform vs. Revolution:
Their ›Revisionism‹ Reviewed,« Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory
57, no. 122 (2010), Democracy and Exchange: 176.
84 Andrew Zimmerman, »From the Second American Revolution to the First International and Back Again: Marxism, the Popular Front and the American Civil
War,« in The World the Civil War Made, eds. Gregory P. Downs and Kate Masur
(Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press, 2015), 304.
67
68
Frank Jacob
Engels on Revolution
From early on, it was clear for Engels that a »revolution by legal
means — in itself a contradiction, a practical impossibility«85 was impossible, because the capitalist elites would not allow a new social
order to come into existence in a politically legal way. The early communists, who organized themselves not only in Paris but also in cities
of northern Germany,86 consequently had to figure out how to reach
a better future, which for Engels was not utopian at all87 but also
not achievable without conflict between the classes, namely between
the exploiting and the exploited ones. In a later preface to the 1887
American edition of his famous work The Condition of the Working
Class in England (1845), Engels again highlighted the necessity for a
revolution when he remarked: »What the Socialists demand, implies
a total revolution of the whole system of social production.«88 That
this revolution would be the expression of a class struggle was also
highlighted in the 1891 preface to the English edition of the work:
»So long as the wealthy classes not only do not feel the want of any
emancipation, but strenuously oppose the self-emancipation of the
working-class, so long the social revolution will have to be prepared
and fought out by the working-class alone.«89 In the famous work
itself, Engels described not only the life and precarious situation of
the English working class, but also how this modern proletariat had
been created by the industrial revolution, which he considered to be
85
86
87
88
89
Frederick Engels, »The Internal Crises,« Rheinische Zeitung, no. 343 and 344,
December 9 and 10, 1842. Accessed July 29, 2020. https://marxists.catbull.com/
archive/marx/works/1842/12/09.htm.
Frederick Engels, »Continental Socialism,« in: Karl Marx and Frederick Engels,
Collected Works, vol. 4 (London: Lawrence & Wishart 2010), 212 – 213.
Frederick Engels, »Description of Recently Founded Communist Colonies Still
in Existence,« in: Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, vol. 4 (London: Lawrence & Wishart 2010), 214 – 228.
Friedrich Engels, The Condition of the Working Class in England, London 1891
[Leipzig 1845]. Accessed July 29, 2020. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/
works/download/pdf/condition-working-class-england.pdf.
Ibid.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
»of the same importance for England as the political revolution for
France, and the philosophical revolution for Germany.«90
The sorrows and sufferings of the English workers, however,
would, according to Engels, only cease to exist as the consequence of
a revolution: »When such insanity prevails in the property-holding
class, when it is so blinded by its momentary profit that it no longer
has eyes for the most conspicuous signs of the times, surely all hope
of a peaceful solution of the social question for England must be
abandoned. The only possible solution is a violent revolution, which
cannot fail to take place.«91 Considering Engels’s early work, it is remarkable that he had already identified the relation between capitalist
exploitation and the stimulation for a revolution that is created by
the exploitative politics of the ruling class. For the young man, who
had been involved in the business of the ruling class but also seen
the misery it created in towns like Manchester, consequently argued
that the continuation of the current exploitative means of capitalism
would eventually allow no other choice for the masses but to rise
through revolution to change the existent economic, political, and
social system. Or, as Engels formulated it,
assuming that England retained the monopoly of manufactures, that
its factories perpetually multiply, what must be the result? The commercial crises would continue, and grow more violent, more terrible,
with the extension of industry and the multiplication of the proletariat. The proletariat would increase in geometrical proportion, in
consequence of the progressive ruin of the lower middle-class and the
giant strides with which capital is concentrating itself in the hands of
the few; and the proletariat would soon embrace the whole nation,
with the exception of a few millionaires. But in this development
there comes a stage at which the proletariat perceives how easily the
existing power may be overthrown, and then follows a revolution.92
90
91
92
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid.
69
70
Frank Jacob
As the English bourgeoisie would not correct the course of history
by itself, a revolution seemed inevitable. This also means that the
prophecy of revolution was already expressed by Engels in his initial
work, although in a specifically English national context. It was consequently obvious that a conflict between the classes needed to find
its climax in revolution, which needed to be prepared and led by the
working class: »So long as the wealthy classes not only do not feel the
want of any emancipation, but strenuously oppose the self-emancipation of the working class, so long the social revolution will have to be
prepared and fought out by the working class alone.«93
In his »Principles of Communism« (»Grundsätze des Kommunismus,« 1847), Engels would continue his reflections on communism
and revolution. The former he considered to be the doctrine of the
conditions for the liberation of the proletariat, the class that solely
gains within the capitalist system by selling its labor: »The proletariat,
or the class of proletarians, is, in a word, the working class of the 19th
century.«94 In contrast to the slave, the proletarian has to sell his work
at a daily or hourly rate and has no secured existence. The proletarian, again in contrast to the slave, is consequently part of capitalist
competition and is accepted as a member of society. Consequently,
the proletarian has a better legal status than the slave, but is regularly
exploited while his life is threatened by this form of capitalist exploitation. While the slave can be liberated when slavery is abolished,
the proletarian, however, can only be free when private property as
such ceases to exist.95
The communists at the same time know, as Engels describes in
his answer to question 16, which asks how the abolition of private
property can be achieved, that revolutions are not purposely and ar93
94
95
Ibid.
Friedrich Engels, »Grundsätze des Kommunismus (1847),« in Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels, Werke, vol. 4 (Berlin: Dietz, 1974), 361 – 380. Accessed June 13,
2020. http://www.mlwerke.de/me/me04/me04_361.htm. English translations
taken from: https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1847/11/prin-com.htm
Ibid.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
bitrarily made, but that they are the result of existent preconditions.96
Once the global proletariat is forced into such a revolution by its
steady exploitation, it will lead to the end of private property and
the capitalist exploitation of the masses. In his answer to question
18, which asks for the course of such a revolution, Engels describes a
12-point agenda for the measures that would have to be taken by the
proletariat, once a democratic system had been established. Engels
argues that without a proletarian lead and instrumentalization of the
revolution, a change of the social order would not be possible. His 12
measures shall therefore be quoted here in some more detail:
1. Limitation of private property through progressive taxation, heavy
inheritance taxes, abolition of inheritance through collateral lines
(brothers, nephews, etc.) forced loans, etc.
2. Gradual expropriation of landowners, industrialists, railroad magnates and shipowners, partly through competition by state industry, partly directly through compensation in the form of bonds.
3. Confiscation of the possessions of all emigrants and rebels against
the majority of the people.
4. Organization of labor or employment of proletarians on publicly
owned land, in factories and workshops, with competition among
the workers being abolished and with the factory owners, in so
far as they still exist, being obliged to pay the same high wages as
those paid by the state.
5. An equal obligation on all members of society to work until such
time as private property has been completely abolished. Formation of industrial armies, especially for agriculture.
6. Centralization of money and credit in the hands of the state through a national bank with state capital, and the suppression of all
private banks and bankers.
7. Increase in the number of national factories, workshops, railroads,
ships; bringing new lands into cultivation and improvement of
96
Ibid.
71
72
Frank Jacob
land already under cultivation — all in proportion to the growth
of the capital and labor force at the disposal of the nation.
8. Education of all children, from the moment they can leave their
mother’s care, in national establishments at national cost. Education and production together.
9. Construction, on public lands, of great palaces as communal dwellings for associated groups of citizens engaged in both industry
and agriculture and combining in their way of life the advantages
of urban and rural conditions while avoiding the one-sidedness
and drawbacks of each.
10. Destruction of all unhealthy and jerry-built dwellings in urban
districts.
11. Equal inheritance rights for children born in and out of wedlock.
12. Concentration of all means of transportation in the hands of the
nation.97
Once the first strike against private property has been waged by the
proletariat, Engels continues, the latter will be forced to drive the
change of the existent economic and social order further and further
and »[f ]inally, when all capital, all production, all exchange have
been brought together in the hands of the nation, private property
will disappear of its own accord, money will become superfluous,
and production will so expand and man so change that society will
be able to slough off whatever of its old economic habits may remain.«98
With regard to the character of the future revolution as a world
revolution, Engels also highlights that the globalization of capitalism will eventually cause a universal and global revolution, one that
will probably change the world in our century, as capitalism seems to
have reached its maximum extent and is currently facing an extreme
global crisis, caused by the COVID-19 pandemic. Engels, however,
97
98
Ibid.
Ibid.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
although writing in the 19th century, had already foreseen that the
anti-capitalist revolution would ultimately be a world revolution:
By creating the world market, big industry has already brought all the
peoples of the Earth, and especially the civilized peoples, into such
close relation with one another that none is independent of what
happens to the others. Further, it has co-ordinated the social development of the civilized countries to such an extent that, in all of them,
bourgeoisie and proletariat have become the decisive classes, and the
struggle between them the great struggle of the day. It follows that
the communist revolution will not merely be a national phenomenon
but must take place simultaneously in all civilized countries … It is
a universal revolution and will, accordingly, have a universal range.
Engels, in this text, already developed some of the basic considerations
of communism that would later also be expressed in the Communist
Manifesto (1848)99 that, although relatively unimportant during the
Revolution of 1848, would turn into a key document of human history.100 Although the text lost some of its appeal after the end of the
Cold War, the present crisis stimulated some interest again, especially
since more and more young people are looking for alternatives to
the capitalist world order. Marx and Engels consequently pointed the
navigators of a revolutionary course to the future.101
In their key theoretical text, the two intellectuals argued that the
history of all past societies must be understood as one of class struggle.102 In this struggle, the whole of society is divided according to two
main classes, namely the bourgeoisie and the proletariat.103 While the
99
100
101
102
103
On the genesis of the Communist Manifesto see Erbentraut and Lütjen, »Eine
Welt zu gewinnen,« 79 – 84. On the importance and impact of this text see Hunley, Life and Thought of Friedrich Engels, 65 – 79.
Erbentraut and Lütjen, »Eine Welt zu gewinnen,« 73.
Ibid., 76.
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, »Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei (1848),«
in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Werke, vol. 4 (Berlin: Dietz, 1959), 462.
Ibid., 463.
73
74
Frank Jacob
revolutionary class, i. e. the proletariat, holds the power to eventually
overcome the existent order and is therefore joined by some enlightened parts of the ruling class, it is the former that is the only truly
revolutionary class.104 The already existent yet hidden civil war between the classes will eventually turn into an open revolution, which
will become the base for the violent end of the bourgeoisie and the
establishment of proletarian rule.105 The communists are perceived as
part of the international workers‹ parties, namely the one that drives
the proletariat forward to take their revolutionary chance if the latter
should appear in a time of crisis.106 The communist revolution will
eventually break with the existent conditions of property and capital
in the most radical way possible to end the exploitation of one part
of society by another.107 The revolution would have to make that possible by first establishing a democratic republic that could then be
turned into a classless society, and therefore Engels explained in 1892
that »Marx and I, for forty years, repeated ad nauseam that for us the
democratic republic is the only political form in which the struggle
between the working class and the capitalist class can first be universalized and then culminate in the decisive victory of the proletariat.«108
Regardless of the claims and the attempt to provide a scientific explanation of class struggle and the role of the revolution in overcoming it, the manifesto had, in a way, predicted the revolutionary events
of 1848, although the outcome was quite different to that which was
expected by the two German revolutionaries.109 While Marx tried to
forge the »›people’s alliance,‹ the worker-peasant-petit bourgeois coalition to fight for the democratic revolution«110 through his work for
the Neue Rheinische Zeitung, Engels himself was actually involved in
104
105
106
107
108
Ibid., 471 – 472.
Ibid., 473.
Ibid., 474.
Ibid., 480 – 481.
August H. Nimtz, »Marx and Engels on the Revolutionary Party,« Socialist Register 53 (2017), Rethinking Revolution: 249.
109 Ibid., 250.
110 Ibid., 251.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
military operations during the revolutionary war, but eventually both
men had to accept the facts, namely the failure of the revolutionary
movement to gain mass support and to overthrow the existent order.
In the end, it seems to have been clear that their predictions were only
partly true, which is why both intellectuals continued 1) to consider
their revolution theory to be a work in progress and 2) to further
study historical events in relation to revolutionary processes. Since
both of them had to live in exile due to their own roles during the
Revolution of 1848, the failure was particularly felt by both intellectuals and their intensified interest to find out about the reasons for the
revolution’s failure was quite natural.
In 1850, Engels published The Peasant War in Germany,111 a work
that, to quote US anthropologist Eric R. Wolf, »represents a milestone in social history, and remains a major contribution to debates
about the historic role of peasantry today as in the past,« because »it
attempted to understand the forces of revolution and counterrevolution as consequences of a determinate relationship of classes.«112 With
The Peasant War in Germany, Engels tried to provide more than just a
reflection about a historical episode of the past. He went way beyond
that, and presented a »class analysis of the German countryside« and
discussed »the question of historical maturity of the peasantry, the
special features of peasant movements, the role of the peasantry in
history, and the relationship between revolutionary leaders and the
masses.«113 He consequently tries to follow his own suggestions by
considering »revolutionary« events of the past in their specific contexts to better understand why they happened or eventually failed.
Engels therefore began to analyze different revolutionary case studies
to gain further insight for his theoretical understanding of revolutionary processes.
111
Friedrich Engels, »Der deutsche Bauernkrieg (1850),« in Karl Marx and Friedrich
Engels, Werke, vol. 7 (Berlin: Dietz, 1960), 327 – 413.
112 Wolf, »The Peasant War in Germany,« 83 – 84.
113 Theodor Bergmann, »Engels on Agriculture,« Science & Society 62, no. 1 (1998),
Friedrich Engels: A Critical Centenary Appreciation: 147.
75
76
Frank Jacob
Engels also wanted to emphasize that there was a German revolutionary tradition, although the German states had since 1815 instead
been in support of the counter-revolutionary forces of Europe:
The German people are by no means lacking in revolutionary tradition. There were times when Germany produced characters that
could match the best men in the revolutions of other countries; when
the German people manifested an endurance and energy which, in a
centralized nation, would have brought the most magnificent results;
when the German peasants and plebeians were pregnant with ideas
and plans which often made their descendants shudder.114
Regardless of this emphasis, the revolutionary events since 1848 had
shown that a post-revolutionary unified Germany was not yet a possibility. This problem would also be at the center of Engels’s considerations in »Revolution and Counter-Revolution in Germany«
(1851 / 52).115
The articles that were published by the New York Daily Tribune under Marx’s name between 25 October 1851 and 23 October 1852 were
only identified to have originated in Engels’s thought and to have been
written by him in 1913, and their first publication in book form had
been made possible by Eleanor Marx (1855–1898) in 1896. It was written
in the aftermath of the Revolution of 1848, after which, according to
Engels, the »forces of the past« were again the »forces of the present,«
because the revolutionary parties had suffered from the most severe
defeat.116 Regardless of the failure to achieve its revolutionary aims, the
movement had shown and proved that revolutions are not made by
114 Engels, »Der deutsche Bauernkrieg (1850),« 329. English translation taken from
https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1850/peasant-war-germany/ch01.
htm.
115 Friedrich Engels, »Revolution und Konterrevolution in Deutschland (1851 / 52),« in
MEW 8: 5 – 108. Accessed June 13, 2020. https://www.marxists.org/deutsch/archiv/
marx-engels/1851/deutsch/index.htm.
116 Ibid.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
a handful of evil agitators but are an expression of disagreement by
the masses and that each revolutionary eruption must be considered
the consequence of a social need, whose fulfillment or achievement is
prevented by outdated institutions and their representatives. The attempt to prohibit the revolutionary forces from achieving change will,
as Engels continued in his analysis, eventually force the masses to break
their chains to gain true freedom and liberation as well as a true chance
to achieve what they deem necessary with regard to a new and better
social order.117 The Revolution of 1848 was consequently not caused by
individuals, but rather was an eruption of the wish of the masses to
create a new, better future. Engels also argues that the role of the petit
bourgeoisie, especially in Germany, had been decisive during the revolution, as this class was willing to replace the bourgeoisie but, at the
same time, feared falling down to become part of the proletariat as well.
What Engels emphasizes here is the diversity of those who might participate in a revolutionary process for different reasons and, for as long
as no change has been achieved, build a homogenous mass that directs
its anger against the existent establishment, yet will fall apart once the
initial aims of the revolutionary process have been achieved.118
The famous German intellectual therefore realized and foresaw
many problems revolutions would face in the future as well. A successful revolutionary change needed the unity of those who longed
for it. For Engels, the Revolution of 1848 failed because the bourgeoisie feared the proletariat more than the counter-revolutionary forces.119
In 1895, when he wrote the introduction to a new edition of Marx’s
The Class Struggles in France, 1848 – 1850, Engels, from a retrospective,
again argued that a new revolution would only be possible as a consequence of a crisis and that all revolutions of the past had been expressions of a continuing class struggle between those who ruled and
117 Ibid.
118 Ibid.
119 Friedrich Engels, »Die Rolle der Gewalt in der Geschichte (1887 / 8),« in MEW 21:
408. A similar evaluation could be taken into consideration for the German Revolution of 1918 / 19.
77
78
Frank Jacob
those who were exploited.120 At the same time, he emphasized that
all these revolutions of the past had been minority revolutions, i. e.
changes that were led, instrumentalized, and exploited by a leading
minority who claimed to lead and rule in the name of a majority.121
The radicalization of revolutionary processes was also described as
the consequence of the wishes of a majority, whose representatives
claimed to follow the original revolutionary ideals, protecting them
from, amongst others, the counter-revolutionary forces. The revolutionary masses, on the other hand, lose their energy and will to
drive the revolution any further — one could argue this is because
the masses tend to be less radical than anticipated–, especially since
utopian dreams often turned into bitter disappointment about the
promised change.122 After 1851, according to Engels, the chance for a
revolution from below had ended and what followed were revolutions
from above. He also argued that the time in which small groups were
able to launch a revolutionary development or process had ended and
that a true revolution could only be reached if the masses got actively
involved, claiming their only »true historical right,« i. e. »the right for
revolution.«123
The Afterlife of Engel’s Thoughts on Revolution, or:
What to Make of Engel’s Revolution Theory?
It was the incompleteness of Marx and Engels’s writings with regard to revolution theory that allowed so many to reinterpret them
according to current revolutionary processes. They claimed themselves to be acting on behalf of the two eminent revolutionaries and
120 Friedrich Engels, »Einleitung zu Karl Marx‹ ›Klassenkämpfe in Frankreich 1848
bis 1850‹ (1895),« in MEW 22: 511 and 513.
121 Ibid., 513. Reading this text passage one could also argue, that Engels predicted
many corruptions of revolutionary processes, e. g. Russia in 1917.
122 Ibid., 514.
123 Ibid., 523 – 524.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
theoretical thinkers of the 19th century, although they were acting
in the realities of the 20th century.124 Of course, Engels, like Marx as
well, also considered the French Revolution as an example of when
the masses actively sought change,125 but was disappointed when
they failed to stay active in 1848. Yet by witnessing the latter events,
Engels in particular understood that revolutions would never be
fully explained solely by theory. They need the masses to be successful, and the masses tend to react according to their necessities and
current demands, not according to a plan, a script, or theoretical
assumptions. Therefore, the human factor is probably the most decisive one in every revolutionary process. A successful revolution,
and this aspect is supposedly the most important one in Engels’s
theoretical approach, needed to be a revolution by the majority of
the people.126 Liana Longinotti highlights this in particular when
she writes that
[t]he considerations that are articulated around the theme of the »majority revolution« not only arose in Engels from the lesson of caution
derived from the bankruptcy experience of the previous revolutions,
but at the same time represented the definitive landing point of a
reflection, extended over time, around the ways and forms of the
proletarian revolution, which, after starting from the delineation of
its successive phases and having passed through the subsumption of
the democratic stage within the socialist revolution, came to nuclear
its specific and distinctive features with respect to the great bourgeois
revolutions.127
124 A. James Gregor, Marxism and the Making of China: A Doctrinal History (New
York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014), 25.
125 Friedrich Engels, »Die Entwicklung des Sozialismus von der Utopie zur Wissenschaft (1880),« in MEW 19: 194.
126 Liana Longinotti, »Friedrich Engels e la ›Rivoluzione di maggioranza‹,« Studi
Storici 15, no. 4 (1974): 822.
127 Ibid., 823.
79
80
Frank Jacob
Engels, who in his later years played an important role in making
Marx’s work available and advertising its value,128 at the same time
remained a revolutionary and was almost sad about the neglect of a
revolutionary necessity by the German Social Democrats. In a letter
to Richard Fischer (1855 – 1926), he argued: »In the Vorwärts the revolution is sometimes denied with the same effort as it was preached
for — maybe sometimes again — in the past.«129 The Engels of the
1890s, in contrast to his more youthful self of the 1840s, had witnessed
two failed revolutionary attempts, and now wanted to wait until the
Social Democratic influence on society was sufficiently strong130 and
until the military had been sufficiently politicized, especially since he
knew that a revolution without the latter’s support might be as senseless as it would be hopeless.131
In contrast to his later instrumentalization in internal party fights
about the revolutionary character of the German Social Democratic
Party (SPD), Engels had never given up his belief in and hopes for a
successful revolution.132 Nevertheless, his edition of Marx’s The Class
Struggles in France 1848 – 1850 and his introduction for many seemed
to anticipate many of Eduard Bernstein’s (1850 – 1932) later claims
about peaceful political tactics and the abandonment of the revolution.133 Hence, »Engels would have found a parliamentary system gen128 Michael C. Howard and John E. King, A History of Marxian Economics, vol. 1:
1883 – 1929 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989), 3 – 20; J. Jemnitz,
»Engels and the Problems of the International Labour Movement in the 1890s,«
Acta Historica Academiae Scientiarum Hungaricae 17, no. 3 / 4 (1971): 225 – 255.
129 Friedrich Engels to Richard Fischer, March 8, 1895, cited in Hans-Josef Steinberg, »Revolution und Legalität: Ein unveröffentlichter Brief Friedrich Engels’s
an Richard Fischer,« International Review of Social History 12, no. 2 (1967): 182.
130 Ibid., 184.
131 Ibid., 187.
132 Ibid., 187 – 188. Also see Neumann and von Hagen, »Engels and Marx on Revolution,« 278; Hollander, »Marx and Engels on Constitutional Reform vs. Revolution,« 53.
133 Ibid., 51 – 52. On Bernstein and his revisionist position see: Manfred B. Steger,
The Quest for Evolutionary Socialism: Eduard Bernstein and Social Democracy
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
erating a working-class majority unwilling to carry out a communist
program unacceptable«134 and was never in favor of abandoning the
revolution as the ultima ratio of Social Democratic politics.135
Regardless of his wish for a revolutionary change, Engels would
also not have been in favor of Lenin’s interpretation of his and Marx’s
work.136 From the Russian revolutionary’s perspective, as Bertram D.
Wolfe (1896 – 1977), the American communist, scholar, and later anti-communist during the Cold War, remarked,
[i]t was embarrassing to note that Engels had lived on to 1895, and
had been brilliantly prophetic in describing the line-up, the magnitude, the nations under arms, the upsurge of national feeling, the
socialist desire to avert war (pacifism) and to defend the fatherland
(defensism), the possibility that the socialist parties and the International would be temporarily drowned and broken by a flood of
chauvinism, the million-massed death toll, the spread of ruin, demoralization and barbarism throughout Europe, in the very war into
which Europe had now entered.137
After their death, as Engels had complained in a letter to Paul Lafargue (1842 – 1911) in 1882, his and Marx’s works had been turned
»into the dogmatism of a scientific oracle«138 instead of an attempt to
understand a revolution in its timely context, something that would
become even worse with regard to Soviet Marxism.139 Although lat134 Hollander, »Marx and Engels on Constitutional Reform vs. Revolution,« 54.
135 Hans-Josef Steinberg, »Freiheit und Notwendigkeit: Aus einem verlorenen Brief
von Friedrich Engels an Ernest Belfort Bax vom Jahre 1886,« International Review
of Social History 18, no. 2 (1973): 276 – 280.
136 Bertram D. Wolfe, »Lenin Has Trouble with Engels,« The Russian Review 15,
no. 3 (1956): 197. Also see the more detailed discussion in A. James Gregor, Marxism, Fascism, and Totalitarianism: Chapters in the Intellectual History of Radicalism
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2009), 102 – 135.
137 Wolfe, »Lenin Has Trouble with Engels,« 209.
138 Cited in Schäfer, »Friedrich Engels,« 36.
139 Herbert Marcuse, »Dialectic and Logic Since the War,« in Marxism, Revolution
and Utopia (Collected Papers of Herbert Marcuse, vol. 6), eds. Douglas Kellner
81
82
Frank Jacob
er revolutions would draw inspiration from past events and even attempt to recreate them,140 Engels was never in favor of a dogmatic
revolution theory, especially not in his own writings, where he instead
attempted to describe things to take into consideration for future
revolutionary processes. Like Marx, he was affected by the failed European revolutions in 1848:
Like most of their intellectual contemporaries, they now repudiated
utopianism and turned to »science« as the instrument of progress.
Their revolutionary goals remained unchanged, as did their belief that
labor would one day be transformed from a tool of subjugation to a
»means of emancipation, by offering each individual the opportunity to develop all his faculties, physical and mental, in all directions
and exercise them to the full,« making work a »pleasure instead of a
burden.«141
Engels, however, also realized that the masses were often not the most
reliable revolutionaries: »we men and women are unfortunately so
stupid that we never pluck up courage for real progress unless urged
to it by sufferings that seem almost out of proportion.«142 Yet the role
of the individuals, like their impact on the revolutionary outcomes,
and Clayton Pierce (London / New York: Routledhge 2014), 88.
140 Stephen Eric Bronner, »The Communist Manifesto: Between Past and Present,«
in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto, ed. Jeffrey C.
Isaac (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2012), 145.
141 Joan Campbell, Joy in Work, German Work: The National Debate, 1800 – 1945
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989), 23 – 34. According to Hal
Draper and E. Haberkern, »Marx and Engels came to believe that the French
had ceded the leadership of the revolutionary movement, at least temporarily, to
the Germans.« Hal Draper and E. Haberkern, Karl Marx’s Theory of Revolution,
vol. 5: War and Revolution (New York: NYU Press, 2005), 130.
142 Letter by Engels, February 24, 1893, in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Correspondence 1846 – 1895 (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1934), 510, cited in William
A. Pelz, »Class and Gender: Friedrich Engels’s Contribution to Revolutionary
History,« Science & Society 62, no. 1 (1998), Friedrich Engels: A Critical Centenary
Appreciation: 117.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
could only be understood in a concrete space-time continuum, and
therefore Engels did realize that 1848 was not 1793, that 1871 was not
1848, and so on.143 Due to this realization, the famous German intellectual also always studied the role of common people: »His contributions to understanding the importance of class are many, but among
the most significant are: discerning the importance of the popular
masses in history; understanding how common people express themselves within the culture and language of their times; demonstrating
how historical consciousness is necessary for radical change; and placing the main emphasis on class struggle, as the motor which moves
historical development forward.«144 Considering the role of individuals and the factors that determined their daily life, Engels, applying
Marx’s theoretical ideas about historical materialism, also understood
that »the final causes of all social changes and political revolutions
are to be sought, not in men’s brains, not in men’s better insight into
eternal truth and justice, but in changes in the modes of production
and exchange. They are to be sought not in the philosophy, but in the
economics of each particular epoch.«145 All in all, for Engels,
Marxist revolution required circumstances that made available a society in which the »vast majority« of the population had been rendered
»proletarian,« in the process of which commodity production had
fully matured, generating the material wherewithal to fully liberate
143 Ibid., 118.
144 Ibid., 121.
145 E. N. Trubetskoi, »Toward Characterization of the Theory of Marx and Engels
on the Significance of Ideas in History,« in Problems of Idealism, ed. Edward A.
Purcell (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2003), 127. Trubetskoi criticizes
Engels’s view for being too narrowly focused on historical materialism here: »In
this whole theory there is a large share of truth. It is impossible to deny that
economic facts play a primary role in social revolutions, or that people are generally inclined to sympathize with precisely the legal and political princi-ples that
most correspond to their interests. It is another question whether only economic
interests should be treated as independent causes of social revolutions, whether
they alone determine the legal and political ideals of people.« Ibid., 139. Also see
ibid., 274.
83
84
Frank Jacob
humanity from the curse of poverty and compulsory labor. Among
some of the very last things he was to write, Engels reminded revolutionaries once again that the only truly Marxist revolution was
one undertaken by a population that was essentially urban and proletarian, that would seize the »gigantic productive forces« provided
by mature machine capitalism, so that they might be marshaled to
»planned production.«146
So what are we supposed to make of Engels’s revolution theory, or
is there anything we can make of it at all? While it does not make
sense for revolutionaries to identify themselves with the past,147 it
does make sense to take a minute to look back at Engels’s writings.
They offer us a lot of thoughts about revolutions and provide hope for
their success, while at the same time do not neglect the dangers of every revolutionary process. Engels’s writings about revolutions were an
incomplete theoretical framework, yet were enough to engage future
generations to think about the possibilities, necessities, and problems
revolutions can cause. Therefore, his writings about revolution are
even more important today. Not because we should be too inspired
by 1848 or any other revolution of the past, but rather to sharpen
our mind for possible revolutions in the future. Crises are a necessary
precondition, the role of the masses is essential, and what role will
the military play? Such considerations, willingly or unwillingly, must
lead back to the revolution theory of Friedrich Engels, and it could be
argued that those who wish to see a successful revolution of a majority
would be wise to read his works in advance. If they can avoid the failure of a future revolution, that is maybe only pure chance, but at least
they would be prepared for the possible turns of any revolutionary
process. Considering the importance of such a legacy, it is tragic that
the revolutionary Engels never experienced a successful revolution.
146 Gregor, Marxism and the Making of China, 26. Engels’s citations are taken from
Engels, »Nachwort (1894) [zu ›Soziales aus Russland‹],« MEW 22: 426 – 428.
147 Eric Hobsbawm, »Revolution,« in Revolution in History, eds. Roy Porter and
Mikuláš Teich (Cambridge / New York : Cambridge University Press, 1986), 9.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
After 200 years, it is time to prove his ideas about revolutions and to
use them effectively to provide true freedom for all.
Works Cited
Andrew, Christopher. Secret World: A History of Intelligence. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press, 2018.
Berger, Martin. »Disentangling Engels from Marxandengels.« International
Labor and Working-Class History 12 (1977): 41 – 44.
—. »Engel’s Theory of the Vanishing Army: A Key to the Development of
Marxist Revolutionary Tactics.« The Historian 37, no. 3 (1975): 421 – 435.
Bergmann, Theodor. »Engels on Agriculture.« Science & Society 62, no. 1
(1998), Friedrich Engels: A Critical Centenary Appreciation: 145 – 162.
Bleuel, Hans Peter. Friedrich Engels: Bürger und Revolutionär. Bern / Munich:
Scherz, 1981.
Bronner, Stephen Eric. »The Communist Manifesto: Between Past and Present.« In Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto, ed.
Jeffrey C. Isaac, 144 – 165. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2012.
Campbell, Joan. Joy in Work, German Work: The National Debate, 1800 – 1945.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989.
Claeys, Gregory. »The Political Ideas of the Young Engels, 1842 – 1845:
Owenism, Chartism, and the Question of Violent Revolution in the
Transition from ›Utopian‹ to ›Scientific‹ Socialism.« History of Political
Thought 6, no. 3 (1985): 455 – 478.
Concheiro, Elvira. »A Century after His Death: Friedrich Engels and the
Concept of Political Parties.« Science & Society 62, no. 1 (1998), Friedrich
Engels: A Critical Centenary Appreciation: 163 – 180.
Davis, Horace B. »Nations, Colonies and Social Classes: The Position of
Marx and Engels.« Science & Society 29, no. 1 (1965): 26 – 43.
Draper, Hal and E. Haberkern, Karl Marx’s Theory of Revolution, vol. 5: War
and Revolution. New York: NYU Press, 2005.
Edelstein, Dan. »Revolution in Permanence and the Fall of Popular Sovereignty.« In The Scaffolding of Sovereignty: Global and Aesthetic Perspectives
on the History of a Concept, eds. Zvi Ben-Dor Benite, Stefanos Geroulanos and Nicole Jerr, 371 – 392. New York: Columbia University Press,
2017.
85
86
Frank Jacob
Eichhorn, Wolfgang. »Gesetzmäßigkeit von Revolutionen.« Sitzungsberichte
der Akademie der Wissenschaften der DDR. Gesellschaftswissenschaften 11
(1984).
Engelberg, Ernst and Wolfgang Küttler, eds. Formationstheorie und Geschichte: Studien zur historischen Untersuchung von Gesellschaftsformationen Werk von Marx, Engels und Lenin. Berlin: Akademie-Verlagm 1978.
Engels, Friedrich. »Continental Socialism.« In: Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, vol. 4, 212 – 213. London: Lawrence & Wishart 2010.
—. »Der deutsche Bauernkrieg (1850).« In Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels,
Werke, vol. 7, 327 – 413. Berlin: Dietz, 1960.
—. »Description of Recently Founded Communist Colonies Still in Existence.« In: Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Collected Works, vol. 4,
214 – 228. London: Lawrence & Wishart 2010.
—. »Die Entwicklung des Sozialismus von der Utopie zur Wissenschaft
(1880).« In Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Werke, vol. 19, 189 – 201. Berlin: Dietz, 1962.
—. »Die Rolle der Gewalt in der Geschichte (1887 / 8).« In Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels, Werke, vol. 21, 405 – 461. Berlin: Dietz, 1962.
—. »Einleitung zu Karl Marx‹ ›Klassenkämpfe in Frankreich 1848 bis 1850‹
(1895).« In Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Werke, vol. 22, 509 – 527. Berlin: Dietz, 1963.
—. Herr Eugen Dühring’s Revolution in Science (Anti-Dühring). New York:
International Publishers, 1939.
—. »Grundsätze des Kommunismus (1847).« In Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Werke, vol. 4 , 361 – 380. Berlin: Dietz, 1974. Accessed June 13, 2020.
http://www.mlwerke.de/me/me04/me04_361.htm.
—. »Revolution und Konterrevolution in Deutschland (1851 / 52).« In Karl
Marx and Friedrich Engels, Werke, vol. 8, 5 – 108. Berlin: Dietz, 1988. Accessed June 13, 2020. https://www.marxists.org/deutsch/archiv/marx-engels/1851/deutsch/index.htm.
—. The Condition of the Working Class in England, London 1891 [Leipzig 1845].
Accessed July 29, 2020. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/
download/pdf/condition-working-class-england.pdf.
—. »The Internal Crises.« Rheinische Zeitung, no. 343 and 344, December
9 and 10, 1842. Accessed July 29, 2020. https://marxists.catbull.com/archive/marx/works/1842/12/09.htm.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
Erbentraut, Philip and Torben Lütjen. »Eine Welt zu gewinnen: Entstehungskontext, Wirkungsweise undNarrationsstruktur des ›Kommunistischen Manifests‹.« In Manifeste: Geschichte und Gegenwart des
politischen Appells, eds. Johanna Klatt and Robert Lorenz, 73 – 98. Bielefeld: Transcript Verlag, 2010.
Fetscher, Iring. »Friedrich Engels, Polen und der Russische Imperialismus.«
Osteuropa 7, no. 6 (1957): 431 – 432.
Gregor, A. James. Marxism and the Making of China: A Doctrinal History.
New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2014.
—. Marxism, Fascism, and Totalitarianism: Chapters in the Intellectual History
of Radicalism. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2009.
Hammen, Oscar J. »Alienation, Communism, and Revolution in the
Marx-Engels Briefwechsel.« Journal of the History of Ideas 33, no. 1 (1972):
77 – 100.
Henderson, William O. The Life of Friedrich Engels, 2 vols. London: Frank
Cass, 1976.
Hobsbawm, Eric. »Revolution.« In Revolution in History, eds. Roy Porter
and Mikuláš Teich, 5 – 46. Cambridge / New York : Cambridge University
Press, 1986.
Hollander, Samuel. Friedrich Engels and Marxian Political Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.
—. »Marx and Engels on Constitutional Reform vs. Revolution: Their ›Revisionism‹ Reviewed.« Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 57,
no. 122 (2010), Democracy and Exchange: 51 – 91.
Howard, Michael C. and John E. King. A History of Marxian Economics,
vol. 1: 1883 – 1929. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989.
Hundt, Martin. »Zur Entwicklung der marxistischen Revolutionstheorie
nach der Revolution von 1848 / 49.« Marx-Engels-Jahrbuch 10 (1986):
31 – 64.
Hunley, J. D. Life and Thought of Friedrich Engels: A Reinterpretation of His
Life and Thought. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991.
Hunt, Tristram. Friedrich Engels: Der Mann, der den Marxismus erfand, transl.
by Klaus-Dieter Schmidt, third edition. Berlin: List, 2020.
Ito, Narihiko. »Realismus und Utopismus.« In Zwischen Utopie und Kritik:
Friedrich Engels – ein »Klassiker« nach 100 Jahren, eds. Theodor Bergmann,
Mario Keßler, Joost Kircz and Gert Schäfer, 23 – 33. Hamburg: VSA, 1996.
Jacob, Frank. 1917: Die korrumpierte Revolution. Marburg: Büchner, 2020.
87
88
Frank Jacob
Jemnitz, J. »Engels and the Problems of the International Labour Movement in the 1890s.« Acta Historica Academiae Scientiarum Hungaricae 17,
no. 3 / 4 (1971): 225 – 255.
Joseph, Jonathan. Social Theory: Conflict, Cohesion and Consent. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press, 2003.
Kitchen, Martin. »Friedrich Engels’s Theory of War.« Military Affairs 41, no. 3
(1977): 119 – 124.
Kossok, Manfred. »Karl Marx und die Grundlegung wissenschaftlicher Revolutionsauffassung.« Zeitschrift für Geschichtswissenschaft 28, no. 2 (1980):
99 – 118.
—. »Revolution und Weltgeschichte im Werk von Walter Markov.« In Walter Markov, Weltgeschichte im Revolutionsquadrat, ed. and introduced by
Manfred Kossok, vii-xv. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1982.
—, ed. Studien über die Revolution. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1969.
— and Walter Markov, eds. Studien zur vergleichenden Revolutionsgeschichte
1500 – 1917. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1974.
Krieger, Leonard. »Marx and Engels as Historians.« Journal of the History of
Ideas 14, no. 3 (1953): 381 – 403.
Labica, Georges. »Engels and Marxist Philosophy.« Science & Society 62, no. 1
(1998), Friedrich Engels: A Critical Centenary Appreciation: 13 – 34.
Lenin, Wladimir I. »Über die Volksfeinde.« In Werke, vol. 25, 45 – 46. Berlin:
Dietz, 1972.
Leopold, David. »The Structure of Marx and Engels’s Considered Account of
Utopian Socialism.« History of Political Thought 26, no. 3 (2005): 443 – 466.
Levine, Norman. The Tragic Deception: Marx contra Engels. Santa Barbara / Oxford, Clio Books, 1975.
Longinotti, Liana. »Friedrich Engels e la ›Rivoluzione di maggioranza‹.« Studi Storici 15, no. 4 (1974): 769 – 827.
Löwy, Michael. »Friedrich Engels on Religion and Class Struggle.« Science & Society 62, no. 1 (1998), Friedrich Engels: A Critical Centenary Appreciation: 79 – 87.
Lucas, Erhard. »Marx‹ und Engels’s Auseinandersetzung mit Darwin: Zur
Differenz zwischen Marx und Engels.« International Review of Social History 9, no. 3 (1964): 433 – 469.
Marcuse, Herbert. »Dialectic and Logic Since the War.« In Marxism, Revolution and Utopia (Collected Papers of Herbert Marcuse, vol. 6), eds.
Friedrich Engels and Revolution Theory
Douglas Kellner and Clayton Pierce, 82 – 93. London / New York: Routledge 2014.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. »Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei
(1848).« In Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Werke, vol. 4, 459 – 493. Berlin: Dietz, 1959.
—. The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (1852). Accessed August
20, 2020. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1852/18thbrumaire/.
— and Friedrich Engels. The German Ideology. Moscow: Progress Publishers,
1976.
Moss, Bernard H. »Marx and Engels on French Social Democracy: Historians or Revolutionaries?« Journal of the History of Ideas 46, no. 4 (1985):
539 – 557.
Murphy, John, ed. Socialism and Communism. New York: Britannica Educational Publishing, 2015.
Neumann, Sigmund and Mark von Hagen. »Engels and Marx on Revolution, War, and the Army in Society.« In Makers of Modern Strategy from
Machiavelli to the Nuclear Age, ed. Peter Paret, 262 – 280. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1986.
Nimtz, August H. »Marx and Engels on the Revolutionary Party.« Socialist
Register 53 (2017), Rethinking Revolution: 247 – 264.
Oncken, Hermann. »Friedrich Engels und die Anfänge des deutschen Kommunismus.« Historische Zeitschrift 123, no. 2 (1921): 239 – 266.
Pelz, William A. »Class and Gender: Friedrich Engels’s Contribution to Revolutionary History.« Science & Society 62, no. 1 (1998), Friedrich Engels: A
Critical Centenary Appreciation: 117 – 126.
Schäfer, Gert. »Friedrich Engels: Builder of Closed Systems?« Science & Society 62, no. 1 (1998), Friedrich Engels: A Critical Centenary Appreciation:
35 – 47.
Schmeitzner, Mike. »Lenin und die Diktatur des Proletariats – Begriff,
Konzeption, Ermöglichung.« Totalitarismus und Demokratie 14 (2017):
17 – 69.
Silberner, Edmund. The Problem of War in Nineteenth Century Economic
Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1946.
Singh, Rustam. »Status of Violence in Marx’s Theory of Revolution.« Economic and Political Weekly 24, no. 4 (1989): 9 – 20.
89
90
Frank Jacob
Stadler, Peter. »Wirtschaftskrise und Revolution bei Marx und Engels: Zur
Entwicklung ihres Denkens inden 1850er Jahren,« Historische Zeitschrift
199, no. 1 (1964): 113 – 144. 52x
Steger, Manfred B. The Quest for Evolutionary Socialism: Eduard Bernstein
and Social Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997.
Steinberg, Hans-Josef. »Freiheit und Notwendigkeit: Aus einem verlorenen
Brief von Friedrich Engels an Ernest Belfort Bax vom Jahre 1886.« International Review of Social History 18, no. 2 (1973): 276 – 280.
Hans-Josef Steinberg, »Revolution und Legalität: Ein unveröffentlichter
Brief Friedrich Engels’s an Richard Fischer,« International Review of Social History 12, no. 2 (1967): 177 – 189. 54x
Trubetskoi, E. N. »Toward Characterization of the Theory of Marx and Engels on the Significance of Ideas in History.« In Problems of Idealism, ed.
Edward A. Purcell, 124 – 142. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2003.
Ree, Erik van. »Marxism as Permanent Revolution.« History of Political
Thought 34, no. 3 (2013): 540 – 563.
Wallach, Jehuda L. Die Kriegslehre von Friedrich Engels. Frankfurt am Main:
Europäische Verlagsanstalt, 1968.
Wittfogel, Karl A. »The Marxist View of Russian Society and Revolution.«
World Politics 12, no. 4 (1960): 487 – 508.
Wolf, Eric R. »The Peasant War in Germany: Friedrich Engels as Social Historian.« Science & Society 51, no. 1 (1987): 82 – 92.
Wolfe, Bertram D. »Lenin Has Trouble with Engels.« The Russian Review 15,
no. 3 (1956): 196 – 209.
Zimmerman, Andrew. »From the Second American Revolution to the First
International and Back Again: Marxism, the Popular Front and the
American Civil War.« In The World the Civil War Made, eds. Gregory P.
Downs and Kate Masur, 304 – 336. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North
Carolina Press, 2015.
Zirke, Gerhard. Der General: Friedrich Engels, der erste Militârtheoretiker der
Arbeiterklasse. Leipzig: Urania-Verlag, 1967.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the
Formation of the Manchu State
Understanding the Pre-State Manchu Society
from an Engelsian Perspective (1550 – 1651)
Jia Feng
Introduction
In The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State (1884), Friedrich Engels portrays a progressive picture of how human society
evolved from a simple gentile order to the state in correspondence
with the development of social production and the changed forms
of property distribution, more specifically from common to private
ownerships. To illustrate this fundamental transformation, much ink
has been spilled on the institutions of society organized in peacetimes
based on and in wartimes mobilized by gens, which Engels defines as
»the foundation of the social order of most, if not all, the barbarian
peoples of the world.«1 In a gens, all members shared equal tribal and
gentile rights, such as equal share of common property, equal voice in
democratic assembly, and shared obligations to revenge and defense.2
Several gentes constitute a phratry (brotherhood), and several phratries constitute a tribe.3 Facing common enemies might bring different gens into a temporary confederation, but most of them dissolved
right upon the fading of threats.4 As Engels argues, the gentile system
was simply a »natural grouping,« suited perfectly to sparse popula-
1
2
3
4
Friedrich Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State (Chippendale, Australia: Resistance Books, 2004), 53.
Ibid., 88 – 92.
Ibid., 92 – 93.
Ibid., 95.
92
Jia Feng
tions over a vast territory.5 Although war captives were indeed admitted into the conqueror’s tribe, because of the extremely undeveloped
level of social production, where human labor »yielded no noticeable
surplus as yet over the cost of its maintenance,« war prisoners were
killed. Even for the tribes that indeed adopted the defeated as equal
members, »the tribe remained the boundary for man, in relation to
himself as well as to outsiders.«6
As Engels argues, arising from the development of social production, intertribal wars not only broke loose the gentile institutions
based on personal ties of blood but also facilitated the rise of public power, the institutionalization of which was the state. In other
words, the state emerged inevitably at the price of the dissolution
of the old gentile order. Engels suggests that the rise of patriarchal
authority and the inheritance of property by children was at the root
of incentives of the supreme tribal leaders to extend their territories
by waging wars.7 The development of private property also rendered
it necessary to create hereditary system by replacing elective offices
and, due to the corresponding demand for surplus human labor, to
expand the enslavement of war prisoners to fellow members of the
tribe. Personal wealth is thus »respected as the highest treasure, and
the old gentile institutions are perverted in order to justify forcible
robbery of wealth.«8
Incorporating more people set in motion the growth of institutions serving public purposes, more specifically the increasing centralized royal power. The institutions that facilitated royal power
included the rise of the retinue. The quickly expanding population
could not be governed anymore »by means of the old gentile constitution.« The king’s permanent retinue or royal hereditary offices
took its place.9 Public power existed in various forms, including the
5
6
7
8
9
Ibid., 148.
Ibid., 65, 99.
Ibid., 106.
Ibid., 107.
Ibid., 143.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
police force, army, and administrative officers.10 New rules also arose
that institutionalized the unequal distribution of booty and the concentration of wealth in the hands of the military commander and
subcommanders or rising nobility.11
Especially illuminating is Engels’s insight on the lasting influence
of the old gentile mentality when gentile organizations dissolved in
many places in the face of the growing state machine.12 When commenting on why, in the 5th century, the invading Germans could
transform the declining Roman empire that had a far greater level of
civilization than the invaders themselves, Engels writes,
What was the mysterious charm with which the Germans infused
new vitality into dying Europe? Was it the innate magic power of the
German race, as our jingo historians would have it? By no means. Of
course, the Germans were a highly gifted Aryan tribe, especially at
that time, in full process of vigorous development. It was not their
specific national qualities that rejuvenated Europe, however, but simply—their barbarism, their gentile constitution.13
The »gentile mentality« also entailed »personal efficiency and bravery,«
which was widely seen in nomadic groups, and the sense of cohesion
settling in gentes.14 In other words, when »conquered and conquerors were almost at the same stage of economic development and the
economic basis of society remained the same as before … the gentile
constitution could continue for many centuries in a changed, territorial form.«15
The founders of the Qing dynasty (1644 – 1911), the last dynasty in
Chinese imperial history, were ethnically Manchus, who originated in
10
11
12
13
14
15
Ibid., 115, 136.
Ibid., 136, 143.
Ibid., 115.
Ibid., 145 – 146.
Ibid., 146.
Ibid., 157.
93
94
Jia Feng
Manchuria, part of the northeastern provinces of today’s China.16 The
name »Manchus« was not officially adopted until 1636, before which
later Manchu conquerors were called »Jurchens« by the Ming people
due to their shared ethnic origins with the Jin dynasty (1115 – 1234)
founders.17 At the turn of the 15th century, there were three major
Jurchen sub-groups: the Jianzhou, the Haixi, and the Yeren, so-called
because of their varying degrees of economic development.18 In the
late 16th century, the Jianzhou branch rose to dominance by annexing
the other Jurchen tribes, and within decades went on to conquer the
Ming court (1368 – 1644).
In this paper, I will demonstrate that The Origin of the Family,
Private Property, and the State offers certain important insights to
our understanding of the transition of late 16th- and early 17th-century Manchu tribal society into a state. For example, Engels makes
it clear that the gens is an institution »common to all barbarians
up to their entry into civilization.«19 Pre-conquest Manchu society,
as I will point out below, despite its regular economic exchanges
with the then reigning Ming court (1368 – 1644), was tribal in nature,
organized by different equivalents of gens, phratries, and tribes.
Hunting organizations were also based on gentes, first as the niru
(company), the basic hunting and later military unit under which
Jurchen men were organized, and then the gusa, larger divisions
consisting of several niru, or banners. These were the foundational
organizations of the Eight Banners System, the Manchus’ trademark system, which recent revisionist Qing historiography claims
to be the institutional bulwark of Manchu senses of in-groupness
16
17
18
19
Franz Michael, The Origin of Manchu Rule in China: Frontier and Bureaucracy as
Interacting Forces in the Chinese Empire (New York: Octagon Books, 1965), 12.
Liu Xiaomeng, Manzu cong buluo dao guojia de fazhan (Beijing: Zhongguo shehui kexue chubanshe, 2007), 1.
Pei Huang, Reorienting the Manchus: A Study of Sinicization, 1583 – 1795 (Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press, 2011), 101.
Engels, Origin, 88.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
or Manchu ethnic identity and to play a crucial role in making and
maintaining Qing rule.20
The fact that pre-conquest Manchu society was fundamentally
tribal and no exception to what Engels says about pre-state social
organizations carries important theoretical weight because this fact
poses a question on the special nature of the »Manchu way,« a package of time-honored Manchu customs, especially warrior values and
martial culture dating back to the Manchu tribal and hunting age,
the upholding of which is designated by recent Qing historiography
as crucial to the strengthening and maintaining of the dynasty’s rule.
Moreover, in its narration of the earliest period of Qing history, this
scholarship tends to see the tribal-era development of banners, hunting units by origin, not only as a uniquely Manchu innovation but
also as offering incentives to enhanced Manchu ethnic solidary, a
key element to the transformation of Manchu tribes into the state.21
Drawing upon insights from Engels’s The Origin of the Family, Private
Property, and the State, I will not only argue that the banners, essentially military units organized according to Manchu gentes, were not
exceptions to any other early society before their entry into or contact
with civilization, but also that this ethnic-centered view falls short in
explaining the socio-economic and correspondingly political process
of Manchu state-building.
20
21
Mark Elliott, The Manchu Way: The Eight Banners and Ethnic Identity in Late Imperial China (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2001). Recent revisionist Qing
historiography argues that the Manchu ethnic identity persisted throughout the
dynasty and that the Manchu ruling class‹ conscious efforts to institutionalize
the differences between the conquerors and the conquered not only enhanced
the cohesion among the conquest elites but also strengthened the ties with culturally adjacent Inner Asian minority groups. See Pamela Crossley, A Translucent
Mirror: History and Identity in Qing Imperial Ideology (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1999); Evelyn S. Rawski, The Last Emperors: A Social History of
Qing Imperial Institutions (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998). For a
review of the New Qing history scholarship, see Joanna Waley-Cohen, »The New
Qing History,« Radical History Review 88 (2004): 193 – 206.
Elliott, The Manchu Way, 8 – 13.
95
96
Jia Feng
My argument in this paper consists of two distinct but interrelated
parts. First, I will argue that the Manchus‹ persistent consciousness to
maintain their identities as a distinct ethnic group, and in particular
such virtues as the toughness and virility suited to hunting and tribal
life, in fact evinces the lasting legacy of Manchu »gentile mentality«
in Engels’s discussion of the role of barbarism in rejuvenating the conquered but more civilized societies. This mechanism by which gentile
institutions continued to exist for a long time in changed forms, however, is not a unique quality of Manchus, but common to »the most
diverse savage and barbarian peoples of the present day.«22
The second part of my argument is related to the first, in the sense
that to fully comprehend the Manchu state-building process in the
late 16th and early 17th centuries, it is critical to recognize the tribal
and gentile origins of the Eight Banners System and to analyze the
making of the Qing state not as enhancing those tribal elements, but
as an opposite process of undermining, in part at least, the Manchu
gentile constitution. More specifically, I will argue that the Manchu
state arose precisely at the price of dissolving the economic principle
of the »eight privileges,« namely the equal distribution of booty, people, and lands among eight great families, the latter of which derived
from Manchu time-honored customs and economically buttressed
the Eight Banners System. I will demonstrate that the rapidly expanding territories and substantially increased number of people brought
under the control of the regime created new institutional options for
the throne’s incumbent to enhance his power through mobilizing
new tax resources and establishing new administrative organizations
and allowed him opportunities to maneuver the gentile principles of
equality among tribal members in a despotic direction. The economic
principle that conditioned the Eight Banners System became increasingly contradictory with the development of political centralization;
the consolidation of royal power precisely resulted from the defeating
of the dominance of old gentile Manchu rules. In short, it was pre22
Engels, Origin, 126, 157.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
cisely in the place where the dominance of the gentile constitution
of the Manchu conquest regime dissolved that the Qing state arose.
Despite taking Engels’s insights on gentile institutions of early
human society seriously, however, I do not mean to say that all prestate societies were the same, nor do I deny the unique characteristics,
trajectories, and dynamics of the Manchu state-building process. In
fact, because Engels’s theoretical framework is based on empirical evidence primarily from Europe and occasionally from America, much
more work could be done from the perspective of non-Western histories to form a more balanced account of the transition from tribal
society to the state. More specifically, I will delineate in detail the
changing land and population policies of the Manchu conquest regime and, in particular, how the increased number of people brought
under the conqueror’s control turned the Manchu state formation
in a centralized direction. While this study will reveal the not too
special socio-economic origin of the »Manchu Way,« it will also take
on Engels’s insights on the almost universal transition of early human
society from gens to state to argue that the Manchu state arose not
from the maintaining of gentile principles, but at the cost of them.
Thus, Engels’s analysis of the breakdowns of the gens as an inevitable
part of the emergence of state sheds new light on the socio-economic
elements of Manchu state-building in the early 17th century and the
nature of the »Manchu Way.«
The Manchu Gentile Society Before Conquest
Before conquest, the Jurchen society was organized in tribes, with
the hala (clan, family) as the basic tribal unit followed by the mukun
(clan, extended family), a social organization that grew out of and
increasingly replaced the hala as a more elemental unit to organize
people due to population growth, migration, and intertribal wars.
In early Jurchen history, the hala was the very earliest social form
and thus the first social identity, which had a continued legacy across
97
98
Jia Feng
generations. The word hala was among the oldest Manchu words.23
Sharing the same hala usually indicated sharing the same geographical and ancestral origin.24 Jurchen society of the hala stage also shared
marriage and other social organizing principles with other barbarians.
For example, Manchu ethnogenesis records often show a marriage of
a male to a female from a different hala, which indicates the prohibition of marriage within the same tribal group.25 Other early Manchu
records also demonstrate the practices of adopting individual members of a gens who had been either hit by a natural disaster or on the
losing side of an intertribal war into another.26
As Jurchen society grew both in size and complexity, the new social organization of the mukun emerged to replace the hala as the
most basic clan unit. A distinct feature of the mukun was that, unlike
the hala, being members of the same mukun did not necessarily mean
either the same ancestry or the same surname. Instead, while people in the same mukun might have different ancestral origins, people
sharing the same ancestry might have different surnames.27 By the
mid-16th century, due to the high frequency of migration as a result
of wars, trades, and some sort of tribal annexation, the mukun had
replaced the hala in some more advanced societies such as Jianzhou
and Haixi Jurchens.28 In short, while the difference between the hala
and mukun was not always so clear, generally speaking, the hala was
larger than the mukun. As Aisin Gioro, the surname of the Qing ruler,
demonstrated, within the Gioro hala, there were many other mukun
than Aisin itself, such as Yi’ergen, Hulun, Tongyan, etc.29
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
Liu, Manzu cong buluo dao guojia de fazhan, 18.
Liu Xiaomeng, Manzu de shehui yu shenghuo (Beijing: Beijing tushuguan chubanshe, 1998), 18.
Manzhou shilu, vol. 1 (Taibei: Huawen chubanshe, 1964), 4 – 5.
Liu, Manzu cong buluo dao guojia de fazhan, 21.
Liu, Manzu de shehui yu shenghuo, 14.
Ortai et al., eds., Baqi manzhou shizu tongpu, vol. 12 (Shenyang: Liaohai chubanshe,
2002 [1744]), 12.
Mo Dongyin, Manzushi luncong (Beijing: Renmin chubanshe, 1958), 23.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
As a nomadic group, hunting was the central aspect of Jurchen
economic life. In early Jurchen society, the uksun was the basic hunting unit.30 The very activity of hunting required each band to maintain a moderate size for quicker mobility, making the uksun a more
desirable form than the mukun. Hunting spoils were equally distributed between tribal members, a fact that complies perfectly with what
Engels says about barbarians up to their entry into civilization who
lived in gens governed by the principles of democracy and equality
between individuals.31 In the Manchu language, each share was called
a ubu. Originally denoting the equal distribution of hunting spoils,
the ubu later became the unit of the equal distribution of booty, captives, lands, and power.32
Within each uksun, more direct blood ties were maintained in
a boo, or a family. The Jurchen hunting and gathering economy set
an upper limit on the size of a family; while the eldest sons moved
out upon adulthood to establish their own independent families, the
youngest stayed to inherit the family fortune.33
Hunting activities were generally organized based on the family-clan organization. Jurchen hunters made their hunting tours in
companies based on the unit of the gasan. In each tour, every hunter
was allowed to shoot one arrow. The basic hunting unit was decimally
organized, and was composed of a headman (ejen) and nine hunters.34
The ejen was chosen based on his recognized hunting experience.35
Social organizations that arose from hunting practices prompted
the forging of early quasi-military institutions. In daily and smallscale hunting activities, Jurchen hunters marched in groups, encircled
a large swath of forest from all directions, gradually tightened the
30
31
32
33
34
35
Liu, Manzu de shehui yu shenghuo, 29.
Engels, Origin, 88, 90.
Chen Wenshi, »Qingtaizong shidai de zhongyao zhengzhi cuoshi,« in Chen
Wenshi, Mingqing zhengzhi shehui shilun, vol. 2 (Taibei: Taiwan xuesheng shuju,
1991), 423 – 525.
Liu, Manzu cong buluo dao guojia de fazhan, 47.
Taizu shilu, vol. 3 (Taibei: Huawen chubanshe, 1964), 6.
Zhao-lian, Xiaoting zalu (Beijing: Zhonghuashuju, 2017 [1814 – 1826]), 220.
99
100
Jia Feng
circle, and finally drove animals within into a clearing to be shot.36
A larger-scale hunting activity, known in Manchu as aba, contained
a couple of decimal units. Before marching into the targeted forest,
hunters gathered in arrays, distinguished by the colors of their banners. In a broader view, the banners were spread like a tree diagram,
with the yellow banner placed at the center bottom, two shoulder
banners colored red and white down to the left and right, and two
head banners of blue placed further below each of the shoulder banners.37 The Manchu word niru means a big arrow. In traditional
Jurchen hunting practices, since each warrior was allowed one arrow
and nine warriors went out together under the leadership of a banner
headman, niru later developed into the most rudimentary military
unit, and niru ejen connoted the leader of each niru who gave out
commands through banner signals.38
Even before the launching of large-scale Manchu conquests, these
basic gentile institutions of Jurchen society underwent changes due to
intertribal marriages, migration, and war, the last of which in particular took people beyond boundaries of the gentes they were originally
born into, giving rise to a new identity based on place rather than
original gens. The Manchu word gasan is precisely meant to denote
the villages surrounding castles used for military defense.39 In the mid15th century, Jurchen settlements along the Tumen River were found
to have members of different lineages within the same village. That is
to say, while some villages were composed only of members from the
same hala, others were a blend of people with different lineage ties.40
Although they shared similar social organizations and economic forms of life, Jurchens across tribes were by no means the same.
Residing in the eastern and southern portions of Manchuria geographically most adjacent to Korean and Ming influence with richer
36
37
38
39
40
Elliott, The Manchu Way, 57.
Mo, Manzushi luncong, 65.
Zheng, Tanwei ji, 175.
Liu, Manzu cong buluo dao guojia de fazhan, 38.
Ibid., 52.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
soils, milder winters, and more plains suited to farming, the Jianzhou
branch of Jurchens developed more advanced sedentary ways of life
with a higher ratio of agriculture in their economy than other tribes.41
Their adjacency with the Ming, moreover, made possible their looting campaigns in Liaodong, from which Jurchens brought back both
agricultural tools and people.42 By the mid-16th century, intertribal
competitions for resources were so intense that large-scale intertribal
wars had begun, culminating in the dominance of the Jianzhou, the
origins of later Manchu rule.
In sum, the hala and later the mukun, namely gentes for Manchus, were the basic institutions of Jurchen society by the mid-16th
century, complying perfectly with Engels’s statement that »the gens
is an institution common to all barbarians up to their entry into
civilization.«43 Gentile institutions also played an important role in
the social and economic lives of Jurchens. As the foregoing discussions have shown, hunting activities were organized based on gentile
divisions, and the way that prey was distributed demonstrated that
equality between tribal members was the rule of the day.44 Moreover,
the emergence of gasan, namely villages in which residents were not
necessarily from the same gens, shows the increasing complexity of
Jurchen society. By this time, the organization of Jurchen society was
not yet that of a state, and in fact a state was far from an evitable
option.45 Most tribes never turned into a state until the rise of the
Jianzhou branch, the one that first turned »habitual cooperation«
among tribes into a regular »permanent league« and then continued
to challenge the Ming rule.46
41
42
43
44
45
46
Huang, Reorienting the Manchus, 101.
Mo, Manzushi luncong, 47.
Engels, Origin, 88.
Certain features of the Manchu gens before their conquest in the late 16th century remarkably resembled what Engels says about the Iroquois gens. Ibid., 88 – 92.
Ibid., 95 – 97.
Ibid., 96.
101
102
Jia Feng
Early Conquests and Using »Banners«
to Absorb New Population
In the 1570s, large-scale intertribal wars started. After Nurhaci
(1559 – 1626) succeeded to the leadership of the Jianzhou branch in
1583, Jianzhou soon rose to supreme power in Manchuria. Having
taken over a number of tribal city-states near his residence at Hulan
Hada, he won a decisive victory over the allied army of Hulun Ssu
Kuo in 1593, bringing home 3,000 horses and thousands of suits of
armor while causing 4,000 casualties. Early victories gave Nurhaci
not only prestige among Jurchen tribes but also booty to cover the
costs of future expansions.47 Weaker tribes chose to surrender without
resistance. In 1588, following the pledge of the Suwan chief, more
tribes joined, bringing their people to Nurhaci’s territory.48 Of the 66
tribes Nurhaci incorporated, 17 surrendered without resistance.49 In
the years 1599 – 1601, he conquered the Hada and added charters of
the surrendered to the 500 charters he already possessed, becoming
the wealthiest chieftain in Manchuria.50 In 1607 he conquered the
Hoifa, and finally, in 1613, after he defeated Ula, the vast majority of
Jianzhou and Haixi lands and people were brought under his control.51
A commander of an army of only 500 soldiers in 1583, within two
decades, Nurhaci had unified all Jurchen tribes.
One strategy Nurhaci adopted was to absorb the conquered population without dismantling their social institutions. More specifically,
what Nurhaci did was to organize newly subordinated groups into
niru while keeping their old clan organizations intact.52 For example,
47
48
49
50
51
52
Arthur W. Hummel, Eminent Chinese of the Ch’ing Period (1644 – 1912) (Washington DC: US Government Printing Office, 1943), 596.
Wang Xianqian, ed., Donghua lu, vol. 1 (Shanghai: Shanghai guji chubanshe,
2002 [1884]), 12.
Hideo Ishibashi, Shindai Chūgoku no shomondai (Tokyo: Yamakawa shuppansha,
1995), 25.
Huang, Reorienting the Manchus, 70.
Hummel, Eminent Chinese, 596.
Zhao Erxun, ed., Qingshi gao, (Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1977 [1928]), 9232.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
103
in 1593, while defeating the Zhusheli, Nurhaci moved its people to his
own territories. In 1599, while conquering the Hada tribe, Nurhaci
incorporated them into his household registration system.53 Through
the transformation of the hunting niru into the military niru, Nurhaci infused into those previously dispersed Jurchen tribes a new relationship with the Manchu regime.
Meanwhile, Nurhaci allowed the headman of the conquered tribe
to maintain his original status, namely to become the niru-ejen, the
leader of the newly forged military company. For instance, in 1595 / 6,
during his return tour from Jianzhou Jurchen, the Korean diplomat
Shen Zhongyi wrote that under the leadership of the brothers Nurhaci and Surhaci, there were two hundred military headmen. All of
them were old tribal chieftains and governed their own former tribal
members.54 The tribal leaders were incorporated into the Jianzhou
conquest regime, while old tribal organizations such as gasan, mukun
and uksun were left undisturbed. A new identity to the conqueror’s
regime began to transcend the previous allegiance to the tribe. By
bringing together people with diverse tribal affiliations and geographical origins, Nurhaci’s conquest set in motion a remarkable political
integration of Jurchen society.55
As Nurhaci’s military conquests progressed successfully, the niru
organizations, originally hunting organizations, extended to other areas of Jurchen lives and gradually became a principal institution that
worked to reconfigure Jurchen society and to rationalize the management of the Jurchen population. In 1616, the functions of niru
companies extended to civilian areas. For example, in July of 1616,
Nurhaci asked each niru to dispatch three persons to help build 200
53
54
55
Zheng, Tanwei ji, 10 – 11.
Shen Zhongyi, »Jianzhou jicheng tuji,« in Qingchu shiliao congkan dishi, ed.
Liaoning daxue lishixi (Shenyang: Liaoning daxue lishixi, 1979), 23.
Zhou Yuanlian, Qingchao xingqi shi (Changchun: Jilin wenshi chubanshe, 1986),
118 – 119.
104
Jia Feng
boats.56 Other examples can be found in areas of agricultural production, public services, festival celebrations, military logistics, etc. For
instance, in 1613, Nurhaci asked each niru to send ten adult males and
four cattle to cultivate wastelands.57 In 1622, he asked each niru to
offer three cattle as sacrifices for the end-of-year celebration.58 Starting as the basic hunting unit of ten warriors, the niru later extended
its application not only to military occasions to have 300 warriors in
each of them but also to the general population as a unit of the equal
distribution of public duties.
When conquests remained confined to Manchuria before 1621,
conquered populations were divided largely by ethnic differences. The
conquered Jurchens, or jusen in Manchu, were incorporated into the
conquerors‹ niru organizations, while Chinese, Koreans, and Mongolians, or ethnically non-Jurchens, became booi aha or household slaves
of the conquerors.59 In other words, while the conquered from other
Manchu tribes became jusen, enjoying a similar status to the old jusen
of Nurhaci’s original tribes, the non-Manchu conquered populations
were subjugated as booi bondservants. The jusen population enjoyed a
free status because a long-cherished tradition of pre-conquest Jurchen
society was that Jurchens never enslaved their own men.60 For instance, in 1603, after Nurhaci conquered the Hada tribe, he moved
Hada people to regions adjacent to his residence and enrolled them in
the already existing niru population registration system. Applying the
same rule to the vanquished Huifa tribe, in 1607 Nurhaci »disarmed
its troops but enlisted its people.« Having conquered the powerful
56
First Historical Archive, ed., Manwen laodang (Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1990),
47.
57 Ibid., 19.
58 Ibid., 280.
59 For a detailed semantic analysis of the word Manju and its relationship with
jusen, see Ishibashi, Shindai chūgoku no shomondai, 19 – 36.
60 Wang Zhonghan, ed., Chaoxian lichao shilu (Shenyang: Liaoning daxue lishixi,
1979), 127.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
105
Ula tribe, in 1613 Nurhaci granted niru memberships to its »tens of
thousands of households.«61
Generally speaking, before the conquests extended to areas with
a non-Manchu population as a majority, the conquered population
from other Manchu tribes was usually organized into niru organizations, while ethnically non-Manchu people, mostly Chinese and
Koreans, were subjugated as booi aha. Incorporating the conquered
population in such ways perfectly suited the Manchu regime during
the early conquests when a regular tax system remained absent and
public duties could be accomplished at the lowest possible cost.62
In 1619, Nurhaci won a decisive battle at Sarhu, his first major
confrontation with the Ming court, which marked the beginning of
the expansion of his conquests to the Han Chinese territory. That
year, Nurhaci took over 70 fortified towns, including Fushun, Kaiyuan, and Tieling. Tens of thousands of Chinese as well as Koreans
fighting for the Ming were captured. These captives were distributed as booi aha among the Manchu nobles and put to work on the
private landed estates of Manchu nobles as agricultural slaves.63 This
battle thus significantly expanded the booi aha population and fueled
the growth of tokso while also creating a larger imbalance of wealth
among the Manchus.
Upon taking over Mukden, Nurhaci laid claim to vacated and
uncultivated lands, equalized land shares, and conducted a universal redistribution of lands. »Masterless« lands, left behind by the
thousands of Liaodong people who had fled, were transformed into
state-controlled lands.64 Similarly to what Engels says about the ways
that Germans distributed land among themselves upon conquering
Roman provinces, on July 14th of 1621, Nurhaci decreed a reclamation
61
62
63
64
Li Yanguang and Guan Jie, Manzu tongshi (Shenyang: Liaoning minzu chubanshe,
1991), 143.
Manwen laodang, 19, 37; Zheng, Tanweiji, 195 – 199.
Wang, Qingshi zakao, 24.
Kenneth M. Swope, The Military Collapse of China’s Ming Dynasty, 1618 – 44
(New York: Routledge, 2014), 37 – 38.
106
Jia Feng
of 300,000 xiang (a Chinese equivalent of 10,000 square meters) of
wasteland in Haizhou and distributed it to Manchu soldiers in residence.65 He then extended the offer of land to Han Chinese from the
previous five Liaodong garrisons, asking each recipient to pay a quota
of grain in tax and corvee labor duties in return.66 In November, military duties were added to the mandatory service required from each
adult male land recipient.67 The land redistribution was carried out
only on »masterless« lands, based on the spirit of bringing the least
disruption to the existing social order.68
Entering regions with a Han Chinese population as the majority changed the fiscal system of the conquering regime dramatically.
The conquered land and population in Liaodong brought invaluable
revenue and the manpower needed to build the public sector of the
conquering regime. The land distribution and the subsequent tax collection were all patterned on the Ming model.69 In March of 1621, the
land quota that each adult male received settled on five xiang of grain
fields and one xiang of cotton fields. 70 In addition, Liaodong people
were also asked to pay corvee labor and undertake military service as
assigned by the regime.71
The availability of agricultural revenues fueled the early development of bureaucracy. To establish tighter local controls, the Manchu
regime followed the Ming practice of organizing commoners under
hundred-man chiefs (baizhang), who represented the state in charge
of local administration.72 In 1621, to better handle ethnic relations,
the crown founded the Bureau of Supreme Judges (Dutang yamen).
This court was charged with providing residences for the Chinese,
handling escapees, transporting military logistic supplies, harvesting
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
Engels, Origin, 142; Manwen laodang, 219.
Manwen laodang, 244.
Ibid., 256, 263.
Jin-liang, Manzhou midang (Taibei: Wenhai chubanshe, 1967), 60.
Zhou, Qingchao xingqi shi, 266.
Manwen laodang, 220.
Li and Guan, Manzu tongshi, 203.
Manwen laodang, 271.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
107
grain, and negotiating merchandise prices.73 In 1622, 24 legal judges (duanshiguan) were appointed to supervise legal practices within
banners.74
The conquerors distributed lands among themselves, and their
corvee labor duties were shifted to the conquered Chinese. Because
of the taxes and corvee labor contributed by the Chinese, the Manchu
jusen commoners enjoyed less tax and service burdens. Their duties
could thus concentrate on those that were truly »Manchu« since the
gentile age. Such labor included digging ginseng, hunting, raising
horses, escorting trading tours, baking seawater, etc.75
Although progress in state-building had been made as the conquests expanded, the regime still only had limited tax resources, inevitably hampering the development of bureaucracy and supporting
the continued strengthening of the old Manchu gentile rule of »eight
privileges« (bafen). The rule of »eight privileges,« also called jakun
ubu in Manchu, which originated from the tribal hunting tradition,
stipulated the equal distribution of spoils, lands, and people among
the Manchu top leadership, a principle of property distribution commonly found in gentile societies.76 It functioned first as a principle of
distribution of booty. Valuables from booty such as gold, silver, and
silk were assembled, equally distributed to each hoiso beile (the commander of a banner) and finally through each individual beile into
the hands of those who participated in the campaign.77 The rule soon
became a set of overarching principles for organizing the new Manchu state. More specifically, the Manchu princes, primarily Nurhaci’s
sons and nephews, were granted one share of the eight equal portions
of the political, economic, and legal power of the Manchu state. This
73
74
75
76
77
Yao Nianci, Qingchu zhengzhishi tanwei (Shenyang: Liaoning minzu chubanshe,
2008), 101.
Ibid., 82.
Wang, Qingshi zakao, 20.
Similar military democracy was also found among Romans and Greeks. See Engels, Origin, 122 – 123.
Manwen laodang, 95.
108
Jia Feng
system was officially confirmed in March of 1622 when the eight hosoi
beile were declared to be the central committee of the Manchu state.
Under this structure, decisions on the imperial succession, state affairs
generally, and serious legal cases not handled by lower courts were
made collectively.78
While this principle offered a ruling solution for such a rudimental regime with only limited fiscal resources, it later ran counter to the
strengthening of royal power, the latter of which became increasingly
imminent for the consolidation of the regime’s ever-expanding conquests. Within his own banner, the beile prince’s power was unparalleled. He was both the owner of the largest estates and the master of
the booi aha population within his own banner. To be sure, Manchu
jusen commoners within a banner had to meet labor and other services demanded by the crown. But it was the beile prince who represented his banner at the imperial conference, and all public orders of
the state had to be passed down through him. Therefore, under the
system of the »eight privileges,« although the emperor did enjoy more
public authority and his own yellow banner was widely acknowledged
as being superior, he could not make arbitrary decisions. All state
matters had to be discussed with the seven beile princes first.79 The
Manchu emperor’s power was so limited that a later Chinese advisor
at the Manchu court quipped that the crown was no different from
a beile prince of his own yellow banner.80 This consultative nature of
the feudal confederacy of the early Manchu state, formalized with the
establishment of the Eight Banners System, planted the seeds of the
future political crisis.
When first entering Liaodong in 1621, Nurhaci did attempt to
continue the old practices of subjugating all captives as serfs into
Manchu princely estates, or tokso in Manchu. Between 1621 and 1625,
the regime suffered from an extreme grain shortage, and the insuffi78
79
80
Ibid., 345 – 348.
Meng Sen, Mingqingshi lunzhu jikan (Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1959), 218.
Luo Zhenyu, ed., Tiancong chao chengong zouyi (Taibei: Tailian guofeng chubanshe,
1968), 276.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
109
cient development of the tax-collecting bureaus worsened the problem. To meet the financial needs of the military emergency, the ruler
had to reorient his fiscal plan back to the »eight privileges« principle
by subjugating the Chinese to be agricultural slaves on private princely estates.81 According to this policy, all Chinese and their lands were
reorganized into equal-sized landed estates, each equipped with 100
xiang of lands, 13 adult males, and 7 oxen. These new estates were
then distributed to all Manchu military nobles based on their rank.82
When the taxes collected from the agricultural production of the
Ming model could not meet the requirements of the state’s budget,
the old mode of production, featured by a promotion of the growth
of privately owned landed estates and the use of forced bondservant
labor, returned.83
This policy immediately provoked Chinese resistance and significantly reduced agricultural productivity, making the existing grain
shortage even worse.84 Intimidated by the oppressive Manchu policy
in 1625, more Chinese fled, the incentive to work dropped, and harvests hit a new low.85 This policy granted more economic autonomy
to beile princes. The economic power of the Manchu nobility soared,
but at the cost of undermining the public coffers of the regime. On
the newly formed princely estates, tax-collecting power fell into the
hands of beile princes, accelerating fiscal decentralization.86 In short,
as conquests continued to expand, applying old gentile organizations
to incorporate the conquered population was confronted with resistance and chaos. Thus, the Manchu population policy in the years
1621 – 1625 showed that the old practice of turning the non-Manchu
population into household slaves was meeting its limits.
81
82
83
84
85
86
Jin-liang, Manzhou midang, 73.
Manwen laodang, 644.
Zhou, Qingchao xingqi shi, 347, 351.
Ibid., 345, 347; Wu Tingyu et al, eds., Qingdai manzhou tudi zhidu yanjiu
(Changchun: Jilinwenshi chubanshe, 1993), 29.
Manwen laodang, 858.
Meng, Mingqingshi lunzhu jikan, 233.
110
Jia Feng
Continued Conquests, Dismantled Gentile Constitution,
and the Rise of Royal Power
In The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State, Engels
suggests that among many other favorable factors for the rise of royal
power that arose from military conquests, there was one institution
that especially favored it: »the retinue.«87 In regards to the mechanism of continued warfare and the rise of royal power, Engels writes:
»The military commander who had acquired fame gathered around
his person a host of booty-loving young warriors pledged to loyalty to
him personally, as he was to them. He fed them, gave them gifts and
organized them on hierarchical principles: a bodyguard and a troop
ready for immediate action in short expeditions, a trained corps of
officers for larger campaigns.«88 Never-ending conquests were necessary, because, as Engels explains, »they could be held together only by
continuous warfare and plundering expeditions.«89
As early Manchu conquests remained confined to Manchuria,
several factors conducive to the strengthening of the ruling power had already arisen. The first was the booi or bondservants of the
Manchu ruler. Most Chinese booi came from captives taken between
1618 and 1621 in Fushun and Shenyang, constituting the main staffing for the later establishment of the Qing Imperial Household Department (neiwufu).90 The booi were among the earliest followers of
Nurhaci’s military career. In 1584, when an assassin posed a security
threat to Nurhaci, it was his booi niyalma that protected him from
being harmed.91 During the time when supplies of Jurchen soldiers
fell short, it was the booi who either fought shoulder to shoulder with
87
88
89
90
91
Engels, Origin, 136.
Ibid.
Ibid.
Preston M. Torbert, The Ch’ing Imperial Household Department: A Study of its
Organization and Principal Functions, 1662 – 1796 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1970), 16 – 17.
Manzhou shilu, 9.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
their masters or provided logistical support. The booi also engaged in
collecting war spoils for their masters.92 In the early days of Nurhaci’s
career, when well-equipped and organized troops fell short, it was his
booi warriors who played a crucial role in securing his early victories.93
By serving as his private security guards, personal servants, and more
generally as a category of the population that was only supposed to
owe their service to the leader, booi played a role in the rise of Nurhaci’s power.
Personal agents of a similar kind also included the khan’s private
guards, known as bayara. The word bayara means guard or troops on
guard duty. In organizational terms, bayara were selected based on
military merit from each niru to undertake public duties. The bayara
warriors were recruited from each niru to meet a variety of military
duties.94 In 1635, after the division between the Upper Three Banners
and the Lower Five Banners was made, the institutional structure
of the bayara troops was changed correspondingly.95 After the Manchu state became a national regime in 1644, the Upper Three bayara
troops (Bordered Yellow, Plain Yellow, and Plain White) became privy
security guards of the emperor.96
In The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State, Engels
not only shows that the emergence of the state was the result of the
development of private property, but the accumulation of wealth into
the military commander’s hands facilitated it.97 The early rise of Manchu power evinces this aspect. More specifically, through the monop92
Du Jiaji, Baqi yu qingchao zhengzhi lungao (Beijing: Renmin chubanshe, 2008),
95.
93 Zheng, Tanwei ji, 111.
94 Korehiro Anami, Shinsho gunji shi ronkō (Tokyo: Kōyō shobō, 1980), 181.
95 For documental evidence of the division between Upper Three and Lower Five
Banners and its influence on the founding of the Imperial Household Department, see Meng, Mingqingshi lunzhu jikan, 243. Also see Jonathan Spence, Ts’ao
Yin and the K’ang-hsi Emperor, Bondservant and Master (New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 1978), 10.
96 Zheng, Tanwei ji, 187.
97 Engels, Origin, 106 – 107.
111
112
Jia Feng
olized control of Jurchen special products such as ginseng, pearl, and
furs and other measures to expand his fiscal resources, Nurhaci gained
crucial funding for his early military successes. A special Jurchen article that perhaps played the greatest role in Nurhaci’s rise was ginseng. In the 16th century, the Ming court’s high demand for ginseng
supplies gave this product a great market value.98 Abundant evidence
shows that the rise of Nurhaci’s power went hand in hand with his
success in the ginseng business. »At the age of nineteen, Nurhaci is
said to have left his father to trade in ginseng at the Fushun horse
market.«99 By the 1590s, »Nurhaci had already amassed a great fortune
by monopolizing the trade in pearls, ginseng, fur, etc.; by mining; by
taking silver in return for his yearly tribute to the Ming court; and by
pillaging weaker tribes.«100 In particular, by inventing a new method
of preserving ginseng, Nurhaci was able to sell it more dearly, which
brought him more profits.101 By the end of the 16th century, Ming
officials had already noticed that it was Nurhaci’s monopolization of
ginseng on frontier horse markets that gave him dangerous economic
power. Witnessing the Jurchen threat looming large in the 1620s, the
Ming official on the Liaodong Peninsula, Cheng Kaihu, wrote, »Nurhaci (nuqiu) had long been wealthy and powerful by monopolizing
profits of furs and ginseng.«102
The emergence of retinues or private bodyguards and the »robbery
of wealth« by the supreme military commander, as Engels has shown,
were but by-products of continued conquests. It was the latter that,
in the end, shattered the old gentile institutions, which for a long
98
Van Jay Symons, »The Ch’ing Ginseng Monopoly« (PhD diss., Brown University,
1974), 121.
99 Ibid., 122.
100 Hummel, Eminent Chinese, 596.
101 Zhou Yuanlian, Qingchao kaiguoshi yanjiu (Shenyang: Liaoning renmin chubanshe,
1981), 58.
102 Cheng Kaihu, »Dongyi nu’erhachi kao,« in Qing ruguan qian shiliao xuanji,
vol. 1, ed. Pan Zhe, Li Hongbin and Sun Fangming (Beijing: People’s University
Press, 1985), 106.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
time before the conquest had played an overarching role in shaping
Manchu society.103
When Abahai (1592 – 1643), Nurhaci’s eighth son, succeeded to the
throne in 1627, tribal military democracy remained the political ethos
that dominated the regime. On his deathbed, Nurhaci issued a set of
instructions that granted more economic and political power to the
beile princes with the »eight privileges.« He believed that it was a collegial rule, in which all the banner princes were to have an equal voice
in policy formation, rather than an imperial system that helped guarantee the political success of the Manchu state. He urged the various
princes to share the wealth acquired equally as their state expanded
and to remonstrate with each other if any wrongdoing occurred.104
Such a principle of collegial rule made the beile princes the equal
beneficiaries of the thrones and lands of all subjugated peoples; nonetheless, it also reflected the fiscal limits of the Manchu regime and its
inability to afford a fully functional bureaucracy. In 1634, responding
to a criticism that the Manchu state cared more about taking wealth
for the ruler alone rather than for building stronger public coffers,
Abahai’s Chinese advisor explained, »Because lands of our state have
not expanded enough and people are still struggling for existence, the
day that Ming taxation system being applied in our state has not yet
come.«105 In the 1620 – 1630s, this immature fiscal system left the Manchu state no choice but to adopt a fiscal policy called »raising people
by eight banners« (baqi fenyang guoren; Manchu: ujimbi), namely to
let the eight beile princes share both the burdens of state administration and the power of the state.
After 1627, Manchu conquest entered a golden era, marked by a
string of new military successes in regions with majority Chinese and
Mongol populations. In 1630, Abahai went on to conquer the towns
103 Engels, Origin, 107.
104 Taizong shilu, 4.
105 Taizong shilu, 301.
113
114
Jia Feng
of Luanzhou and Qian’an, among others.106 The year 1631 saw his
splendid victory in the Siege of Dalinghe.107 These military successes
brought about a significant change to the previous structure of the
Eight Banners System, the institutional bulwark of the old principle
of »eight privileges,« which remained untouched when Abahai succeeded the throne.
The first change was the addition of the eight Mongol banners.
In 1621, two Mongol niru companies were formed from 645 Mongol
households of the Kalga tribe brought to the Manchu state.108 The
years after 1622 saw a large-scale incorporation of the Mongol population into the Manchu regime. In 1631, two separate Mongol banners (menggu erqi), detached from the Manchu banners, were established.109 In 1635, the Mongol banners expanded to eight, paralleled
with the already existing eight Manchu banners.110
The second change, related to the first, was to create eight Chinese
banners, which shaped the Manchu regime in a more profound way.
For the first few decades in the history of the Manchu conquest, when
it came to the issue of Chinese captives, the usual approach adopted
by the Manchu regime was simple but brutal: either to kill them all
or to subjugate them as bondservants.111 The first significant change
occurred after the Siege of Liaodong in 1621. Then, after Abahai assumed his rule in 1627, there developed a clear tendency for Chinese
institutions to rise up in the Manchu state machinery. The year 1628
saw the first civil service exam organized by the Manchu regime to
select Chinese talents with a booi status to serve in Manchu bureaus.112
As the conquest regime expanded to the Ming territories, the Manchu
ruler gradually turned from the old co-habitancy policy of Manchus
106 Chen Jiahua and Fu Kedong, »Baqi hanjun kaolve,« in Manzushi yanjiuji, ed.
Wang Zhonghan (Beijing: Zhongguo shehui kexue chubanshe, 1988), 290.
107 Manwen laodang, 1131 – 57.
108 Yao, Qingchu zhengzhishi tanwei, 158; Wang, Qingshi zakao, 119.
109 Yao, Qingchu zhengzhishi tanwei, 158 – 159.
110 Ibid., 159 – 160.
111 Manwen laodang, 62.
112 Yao, Qingchu zhengzhishi tanwei, 161.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
and Chinese to the idea of establishing separate Chinese banners. In
1637, the number of Chinese banners increased to two, four in 1639,
and finally eight in 1642.
The establishment of eight Mongol and Chinese banners not only
signified a new way by the Manchu regime to incorporate a conquered population who were ethnically different, but also provided
leeway for the throne to break the collegial rule with seven top Manchu nobles and centralize power in his own hands. One telling example of how the incorporation of the conquered populations changed
the nature of the regime was the establishment of three additional
Mongol banners that did not fall under the jurisdiction of the »eight
privileges« and were under the throne’s direct control. That is, while
the total number of male adults of the eleven Mongol banners formed
in 1635 was 16,953, the three Mongol banners falling outside the »eight
privileges« had 9,123 male adults, making up more than half of the total.113 More evidence suggests that this practice as to the organization
of Mongol banners later became the norm.114 In addition, in 1636,
the three outside vassal Mongol banner leaders were granted imperial
titles by the throne, forging a tangible sense of personal loyalty among
the banner leaders to the throne.115 All of this helped to enlarge the
crown’s personal authority and to gain an upper hand over the princes.
A similar arrangement was found in the establishment of the Chinese banners. In 1633, after Kong Youde (1602 – 1652), Geng Zhongming (?-1649), Shang Kexi (1604 – 1676) and Shen Zhixiang (?-1648),
the four high-ranking frontier officials of the Ming, shifted loyalty
to the Manchu, they were organized into special Chinese banners
that fell outside of the jurisdiction of the »eight privileges.« In Manchu, the relationship between Chinese bannermen and their Manchu
banner leader was called ujimbi, a paternal relationship in which the
Manchu banner leader was the giver of a livelihood. However, the
Chinese bannermen who were in the ranks of special Chinese banners
113 Qi Yunshi, Huangchao fanbu yaolve (Taibei: Wenhai chubanshe, 1965), 21.
114 Tayama, Shindai ni okeru Mōko no shakai seido, 79 – 81.
115 Du, Baqi yu qingchao zhengzhi lungao, 112.
115
116
Jia Feng
were different, because the sole authority for them was the Manchu
imperial court.116
Thanks to the large-scale incorporation of the Chinese and Mongol population into the Manchu regime during this period, Abahai
began to break up the dominance of the »eight privileges« in the political system and to exceed his own power over the princes by controlling more people, lands, and revenues. In 1627, Abahai established
eight senior ministers (ba dachen) and eight banner lieutenant-generals (gusan i ejen) to be dispatched to each banner under the guise
of assisting beile princes on banner affairs. He further established the
new offices of 16 senior officials (shiliu dachen), designed to work with
banner leaders on military affairs and judicial inquisitions.117 Through
these arrangements, the imperial power began to have a strong presence within the banners. The old political order in which princes had
hereditary control over their bannermen and enjoyed absolute administrative autonomy within their banners began to be challenged.118
As territories of the regime expanded, Abahai also acquired a greater fiscal base to carry his centralization agenda even further forward.
In 1629, the Three Inner Courts (nei san yuan), a modified version
of the previous Literary Office (wenguan), were established, charged
with offering administrative advice and secretarial assistance to the
crown.119 Thereafter, this literary bureau became increasingly attractive to Chinese talents who were familiar with Confucian statecraft
and offered them an opportunity to play an advisory role in the decision-making of the Manchu court. The year 1631 saw the establishment of Six Boards (liubu; Manchu: ninggun jurgan) on the Ming
116 Zhang Jinfan and Guo Chengkang, Qing ruguanqian guojia falv zhidushi (Shenyang: Liaoning minzu chubanshe, 1988), 398 – 404; Chen Jiexian, Huangtaiji
xiezhen (Taibei: Yuanliu chubanshe, 2004), 161 – 162; Chen, Mingqing zhengzhi
shehui shilun, vol. 2, 481.
117 Taizong shilu, 6.
118 For a discussion of the actual overlapping staffing during Nurhaci’s reign between banner officers and court officers, see Chen, Mingqing zhengzhi shehui
shilun, 437.
119 Zhang and Guo, Qing ruguanqian guojia falv zhidushi, 83 – 86.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
model, a milestone in the development of the administrative machinery of the Manchu state. Upon his Chinese advisor’s advice, Abahai
went on to establish the Censorate (ducha yuan) in 1636, an independent bureau that supervised and impeached the misconduct of
Manchu nobles and state officials.120 Despite the Manchu dominance,
the staffing of the Six Boards did enjoy a broad ethnic representation.
More importantly, for the first time, Chinese advisors made their way
to the top administrative bureaus of the Manchu court, and the later
trajectory of the development of the Manchu state did prove that they
were the best allies for Abahai’s scheme of centralization.121
As Abahai took those forceful steps to subdue the powerful hosoi
beile princes and placed bureaucratic constraints on them, the principle of the »eight privileges« itself began to change. In 1631, Abahai made a major modification to this principle by granting imperial
protection to any individual who stepped forward to be open about
any misconduct of the beile princes.122 This revision of the »eight privileges« began to loosen the autonomy of the princes‹ patrimony and
thereby placed the princes under the surveillance of the state’s laws. In
1634, Abahai began to revise the time-honored Manchu practice that
the eight princes should share power and wealth equally, and replaced
it with one whereby any benefit acquired from conquests should go
to the »deficient banners« (buzu zhi qi) first.123 This change gave the
Manchu emperor the discretion to decide which banner should be
considered as »deficient,« representing the start of the imperial intervention of the economic jurisdiction of the »eight privileges.« In
1635, the state’s law further deemed the act of hiding the population
as bondservants in order to evade the state’s taxes, which was widely
120 See Xu Mingyuan’s memorial dated February 22, 1634 in Luo, Tiancong chao
chengong zouyi, 399 – 401.
121 For a chart of Manchu, Chinese, and Mongol officials who were appointed to
the Six Boards in 1631, see Zhang and Guo, Qing ruguanqian guojia falv zhidushi,
55.
122 Taizong shilu, 153.
123 Zhongguo diyi lishi dang’anguan, ed., Qingchu neiguoshiyuan manwen dang’an
yibian, vol. 1 (Beijing: Guangming ribao chubanshe, 1989), 111.
117
118
Jia Feng
prevalent in banners as a way to increase the princes‹ personal wealth,
as illegal.124 By making those profound revisions to the »eight privileges,« the imperial power strengthened its control over the clan rule.
The feudal and decentralizing tendency of the clan rule, formed and
buttressed by the Eight Banners System, was effectively constrained.
Despite Abahai’s gains, the fashioning of imperial power was not
completed within his reign, because the crown’s advantage in terms
of the sheer number of banners he possessed was not yet dominant.125
The limits of the accomplishments achieved by Abahai toward a centralized throne were best reflected in the succession crisis following
his death in 1643. Instead of being set by the deceased crown’s testamentary edict, his son’s succession was decided by a joint conference of powerful nobles.126 Abahai’s centralization efforts had met
their limits, because the throne had not taken control of an economy
strong enough to build an efficient bureaucracy. This inevitably led
to the economic reliance of the crown on the financial support of the
princes. When the Manchu regime first entered Beijing in 1644, a
symbolic event of the establishment of the Qing rule, the regime still
faced mounting fiscal challenges, which left Shunzhi (1638 – 1661) no
option but to turn to the princes for help.127
It was the turning into a national regime that fundamentally
changed the fiscal bases of Manchu rule. Upon taking over Beijing,
Manchu rulers made systematic efforts to restore the tax collection
on the Ming model.128 By 1661, the last year of the Shunzhi emperor’s
124 Ibid., 148. For a decree concerning this problem in 1635, see Nobuo Kanda, Jun
Matsumura, and Hidehiro Okada, eds., Kyū Manshūtō (Tokyo: Tōyō bunko,
1972), 61. For a legal case in 1639 concerning the state’s intervention in the tax
evasion problem, see First Historical Archive, ed., Shengjing xingbu yuandang
(Beijing: Qunzhong chubanshe, 1985 [1639 – 1640]), 181.
125 Yao, Qingchu zhengzhishi tanwei, 252 – 53.
126 Robert Oxnam, Ruling from Horseback: Manchu Politics in the Oboi Regency,
1661 – 1669 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1975), 38 – 40.
127 Shin’yo jokei (Seoul: Keijo Teikoku Daigaku Hobun Gakubu, 1935), 425.
128 Frederic Wakeman, Jr., The Great Enterprise: The Manchu Reconstruction of Imperial Order in Seventeenth-Century China (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1985), 416.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
reign, the total count of agricultural lands had reached 549,357,640
mu (one mu is roughly equivalent to 66.7 square meters). The gap
compared to the count of 701,397,628 mu in 1578 is largely due to
the exclusion of lands still under the control of the Southern Ming
court at the time.129 This data suggests that in the first two decades
of the Qing dynasty’s rule, taking control of the national economy
gave the Manchu throne the fiscal resources it needed to build a fully
functioning bureaucracy.
The expansion of the fiscal base of the Qing state in the post-1644
era fundamentally changed the power balance between the throne
and the nobility in general, and the nature of the Eight Banners System in particular. The years 1643 – 1651 saw a remarkable reduction in
the number of princely power contenders and continued tendencies
to gravitate power toward the throne, laying the foundation for the
Upper Three Banners after the young Shunzhi emperor assumed his
personal rule.130 In the post-1644 period, while each bannerman was
granted a piece of banner land as their salary farm, they also began
to receive silver or rice salaries directly from the crown. Initially only
granted to cavalry soldiers, offers of silver or rice stipends extended
to craftsmen, infantrymen, guards, and armored soldiers, although
the salary gap still existed, with a soldier’s monthly salary being two
tales and a craftsman’s salary only one tale.131 A significant salary increase occurred after the Qing defeated the Southern Ming court
(1644 – 1662), because this victory, by expanding tax-collecting areas
to South China, brought the Qing more revenues.132
129 Liang Fangzhong, Zhongguo lidai hukou tiandi Tianfu tongji (Shanghai: Shanghai renmin chubanshe, 1980), 341, 380.
130 The three banners were his own Plain White banner, with the new additions of
Plain Blue (preceded by Manggultai) and Bordered White (preceded by Dodo).
131 Fu Lehuan, Liaoshi congkao (Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1984), 419.
132 For scholarly literature on the Southern Ming, a loyalist movement that was
active in South China following the collapse of the Ming Dynasty in 1644, see
Lynn A. Struve, The Southern Ming, 1644 – 1662 (New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 1984); Wakeman, Jr., The Great Enterprise, 319 – 413.
119
120
Jia Feng
The changes to the military and political systems of the regime
were also seen in the establishment of the Green Standard Army (lvying), a centralized army recruited exclusively from the Chinese population.133 The earliest recruits came from those who had surrendered
from the Ming army, later joined by recruits who opted to do so as a
way of making a living.134 Unlike Manchu bannermen, soldiers in the
Green Standard Army received salaries paid in monetary cash and / or
in rice directly from the state fiscal system.135 In 1654, the number of
Green Standard Army soldiers became triple that of Manchu banner
soldiers. To feed the new troops, the Qing government paid an annual salary of 11,518,400 tales in silver. Although the Qing government
occasionally sought new financial sources to supplement the salary
payments by selling offices (juanna) and opening up wasteland, in
general, the majority of Chinese soldiers‹ salaries were distributed by
the Board of Revenue.136 Since the salaries of the soldiers came from
the government, not the princes, they became the crown’s soldiers,
not to be compromised by the rule of the »eight privileges« anymore.
This changed power balance between the crown and the princes
was immediately seen in the creation of new government regulations,
designed to further check the influence of the princes in state affairs.
In 1651, the Shunzhi emperor decreed that bureaucrats working in
a banner did not have to come from the same banner. For example,
a plain yellow bannerman could have an appointment in the plain
white banner, a bordered yellow bannerman could have the same in
the plain yellow banner, etc. Since then, the princes began to lose
personal control of personnel and appointments within their own
133 Luo Ergang, Lvying bingzhi (Shanghai: Commercial Press, 1937), 26.
134 Ibid., 17.
135 The earliest record about the salaries of Green Standard Army soldiers was found
in 1654, which was 11,518,400 tales of silver. For sources of Green Standard Army
soldiers‹ salaries, see Lai Fushun, »Qingchu lvying bingzhi« (MA diss., Institute
of Literary Studies of Private Chinese Culture College, Taibei, 1977), 167. For a
representative view concerning the importance of the Manchus‹ privileged identities as the conquerors, see Elliott, The Manchu Way, 2 – 13, 175 – 209.
136 Lai, »Qingchu lvying bingzhi,« 168.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
banners. By 1651, the princes had even lost their power in the imperial decision-making process. Thereafter, they took part in discussions
on state affairs only as high-ranking state officials, not in the same
way as they used to in the Deliberative Council of Princes.137 In 1651,
the incumbent of the Manchu throne both nominally and in reality
established his imperial authority, not by strengthening the gentile
military democracy that facilitated the conquest in its early stages, but
by passing beyond it: »the gentile order was finished« and »the state
took its place.«138
Conclusion
Engels’s The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State provides invaluable insights on the politico-economic aspects of the early
Qing state-building process and, more generally, on the transition
from the Manchu tribal society to the state. First, recognizing the
fact that the pre-conquest Manchu society was fundamentally tribal
and no exception to what Engels says about pre-state social organizations gets to the very root of the nature of the Eight Banners System,
a trademark Manchu institution, which recent Qing historiography
has regarded as the key to the maintaining of the Manchu ethnic
identity throughout the dynasty and thus to the understanding of
the nature of the Qing rule. The foregoing discussion has shown that,
originating in the Manchu tribal era, the banners were, by origin, a
constellation of gens-based hunting units. Using hunting units as early regime-building bases was not uncommon to other minority conquest groups in world civilizations, nor, after the state was in place,
was the lasting influence of the »Manchu Way,« namely certain virtues such as toughness and virility in hunting and tribal life, unique.
When discussing how the Athenian state arose to replace the gentes,
137 Du, Baqi yu qingchao zhengzhi lungao, 257 – 259.
138 Engels, Origin, 137.
121
122
Jia Feng
Engels argues that although »the organs of the gentile constitution
were eliminated from public affairs … their moral influence, the traditional conceptions and views of the old gentile period, survived
for a long time and expired only gradually.«139 It was rather common
among many other minority conquest groups for the »gentile mentality« to linger in its influence on the new social condition, despite the
fact that »organs of the gentile constitution« were being transformed
into organs of the state, and, for the benefit of the conquerors, this
had to be done »quickly.«140
My second point is that only by coming to the gentile root of the
Eight Banners System can we fully understand the Qing state-building process in the first half of the 17th century. More specifically, I
have argued that although tribal organizations such as banners played
a crucial role in absorbing conquered populations when conquests
remained confined to Manchuria, such organizations met their limits
after the conquests extended to regions with a Han Chinese population as a majority, because, to borrow Engels’s words, it was impossible to absorb the entire mass into »gentile bodies« or to »rule
them with the aid of the latter.«141 As Engels suggests, »[a]s soon as
society passed beyond the limits for which this constitution sufficed,
the gentile order was finished. It burst asunder and the state took its
place.«142 Our story above precisely shows that the Qing state arose
not by sticking to or enhancing the gentile rule of »eight privileges,«
but by undermining it. In sum, Engels’s insights on the economic
bases of the transition of the tribal society into the state remain relevant, not only to early civilizations but also to a minority conquest
regime in early modern China. While certainly not intending to offer
a universal theory to explain all the complex and diverse paths of
tribes transitioning into states, Engels’s work at least can serve to enlighten the importance of getting to the politico-economic roots of
139
140
141
142
Ibid., 115.
Ibid., 143, 146.
Ibid., 143.
Ibid., 137.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
certain ethnically colored institutions. In this case, it was those politico-economic forces that motivated the transition of Manchu society
from tribe to state that determined the manner and degree to which
a particular ethnic identity influenced the new order — not vice versa.
Works Cited
Anami, Korehiro. Shinsho gunji shi ronkō. Tokyo: Kōyō shobō, 1980.
Chen, Jiahua and Fu Kedong. »Baqi hanjun kaolve.« In Manzushi yanjiuji,
edited by Wang Zhonghan. Beijing: Zhongguo shehui kexue chubanshe,
1988.
Chen, Jiexian. Huangtaiji xiezhen. Taibei: Yuanliu chubanshe, 2004.
Chen, Wenshi. »Qingtaizong shidai de zhongyao zhengzhi cuoshi.« In Chen
Wenshi, Mingqing zhengzhi shehui shilun, vol. 2. Taibei: Taiwan xuesheng
shuju, 1991.
Crossley, Pamela. A Translucent Mirror: History and Identity in Qing Imperial
Ideology. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1999.
Du, Jiaji. Baqi yu qingchao zhengzhi lungao. Beijing: Renmin chubanshe,
2008.
Elliott, Mark. The Manchu Way: The Eight Banners and Ethnic Identity in Late
Imperial China. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2001.
Engels, Friedrich. The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State.
Chippendale, Australia: Resistance Books, 2004.
First Historical Archive, ed. Manwen laodang. Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1990.
First Historical Archive, ed. Shengjing xingbu yuandang. Beijing: Qunzhong
chubanshe, 1985 [1639 – 1640].
Fu, Lehuan. Liaoshi congkao. Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1984.
Hummel, Arthur W. Eminent Chinese of the Ch’ing Period (1644 – 1912). Washington DC: US Government Printing Office, 1943.
Ishibashi, Hideo. Shindai Chūgoku no shomondai. Tokyo: Yamakawa
shuppansha, 1995.
Jin-liang. Manzhou midang. Taibei: Wenhai chubanshe, 1967.
Kaihu, Cheng. »Dongyi nu’erhachi kao.« In Qing ruguan qian shiliao xuanji,
vol. 1, edited by Pan Zhe, Li Hongbin and Sun Fangming. Beijing: People’s University Press, 1985.
123
124
Jia Feng
Kanda, Nobuo, Jun Matsumura, and Hidehiro Okada, eds. Kyū Manshūtō.
Tokyo: Tōyō bunko, 1972.
Lai, Fushun. »Qingchu lvying bingzhi.« MA diss., Institute of Literary Studies of Private Chinese Culture College, Taibei, 1977.
Li, Yanguang and Guan Jie. Manzu tongshi. Shenyang: Liaoning minzu
chubanshe, 1991.
Liang, Fangzhong. Zhongguo lidai hukou tiandi Tianfu tongji. Shanghai:
Shanghai renmin chubanshe, 1980.
Liu, Xiaomeng. Manzu cong buluo dao guojia de fazhan. Beijing: Zhongguo
shehui kexue chubanshe, 2007.
Liu, Xiaomeng. Manzu de shehui yu shenghuo. Beijing: Beijing tushuguan
chubanshe, 1998.
Luo, Ergang. Lvying bingzhi. Shanghai: Commercial Press, 1937.
Luo, Zhenyu, ed. Tiancong chao chengong zouyi. Taibei: Tailian guofeng
chubanshe, 1968.
Manzhou shilu, comp. by reign. Reprint. Taibei: Huawen chubanshe, 1964.
Meng, Sen. Mingqingshi lunzhu jikan. Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1959.
Michael, Franz. The Origin of Manchu Rule in China: Frontier and Bureaucracy as Interacting Forces in the Chinese Empire. New York: Octagon Books,
1965.
Mo, Dongyin. Manzushi luncong. Beijing: Renmin chubanshe, 1958.
Ortai et al., eds. Baqi manzhou shizu tongpu. Shenyang: Liaohaichubanshe,
2002 [1744].
Oxnam, Robert. Ruling from Horseback: Manchu Politics in the Oboi Regency,
1661 – 1669. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1975.
Pei, Huang. Reorienting the Manchus: A Study of Sinicization, 1583 – 1795. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2011.
Qi, Yunshi. Huangchao fanbu yaolve. Taibei: Wenhai chubanshe, 1965.
Rawski, Evelyn S. The Last Emperors: A Social History of Qing Imperial Institutions. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1998.
Shen, Zhongyi. »Jianzhou jicheng tuji.« In Qingchu shiliao congkan dishi, edited by Liaoning daxue lishixi. Shenyang: Liaoning daxue lishixi, 1979.
Shin’yo jokei. Seoul: Keijo Teikoku Daigaku Hobun Gakubu, 1935.
Spence, Jonathan. Ts’ao Yin and the K’ang-hsi Emperor, Bondservant and Master. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978.
The Gens, Military Conquest, and the Formation of the Manchu State
Struve, Lynn A. The Southern Ming, 1644 – 1662. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1984.
Swope, Kenneth M. The Military Collapse of China’s Ming Dynasty, 1618 – 44.
New York: Routledge, 2014.
Symons, Van Jay. »The Ch’ing Ginseng Monopoly.« PhD diss., Brown University, 1974.
Taizu shilu, comp. by reign. Reprint. Taibei: Huawen chubanshe, 1964.
Torbert, Preston M. The Ch’ing Imperial Household Department: A Study of its
Organization and Principal Functions, 1662 – 1796. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1970.
Wakeman Jr., Frederic. The Great Enterprise: The Manchu Reconstruction of
Imperial Order in Seventeenth-Century China. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1985.
Waley-Cohen, Joanna. »The New Qing History.« Radical History Review 88
(2004): 193 – 206.
Wang, Xianqian, comp. Donghua lu. Shanghai: Shanghai guji chubanshe,
2002 [1884].
Wang, Zhonghan, ed. Chaoxian lichao shilu. Shenyang: Liaoning daxue lishixi,
1979.
Wu, Tingyu et al., eds. Qingdai manzhou tudi zhidu yanjiu. Changchun:
Jilinwenshi chubanshe, 1993.
Yao, Nianci. Qingchu zhengzhishi tanwei. Shenyang: Liaoning minzu
chubanshe, 2008.
Zhang, Jinfan and Guo Chengkang. Qing ruguanqian guojia falv zhidushi.
Shenyang: Liaoning minzu chubanshe, 1988.
Zhao, Erxun, ed. Qingshi gao. Beijing: Zhonghua shuju, 1977 [1928].
Zhao-lian. Xiaoting zalu. Beijing: Zhonghuashuju, 2017 [1814 – 1826].
Zhongguo diyi lishi dang’anguan, ed. Qingchu neiguoshiyuan manwen
dang’an yibian, vol. 1. Beijing: Guangming ribao chubanshe, 1989.
Zhou, Yuanlian. Qingchao kaiguoshi yanjiu. Shenyang: Liaoning renmin
chubanshe, 1981.
Zhou, Yuanlian. Qingchao xingqi shi. Changchun: Jilin wenshi chubanshe,
1986.
125
126
Jia Feng
Acknowledgements of Funding Supports
This work is supported by the National Social Science Fund of China
(20CZS036), Shandong Social Science Planning Fund Program
(19BYSJ56), and the Fundamental Research Funds of Shandong University (2018TB027).
The Contribution of Engels to the
Critique of Political Economy1
Renildo Souza
Friedrich Engels, at the age of 24, launched an effort to criticize Classical Political Economy. In his indignation, the young Engels condemned the triumphant theory of Adam Smith as the hypocrisy of
»beautiful speeches about a love of humanity and cosmopolitanism.«2
Besides protesting, in his Outlines of the Critique of Political Economy,3
he paused in his analysis of classical economic categories, providing
important embryonic formulations for Marxism.
The interpretation of the structure and operation of the capitalist economy, according to the laws, tendencies and regularities from
a socio-historical standpoint, is an integral and relevant part of the
elaboration and evolution of Marxist thought. The first steps in the
critique of economic thought were taken by Engels. Before his meeting with Karl Marx, he wrote Outlines (1843 – 1844), and he published
Franco-German Annals in February of 1844. Engels, although he was
quite young, benefited from his experience in the family business in
Manchester, the center of the English Industrial Revolution; he was
1
2
3
This contribution is a translation of »A Contribuição de Engels para a Crítica da
Economia Política,« in Friedrich Engels e a ciência contemporânea, eds. Muniz Ferreira, Ricardo Moreno, and Mauro Castelo Branco (Salvador: EDUFBA, 2007),
29 – 52. The editor of the present volume would like to thank the author and the
publisher of the original work to include this translation.
Friedrich Engels, »Esobozo de crítica de la economia política,« in Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels, Escritos econômicos vários (Barcelona: Grijalbo, 1975), 4.
In this text, the works Outlines of the Critique of Political Economy, The Condition
of the Working Class in England, The Origin of the Family, Private Property and
the State, Fundamentals of Political Economy Criticism (Grundrisse), and A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy will be designated, respectively, as
Outlines, Condition, The Origin of the Family, Grundrisse, and Contribution.
128
Renildo Souza
also a witness of the Chartist movement. He was immersed in an
environment in which the classical political economy of Adam Smith
and David Ricardo flourished.
In the preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, Marx, when referring to Engels, speaks of »his brilliant outline of
a critique of economic categories.«4 It should be noted that the title
of Engels’s article was borrowed by Marx for the subtitle of his masterwork, Capital. Outlines is quoted a few times by Marx in volume
one of Capital.
Evidently, in his Outlines, Engels was in agreement with Smith in his
criticism of the mercantilist system. He disputed the equating of bullion
to wealth, the centrality of trade balance, and rivalry and war among
nations. However, he pointed out that the first stage of trade had already
been surpassed: »it was understood that our treasure, the capital that
remained inactive, increased continually when in circulation.«5 Here we
see the identification, in germinal form, of the idea of the circulation
of money as capital, which results in the valorization of value. However,
there is still the need, obviously, to locate the ›secret‹ place where value
is created, the sphere of production, and the concept of surplus-value.
Engels signaled the emergence of Political Economy as a »natural
consequence of the spread of commerce.«6 He understood that »the
eighteenth century, the century of revolution, also revolutionized the
economics.«7 All in all, Engels surpassed the evaluation of the practical conceptions of mercantilism and criticized Political Economy itself.
»Modern economics—the system of free trade based on Adam Smith’s
Wealth of Nations—reveals itself to be that same hypocrisy, inconsistency and immorality which now confront free humanity in every sphere.«8
Cyril Smith emphasized the contradiction between the previous defi4
5
6
7
8
Karl Marx, »Prefácio,« in Contribuição para a Crítica da Economia Política (São
Paulo: Nova Cultural, 1999), 53.
Engels, »Esobozo,« 3 – 4.
Ibid., 3.
Engels, »Outlines,« 419
Ibid, 420.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
nition of Political Economy (according to the Outlines)9 and the other
definition provided by Engels in Anti-Dühring: »Political Economy, in
the broadest sense of the term, is the science of the laws that govern
the production and exchange of the material means of life in human
society.«10
Nonetheless, this contradiction, noted by Smith, cannot be supported. In the passage of Anti-Dühring used by Smith, Engels is using
the term ›Political Economy‹ as an embryonic interpretation that reflects diverse economic forms depending on the concrete conditions
of production and distribution in each place and in each historical period. He mentioned the problem of rudimentary forms of economic
understanding. He referred to economy in general. Therefore, Engels
was speaking hypothetically. He makes clear that »this Political Economy, conceived in these terms, with such amplitude (i. e., covering
diverse human societies), is yet to be created. Everything that we have
until now in terms of economic science is reduced, almost exclusively,
to a genesis and to the development of the capitalist regime of production.«11 Thought was restricted to Classical Political Economy, the
liberalism of the writings of Adam Smith, John Ramsay McCulloch,
James Mill, T. R. Malthus, J. B. Say and David Ricardo. It seems that
Cyril Smith made a lot of noise for nothing.
Extreme Moral Argumentation
In the book Condition, Engels repeated the moral emphasis already
present in the Outlines, asserting that the English bourgeoisie was
an immoral and incurably selfish class.12 He protested that the bour9
10
11
12
Cyril Smith, »Friedrich Engels and Marx’s Critique of Political Economy,«
Capital & Class 62 (1997): 127.
Friedrich Engels, Anti-Dühring (Rio de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1990), 123.
Ibid., 130.
Friedrich Engels, A situação da classe trabalhadora em Inglaterra (Lisboa: Presença), 364 – 365.
129
130
Renildo Souza
geois individual was indifferent to the hunger of workers and was
concerned only with profit. For the bourgeois, »whoever does not
make money is an idiot.« It was a »system of life in which each person
works and enriches himself without showing concern for others.«13
This overwhelming, humanist, and moral argument reveals the
limits of Engels’s Outlines. The author repeatedly cited envy, avarice,
covetousness, the right of the mightiest, cunning, and hypocrisy in
contrast to honesty, sincerity, and reason. Mercantilism was a fraud,
»the most repugnant selfishness,« while Political Economy was the
»science of enrichment that springs out from the envy and avarice of
the merchants.« On all these pages, we see the most outrageous indignation and moral condemnation. Already maturing, in 1884, Engels,
in his work The Origin of the Family, amplified the focus of temporality, proposing that »the most vulgar ambition has been the driving
force of civilization from its early days to the present; its defining
objective is wealth, and always wealth, but not the wealth of society
but that of the petty individual.«14
Ethical protest is essential. However, in science, it is not enough
to simply replace an economic explanation with moral disapproval.
The first moral protests by people like the leaders of Utopian Socialism (Saint-Simon, Fourier, and Owen) or the explosive episodes of
indignation of the working masses reflected an injustice, resulting in
the inequality of real economic conditions (in relation to the different
social classes). It should then be recognized that »this appeal to morality and to right (law) does not make us advance scientifically even
an inch.«15
Moral protest, however, is inseparable both from the observation
of the social and environmental ills caused as the result of the economic reproduction of capitalism and from the examination of the alternative to that state of affairs. The economic mechanism that preserves
13
14
15
Ibid., 120.
Friedrich Engels, A origem da família, da propriedade privada e do Estado, 10th ed.
(Rio de Janeiro: Civilização Brasileira, 1985), 199 – 200.
Engels, Anti-Dühring, 129.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
the interests and privileges of the ruling classes destroys the values and
the sociability necessary for the ethics and the relationships among
men. Instead of romanticism, naiveté, mere utopia, pious vows, and
attacks against windmills, there is, besides other deficiencies, in the
writings of the young Engels (in the Outlines), a complex and rich
relationship between the ethical elements and the socio-economic
analysis. Engels argues about the characteristics of the system of competition and private property, pointing towards classist domination
while also discussing anarchy and economic crises, and the possibility
of the affirmation of collective consciousness and social revolution.
We must take into account that the ›modern‹ restoration of slavery
by capitalism, the horrors of colonialism, and the social consequences
of the industrial revolution have accumulated a lot of material, providing many reasons for moral denunciation. Furthermore, for socialists, there can be no wall between economic development and ethics.
The capitalist economic infrastructure is associated with the superstructure of prejudices, conservatism, and selfishness in bourgeois
society. Gramsci drew attention to the need for a struggle in a moral
and cultural direction, configuring a counter-hegemony of the workers and their allies with the aim of gaining power. In the new society,
the socialist ethic consists of values like liberty, solidarity, and justice,
rejecting the reductionism of the socialist transition to tasks for the
development of productive forces. This ethic demands responsibility
in the use of material resources; preserving the environment better, it
demands democracy and the participation of the masses.
In 1882, Engels, in the preface to the German edition of Condition, clarified that the context in which he made his first theoretical
incursions was marked by a »juvenile stage of capitalist exploitation«
in England.16 Thus, he correlates this fury of limitless exploitation
with the beginnings of big industry. For this reason, at this point,
in 1892, he believed that that stage had been surpassed in England
16
Friedrich Engels, »Introdução,« in A situação da classe trabalhadora em Inglaterra
(Lisboa: Presença), 432.
131
132
Renildo Souza
while capitalism advanced in France, Germany, and, especially, in the
United States.
Engels explained that on the new English economic stage, cunning and small thefts against the workers no longer made sense, considering the progress of big industry and the broader markets.17 Big
companies found the need for a certain commercial morality and to
concentrate their time and attention on more relevant aspects of their
business. Only small manufacturers still went for the pennies, the
petty tricks, in order to survive. Social reforms, like the end of the
›truck system,‹ and the law of ten hours, were »measures that challenged the spirit of free trade and unrestrained competition, but, at
the same time, they increased the superiority of the colossal capitalists
even more.«18 The need for the presence of a large number of workers
in the major companies led the bigger industrialists to prevent useless
conflicts and to accept the operation of labor unions. All this was in
conformity with the acceleration of the concentration of capital and
the suppression of minor competitors.
For this reason, Engels modified his previous explanation of exploitation caused by immoral human behavior.
Thus,
… we should not seek the cause of this misery of the working class
in these secondary effects but rather in the entire capitalist system.
The worker sells his labor to the capitalist for a daily sum. After a few
hours of work, he has reproduced the value of that sum, but his work
contract demands that he continue working for a certain number of
hours to finish the working day. At this point, the value he produces
during these extra hours constitutes surplus-value, which costs nothing to the capitalist, but which he keeps in his pocket. This is the basis of the system, which increasingly divides civilized society: on the
one hand, the likes of Rothschild and Vanderbilt — owners of all the
17
18
Ibid., 428.
Ibid., 430.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
means of production and subsistence, and on the other, an enormous
mass of salaried workers, who only have their labor.19
In juvenile capitalism, the worst abuses of the process of industrialization are found in peripheral countries like Brazil, as demonstrated in
the tragic inequality of the distribution of income and the miserable
living conditions of the huge working masses. In countries of this
type, moreover, during this neoliberal era, new difficulties emerge,
once again stressing the importance of extracting absolute surplus value. This resulted in making work more precarious, with partial hours
and temporary contracts, outsourcing, hourly wages, the revocation
of labor rights, pseudo-cooperatives of work, precarious systems of
production engaging all the members of the family, etc.
Highlighting Economic Contradictions
Engels proposed a critique of Political Economy, declaring that he
had turned to the study of the fundamental categories of classical
theory, showing its contradictions and consequences.20 He noted that
Political Economy’s operation of interpreting the system with the
isolation and individualization of interests, reducing »everything to
a web of particular interests, only results in opening the way for a
great transformation in which our century is going, which will lead
humanity to reconcile with nature and with itself.«21
Why did Engels say that »the defenders of freedom of trade (that
is, the classic economists) are worse monopolists than the old mercantilists?«22 Why did liberalism hide the basic, sacrosanct monopoly
represented by bourgeois private property? The existence of private
property for a few and the misery of the English people excluded any
19
20
21
22
Ibid., 430 – 431.
Engels, »Esobozo,« 6.
Ibid., 8.
Ibid., 5.
133
134
Renildo Souza
sense of coherence expressed in national wealth. However, focusing
his attention on commerce, a consequence of private property, Engels
erroneously saw the exchange of goods as »a direct source of profit,« since it is about »selling a higher price and buying as cheaply as
possible.«
In the controversy over value, Engels failed to understand the determination of value by the cost of production, in the sense of the
quantity of labor incorporated into it, as Ricardo proposed.23 Engels
saw this as »absurd abstractions.« Correctly, he criticized Jean B. Say,
who defined value only by the perception of the usefulness of the
good, showing the subjectivity of this type of evaluation. Engels, then,
proposed a kind of conciliation, asserting that »value is the relationship between cost of production and usefulness.« However, this could
only be an approximation for a conventional definition of the market
price.
It was only much later that Marx clarified the distinction between
value, price of production, and market price. According to the distinction of the organic composition of capital, among companies, values
would be transformed into prices of production, equalizing the rate of
profit in different sectors within the field of competition. There would
be a redistribution of surplus-value among companies through the
difference between price and value, but the total value, the total surplus value, and its conformity with labor time would be maintained.
Thus, the theory of value-labor was innovated and maintained. On this
theme, Engels, looking at arguments about value, presented a complement to the third volume of The Capital, in which he addressed the
relationship between the law of value and the rate of profit, defending
the solution given by Marx for the transformation of values into production costs (in view of the criticism and confusion).24
In his Outlines, Engels perceives the contradiction present in the
theory of distribution of goods. Income would be composed of the
23
24
Ibid., 8 – 10.
Friedrich Engels, »La ley del valor e la quota de ganancia,« in Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels, Escritos econômicos vários (Barcelona: Grijalbo, 1975), 232 – 248.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
135
remunerations of the so-called land, capital and labor services. However, »capital and labor are the same thing since [classic] economists
themselves have confessed that capital is ›accumulated labor‹«25. The
separation of labor and capital, born from private property, is an expression of »the division of mankind into capitalists and workers — a
division which daily becomes ever more acute, and which, as we shall
see, is bound to deepen.«26
Outlines presents an approach to the relationship between science
and value that would later be developed by Marx in Grundrisse. Engels identified the negligence of Classic Economics with regard to the
specific contribution of science towards the increase of goods: »the
progress of science does not enter into its calculations.«27 He shows
the emergence of mechanical inventions in England to be a reaction,
among other things, to the lack of workers.28 The effect of the introduction of machines was the reduction, relatively speaking, of the
demand for labor. A part of the workers became unemployed while
the other part saw their salaries reduced. Under these circumstances,
the bargaining power of the collective actions of the workers became
less effective.
Engels, in his Outlines, agrees with the Classic Economic argument that machines reduced the prices of goods, broadening the markets and resulting in new positions for the unemployed. However,
he disputes the magnitude of these benefits. Let us remember the
perennially large number of unemployed, the constant technological
change, the division of labor that limited the worker to one specific
activity in the function of the type of machine, and the difficulty for
the worker to change to a new occupation.
25
26
27
28
Engels, »Esobozo,« 11 – 14.
Engels, »Outlines,« 430.
Ibid., 11, 24.
Engels, at this point, did not yet understand the distinction between labor and
a special merchandise workforce, later clarified by Marx. In 1891, Engels wrote
the preface to Wage Labour and Capital, which was a work written by Marx and
published in 1849. In this preface, Engels provides a detailed explanation on the
difference between concepts of labor and the workforce.
136
Renildo Souza
In volume three of The Capital, Engels presents an addendum explaining that the increase in productivity consists of the decrease of
live work and the increase of dead work, resulting in the reduction of
the total sum of work in the commodity. He notes that this tendency
to seek an increase in the productivity of labor is of no interest to capital in any circumstance. It matters »only when one saves more on the
paid part of live work, than it is augmented in past work.«29 However,
he exaggerated the contradictions and the limits of the system, as is
evidenced by technological progress in the contemporary capitalism.
Engels concluded that the capitalist mode of production requires an
increase in productivity, but in certain circumstances it contradicts
itself, showing its senility, curbing that development of productivity.
It is obvious that Marx emphasized the centrality of the contradiction between the relations of production and the development of
productive forces. This contradiction was essential for overcoming the
capitalist mode of production. However, in Grundrisse, Marx presents the contradiction in a manner in which, implicitly, technological
progress is not restrained:
The purpose of this production is, and continues to be, the magnitude of immediate working time …. To the extent, however, that
big industry develops, the creation of effective wealth becomes less
dependent on working time … than on the power of agents [from
science and technology] set in motion … power that in turn … has
no relationship with the immediate working time that its production
costs, depending more on the general state of science and the progress
of technology …. Capital itself is a contradiction in progress [due to
the fact] that it tends to reduce working time to a minimum, but on
the other hand it puts working time as the only measure and source
of wealth …. On the one hand, it awakens to life all the powers of
science and nature, as well as social cooperation and exchange, in
29
Karl Marx, O Capital: Crítica da Economia Política, book 3, vol. IV.1, 3rd ed. (São
Paulo: Nova Cultural, 1988), 186 – 188.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
order to make the creation of wealth (relatively) independent of the
working time employed in it. On the other hand, it proposes to measure these gigantic social forces created in this way in working time
and reduce them to the required limits in order that the value already
created is maintained as value.30
Engels implicitly placed competition as the main moment of economic activity, instead of production, just as Marx would formulate
later. Engels did not yet understand that production, distribution,
circulation, and consumption were indispensable, interlinked, and
reciprocal conditioning moments within the same process. If, however, the Classical Economist classified the system through the beautification of free competition, contrary to the monopolies prevalent
under mercantilism, then Engels’s attraction to the study of competition and the market was only natural. The defense of free competition
and the market by Smith is now retaken by neoliberalism, exalting
the advantages of the market as the only regulating principle of the
economy.
In Outlines, it is made clear that the consumer does not have
perfect information about the goods offered in the market, as the
Neoclassical Economy still assumes today. In spite of the veil of the
freedom of the market, hiding the defects of the system, Engels genially anticipates the tendency of free competition to transform itself
into a monopoly. In spite of liberal preaching, competition, based
on interests that aspire to domination, »always ends in monopoly.«
Our author continues by clarifying that this does not mean the end
of competition among companies since »a monopoly cannot contain
the flow of competition.«31
The tendency to centralization and the concentration of capital
was further developed by Marx in Capital. That law of movement
30
31
Karl Marx, Elementos fundamentales para la crítica de la economia política (Grundrisse) 1857 – 1858, vol. 2. 13th ed. (México: Siglo Veintiuno, 1997), 227 – 229. My
emphasis.
Engels, »Esobozo,« 15, 23.
137
138
Renildo Souza
originated from accumulation and competition, which are coercively
inevitable. It stemmed from the possibilities opened by the credit system, from the role of limited liability companies, exemplified by the
masses of capital of the English railroads. It stemmed from the need
to increase the organic composition of capital due to the indispensable technological progress.
The capitalist dynamic, based on instability and imbalance, is
marked by periodic crises, occurring »with the same regularity as that
of comets,«32 remarks Engels. Instead of information, calculation and
planning, the economy is afflicted by the »lack of conscience of the
interested parties.« This is what the natural law of economic equilibrium comes down to, in spite of the illusions of Political Economy.
Whereas Classical Economists emphasized the harmonious nature of
the economy and individual interests, Engels argued for the necessity
for a collective conscience and the actions of men, not of loose atoms.
This argument about collective human will had nothing to do with
the positivism that, with some simplifications, some tried to accuse
Engels, as we can see:
What can we think of a law that can only be imposed through periodic revolutions? That it is precisely a natural law, based on the lack
of conscience of the interested parties. If producers as such knew how
much the consumers needed, if they could organize production and
distribution, it would be impossible for there to be fluctuations in the
competition [market] and their tendency towards crises. It produces
in a conscious manner, and it overrides all those artificial and unsustainable contradictions. However, as long as it continues to produce,
as it does now in an unconscious manner, there will continue to be
commercial [economic] crises, and each one of them will be necessarily more universal and, consequently, more devastating than the
previous ones. It will ruin a greater number of small capitalists, and it
will increase, in greater proportions each time, the class of those who
32
Ibid., 16.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
139
live off their work. In other words, it will increase the mass of labor
that requires occupation, which is the fundamental problem of our
economists, until finally a social revolution that our economists are
incapable of imagining is provoked.33
In spite of its limitations, Outlines has a general view in which private property and competition are unmasked as the fundamentals of
Classical Political Economy. In the work Condition, Engels reaffirms
the appearance of periodic crises when the internal and external markets become filled with English products.34 This is a description of a
certain regularity of the cycles of overproduction. It is an open challenge to Smith’s self-regulation of the market and Say’s law of markets,
supported by Ricardo, in which production creates its own demand,
without the possibility of a crisis.
According to Engels, the concept of anarchy in the system covers
both the productive effort and the distribution of consumer goods.35
This anarchy is linked to the object of profit instead of the satisfaction of social needs. He concluded that this anarchic operation of
the economy is what imposed the disturbances and crises. Malthus‹
theory of population,36 justifying the »contradiction between simultaneous wealth and misery,« demanded a response. On the one hand,
Engels, with a certain »productivist« charge,37 responded that, in the
case of agriculture, »in a conscious manner and in the interest of ev33
34
35
36
37
Ibid., 16.
Engels, Classe trabalhadora, 120.
Ibid.
»Population, when not controlled, increases in a geometric progression. The
means of subsistence only grow in an arithmetic proportion […]. Without doubt
it is disheartening to think that the great obstacle on the road to any perfecting of
society is of such a nature that we cannot hope to ever overcome it. The permanent tendency of the human species is to grow beyond the means of subsistence,
and one of the general laws of nature is that we do not have any reason to think
that it will change.« Thomas Robert Malthus, Ensaio sobre a população (São Paulo: Nova Cultural, 1996), 246, 360 – 361.
This productivism, contrasting with ecological concerns, is immediately relativized when Engels explains that this unlimited capacity, consciously conducted,
140
Renildo Souza
eryone,« »the investment of capital, labor and science could potentialize the capacity of production of the soil infinitely.«38 On the other hand, referring to the general conditions of the market, he stated
that »population is only excessive where the capacity of production
is excessive.« The unemployed workforce is only an excessive capacity
under certain economic circumstances. Engels, despite the emphasis
on competition, does not shy away from reasoning about production
fluctuations. He reasons that there is a type of equilibrium in which
the productive impulse is weak, in which unemployment and hunger are inevitable. If production accelerates, then we are open to the
possibility of creating a future situation of super-production or even
stagnation.
English industry needed a »reserve of unemployed workers.«39 That
reserve was permanent except during »short periods of greater prosperity.« The magnitude of this reserve varies according to the behavior
of the market, with greater or lesser occupation. A company’s search
for an increase in the productivity of each worker is associated with
the problem of unemployment. Thus, »the productivity of each worker raised to its maximum by competition, the division of labor, the
introduction of machinery, and the utilization of natural forces are
factors that lead to the unemployment of a multiplicity of workers.«40
This formulation about the reserve of unemployed workers would later
be developed by Marx as the concept of the »industrial reserve army.«
In contrast to the use of overpopulation to explain misery (and
unemployment), in Malthus‹ proposition, Neoclassical Economics
has enthroned, since the last decades of the nineteenth century, the
balance of the labor market, with the economy naturally functioning at full employment and without crises. Only later, during the
Great Depression, did John M. Keynes present a formulation of the
38
39
40
would reduce »the burden of work that weighs upon humanity,« i. e. upon the
workers.
Engels, »Esobozo,« 18.
Engels, Classe trabalhadora, 123.
Ibid., 119.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
possibility that the economy would fall back and prostrate itself in a
form of equilibrium with unemployment. Thus, Keynes broke with
Neoclassicism and recognized the existence of involuntary unemployment. This conclusion could, in a certain way, be associated with Engels’s intuition linking unemployment with the effects of the rate of
growth of production.41
Popularization of Economic Theory
Engels denounced the emergence of an abstract materialism, distant
from concrete contradictions, in the explanation of the contempt and
humiliation of men, that is, the »suffering of Christians.«42 God was
exchanged for nature as something absolute, inevitable, for the effects of the economy upon the fate of men. Thus, Political Economy,
instead of bringing forth a revolutionary examination of economic
contradictions, preferred to adapt itself to the coming bourgeois era.
For this reason, Classical Economists only represent intermediate
progress with regard to the mercantilists.
Throughout the history of capitalism, there is a conventional theory, with various versions, that attempts to naturalize the economy.
It sounds like an interdiction against any political intervention that
is contrary to bourgeois interests. Engels exposes classical theory as
an effort to beautify the economy through the exaltation of gains
for the consumers (which today is called the »principle of consumer
sovereignty«) and the celebration of the market as a bond of harmony
between nations and individuals.
41
42
In Keynes‹ thought, there is a reference to the analysis of Malthus (see Principles
of Political Economy, Chapter VII), one of the representatives of Political Economy, who was alone in his argument about the possibility of the general saturation of merchandise and the insufficiency of demand, which contrasted with the
statement of Say’s law that prevails in Classical Economics.
Engels, »Esobozo,« 4.
141
142
Renildo Souza
On the distinction between scientific Political Economy and vulgar Economics, Marx stated:
And to clarify once and for all, I understand as Classical Political
Economics all economics since William Petty, which investigates the
internal nexus of the bourgeois conditions of production as the antithesis of vulgar economics (which only moves within the apparent
nexus), ruminating again on the material already provided by scientific economics, offering a plausible understanding of phenomena
that are coarser and for the domestic use of the bourgeoisie, and is
limited, moreover, to systematizing, pedantizing, and proclaiming as
eternal truths the banal and presumptuous ideas that the agents of
bourgeois production create around the world, which for them are
the best possible.43
Political Economy only had a scientific character until David Ricardo,
according to the judgment of Marx.44 Thus, the economy started to
have a vulgar character from 1830, when the class struggle began to
manifest itself with more clarity. Economic categories started to be
presented directly, wrapped in the veil of ideological contraband of
the class interests of the bourgeoisie.
The author of Outlines presents similar reasoning to Marx’s classification of vulgar Economics, but attacking, in some ways, even
Ricardo himself: »While Smith and Malthus only met with loose
fragments, later economists already had the whole system finished
before them; all the consequences were in plain view, the contradictions were evident.«45 There was a course of vulgarization, that is, a
growing bourgeois ideologization of Political Economy. Ricardo was
blamed for the scientific regression more than Smith, while Stuart
43
44
45
Karl Marx, O Capital: Crítica da Economia Política, book 1, vol. I.1 (São Paulo:
Abril Cultural, 1988), 76, n. 32.
Karl Marx, »Posfácio da segunda edição,« in O Capital: Crítica da Economia
Política, book 1, vol. I.1 (São Paulo: Abril Cultural, 1988), 22 – 23.
Engels, »Esobozo,« 5.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
143
Mill had contributed more to the misrepresentation of economics
than Ricardo.
In epistemological terms, Engels’s intuition has great importance.
It shows an escalation of superficiality or incessant reductionism,
which accompany the unfolding of the dominant economic thought.
And this is confirmed more and more, over time. In Political Economy, the attempt to naturalize economic facts, detaching them from
the social and historical context, was repelled by Marx and Engels.
Based on materialist conception of history, it was not possible to understand the capitalist system itself as something natural, eternal, the
end of the evolution of humanity.
From the time of the founders of Marxism until today, things
have only worsened in the field of the dominant economic theory.
As we know, the accumulation of capital in our times has come to
be understood as a gift of nature according to the automatism of the
market, so long as each individual is not cut off from his activity, his
entrepreneurship, and his self-interest by government interventionism, and »syndicalist monopolies«. Therefore, let us look, briefly, at
this growing abstraction of economic theory in the face of the prevailing socio-economic reality in the capitalist system. The Neoclassical
school, which emerged in the 1870s (particularly with Leon Walras,
William Stanley Jevons, and Carl Menger), abandoned the focus of
Political Economy on the determination of value based on labor. It
covered up the investigation of problems regarding the distribution of
goods among the social classes, putting aside Ricardo’s concerns. They
simplified the difficulties of effective demand, in spite of Malthus‹
early warnings. Even the general equilibrium of Walras and the quantitative theory of money sanctioned reductionist visions of the general
problems of production and circulation in the economy.
From Classical theory, the Neoclassical authors broadened and
radicalized the concepts of the naturalization, harmony, and equilibrium of the economy. In the Neoclassical context, the marginalist
analysis appears as an expression of the premises of rationality and
the maximizing behavior of homo economicus. Thus, the preferences of
144
Renildo Souza
the consumer enthrone the deciding role, resulting from the individual’s choice in driving the economy. As a microeconomics of pricing,
the theory was actually reduced to quantitativist formalism in order
to simply describe the operation of the markets. The self-regulation of
markets would promote economic stability.
The history of the vulgarization of economic thinking according
to dominant ideas has been a long one. Keynesian thought, partially divergent from this decadence, identified involuntary unemployment and economic malfunctions, but this generated the illusion
that government action would be capable of preventing the crises of
capitalism. From the 1970s onwards, there has been an upsurge in the
vulgarization of economics with the monetarism of Milton Friedman
and, later, the so-called school of rational expectations of Robert Lucas. The latter would represent the so-called ›new classics,‹ as if it was
a radicalized and worsened return to Classical Economics. There is a
return to the aversion to any governmental intervention, assuming
unlimited rationality on the part of individuals and sanctifying the
self-regulation of the markets.
History and Economics
In the preface to Origin, Engels attests that the materialist analysis
of history is Marx’s and, he adds, »to a certain extent, our.« In the
epistemology of classical Marxism, an association predominates between the economic explanation and the theory of historical materialism.46 The economy is a decisive, though not exclusive, factor in
the evolution of society. For this reason, Engels considered that an
increase in productivity was the key to understanding the evolution
of private property, exchange, and the use of others‹ labor, resulting
in contradictions among the recently constituted social classes.47 Over
46
47
Jacob Gorender, »Introdução,« in Karl Marx, Para a crítica da economia política:
Salário, preço e lucro (São Paulo: Abril Cultural, 1982), vii.
Engels, A origem da família, 3.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
145
time, moving from adaptation to incompatibility between the new
conditions and the old structure, there emerged, after a long time,
the superseding of a society based on ties of kinship by a society organized around the power of the State and relationships of property.
In civilization, slavery took deep roots, and society was divided
between an exploiting class and a class of the exploited.48 Over the
course of time, the development of civilization always manifests the
contradiction between the progress of production and the conditions
of the oppressed class.49 In civilization, there is a march towards the exacerbation of the division between labor and mercantile production.50
In the evolution of capitalism, there was a period of so-called
›primitive accumulation‹ between the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. From the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries on, in England,
there has been capitalism with its own technology, with big industry
and the actual subsuming of labor to capital. Maurice Dobb records
that Engels was one of the first to use the term Industrial Revolution
to describe the transformations in the English economy and society.51
Engels compared the importance of the Industrial Revolution, which
had the creation of the proletariat as its main result, to the magnitude of the French Revolution. In the introduction to Condition, Engels asserted that the Industrial Revolution in England »transformed
bourgeois society in its totality.«52
In order to study the proletariat, Engels did fieldwork, as he explains in the preface to Condition: »I lived for a long time among
you [the workers], and for this reason I am well informed about your
living conditions.«53 This accelerated industrialization demanded the
emigration of »compact masses of workers« from the countryside and
48
49
50
51
52
53
Ibid., 198.
Ibid., 200.
Ibid., 196.
Maurice Dobb, A evolução do capitalismo, 6th ed. (Rio de Janeiro: Zahar, 1977),
316, n. 3.
Friedrich Engels, »Prefácio: Aos trabalhadores ingleses,« in A situação da classe
trabalhadora em Inglaterra (Lisboa: Presença), 15.
Ibid., 7.
146
Renildo Souza
provoked a rapid demographic growth.54 Artisans were ruined, and
workers lost »the last vestiges of independent activity,« resulting in
the blocking of mobility for the middle social strata.55 This situation
forces us to think, to become aware, and opens up, for the first time,
the possibility for the proletariat to begin an independent movement,
concludes our author.
Concerning the State in general, Engels presents two fundamental
traits: first, the State is a cohesive force of civilized society; and second,
the State, always, in all typical periods, is an exclusive institution of
the dominant class and consists, essentially, of an instrument of repression against the oppressed and exploited class.56 Therefore, in the
State, there is, simultaneously, a duplicity of cohesion and repression.
Despite the classist character of the State, in the case of capitalism, the
bourgeoisie has some reservations about the role of the State in certain matters that may contradict their economic interests. The bourgeoisie uses the State against the proletariat, but it keeps the State,
according to their ability and convenience, distant from certain issues
related to economic activity.57
After the crisis of 1847, Engels identified the emergence of a new
industrial era.58 The liberalization of foreign trade emerged with the
repeal of the grain law, the expansion of colonial markets, the opening
of China, the conclusion of the ruin of millions of weavers in India as
a result of the competition from mechanical weaving in England, and
the accelerated economic transformation of the United States.
In Condition, Engels predicted, in 1844, the overcoming, within
twenty years, of English industry by competition and the subsequent
spread of unemployment to the majority of the proletariat,59 who
54
55
56
57
58
59
Engels, »Introdução,« 33.
Ibid., 18, 34.
Engels, A origem da família, 196.
Engels, Classe trabalhadora, 366.
Friedrich Engels, »Prefácio à edição inglesa em 1892,« in A situação da classe trabalhadora em Inglaterra (Lisboa: Presença), 428 – 429.
Engels, Classe trabalhadora, 387 – 388.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
would be left with no alternative but »to die of hunger or start a revolution.«60 In 1892, Engels recorded, as a confirmation of this forecast,
the rupture of the English industrial monopoly, setting a watershed
that would lead the English proletariat to the loss of its privileges
and free itself from the influence of its workers‹ aristocracy and turn
towards the cause of socialism.61
Towards the end of the nineteenth century and at the beginning
of the twentieth century, new circumstances emerged through financial capital, monopolies, and the end of the partition of overseas
colonies by the great powers. Capitalism had entered its imperial
stage, as evidenced by the development of Marxist theory through
Rudolf Hilferding, Rosa Luxemburg, Nikolai Bukharin, and Vladimir Lenin.
This new era of financial domination did not escape the notice of
Engels.62 Thus, in the last year of his life, 1885, he wrote a note, later
incorporated in Capital, analyzing the role of the stock market in the
capitalist system. Engels noted the great changes in the significance of
the stock exchange since Marx had written the third volume of Capital. The stock market had become »the most important representative
of capitalist production.« Along with the acceleration of accumulation, the group of rentiers was growing and new forms of associations
were emerging in order to facilitate the investment of great amounts
of capital. These new circumstances favored the emergence of trusts
of production in commerce, banks, and lending institutions. Agriculture, foreign investments, and colonization companies would also
become linked to the stock market.
60
61
62
»It is not right to suppress in the text numerous prophecies, in particular the
one about an imminent social revolution in England, which were inspired by
my juvenile ardor. What is surprising is not that many of those predictions did
not come about but that many others were just and that in the critical period of
English industry — consequence of the continental competition, mainly American — have effectively arrived.« Ibid., 434.
Engels, »Prefácio à edição inglesa,« 432. Also see Dobb, Capitalismo, 366.
Friedrich Engels, »La bolsa,« in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Escritos econômicos vários (Barcelona: Grijalbo, 1975), 248 – 249.
147
148
Renildo Souza
Engels’s Place in his Collaboration with Marx
on Economics
There is some controversy around the legacy of Engels, including in
his critique of Political Economy. Some find that Engels promoted a
revision of Marx’s theory, turning towards a sort of reductionism or
determinism. It is not the purpose of this article to deal exhaustively
with this problem, but it is important to address his synthesis. J. D.
Hunley points out that, since the 1960s, there has been an increase in
questions about the compatibility between Marx and Engels.63 Hunley adds that the prevailing view today is that there are important differences between the two German revolutionaries. Eduard Bernstein
(in the 1890s), Rodolfo Mondolfo (1912), George Lichtheim (1961),
Norman Levine (1975), Terrell Carver (1883), and others are some of
the so-called dichotomists since they have refuted, in different measures, the intellectual affinity between Marx and Engels.
Levine claims that there are important discrepancies between the
first section of Engels’s edition of Volume 2 of Capital and the manuscripts kept in the International Institute of Social History. Among
other things, this would result in the substitution of the Hegelian
understanding of the totality of the economic process with Marx’s
on the empiricist emphasis on particularity on the part of Engels.64
However, among the various materials left by Marx, we can see both
possibilities (totality and particularity), thus revealing some ambiguity, according to Hunley. Jerrold Seigel recognizes that there are
discrepancies between the manuscript and the edited text of Volume
3, but, in contrast to Levine, he sees the modifications introduced by
Engels as necessary and justified. In his view, Engels rearranged some
sections of chapters 13 and 14 of Volume 3 and attributed a more important role to neutralizing forces of the law of the decreasing tenden63
64
J. D. Hunley, »The Intellectual Compatibility of Marx and Engels,« Social Theory &
Practice 17, no. 1 (1991): 1.
Ibid., 8.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
149
cy of the rate of profit. That solution by Engels reduced the positivism
of the text, according to the law mentioned above.65
Hunley concluded that the two friends were in agreement on
the fundamental issues. The great proof of unity was the harmonious work that they did together for almost 40 years, which included
books and numerous journal articles.66 It was Engels who suggested
the title and the opening sentences of The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Napoleon. Engels also provided valuable insights into the mode of
Asian production that were taken up by Marx.
In view of the strong accusation of vulgar economic determinism
imputed on Marx and, above all, Engels, it is crucial to mention the
letter that the latter sent to Bloch on September 21, 1890:
According to the materialist conception of history, the factor that
ultimately determines history is the production and reproduction
of real life. Neither Marx nor I stated anything more than this. If
someone modifies the thesis saying that economic facts are the only
determinant facts, then he would be making the thesis empty, abstract, and absurd. The economic situation is the basis, but the different factors of the superstructure that is built upon it — the political
forms of the class struggle, the constitutions that, once a battle is
won, the triumphant class writes, etc., the judicial forms, and even
the reflections of all these real struggles in the brains of those who
participate in them, the political, juridical and philosophical theories,
the religious ideas and the further development that leads them to
become a system of dogmas — also exert influence upon the course of
historical struggles and, in many cases, determine their shape, as the
predominant factor. It is a reciprocal game of actions and reactions
among these factors, in which, through an infinite number of cases
(that is, things and events whose internal connection is so remote or
so difficult to demonstrate that we can consider it non-existent), the
65
66
Ibid.
Ibid., 17 – 18.
150
Renildo Souza
economic movement always imposes itself as a necessity. If that was
not the case, applying the theory to any historical epoch would be
easier than solving a first-degree equation.67
Cyril Smith claims that Engels did not understand Marx’s attitude
with regard to Political Economy.68 For this critic, Engels would have
gradually distanced himself from his valuable discoveries recorded in
Outlines, abandoning the ethical and human vision, neglecting the
monopolistic meaning of bourgeois private property. One of the important findings of Outlines, the verification that the old mercantile
system had »a certain open, catholic frankness,« did not indulge in
theoretical economic competitions in order to cover up all its commercial immoralities.69 It changed reality and economic discourse.
In Outlines, it was identified that in the new global conditions, now
more humanized and attaching greater importance to value and morality, there was a place for Classical Economic theory in the form
of Adam Smith. In Outlines, the pioneering perception of the links
between economics and religion, within the framework of Protestantism, made Engels admire Adam Smith as an economic Lutheran, according to Cyril Smith.
Adam Smith showed the human aspect of commerce (that is, economic liberalism): without wars among nations, without deliberate
economic privileges by the State, without repression of the freedom
to decide by each economic agent, without the prohibition of the will
of the consumer in the act of exchange. This humanism, however, was
very partial. All of this, in essence, was a »way to abuse morality for
immoral goals.«70 In fact, private property prevailed as a monopoly,
free competition to defraud consumers, civilization as exploitation
67
68
69
70
Friedrich Engels, »Carta de Engels a Bloch, em 21 de setembro de 1890,« in
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Obras Escolhidas, vol. 3 (São Paulo: Alfa-ômega),
284 – 285.
Smith, »Engels and Marx,« 123 – 142.
Engels, »Esobozo,« 7.
Ibid.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
of the people in the colonies, free-for-all competition, antagonism
between collective and individual interests.
Cyril Smith believes that Engels would have departed from the
criticism of the categories of Political Economy, namely: use value
and exchange value, value and price, labor, profit, and income. Engels
would have underestimated the dual character of labour, the forms
of value and fetishism.71 In contrast, Engels would have focused, over
time, unilaterally on the concept of surplus-value, would have turned
to the appreciation of value, emphasizing merely quantitative aspects.
He would have become entangled in the question of materialist dialectics. He did not value his own critique of the population theory
of Malthus in the terms that had already been established in Outlines.
He did not go back to the universal human base employed to criticize
both mercantilism and Political Economy.72
According to Cyril Smith, Marx’s critique of Political Economy
did not turn to an empirical, factual description of the operation of
capitalism nor to the proposition of the economic elements of socialism.73 The word ›capitalism‹ does not appear in Capital. The Marxist
critique would have turned to the ideas and interpretations of the
classics concerning the social relationships engendered by capital and
its consequent contradictions. Cyril Smith thinks that criticism, for
Marx, had the priority of challenging, in theory, in categories, in the
most advanced and coherent system of economic thought, that is to
say, Political Economy (since it explains the nature of modern society).74 The inhumanity of bourgeois relationships was theorized as
something natural and eternal by Political Economy.
For Marx, the point of departure of the critique of Political Economy had to be human society, social humanism, in the view of Cyril
Smith.75 Instead of capitalism, Marx spoke of capital as a social rela71
72
73
74
75
Smith, »Engels and Marx,« 136.
Ibid., 126 – 128.
Ibid., 124 – 125.
Ibid., 124 – 126.
Ibid., 125.
151
152
Renildo Souza
tionship, hidden by the fetishism of merchandise. Value, for Marx,
surpassed quantification and expressed human relationships as if they
were relationships among things (20 yards of linen = one coat).
In the face of these criticisms by Cyril Smith, it is worth asking: is
it true that, for Engels, the understanding of economics and classical
thought was different? Let us see what he says: »The economy is not
about things but rather relationships among people, and, ultimately, between classes, although these relationships are always linked to
things and they look like things.«76
The facts made it difficult for Engels to accept the accusation of
falsifying Marx’s thought. In the end, there were almost 40 years of
intellectual collaboration between the two of them, with many texts
written with the input of both. Furthermore, it is important to take
into consideration all the revolutionary activity, in political affinity,
that defined the lives of these friends. It is significant that after the
death of Marx, the great political authority of the socialist movement
was Engels, and even after his own death, his influence extended for
many years among the ranks of the Second (Social-Democratic) International. There are many reasons for calling Marx and Engels the
Dioscuri, the twin heroes of Greek mythology. For Paul Lafargue and
Wilhelm Liebknecht, Engels was Marx’s alter ego. Marx’s daughter,
Eleanor, referring to their life and work, said that it was impossible
to separate them.77
It is counterproductive, in theory and method, to promote a clear
separation between the work of Marx and the work of Engels.78 With
76
77
78
Friedrich Engels, »A contribuição para a crítica da economia política, de Karl
Marx,« in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Obras Escolhidas, vol. 1 (São Paulo:
Alfa-ômega), 311.
Hunley, »Intellectual Compatibility,« 1.
In 1844 Engels published the Outlines and wrote Condition. Referring to his ideas
during this period, Engels recognized, in 1892, with regard to Condition that »a
book in which what is good is as much as what is bad shows the youth of the
author« (427), I was twenty years-old, today I am three times older, and when
I reread that book, I do not think that I need to be ashamed of it, and »it is not
worth noting that the general theoretical point of view of this book — on the
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
153
regard to economics, in the division of work between the two friends,
Marx took care of the deepening and systematizing of economic theory, but Engels was the precursor for some relevant ideas. He brought
forth embryonic elements that stimulated Marx’s study of economics.
It is also inevitable to recognize that Engels assumed responsibility for
editing the last two volumes of Capital, which included the technical
work of redacting and, in the case of Volume 3, he made the effort to
render intelligible some materials that had been left in rough shape
by Marx. In that effort, beside his explanatory notes, Engels wrote the
chapter on the effect of rotation on the rate of profit. Furthermore,
we cannot ignore Engels’s effort to popularize Capital, breaking the
so-called ›Conspiracy of Silence‹ through the publication of reviews
and summaries in multiple forms of print.
The possibility of differences in focus and understanding between
both thinkers is natural. Without a doubt, Engels always made the
main role of Marx clear in the context of their collaboration. This
is especially noted with regard to their economic studies. In spite
of this, Engels was sought by Marx before the writing of Capital to
collaborate on certain investigations, in addition to their correspondence and the debates they held on economics and literature. In this
sense, we can consider the following examples: Engels’s criticisms of
concepts that underestimated the progress of agriculture; Engels’s reception of Marx’s ideas that were contrary to what is called the quantitative school of currency (currency in circulation determining prices,
foreign trade and crises79); the information Engels provided to Marx
79
philosophical, economic and political plain — does not exactly coincide with my
current position. In 1844 there was no modern international socialism that the
works of Marx almost exclusively made into a science. My book represents one
of the phases of that embryonic movement. (433). (Preface to the English 1892
edition of The Condition of the Working Class in England).
The monetarism of Milton Friedman, starting in the 1970’s, had its origins in
ideas already refuted by Marx 150 years earlier. The dynamic of the economy and
the movement of prices make the circulation of currency and the credit system
into derivative phenomena, although a serious mistake of a Central Bank in
monetary policy can create economic problems.
154
Renildo Souza
on the share of consumption by capitalists in the revenues of their
companies; and the report Engels wrote, at Marx’s request, about the
cotton crisis of 1965.80
The accusations that are made are either exaggerated or totally
false. Thus, for example, there is no room to say that Engels influenced Marx negatively, supposedly simplifying, for the sake of popularization, the explanations in chapter 1 of Volume 1 of Capital. In
fact, it was in response to Marx’s letter, dated 3 June 1867, that Engels,
without prejudice of logical or conceptual argument, suggested the
use of historical illustrations on the process of the formation of money in addition to the organization of the presentation of the text.
Engels himself explained his methodology in his preface to Contributions.81 For him, it was possible to employ two methods, historical and logical, in the critique of Political Economy. With regard to
the historical method, he says: »This form presents, apparently, the
advantage of greater clarity since in it we find the real development
of things, but in practice the only thing that would result, in the best
of cases, would be its popularization. … Therefore, the only method
recommended is the logical one. However, this is, in reality, nothing
but the historical method, stripped only of its historical form and its
disturbing contingencies.«82
Even in works that do not have economics as their main theme,
Marx and Engels always make references to economic problems. For
example, in The German Ideology, there is a strong presence of economic elements. And so, as in their collaborative works, is it possible
to locate and separate the economic contributions of Marx and Engels, and then place those contributions in opposition, one in relation
to the other? This would not make sense. It is obvious that there is a
80
81
82
Instituto de Marxismo-Leninismo, PCUS. Biografia de Friedrich Engels (Lisboa:
Avante, 1986), 411 – 413.
Preface in 1859, that is, 15 years after Outlines, which negates the accusation that
Engels, with the passing of time, had lost his understanding of Political Economy
and had distanced himself from Marxist thought in this field
Engels, »Contribuição,« 310.
The Contribution of Engels to the Critique of Political Economy
sense of unity throughout their work, even though it was written by
two people.
Translated by Gilmar Visoni-Alonzo
Works Cited
Dobb, Maurice. A evolução do capitalismo. 6th ed. Rio de Janeiro: Zahar,
1977.
Engels, Friedrich. »Esobozo de crítica de la economia política.« In Escritos
econômicos vários, by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. Barcelona: Grijalbo, 1975.
—. »La ley del valor e la quota de ganancia.« In Karl Marx and Friedrich
Engels, Escritos econômicos vários. Barcelona: Grijalbo, 1975.
—. »La bolsa.« In Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Escritos econômicos vários.
Barcelona: Grijalbo, 1975.
—. A situação da classe trabalhadora em Inglaterra. Lisboa: Presença.
—. »Prefácio: Aos trabalhadores ingleses.« In A situação da classe trabalhadora
em Inglaterra. Lisboa: Presença.
—. »Introdução.« In A situação da classe trabalhadora em Inglaterra. Lisboa:
Presença.
—. »Prefácio à edição inglesa em 1892.« In A situação da classe trabalhadora em
Inglaterra. Lisboa: Presença.
—. »A contribuição para a crítica da economia política, de Karl Marx.« In
Obras Escolhidas, vol. 1, by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. São Paulo:
Alfa-ômega.
—. »Carta de Engels a Bloch, em 21 de setembro de 1890.« In Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels, Obras Escolhidas, vol. 3. São Paulo: Alfa-ômega.
—. A origem da família, da propriedade privada e do Estado. 10th ed. Rio de
Janeiro: Civilização Brasileira, 1985.
—. Anti-Dühring. Rio de Janeiro: Paz e Terra, 1990.
Gorender, Jacob. »Introdução.« In Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Para a
crítica da economia política: Salário, preço e lucro. São Paulo: Abril Cultural, 1982.
155
156
Renildo Souza
Hunley, J. D. »The intellectual compatibility of Marx and Engels.« Social
Theory & Practice 17, no. 1 (Spring 1991): 1 – 22.
Instituto de Marxismo-Leninismo. PCUS. Biografia de Friedrich Engels. Lisboa: Avante, 1986.
Malthus, Thomas Robert. Ensaio sobre a população. São Paulo: Nova Cultural,
1996.
Marx, Karl. Elementos fundamentales para la crítica de la economia política
(Grundrisse) 1857 – 1858, vol. 2. 13th ed. México: Siglo Veintiuno, 1997.
—. »Posfácio da segunda edição.« In O Capital: Crítica da Economia Política,
book 1, vol. I.1. São Paulo: Abril Cultural, 1988.
—. O Capital: Crítica da Economia Política, book 1, vol. I.1. São Paulo: Abril
Cultural, 1988.
—. O Capital: Crítica da Economia Política, book 3, vol. IV.1. 3rd ed. São Paulo: Nova Cultural, 1988.
—. »Prefácio.« In Contribuição para a Crítica da Economia Política. São Paulo:
Nova Cultural, 1999.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. A ideologia alemã. São Paulo: Martins Fontes, 2002.
Smith, Cyril. »Friedrich Engels and Marx’s critique of political economy.«
Capital & Class 62 (1997): 123 – 142.
The Psychology of Friedrich Engels
From the Materialist Theory
of Manual Labor to the Critique
of Empiricism and Ideology1
David Pavón-Cuéllar
Introduction: Engels as a Marxist Psychologist
Friedrich Engels (1820 – 1895) was a Marxist, but only to the extent
that Marx was also an Engelsian. The two men followed each other,
they learned together and forged their ideas together, including those
of a psychological nature. Substantive parts of the psychology that we
attribute to Marx, presented and explained recently,2 are also attributable to Engels. Hence, some authors prefer to speak of the psychology
of Marx and Engels.3 However, there are also original Engelsian contributions that must be considered separately, not because they contradict Marxian theory but because they preceded Marx’s theory and
advanced it through new avenues that paved the way for a Marxian
psychology, stabilizing concepts that were still volatile in Marx.
As we shall see, it is to the young Engels that we owe some of the
first psychological formulations of Marx’s psychologies of material and
historical determination, economic personifications, bourgeois individuality, and resistance and rebellion. We also know the original mature
Engelsian theories about psychic life: about its origin in manual work,
1
2
3
The present chapter is a translation of »La psicología de Friedrich Engels: de las
teorías materialistas del trabajo manual y del reflejo a la crítica del empirismo y
de la ideología«, Dialectus 2(6) (2015): 150 – 162. The editor would like to thank
the author and the publisher of the original work for the possibility to include it
in the present volume.
»Las dieciocho psicologías de Karl Marx,« Teoría y Crítica de la Psicología 5 (2015):
105 – 132.
See Samuel P. Coe, Contemporary Psychology in Marx and Engels (New York:
American Institute for Marxist Studies, 1978).
158
David Pavón-Cuéllar
its constitution as a reflection of the real, its mediating function between subject and mundane-corporeal reality, and its immaterial figuration as a primitive form of understanding dream phenomena. Engels
offers us an interesting theoretical-methodological critique of empiricist materialism in his elucidation of the psyche, as well as a denunciation of the psychological operation in the essence of ideology and the
expansion of the horizon of the psychological-materialist explanation,
beyond the productive, social basis and towards the foundations of sexual reproduction.
Considering the importance of the articulations of Marxism and
psychoanalysis in the various intellectual movements of the last 150 years,
we will pay close attention to co-incidences between the Engelsian and
Freudian perspectives. We will see Engels agree with Freud in his emphasis on sexuality and family, as well as in the valorization of symptoms,
the problematization of individuality, the consideration of corporeal
materiality (and not only the mundane form), and the redirection of
the abstract dualism of soul-body to the concrete monism of the body,
and even the demonstration of psychic determination through hypnotic
suggestion. With regard to the commonalities with Marx, we will also
see how they are permanent and tend to systematize into a unitary theory, which will justify our assertion that Engels’s is the first of the Marxist
psychologies. However, this does not exclude the existence of a critical
tension between the psychological discipline and Engels’s perspective.
The Soul of the English Workers:
The First Materialist Psychology
In his early work The Condition of the Working Class in England,4 Engels presents some psychological reflections that Marx later develops.
The psychology of material determination was already delineated in
4
Friedrich Engels, La situación de la clase obrera en Inglaterra (Moscow: Progreso,
1980 [1845]).
The Psychology of Friedrich Engels
159
his dialectical characterization of the workers, who were both harmed
by as well as beneficiaries of economic exploitation: deprived of »intellectual activity« and »degraded« to »the condition of beasts,« they
were nonetheless favored with »completely developed feelings« and
»strong passions« thanks, precisely, to their lack of bourgeois »intellectual culture« that »makes selfishness the main passion« and »concentrates all strength on money.«5 In terms of economic personification,
the bourgeois man is a »money-man« who only seeks »accumulation,«
whereas the worker is »more social« and his eyes are open more widely
since he does not relate to the world with selfishness and prejudices,
from which he is protected by his »imperfect culture.«6
In the Engelsian psychology of the English workers, as well as in
the later perspectives of Marx and Freud,7 the cultural disadvantage
implies, dialectically, a vital advantage. The workers’ lack of culture
allows them to develop their sociability, knowledge, passions and feelings. Their fortune lies in their misery. Analogously, the misery of the
bourgeois individual is rooted in his wealth, which isolates him in his
prejudiced and selfish individuality.
Anticipating the theory of mass society, Engels transforms the psyche of bourgeois individuality into the hegemonic model of modern
cities that promotes »sordid egotism,« the »isolation of each individual in his private interests,« and the fragmentation of society into
»atoms« or »monads.«8 The »great cities« would discover the »disease
of the social body,« and this was positive for Engels and his revalorization of the symptom because this enabled him to learn the »appropriate means to heal it.«9 This same Engelsian dialectic, a precursor of
the Freudian principle of abstinence and of the Marxian psychology
5
6
7
8
9
Ibid., 89.
Ibid., 53.
Karl Marx, Manuscritos: economía y filosofía (Madrid: Alianza, 1997 [1844]);
S. Freud, »El porvenir de una ilusión,« in Obras completas, vol. XXI (Buenos
Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1927]), 1 – 56.
Engels, La situación de la clase obrera en Inglaterra, 11 – 12.
Ibid., 52.
160
David Pavón-Cuéllar
of resistance and rebellion, also operates in the conviction that the
workers, »treated like beasts,« are able to »save the consciousness and
feelings of their humanity« in their »continuous internal rebellion.«10
The young Engels preceded Marx and Freud in the revalorization
of the symptom, in the discovery of vital misery in cultural wealth,
in problematizing individuality, in envisioning economic personification, and in underscoring material determination. The same young
Engels was also a pioneer when he delineated a psychology of the
historical determination of the English workers, in whose psyche
he found the vestiges of past migrations, cultural fusions, economic changes, etc. Engels criticized those who »only recognize psychological development, the development of the abstract man, outside
any connection to the past, when, in fact, the world depends on the
past.«11 Such dependency, contradicting the amnesic tendencies of
psychology, shows the presence of the past in everything that is present in the world, since everything depends on the past.
Materialism of the Hands:
The Origins of Corporeal Psyche
Considerations of the present and the past are constant in the thought
of Engels, and this makes him delve into the most remote, pre-historic and even pre-human times. These explorations always have a
materialistic character. He is searching for the historical material determination, which, once discovered, serves to critique the idealistic
and amnesic affectations of our knowledge.
If man now tends to explain »his acts through his thoughts« psychologically, it is because previously there were those who made the
work »planned by their heads« be »executed by the hands of others.«12
10
11
12
Ibid., 49.
Ibid., 99.
Friedrich Engels, »El papel del trabajo en el proceso de transformación del mono
en hombre,« in Obras filosóficas (Mexico: FCE, 1876), 418.
The Psychology of Friedrich Engels
It was in this way that the mental-intellectual, the future subject of
psychology, was abstracted from the corporeal-manual, distancing itself from it in order to devalue it, exploit it, marginalize it, dominate
it, and repress it. Such an exercise of power, as a dominant-repressive
material determination, allowed the powerful to acquire his apparently elevated and independent existence as spirit, ideal, refined soul,
and the psychic, distinct from the somatic and susceptible to being
studied by psychology. Like Marx and Freud, Engels redirects the
soul-body duality towards the concrete material totality in which it
originates through a process of abstraction. Such abstraction is idealization and psychologization, and it is also social dissociation and a
cultural-economic division between two parts of the body: the heads
that do the planning, the powerful, and the obedient hands that do
the work, the exploited. In the Engelsian explanation of the origin
of humanity, it is the body that adopts an »erect posture« and thus
frees the hands, which, thanks to their lack of occupation, can then
turn towards work that becomes progressively more complicated and
collectivized, which in turn incentivizes the development of language,
the transformation of the senses, and the conversion of the »monkey
brain« into a »human brain,« which ends up thinking of itself as an
incorporeal, spiritual, ethereal soul.13 It is true, then, that the psyche
of Engels, as well as that of Marx and Freud, comes from the body
and owes everything it is to the body. Humanity stands out, in the
end, because of its erect body with its manual work and because of
its rational soul with its intellectual work. If the intellect became free
from the hands, it is because the hands freed themselves from the
erect body. It was »with the hands« that »the head developed« and
»consciousness emerged.«14
Engels’s explanation, just like Marx’s and Freud’s, is perfectly materialistic. Matter is the first, most decisive and most fundamental
element. The development of the human psyche is founded on the
13
14
Ibid., 412 – 418.
Friedrich Engels, »Dialéctica de la naturaleza,« in Obras filosóficas (Mexico: FCE,
1883), 299.
161
162
David Pavón-Cuéllar
development of language, the brain and the senses. This development
is grounded in complex and collective work rooted in turn in the corporeal materiality of the hands, which become independent as they
detach themselves from the ground.
Materialism of Reflection:
The Unreal Object of Psychology
In Engels’s materialistic approaches to psychology, the theory of
corporeal-manual humanization (the material origin of human psychism) is complemented with conceptions of the socio-economic
material bases of the historical psychic configurations. The »moral
ideas« of each epoch, for example, are ultimately explained by the
»economic relationships« from which they come, »consciously or
unconsciously.«15 The existence of private property imposes the moral precept of »thou shall not steal,« as well as other contents of our
consciousness, thoughts and feelings, invariably »determined by our
current realities.«16
The Engelsian notion of the historical material determination
tends to be schematized in a theory of reflection that ends up establishing itself as the guiding principle of the Leninist perspective17 and
some of the main currents of Soviet Marxist psychology,18 but which
originates in Marx’s ideas such as the one that defines »the ideal« as
»the material translated and transposed into the head of a man.«19 In
15
16
17
18
19
Friedrich Engels, »La subversión de la ciencia por el señor Eugen Dühring (»Anti-Dühring«),« in Obras filosóficas (Mexico: FCE, 1878), 81.
Ibid., 158.
Vladimir I. Lenin, Materialismo y empiriocriticismo (Beijing: Ediciones en Lenguas
Extranjeras, 1975 [1908]).
See Sergei L. Rubinstein, Principios de psicología general (Mexico: Grijalbo, 1982
[1940]); Alexis N. Leontiev, Actividad, conciencia y personalidad (Mexico: Cartago, 1984 [1977]).
Karl Marx, »Postfacio a la segunda edición,« in El Capital (Mexico: FCE, 2008
[1873]), xxiii.
The Psychology of Friedrich Engels
163
the Engelsian development of reflex theory, we begin with the metaphor of the idealist consciousness critically conceived as a »concave
mirror« that inverts things into a »deformed image« of »historical reality,«20 but, very rapidly, through »religious reflections« of the »real
foundation,«21 we arrive at the representation of ideas and other mental contents as »more or less abstract images of real things and phenomena,«22 as »reflections in our thought« of the »real conflicts,«23 and
as »refracted images of the real things.«24
The reflected images, identified with the psyche, constitute
well-defined and limited objects that apparently allow us to preserve
psychology, preventing its object from becoming dissolved in the
world and in the body, as happens with the young Marx25 and the old
Freud.26 Unlike Marxist and Freudian theories (which end up assimilating psychism into its economic-industrial and somatic-impulsive
material determination), Engels maintains the object of psychology
on the superficial field of the mirror that reminds us of the surface to
which Freud reduced the ego and its psychology.27 The mirror creates
a psychic world, deformed and sometimes inverted, that distinguishes itself from the world but does not stop being purely superficial,
apparent, and imaginary. If we dig deeper into this world, we will go
through it and we’ll leave it behind.
It is true that reflection theory preserves psychology, not exactly
as a positive science, but rather as a negative study of an unreal
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
Engels, »Anti-Dühring,« 83 – 84.
Ibid., 276.
Friedrich Engels, »Del socialismo utópico al socialismo científico,« in Obras filosóficas (Mexico: FCE, 1880), 593.
Ibid., 597.
Friedrich Engels, »Ludwig Feuerbach y el fin de la filosofía clásica alemana,« in
Obras filosóficas (Mexico: FCE, 1888), p. 562.
Marx, Manuscritos.
Sigmund Freud, »Esquema del psicoanálisis,« in Obras completas, vol. XXIII
(Buenos Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1938]), 133 – 210.
Sigmund Freud, »El yo y el ello,« in Obras completas, vol. XIX (Buenos Aires:
Amorrortu, 1998 [1923]), 1 – 66; Sigmund Freud, »El malestar en la cultura,« in
Obras completas, vol. XXI (Buenos Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1929]), 57 – 140.
164
David Pavón-Cuéllar
object. And if it seems that we are falling into a certain dualism,
this no longer divides the world into two realities, physical and psychic, but into the physical reality and the psychic unreality, into
the imaginary and the real, into what is reflected and its deformed
reflection. Psychology must adhere to the unreal reflection, which is
the only psychic thing, which can only be explained by what is real,
by what is reflected, by the non-psychic, which, besides being what
is reflected, is also the socio-economic thing by which its reflection
is deformed on the ideological plane through »inversions« and other
»complications.«28
The deformation of the psychic reflection (the difference that
resists its assimilation into the physical-material reality) is determined and constituted by this same reality, by the economic system,
by social classes and interests. What is reflected is what deforms
itself ideologically, internally, in its own conscious exterior reflection. If men make history unconsciously and not only consciously,
it is because their »ideal motives« exist interiorly and do not just
reflect exteriorly the real »historical causes« that »determine them«
and that »in the minds of the acting men are transformed into those
motives.«29
The Engelsian psychic motive, like the Freudian one, is not just
a figuration of its immanent cause but transformation. In other
words, what psychology is concerned with is not only the reflection
of reality, its conscious deformed representation, but also its unconscious deforming presence, that is, the presence of what reflects
itself in knowledge, deforms itself in ideology, and transforms itself
in history. The whole deformed psychic reflection, the object of psychology, continues assimilating itself, monistically, to the deforming, reflecting and reflected non-psychic.
28
29
Engels, »Ludwig Feuerbach,« 562 – 574.
Ibid., 566.
The Psychology of Friedrich Engels
165
From Empiricism to Mysticism:
A Critique of Observational and Experimental Psychology
We have already seen that Engels’s materialism does not lead, through
reflection theory, either to the old body-soul duality or to a positive
psychological science. We will now be able to observe that the Engelsian materialist psychology is not compatible with either an exclusively cerebral, cranial, neuronal materialism or with a purely observational or experimental empiricism. Engels makes this very clear in his
critique of the phrenological projections of psychism on the shapes
and parts of the cranium.
In order to arrive at his critique of the empiricist materialism of
phrenology, Engels chose a path similar to the one that Freud would
choose when distancing himself from the empiricist materialism of
the scientificist medicine of the nineteenth century. Both used hypnosis, which, in both cases, demonstrated the mental determination
of the physical and the necessity to theorize observation, allowing
them to go beyond a series of empiricist excesses and materialist illusions. In the case of Engels, the hypnosis of an adolescent from Manchester, in the winter of 1843 – 44, allowed him to refute the supposed
phrenological location of certain psychic functions in certain parts of
the cranium when he demonstrated that the location could be modified when the subject, in a hypnotic state, was induced to respond to
the stimulation of other parts of the body and head. It was in this way
that Engels, in his own words, discovered »a series of phenomena as
the basis of the phrenological charlatanry, the majority of which were
only different in a certain degree to the ones manifested in a waking
state.«30
Many years before Freud admitted the influence of a sort of hypnosis in social life, specifically in mass phenomena, Engels recognized
that the same type of suggestion exists in the waking state and studied
it in order to explore the psychic causality of body responses. This cau30
Engels, »Dialéctica de la naturaleza,« 315.
166
David Pavón-Cuéllar
sality would not be perceived in the empirical investigations that limited themselves to observation and experimentation, thus condemning
themselves to »the chimera, credulity and superstition,« that science often incurs when it »emphasizes simple experience« and »treats thought
with contempt.«31 Do we not have here a sort of premonition of what
would be a significant part of the modern psychological discipline?
Our psychology, in fact, falls into the »most trivial empiricism« that
»despises everything that is theory« and thus leads us to »mysticism.«32
The mystical delusion would serve to establish those relationships that
we have not established through »theoretical thought,« which, according to Engels, exists precisely to »relate [the facts] to each other« or to
»penetrate the relationship that exists between them.«33
The Origin of the Family and Sexual Love:
Beyond Psychology
When readdressing Marx’s ethnological notes, Engels34 elaborated
an intricate structure of theoretical relationships between scarce and
doubtful empirical facts related to the pre-historic origins of the family
and sexual love. The result was an enormous construct that not only
reminds us of the fascinating interpretative excesses of Freud35 regarding
the primordial horde but also contains valuable ideas that can serve as a
bridge between Marxism and Freudian psychoanalysis. Many of these
ideas come from Marx and, in particular, from his reading of Morgan,36
as in the case of the cardinal theses of primitive communism and its »in31
32
33
34
35
36
Ibid., 313.
Ibid., 320.
Ibid., 321.
Friedrich Engels, El origen de la familia, de la propiedad privada y del Estado
(Mexico: Colofón, 2011 [1884]).
Sigmund Freud, »Tótem y Tabú,« in Obras completas, vol. XIII (Buenos Aires:
Amorrortu, 1998 [1913]), 1 – 164.
Lewis H. Morgan, Ancient Society, or: Researches in the lLnes of Human Progress
from Savagery, through Barbarism to Civilization (New York: Holt, 1877).
The Psychology of Friedrich Engels
comparably superior vitality« over advanced societies37 and the (almost
Freudian) conception of the monogamous family as a »microcosm of
all the antagonisms that would later develop in society and the State.«38
In the work of Engels, based on that of Marx,39 we see an expansion of the Marxist field of research from the »means of production«
to the »means of reproduction«40 and from the »class struggle« to the
»struggle between man and woman.«41 In this way, the socio-economic sphere, emphasized by Marxism, gives way to the familial-sexual
sphere, emphasized by Freudian psychoanalysis. Like Freud,42 Engels
did not separate both spheres but instead perceived a close relationship between the two: the familial-sexual transition from matriarchate
to patriarchate represents the socio-economic victory of »individual
property over spontaneous primitive communism,«43 the first »class
oppression« was the oppression of »the feminine sex by the masculine
sex,«44 and in modern society, »the family man is the bourgeoisie within the family« while »the woman represents the proletariat.«45
If the bourgeoisie is condemned to the monogamous family as a
space for the exploitation of women, then the »oppressed classes« can
aspire to equality between the sexes and to »marriage for love« and not
»for convenience.«46 The authentic sexual-loving feeling, the core of
psychism in Freudian theory, turns into a privilege of the oppressed in
the Engelsian representation of the society of classes. Besides being a
social and classist phenomenon, this feeling is historically fixed in the
barbarian invasions at the end of the Roman Empire. Engels searched
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
Karl Marx, »Proyecto de respuesta a la carta de V. I. Zasulich,« in Obras escogidas
de Marx y Engels, vol. III (Moscow: Progreso, 1980 [1881]), 86.
Karl Marx, Los apuntes etnológicos de Karl Marx (Madrid: Siglo XXI y Pablo
Iglesias, 1988 [1882]), 94 – 95.
Marx, »Proyecto de respuesta«; Marx, Los apuntes etnológicos.
Marx, Manuscritos, 35.
Ibid., 74 – 75.
Freud, »Tótem y Tabú.«
Engels, El origen de la familia, 62 – 74.
Ibid., 74.
Ibid., 84.
Ibid., 81 – 93.
167
168
David Pavón-Cuéllar
for the pre-historic origin of a gens that emerged from »group marriage« in which »whole groups of men and whole groups of women
possess each other reciprocally,« thereby »shutting out jealousy« and
ensuring the »union of forces« necessary for the »evolution from animality to humanity.«47 This group-social origin of being human, of
the family and of sexuality contrasts with the familial-sexual origin of
humans and social groups in Freud.48 However, outside of this contrast, Freud and Engels agree on the historical problematization-relativization of feelings of love, monogamous sexuality and the nuclear
family in its modern Western versions. Neither of them accepts universal and eternal categories. Both insist on going beyond psychology,
refraining from psychologizing social and cultural institutions.
The Soul Apart: Psychology as the Essence of Ideology
Engels went all the way back to pre-history in order to explain not
only the origins of humanity, the family and sexual love, but also the
human psyche as an entity separate from the human body. We have
already seen that such an irruption of the object of psychology was
explained through the development of the hand, language and brain,
with the resulting division between the manual work of the slave and
the intellectual work of the master. This Engelsian idea, compatible
with the Marxian view, would later give way to the hypothesis that
the pre-historic man, »excited by dreams, started to believe that his
thought and his sensations were not activities of his body but of a
separate soul that lived inside him.« And »since that day, man has not
been able to stop thinking about the relationship between the soul
and the external world.«49
47
48
49
Ibid., 40.
Freud, »Tótem y Tabú«; Sigmund Freud, »Psicología de las masas y análisis
del yo,« in Obras completas, vol. XVIII (Buenos Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1921]),
63 – 136.
Engels, »Ludwig Feuerbach,« 546.
The Psychology of Friedrich Engels
169
The idealistic abstraction of the soul existing apart is reconnected with the concrete, mundane-corporeal totality in the Engelsian
approach to psychology. This reconnection compares psychism to a
mediating function between the human subject and everything that
acts upon him and »moves his life« and must »manifest« itself psychically in his »head«: on the one hand, there is the body that manifests
itself in sensations like »hunger and thirst«; on the other hand, there
is the »external world« that »reflects« itself in the »shape of sensations,
thoughts, impulses and willful determinations.«50 It is in this way that
the psychological, individualist dualism of body-and-soul is transformed in a sort of monism in which we can only distinguish two
expressions of the same mundane-corporeal totality: its presence in
the »propelling or determinant causes« and its representation through
psychic reflections in the »ideological forms« of the »ideal or conscious motives.«51
In Engelsian theory, the object of psychology is reduced to an
ideological reflection, ideal and conscious, of the world and the body.
The psychological abstraction for which this reflection sees itself as
a soul apart is the essential mechanism of ideology understood as
»an activity that is in charge of thoughts, considered as entities with
their own existence and developed in an independent manner, subject
only to their own specific laws.«52 This Engelsian definition of ideology is in itself a definition of psychology. However, more than being
a precedent for a future critical Marxist conception of psychology as
ideology,53 it is also an original representation that is also critical of
ideology as psychology.
50
51
52
53
Ibid., 553.
Ibid., 566 – 567.
Ibid., 571.
Carlos L. Sastre, La psicología, red ideológica (Buenos Aires: Tiempo contemporáneo, 1974); Néstor A. Braunstein et al. Psicología: Ideología y ciencia (Mexico: Siglo XXI, 1975); Ian Parker, La psicología como ideología (Madrid: Catarata, 2010).
170
David Pavón-Cuéllar
Conclusion: Engels as a Marxist Critic of Psychology
The Engelsian critique of ideology is also a critique of the psychological mechanism through which a psychic, ideal or intellectual object
abstracts itself from the concrete reality, conceived as relatively independent and ruled by its own laws. This mechanism is psychology
itself and, consequently, when he criticized it, Engels also criticized
psychology. In contrast with what is criticized, Engelsian research
incorporates the psychic object in its concrete social, economic and
historical reality on which it depends and by whose laws it is ruled.
We can say, in this sense, that Engels was not so much a psychologist
as a critic of psychology.
The Engelsian critique of psychology began early on in his investigations of English workers, in which the psyche spreads out of its
own domain and dissipates through society, the economy and history.
Then, this object of psychology is presented as a product of the classist
division between head and hands, a division upon which psychology
would be founded and which would be fought by the communist in
his struggle against classism. In his fight against class society and its
psychological product, Engels would reduce the psychic to an unreal,
apparent and superficial condition, a reflection in which there is only
the reflected non-psychic and its distortion, which, ultimately, will be
explained by the real reflected and not by the unreal reflection.
As we have seen, Engels’s Marxist critique does not stop at a strictly empirical psychology in which he alerts us to the dangers of a mysticism that would compensate for the lack of theory. Theoretical reflection, in the direction that Engels sets, can only take us beyond the
boundaries of psychology, even when dealing with the more intimate
and personal elements (such as sexual love), which are redirected to
their historical, group-social origins. How can we not go past the psychology that we investigate when Engels conceives it as a simple surface, the appearance and representation of that which hides from us?
Translated by Gilmar Visoni-Alonzo
The Psychology of Friedrich Engels
Works Cited
Braunstein, Néstr et al. Psicología: Ideología y ciencia. Mexico: Siglo XXI, 1975.
Coe, Samuel P. Contemporary Psychology in Marx and Engels. New York:
American Institute for Marxist Studies, 1978.
Engels, Friedrich. La situación de la clase obrera en Inglaterra. Moscow: Progreso, 1980 [1845].
—. »El papel del trabajo en el proceso de transformación del mono en hombre.« In Obras filosóficas, 412 – 422. Mexico: FCE, 1876.
—. »La subversión de la ciencia por el señor Eugen Dühring (»AntiDühring«).« In Obras filosóficas, 1 – 284. Mexico: FCE, 1878.
—. »Del socialismo utópico al socialismo científico.« In Obras filosóficas,
578 – 636. Mexico: FCE, 1880.
—. »Dialéctica de la naturaleza.« In Obras filosóficas, 285 – 533. Mexico: FCE,
1883.
—. El origen de la familia, de la propiedad privada y del Estado. Mexico:
Colofón, 2011 [1884].
—. »Ludwig Feuerbach y el fin de la filosofía clásica alemana.« In Obras filosóficas, 535 – 575. Mexico: FCE, 1888.
Freud, Sigmund. »Tótem y Tabú.« In Obras completas, vol. XIII, 1 – 164. Buenos
Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1913].
—. »Psicología de las masas y análisis del yo.« In Obras completas, vol. XVIII,
63 – 136. Buenos Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1921].
—. »El yo y el ello.« In Obras completas, vol. XIX, 1 – 66. Buenos Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1923].
—. »El porvenir de una ilusión.« In Obras completas, vol. XXI, 1 – 56. Buenos
Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1927].
—. »El malestar en la cultura.« In Obras completas, vol. XXI, 57 – 140. Buenos
Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1929].
—. »Esquema del psicoanálisis.« In Obras completas, vol. XXIII, 133 – 210.
Buenos Aires: Amorrortu, 1998 [1938].
Lenin, Vladimir I. Materialismo y empiriocriticismo. Beijing: Ediciones en
Lenguas Extranjeras, 1975 [1908].
Leontiev, Alexis N. Actividad, conciencia y personalidad. Mexico: Cartago,
1984 [1977].
Marx, Karl. Manuscritos: economía y filosofía. Madrid: Alianza, 1997 [1844].
171
172
David Pavón-Cuéllar
—. »Postfacio a la segunda edición.« In El Capital, xvii-xxiv. Mexico: FCE,
2008 [1873].
—. »Proyecto de respuesta a la carta de V. I. Zasulich.« In Obras escogidas de
Marx y Engels, vol. III, 85 – 90. Moscow: Progreso, 1980 [1881].
—. Los apuntes etnológicos de Karl Marx. Madrid: Siglo XXI y Pablo Iglesias,
1988 [1882].
Morgan, Lewis H. Ancient society; or, researches in the lines of human progress
from savagery, through barbarism to civilization. New York: Holt, 1877.
Parker, Ian La psicología como ideología. Madrid: Catarata, 2010.
Pavón-Cuéllar, David. »Las dieciocho psicologías de Karl Marx.« Teoría y
Crítica de la Psicología 5 (2015): 105 – 132.
Rubinstein, Sergei L. Principios de psicología general. Mexico: Grijalbo, 1982
[1940].
Sastre, Carlos L. La psicología, red ideológica. Buenos Aires: Tiempo contemporáneo, 1974.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology1
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
Strictly speaking, for the anthropologist, the title of this article brings
up the issue related to the so-called ›primitive society,‹ which gave rise
to many ideological positions. These ideological positions shared the
belief that societies were based on blood or in soil, and that the consequent principles of descendance and territoriality could be equated to
race and citizenship. The evolutionary or evolutionist structure offered
the hope that although institutions may vary from society to society,
they formed a hierarchy through which all would eventually progress.2
The Antecedents to Lewis Morgan
The first ideas developed on the theme had India as locus empiricus,
apparently the central political issue of the 1850s, and the dispute
over the prevalence of law with regard to traditional customs and
principles related to individual land rights derived from the British
government and considerable parts of the utilitarian current. Henry S.
Maine (1822 – 1888) intervened in the dispute, advocating for retaining
the traditional system in India and, therefore, opposing a civil law
based on a simplified English law. In fact, he and Bentham were on
1
2
The present article is an extended translation of »Engels e a etnologia evolucionista,« in Friedrich Engels e a ciência contemporânea, eds. Muniz Ferreira, Ricardo
Moreno, and Mauro Castelo Branco (Salvador: EDUFBA, 2007), 65 – 84. The
editor would like to thank the author and the publisher for the possibility to
include the translation in the present volume.
Adam Kuper, The Invention of Primitive Society (London, Routledge, 1988).
174
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
opposite sides: whereas Bentham believed that government was based
on a social contract established by individuals for the protection of
property, Maine proposed that original societies were based on families related by status and shared property. The so-called ›primitive
societies‹ were subjected to a patrimonial despot.3
In his book Ancient Law, Maine sought to offer a solution to the
conflict between the legal ideas of India and those of the British Empire through a legal history of the family under the mantel of Indo-European nations along a spectrum that connected India with ancient
Germany and the British Crown through Rome. Nothing, in the light
of that argument, prevented India from developing under British
guidance, as had previously happened with Germany thanks to Rome.
The assumption, generalized at the time, that ›primitive peoples‹
carried out female infanticide indiscriminately was one of the means
used by McLennan to attack Maine’s patriarchal theory. His argument imputed the practice of the large-scale search for women in
external areas, which gave rise to the term ›exogamy.‹ On the other
hand, since there was supposed to be a permanent struggle between
communities, exogamy could not have resulted from a peaceful modality of approach but from acts of violence on the part of men in
the position of beings forced to capture wives. These women, captured in small numbers relative to the demand, would be shared in a
group under an arrangement called ›rough polyandry.‹ The more or
less obvious conclusion was that, under such circumstances, it was
difficult to establish paternity, as a result of which the first system of
kinship would have to be based on bloodlines defined only by the
female lineage.4 As Radcliffe-Brown noted many years later (1951),
McLennan historically interpreted the custom of presenting the taking of a woman by one group from another as an act of hostility as a
vestigial manifestation of the primitive conditions of human society.
He presented the kidnapping or capture of women by another group
3
4
Ibid., 7.
Ibid., 37.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
as the only way to obtain wives and generalized its diffusion.5 In this
way, the excesses of evolutionist formulations were highlighted and
delegitimized.
The roughest forms of women sharing would have increasingly
given way to a more refined and restrictive arrangement, in which
uterine brothers with a recognized degree of solidarity would share
a woman, a modality called ›Tibetan polyandry,‹ considered by McLennan to be a stage in the development of marriage whose most
important implication would be the sharing of descendance by the
sons of a woman. In practice, Tibetan polyandry constituted another
step towards the recognition of paternity. The idea of paternity, in
turn, became firmly established, and its development was stimulated
by the parallel growth of the welfare economy, which resulted from
the necessity of having rules to govern the transmission of property
between generations.
As the reader may realize, these ideas are built upon precarious
correlations and false assumptions. This is due to their character as
preliminary outlines in attempts to establish a nexus between past
and present according to an ascending linear march. Regarding literature that deals particularly with kinship, Radcliffe-Brown incisively
pointed out that the theories that produced it »can only be called
pseudo-historical,« imputing upon them unhappy results through the
»legacy of erroneous ideas.« This legacy would be gradually discarded
in favor of the development of field studies that did not refer to the
origin of social systems, except when the actual history was known,
in a clear allusion to the conjectures of McLennan, Maine and their
contemporaries that ventured into this area.6
5
6
Alfred Reginald Radcliffe-Brown, »O Método Comparativo em Antropologia,«
in Antropologia, edited by J. C. Melatti (São Paulo: Ática, 1978), 53.
Alfred Reginald Radcliffe-Brown, »Introducción,« in Sistemas Africanos de
Parentesco y Casamento, eds. Alfred Reginald Radcliffe-Brown and Daryll Forde
(Barcelona: Editorial Anagrama, 1982), 60.
175
176
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
Lewis H. Morgan and the Order of Social Development
In 1871, a more elaborate version of McLennan’s thesis — that the first
systems based on kinship would have been matrilineal, and the order
of social development had the sequence tribe / gens / family — was published by an American attorney, Lewis Henry Morgan. The Primitive
Society provided a long and ambitious record of political and social
evolution that, similarly to McLennan’s formulations, started with a
matrilineal group and ended with the triumph of the state and the
family. However, unlike his predecessors, Morgan had established, for
the purposes of his research, a relationship with the Iroquois of New
York, from whom he collected copious kinship terminology, and with
the Crow from Missouri, from whom he recorded information on
rituals and religious behaviors.7
Morgan was particularly interested in issues concerning American
ethnology and, before writing The Primitive Society, he published Letters on the Iroquois by Skenandoah (American Review, 1847), League of
the Iroquois (1851), and Systems of Consanguinity and Affinity of the Human Family (1871). In this last work, hereafter referred to as SCAHF,
he distinguished descriptive systems — in which there were different
terms for linear and collateral relatives, i. e. for father and mother,
husband and wife, brother and sister, and son and daughter, none of
which was applied outside the family nucleus — and he claimed that
such systems would mirror the reality of biological kinship, clearly
demarcating degrees of blood relationships.8 The systems of classification, on the contrary, would not reflect the natural degrees of kinship
but would bring relationships of different types together under one
term, which could refer to father, brother of the father, or son of the
7
8
Lewis Henry Morgan, A Sociedade Primitiva, Vol. I (Lisbon: Presença; São Paulo:
Martins Fontes, 1976), 191.
The descriptive systems would be characteristic of all North American indigenous peoples (with the exception of the Inuit), southern Indian, Chinese, Southeast Asian and Pacific peoples, which for Morgan showed the unity of North
American indigenous peoples and its relationship with Asian peoples.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
brother of the father, confusing different forms and degrees of biological parentage, as recorded among the Iroquois.9
The question, as Levi-Strauss pointed out, is that kinship should be
interpreted as a phenomenon of structure and not as the result of the
simple juxtaposition of terms and customs.10 Furthermore, the systems
of kinship cover two very different types of reality, that is, the terminological system (system of vocabulary) and the system of attitudes, of a
psychological and social nature. It is additionally always necessary to distinguish between two types of attitudes, i. e. those that are diffused and
deprived of an institutional character, and obligatory attitudes, sanctioned by taboos or privileges and expressed through fixed rituals. »In
addition to automatically reflecting a nomenclature, these attitudes often appear as secondary elaborations destined to resolve contradictions
and overcome insufficiencies inherent to the terminological system.«11
Morgan, on the contrary, gave excessive relevance to terminologies
to the detriment of the system of attitudes. When opposing McLennan’s refusal to admit that the systems that he had classified in terms of
consanguinity and affinity (purely conventional and only established as
a means to address one other when greeting), Morgan observed that a
system of forms of greeting is ephemeral and postulated that a system
of consanguinity is something very different, to the extent that the relationships of kinship that characterize it derive from the family and the
matrimonial regime, being more permanent than the family itself since
the latter evolves while the system remains immutable. This conception
led to: a) the reification of kinship relationships, apprehended as mere
expressions of the real conditions in which society lived in the period
that the system was constituted, exerting an important influence on the
daily life of human beings; and b) the conclusion that the uniformity
9
10
11
Lewis Henry Morgan, Systems of Consanguinity and Affinity of the Human Family
(Washington, DC: Smithsonian Contributions of Knowledge, 1871).
Claude Lévi-Strauss, As Estruturas Elementares do Parentesco (Petrópolis: Paz e
Terra; São Paulo: EDUSP, 1976), 164.
Claude Lévi-Strauss, Antropologia Estrutural (Rio de Janeiro: Tempo Brasileiro,
1970), 55 – 56.
177
178
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
of immense regions of the globe and its preservation through very long
periods of time should be the link to bring about marriage rules.12
Thus, he tried to explain the origin of two systems of consanguinity
and affinity from the forms of marriage and family from which they
derived, admitting via hypothesis the existence of those forms. Having
obtained a satisfactory explanation for each system, the previous existence of each modality of marriage and family could be deduced from
the system that they explained. He also admitted that the sequence
postulated was based, in part, on hypotheses, but it was sufficiently
corroborated by the evidence to be taken into consideration. Future
ethnologists were left to »establish a full picture of this sequence.«13
Let us see how he proceeded in the case of a consanguineous family.
Considered the first and oldest form of the family institution, it would
have stopped existing »even among the most backward savage tribes,«
hence, it would not be possible to provide direct evidence of its existence.14
The proof, then, that it had existed at a given moment in human history
would have to be conclusive—»otherwise it would not demonstrate our
thesis«—that is, strengthened by a system of consanguinity and affinity
that for many centuries survived the marriage customs that had presided
over its birth and whose presence demonstrated that this family existed
at the moment the Malay system took shape.15 We are, then, confronted
with something that resembles the petition of principle in Aristotelian
terms: »Revealing relationships of kinship that ruled the consanguineous family and its existence implies the existence of this type of family.
Furthermore, it strengthens the theoretical certainty of the existence of
the consanguineous family at the time it was established.«16
Another criticism directed at Morgan (who did not doubt the value of
the terminologies of kinship to reveal the method of organizing relation12
13
14
15
16
Lewis Henry Morgan, A Sociedade Primitiva, Vol. II (Lisbon: Presença; São Paulo:
Martins Fontes, 1978), 271.
Ibid., 138.
Ibid., 139.
Ibid., 139 – 140.
Ibid., 140.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
ships) was his attempt to classify all terminological systems using the two
types referred to above when it was perfectly possible to use both classificatory and descriptive principles, as Daryll Forde, among others, proved
for the Yakö, a people established in the Ogoha province of southern
Nigeria. According to Forde, their system constitutes an example of the
total and simultaneous development of both groups of matrilineal and
patrilineal relatives that, at the time of his fieldwork, were suffering from
the impact of Western institutions but continued to give both lines of
affiliation the same relevance. Forde identified the Abayong, Agwa’aguna
and the Enna as other groups holding a similar dual system to the Yakö.17
The restriction ascribed to SCAHF did not diminish its relevance,
so much so that Claude Levi-Strauss did not hesitate in saying that
Morgan founded, simultaneously, social anthropology and kinship
studies18 and that he and Frank Hamilton Cushing were the great
precursors of structural research.19
The Primitive Society
In The Primitive Society, Morgan postulated that »the history of humanity is one in its origin, its experience, and its progress.«20 Endowed
with essentially identical intelligence and a similar physical organism
by virtue of their common origin, in the same ethnic period, humans
have always arrived at the same results, in all times and all places.21
It was this trait that led man to the invention of the arrow, which
expresses the thought of a wild man, the fusion of iron ore, which
represents the more developed intelligence of the barbarian, and, last17
18
19
20
21
Daryll Forde, »Doble Filiación entre los Yakö,« in Sistemas Africanos de Parentesco
y Matrimonio, eds. Alfred Reginald Radcliffe-Brown and Daryll Forde (Barcelona: Editorial Anagrama, 1982 [1950]), 317.
Lévi-Strauss, Antropologia Estrutural, 325.
Ibid., 314.
Morgan, Sociedade Primitiva I, 8.
Morgan, Sociedade Primitiva II, 308.
179
180
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
ly, steel, the materialized triumph of civilization. Finally, the labors,
difficulties, and successes of the barbarians and savages would have
been part of the »plan of the Supreme Intelligence,« who envisioned
to make from the savage a barbarian, and from this a civilized man.22
His purpose was to prove that human progress continued its march
through successive ethnic periods, internally demarcated by certain subsistence arts, as evidenced by inventions, discoveries, and the development of ideas of government, family, and property. In a peremptory way,
he stated that these inventions and discoveries were directly related to
the progress of humanity, and as social and civil institutions developed
from original seeds of thought, they would represent the same scale of
development. Taken together and compared, these institutions, inventions and discoveries tended to demonstrate the origin of humanity in
parallel to the needs of humans at the same stage of development and the
identity of the activity of the human spirit in similar social conditions.23
Organization into gens, fraternities, and tribes would have prevailed
throughout the longest part of the most recent savage stage and throughout the period of barbarism. The family, in a similar manner, would
have assumed successively different forms, giving rise to systems of consanguinity and affinity that would attest to the experiences of humanity
during the transition from the consanguineous family to the monogamic
family. Finally, forms of government, under the two general systems, had
very different bases. The first system depended on people and personal
relationships, and it constituted a society whose organizing unity was the
gens, from which the fraternity, the tribe, and the confederation of tribes
would emerge (through successive integration); the second system was
based on territory and property and was characterized by constructing a
state (civitas). The city or agglomerate, circumscribed by limits in whose
interior property was established, constituted the foundation of the state
and would lead to political society. The notion of private property presented the same evolution and the same development.24
22
23
24
Ibid., 308 – 310.
Morgan, Sociedade Primitiva I, 8.
Ibid., 8 – 9, 16 – 17, 19.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
The principle that apparently operated throughout human history was a tendency towards moral progress in the form of the organic
movement of society to distance itself from unfavorable conditions.
The decline of classificatory systems of kinship and their replacement by descriptive ones would have been impelled by the influence
of relationships of property, a sign of so-called ›civilization.‹ The
distribution of goods would be observed, and there was thus a sequence in the direction of concentration: if, in the so-called savage
state, goods were distributed by members of the gens, in the early
phase of barbarism they were restricted to the agnatic relatives, and
finally, in the latter phase, goods were transmitted to sons as sole
heirs.25
Ethnic Periods and Arts of Subsistence
I. FIES
II. FMES
III. FSES
IV. FIB
V.
FMB
VI. FSB
VII. Civilization
25
Natural means of subsistence
Consumption of fish and use of fire
(Australia and Polynesia)
Invention of the bow and arrow
(Coastal Tribes of the Americas)
Invention of pottery
(Amerindians east of the Mississippi)
Animal domestication in the Oriental Hemisphere and irrigation, brick buildings in the
Western hemisphere (Indians of New Mexico,
Mexico, Central America and Peru)
Smelting of iron ore (Homeric Greek tribes, Italic tribes, Germanic tribes during Roman times)
Use of the phonetic alphabet and the production
of literature
Morgan, Sociedade Primitiva II, 62.
181
182
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
Source: A Sociedade Primitiva I, 20 – 24
According to Morgan, the systematic progress of ethnology demanded that the development of the normal living conditions of savage
and barbarian tribes be studied in regions where the institutions were
homogeneous. Thus, Polynesia and Australia would be the best places
for the study of societies in a savage state, whereas for the early and
later phases of barbarism, the best field of study would be the Americas during the time of their discovery.26
Development of Types of Family
–
–
–
–
–
–
–
–
–
–
–
–
–
Promiscuous intercourse
Intermarriage or the cohabitation of brothers and sisters
Communal family (first stage of the family)
Hawaiian custom
Malay form of the classificatory system
Tribal organization
Turanian and Ganowanian systems of relationships
Marriage between couples
Barbarian family (second stage of the family)
Polygamy
Patriarchal family (third stage of the family)
Polyandry
Emergence of private property and establishment of linear succession
– Civilized family (fourth stage of the family)
– Decline of classificatory systems of kinship, replaced by descriptive systems
Morgan dedicated close to half of his book to the development of the
system of the gens, based on the fact that it had survived the greater
part of human history. The stages of progress were illustrated by five
26
Ibid., 206.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
183
crucial case studies, each one of which was given its special relevance:
Australian, Iroquois, Aztec, Greek, and Roman.
The Australian case represented the most primitive system, being only a short distance from the initial condition in which brother
supposedly married sister in a form of incestuous group marriage;
the Iroquois material was used to illustrate the subsequent stage of
evolution in which the democratic gens was associated with larger
federations; and the Aztecs, who would follow, were at the middle
stage of barbarism. Later, Morgan classified the Aztec stage as a more
advanced version of the Iroquois federation. His particular interest in
the Aztecs was related to his attempt to refute the sources represented
by Spanish chroniclers in which the Aztec monarchy was presented as
analogous to European monarchies.27 He gave credence to the chronicles insofar as they described the actions of the conquistadors and
the personal characteristics of the Indians, as well as their technology,
diet, and dress; however, Morgan did not give any value to what the
chroniclers wrote about the natives‹ society and government. In this
respect, the value of the Spanish chroniclers‹ narratives was »practically null, since they did not know or learn anything with regard to the
issue,« leading to his rejection of their formulations and to his study
of the issue from the beginning, »using, however, that which is in
concordance with what we know about Indian society.«28
As far as the Greeks are concerned, their primitive government
was essentially democratic, as gens, fraternities, and tribes were organized as self-governed bodies based upon the principles of freedom,
equality, and fraternity, whereas the Roman empire was artificial and
illogical, albeit capable of great achievements.29
When the data produced by Morgan or collected from the available bibliography proved insufficient to support his ambitious project,
he complemented them with other means, such as established English informants or bureaucratic or religious injunctions in different
27
28
29
Morgan, Sociedade Primitiva I, 69.
Ibid., 225.
Morgan, Sociedade Primitiva II, 70.
184
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
parts of the world. For Australia, for example, he used the help of English missionaries, and for other ethnographic contexts, he used the
most diverse sources, such as Edward Tylor (Early History of Mankind
and Primitive Culture), Homer (The Iliad and The Odyssey), Herrera
(History of America), Lucretius (De Rerum Natura), Prescott (Conquest
of America), Fernando de Alvarado Tezozomoc (Mexican Chronicle),
Titus (Germania), Cicero (Topica), and many others.
The Reception of Morgan by Engels
Several authors, in the field of anthropology, disagree on the point
that Morgan actually developed a materialist theory of history, taking
into consideration that he also saw socio-political progress to be a
signal of God, part of the master plan of the Supreme Intelligence, in
which the barbarian was preceded by the savage and followed by civilization.30 What would have motivated Engels and Marx to embrace
his ideas with such enthusiasm? In order to answer this question,
it may be necessary to remember that Marx published little about
non-European societies in that field, his most important contribution
was his model of Asian production, a type of society with state organization whose village communities held communal land and would
distribute the surplus internally, except for a certain amount reserved
for the state. This model presented theoretical problems for Marxism,
in part because Marx did not consider development to be geographically specific, and in part because it did not clearly signal the direction
that societies of that type could take in terms of development.31
Towards the end of his life, Marx became attracted to new anthropology, having written extensive notes on the works of Morgan
and his predecessors, notes that he never got to use. Engels then used
these notes as the starting point for The Origin of the Family, Private
30
31
Ibid.
Kuper, Invention of Primitive Society, 74.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
185
Property, and the State (1884), hereafter referred to as OFPPS. There is
no way to know if Engels expressed Marx’s enthusiasm in an exaggerated form or in what way Marx related Morgan’s sequence of development to the Asiatic model.32 However, the consensus is that Morgan
became especially relevant within the Marxist tradition. The aspect
of Morgan’s theory that interested Engels the most was his rediscovery of the primitive matriarchal gens as the first stage of the gens in
primitive peoples, which would be as important to anthropology as
Darwin’s theory was to biology and the Marxist theory of value was to
political economy. The evolutionary importance of this discovery was
in showing a history of the development of the family as the product
of historical processes and not as a natural institution.
It is worth noting, preliminarily, the various convergences among
the formulations of Morgan, Marx, and Engels, starting with the importance given to kinship relations within the context of so-called
pre-capitalist societies. Claude Levi-Strauss, in responding to criticisms leveled by Georges Gurvitch regarding his distinction between
stationary, fluctuating, and cumulative history, observed, quite appropriately, that the idea that societies considered primitive were ruled by
links of consanguinity (kinship structures) and not by relationships of
production is frequently expressed in Marx and Engels, who argued
that, if those societies were not destroyed from the outside, they could
perpetuate themselves indefinitely.33
These themes, the French anthropologist reminds us, are constantly taken up in Capital in relation to Indian and Germanic societies,
which were, at that time, more ›primitive‹ than Marx thought. These
themes were generalized by Engels in Anti-Dühring and OFPPS.34 In
order to clarify the parallel between the »Germans of Tacitus« and the
»American Redskins,« Engels said:
32
33
34
Lawrence Krader, The Ethnological Notebooks of Karl Marx (Assen: Van Gorcum,
1974).
Kuper, Invention of Primitive Society, 72 – 73.
Lévi-Strauss, Antropologia Estrutural, 361 – 362.
186
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
The similarity is in fact more striking in that the mode of production
is so fundamentally different — here hunters and fishermen, without
husbandry or agriculture, there the nomadic breeding that passes to
the culture of the fields. This proves precisely how much, at this stage,
the mode of production is less decisive than the degree of composition
of the old ties of consanguinity and the ancient reciprocal community
of the sexes in the tribe. Without that, the Tlingit of the formerly
Russian America35 could be copies of the old Germanic tribesmen.36
In response to Kautsky’s attempt to interpret primitive societies according to historical materialism and through the exclusive use of economic
notions, such as that of barbarism, Engels replied: »It is not barbarism
that proves the primitive character but the degree of integrity of the old
links of consanguinity in the tribe. It is those that must be established
in a particular case before one is able to draw conclusions for particular
tribes from those phenomena.«37 For all these reasons, we can conclude
that Morgan’s attempt to elaborate a new typology of systems of kinship,
in light of the knowledge acquired and the emphasis given to the organization of the gens, attracted the genuine interest of Marx and Engels.
Was the Materialist Conception of History
Rediscovered by Morgan?
In the preface to OFPPS, Engels states, dramatically, that:
…the following pages will be, in a way, the execution of my will.
Marx was willing to present the results of Morgan’s research in rela35
36
37
Russian colonial possessions in America between 1733 and 1867, currently the
U.S State of Alaska and the most distants settlements to Southern California and
Hawaii.
Ibid., 362.
Letter from Engels to Marx, December 8, 1882, cited in Lévi-Strauss, Antropologia Estrutural, 364 – 365.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
187
tion to the conclusions of his (to a certain extent, our) materialistic
analysis of history, to clarify in that way, and only in that way, his
entire scope. In America, Morgan rediscovered, in his own way, the
materialistic conception of history, formulated by Marx forty years
earlier — and, based on it — arrived, contrasting barbarism and civilization, at the same essential results as Marx. I have, however, not only
the detailed excerpts that Marx obtained from Morgan’s work but
also the criticisms that he annotated that I will reproduce whenever
they seem relevant.38
Engels points out that the social order in which men live at a given
time or in a given country is conditioned by two types of production, that is, by the degree of development of labor, on the one
hand, and of the family, on the other; the less developed labor is,
the more restricted the quantity of its products and, consequently,
the wealth of society are; »with all the greater strength is the dominant influence of the bonds of kinship over social regime manifested.«39 Thus, Morgan’s great merit was the discovery and the reestablishment, in its essential traits, of this pre-historic foundation of
our written history, as well as in finding, in the free unions of gens
among North American Indians, the key to deciphering important
enigmas, until then unresolved, about the history of Greece, Rome,
and Germany.40
As is widely known, for the materialist conception, political economy constitutes the fundamental and determinant factor in man’s
historical and social life. In this sense, Marxist materialism is, in fact,
»economic materialism,« which identifies the trace of the union between the evolution of nature41 and the evolution of human society
38
39
40
41
Letter from Engels to Kautsky, February 10, 1883, cited in Maximilien Rubel,
Karl Marx: Essai de biographie intellectuelle (Paris, 1957), 301 – 302.
Friedrich Engels, A Origem da Família, da Propriedade e do Estado (Lisbon: Presença), 7 – 8.
Ibid., 8.
Ibid., 9.
188
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
in the economic process conceived as »material production« through
which men reproduce and continuously develop their means of existence and, therefore, their existence and everything contained in
it. Every other event of historical, social, and practical existence, including spiritual existence, has less influence over the development of
everything.42
Engels’s embracement of the way in which Morgan rediscovered
the materialistic conception of history was not without restrictions.
In the history chapters devoted to Greece and Rome, Engels did not
limit himself to reproducing the documentation of Morgan but also
increased the data at his disposal; the section concerning the Celts
and the Germans was ›essentially‹ his, since Morgan’s documents on
the matter were second-hand; and, finally, he was forced to recreate
the whole economic argument, which underscored that although it
was sufficient for Morgan’s objective, it was not for his.43
In this manner, the initially enthusiastic reception became more
rhetorical, and Engels would later tone down his wording when he
recognized that Morgan was the first who knowingly introduced a
precise order to the pre-history of humanity and did so in light of the
assumption that all of the great eras of human progress coincide, more
or less directly, with the times when sources of subsistence broaden.
The parallel development of the family, however, did not offer criteria
that were as conclusive for delimiting the different periods as those
offered by the arts of subsistence.44
42
43
44
Karl Korsch emphasizes the value that Marx attributed to the complement and
reasoning of his socio-historical materialism for the »natural sciences.« To prove
it, he cites the observation that he made about Darwin’s theory of natural selection in a letter dated December 19, 1869: »Although roughly elaborated, as is the
English custom, this is a work that contains the natural history foundations that
serve our ideas.« Karl Korsch, Marxismo e Filosofia (Porto: Edições Afrontamento, 1966), 160.
Ibid., 158.
Engels, Origem, 10.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
189
Translator … Traitor?
The assumption that the Asiatic mode of production was no more in
1884, in OFPPS, became a problem for specialists in the evolution of
Marxist theory. As the reader may remember, for Marx, the Asiatic
mode of production is, necessarily, the one that remains for the longest, which is implicit in its assumptions; the individual does not become independent from the community, and there is a self-sustaining
circle of production, a unity of agriculture and manufacture. If the
individual changes his relationship with the community, he changes
the community and acts in a destructive manner upon it, and thus
upon its economic assumptions. »In the Oriental model, the loss of
property is almost never possible, except through completely external influences, since the individual member of the community never
enters into a free relationship to lose his economic objective with the
community.«45
The exchange of letters of June 1853 between Marx and Engels is
evidence of the conviction of both that the absence of private property is the »key to the whole Orient.« That is the conclusion of Jean
Chesneaux, who problematized the influence that the publication of
The Primitive Society, which Engels read in 1883, had on him, and he
recalled that Plekhanov had proposed to attribute this influence to the
apparent change in Engels’s attitude. However, instead of supporting
the accusation that Engels had been disloyal to Marx’s opinion on the
Asiatic mode of production, Chesneaux thought that it was more appropriate to determine the reach — decisive, but limited — of OFPPS,
which did not seek to analyze the evolution of all human societies.46
In the prologue to the republished version of the article »A notion of the ›Asiatic mode of production‹ and the Marxist schemes
of the evolution of society,« published originally in 1964, Maurice
Godelier admits having been wrong in concluding that Engels, after
45
46
Ibid., 31.
Karl Marx, Elementos Fundamentales para la Critica de la Economía Política
(Grundisse) (Madrid: Siglo XXI, 1857 – 1858), 446 – 455.
190
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
reading Morgan, had abandoned the concept of the Asiatic mode
of production. A more detailed analysis and the chronology of the
correspondence between Marx and Engels left no doubt in his mind
that neither of them rejected the ideas elaborated from 1853 to 1877
on the existence of ›despotic‹ forms of state, as edified in Asia, Russia,
and other regions.47
He notes that Marx, in 1881, after reading Morgan, affirmed, once
again, the existence of a despotic state in Russia and tried to discover
its foundations, not in the necessity for great works but in the dispersion and isolation of agricultural communities in an immense territory, and in the Mongol domination. On the other hand, in OFPPS,
he left behind the histories of Asia and America because, contrary
to the history of the Greco-Roman West, the former would not develop, according to Engels, more direct forms of transition from old
clannish communities to the typical forms of states and class societies. In this way, OFPPS deepens, in light of Morgan’s formulations,
one of the ways of transitioning to the state that Engels suggested in
Anti-Dühring, that is, the Western way that leads to a generalization
of productive slavery and mercantile production. Godelier claims,
therefore, that there is continuity between Grundisses, Anti-Dühring,
and OFPPS, the theses on the Asiatic mode of production having
remained valid for Engels and continuing to designate a form of transition from societies without classes to societies with classes, »a transition that is incomplete and motivates slowness or stagnation in social
development.«48
The position defended by Godelier seems to me to be the correct
one, which it may be possible to demonstrate by referring directly
to OFPPS. At the end of this book, Engels investigates the general
47
48
Jean Chesneaux, »O Modo de Produção Asiático: Algumas Perspectivas de
Pesquisa,« in O Modo de Produção Asiático, ed. Centro de Estudos e de Pesquisas
Marxistas (C. E. R. M.) (Lisbon: Seara Nova, 1974), 22 – 23.
Maurice Godelier, »A noção de modo de produção asiático e os esquemas marxistas de evolução das sociedades,« in O Modo de Produção Asiático, ed. Centro de
Estudos e de Pesquisas Marxistas (C. E. R. M.) (Lisbon: Seara Nova, 1974), 53.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
economic conditions that undermined, in the so-called later phase
of the barbarian stage, the organization of the gens-based society and
made it disappear. Up until this stage, production had been essentially collective, and consumption also took place under a regime of
direct distribution of goods in the midst of small or large communal collectivities. Production, then, did not overlap with producers. I
suppose that Engels was describing the Asiatic model, in whose mode
of production the division of labor was gradually introduced. It was
in this way that production and common appropriation were undermined, with individual appropriation emerging as the dominant
rule, which opened the path to mercantile production, in short, the
dominant model.49
Final Considerations
For Franz Boas the question related to the origin of universal ideas
was the most difficult problem in anthropology. He rebelled against
the point of view that the same ethnological phenomena always have
the same causes, as well as against the generalization that the similarity of ethnological phenomena found in different regions of the world
is proof that the human mind obeys the same laws in all places. He
urged anthropologists to demand that the causes from which a phenomenon developed be investigated and that comparisons be restricted to those phenomena that could be proven to be effects of those
same causes.50 Boas became a firm opponent of what he designated
as the excesses of evolutionism and emphasized that the evolutionist hypothesis implied the idea that modern civilization represented
the highest cultural development, with the implication that all other
cultural types were considered more primitive. He concluded: »We
retrospectively build an orthogenetic development in the direction
49
50
Ibid., 53 – 55.
Engels, Origem, 209.
191
192
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
of our own modern civilization.« We contrapose, then, against the
general evolutionary scheme, the admission of the existence of diverse
»definitive and coexisting« types of civilization.51
Claude Levi-Strauss understood Boasian anti-evolutionism as a
reaction derived from the fact that he used mainly mechanical models (whose constitutive elements are scaled according to the phenomena studied), for which a notion of evolution does not have a heuristic value.52 In doing so, he identified the weakness of evolutionist
studies, that is, the utilization of mechanical models when statistical models should have been employed. The correct interpretation
of Levi-Strauss eliminated, however, the strong critical position of
Boas in relation to the evolutionary schemes developed throughout
the nineteenth century, in which he identified a strong tendency to
combine the historical aspect with the subjective evaluation of the
various phases of development, the present serving as the standard
of comparison.
The frequently observed change from supposed simple forms to
more complex forms, from uniformity to diversity, was interpreted as
a change from something of less value to something of greater value.
Thus, he accurately concluded that the historical view assumed, in
many cases, a poorly concealed teleological matrix.53 Furthermore, he
observed that the generalizing method of the science of the period,
according to which a real event did not possess scientific value in itself but only to the extent that it led to the discovery of a general law,
collided with a purely historical vision, causing the subordination of
historical facts to the concept of natural law. All the sciences that adopted the historical point of view would soon evolve into attempts to
discover the laws that determined evolution, and anthropology was
not, in that sense, an exception.54 Boas did not shy away, however,
51
52
53
54
Franz Boas, Antropologia Cultural (Rio de Janeiro: Zahar, 2004 [1896]), 29, 31 – 32.
Ibid., 42.
Lévi-Strauss, Antropologia Estrutural, 310.
Franz Boas, A formação da antropologia americana, 1883 – 1911: Antologia (Rio de
Janeiro: Contraponto / Editora UFRJ, 2004), 44.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
from admitting that anthropology owes its existence to the stimulus
provided by those scholars and the conclusions they reached, but, at
the same time, he exhorted us to not overestimate the influence of
their bold generalizations.55
Afterword
Kevin B. Anderson readdressed,56 albeit much later than Lawrence
Krader,57 the notebooks of Karl Marx, also called »annotations of
Marx,« »ethnological notebooks,« and »notebooks of citations,« in
which Marx summarized passages of books that he was studying,
among which was Ancient Society by Lewis Morgan. These notebooks
(to which Engels would not do justice) show him as a subtle and dialectical reader at a moment in which he seemed to be turning towards
»new directions,« towards non-Western societies, which would give
rise to new theoretical dislocations.58
Certain aspects emphasized by Anderson clarify the motivations
behind Marx’s interest in Morgan and, above all, in the relevance of
non-Western, pre-capitalist societies in order to enhance their perception through a comparison of social forms in order to reorient his
thoughts on fundamental themes — such as history and the relationship between complementarity and Western and non-Western social
55
56
57
58
Ibid., 45.
Kevin B. Anderson, Marx at the Margins: On Nationalism, Ethnicity and
Non-Western Societies (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011); Kevin B. Anderson, Marx nas Margens: Nacionalismo, Etnia e Sociedades Não Ocidentais (São
Paulo: Boitempo, 2019).
Lawrence Krader, The Ethnological Notebooks of Karl Marx (Amsterdam: Internationaal Instituut voor Sociale Geschiedenis, 1974).
Societies that had been the object of colonization (India, Indonesia, Algeria,
etc.); societies located outside the developing global capitalist system (Poland,
Russia, China, etc.); and societies that were included in that system (the United
States and Ireland).
193
194
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
formations — for the unleashing of revolutionary developments. This
is the direction of this brief afterword.
Marx’s position in favor of differentiated examinations of European and Asian history, and contrary to the mere transference of
concepts of social structure originating in the European model to
non-Western societies, already suggested that he was in the process of
an inflection that would move him away from the unilinear perspective expressed in the Communist Manifesto (and which would make
him adopt a multilinear perspective).59
For this inflection, the notes of Maxim Kovalevski (a Russian
sociologist and jurist), Lewis Morgan (on the American Indians)
and Robert Sewell (a colonial official in India) may be determinant.
Thanks to the former two, Marx came to admit that Indian society
had a history, and the lines of castes that he saw in 1853 as »unsurmountable barriers that prevented social cohesion in the face of foreign invasion« became, by 1879, something that amazed him due to
their porosity. The supposition of an »invincible march of great historical forces« gave way to the contingent character of conquests, like
those of the Muslim and British conquests in India.60
Marx’s anti-colonialist position also emerges in his late writings
and notes,61 either when taking the side of the colonized by suppressing the excerpts of Sewell portraying the British conquest as a heroic
struggle against Asiatic barbarism, or when reporting the death by
suffocation of 100 British soldiers int the »Black Hole of Calcutta«, or
when he highlighted the transformation of ancient forms of property into unrestricted private property through the voracious forms of
59
60
61
Anderson, Marx nas Margens, 312.
Ibid., 315 – 316.
For Anderson, Marx’s anti-colonialist side became more pronounced in the years
1856 – 1857 through his articles in the New York Tribune. He supported the Chinese resistance against the British during the Second Opium War and the revolt
of the Sepoys in northern India during 1857 – 1859. It was during this period
that some of his new thoughts on India were incorporated into the Grundrisse
(1857 – 1858), as well as his multilinear theory of history. Anderson, Marx nas
Margens, 348.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
195
British capitalism.62 He supported the Polish uprising of 1863, judged
as fundamental for the labor and socialist movements, and he alerted
the First International to the possibility that the denial of political
and social rights to emancipated slaves in the United States would
precipitate a bloodbath in the country.63 He also wrote notes about
the colonial system of repartimiento in Spanish America, where Amerindians were hunted down if the supply of agricultural labor declined.64 He also commented on the system of encomiendas, which
imposed heavy communal taxes that led to the flight and suicide of
many Amerindians.65
Kovalevski’s notes about Algeria were concerned with communal
forms of property in the pre-colonial and colonial periods, whose
strength was prevalent in the Maghreb region. The French National
Assembly of 1873 tried to disassemble the foundations of communal
property, convinced that the breakdown of the connection between
the Arabs and the land would be the only way to prevent an anti-colonial revolt.66
The persistence of these communal structures would lead Marx
to interpret them, preliminarily, as a potential source of resistance to
capital, and, later, as a source of revolution when impelled by an »external subjective factor,« i. e. in association with a self-conscious and
organized working-class movement.67
In his last writing on Russia, Marx would move away from the
»model of implicitly unilinear development« when he admitted the
possibility that non-capitalist societies may transition directly to socialism from autonomous communal structures. However, the condition for this to happen, as Marx and Engels state in the preface to
the 1882 edition of the Manifesto (which was, incidentally, Marx’s last
62
63
64
65
66
67
Ibid., 319.
Ibid., 225.
Ibid.
Ibid., 216.
Ibid., 323 – 324.
Ibid., 341.
196
Maria Rosário de Carvalho
publication), would be through the association of communal structures with social sectors of the developed West.68 Similarly, any new
system could emerge in the context of a wider social transformation
involving the Western working class.69 It would be possible, then, for
non-Westerners to share »the fruits of Western modernity.«
Translated by Gilmar Visoni-Alonzo
Works Cited
Anderson, Kevin B. Marx at the Margins: On Nationalism, Ethnicity and
Non-Western Societies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2011.
Anderson, Kevin B. Marx nas Margens: Nacionalismo, Etnia e Sociedades Não
Ocidentais. São Paulo: Boitempo, 2019.
Boas, Franz. Antropologia Cultural. Rio de Janeiro: Zahar, 2004 [1896].
Boas, Franz. A formação da antropologia americana, 1883 – 1911: Antologia. Organização e introdução de George W. Stocking Jr. Rio de Janeiro: Contraponto / Editora UFRJ, 2004.
Chesneaux, Jean. »O Modo de Produção Asiático: Algumas Perspectivas de
Pesquisa.« In O Modo de Produção Asiático, edited by Centro de Estudos
e de Pesquisas Marxistas (C. E. R. M.). Lisbon: Seara Nova, 1974.
Engels, Friedrich. A Origem da Família, da Propriedade e do Estado. Lisbon:
Presença.
Forde, Daryll. »Doble Filiación entre los Yakö.« In Sistemas Africanos de Parentesco y Matrimonio, edited by Alfred Reginald Radcliffe-Brown and
Daryll Forde. Barcelona: Editorial Anagrama, 1982 [1950].
Godelier, Maurice. »A noção de modo de produção asiático e os esquemas
marxistas de evolução das sociedades.« In O Modo de Produção Asiático,
edited by Centro de Estudos e de Pesquisas Marxistas (C. E. R. M.). Lisbon: Seara Nova, 1974.
Korsch, Karl. Marxismo e Filosofia. Porto: Edições Afrontamento, 1966.
68
69
Ibid., 328.
Ibid., 341 – 342.
Engels and Evolutionist Ethnology
Krader, Lawrence. The Ethnological Notebooks of Karl Marx. Assen: Van Gorcum, 1974.
Krader, Lawrence. The Ethnological Notebooks of Karl Marx. Amsterdam: Internationaal Instituut voor Sociale Geschiedenis, 1974.
Kuper, Adam. The Invention of Primitive Society. London, Routledge, 1988.
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. Antropologia Estrutural. Rio de Janeiro: Tempo Brasileiro, 1970.
Lévi-Strauss, Claude. As Estruturas Elementares do Parentesco. Petrópolis: Paz
e Terra; São Paulo: EDUSP, 1976.
Marx, Karl. Elementos Fundamentales para la Critica de la Economía Política
(Grundisse). Madrid: Siglo XXI, 1857 – 1858.
Morgan, Lewis Henry. Systems of Consanguinity and Affinity of the Human
Family. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Contributions of Knowledge,
1871.
Morgan, Lewis Henry. A Sociedade Primitiva, Vol. I. Lisbon: Presença; São
Paulo: Martins Fontes, 1976.
Morgan, Lewis Henry. A Sociedade Primitiva, Vol. II. Lisbon: Presença; São
Paulo: Martins Fontes, 1978.
Radcliffe-Brown, Alfred Reginald. »O Método Comparativo em Antropologia.« In Radcliffe-Brown: Antropologia, edited by J. C. Melatti. São Paulo:
Ática, 1978.
Radcliffe-Brown, Alfred Reginald. »Introducción.« In Sistemas Africanos de
Parentesco y Casamento, edited by Alfred Reginald Radcliffe-Brown and
Daryll Forde. Barcelona: Editorial Anagrama, 1982.
Rubel, Maximilien. Karl Marx: Essai de biographie intellectuelle. Paris, 1957.
197
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
An Interpretation of the Concept
of the Dialectics of Nature1
Gottfried Schweiger
»Marx and I were pretty well the only people to rescue conscious
dialectics from German idealist philosophy and apply it in the materialist conception of nature and history.«2
It was due to (unfortunate) external circumstances, including in
particular the death of Karl Marx and the need to finish and edit
his work on political economy, that Friedrich Engels never found
the time to flesh out his philosophy of nature and that he was not
able to explicate the mentioned ›rescue‹ of dialectics and its application with regard to the natural world. Engels’s Dialectics of Nature
was only left as a fragment, which complicates its interpretation
and leaves many questions open.3 His other work that deals with
1
2
3
This is a revised version of a German text that was published almost ten years ago.
I did not have time to incorporate recent literature on Engels, in particular Kaan
Kangal’s recent and thoughtful study Friedrich Engels and the Dialectics of Nature
(Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2020).
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, »Anti-Dühring,« in Collected Works, vol. 25
(1987), 11. I will cite Marx and Engels and thereafter provide the volume / page
number. I will also always provide the original German text. »Marx und ich waren wohl ziemlich die einzigen, die aus der deutschen idealistischen Philosophie
die bewußte Dialektik in die materialistische Auffassung der Natur und Geschichte hinübergerettet hatten.« Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Werke, edited
by the Institut für Marxismus-Leninismus beim Zentralkomitee der SED (Berlin
1956-) [= MEW], 20: 10.
The origins and the history of Engels’s Dialectics of Nature are explored in Anneliese Griese, »Engels’s ›Dialektik der Natur‹. Theoretische Konzeption und
philosophiehistorische Auseinandersetzung,« Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 29, no. 6 (1981): 613 – 628; Anneliese Griese and Gerd Pawlzig, »Friedrich
Engels und Charles Darwin,« in Dialektik 5: Darwin und die Evolutionstheorie,
200
Gottfried Schweiger
questions of the natural sciences and nature is Anti-Dühring, a polemic against Eugen Dühring and his »revolution in science.« As
a polemic, this work should not be misread as systematic treatise
and is no substitute for what the Dialectics of Nature should have
been, other than that remarks about a dialectics of nature and the
natural sciences are scattered throughout the work. In this chapter
I will, nonetheless, try to explicate Engels’s concept of a philosophy
of nature, but not without also acknowledging the shortcomings
and missteps in the existing fragments and texts. I will focus on two
questions. First, what is Engels’s concept of a philosophy of nature,
and what should its relation with the natural sciences be? Second,
what is the relation of Engels’s concept of a philosophy of nature to
the one of Hegel, where is Engels different from Hegel, and where
are there certain similarities?
Engels develops his philosophy of nature as a necessary addition
to Marx’s political economy, without which the project of historical
and dialectical materialism would be incomplete. There are no indications that Marx did not think highly of this enterprise or that Engels would be misguided to view the dialectics of nature as complementing the dialectics of history and society. Engels was convinced
that a dialectics of nature could not be done without an engagement
with Hegel’s philosophy, in particular his philosophy of nature. With
Hegel, classical philosophy had come to its end, Marx and Engels
believed, and so had the philosophy of nature. Engels was convinced
that with the advent of the modern natural sciences, the whole project of a philosophy of nature had become obsolete. He wrote: »Toed. Hans Heinz Holz and Hans Jörg Sandkühler (Cologne: Pahl-Rugenstein,
1982), 127 – 153; Anneliese Griese and Gerd Pawlzig, »Naturwissenschaft und Dialektik in der 2. Hälfte des 19. Jahrhunderts,« in Naturdialektik — Naturwissenschaft: Das Erbe der Engelsschen ›Dialektik der Natur‹ und seine aktuelle Bedeutung
für die Wissenschaftsentwicklung, ed. Manfred Buhr and Herbert Hörz (Berlin:
Akademie-Verlag, 1986), 32 – 48; Kurt Bayertz and Wolfgang Krohn, »Engels im
Kontext. Natur- und Wissenschaftsphilosophie im Zeitalter des Szientismus,«
in Dialektik 12: Die Dialektik und die Wissenschaften, ed. Hans Heinz Holz and
Hans Jörg Sandkühler (Cologne: Pahl-Rugenstein, 1986), 66 – 98.
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
201
day, when one needs to comprehend the results of natural scientific
investigation only dialetically, that is, in the sense of their own interconnection, in order to arrive at a ›system of nature‹ sufficient for our
time; when the dialectical character of this interconnection is forcing
itself against their will even into the metaphysically-trained minds
of the natural scientists, today natural philosophy is finally disposed
of. Every attempt at resurrecting it would be not only superfluous
but a step backwards.«4 Despite this programmatic retirement of a
philosophy of nature, the Dialectics of Nature, which Engels himself
planned and laid out in fragments, is a work of a philosophy of nature, but a philosophy of nature of a new type. I will try to explain
this type here.
The Natural Sciences
as the Heirs of the Philosophy of Nature
Engels shares the view that a philosophy of nature should be understood as an enterprise that tries to understand and analyze nature, its
essence and laws, but from a philosophical perspective. While the natural sciences are concerned with questions relating to particular natural objects, the relations between them or particular laws of nature,
a philosophy of nature has a wider aim and aims to uncover deeper
truths (and also truths that are more steadfast than those of the natural sciences). Engels believes, as we can see in the quote above, that
such a philosophy of nature has become obsolete because the natural
4
Marx and Engels, »Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy,« Collected Works, vol. 26 (1987), 386. »Heute, wo man die Resultate
der Naturforschung nur dialektisch, d. h. im Sinn ihres eignen Zusammenhangs
aufzufassen braucht, um zu einem für unsere Zeit genügendem ›System der Natur‹ zu kommen, wo der dialektische Charakter dieses Gesamtzusammenhangs
sich sogar den meta-physisch geschulten Köpfen der Naturforscher gegen ihren
Willen aufzwingt, heute ist die Naturphilosophie endgültig beseitigt. Jeder Versuch ihrer Widerbelebung wäre nicht nur überflüssig, er wäre ein Rückschritt.«
MEW 21: 296.
202
Gottfried Schweiger
sciences can take its place. But Engels includes one condition for that
to happen, namely that the natural sciences become »dialectic.« In one
fragment, he writes the following in this respect: »Only when natural
and historical science has become imbued with dialectics will all the
philosophical rubbish—other than the pure theory of thought—be
superfluous, disappearing in positive science.«5 Engels also believes
that this incorporation of dialectics into the natural sciences is something scientists have to do themselves and which they are forced to do
if they want to continue to make progress. For him, empirical research
alone is not sufficient to understand nature, but they need sufficient
and better theories to explain the empirical knowledge they gather.
Nature itself is dialectical for Engels, and if the natural sciences want
to better understand nature, they will have to become dialectical. He
writes in the Anti-Dühring: »Empirical natural science has accumulated such a tremendous mass of positive material for knowledge that
the necessity of classifying it in each separate field of investigation
systematically and in accordance with its inner inter-connection has
become absolutely imperative. It is becoming equally imperative to
bring the individual spheres of knowledge into the correct connection with one another. In doing so, however, natural science enters
the field of theory and here the methods of empiricism will not work,
here only theoretical thinking can be of assistance.«6 And for Engels,
this »theoretical thinking« is dialectical, because only dialectics can
explain nature and natural processes and developments. He writes:
5
6
Marx and Engels, »Dialectics of Nature,« Collected Works, vol. 25 (1987), 491.
»Erst wenn die Natur- und Geisteswissenschaften die Dialektik in sich aufgenommen, wird all der philosophische Kram — außer der Lehre vom reinen Denken — überflüssig, verschwindet in der positiven Wissenschaft.« MEW 21: 296.
Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 25, 338. »Die empirische Naturforschung
hat eine so ungeheure Masse von positiven Erkenntnisstoff angehäuft, daß die
Notwendigkeit, ihn auf jedem einzelnen Untersuchungsgebiet systematisch und
nach seinem inneren Zusammenhang zu ordnen, schlechthin unabweisbar geworden ist. Ebenso unabweisbar wird es, die einzelnen Erkenntnisgebiete unter
sich in den richtigen Zusammenhang zu bringen. Damit aber begibt sich die
Naturwissenschaft auf das theoretische Gebiet, und hier versagen die Methoden
der Empirie, hier kann nur das theoretische Denken helfen.« MEW 20: 330.
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
203
»But it is precisely dialectics that constitutes the most important form
of thinking for present-day natural science, for it alone offers the analogue for, and thereby the method of explaining, the evolutionary
processes occurring in nature, inter-connections in general, and transitions from one field of investigation to another.«7 Engels acknowledges in this passage, and throughout his writings, a »reflection theory« (»Widerspiegelungstheorie«) of knowledge and truth, which has its
roots in Aristotle and was further explored and canonized in classical
and orthodox Marxism, for example by Lenin. Knowledge, according
to this theory, is constituted by thinking and reflecting on the outside
world. Because nature and thinking are both dialectical, knowledge
is only possible. Thinking represents »subjective dialectics,« and nature, as well as everything else existing outside the mind, represents
»objective dialectics.«8 Based on these epistemological and ontological premises, Engels believes that the natural sciences will themselves
incorporate dialectical thinking as soon as they want to make further
progress. Herbert Hörz called this the »objective force« of dialectics,
which compels the natural sciences to become dialectical.9 Philoso7
8
9
Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 25, 362. »Grade die Dialektik ist aber für
die Naturwissenschaft die wichtigste Denkform, weil sie allein das Analogon
und damit die Erklärungsmethode bietet für die in der Natur vorkommenden
Entwicklungsprozesse, für die Zusammenhänge im ganzen und großen, für die
Übergänge von einem Untersuchungsgebiet zum anderen.« MEW 20: 330 – 331.
»Dialectics, so-called objective dialectics, prevails throughout nature, and socalled subjective dialectics, dialectical thought, is only the reflection of the motion through opposites which asserts itself everywhere in nature, and which by
the continual conflict of the opposites and their final passage into one another,
or into higher forms, determines the life of nature.« Marx and Engels, Collected
Works, vol. 25, 492. »Die Dialektik, die sog. objektive, herrscht in der ganzen
Natur, und die sog. subjektive Dialektik, das dialektische Denken, ist nur Reflex
der in der Natur sich überall geltend machenden Bewegung in Gegensätzen, die
durch ihren fortwährenden Widerstreit und ihr schließliches Aufgehen ineinander, resp. in höhere Formen, eben das Leben der Natur bedingen.« MEW 20: 481.
Herbert Hörz, »Naturdialektik und moderne Naturwissenschaft,« in Naturdialektik — Naturwissenschaft: Das Erbe der Engelsschen ›Dialektik der Natur‹ und
seine aktuelle Bedeutung für die Wissenschaftsentwicklung, ed. Manfred Buhr and
Herbert Hörz (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1986), 11 – 31. See also his magnum
204
Gottfried Schweiger
phy could ›help‹ them and support that development, but in the end,
they are no longer necessary in the field of knowledge about nature,
its history and developments. Thus no separate enterprise of a philosophy of nature is longer needed. Engels believed that the natural
sciences are already implicitly dialectal, but without being aware of
that or openly acknowledging this, and throughout his writings on
nature, he referred to recent discoveries and theories in the natural
sciences that he believed would support his thesis. Still, Engels also
put forward the thesis that the natural sciences were still dominated
by non-dialectical thinking, which he called »metaphysical thinking,«
and which hindered its further progress.
Dialectics would help the natural sciences to overcome this. He
writes in a longer passage: »One can scarcely pick up a theoretical
book on natural science without getting the impression that natural scientists themselves feel how much they are dominated by this
incoherence and confusion, and that the so-called philosophy now
current offers them absolutely no way out. And here there really is no
other way out, no possibility of achieving clarity, than by a return, in
one form or another, from metaphysical to dialectical thinking. This
return can take place in various ways. It can come about spontaneously, by the sheer force of the natural-scientific discoveries themselves,
which refuse any longer to allow themselves to be forced into the old
Procrustean bed of metaphysics. But that is a protracted, laborious
process during which a tremendous amount of unnecessary friction
has to be overcome. To a large extent that process is already going on,
particularly in biology. It could be greatly shortened if the theoreticians in the field of natural science were to acquaint themselves more
closely with dialectical philosophy in its historically existing forms.«10
10
opus: Herbert Hörz, Marxistische Philosophie und Naturwissenschaften (Cologne:
Pahl-Rugenstein, 1974).
Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 25, 340 – 341. »Man kann kaum ein theoretisches naturwissenschaftliches Buch in die Hand nehmen, ohne den Eindruck
zu bekommen, daß die Naturforscher es selbst fühlen, wie sehr sie von dieser
Zerfahrenheit und Verworrenheit beherrscht werden und wie ihnen die jetzt
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
205
Engels mentions biology here because he, as well as Marx, believed
that the discovery of the evolution of species and Darwin’s theoretical
work were the most recent and most impressive examples of dialectics in nature. The evolution of new species and its underlying »laws
of nature« are dialectical, in their view. Based on these premises, a
distinct philosophy of nature is no longer needed or desirable. For
Engels, the scope and aim of a philosophy of nature was always to
study and research nature, its laws and essence. This was no longer
needed, now that the natural sciences were themselves able to do this.
For him, philosophical and scientific knowledge of nature were no
longer separate but one and the same if they incorporated dialectical
thinking. What remains for philosophy, with respect to nature and
the natural sciences, is epistemology, logics and methodology.
To sum up, Engels’s thesis that the whole project of a philosophy
of nature has become superfluous rests upon two distinct premises.
The first premise is ontological and states that nature is dialectical, and
the second is epistemological and methodological, stating that the
natural sciences can and will become dialectical. Engels aims to show
both throughout his writings, and the Dialectics of Nature would
have been a ›long argument‹ for both theses. That is the reason why
the Dialectics of Nature is a work incorporating discussions about the
essence of nature, the relation between philosophy and the natural
sciences, and long treatments of recent discoveries and knowledge of
the natural sciences, which Engels interprets in such a way that they
landläufige sog. Philosophie absolut keinen Ausweg bietet. Und hier gibt es nun
einmal keinen andern Ausweg, keine Möglichkeit, zur Klahrheit zu gelangen, als
die Umkehr, in einer oder anderen Form, vom metaphysischen zum dialektischen Denken. Diese Rückkehr kann auf verschiednen Weg vor sich gehen. Sie
kann sich naturwüchsig durchsetzen, durch die bloße Gewalt der naturwissenschaftlichen Entdeckungen selbst, die sich nicht länger in das alte metaphysische
Prokrustesbett wollen zwängen lassen. Das ist aber ein langwieriger, schwerfälliger Prozeß, bei dem eine Unmasse überflüssiger Reibung zu überwinden ist. Er
ist großenteils schon im Gang, namentlich in der Biologie. Er kann sehr abgekürzt werden, wenn die theoretischen Naturforscher sich mit der dialektischen
Philosophie in ihren geschichtlich vorliegenden Gestalten näher beschäftigen
wollen.« MEW 20: 332.
206
Gottfried Schweiger
support his ontological thesis of the dialectical nature of nature. From
the perspective of a present-day reader, Engels’s insistence that the
natural sciences should become dialectical and his ontological view
that nature itself is dialectical seem quite odd and in contradiction
with modern natural sciences and philosophy. Dialectics is discredited in many ways, and today the standard position towards the natural sciences is that they are not dialectical and that it is not up to
philosophy to criticize them for being non-dialectical. Engels’s view
was different; he saw himself as an eager supporter of modern natural
sciences and tried to free them from philosophy and »metaphysical
thinking,« which he saw at its best in Hegel’s philosophy and his
philosophy of nature. But Engels was not a positivist either. He was
convinced that the natural sciences needed dialectics and that they
could also learn something from classical philosophy, in particular
from Hegel, otherwise they would be unfree and bound to ›bad‹ philosophical assumptions and methods.
Engels’s and Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature
We can now discuss the relation between Engels’s idea of a dialectics
of nature and Hegel’s philosophy of nature in more detail. However,
before we do so, a few words need to be said about Hegel’s philosophy of nature.11 Unfortunately, basically everything we know about
this work is what is said in the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical
Sciences, since Hegel did not write a separate book on the philosophy
of nature. There is not much text available in the Encyclopaedia and
what is there is written in a particular style because the Encyclopaedia
was intended by Hegel to be a ›textbook‹ for his lectures; as such,
11
Much has been written about Hegel’s philosophy of nature and views have
changed over time. While even many Hegelians rejected Hegel’s philosophy of
nature as pure speculation and absurd for a long time, recent work is more favorable. I provide an overiew of the debate in my book: Gottfried Schweiger,
Dialektische Naturphilosophie (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2011).
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
207
the text leaves many details open and room for interpretation. We
know that Hegel provided much more information and detailed arguments in his lectures, and he lectured on the philosophy of nature
several times during his time in Berlin in the 1820s. Some lectures are
now available through the transcripts of students, which makes them
unreliable to some extent.12 Furthermore, a lot of text is also available
through the so-called »Zusätze,« which were compiled by Karl Ludwig Michelet and added to some editions of the Encyclopaedia.13 The
Zusätze are also not entirely reliable and are based on the transcripts
of lectures as well, but Michelet did not provide the sources. Still, every interpretation of Hegel’s philosophy of nature will have to draw
on these sources, simply because the original text in the Encyclopaedia is insufficient and only provides the core of Hegel’s thought. Hegel himself would not have argued that his text in the Encyclopaedia
should count as a fully fleshed out philosophy of nature.
For Hegel, it is evident that the natural sciences cannot substitute
the philosophy of nature precisely because they are not dialectical in
his view. In the Zusatz to §246 of the Encyclopaedia, he writes about
physics, which stand for him for all natural sciences: »Now the inadequacy of the thought-determinations used in physics can be traced
to two points which are closely bound up with each other. (α) The
universal of physics is abstract or only formal; its determination is not
immanent in it and it does not pass over into particularity. (β) The
determinate content falls for that very reason outside the universal;
and so is split into fragments, into parts which are isolated and detached from each other, devoid of any necessary connection, and it is
12
13
For example, Georg W. F. Hegel, Naturphilosophie, Bd. I: Die Vorlesung von
1819 / 20, ed. Manfred Gies with Karl-Heinz Ilting (Naples: Bibliopolis, 1982);
Georg W. F. Hegel, Vorlesung über Naturphilosophie, Berlin 1823 / 24, ed. Gilles
Marmasse, postscript by K. G. J. von Griesheim (Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang,
2000).
Georg W. F. Hegel, Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, Part Two (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1970).
208
Gottfried Schweiger
just this which stamps it as only finite.«14 Only philosophy can ›think‹
nature as it is, that is to say, dialectical. That is what Hegel tried in his
philosophy of nature, and that is why most of the text is invested in
doing something quite similar to Engels: Hegel interpreted findings
and theories of the natural sciences with the aim to show that nature
is indeed dialectical. But Hegel was not a dialectical materialist but
an idealist, and thus his relation with the natural sciences is complicated. At several points in his philosophy of nature, he assumes that
his philosophical enterprise needs the natural sciences to access the
dialectics in nature15, while at some other points he seems to suggest
that a philosophy of nature could be done entirely without reference
to the natural sciences and that one could ›deduce‹ most if not all
that is philosophically important about nature from thinking alone,
without the need for any empirical research.16 It is unclear how far
14
15
16
Hegel, Encyclopaedia, §246, Zusatz. »Das Ungenügende nun der physikalischen
Denkweise läßt sich auf zwei Punkte zurückführen, die aufs engste zusammenhängen. a) Das Allgemeine der Physik ist abstrakt oder nur formell; es hat seine
Bestimmungen nicht an ihm selbst oder geht nicht zur Besonderheit über. b) Der
bestimmte Inhalt ist eben deswegen außer dem Allgemeinen, damit zersplittert,
zerstückelt, vereinzelt, abgesondert, ohne den notwendigen Zusammenhang in
ihm selbst.« Hegel, Werke (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1970).
For example: »The Philosophy of Nature takes up the material which physics
has prepared for it empirically, at the point to which physics has brought it, and
reconstitutes it, so that experience is not its final warrant and base. Physics must
therefore work into the hands of philosophy, in order that the latter may translate into the Notion the abstract universal transmitted to it, by showing how this
universal, as an intrinsically necessary whole, proceeds from the Notion.« Hegel,
Encyclopaedia, §246, Zusatz. »Die Naturphilosophie nimmt den Stoff, den die
Physik ihr aus der Erfahrung bereitet, an dem Punkte auf, bis wohin ihn die
Physik gebracht hat, und bildet ihn wieder um, ohne die Erfahrung als letzte
Bewährung zugrunde zu legen; die Physik muss so der Philosophie in die Hände
arbeiten, damit diese das ihr überlieferte verständige Allgemeine in den Begriff
übersetze, indem sie zeigt, wie es als ein in sich selbst notwendiges Ganzes aus
dem Begriff hervorgeht.«
»The relation of philosophy to the empirical sciences was discussed in the general introduction [to the Encyclopaedia]. Not only must philosophy be in agreement with our empirical knowledge of Nature, but the origin and formation of
the Philosophy of Nature presupposes and is conditioned by empirical physics.
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
209
›thinking‹ alone can provide knowledge about nature, its laws and objects, but Hegel believes that at its core nature is dialectical, which for
him means that nature is developmental but not historical. Maybe it
is because Hegel lived before Darwin, but history for him is reserved
for human history and development in nature only happens within
a particular organism; there is no evolution. So while Engels strongly believed that evolution is proof of the dialectics of nature, Hegel
confines the dialectics of nature to a dialectics of the Notion or Idea.
Hegel writes: »A thinking consideration must reject such nebulous, at
bottom, sensuous ideas, as in particular the so-called origination, for
example, of plants and animals from water, and then the origination
of the more highly developed animal organisms from the lower, and
so on.«17 Hegel can make this separation between Notion and Idea
17
However, the course of a science’s origin and the preliminaries of its construction
are one thing, while the science itself is another. In the latter, the former can no
longer appear as the foundation of the science; here, the foundation must be
the necessity of the Notion. It has already been mentioned that, in the progress
of philosophical knowledge, we must not only give an account of the object as
determined by its Notion, but we must also name the empirical appearance corresponding to it, and we must show that the appearance does, in fact, correspond
to its Notion. However, this is not an appeal to experience in regard to the necessity of the content.« Hegel, Encyclopaedia, §246, Zusatz. »Nicht nur muß die
Philosophie mit der Naturerfahrung übereinstimmend sein, sondern Entstehung
und Bildung der philosophischen Wissenschaft hat die empirische Physik zu ihrer Voraussetzung und Bedingung. Ein anderes aber ist der Gang des Entstehens
und die Vorarbeiten einer Wissenschaft, ein anderes die Wissenschaft selbst; in
dieser können jene nicht mehr als Grundlage erscheinen, welche hier vielmehr
die Notwendigkeit des Begriffs sein soll. — Es ist schon erinnert worden, daß,
außerdem daß der Gegenstand nach seiner Begriffsbestimmung in dem philosophischen Gange anzugeben ist, noch weiter die empirische Erscheinung, welche
derselben entspricht, namhaft zu machen und von ihr aufzuzeigen ist, daß sie
jener in der Tat entspricht. Es ist dies jedoch in Beziehung auf die Notwendigkeit
des Inhaltes kein Berufen auf die Erfahrung.«
Hegel, Encyclopaedia, §249, Zusatz. »Solcher nebuloser, im Grunde sinnlicher
Vorstellungen, wie insbesondere das sogenannte Hervorgehen z. B. der Pflanzen
und Tiere aus dem Wasser und dann das Hervorgehen der entwickelteren Tierorganisationen aus den niedrigeren usw. ist, muß sich die denkende Betrachtung
entschlagen.« He further explains: »It is a completely empty thought to represent
species as developing successively, one after the other, in time. Chronological
210
Gottfried Schweiger
and the appearance (Erscheinung) of nature because for him, nature
is the other of the idea but is still bound to it and interwoven with it.
He writes in paragraph §246 of the Encyclopaedia: »Nature has presented itself as the Idea in the form of otherness. Since therefore the
Idea is the negative of itself, or is external to itself, Nature is not merely
external in relation to this Idea (and to its subjective existence Spirit);
the truth is rather that externality constitutes the specific character in
which Nature, as Nature, exists.«18 What Hegel really means by this
characterization of nature and how he understands the relation of
the Notion and the Idea to nature is far from easy to grasp, which is
also because several seemingly conflicting remarks are available in the
Zusätze and in transcripts of his lectures, and I will leave that question
open here. What is important is to understand that, for Hegel, philosophy can understand the Notion or Idea that is present in nature (in
the form of its Otherness), and that is what it should do. Philosophy
is able to ›deduce‹ what is in nature a priori.19 Hegel writes: »None the
18
19
difference has no interest whatever for thought.« Hegel, Encyclopaedia, §249,
Zusatz. »Es ist völlig leer, die Gattungen vorzustellen als sich nach und nach in
der Zeit evolvierend; der Zeitunterschied hat ganz und gar kein Interesse den
Gedanken.«
Hegel, Encyclopaedia, §246. »Die Natur hat sich als die Idee in der Form des Andersseins ergeben. Da die Idee so als das Negative ihrer selbst oder sich äußerlich
ist, so ist die Natur nicht äußerlich nur relativ gegen diese Idee (und gegen die
subjektive Existenz derselben, den Geist), sondern die Äußerlichkeit macht die
Bestimmung aus, in welcher sie Natur ist.«
That is one prominent interpretation of Hegel’s method, defended, for example,
by Wolfgang Neuser and Vittorio Hösle. Neuser writes: »According to Hegel,
natural philosophy then proves to be philosophy in that it can specify Notions
a priori. […] The content of the specification of Notions can only be proved in
the philosophical a priori deduction.« (»Nach Hegel erweist sich Naturphilosophie dann darin als Philosophie, daß sie Begriffsbestimmungen apriori angeben
kann. […] Der Inhalt der Begriffsbestimmungen kann nur in der philosophischen a priori-Deduktion erwiesen werden.«) Wolfgang Neuser, »Die Naturphilosophie,« in Hegels »Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften« (1830):
Ein Kommentar zum Grundriß, ed. Hermann Drüe et al. (Frankfurt am Main:
Surhkamp, 2000), 141 – 142. Hösle even argues that such an a priori deduction
of natural objects, relations and laws can produce knowledge that has not yet
been discovered or proved by the natural sciences. In such a case, philosophy of
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
less, Reason must have confidence in itself, confidence that in Nature
the Notion speaks to the Notion and that the veritable form of the
Notion which lies concealed beneath Nature’s scattered and infinitely
many shapes, will reveal itself to Reason.«20 Engels, on the other hand,
rejects such idealist metaphysics; for him, a philosophy of nature does
not reflect on any kind of Notion or Idea that exists in nature (and
forms it) because there is no such thing — for Engels, nature stands
alone and for itself.
Despite the ontological differences between Hegel and Engels,
and also despite the fact that Engels views Hegel’s philosophy of
nature as obsolete and wrong in its intentions, both works show a
lot of similarities in that both philosophers invest much work into
interpreting the findings and theories of the natural sciences and
both claim that, through this work of interpretation, they can show
that nature is dialectical. They do that with different goals in mind,
no less. As I showed earlier, Hegel is convinced that the natural
20
nature can show that such objects, relations or laws must necessarily exist, even
though the natural sciences are not yet aware of them. Hösle writes: »[S]o there
may be the case that the a priori working philosopher, in fact, correctly works out
conceptual structures, but that these do not correspond to any empirical conception of his time, because simply the sciences have not yet discovered the reality
corresponding to the conceptual structure at the time.« (»[S]o kann es den Fall
geben, daß der apriorisch verfahrende Realphilosoph zwar korrekt begriffliche
Strukturen herausarbeitet, daß diese aber keiner empirischen Vorstellung seiner
Zeit entsprechen, weil einfach die Wissenschaften zu seiner Zeit noch nicht die
der begrifflichen Struktur korrespondierende Wirklichkeit entdeckt haben.«)
Hegel, Encyclopaedia, §376, Zusatz. »Aber dessen ungeachtet muß die Vernunft
das Zutrauen zu sich selbst haben, daß in der Natur der Begriff zum Begriffe
spricht, und die wahrhafte Gestalt des Begriffes, die unter dem Außeinander
der unendlich vielen Gestalten verborgen liegt, sich ihr zeigen wird.« Right at
the beginning of the philosophy of nature, Hegel makes it clear what he aims to
achieve: »As the Philosophy of Nature is a comprehending [begreifende] treatment,
it has as its object the same universal, but explicitly, and it considers this universal
in its own immanent necessity in accordance with the self-determination of the
Notion.« Hegel, Encyclopaedia, §246. »Indem die Naturphilosophie begreifende
Betrachtung ist, hat sie dasselbe Allgemeine, aber für sich zum Gegenstand und
betrachtet es in seiner eigenen, immanenten Notwendigkeit nach der Selbstbestimmung des Begriffs.«
211
212
Gottfried Schweiger
sciences will always be deficient and not be able to fully grasp the
Nation or Idea in nature, while Engels is convinced that the natural
sciences will make any philosophy of nature and thus also his own
work superfluous as soon as they become themselves dialectical enterprises. But although Engels rejects Hegel’s idea of a philosophy
of nature as some kind of better natural science, the dialectics that
he aims to prove is present in nature and can be acquired by the
natural sciences is something he takes from Hegel. Engels writes
in this respect: »It is, therefore, from the history of nature and human society that the laws of dialectics are abstracted. For they are
nothing but the most general laws of these two stages of historical development, as well as of thought itself. And indeed they can
be reduced in the main to three: The law of the transformation of
quantity into quality and vice versa; The law of the interpenetration
of opposites; The law of the negation of the negation. All three are
developed by Hegel in his idealist fashion as mere laws of thought:
the first, in the first part of his Logic, in the Doctrine of Being; the
second fills the whole of the second and by far the most important
part of his Logic, the Doctrine of Essence; finally the third figures as
the fundamental law for the construction of the whole system. The
mistake lies in the fact that these laws are foisted on nature and
history as laws of thought, and not deduced from them. This is
the source of the whole forced and often outrageous treatment; the
universe, willy-nilly, has to conform to a system of thought which
itself is only the product of a definite stage of development of human thought. If we turn the thing round, then everything becomes
simple, and the dialectical laws that look so extremely mysterious in
idealist philosophy at once become simple and clear as noonday.«21
21
Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 25, 356. »Es ist also die Geschichte der
Natur wie der menschlichen Gesellschaft, aus der die Gesetze der Dialektik abstrahiert werden. Sie sind eben nichts andres als die allgemeinsten Gesetze dieser
beiden Phasen der geschichtlichen Entwicklung sowie des Denkens selbst. Und
zwar reduzieren sie sich der Hauptsache nach auf drei:
•
das Gesetz des Umschlagens von Quantität in Qualität und umgekehrt;
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
In this passage, Engels makes several important claims that help us
to better understand his dialectics of nature. The first claim is that
the laws of dialectics can be found in nature itself and that Hegel
was wrong to assume that they are only laws of thought. The second
claim is that the relation of nature and thought or nature and Notion is turned around, and that Engels claims that nature is foundational. Thirdly, he rejects Hegel’s methodology in his philosophy
of nature, which claims that it can ›think‹ nature without reference
to the natural sciences. It is the other way around for Engels. The
natural sciences provide proof for the truth of dialectics and that it
really exists in nature, while Hegel thought of the natural sciences
as unable to provide any such definitive proof. Fourthly, despite his
critique of Hegel and his dismissal of his methodology and idealist
philosophy, Engels was convinced that Hegel said a lot of truths
about nature and the dialectics within it. He even defended Hegel against objections that assumed that his dialectics was nothing
more than speculation or even plain wrong.22
22
•
das Gesetz von der Durchdringung der Gegensätze;
•
das Gesetz von der Negation der Negation.
Alle drei sind von Hegel in seiner idealistischen Weise als bloße Denkgesetze entwickelt: das erste im ersten Teil der »Logik,« in der Lehre vom Sein; das zweite
füllt den ganzen zweiten und weitaus bedeutendsten Teil seiner »Logik« aus, die
Lehre vom Wesen; das dritte endlich figuriert als Grundgesetz für den Aufbau
des ganzen Systems. Der Fehler liegt darin, daß diese Gesetze als Denkgesetze der
Natur und Geschichte aufoktroyiert, nicht aus ihnen abgeleitet werden. Daraus
entsteht dann die ganze gezwungene und oft haarsträubende Konstruktion: Die
Welt, sie mag wollen oder nicht, soll sich nach einem Gedankensystem einrichten, das selbst wieder nur das Produkt einer bestimmten Entwicklungsstufe des
menschlichen Denkens ist. Kehren wir die Sache um, so wird alles einfach und
die in der idealistischen Philosophie äußerst geheimnisvoll aussehenden dialektischen Gesetze werden sofort einfach und sonnenklar.« MEW 20: 348.
»It must however be recalled that the natural scientists‹ polemic against Hegel,
in so far as they at all correctly understood him, was directed solely against these
two points: viz., the idealist point of departure and the arbitrary, fact-defying
construction of the system.« Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 25, 343. »Es
ist aber daran zu erinnern, daß die naturwissenschaftliche Polemik gegen Hegel,
soweit sie ihn überhaupt richtig verstanden, sich nur gegen diese beiden Punkte
213
214
Gottfried Schweiger
Hans Heinz Holz: From Engels to Hegel
and the Plan of the Dialectics of Nature
Hans Heinz Holz provides us with one of the most sophisticated interpretations of both Hegel’s and Engels’s work. I want to discuss a
few of his insights in his work and also where, in my view, he errs in
his interpretation of the programmatic of the Dialectics of Nature. In
this discussion, I also want to explore a few more of the basic tenets
of Engels’s concept. Holz aims to show that the Dialectics of Nature is
a necessarily ontological project. He distinguishes between a philosophy of nature as the project of an interpretation of the findings of the
natural sciences and a philosophy of nature that takes the place of an
ontology. Ontology, for Holz, is a necessary part of the Marxist philosophical program and the dialectics of nature takes its place.23 Holz
specifies these two levels or domains of a dialectics of nature: »This
means that a dialectics of nature unfolds on two levels: On the one
hand, in that general and fundamental domain of an ontology of nature and of the regions and layers of natural being, i. e. an ontology of
the forms of movement of matter and of natural history; on the other
hand, in those areas of the specification of nature that are opened up
by the individual natural sciences and in which statements about the
particular form of dialectical processes and structures result depending directly on the respective state of the development of science and
are consequently also quite clearly provisional and outdatable.«24 In
gerichtet hat: den idealistischen Ausgangspunkt und die den Tatsachen gegenüber willkürliche Konstruktion des Systems.« MEW 20: 334.
23 »In this sense, the dialectics of nature is a theory of the world’s constitution of
being [Seinsverfassung der Welt] and thus takes the place of metaphysics in the
system of forms of knowledge and its ideological function.« Hans Heinz Holz,
Weltentwurf und Reflexion Versuch einer Grundlegung der Dialektik (Stuttgart: J. B.
Metzler, 2005), 540. »In diesem Sinne ist die Naturdialektik eine Theorie von der
Seinsverfassung der Welt und übernimmt damit die Stelle der Metaphysik im
System der Wissensformen und deren weltanschauliche Funktion.«
24 Holz, Weltentwurf und Reflexion, 556 – 557. »Das bedeutet, daß eine Dialektik der
Natur sich auf zwei Ebenen entfaltet: Einmal in jenem allgemeinen und fundamentalen Bereich einer Ontologie der Natur und der Regionen und Schichten
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
his view, Engels’s Dialectics of Nature aimed to combine these two distinct tasks, but most of the text that he was able to finish falls under
the second category and is, therefore, largely outdated today. A similar
objection could be raised towards Hegel’s philosophy of nature but
with the difference that Engels was well aware of this, while Hegel’s
program of an idealistic philosophy of nature aimed to uncover undisputable and everlasting truths also in the second area, which Holz
calls »the specification of nature,« which are, for Holz, only available
through the natural sciences and which are fallible.
Holz believes, in contrast to Engels, as I think, that the first task
of a dialectics of nature, the development of a dialectical ontology, is not bound to the natural sciences and thus not dependent on
the current state of their development or particular findings. Rather,
as he aims to show, the basic ontological premises of dialectics and
that the natural world is dialectical can be proven independently of
the natural sciences. That brings Holz’s concept of a philosophy of
nature closer to Hegel’s. Holz bases his interpretation that Engels
makes such a sharp distinction with regard to the ontological side of
the Dialectics of Nature on a few remarks of Engels. For example, Engels writes that, according to his »Outline of the General Plan« of the
Dialectics of Nature, it contains »dialectics as the science of universal
interconnection« (»Dialektik als Wissenschaft vom Gesamzusammenhang«).25 For Holz, this »science of universal interconnection« can
only be the product of philosophical »speculation,« hence ontology,
not the product of an interpretation of the findings of the natural
sciences. The »universal interconnection,« which in other places is
translated as »totality« and which somehow better grasps its meaning,
25
des natürlichen Seins, also eine Ontologie der Bewegungsformen der Materie
und der Naturgeschichte; zum anderen in jenen Bereichen der Spezifikation der
Natur, die durch die einzelnen Naturwissenschaften erschlossen werden und in
denen Aussagen über die bestimmte Form dialektischer Prozesse und Strukturen unmittelbar abhängig vom jeweiligen Stand der Wissenschaftsentwicklung
auftreten und folglich auch ganz unmittelbar vorläufig und überholbar sind.«
Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 25, 313; MEW 20: 307.
215
216
Gottfried Schweiger
is for Holz not an empirical object26 in contrast to everything else
that exists in nature, which are objects, and the relations between
them. Thus the method of this variation of a dialectics of nature
as ontology is not an interpretation of the findings of the natural
sciences but a philosophical reflection on the very grounds of reality. Holz writes in this regard: »Rather, the dialectic of nature — as a
philosophical theory of nature […] is to be derived from the theory
of the reflection of the objective reality through consciousness.«27
And he continues: »[T]he dialectic of nature [is] to be derived from
the dialectic of thought, without having to fall into a subjective-idealistic constitutional theory.«28 This is, obviously, a reference to the
Kantian approach, which states that ontology and epistemology are
inseparable. Holz believes that a materialist dialectics of nature can
be constructed starting from the epistemological premises of a theory
of reflection, and he assumes that Engels’s work can be interpreted in
such a way to support this approach.
This interpretation of Engels is misguided for two reasons in particular. And it is a step back to Hegel, and his idea of a philosophy of
nature, that Engels would not support. Firstly, Engels is quite clear
that his method is not one of speculation and he does not deduce
or construct the dialectics of nature starting from an ontological
or epistemological idea. He uses very different notions to describe
26
27
28
Holz is very close to Hegel in this interpretation when he writes: »That the totality [Gesamtzusammenhang] is always only thought, that is, given as an idea or
in the form of a metaphysical model, does not mean that it exists only as an idea
(idealiter); the idea is rather the reflection of the reality of the world as totum.«
Holz, Weltentwurf und Reflexion, 541, n. 3. »Daß der Gesamtzusammenhang immer nur gedacht, das heißt als Idee oder in der Form eines metaphysischen Modells gegeben ist, besagt nicht, daß er nur als Idee (idealiter) existiere; die Idee ist
vielmehr die Widerspiegelung der Realität der Welt als totum.«
Holz, Weltentwurf und Reflexion, 560. »Vielmehr ist die Naturdialektik — als philosophische Theorie der Natur […] herzuleiten aus der Theorie von der Widerspiegelung des objektiven Seins durch das Bewußtsein.«
Holz, Weltentwurf und Reflexion, 561. »[D]ie Dialektik der Natur [ist] im Rückschluß aus der Dialektik des Denkens zu gewinnen, ohne dabei in eine subjektiv-idealistische Konstitutionstheorie verfallen zu müssen.«
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
his methods. He claims that the dialectics of nature, the dialectical
laws, etc., are to be »found« (»auffinden«) in the natural sciences and
their findings, that they can be »derived« (»ableiten«) or »abstracted« (»abstrahieren«) from them. He is very clear that this is not a
very philosophical enterprise at all, far from the speculative methods
of Holz or Hegel, for that matter. I believe that Kurt Bayertz and
Wolfgang Krohn, among others, interpret this correctly when they
write: »This is the goal of the dialectics of nature, which according
to Engels’s self-understanding, however, must not be a restitution of
a philosophy of nature separated from the specialized sciences, but
must reconstruct the envisaged comprehensive conception of nature
[Gesamtbild der Natur] from the results of the specialized sciences
themselves.«29 In the German Democratic Republic, and throughout
orthodox Marxism, this was the mainstream interpretation of Engels
and his Dialectics of Nature. Herbert Hörz, who was the main figure
in the canonization of this interpretation, established the notion or
concept of »generalization« (»Verallgemeinerung«) to describe Engels’s
method. And because the Dialectics of Nature is the result of such a
generalization of the findings and theories of the natural sciences, a
distinct philosophy of nature, at least in the sense of Hegel or Holz, is
obsolete and bourgeois.30
Secondly, Engels not only rejects the method Holz proposes but
also his idea that we need something like such an ontology or »science
of totality.« Rather, Engels assumes that what the natural sciences can
29
30
Bayertz and Krohn, »Engels im Kontext,« 82. »Dies ist das Ziel der Dialektik der
Natur, die dem Engelsschen Selbstverständnis nach jedoch keine Restitution einer von den Fachwissenschaften getrennten Naturphilosophie sein darf, sondern
das angestrebte Gesamtbild der Natur aus den Resultaten der Fachwissenschaft
selbst zu rekonstruieren hat.«
»Marxist philosophy does not need to be supplemented by a philosophy of nature inasmuch as it is itself also the generalization of the results of the natural
sciences.« Herbert Hörz and Karl-Friedrich Wessel, eds., Philosophie und Naturwissenschaften (Berlin: Deutscher Verlag der Wissenschaften, 1986), 17. »Die
marxistische Philosophie bedarf insofern keiner Ergänzung durch eine Naturphilosophie, als sie selbst die Verallgemeinerung auch der Ergebnisse der Naturwissenschaften ist.«
217
218
Gottfried Schweiger
tell us about nature and the dialectics within it are sufficient: »As soon
as each special science is bound to make clear its position in the great
totality of things and of our knowledge of things, a special science
dealing with this totality [Wissenschaft vom Gesamtzusammenhang]
is superfluous. That which still survives independently of all earlier
philosophy is the science of thought and its laws—formal logic and
dialectics. Everything else is subsumed in the positive science of nature and history.«31
Conclusions
What Engels wanted to do in the Dialectics of Nature was threefold. He wanted to show that there actually is a dialectics of nature,
which means that he wanted to show that the laws of dialectics are
actually operating in nature. That dialectics is not just an idea and
that it is not just present in human history but in everything that
exists. One major insight for him in this respect was that nature is
historical, that nature is ever-changing and developing. While Hegel only knows a dialectics of Notion and denies the historicity of
nature, Engels was a staunch supporter of the idea of evolution. For
him, evolution was a dialectical process, and the natural sciences
themselves would become aware of that sooner rather than later. For
Engels, there was no longer a sharp break between natural and human history; instead, they are interwoven and the latter evolved out
of the former. He writes: »The whole of nature also is now merged
in history, and history is only differentiated from natural history
31
Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 25, 26. »Sobald an jede einzelne Wissenschaft die Forderung herantritt, über ihre Stellung im Gesamtzusammenhang
der Dinge und der Kenntnis von den Dingen sich klarzuwerden, ist jede besondre Wissenschaft vom Gesamtzusammenhang überflüssig. Was von der ganzen
bisherigen Philosophie dann noch selbständig bestehen bleibt, ist die Lehre vom
Denken und seinen Gesetzen — die formelle Logik und die Dialektik. Alles andre geht auf in die positive Wissenschaft von Natur und Geschichte.« MEW 19:
207.
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
219
as the evolutionary process of self-conscious organisms.«32 Secondly,
Engels aimed to show that a separate philosophy of nature, which
aims to uncover universal truths about nature and which is somehow superior to the natural sciences, had become obsolete. Rather,
what is necessary is to study and interpret the findings of the natural sciences, and the dialectics of nature thus becomes evident and
stands for itself. For sure, Engels does not say much about how such
an interpretation should be made, and his own work is not of much
help either in this respect. Engels does not clearly say, for example,
what should be done if some findings or theories of the natural
sciences point in a different direction or outright deny dialectics.
Should philosophy then criticize the natural sciences or try to prove
them wrong? Engels himself does not shy away from such criticism
and accuses the natural sciences from time to time in his work of
being infiltrated by »bad« metaphysics and that they are themselves
not able to understand that they are dialectical, even if they do not
see or want that. He does that, though, with the intention to support them to become better natural sciences and to set them free
from such bad metaphysics. Thirdly, and closely related to the previous point, Engels proposes a new relation between philosophy and
the natural sciences, which can, at least in some points, be described
as positivistic. He not only acknowledges that the natural sciences
are the best available sources for knowledge about nature, but he
also believes that philosophy depends entirely on them if it wants
to say something meaningful about nature and natural processes.
And because the natural sciences are themselves developing and the
process of knowledge generation is never finished, so is the project
of a dialectics of nature open-ended.
32
Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 25, 516. »Jetzt auch die ganze Natur in
Geschichte aufgelöst, und die Geschichte nur als Entwicklungsprozeß selbstbewußter Organismen von der Geschichte der Natur unterschieden.« MEW 20:
504.
220
Gottfried Schweiger
Engels’s project of a dialectics is unfinished. It was largely ignored
outside of orthodox Marxism and sharply criticized,33 even by most
Marxists in what were the Western countries during the Cold War.
Natural scientists also largely ignored Engels’s writings, and they
showed basically no interest in doing what Engels hoped they would
do: prove that nature is dialectical.34 That is unfortunate, because the
basic premises of Engels’s concept are worth re-reading and studying.
Even if he is wrong, he provides the modern reader with an interesting discussion of the aims and scope of a philosophy of nature, its
methods, and its relation with the natural sciences.35 The latter point
is crucial for all of the modern philosophy of nature, which still is
positioned somewhere between Hegel or Holz and Engels, in that it
is either envisaged as an enterprise separate from the natural sciences
or an enterprise closely bound to and dependent on them. Even if
there is nothing like a dialectics of nature and nature does not follow
the laws of dialectics, the question remains as to whether there is anything particularly philosophical to say about nature or to discover in
the findings and theories of the natural sciences.
33
34
35
Helena Sheehan, Marxism and the Philosophy of Science: A Critical History (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1993).
Two exceptions in the Western countries were John B. S. Haldane, The Marxist
Philosophy and the Sciences (New York: Random House, 1939) and Richard Levins
and Richard C. Lewontin, The Dialectical Biologist (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1985).
Bonifaz Kedrow interpreted the Dialectics of Nature as a dialectics of the natural
sciences. He argues that Engels was concerned with showing that the natural
sciences are dialectical in themselves and that they stand in dialectical relations
with each other. The dialectics of the natural sciences reflects the dialectics of
nature, for example, like the transition from dead matter to living organisms is
dialectical, as is the relation between chemistry and biology. Bonifaz M. Kedrow,
Friedrich Engels über die Dialektik der Naturwissenschaft (Colognne: Pahl Rugenstein, 1979); Bonifaz M. Kedrow, Klassifizierung der Wissenschaften, vol. 1 (Cologne: Pahl-Rugenstein, 1975).
Friedrich Engels’s Philosophy of Nature
Works Cited
Bayertz, Kurt and Wolfgang Krohn. »Engels im Kontext. Natur- und Wissenschaftsphilosophie im Zeitalter des Szientismus.« In Dialektik 12: Die
Dialektik und die Wissenschaften, edited by Hans Heinz Holz and Hans
Jörg Sandkühler, 66 – 98. Cologne: Pahl Rugenstein, 1986.
Griese, Anneliese and Gerd Pawlzig. »Friedrich Engels und Charles Darwin.«
In Dialektik 5: Darwin und die Evolutionstheorie, edited by Hans Heinz
Holz and Hans Jörg Sandkühler, 127 – 153. Cologne: Pahl-Rugenstein,
1982.
— and Gerd Pawlzig. »Naturwissenschaft und Dialektik in der 2. Hälfte des
19. Jahrhunderts.« In Naturdialektik — Naturwissenschaft. Das Erbe der
Engelsschen »Dialektik der Natur« und seine aktuelle Bedeutung für die
Wissenschaftsentwicklung, eds. Manfred Buhr and Herbert Hörz, 32 – 48.
Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1986.
Griese, Anneliese. »Engels’s »Dialektik der Natur«. Theoretische Konzeption
und philosophiehisto rische Auseinandersetzung.« Deutsche Zeitschrift
für Philosophie 29, no. 6 (1981): 613 – 628.
Haldane, John B. S. The Marxist Philosophy and the Sciences. New York: Random House, 1939.
Hegel, Georg W. F. Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences, Part Two. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970.
—. Naturphilosophie, Bd. I: Die Vorlesung von 1819 / 20. Edited by Manfred
Gies with Karl-Heinz Ilting. Naples: Bibliopolis, 1982.
—. Vorlesung über Naturphilosophie, Berlin 1823 / 24. Edited by Gilles Marmasse, postscript by K. G. J. von Griesheim. Frankfurt am Main: Peter
Lang, 2000.
—. Werke. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1970.
Holz, Hans Heinz. Weltentwurf und Reflexion Versuch einer Grundlegung der
Dialektik. Stuttgart: J. B. Metzler, 2005.
Hörz, Herbert. Marxistische Philosophie und Naturwissenschaften. Cologne:
Pahl-Rugenstein, 1974.
—. »Naturdialektik und moderne Naturwissenschaft.« In Naturdialektik — Naturwissenschaft. Das Erbe der Engelsschen »Dialektik der Natur«
und seine aktuelle Bedeutung für die Wissenschaftsentwicklung, edited by
Manfred Buhr and Herbert Hörz, 11 – 31. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1986.
221
222
Gottfried Schweiger
— and Karl-Friedrich Wessel, eds. Philosophie und Naturwissenschaften. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 1986.
Kangal, Kaan. Friedrich Engels and the Dialectics of Nature. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillian, 2020.
Kedrow, Bonifaz M. Friedrich Engels über die Dialektik der Naturwissenschaft.
Cologne: Pahl-Rugenstein, 1979.
—. Klassifizierung der Wissenschaften, Vol. 1. Colgogne: Pahl-Rugenstein, 1975.
Levins, Richard and Richard C. Lewontin. The Dialectical Biologist. Cambridge, MA, 1985.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. »Anti-Dühring.« In Collected Works, Vol. 25.
1987.
—. Werke. Edited by the Institut für Marxismus-Leninismus beim Zentralkomitee der SED. Berlin, 1956-.
—. »Dialectics of Nature.« In Collected Works, vol. 25, 1987.
—. »Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy.« In
Collected Works, vol. 26. 1987.
Neuser, Wolfgang. »Die Naturphilosophie.« In Hegels »Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften« (1830). Ein Kommentar zum Grundriß, edited
by Hermann Drüe et al. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 2000.
Schweiger, Gottfried. Dialektische Naturphilosophie. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang, 2011.
Sheehan, Helena. Marxism and the Philosophy of Science: A Critical History.
Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1993.
The Relationship
between Art and Politics
On the Letter of Friedrich Engels
to Margaret Harkness1
Henrique Wellen
An Allegory on Art and Politics
There is a famous fable about the relationship between art and politics. In the story (presented here with some alterations), a king, vain
and materialistic in equal measure, vindictive and with revolutionary
pretensions, made a call upon all artists to paint a portrait of him
with the intention of selecting the one that portrayed him in the
most realistic manner. The winner, as was the practice in that imaginary era, would also obtain a noble title. However, a specific corporal
trait of the subject of the painting introduced an unusual element to
the contest and made it a difficult and dangerous proposition. The
king had a physical malformation on his entire left side that was
impossible to leave out of the portrait. This existential question that
could determine the fate of the artists led to artistic alternatives and
subterfuges that produced paintings of astounding complexity. How
could it be possible to portray the king faithfully without offending
him, given his vain sensibilities? If, on the one hand, the painting
should reflect the closest representation of reality, the painter should
also be careful not to present his subject in a light where he might
suffer social humiliation as a result of his physical shortcomings being exposed.
1
This contribution is the translation of »Relação entre arte e política: sobre a carta
de Friedrich Engels a Margaret Harkness,« Revista Espaço Acadêmico 17, no. 199
(2017): 11 – 21 and the editor would like to thank the author and the publisher of
the original work for granting permission to publish it in the present volume.
224
Henrique Wellen
The first contestant, after much reflection on the nuances and implications of this paradox, resolved to depart from the second premise,
since that one, being less explicit than the first, could save him from
greater aggravations and would reduce the severity of his punishment.
He thus opted to avoid a faithful portrait of the monarch, especially
the representation of his physical defect, so by avoiding the physical
problems of the king, he ended up creating a work of art that, in his
view, would be superior to reality itself. When he finished his work,
one could observe that the portrait looked superior to the real-life
subject. In order to achieve that artistic effect, the painter used a risky
subterfuge: the subject seemed to be in great physical shape, without
a single defect.
The king appeared painted from the front with very bright colors
and with accented shadings, portrayed with a strength that would
make Hercules envious and a sagacity that would fool Ulysses himself.
As expected, the first impression that the painting created in the king
was one of satisfaction and plain happiness. When he saw himself
represented in that way, without any defects and showing corporal
strength, his face showed a mixture of pride and sadness, and, according to some witnesses, a few tears could be seen rolling down his
face. There was a long pause in which the king, immersed in thoughts
about the past, the present and the future, imagined himself in the
physical condition depicted by the painting. How many humiliations
could have been avoided! How many compliments he would have
received! The painting evoked a myriad of sensations and feelings in
the consciousness of the monarch, but, at the same time, it suggested
the possibility of an alternative life that he was able to erase from his
mind only with great effort.
Even though immersing himself in his thoughts gave him an intense sensation of joy, the return to reality, the return from that cathartic subjectivity, had a drastic impact in the most intimate corners
of his being. When confronted with hard reality, he realized that it
had had an even greater effect than his imagination. In reality, that
painting was like a Siren’s song, analogous to the temptations experi-
The Relationship between Art and Politics
225
enced by Ulysses,2 barely useful to outwit the people with regard to
the reality that he needed to confront. And so, exhibiting an amalgam
of rancor and materialistic axioms, the king made a pronouncement
on the painting and the fate of its creator.
That painting — said the king — is clearly surrounded by idealistic
elements and, for that reason, it represents a counter-revolutionary
person. And since the painting cannot express a concrete reality, it
serves as an instrument for human and social alienation. It therefore
represents an attempt to counter revolutionary forces, an opiate of
the people, because it induces them to fall asleep in the face of reality.
And so there is no alternative but to punish the artist with the death
penalty. And this is how the king dealt with the first painter and the
first painting.
The second candidate felt a lot of paradoxical sensations; he felt
relief because it was not his life that had been condemned to end but,
on the other hand, the possibility of death was still very real for him.
And here there is an important lesson about the rejection of art with
idealist and subjectivist content, art intended as an escape from reality.
He would not make the same mistake, and he would make an effort
to portray the object with as much fidelity as possible. No arbitrary
additions would be made. The work would simply reflect what is
explicit and natural.
Based on these premises, the second candidate made a great effort
to take away the processes and contradictions that could affect the
corporal or mental expression of the king. In his painting, the king
would be portrayed as a simple object, as a simple thing. If this had
happened in a different period, one could say that the second artist
2
In The Odyssey, through the use of a synthesis of oral history and myths, Homer
narrated the adventures of Ulysses in his attempt to return home after the Trojan
War. In his journey, one of the main challenges that the hero faced was his encounter with the Sirens who tried to seduce the sailors with their song. Ulysses
ordered that all members of his crew cover their ears with wax, but he would be
tied to the mast of the ship so that he could listen to the Sirens and survive. See
Homer, A Odisseia (São Paulo: Editora 34, 2011).
226
Henrique Wellen
would, in a Positivist manner, »consider everything as simple things.«3
In order not to repeat the mistake of his predecessor, he would produce an elemental copy of that which would express immediacy and
the physical appearance of the king. In that way, with the king having
an explicit physical deficiency, there would be no way to hide his
shortcomings through idealist subterfuges. The second artist gathered
his artistic abilities to produce a purely scientific reflection that would
adhere to the rules of nature, just like the laws of gravity.
And so he presented the king frontally, showing not only his human nature but also representing his immutable human condition.
The naturalist content was rooted in the desire to immortalize that
situation as the only possible one for the king, and for that reason, he
should be worshiped like a statue not only in the present but forever.
The details of the second painting were so surgical that one could observe so many defects of reality itself on the body of the king and on
his clothes, as well as in the surroundings of the portrait, that at first
glance they were hard to identify. The painting showed several defects,
but, as stated by the author of the work, they were not creations of the
mind of the artist but only exact copies from that which served as the
model for the painting.
When faced with this new and unexpected painting, the impact
felt by the king was the opposite of the one caused by the first work.
If the first idealist painter brought him feelings of happiness and satisfaction, the second painting inspired feelings of sadness and rejection.
The king was stunned; at that moment, he was simultaneously subject
and object, looking at the most minute corporal defects. Seeing himself portrayed in such a manner, he not only felt diminished but also
experienced an unfamiliar sense of impotence. If in the first painting
he could be compared to great heroes who had been able to alter the
fate that the gods had imposed upon humanity, in the second paint3
According to Durkheim, at the beginning of the second chapter of The Rules of
the Sociological Method, »The first and most fundamental rule is to consider social
facts as things.« Émile Durkheim, As Regras do Método Sociológico (São Paulo:
Martins Fontes, 2007), 15.
The Relationship between Art and Politics
227
ing he seemed like a man who could hardly cope with the most insignificant challenges of life. At that moment, the king, master over the
destinies of countless people, felt powerless against the world. And so
the feeling that invaded him at that moment was one of resignation,
of the knowledge that nothing could be done to change the human
condition. This was accompanied by a sense of paralysis, just as with
the first painting, but for opposite reasons. When the king saw himself idealized in the first painting, he felt as if he had escaped reality
(seduced by the song of the Sirens); faced with the second image, he
felt that his body was devoid of force, like a statue made of stone, as
if he was experiencing the effects of having seen Medusa.4 Hoping to
chase away the naturalism presented in the painting, the king spoke
loudly and with even more vigor than previously. This painting, he
said, is even more alienating than the first one since it lacks a sense
of history and a sense of social dynamic; one needed to be extremely
strong not to succumb to the sense of resignation irradiated by this
work. And so, with a proud defense of his alleged historical heroic
traits, the king condemned the artist to the same fate as the first one.
Given the fates of the two artists, there was great fear when a new
candidate emerged. If the two artists had been executed after being
accused of the opposite of what they had wanted to portray, the main
concern with regard to the contest was not the benefit that one could
obtain but their own survival. At this moment, after everything that
had occurred, the new candidate stepped forward.
If the first painter (contrary to his intention of glorifying the
king) was executed on charges of idealism, and the second candidate
(who intended to portray the king in a more descriptive manner)
4
In Greek mythology, Medusa was a monster of the underworld (a Gorgon) that
had the body of a woman and serpents on her head instead of hair. As related
in the adventures of Perseus, Medusa had the power of turning anyone who saw
her into stone. References to Gorgons precede the feats of the demi-god Perseus.
They were present in Aeschylus‹ Prometheus Chained as monsters who inhabited the plains of Quistene. See Aeschylus, »Prometeu accorentado,« in Prometeu
acorrentado — Édipo Rei — Medéia by Aeschylus, Sophocles and Euripides (São
Paulo: Abril cultural, 1980), 39.
228
Henrique Wellen
received the capital penalty under charges of naturalism, why would
anyone want to enter this contest? The new candidate had probably lost his senses, and that is why he drove towards his death so
willingly. And even though this situation scared all those present,
the king’s pronouncement was an even greater surprise. After announcing that he was already devoid of the hope of finding a painting that would reflect his wishes and, therefore, was close to ending
the whole process, he remarked upon how surprised he was to find
a work that could bring him such artistic and political satisfaction.
Not satisfied with this compliment, the king continued to extol the
third artist’s virtues and his ability to depict the king in such a precise aesthetic manner, without a hint of idealism or naturalism. The
artist was thus deserving of all the titles and prizes promised to him.
Furthermore, he would become a magistrate of the kingdom for life.
For having demonstrated such competence in the aesthetic field, the
painter should, according to a royal decree, assume the master chair
in the field of arts and culture of the State. The general surprise from
all those present (with the exception of the painter and his subject)
was understandable. And everyone was curious as to the content of
the portrait. What colors were used? What kinds of strokes were
used? Was there a contrast of light and shadow? The use of curved
lines or any other techniques typical of illusionist painting?5 There
was only one way to find out, but the intimidation derived from all
that had happened had drained all the courage necessary to placate
the collective curiosity. There was such joy and such relief when the
king, extremely pleased with his portrait, invited everyone present to
contemplate the masterpiece. And thus, everyone was able to appreciate the virtues presented in the painting and confirm that it was
deserving of praise.
5
One of the most common expressions of Brazilian reality in the so-called ›illusionist paintings‹ is found in Baroque art. These paintings create figures that
enhance the spiritual and religious elements to the detriment of rational and
Renaissance traits. To that end, artists used several resources, such as the juxtaposition of colors, light and shadow, drapes, and curved lines.
The Relationship between Art and Politics
229
Friedrich Engels and the Triumph of Realism in Literature
In the spring of 1888, Friedrich Engels, the famous German communist, sent a letter to Margaret Harkness in which he communicated
some of his thoughts about one of the writer’s works entitled City
Girl. Harkness (who used the pseudonym John Law) was an English
writer who, as a result of contacts with socialist thinkers like Eleanor Marx (Karl Marx’s daughter), had made incursions into political
thought and was resolved to use her literary talents in the advancement of the socialist cause.
The content of the letter did not demonstrate any analytical pretensions about aesthetics but, nevertheless, it stands as a landmark of
great importance for the Marxist analysis of the relationship between
art and politics.6 The letter centers on the relationship between art
and politics and, especially, on the specificity of each of their qualities
and the elements that the writer utilizes to avoid equalizing art and
politics. The letter addresses in an essentialist and introductory manner the parameters that must be used to carry out a realistic analysis
of literature and the relationship between those determinations and
the political consciousness of the author.
With this argument in mind, and after congratulating Harkness
for her artistic talent and courage to write such a work, Engels proceeded to analyze the quality of the book,7 defining what should be
at the center of a work of art, namely its realistic character. Realism
in art »implies, beside truth of detail, the truthful reproduction of
typical characters under typical circumstances.«8 In this manner, next
6
7
8
Several authors within the Marxist tradition point to the premise of the triumph
of realism as the foundation of aesthetic analysis and cite Engels’s letter as the
fundamental reference. Among the analyses that deal with this topic are the
works of György Lukács. For a didactic synthesis of the relationship between
Lukács‹ analysis and Engels’s position, see Ranieri Carli, A estética de György
Lukács e o triunfo do realismo na literature (Rio de Janeiro: EDUFRJ, 2012).
Engels uses the term »ein kleines Kunstwerk« to describe Harkness‹ novel.
Friedrich Engels, »Engels to Margaret Harkness,« in Marx & Engels Collected
Works, Vol. 48: Letters 1887 – 90 (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 2010), 167.
230
Henrique Wellen
to narrative faithfulness and the delineation of characters and events,
there must be a »typicality« to the work.
For Engels, that is the central problem of the analyzed work, since
the imbalance of that relationship marks an insufficiency on the part
of the writer. On the one hand, the characters are »typical enough,«
but on the other, »the circumstances which surround them and make
them act are not perhaps equally so.«9 Engels cites the way in which
the working-class characters in City Girl are lacking with regard to historical development. The tuning fork between art and the portrayed
reality was out of tune since Harkness‹ narrative presents a working
class that played a passive role and needed external help (something
that was valid for conditions in England at the beginning of the 19th
century). Such conditions were very different from what English
workers were experiencing during the last quarter of the 19th century
when they had become organized into labor unions and political parties. At that point, they had become an active political force.10
One of the elements of the character of typicality noted by Engels
can be found in the precise figurative expression of the reflected moment of reality. Art cannot do without that realistic relationship with
a specific reality. Such a condition would not necessarily be derived
from the submission of art to history, as if the former had to portray
the most perfunctory details of the latter.11 What Engels pointed out
9
10
11
Ibid.
An important framework in this development was the so-called »Spring of the
Peoples,« a series of insurrections that spread throughout Europe in 1848. This
represented the gradual strengthening of the working class in the political struggle against capitalist exploitation. Providing historical, political, and documentary evidence of this movement, we have the Communist Manifesto, composed and
published by Marx and Engels during this historical moment. See Karl Marx and
Friedrich Engels, Manifesto do Partido Comunista (São Paulo: Cortez, 1998).
There is no consensus for this premise either among the many art critics or
among the Marxist aesthetes, as we can see in the critiques of Perry Anderson
on the events and character of the war between France and Russia narrated in
Tolstoy’s War and Peace. See Perry Anderson, »Trajetos de uma forma literária,«
Revista Novos Estudos 77 (March 2007): 205 – 220; Leo Tolstoy, Guerra e Paz (São
Paulo: Cosac Naify, 2011).
The Relationship between Art and Politics
was the indispensable relationship between those two forms of representation (art and history) in order to prevent art from becoming a
form of escape from reality, as well as an arbitrary crystallization of its
appearance. However, one could question whether the German communist wanted to present this admonition as an attempt to defend or
to aggrandize the political struggle of the workers for the construction of socialism. The answer to this conflict appears in the following
comments, in which instead of pleading for the artistic writing of
socialist content, he praises a very different condition: »I am far from
finding fault with your not having written a socialist novel,« or, as the
Germans called it, a Tendenz-roman (an engaged novel), in order to
»glorify the social and political ideas of the author.«12 That is to say,
instead of criticizing Harkness for not writing a novel engaged in proletarian causes, the impenitent defender of the working class praises
the English writer precisely for the fact that she did not introduce
her own political and ideological preferences into the narrative of the
novel. And just to make things even clearer, Engels adds: »The more
the opinions of the author remain hidden, the better for the work of
art.«13
As a way of exemplifying what he defends as realism in art (and, in
this case, the possibility and necessity of creating a great work of art
independent of the political proclivities of the author), Engels weaves
comparisons among literary works produced by artists with very different ideologies. Whereas Émile Zola was a writer known not only
for his literary work but also for his socialist political engagement,
Honoré de Balzac was an author whose political perspective could
be qualified as not only conservative but also sympathetic towards
reactionary (and aristocratic) positions. Faced with both authors, one
would expect that Engels, the defender of the working class, would be
more sympathetic towards Zola’s work.14 However, as he admonished,
12
13
14
Engels, »Engels to Margaret Harkness,« 167.
Ibid.
It is important to note that Émile Zola is the author of one of the artistic pieces
of great importance in denouncing the exploitation of the workers by the capital-
231
232
Henrique Wellen
such a relationship should not be transposed to artistic specificity. In
other words, what would serve in the effort to develop political militancy would not necessarily be useful in terms of aesthetic appreciation. It is precisely in this spirit that Engels issues his judgment on the
author who is the real French master of world literature:
Balzac was politically a Legitimist; his great work is a constant elegy
on the irretrievable decay of good society; his sympathies are all with
the class doomed to extinction. But for all that his satire is never
keener, his irony never bitterer, than when he sets in motion the very
men and women with whom he sympathises most deeply—the nobles. And the only men of whom he always speaks with undisguised
admiration, are his bitterest political antagonists, the republican heroes of the Cloîtred Saint-Méry, the men, who at that time (1830 – 36)
were indeed the representatives of the popular masses. That Balzac
thus was compelled to go against his own class sympathies and political prejudices, that he saw the necessity of the downfall of his favourite nobles, and described them as people deserving no better fate; and
that he saw the real men of the future where, for the time being, they
alone were to be found—that I consider one of the greatest triumphs
of Realism, and one of the grandest features in old Balzac.15
In the case of that illustrious French author, the triumph of realism
was expressed in the fact that his political and social beliefs did not
impose limits on the typical representation of characters and events.
The issue, made explicit in the quote above, is to defend the autonomy
of art before politics in the sense that the specific quality of the former
cannot be substantiated by the latter. That is to say, art has its own
specificity and, even if political determinations are not absent, those
elements only have expressive validity as part of the whole context.
15
ists. In Germinal, Zola exposes the ordeals experienced by coal miners oppressed
under the thumb of capitalism. See Émile Zola, Germinal (São Paulo: Estação
Liberdade, 2012).
Engels, »Engels to Margaret Harkness,« 168.
The Relationship between Art and Politics
233
When dealing with aesthetic objects, it is the specificity of art that
must absorb political elements in its particularity and not the other
way around.
Engels did not claim that realist artist is endowed with ideological
neutrality or that he is devoid of political values or ideas, but rather
that the measure of art cannot be subsumed by its political interests.
Realist art does have, however, a lot of values that can, depending on
the audience, produce reflective effects with political content. However, it is not these effects that measure the greatness of the work of art
that produced them. Due to the need to represent reality departing
from its essence, realism endorsed by defenders of communism presupposes a necessary reflection of the historical dynamic, its processes,
and its immanent contradictions.
This why the search for the artistic representation of typicality in
both characters and events is prohibited by the escape from reality as
well as by the naturalization of reality. This is because neither artistic
idealism (very present in avant-garde and subjectivist conceptions)
nor artistic naturalism (which in the case analyzed by Engels is exemplified by Zola) can express the complexity of the historical dynamic
in its essential movements of continuity and rupture.
In both of the analyzed cases of aesthetic figurations, history appears, to a greater or lesser degree, fractured in its processes, either by
the fantastic propelling of the character towards his social possibilities
or by the imagery taken from the character’s immanent capacity for
historical intervention. The relationships between individual and society, between subjectivity and objectivity, and between teleology and
causality are such that, when one pole is hypertrophied at the expense
of the other, the artistic reflection will not capture the typical essence
of the characters and events in the mediation between the singular
and the universal.
In both cases, a painting about reality will represent a curtailment
imposed on the character, either by his awareness of the concrete possibilities that surround him or by his interventionist practice against
greater obstacles. Fundamentally, what will happen in these cases are
234
Henrique Wellen
watertight paintings about history that do not represent the complexity of reality portrayed artistically but rather express, in a direct or
indirect manner, the values, thoughts, and wishes of the artist himself.
Translated by Gilmar Visoni-Alonzo
Works Cited
Aeschylus. »Prometeu accorentado.« In Aeschylus, Sophocles and Euripides, Prometeu acorrentado — Édipo Rei — Medéia. São Paulo: Abril cultural,
1980.
Anderson, Perry. »Trajetos de uma forma literária.« Revista Novos Estudos 77
(2007): 205 – 220
Carli, Ranieri. A estética de György Lukács e o triunfo do realismo na literature.
Rio de Janeiro: EDUFRJ, 2012.
Durkheim, Émile. As Regras do Método Sociológico. São Paulo: Martins Fontes,
2007.
Engels, Friedrich »Engels to Margaret Harkness.« In Marx & Engels Collected
Works, Vol. 48: Letters 1887 – 90. London: Lawrence & Wishart, 2010.
Homer. A Odisseia. São Paulo: Editora 34, 2011.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. Manifesto do Partido Comunista. São Paulo:
Cortez, 1998.
Tolstoy, Leo. Guerra e Paz. São Paulo: Cosac Naify, 2011.
Zola, Émile. Germinal. São Paulo: Estação Liberdade, 2012.
Friedrich Engels
From the ›Woman Question‹
to Social Reproduction Theory
Vincent Streichhahn
The so-called ›woman question‹ appeared in the context of the bourgeois revolution of 1848 as a political field of conflict in Germany. It
is a broad bundle of topics that were negotiated in the 19th century in
the political, social and literary fields. »It represented a space of political argument in which the nature, implications and origins of sexual
difference might be debated, and was regarded as intensely significant
for both its symbolic and its practical import.«1 The situation of single and married women, women’s work, sexuality, as well as political
rights for the female sex were among the issues discussed. On the one
hand, this discourse opened up a space in which women could think
about themselves differently, while on the other hand, actors of all
political persuasions were forced to react to the ›woman question‹ in
order to become or remain hegemonic in this political field.2
The ›woman question,‹ in this case the right to women’s gainful
employment or suffrage, was more than controversial in the organizations of the young German labor movement. The General German
Workers‹ Association (Allgemeiner Deutscher Arbeiterverein) under
the leadership of Ferdinand Lassalle (1825 – 1864) openly advocated
a ban on women’s work, because female workers were considered
competition in the job market. The Social Democratic Workers‹
1
2
Lucy Delap, »The ›Woman Question‹ and the Origins of Feminism,« in The
Cambridge History of Nineteenth Century Political Thought, ed. Gareth Stedman
Jones and Gregory Claeys (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 319.
On the defensive reaction against female emancipation efforts in the German
Empire see Ute Planert, Antifeminismus im Kaiserreich: Diskurs, soziale Formation
und politische Mentalität (Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1998).
236
Vincent Streichhahn
Party (Sozialdemokratische Arbeiterpartei), founded by August Bebel
(1840 – 1913) and Wilhelm Liebknecht (1826 – 1900) in 1869, also presented an extremely antagonistic picture. Although the first voices
raised in their ranks called for the political and economic equality of
the sexes, they did not prevail. The unification party conference of
the Socialist Workers‹ Party of Germany (Sozialistische Arbeiterpartei
Deutschlands) in Gotha in 1875 did not change much about this.3
It took the commitment of Bebel, who in 1879 wrote what is probably the most popular book of the German labor movement,4 namely
Woman and Socialism (Die Frau und der Sozialismus),5 to reverse the
trend. Five years later followed the famous publication by Friedrich
Engels (1820 – 1895) entitled The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State (Der Ursprung der Familie, des Privateigentums und
des Staats).6 After the repeal of the Socialist Laws (1878 – 1890), the
›woman question‹ was at least programmatically taken into account
by the German Social Democratic Party, allowing the activities of the
proletarian women’s movement to develop increasingly within their
structures in the following years.7
3
4
5
6
7
Manfred Scharinger, Proletarische Frauenbewegung. Kritische Bilanz und politische
Lehren (Vienna: Arbeitsgruppe Marxismus, 2009), 28 – 51.
In 1898, the Berliner Illustrierte asked its readers about the most influential book
of the last century. Bebel’s Woman and Socialism hardly after the Conversational
Encyclopaedia, the Bible and On the Origin of Species by Darwin already ranked
fourth (Willy Brandt, »Hundert Jahre nach August Bebel. Ein Bestseller dient
der Gleichberechtigung,« in Frauen heute. Eine Bestandsaufnahme, ed. Willy
Brandt (Reinbek: Rowohlt, 1981), 14.
August Bebel, »Die Frau und der Sozialismus,« in Ausgewählte Reden und
Schriften, vol. 10, ed. Internationales Institut für Sozialgeschichte Amsterdam
(Munich: K. G. Sauer, 1996 [1879]).
Friedrich Engels, »Der Ursprung der Familie, des Privateigentums und des
Staats,« in Marx-Engels-Werke (henceforth MEW), vol. 21 (Berlin: Dietz, 1962),
25 – 173.
Richard Evans, Sozialdemokratie und Frauenemanzipation im deutschen Kaisserreich (Bonn: Dietz Verlag 1979); Elisabeth Haarmann, Schwestern zur Sonne zur
Gleichheit: Die Anfänge der proletarischen Frauenbewegung (Hamburg: ErgebnisseVerlag 1985); Florence Hervé, ed., Geschichte der deutschen Frauenbewegung (Cologne: Pahl-Rugenstein 1982); Heinz Niggemann, Emanzipation zwischen Sozi-
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
237
The present chapter pays special attention to a contextualizing
appreciation of Engels’s theoretical contribution to the ›woman
question.‹ In addition, The Origin of the Family will be confronted
with some selected feminist critiques. Finally, the social reproduction theory (SRT) will be discussed, which in a certain sense is in
a line of tradition with Engels, but also overcomes his theoretical
gaps and deficits in important points. The article focuses on two
theses: 1) on the one hand, Engels’s work, alongside Bebel’s book,
was of great practical importance for overcoming »proletarian anti-feminism«8 as a multidimensional obstacle to organization in the
German working class; and 2) on the other hand, Engels left behind
with The Origin of the Family and the dualism postulated therein a
momentous revision of Marx’s theory that brings fatal theoretical
problems.
Engels and The Origin of the Family
as a Tacit Course Correction
Three possible readings of Engels’s book9 should be mentioned: The
Origin of the Family 1) as the central writing of the Marxist theory of
women’s emancipation, which is probably the most common reading;
2) as a construction process that should give historical materialism a
8
9
alismus und Feminismus: Die sozialdemokratische Frauenbewegung im Kaiserreich
(Wuppertal: Hammer, 1981); Sabine Richebächer, Uns fehlt nur eine Kleinigkeit:
Deutsche proletarische Frauenbewegung (Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch-Verlag 1982).
Werner Thönnessen, Frauenemanzipation: Politik und Literatur der Deutschen
Sozialdemokratie zur Frauenbewegung (1863 – 1933) (Frankfurt am Main: Europäische Verlangsanstalt, 1969).
On the history of the immediate development of the book see Editha Nagel,
»Zur Geschichte der unmittelbaren Entstehung von Friedrich Engels’s Schrift
›Der Ursprung der Familie, des Privateigentums und des Staates‹ und ihre Herausgabe in Deutschland (1884 – 1894),« Beiträge zur Marx-Engels-Forschung 3
(1978): 125 – 141.
238
Vincent Streichhahn
unified form10; and 3) as a tacit course correction against Bebel’s publication, which in its first editions was still predominantly marked by
political liberalism.
In general, The Origin of the Family is presented in the research
literature as one of the early central writings of the Marxist theory of
women’s emancipation. This is factually correct, but it masks the actual intention of the author. That does not mean, of course, that Engels
has nothing to say about the oppression of women, but because his
intention was different, he deals only with certain aspects of this oppression. Overall, he says very little about the situation of women under capitalism.11 Only in the last pages of his book does he reach the
phase of civilization, in which capitalism, in turn, has only a short life.
The comments on this issue are therefore rather scattered throughout
the book. This is no coincidence, but rather the expression of a focus
of interest. In other words, it was its reception by female socialists that
began a few years after publication that made it a classic on this issue.
Because of the proletarian anti-feminism in the labor movement, they
literally absorbed the remarks of Engels and Bebel.
Right at the beginning, it must be mentioned that the controversy
surrounding Engels’s book often gives the impression that the main
subject is the family and everything else is an accessory. This is an unacceptable reduction. The title alone indicates that the family is merely part of a triad that still includes the state and private property. In
10
11
»No (male) commentator on Marxism has taken The Origin of the Family as
methodologically central to Marxism and to understanding Marx« (Terrell Carver, »Marxism and Feminism: Living with Your ›Ex‹,« in Karl Marx and Contemporary Philosophy, ed. Andrew Chitty and Martin McIvor (New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2009), 258).
Working in his father’s company in the textile industry, in which women played
an important role, Engels was well aware of the situation of women under capitalism. In one of his early writings, Engels described the extremely precarious
situation of female workers under capitalism very vividly (Friedrich Engels, »Die
Lage der arbeitenden Klasse in England,« in MEW, vol. 2 (Berlin: Dietz 1972
[1845]), 225 – 506). The widespread absence of such descriptions in The Origin of
the Family shows once again that it was not Engels’s task to systematically explain
the oppression of women under capitalism in this book.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
239
contrast, Engels accomplishes with his work, as he modestly informs
the reader in the preface, the completion of a »legacy.« We can characterize this claim as a kind of ›metapolitics‹ that no longer depends on
climbing into the arduous valley of critique in the melee,12 but rather
aims to cast historical materialism into a coherent form that will shape
posterity. What Engels wanted to show was the concrete application
of historical materialism throughout human history. The family undoubtedly plays an important role in this, but the state and private
property certainly do to no less a degree as well. It was by no means
Engels’s intention to develop a systematic explanation of women’s oppression. With his approach, Engels (perhaps involuntarily) made a
disastrous revision of Marx’s theory, which will be discussed below.
Nevertheless, it must be emphasized that it was an important merit of
Engels to point out the historicity of the family (the state and private
property) and thus deprive it of its supposed immutability.13
The reasons for Engels’s decision to write the book are unfortunately in some ways still mysterious today. The creation process can
only be partially reconstructed through the correspondence of Engels
and some contemporaries. On February 16, 1884, in a letter to Karl
Kautsky (1854 – 1938), Engels reported Marx’s enthusiasm for Lewis
Henry Morgan’s (1818 – 1881) book14: »If I had the time, I would edit
the material with Marx’s notes […], but that is not to be thought of.«15
12
13
14
15
Matthias Bohlender, »Marx, Engels und der ›wahre Sozialismus‹ oder: Die Geburt des ›historischen Materialismus‹ aus dem Handgemenge‹,« in ›Kritik im
Handgemenge‹. Die Marx’sche Gesellschaftskritik als politischer Einsatz, ed. Matthias Bohlender et al. (Bielefeld: Transcript, 2018), 15 – 49.
»However, an adequate political challenge to the status quo requires more than
an awareness that existing social relations are not natural; it is also essential to
point to the tendencies immanent to the system which point beyond it. This aspect of Engels’s analysis in Origin is less successful.« Paul Blackledge, »Frederick
Engels, Social Reproduction, and the Problem of a Unitary Theory of Women’s
Oppression,« Social Theory and Practice 44, no. 3 (2018): 311.
Lewis H. Morgan, Ancient Society (Tucson: University of Arizona Press, 1995
[1877]).
Friedrich Engels, »Engels an Karl Kautsky, 16. Februar 1884,« in MEW, vol. 36
(Berlin: Dietz, 1979), 110.
240
Vincent Streichhahn
From late February to early March, Eduard Bernstein (1850 – 1932) visited Engels in London and reported: »Now, when I came over, he read
to me from these manuscripts and the draft of a book based on Marx’s
excerpts from the American Lewis Morgan’s Ancient Society, evening
after evening until deep into the night.«16 At the same time, the unfinished Capital volumes were waiting for completion. We must assume
that the book project became increasingly important for Engels, and
he almost fell into a kind of frenzy. In a letter to Friedrich Adolph
Sorge (1828 – 1906) dated March 7, he says that Morgan »naturally
rediscovered« Marx’s theory of history and concluded with »communist conclusions for today.«17 And on May 10, he tells Paul Lafargue
(1842 – 1911) that he hopes to finish the manuscript, »a very important
work,«18 by the end of next week.
An additional reading, that of the tacit course correction, should
be suggested here. This means that Engels recognized the significance
of the ›woman question‹ as a political field of conflict, but neither
Bebel’s nor Kautsky’s comments satisfied him. In other words, Engels’s The Origin of the Family is a political intervention written in
order to maintain its own theoretical supremacy in the labor movement. Bebel’s book in particular lacked a well-founded historical-materialistic foundation and Engels wanted to demonstrate his authority
in interpretation. Admittedly, this reading is, in some respects, the
flip side of the construction process, but sets a different accent. In
the following, this reading will be checked for plausibility with some
arguments.
Although Bebel and Engels corresponded with each other, the two
›woman experts‹ of the labor movement did not seem interested in a
joint substantive debate on the ›woman question.‹ This non-relation16
17
18
Quoted after Lawrence Krader, »Einleitung,« in Die ethnologischen Exzerpthefte,
ed. Lawrence Krader (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1976), 117.
Friedrich Engels, »Engels an Friedrich Adolph Sorge, 7. März 1884,« in MEW,
vol. 36 (Berlin: Dietz, 1979), 124.
Friedrich Engels, »Engels an Paul Lafargue, 10. Mai 1884,« in MEW, vol. 36 (Berlin: Dietz, 1979), 145.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
ship is initially surprising, since Engels had a lively correspondence
with Kautsky in the early 1880s on questions of the origins of the
family and marriage,19 as well as on the distribution of his new book.20
In a letter to Engels dated May 11, 1882, Kautsky informed him that
his own publication functioned in a certain sense as a »counterpart«
to Bebel’s work, since in it he focused on the early history of mankind.21 After its publication in the Stuttgarter Kosmos, a Darwinian
monthly journal that was highly regarded at the time, Engels was not
very convinced of its content and sharply criticized some of Kautsky’s
assumptions.22 In contrast, the correspondence with the thoroughbred parliamentarian Bebel was quite sober: only once did Engels
mention to Bebel that he had read his remarks »with great interest«
and had discovered »many good things« in them. He does not really
specify this general remark: »What you say about the development
of industry in Germany is particularly clear and beautiful.« In the
following, Engels only refers to his own position on industrial development in Germany23 and thus deliberately chooses a discursive
avoidance strategy.
It seems obvious, due to the convergence in time, that Engels
wanted to use his writing (not only) to intervene in a corrective manner. He met Kautsky personally in London in 1881 and maintained
a close relationship with him even before Kautsky’s London exile
(1885 – 1890). Therefore, Engels did not hesitate to call his friend quite
harshly to order. Although he appreciated Bebel for his importance
19
20
21
22
23
The three articles written by Karl Kautsky in 1881 – 1882 (»Hetärismus,« »Die
Raubehe und das Mutterrecht: Der Clan,« and »Die Kaufehe und die patriarchale Familie«) were published together: Karl Kautsky, »Die Entstehung der Ehe
und der Familie,« Kosmos: Zeitschrift für einheitliche Weltanschauung auf Grund
der Entwicklungslehre 12, no. 2 (1882): 190 – 207.
Kautsky wrote to Engels on July 16, 1884: »Paper like that from Bebel’s Woman«
(Benedikt Kautsky, ed., Friedrich Engels Briefwechsel mit Karl Kautsky (Vienna:
Danubia-Verlag, 1955), 133).
Ibid., 57.
Ibid., 46 – 164.
Friedrich Engels, »Engels an August Bebel, 18. Januar 1884,« in MEW, vol. 36
(Berlin: Dietz, 1979), 87.
241
242
Vincent Streichhahn
to the German movement, it is precisely this fact that might have
prevented Engels from a direct confrontation with the ›Workers‹ Emperor‹ (Arbeiterkaiser) in terms of content, since he shied away from
the open conflict because of the possible consequences for the organization in Germany.24 However, an open conflict was not necessary
at all, since Bebel willingly allowed himself to be taught by Engels’s
theoretical authority.25
By shifting the focus to the historical development since the primitive societies, which Engels classifies as egalitarian societies in reference to Morgan’s investigations and Marx’s excerpts, he abstains from
an explicit criticism of Bebel. At the same time, he elevates his own
occupation to another level by identifying it as the completion of a
»legacy.«
It can be said that Engels’s book had a considerable influence not
only on Bebel’s Woman and Socialism, which became more popular in
Germany. However, the popularity of Bebel’s book, which introduced
the masses to Marxism, was by no means only due to his remarks
on the ›woman question.‹ As early as 1926, the bourgeois sociologist Hilde Lion (1893 – 1970) described in her study of the women’s
movement that »[f ]or the intellectually vibrant proletarian, Bebel was
almost always the mediator to Marx.«26 In addition, it should not
be forgotten that the socially highly controversial and partly tabooed
topic of sexuality certainly had a certain appeal to readers (like the
authors). The importance of the utopian, i. e. the pointing out of
concrete utopias, must not be overlooked either. For example, Bebel’s
book »was almost the only work in the Marxist literature of the time
24
25
26
Marie-Claire Hoock-Demarle, »Frauen und Frauenemanzipation in Engels Briefen,« in MEGA-Studien Journal 2 (1996): 54 – 65.
Engels turns Bebel’s explanations in a historical-materialistic way. Bebel’s book
continued to grow in the following editions. While the first edition had just 180
pages, the final German version had 519 pages. This was due to the fact that he
took over large parts of Engels’s prehistory and materalistic arguments, but above
all to the fact that he constantly added empirical material.
Hilde Lion, Zur Soziologie der Frauenbewegung: Die sozialistische und die katholische Frauenbewegung (Berlin: Herbig, 1926), 38.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
243
that openly met people’s needs for a detailed and specific account of
the socialist future.«27
Bebel’s Influence, Engels and Political Liberalism
Marxist theory has long been accused of gender blindness. In the
meantime, research has shown that this accusation is not tenable in
its entirety. Heather A. Brown shows in her systematic study Marx on
Gender and the Family: A Critical Study28 how the question of gender
relations and the family runs through the work of Marx and Engels.29
Although it is certainly not a dominant theme, it can nevertheless be
found in the margins of many of their writings.30 Despite this fact,
they did not provide a coherent theory of women’s oppression or gender relations, although some claim that for The Origin of the Family. I
will show below that this is not true. However, from the early writings
to the late work of Marx and Engels, there are aspects that indicate a
27
28
29
30
Lise Vogel, Marxismus und Frauenunterdrückung: Auf dem Weg zu einer umfassenden Theorie (Münster: Unrast Verlag, 2019 [1983]), 148.
Also noteworthy is her analysis of Marx’s ethnographical notebooks, which have
not been examined to date with regard to their position on gender, but which
at the same time form the basis for Engels’s The Origin of the Family. Heather A.
Brown, Marx on Gender and the Family: A Critical Study (Chicago: Haymarket
Books, 2013), 133 – 162, 176 – 209.
Brown claims to have presented the first systematic work on this question
(Brown, Marx on Gender, 3). However, Manfred Scharinger published on this issue a few years earlier. This fact does not detract from the significance of Brown’s
work, as it sets different accents to the more historiographically oriented book
from Austria. Unfortunately, the latter work, probably due to language barriers,
usually gets lost in the reception. Manfred Scharinger, Geschlechterverhältnisse
bei Marx und Engels: Eine kritische Auseinandersetzung (Vienna: Arbeitsgruppe
Marxismus, 2007).
As far as I know, only Sam Stark has mentioned that Marx also dealt with the
situation of women in one of the so-called »London Notebooks« (1850 – 1853):
»But in the common descriptions of this period in the life of Karl Marx as a
time of systematic studies on a critique of political economy, which was only
occasionally interrupted by journalism, this issue has no clear place.« Sam Stark,
»Marx und die Frauenfrage,« Zeitschrift für Ideengeschichte 11, no. 3 (2017): 55.
244
Vincent Streichhahn
preoccupation with gender issues and can be made fruitful in part for
a gender-sensitive analysis. Moreover, and this is hardly mentioned,
the two were early advocates of women’s political participation in
workers‹ associations while the majority of their German comrades
still vehemently opposed it.31
But precisely because of Marx’s and Engels’s fragmentary preoccupation with the ›woman question‹ — almost completely hidden in
the excerpt notebooks32 — it was another book that focused Marxist
attention on the ›woman question‹ for the first time: of course, it was
August Bebel’s Woman and Socialism. Female Marxists in particular
oriented themselves according to these works in the following period.
Clara Zetkin (1857 – 1933) would take the writings of Bebel and Engels
as the starting point for her speech at the founding congress of the Second International in Paris in 1889, which she published quite quickly
as a pamphlet. Marxist theoretical works on the ›woman question‹ in
the 19th century were dominated by German authors, which is also
evident from the reception of these works by foreign female socialists.33
Political activism by women was not a matter of course in the
labor movement at that time. It took two authorities of the German labor movement, Bebel and Engels, to deal with the ›woman
question‹ in order to partially push back ›proletarian anti-feminism‹
within Social Democracy. This was mainly supported by a misogyne
journeyman culture that formed the basis of the young German labor
movement.34 The industrial proletariat, as the ideal type of working
31
32
33
34
Judy Cox, »How Marx and Engels fought for women’s liberation,« International
Socialism, March 29, 2020, https://isj.org.uk/jcox-marx-engels-women-lib/.
It should be noted that it is often not clear what Marx intended to do with the
thousands of pages of excerpts and that he did not use most of them directly for
his work.
Eleanor Marx Aveling and Edward Aveling, »The Woman Question: From a
Socialist Point of View,« Westminster Review 125 (1886): 207 – 222; Nadežda Konstantinovna Krupskaja, Zhenschina-rabotnica [The Woman Worker] (Munich,
1901).
Thomas Welskopp, »›Der Geist ächt männlichen Strebens‹: Mikropolitik und
Geschlechterbeziehungen im Vereinsmilieu der frühen deutschen Arbeiterbewegung,« Kurswechsel 3 (1997): 67 – 81.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
245
class imagined by Marx, was still a minority in the workers‹ organizations in Germany in the 1860s due to the catch-up development of
German capitalism. However, there were at least two other relevant
approaches to Marxism: one via Christianity and one via liberalism.
The latter shaped figures such as Bebel,35 Zetkin, and also Engels and
Marx at different times.
In particular, the influence of liberalism on Marxist political positions and theory development is often misunderstood. In a recent
essay, Cornelia Klinger refers to this fact in a semi-serious way as »a
leftist melancholia about liberal democracy.«36 Klinger thus describes
an affinity that shames the actors: a close relationship between liberalism and the labor and women’s movements. This close relationship
results from »the thinking of the Enlightenment and the ideals of the
bourgeois revolution.«37 This is decisive, since Bebel’s political socialization through liberalism, as well as his contacts with the bourgeois
women’s movement,38 according to my thesis, from the perspective
of the sociology of knowledge represent a constitutional condition of
the Marxist theory of women’s emancipation that could not flourish
in the anti-feminist milieu of the young German labor movement.39
The situation is similar for Clara Zetkin, who came into contact
with the bourgeois women’s movement through her mother at Au35
36
37
38
39
Although Bebel himself was a wood turner, he came into close contact with the
liberal thinking of the time through his membership and chairmanship of the
Workers‹ Educational Association (Gewerblicher Bildungsverein) in Leipzig.
Cornelia Klinger, »Weder eine bürgerliche Ehe noch eine perverse Wahlverwandtschaft: Von Liberalismus und Frauenbewegung zu Neoliberalismus und
Postfeminismus,« in Liberalismus: Traditionsbestände und Gegenwartskontroversen,
ed. Karsten Fischer and Sebastian Huhnholz (Baden-Baden: Nomos, 2019), 362.
Ibid.
Margrit Twellmann, Die deutsche Frauenbewegung: Ihre Anfänge und erste Entwicklung 1843 – 1889 (Kronberg: Athenäum-Verlag, 1976), 139 – 177.
A similar argumentation is found in Evans, who describes not only Bebel’s ideas
»as a reaction to the theoretical views that determined the position of bourgeois-liberal individualism in the woman question.« Evans, Sozialdemokratie und
Frauenemanziaption, 27. The specification made here emphasizes more strongly a
sociological perspective of knowledge.
246
Vincent Streichhahn
guste Schmidt’s (1833 – 1902) teacher training seminar in Leipzig from
1874 to 1878.40 At the end of the 19th century, Zetkin’s theoretical
views on the ›woman question‹ were by no means ›strictly‹ Marxist.
These »developed only gradually. Her articles from the 1880s show
little Marxist influence and generally use arguments borrowed from
either Bebel or Saint-Simon or the bourgeois-liberal theory of women’s emancipation.«41 After the repeal of the Socialist Laws, Zetkin
became one of the outstanding leaders of the proletarian women’s
movement in Germany. In doing so, she earned merit less as a theoretician than as an organizer, agitator, and editor of Die Gleichheit
(Equality).42
Especially in the second women’s movement, Marx and Engels
were accused of having largely ignored gender relations in their work.
Engels and Bebel were even called »fairy-tale uncles of the woman
question« by feminist activists in order to brand their supposed sexism.43 This vehemence, despite certain prejudices of Bebel and Engels regarding the gender question, fails to recognize the significance
of these two books for the constitution of the proletarian women’s
movement in the ranks of the German Social Democrats.
Of course, there were also socialist feminists for whom the works
of Engels and Bebel were indispensable reference works.44 During this
40
41
42
43
44
Clara Zetkin’s mother, Josephine Eißner, maintained good relations with the two
pioneers of the bourgeois women’s movement, Auguste Schmidt and Louise Otto-Peters, which made it possible for her daughter to be admitted to the Leipzig
teacher training seminar. Gilbert Badia, Clara Zetkin: Eine neue Biographie (Berlin: Dietz, 1994), 11 – 14.
Evans, Sozialdemokratie und Frauenemanziaption, 98.
Mirjam Sachse, Von ›weiblichen Vollmenschen‹ und Klassenkämpferinnen: Frauengeschichte und Frauenleitbilder in der proletarischen Frauenzeitschrift ›Die Gleichheit‹ (1891 – 1923) (Kassel: Universitätsbibliothek Kassel, 2011).
Roswitha Burgard and Gaby Karsten, Die Märchenonkel der Frauenfrage: Friedrich Engels und August Bebel (Berlin: Frauen-Selbstverlag, 1975).
Some activists at the time saw The Origin of the Family as the cornerstone of
socialist feminism, primarily because of the fact that Engels historicized the institution of the family and, by demanding the socialization of reproductive tasks,
provided important remarks for a post-capitalist organization of reproduction.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
247
time, they made the first attempts to make the economic writings of
Marx and Engels fruitful for an analysis of women’s oppression under
capitalism. They rely primarily on a critical re-reading of Capital. The
rich debate that developed between socialist feminists from the 1970s
onwards is made clear by the so-called ›domestic-labor debate.‹45
Building on Lise Vogel’s work, the SRT, which is predominantly represented by Anglo-Saxon authors, emerged from this historical controversy.46 This will be discussed in more detail below. Beyond this,
from the end of the 2000s onward, the first systematic attempts were
made to appreciate the complete works of Marx and Engels from a
gender-sensitive perspective.47
To put it all in a nutshell, Marx and Engels certainly reflected on
gender relations in their writings, albeit not systematically. However,
without the influence of political liberalism, the debate would probably not have been so intense. Female Marxists at the turn of the century oriented themselves mainly to Bebel’s and Engels’s works. After
all, it was the task of the second women’s movement to take on classic
works, to subject them to fundamental criticism, and to develop them
further. In the next section, selected feminist critiques of Engels will
be presented in a concise manner to crystallize the crucial points.
Selected (Socialist-)Feminist Critiques
In this section, the criticisms of Engels by three female authors
are explained in more detail, namely those of Simone de Beauvoir
(1908 – 1986), Lise Vogel and Heather A. Brown. In The Other Sex, de
45
46
47
For example: Kate Millett, Sexus und Herrschaft. Die Tyrannei des Mannes in
unserer Gesellschaft (Munich: Desch, 1971), 148 – 172.
For a compact presentation see Lise Vogel, »Hausarbeitsdebatte,« in Historisch-kritisches Wörterbuch, vol. 1, ed. Frigga Haug (Hamburg: Argument Verlag,
2003), 540 – 554.
Tithi Bhattacharya, ed., Social Reproduction Theory: Remapping Class, Recentering
Oppression (London: Pluto Books, 2017).
Brown, Marx on Gender; Scharinger, Geschlechterverhältnisse.
248
Vincent Streichhahn
Beauvoir probably presented the first feminist critique of Engels.48 It
comprises only a few pages but reveals fundamental logical inconsistencies. Vogel,49 on the other hand, is exemplary for a line of criticism that focuses on the dual-system topic. Brown, meanwhile, refers
to Engels’s economic and technical determinism,50 which leads to a
one-sided framework. The criticisms are partly complementary.
As a reminder, Engels’s argumentation51 is presented here in radical brevity: Engels assumed that the primitive societies of mankind
were egalitarian societies. With economic and technical development, i. e. the development of productive forces, people succeeded
in producing a considerable surplus over time. Private ownership of
land and tools, which had previously been common property, was
created. These things used to be inherited along the maternal line
of inheritance (matrilineality) to the children, since only mothers
knew beyond doubt who their biological children were. According
to Engels, maternal rights had to make way for the paternal line of
inheritance (patrilineality). Engels calls this »the world historical defeat of the female sex.«52 As an institution, the family had the primary
purpose of preserving property and bequeathing it to its descendants.
The circle of the family became narrower with time. The women
were obliged to monogamy by the men to ensure that only their
own children would inherit. A central thesis of Engels is therefore
that women’s oppression is directly linked to the emergence of class
societies. The struggle between the sexes, according to Engels, occurs
48
Simone de Beauvoir, Das andere Geschlecht: Sitte und Sexus der Frau (Hamburg:
Rowohlt, 1983 [1949]), 62 – 68.
49 Vogel, Marxismus und Frauenunterdrückung.
50 An argument that Vogel, de Beauvoir and also Michèle Barrett, as another classic
feminist, have already cited in a similar way. Michèle Barrett, »Introduction,« in
The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State (Harmondsworth: Penguin
Books, 1986), 7 – 30.
51 For a more detailed presentation see Scharinger, Geschlechterverhältnisse, 264 – 413;
Brown, Marx on Gender, 163 – 175; Vogel, Marxismus und Frauenunterdrückung,
119 – 145.
52 Engels, »Der Ursprung der Familie,« 61.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
249
at the same time as class relations.53 Engels treats both developments
as simultaneous.
De Beauvoir deals with Engels in her magnum opus, published in
1949, in the context of a tribute to historical materialism. A woman
cannot be considered simply as a sex-determined organism: »the consciousness that woman has of herself is not determined by her sexuality alone: it reflects a situation that depends on the economic structure
of society, a structure that expresses the degree of technological development that humanity has reached.«54 After a concise summary of
Engels’s argumentation, de Beauvoir points to two central cruxes in it.
The main problem is the »transition from public to private ownership,
but nobody tells us how it happened.«55 She notes that Engels himself
admits »[w]e don’t know anything about that yet.«56 According to
de Beauvoir, he neither provides historical evidence nor attempts an
interpretation.
De Beauvoir hits the real sore spot with her second criticism: »Nor
is it convincing that private property necessarily entailed the enslavement of women. Historical materialism [sic!] takes for granted facts
that should be explained; it simply accepts the bond of the interior
that links man with property.«57 Although it is Engels and not the
premises of historical materialism that makes this argument, the criticism is correct. It is logically impossible to deduce from the emergence of private property the inevitable oppression of women.
Why does oppression take place precisely along the category of
gender (and race)? Why does the gendered division of labor have such
serious effects? This cannot be explained simply by the end of matrilineal society due to the introduction of private poverty and patrilin53
54
55
56
57
»The first class opposition that appears in history coincides with the development of the antagonism between man and woman in monogamous marriage,
and the first class oppression coincides with that of the female sex by the male.«
Ibid., 68.
De Beauvoir, Das andere Geschlecht, 62.
Ibid., 64.
Engels, »Der Ursprung der Familie,« 157.
De Beauvoir, Das andere Geschlecht, 65.
250
Vincent Streichhahn
eality. Again, this only describes what needs to be explained. On the
other hand, de Beauvoir also emphasizes the demands of motherhood, which lead to an asymmetrical relationship with men if society
does not deal with them appropriately.
In Marxism and the Oppression of Women: Toward a Unitary Theory,
Vogel focuses on a different theme, which Engels raises with a formulation in the foreword.58 Interestingly, the argument was not taken
up by his contemporaries,59 but only activists of the second women’s
movement did so. In the foreword to the 1884 edition, Engels talks
about two forms of production that take place separately: the production of food and that of people.60 Paradoxically, he thus laid the foundation for a dualism with serious consequences. In doing so, he drew
on the manuscript of The German Ideology,61 which was not published
during his or Marx’s lifetimes. There, in 1846, the two write in a very
similar way: »The production of life, both of one’s own in labor and of
fresh life in procreation, now appears as a double relationship: on the
one hand as a natural, on the other as a social relationship.«62
58
59
Vogel, Marxismus und Frauenunterdrückung, 141 – 143.
»At the end of the century, socialists found the assertion in the preface concerning a duality of social reproduction ›extremely remarkable,‹ in fact ›almost
incomprehensible.‹ Soviet commentators finally agreed that Engels was wrong,
and that this statement could only refer to the earliest stages of human history,
when humans were supposedly so much a part of nature that one could not even
speak of the existence of social relations of production.« Vogel, Marxismus und
Frauenunterdrückung, 142.
60 »According to the materialistic conception, the determining factor in history is,
in the final instance, the production and reproduction of the immediate essentials of life. This, again, is of a twofold character. On the one side, the production
of the means of existence, of articles of food and clothing, dwellings, and of the
tools necessary for that production; on the other side, the production of human
beings themselves, the propagation of the species. The social organization under
which the people of a particular historical epoch and a particular country live is
determined by both kinds of production: by the stage of development of labor
on the one hand and of the family on the other.« Engels, »Der Ursprung der
Familie,« 27 – 28.
61 Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, »Die deutsche Ideologie,« in MEW, vol. 3 (Berlin: Dietz, 1969 [1846]), 5 – 530.
62 Ibid., 29.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
We can extend this point with comments from Terrell Carver, who
emphasizes the importance of this shift. Engels »attempted to build
on this revision an apparatus of twin-track ›determination‹ in history,
involving sex-oppression and class-oppression.«63 These »major revisions to Marx’s theoretical work« had not been dealt with in detail
by the interpretative tradition. Marx had already taken a different
approach in the Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy.64 »The Origin of the Family […] complicates what was
otherwise a settled and (reasonably) simple story of historical ›determination‹ by an identifiably singular factor (production, albeit of
its ›means‹ and ›relations‹) — as opposed to the obviously dual-factor
›production‹ and ›re-production‹.« It was certainly not that simple
and complete in Marx’s writings, but Carver is correct when he remarks that »those problems have rarely, if ever, been addressed outside the feminist context, and given the airing they evidently merit.«65
Vogel argues that by using the manuscript of The German Ideology,
which Engels rediscovered after Marx’s death, he acquired many theoretical weaknesses of their earlier work. By postulating two separate
systems of production of material life, he makes a very rudimentary
distinction between natural and social phenomena, which Marx had
actually overcome. It implies that the family would be an independent unit of social development. »And it is precisely this implication
that has caught the imagination of contemporary socialist feminists,
often tempting them into a quite cavalier reading of the Origin.«66
According to Vogel, however, he should have based his account
on Marx’s theory of social development. She criticizes Engels’s technological determinism, which he takes over from Morgan, the uncritical adoption of the idea of the double production of The German
Ideology and a utopian critique of property. »The Origin constituted a
63
64
65
66
Carver, »Marxism and Feminism,« 258.
Karl Marx, »Einleitung: Zur Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie,« in MEW, vol. 13
(Berlin: Dietz, 1971 [1857]), 615 – 641.
Carver, »Marxism and Feminism,« 260.
Vogel, Marxismus und Frauenunterdrückung, 143.
251
252
Vincent Streichhahn
defective text whose ambiguous theoretical and political formulations
nevertheless became an integral part of socialist legacy.«67
Brown aims in a similar direction to Vogel: »While de Beauvoir,
Barrett, and Vogel all provide important critiques of Engels’s Origin
of the Family, all three tend to conflate the positions of Marx and
Engels.«68 However, the above should make it clear that this does not
apply to Vogel. Brown argues that Marx took a more nuanced approach to this issue »since he was operating within a more dialectical
framework [and was therefore] able to avoid the sort of determinism
that Engels’s study displays.«69 While Engels assumed, according to
Brown, that the introduction of private property created the conditions of women’s oppression, Marx did not believe that property was
the only relevant factor. In contrast, Marx saw that the contradictions
developed very early, even in communal societies. Brown quotes Raya
Dunayevskaya (1910 – 1987) in more detail, which is reproduced here,
since it is a key passage:
Nothing less than the vital question of transitions is at stake in the
differences between Marx’s and Engels’s views. Marx was showing
that it is during the transition period that you see the duality emerging to reveal the beginnings of antagonisms, whereas Engels always
seems to have antagonisms only at the end, as if class society came in
very nearly full blown after the communal form was destroyed and
private property was established. Moreover, for Marx the dialectical
development from one stage to another is related to new revolutionary upsurges, whereas Engels sees it as a unilateral progression.70
The development of class and gender antagonisms is embedded by
Engels in a monocausal narrative. This leads him to the assumption
67
68
69
70
Ibid.
Brown, Marx on Gender, 165.
Ibid.
Raya Dunayevskaya, Rosa Luxemburg, Women’s Liberation, and Marx’s Philosophy
of Revolution (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1982), 180 – 181.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
253
that social conflicts would not have been possible at all before a relevant generation of added value.71 Referring to Marx’s notes on Morgan in the notebooks, Brown explains how Marx saw the potential in
early primitive societies for the development of inequalities that did
not arise from private property. There, Marx recognized »the establishment of ranks — relationship of chief to mass — and the economic
interests that accompanied it.«72
Accordingly, Marx saw a multitude of factors for social conflicts
and for the development of antagonisms. But Marx also assumed a
certain power of action on the part of women, even under the most
difficult conditions, which does not seem to be the case with Engels’s
description of the »world historical defeat of the female sex.« Brown
therefore sees the greatest difference between Marx and Engels in the
more deterministic arguments of the latter. »Engels primarily looks to
economic and technological forces to explain possibilities for change.
Thus, Engels remains within a relatively deterministic and unilinear
framework, whereas Marx‹ formulation allows for greater variety in
outcomes and for much greater degree of human agency, especially
for women.«73
It became apparent that the criticisms of the three authors have
different nuances, but complement each other in part. De Beauvoir
emphasizes that Engels neglects the question of gender and treats its
appearance as a cause. Vogel and Brown are united by their concern
to separate Marx from Engels. While Vogel explains in abstract form
that Engels’s dualism does not explain the social development of the
family and changes because he does not see the family as a component
of social totality, Brown demonstrates it concretely. She argues that
Engels sees social development too deterministically and exclusively
in the field of technology and production, while Marx also considers
social factors. The two views are not mutually exclusive, but complement each other.
71
72
73
Brown, Marx on Gender, 174.
Dunayevskaya, Rosa Luxemburg, 181.
Brown, Marx on Gender, 175.
254
Vincent Streichhahn
Theoretical Confusion in the Marxist Tradition
In the following, I will concentrate on Lise Vogel’s criticism of Engels’s
approach, which postulates two independent forms of production.
Tithi Bhattacharya, currently one of the most impressive theorists in
the field of SRT, succinctly sums up the void of »classical« Marxism
concerning the oppression of women: »There is an unresolved tension
at the heart of Marxist explanations for women’s oppression under
capitalism. Although there is general agreement that the bourgeois
family, as the dominant kinship unit, has something to do with generating and reproducing that oppression, the exact role of the family
varies among Marxists.«74 In other words, Marxist theory has long
failed to theorize the family / domestic labor, which has led to an inadequate explanation of women’s oppression under capitalism. Engels
made a significant contribution to this with his approach.
What role does the family, as one of the core institutions for the
production of life and equally importantly the production of the
commodity labor, play in Engels’s thinking? »Reproductive labor
had social forms that organized it, such as marriage and the family;
but the labor itself was seen as biological. Women who performed
this labor were also naturalized, as biological beings unable to effect
changes in these social orders.«75 Engels reproduced a version of what
Bhattacharya calls »the dependence through sexual division of labor
explanation of women’s oppression.«76 Bebel, too, represents a variant
of this thinking, but in contrast to Engels, he locates the reasons for
women’s oppression on dynamics within the household and in the dependence of women on men. This rather simplistic explanation leads
74
75
76
Tithi Bhattacharya, »Liberating Women from ›Political Economy‹: Margaret
Benston’s Marxism and a Social-Reproduction Approach to Gender Oppression,« Monthly Review, January 1, 2020, https://monthlyreview.org/2020/01/01/
liberating-women-from-political-economy/.
Elisabeth Armstrong, Marxist and Socialist Feminism (Northampton, MA: Smith
College, Faculty Publications).
Bhattacharya, »Liberating Women from ›Political Economy‹.«
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
255
to the fact that Bebel, especially in the first editions of his book, barely
manages to go beyond bourgeois-liberal demands for equality.77 Due
to his materialistic foundation, Engels is more theoretically grounded,
but still deficient.
The programmatic conclusions refer to demands for equal education and the economic independence of women through
wage labor. »Liberal reformers usually emphasized the emancipation-through-education route while the socialist stress was on emancipation-through-waged work, albeit with many overlaps between the
two paths.«78 We recognize in both Bebel and Engels the heritage of
the liberal tradition, which is enriched by socio-material aspects. Engels calls complete legal equality a prerequisite for true social equality
of the sexes. »Then it will be plain that the first condition for the
liberation of the wife is to bring the whole female sex back into public
industry, and that this in turn demands the abolition of the monogamous family as the economic unit of society.«79
Engels and Bebel assumed that the liberation of women is not
possible under capitalism. Both therefore linked the liberation of the
female sex very closely to the fate of the working class. Thus Bebel
wrote in the first edition of his book: »The woman and the worker
both have in common that they have been the oppressed since time
immemorial.«80 According to Bebel, only the common fight could
help: »The woman is also called upon not to be left behind in this
struggle.«81 For Bebel, there was indeed a connection between the
›woman question‹ and the ›labor question,‹ but in his case they do
not fall into one.82 And Engels wrote in a letter to Gertrude Guillaume-Schak on July 5, 1885: »In my opinion, true equality between man
77
78
79
80
81
82
Evans, Sozialdemokratie und Frauenemanzipation, 40 – 52.
Bhattacharya, »Liberating Women from ›Political Economy‹.«
Engels, »Der Ursprung der Familie,« 76.
Bebel, »Die Frau und der Sozialismus,« 10.
Ibid., 198.
»A full and complete solution of the woman question — by which I mean that
women are not only equal to men by law, but are also economically free and
independent of them, and as far as possible equal to them in intellectual train-
256
Vincent Streichhahn
and woman can only become a truth when the exploitation of both
by capital is eliminated and private domestic work is transformed
into a public industry.«83 The demand to socialize private domestic
work would become a central principle of the socialist strategy. In Engels’s case, however, women’s liberation seems to be the inevitable result of capitalist development and shows his economic determinism:
We can already see from this that to emancipate woman and make
her the equal of the man is and remains an impossibility so long as
the woman is shut out from social productive labor and restricted
to private domestic labor. The emancipation of woman will only be
possible when woman can take part in production on a large, social
scale, and domestic work no longer claims anything but an insignificant amount of her time. And only now has that become possible
through modern large-scale industry, which does not merely permit
of the employment of female labor over a wide range, but positively
demands it, while it also tends towards ending private domestic labor
by changing it more and more into a public industry.84
The constant struggle against sexism — even within the working
class — was not at the top of Engels’s priority list. Even a relatively
simple measure to reduce the double burden on women unfortunately did not come to his mind: men can also do work in the household. The sexual division of labor approach has a profound theoretical
weakness. The misleading statement of Engels in his foreword certainly contributed to this confusion. In close reference to Bhattacharya,
three points in particular can be criticized concerning the classical
approach taken by Engels and Bebel.
83
84
ing — is just as impossible under the present social and political institutions as
the solution of the labour question.« Ibid., 10.
Friedrich Engels, »Engels an Gertrude Guillaume-Schak, 5. Juli 1885,« in MEW,
vol. 36 (Berlin: Dietz, 1979), 341.
Engels, »Der Ursprung der Familie,« 158.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
257
1. Perhaps the most important point concerns the fact that »the division of labor explanation set up social production as being externally related to the family, as though the family merely bore the effects of social production rather than was a unit that alongside the
production of commodities co-constituted those very relations
making up the totality of social production under capitalism.«85
2. This approach underestimates the importance that women have
always had in social production. Participation in social production as the key to women’s emancipation does not explain at all why
women have so far failed in their liberation, even though they had
a major role in work in earlier class societies. »The elevation of waged work as the path to equality, similarly, fails to explain why or
how gender inequalities are consistently and reliably reproduced
through the very functioning of that work.«86
3. Engels failed to sufficiently theorize the family under capitalism,
since he causally links the division of labor, property relations and
women’s oppression. The thesis of the dissolution of the family,
already established in the Communist Manifesto, has, despite all
the changes, not been confirmed in any way, however. Historically,
on the other hand, it can be said that working families themselves
held fast to the maintenance of the oppressive institution of the
family, since it apparently promised them security. Even in the
present day, at least in the Western hemisphere, family forms have
pluralized, but by no means dissolved.
Despite all progress in the political practice of the movement evoked
by the writings of Engels and Bebel, which of course still had to be
fought for by women, the theoretical explanatory power of these
approaches is severely limited by the points made. »If this was the
totality of thinking about gender in the Marxist tradition, then we
would be facing a serious problem.«87 Fortunately, various socialist
85
86
87
Bhattacharya, »Liberating Women from ›Political Economy‹.«
Ibid.
Ibid.
258
Vincent Streichhahn
feminists have pointed out in the past that this approach, formulated
in The Origin of the Family, is by no means congruent with the theoretical considerations of Marx. Vogel and Brown have already been
mentioned. Bhattacharya makes a similar point when she writes that
the »Marxist method remains the key to understanding, and solving,
the problem of gender oppression. […] [T]heir writings on general
social production contain the seeds of a far more robust, creative, and
historical materialist theory of gender under capitalism. This is the
social reproduction approach.«88
While it was of immense importance for the common organization of women and men in the workers‹ associations that two authorities of the labor movement dealt with the ›woman question‹ in
a progressive way, they left behind serious theoretical problems. The
political consequence, therefore, is that Engels’s dualism has led to
confusion about the meaning of the family in the socialist tradition
following him.
Socialist Feminism
In the context of the second women’s movement, a debate was held
which is now known as the »domestic-labor debate.«89 Following historical forerunners such as Mary Inman,90 Margaret Benston presented a theoretically important contribution in 1969.91 Benston’s considerations are important because it is probably the first time that
domestic labor was understood as an economic activity and thus located within the capitalist mode of production. What Benston did
88
89
90
91
Ibid.
Vogel, »Hausarbeitsdebatte,« 540 – 554.
Mary Inman was an American communist, who argued that the reproductive
labor of women should be recognized as productive work. Mary Inman, In
Woman’s Defense (Los Angeles: The Committee to Organize the Advancement of
Women, 1940).
Margaret Benston, »The Political Economy of Women’s Liberation,« Monthly
Review 21, no. 4 (1969): 13 – 27.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
259
not yet find, however, was a consideration of what specific commodity domestic work produces. This is the (re)production of commodity labor. Finally, in the 1970s, the ›domestic labor debate‹ unfolded,
which produced important contributions such as those of Mariarosa
Dalla Costa and Selma James,92 Wally Seccombe93 and many others.
»Largely unhappy with the economist focus of these earlier pieces and
dual-system theory, Lise Vogel sought to expand beyond the focus
on domestic labour without positing separate spheres.«94 The central
concern of her approach was to overcome the dualism led by Engels
and adopted by many feminists of the second women’s movement
and to develop a uniform theoretical framework for the analysis of
women’s broaden our understanding of the political economy of social reproduction.«95
Social Reproduction Approach
Vogel’s approach is characterized by the attempt to examine women’s
oppression in the context of a feminist critique of political economy. The value-theoretical specification of the concept of reproduction
can theoretically grasp the structural interlocking of the reproduction of commodity labor and the production of added value far more
systematically than previous approaches, and at the same time free
them from normative assumptions. Furthermore, this value-theoretical concept of reproduction can expand our understanding of class
struggles, which by no means take place only in the factory but also in
the public reproduction sector, such as the health and education sec92
93
94
95
Mariarosa Dalla Costa and Selma James, The Power of Women and the Subversion
of the Community (Bristol: Falling Wall Press, 1972).
Wally Seccombe, »The Housewife and Her Labour under Capitalism,« New Left
Review 83, n oppression under capitalism. »Thus, Vogel begins to o. 1 (1974):
3 – 24.
Brown, Marx on Gender, 69.
Ibid., 70.
260
Vincent Streichhahn
tors.96 Vogel developed her concept of reproduction from a feminist
re-reading of the theory of value in the first volume of Marx’s Capital. Ultimately, Vogel theorizes reproductive work as a component of
Marx’s concept of necessary work.97
In Capital, Marx refers, among other things, to the significance
of gender in determining the value of labor, but explicitly excludes
it from further investigation.98 Nevertheless, his economic writings
contain some important remarks on the reproduction of labor. Marx,
for example, emphasizes the central importance of the consumption
of labor.99 This is characterized by two sides: productive and individual consumption. In the production of goods, the workers themselves consume means of production and thus increase the value of
the product. The worker thereby acts »as the moving force of capital
and belongs to the capitalist.« In individual consumption, on the
other hand, the the worker and her / his labor belongs to her / himself
and »performs vital functions outside the production process.« This
means the consumption of food, »the consumption of which serves to
reproduce the muscles, nerves, bones, brains of existing workers and
to create new workers.«100
Vogel ties in at this point: it is true that individual consumption
describes an area of the daily reproduction of individual workers.
96
Ronda Kipka and Vincent Streichhahn, »Kapital gegen Leben: Plädoyer für
einen politik-ökonomischen Reproduktionsbegriff,« Prokla 197, no. 4 (2019):
585 – 590.
97 Vogel himself does not find the extension of the necessary work entirely convincing in an essay from 2000 and was criticized for this; see Susan Ferguson and
David McNally, »Capital, Labour-Power, and Gender-Relations: Introduction to
the Historical Materialism Edition of Marxism and the Oppression of Women,«
in Lise Vogel, Marxism and the Oppression of Women: Toward a Unitary Theory
(Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2013), xvii-xl, here xxxiii.
98 Karl Marx, »Größenwechsel von Preis der Arbeitskraft und Mehrwert,« in MEW,
vol. 23 (Berlin: Dietz, 1962 [1867]), 542.
99 Karl Marx, »Lohn, Preis und Profit,« in MEW, vol. 16 (Berlin: Dietz, 1962 [1865]),
131.
100 Karl Marx, »Der Akkumulationsprozeß des Kapitals,« in MEW, vol. 23 (Berlin:
Dietz, 1962 [1867]), 596 – 597.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
However, there is no systematic explanation for how this relates to
people outside of the wage employment relationship (e. g. children,
the sick, the elderly). Marx ignores the fact that an entire class of
workers and not only the individual worker must be reproduced.
Moreover, the processes of social reproduction must be organized over
generations in order to ensure the maintenance of the accumulation
of capital in the long term.101 Against the background of these considerations, Vogel develops a typology with which she distinguishes
three areas of the reproduction of the labor force: 1) the production
of the products directly consumed by the worker, 2) the maintenance,
education and care of all those outside the work process, and 3) generative reproduction (primarily childbirth, but also migration, etc.).102
Up to now, the value-theoretical definition of the concept of reproduction has not included gender relations. From a theoretical
point of view, Vogel concludes, the reproduction of the labor force
»is by no means bound to private kinship-based households […]. In
particular, it does not necessarily include any or all of the following
components: heterosexuality, biological reproduction, family forms
or generational renewal.«103 Nevertheless, social reproduction cannot
be thought of at present without the security of women. In order to
understand how the dynamics of capital accumulation (re)produce a
social-reproductive contradiction as well as modern gender (and race)
relations, it is necessary, among other things, to functionally determine the social-reproductive significance of the household for capital.
What is certain is that women still do significantly more unpaid
domestic labor than men and are increasingly exposed to (male) violence in their own families. »While the family is fundamental to
women’s oppression in capitalist society, the pivot of this oppression
is not women’s domestic labour for men or children, however op101 Vogel, Marxismus und Frauenunterdrückung, 145.
102 Ibid., 188.
103 Lise Vogel, »Nachtrag: Hausarbeit neu gedacht,« in Marxismus und Frauenunterdrückung: Auf dem Weg zu einer umfassenden Theorie (Münster: Unrast Verlag,
2019 [2000]), 259.
261
262
Vincent Streichhahn
pressive or alienating this might be.«104 However, the household is
undoubtedly one of the central institutions of women’s oppression
because it functions as a venue for the structurally contradictory relationship between reproduction and the accumulation of capital. The
domestic unit receives its oppressive function through its social-reproductive function for capital. This does not mean, however, that
the specific form of this oppression is deterministic and monocausal,
but rather that it is permanently reproduced through processes of
subjectivation.105 The family remains tenacious because it continues
to be the most practicable model for ensuring the necessary reproduction of the commodity of labor at the lowest cost. However, and
this is a central point of SRT, it is not necessarily responsible for the
reproduction of labor.
But why do predominantly women take over reproductive tasks?
Vogel assumes that the biologically limited period of pregnancy in
class societies tends to lead to a gender-specific division of labor and
its institutionalization. Under capitalism, this ›ideally‹ expresses itself
in the form of the bourgeois nuclear family. This does not mean that
women are more caring because of a supposed ›nature‹ and therefore take over predominantly unpaid reproductive work. The private
and domestic tasks are, however, performed according to the biological-physical facts that reproduction and breastfeeding require bodies
of the ›female‹ sex.106 From the perspective of the ruling class, the
bearing of children tends to be cost-intensive, since potentially value-added-producing labor is withdrawn from the market during this
period. At the same time, childbearing is necessary to generatively
reproduce the working class. In this respect, a socially-reproductive
contradiction arises between the highest possible rate of exploitation
104 Ferguson and McNally, »Capital,« xxv.
105 Julia Dück und Katharina Hajek, »›Intime Verhältnisse‹: Eine gesellschaftstheoretische Erweiterung der Debatte um soziale Reproduktion,« in Feminismus und
Marxismus, ed. Alexandra Scheele und Stefanie Wöhl (Weinheim: Beltz Juventa
2018), 220 – 233.
106 Ferguson and McNally, »Capital,« xxv.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
263
and the long-term preservation of the commodity of labor, which
unfolds the fatal dynamic that produces the androcentric gender relations that are reproduced and naturalized every day through cultural
and symbolic practices.107
It is up to the state as »ideal total capitalist«108 to deal politically with this contradiction in the tension between state, market and
family. The relationship between these three classical poles of welfare
state research109 was applied to social reproduction by Nancy Fraser.
She distinguishes three different phases of reproduction from the
19th century until today.110 The extent to which the processes of social
reproduction are organized by the state, commodified or left within
the family is the result of a variety of factors: labor requirements,
economic conditions, class struggles and contingent developments.
Class struggles can influence the value of the commodity labor, since
it is not a fixed quantity. From a classical Marxist perspective, the
workers, traditionally the industrial proletariat, can increase the value of their labor force through union wage struggles in production.
However, on the one hand, this sociological determination of the
working class does not go far enough but, on the other, the rate
of exploitation can also be tweaked through struggles in the public
reproductive sector.111
Moreover, already in Marx’s work, a class is the variable result of a
historical process in which one class constitutes itself in an antagonistic struggle against another class. According to Cinzia Arruzza, one of
the worst political mistakes, therefore, is to want to determine what
107 Pierre Bourdieu, Die männliche Herrschaft (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp,
2005).
108 Friedrich Engels: »Die Entwicklung des Sozialismus von der Utopie zur Wissenschaft,« in MEW, vol. 19 (Berlin: Dietz, 1987 [1880]), 222.
109 Gøsta Esping-Andersen, The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1990).
110 Nancy Fraser, »Contradictions of Capital and Care,« New Left Review 100 (2016):
99 – 117.
111 Kipka and Streichhahn, »Kapital gegen Leben,« 585 – 590.
264
Vincent Streichhahn
is considered class struggle and what is not.112 The feminist struggles
of recent years have initiated a process of class subjectivation that
has made the organized working class more colorful and feminine.
The reproductive strikes carry a huge potential for class struggles to
unfold, since schools and hospitals are essential for the reproduction
of the whole capitalist system and, at the same time, function as crystallization points where different parts of classes meet. This potential
must be used in the struggle for a society free of domination beyond
exploitation and oppression.
For Vogel, as she writes in her essay from 2000, the attempt of
a uniform materialistic theoretical framework is still an unfinished
project. The representatives of SRT have taken up the thread of that
time again. Finally, the SRT is intended to develop a »historical-materialist reading of social power relations that identifies the conditions
under which race, gender, sexuality and class can be (co-)reproduced,
transformed and potentially revolutionized.«113 So the challenges have
not diminished and are by no means solved, but many activists are
working on these important issues in a promising way.
Outlook
Engels’s The Origin of the Family, indissolubly linked to Bebel’s work,
had an immensely important meaning for the political practice of the
labor movement. Bebel and Engels made it possible to partially overcome »proletarian anti-feminism« so that proletarian women — despite continuing resistance — were able to organize themselves in the
ranks of the German Social Democrats after the fall of the Socialist
Laws. Engels had two main reasons for publishing his book. On the
112 Cinzia Arruzza, »From Women’s Strikes to a New Class Movement: The Third
Feminist Wave,« Viewpoint, December 3, 2018, https://www.viewpointmag.
com/2018/12/03/from-womens-strikes-to-a-new-class-movement-the-thirdfeminist-wave/.
113 Ferguson and McNally, »Capital,« xxxvii.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
265
one hand, the publication was a tacit course correction that seemed
necessary to him due to the publication of Bebel’s work. On the other hand, he apparently believed to have found proof of the Marxist
world view in the works of Marx and Morgan. Engels was determined
to present this proof to the public. It was, however, not him but the
book’s reception by female socialists that began a few years after its
publication that made it a classic on this issue.
Nevertheless, with Engels’s book and the dualism postulated
therein, he left behind a momentous revision of Marx, which mainly preoccupied socialist feminists of the second women’s movement.
Fortunately, the approaches of Engels and Marx are not congruent
on this issue. The Marxist method includes the possibility of solving
the theoretical problems raised. It was Lise Vogel who made the first
well-founded attempt to overcome Engels’s dualism within a unitary
materialist theoretical framework. But as she herself has admitted,
this project is still unfinished.
To bring this project to a conclusion is the concern of many Marxist feminists who have been working on the SRT in the last decade.
»Marxist feminist scholars did not simply expand the definition of
›production‹ to include unpaid and racialized reproductive labor as
its hidden center, but asked what it revealed about capitalism as a
whole.«114 I am convinced that SRT is currently the most fruitful attempt, but it is still an immense task that is becoming increasingly
urgent in the face of worsening crises of civilization. There is, however,
a tradition in Marxism that we should turn to more intensively again
in order to deal with these theoretical and practical challenges. Engels
(and Marx), though not his writing on The Origin of the Family, is an
indispensable reference point for this.
114 Armstrong, Marxism and Socialist Feminism.
266
Vincent Streichhahn
Works Cited
Armstrong, Elisabeth. Marxist and Socialist Feminism. Northampton, MA:
Smith College, Faculty Publications.
Arruzza, Cinzia. »From Women’s Strikes to a New Class Movement: The
Third Feminist Wave.« Viewpoint, December 3, 2018. https://www.view
pointmag.com/2018/12/03/from-womens-strikes-to-a-new-class-move
ment-the-third-feminist-wave/.
Badia, Gilbert. Clara Zetkin: Eine neue Biographie. Berlin: Dietz, 1994.
Barrett, Michèle. »Introduction.« In The Origin of the Family, Private Property
and the State. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1986.
Bebel, August. »Die Frau und der Sozialismus.« In Ausgewählte Reden und
Schriften, vol. 10, edited by Internationales Institut für Sozialgeschichte
Amsterdam. Munich: K. G. Sauer, 1996 [1879].
Benston, Margaret. »The Political Economy of Women’s Liberation.« Monthly Review 21, no. 4 (1969): 13 – 27.
Bhattacharya, Tithi. »Liberating Women from ›Political Economy‹: Margaret Benston’s Marxism and a Social-Reproduction Approach to Gender
Oppression.« Monthly Review, January 1, 2020. https://monthlyreview.
org/2020/01/01/liberating-women-from-political-economy/.
Bhattacharya, Tithi, ed. Social Reproduction Theory: Remapping Class, Recentering Oppression. London: Pluto Books, 2017.
Blackledge, Paul. »Frederick Engels, Social Reproduction, and the Problem
of a Unitary Theory of Women’s Oppression.« Social Theory and Practice
44, no. 3 (July 2018): 297 – 321.
Bohlender, Matthias. »Marx, Engels und der ›wahre Sozialismus‹ oder: Die
Geburt des ›historischen Materialismus‹ aus dem Handgemenge‹«. In ›Kritik im Handgemenge‹. Die Marx’sche Gesellschaftskritik als politischer Einsatz,
edited by Matthias Bohlender et al., 15–49. Bielefeld: Transcript, 2018.
Bourdieu, Pierre. Die männliche Herrschaft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp,
2005.
Brandt, Willy. »Hundert Jahre nach August Bebel. Ein Bestseller dient der
Gleichberechtigung.« In Frauen heute. Eine Bestandsaufnahme, edited by
Willy Brandt. Reinbek: Rowohlt, 1981.
Brown, Heather A. Marx on Gender and the Family: A Critical Study. Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2013.
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
267
Burgard, Roswitha and Gaby Karsten. Die Märchenonkel der Frauenfrage:
Friedrich Engels und August Bebel. Berlin: Frauen-Selbstverlag, 1975.
Carver, Terrell. »Marxism and Feminism: Living with Your ›Ex‹.« In Karl
Marx and Contemporary Philosophy, edited by Andrew Chitty and Martin
McIvor. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009.
Cox, Judy. »How Marx and Engels fought for women’s liberation.« International
Socialism, March 29, 2020. https://isj.org.uk/jcox-marx-engels-women-lib/.
Dalla Costa, Mariarosa and Selma James. The Power of Women and the Subversion of the Community. Bristol: Falling Wall Press, 1972.
De Beauvoir, Simone. Das andere Geschlecht: Sitte und Sexus der Frau. Hamburg: Rowohlt, 1983 [1949].
Delap, Lucy. »The ›Woman Question‹ and the Origins of Feminism.« In
The Cambridge History of Nineteenth Century Political Thought, edited
by Gareth Stedman Jones and Gregory Claeys. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2011.
Dück, Julia and Katharina Hajek. »›Intime Verhältnisse‹: Eine gesellschaftstheoretische Erweiterung der Debatte um soziale Reproduktion.« In
Feminismus und Marxismus, edited by Alexandra Scheele und Stefanie
Wöhl, 220 – 233. Weinheim: Beltz Juventa, 2018.
Dunayevskaya, Raya. Rosa Luxemburg, Women’s Liberation, and Marx’s Philosophy of Revolution. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1982.
Engels, Friedrich. »Der Ursprung der Familie, des Privateigentums und des
Staats.« In Marx-Engels-Werke, vol. 21. Berlin: Dietz, 1962.
Engels, Friedrich. »Die Entwicklung des Sozialismus von der Utopie zur
Wissenschaft.« In Marx-Engels-Werke, vol. 19. Berlin: Dietz, 1987 [1880].
Engels, Friedrich. »Die Lage der arbeitenden Klasse in England.« In MarxEngels-Werke, vol. 2. Berlin: Dietz, 1972 [1845]
Engels, Friedrich. »Engels an Karl Kautsky, 16. Februar 1884.« in MarxEngels-Werke, vol. 36. Berlin: Dietz, 1979.
Esping-Andersen, Gøsta. The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism. Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990.
Evans, Richard. Sozialdemokratie und Frauenemanzipation im deutschen Kaisserreich. Bonn: Dietz Verlag, 1979.
Ferguson, Susan and David McNally. »Capital, Labour-Power, and Gender-Relations: Introduction to the Historical Materialism Edition of
Marxism and the Oppression of Women.« In Lise Vogel, Marxism and
268
Vincent Streichhahn
the Oppression of Women: Toward a Unitary Theory, xvii-xl. Chicago: Haymarket Books, 2013.
Fraser, Nancy. »Contradictions of Capital and Care.« New Left Review 100
(2016): 99 – 117.
Haarmann, Elisabeth. Schwestern zur Sonne zur Gleichheit: Die Anfänge der
proletarischen Frauenbewegung. Hamburg: Ergebnisse-Verlag, 1985.
Hervé, Florence, ed. Geschichte der deutschen Frauenbewegung. Cologne:
Pahl-Rugenstein, 1982.
Hoock-Demarle, Marie-Claire. »Frauen und Frauenemanzipation in Engels
Briefen.« MEGA-Studien Journal 2 (1996): 54 – 65.
Inman, Mary. In Woman’s Defense. Los Angeles: The Committee to Organize
the Advancement of Women, 1940.
Kautsky, Benedikt, ed. Friedrich Engels Briefwechsel mit Karl Kautsky. Vienna:
Danubia-Verlag, 1955.
Kautsky, Karl. »Die Entstehung der Ehe und der Familie.« Kosmos: Zeitschrift
für einheitliche Weltanschauung auf Grund der Entwicklungslehre 12, no. 2
(1882): 190 – 207.
Kipka, Ronda and Vincent Streichhahn, »Kapital gegen Leben: Plädoyer für
einen politik-ökonomischen Reproduktionsbegriff.« Prokla 197, no. 4
(2019): 585 – 590.
Klinger, Cornelia. »Weder eine bürgerliche Ehe noch eine perverse Wahlverwandtschaft: Von Liberalismus und Frauenbewegung zu Neoliberalismus und Postfeminismus.« In Liberalismus: Traditionsbestände und Gegenwartskontroversen, edited by Karsten Fischer and Sebastian Huhnholz.
Baden-Baden: Nomos, 2019.
Krader, Lawrence. »Einleitung.« In Die ethnologischen Exzerpthefte, edited by
Lawrence Krader. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1976.
Krupskaja, Nadežda Konstantinovna. Zhenschina-rabotnica [The Woman
Worker]. Munich, 1901.
Lion, Hilde. Zur Soziologie der Frauenbewegung: Die sozialistische und die
katholische Frauenbewegung. Berlin: Herbig, 1926.
Marx Aveling, Eleanor and Edward Aveling. »The Woman Question: From a
Socialist Point of View.« Westminster Review 125 (1886): 207 – 222
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. »Die deutsche Ideologie.« In MarxEngels-Werke, vol. 3. Berlin: Dietz, 1969 [1846].
Marx, Karl. »Der Akkumulationsprozeß des Kapitals.« In Marx-Engels-Werke,
vol. 23. Berlin: Dietz, 1962 [1867].
Friedrich Engels: From the ›Woman Question‹ to Social Reproduction Theory
269
Marx, Karl. »Einleitung: Zur Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie.« In MarxEngels-Werke, vol. 13. Berlin: Dietz, 1971 [1857].
Marx, Karl. »Lohn, Preis und Profit.« In Marx-Engels-Werke, vol. 16. Berlin:
Dietz, 1962 [1865].
Millett, Kate. Sexus und Herrschaft. Die Tyrannei des Mannes in unserer Gesellschaft. Munich: Desch, 1971.
Morgan, Lewis H. Ancient Society. Tucson: University of Arizona Press, 1995
[1877].
Nagel, Editha. »Zur Geschichte der unmittelbaren Entstehung von Friedrich
Engels’s Schrift ›Der Ursprung der Familie, des Privateigentums und des
Staates‹ und ihre Herausgabe in Deutschland (1884 – 1894).« Beiträge zur
Marx-Engels-Forschung 3 (1978): 125 – 141.
Niggemann, Heinz. Emanzipation zwischen Sozialismus und Feminismus: Die
sozialdemokratische Frauenbewegung im Kaiserreich. Wuppertal: Hammer,
1981.
Planert, Ute. Antifeminismus im Kaiserreich: Diskurs, soziale Formation und
politische Mentalität. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1998.
Richebächer, Sabine. Uns fehlt nur eine Kleinigkeit: Deutsche proletarische
Frauenbewegung. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch-Verlag, 1982.
Sachse, Mirjam. Von ›weiblichen Vollmenschen‹ und Klassenkämpferinnen:
Frauengeschichte und Frauenleitbilder in der proletarischen Frauenzeitschrift
›Die Gleichheit‹ (1891 – 1923). Kassel: Universitätsbibliothek Kassel, 2011.
Scharinger, Manfred. Geschlechterverhältnisse bei Marx und Engels: Eine
kritische Auseinandersetzung. Vienna: Arbeitsgruppe Marxismus, 2007.
Scharinger, Manfred. Proletarische Frauenbewegung. Kritische Bilanz und
politische Lehren. Vienna: Arbeitsgruppe Marxismus, 2009.
Seccombe, Wally. »The Housewife and Her Labour under Capitalism.« New
Left Review 83, no. 1 (1974): 3 – 24.
Stark, Sam. »Marx und die Frauenfrage.« Zeitschrift für Ideengeschichte 11,
no. 3 (2017): 55 – 66.
Thönnessen, Werner. Frauenemanzipation: Politik und Literatur der Deutschen
Sozialdemokratie zur Frauenbewegung (1863 – 1933). Frankfurt am Main:
Europäische Verlangsanstalt, 1969.
Twellmann, Margrit. Die deutsche Frauenbewegung: Ihre Anfänge und erste
Entwicklung 1843 – 1889. Kronberg: Athenäum-Verlag, 1976.
Vogel, Lise. »Hausarbeitsdebatte.« In Historisch-kritisches Wörterbuch, vol. 1,
edited by Frigga Haug, 540 – 554. Hamburg: Argument Verlag, 2003.
270
Vincent Streichhahn
Vogel, Lise. »Nachtrag: Hausarbeit neu gedacht.« In Marxismus und
Frauenunterdrückung: Auf dem Weg zu einer umfassenden Theorie. Münster: Unrast Verlag, 2019 [2000].
Vogel, Lise. Marxismus und Frauenunterdrückung: Auf dem Weg zu einer umfassenden Theorie. Münster: Unrast Verlag, 2019 [1983].
Welskopp, Thomas. »›Der Geist ächt männlichen Strebens‹: Mikropolitik
und Geschlechterbeziehungen im Vereinsmilieu der frühen deutschen
Arbeiterbewegung.« Kurswechsel 3 (1997): 67 – 81.
In the Shadow of Karl Marx
Perception and Reception of Friedrich Engels
in the Digital Age
Riccardo Altieri
Reciprocity or Hierarchy?
The following article is dedicated to Friedrich Engels’s perception in
academic literature. The aim is to determine why Engels was often
overshadowed by Karl Marx, how he has been ›ignored‹ in the literature, and what influence this shift in perception has had on his
own biography. The center of this study will be his presence on the
Internet compared to that of Marx. Is there a reciprocity of both or
a kind of hierarchy, where Marx is ranked (far) above Engels? But
before talking about the two by name, a comparison of the concepts
that subsume their theories under one term should take place first.
If one searches for the German term ›Engelsismus‹ on the Internet,
one will get different results on different platforms: while Google (G)
has 964 hits, there are 983 on Ecosia (E) and 71,800 on Bing (B) and
Yahoo (Y).1 The English translation ›Engelsism‹ has 4,050 (B / E / Y)
and 45,500 (G) hits. Comparing these terms with the corresponding
terms ›Marxismus‹ and ›Marxism,‹ it can be quickly realized that Marx
outperforms his contemporary Engels everywhere (Fig. 1).
1
Searches were conducted on Bing.com, Ecosia.org, Google.com, and Yahoo.com.
Because of the often-identical algorithms behind B, E, and Y, the results are
sometimes but not always the same. The used data are to be understood purely
quantitatively; there is no qualitative differentiation regarding the plausibility of
the search results.
272
Riccardo Altieri
matches
for
Engelsismus
Marxismus
Engelsism
Marxism
71,800
450,000
4,050
4,030,000
Ecosia (E)
983
450,000
4,050
4,030,000
Google (G)
964
1,520,000
45,500
13,600,000
Yahoo (Y)
71,800
450,000
4,050
4,030,000
on
Bing (B)
Fig. 1: Search engine results for Marxism and Engelsism in German and
English. Search date: April 4th, 2020.
A look at the results on Google, for example, offers the following:
while the term ›Marxismus‹ is approximately 1,575 times more common than ›Engelsismus,‹ we find comparable tendencies for the English translation: there, the term ›Marxism‹ scores nearly 300 times
more hits than »Engelsism.« But do these numbers really reflect the
performance ratio of the theoretical impact of those two authors? The
Berlin Institute for Critical Theory would maybe contradict this assumption. In his Historical-Critical Dictionary of Marxism, Sven-Eric
Liedmann wrote: »In a way, what has been commonly referred to as
›Marxism‹ since about 1890 is more a creation of Friedrich Engels
than Karl Marx, so that Arnold Künzli could say that the expression
›E[ngelsism]‹ was actually more appropriate.«2 A second tool provided
by Google is one called Google Trends. Unfortunately, it is only possible to check the data from 2004 until the present, but in these years,
another unambiguous fact emerges: Karl Marx (red) has an average
impact of 27, while that of Friedrich Engels (blue) is only 3 (Fig. 2).
The peak in 2018 refers to the 200th birthday of Karl Marx, which also
had minor repercussions on the impact value of Engels.
2
Sven-Eric Liedmann, »Engelsismus,« in Historisch-Kritisches Wörterbuch des
Marxismus, vol. 3: Ebene — Extremismus, ed. Wolfgang Fritz Haug (Hamburg:
Argument-Verlag, 1997), 384. This refers to Arnold Künzli, Karl Marx. Eine Psychographie (Wien: Europa, 1966), 18. See also Helmut Hirsch, Friedrich Engels in
Selbsterzeugnissen und Bilddokumenten (Hamburg: Rowohlt, 1968).
273
In the Shadow of Karl Marx
2004
2009
2015
Fig. 2: Google Trends for Marx (red) and Engels (blue). © Google Trends, April 4th, 2020.
2020
274
Riccardo Altieri
Although terms such as the former Marx-Engels Institute in
Moscow, the Marx-Engels Works (Marx-Engels-Werke, MEW) or the
Marx-Engels Complete Edition (Marx-Engels-Gesamtausgabe, MEGA2)
have the names of both philosophers in their titles, Karl Marx was
always in the spotlight while Friedrich Engels stepped back. But this
imbalance was not always so.
Engels vs. Marx?
At the beginning, Engels even stood before Marx. In the first years of
the Second International, Engels was considered an »undisputed authority,« even an »oracle,« by labor leaders and theorists.3 How, when
and where did this shift of perspective occur, then? »The orthodox
Marxist-Leninist myth looks at Marx and Engels as intellectual twins
who took on different tasks for practical reasons.«4 Accordingly, the
short-term dominance of Engels can be determined during the early
phase of his work, which is replaced by a reciprocity for the duration
of orthodox Marxism-Leninism before Karl Marx was clearly granted
preference in contemporary history and the digital age. Any kind of
partisanship and comparison of the two, however, requires critical
consideration, since it mostly takes place superficially.5
Again and again, Engels was accused of making fundamental mistakes in his reading of Marx, which would have led to a complete
distortion of content that can still be found in the perception and
reception through adaptation.6 Even Engels himself had problems
with adequately reviewing Marx’s works, did not feel empowered, and
3
4
5
6
Liedmann, »Engelsismus,« 384.
Ibid.
Ingo Elbe, »Die Beharrlichkeit des ›Engelsismus‹. Bemerkungen zum ›Marx-Engels-Problem‹,« in Marx-Engels-Jahrbuch 2007, ed. Beatrix Bouvier et al.
(München: Oldenbourg Akademie-Verlag, 2008), 105.
Ingo Elbe, Marx im Westen. Die neue Marxlektüre in der Bundesrepublik seit 1965
(Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 2008), 24; Jan Hoff, Marx global. Zur Entwicklung
des internationalen Marx-Diskurses seit 1965 (Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 2008), 199.
In the Shadow of Karl Marx
275
was almost forced by his friend to grant him such a favor.7 Engels
wrote: »Marx was a genius, the rest of us at most were talents.«8 Jürgen Herres would contradict Engels here because, in his opinion, the
latter was equal to his friend in terms of education, knowledge and
language, and even superior in his linguistic skills.9 But later, he became part of the ›Marx Party‹ and voluntarily submitted to his friend.
Together they built a »unity of the different ones.«10 In the year of
Engels’s 200th birthday, Hein Paler published a German book with
the expressive title Friedrich Engels: The Creative Shadow, which is
symbolic of his hidden-remaining character.11
It is common knowledge that Engels came from a well-known
family of entrepreneurs, lived a bourgeois lifestyle throughout his
life — recognizable by clothing style, living situation and habitus — and even owned millions in shares. Many only saw him as a socialist, comparable to a prophet who preaches water but then drinks
wine himself, or in his case, champagne. He left not only £2 million
on his death, but also 150 bottles of the expensive French beverage.12
But was it not precisely his financial security that made Marx’s work
even possible? Engels is not the only millionaire in history who was
also a socialist or communist: Felix Weil, for example, was close to the
Communist Party of Germany (KPD), and later the Communist Party of Germany (Opposition) (KPO) and also the Socialist Workers‹
Party (SAP);13 Diether Dehm is a member of Die Linke (The Left) in
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
Previously contradicted by Hans-Holger Paul, Marx, Engels und die Imperialismustheorie der II. Internationale (Hamburg: VSA-Verlag, 1978), 55.
Elbe, Marx, 105.
Quoted in Jürgen Herres, Marx und Engels. Porträt einer intellektuellen Freundschaft (Stuttgart: Reclam, 2018), 18.
Ibid., 19.
Ibid., 7.
See Hein Paler, Friedrich Engels — Der kreative Schatten (Norderstedt: Books on
Demand, 2020).
Ibid., 16 – 17.
See Jeanette Erazo Heufelder, Der argentinische Krösus. Kleine Wirtschaftsgeschichte der Frankfurter Schule (Berlin: Berenberg-Verlag, 2017).
276
Riccardo Altieri
the German Bundestag;14 and the Marxist-Leninist Party of Germany
(MLPD) receives financial support from millionaires and their heirs
for each election campaign15 — to name just three arbitrary examples.
What they all have in common is that they themselves were never in
the front row of the political movement, but always acted as patrons
in the background or played a somewhat different subordinate role.
If we speak today of Marxism and less often of Engelsism, their
works were by no means closed theories. Rather, it can be seen as a
fragmentary œuvre. While Marx still published the first volume of
Das Kapital during his lifetime, volumes 2 and 3 were edited and published by Engels after Marx’s death.16 Taking everything into account,
their work should be understood primarily as a contribution to early
globalization and its counter-movement.17 It was precisely because he
was so close to Marx that Engels was perfect for publishing and continuing his work.18 But this is also the main reason for his position
within the reception of Marxist history. Michael Krätke stated that
for the duration of orthodox Marxism-Leninism, the perceptions of
Engels in the West and in the East went through different stages of
development. In the Soviet Union and its allied states, the image of
Engels had an increasingly negative connotation. »As a result, Engels
was forgotten as a historian, as a political theorist and as a military
specialist, and as a whole his intellectual achievement was irrelevant,
14
15
16
17
18
Peter Jochen Winters, »Ist die PDS am Ende?,« in Zehn Jahre Deutsche Einheit.
Eine Bilanz, ed. Wolfgang Thierse (Opladen: Leske+Budrich, 2000), 107.
Kevin Hagen, »Sieger im Klassenkampf. Jahr für Jahr kassiert die linksextreme
Splitterpartei MLPD riesige Summen von privaten Einzelspendern. Warum ist das
so? Geschichten über das revolutionäre Erbe,« Spiegel online, December 29, 2015,
https://www.spiegel.de/politik/deutschland/mlpd-die-grossspender-der-kom
munisten-a-1069871.html.
Herres, Marx und Engels, 11.
Ibid., 12 – 13.
Michael R. Krätke, »Das Marx-Engels-Problem: Warum Engels das Marxsche
›Kapital‹ nicht verfälscht hat,« in Marx-Engels-Jahrbuch 2006, ed. Beatrix Beauvier et al. (München: Oldenbourg Akademie-Verlag, 2007), 142.
In the Shadow of Karl Marx
277
compared to the Marxian, his work was not congenially and rather
negatively dismissed.«19
Reception
What did the reception of Engels look like in later decades? If one
considers, for example, the 1st volume of the 2nd edition of Gustav Mayer’s important Engels biography from 1934, Engels appears
there over 1,200 times (Fig. 3). Marx, however, is only mentioned 496
times.20 So Engels is mentioned about two and a half times as often as
his friend. But how about in other works on both or written by them?
Of course, there is no publication that reaches the ideal value of
1.0, since that would mean that Marx’s and Engels’s names were mentioned exactly the same number of times. But as these twenty examples clearly show, there are unambiguous trends: in the eight works
that have Friedrich Engels as their central theme, the Engels-Marx
factor always exceeds the value of 1.0. Conversely, this value always
fell below 1.0 in the six books that have Marx as their main subject.
It really becomes interesting when looking at the values for the six
examples that can be assigned to Marx and Engels equally. There, the
value falls below 1.0 in each and every case. Although this tendency
does not guarantee general statements, it allows forecasts that go in a
clear direction: at least in the works that deal equally with Marx and
Engels, Engels is apparently fundamentally surpassed by Marx — at
least when it comes to the simple frequency of their names appearing.
In the tabular example, Dethmann’s work from 1920 (-1.19) achieved
the ›best‹ value, whereas the ›worst‹ result was achieved by Eubanks in
1984 (-3.61). Of all twenty examples chosen, Dethmann also achieved
the ›top‹ result in the overall comparison. This work is the second
oldest of those reviewed, whereas the ›worst‹ result in total was in the
19
20
Ibid., 143.
Gustav Mayer, Friedrich Engels. Eine Biographie. Erster Band: Friedrich Engels in
seiner Frühzeit (The Hague: Springer Science+Business Media, 1934).
278
20 random works
by release date
Riccardo Altieri
Engels Biographies
Engels
Marx
factor
Marx Biographies
Engels
Marx
factor
126
150
-1.19
440
919
-2.09
Marx/Engels, Articles (1969).
243
320
-1.32
Marx/Engels, Paris
Commune (1980).
137
369
-2.69
Eubanks, Marxism
[1984].
508
1,834
-3.61
407
721
-1.77
Mehring, Karl Marx
[1918].
Engels
Marx
factor
806
1,820
-2.26
Books on/by both
Dethmann, Rätegedanke (1920).
Mayer, Friedrich
Engels [1920].
1,206
496
+2.43
Marx/Engels, Die
deutsche Ideologie
[1932].
Mescheryakov, Life
and Work (1933).
64
196
-3.06
Berlin, Karl Marx
[1939].
119
680
-5.71
McLellan, Karl
Marx [1973].
718
3,305
-4.60
Rosdolsky, Friedrich
Engels [1964].
Stepanova, Frederick
Engels [1985].
552
1,040
208
807
+2.65
+1.29
Schmitt, Introduction [1987].
Carver, Friedrich
Engels (1990).
1,243
502
+2.48
Boden, Red Clausewitz (2001).
1,325
235
+5.64
Hunt, Marx’s General (2009).
1,623
753
+2.16
Hollander, Friedrich
Engels (2011).
1,911
802
+2.38
In the Shadow of Karl Marx
279
Sperber, Karl Marx
(2013).
555
2,448
Heinrich, Karl Marx
(2018).
141
1,479 -10.49
Brie, Sozialist-werden (2020).
543
148
-4.41
+3.67
Fig. 3: The Engels-Marx Ratio in (Biographical) Literature (1918 – 2020)21.
© Riccardo Altieri, April 8th, 2020.
second most recent study, namely Heinrich’s Marx biography from
2018 (-10.49). The best overall result was achieved by the Master’s thesis by Michael A. Boden, a Major in the US Army, from 2001 (+5.64).
Especially in Germany, as a non-academic, Engels always had a
hard time surviving in front of the inflated Marx. He had no high
school or university degree and no doctorate. Or, as Krätke sums it
up, »[i]n Germany, where academic cretinism has always blossomed,
one has to add: the man wasn’t even habilitated!«22 Until today, Engels’s own creativity is defined by his work in the service of Marx; for
example, by the fact that he is considered to be the one whom Marx
could always trust without reservation.23 In Western Marxism, there
is also the exaggerated accusation that Engels did not understand his
friend’s work; maybe he defined Marxism, but he also garbled it up.
He was accused of not having published the Marxian work in its orig21
22
23
All data for this survey come from files of the works of Marx and Engels that
can be obtained in some way on the Internet. The formula for the factor follows
mathematical law: big number divided by small number equals the factor. If the
numerical value is exactly 1.0, there is a reciprocity between Engels and Marx. If
the factor is bigger than 1.0, there is a gradient between Engels and Marx, and if
it is smaller than 1.0 there is an incline between Engels and Marx. Of course, it
is possible that the data are slightly distorted, considering that the name ›Marx‹
also appears in terms such as ›Marxism‹ or can refer to relatives with the same
surname who are mentioned in the books. This also applies to Engelsism and the
Engels family. So, this approach in fact underlines the argument.
Krätke, »Marx-Engels-Problem,« 143, fn. 5.
Ibid., 143 – 144.
280
Riccardo Altieri
inal wording. In doing so, he changed the text to such an extent that
it seems possible to speak of a falsification.24 However, let us get back
to the digital age.
Engels and Marx in the Digital Age
The results from various online search engines for the terms »Engelsismus / Engelsism« and »Marxismus / Marxism« have already been
presented. But how about target words like »Friedrich Engels« and
»Karl Marx«? In the following table (Fig. 4), the searchable platforms
named before have been supplemented by specifically academic ones.
The number of scientific search engines is of course significantly
higher than the chosen selection. However, in order not to exceed
the confines of an essay, a maximum number of twenty was set again.
In addition to the four search engines already used, sixteen explicitly
academic tools were added. The decisive factor was not the level of
the results obtained, but rather their general level of awareness. Although B, E and Y again use the same search algorithms, their result
factor (-5.72) is slightly better than that of G (-6.06), which, however,
was able to achieve significantly more hits. What is essential to note
is how much higher the number of hits was in all four cases for the
search term »Karl Marx« compared to »Friedrich Engels.« And this
one-sided trend unfortunately also runs through all the academic
search engines.
The highest hit results were achieved for »Friedrich Engels« on infotopia (1,300,000) and for »Karl Marx« on VirtualLRC (19,700,000).
But both search engines are among the four ›worst‹ when it comes to
optimizing the Engels-Marx factor. The top result was achieved by academic.microsoft.org (-1.55), which had the lowest hit rate, followed
by Science.gov (-2.12). But however the numbers get interpreted, each
24
Ibid., 147. See also Michael Heinrich, »Engels’s Edition of the Third Volume of
Capital, and Marx’s Original Manuscript,« Science and Society 60, no. 4 (1995).
In the Shadow of Karl Marx
target words
281
Karl
Marx
factor
searchable platforms
Friedrich
Engels
Bing.com (B)
1,030,000
5,890,000
-5.72
Ecosia.org (E)
1,030,000
5,890,000
-5.72
Google.com (G)
4,260,000
25,800,000
-6.06
Yahoo.com (Y)
1,030,000
5,890,000
-5.72
143
25,678
1 346
146,000
-9.41
-5.68
293
455
-1.55
Baidu.com
15,800
75,100
-4.75
base-search.net
1,142
10,806
-9.46
core.ac.uk
12,669
71,445
-5.64
Academia.edu
Paper titles
Papers (full articles)
academic.microsoft.org
126,000
1,040,000
-8.25
Infotopia
1,300,000
15,400,000
-11.85
jstor.org
10,636
60,666
-5.70
Libgen.is
421
999
-2.37
329,000
4,130,000
-12.55
ScienceDirect.com
529
7,857
-14.85
Science.gov
198
419
-2.12
13,400
71,400
-5.33
1,060,000
19,700,000
-18.58
22,295
120,001
-5.38
702
1,482
-2.11
Google Scholar
refseek.com
semanticscholar.org
VirtualLRC.com
worldcat.org
worldwidescience.org
Fig. 4: Search results for Marx and Engels on academic platforms.
© Riccardo Altieri, April 9th, 2020
282
Riccardo Altieri
result reflects that Karl Marx can be found in the digital world many
times more often than his friend and contemporary Friedrich Engels.
This process, which has now lasted well over 100 years and has only
recently emerged in the digital age, is unstoppable in its development
and also irreversible.
Freed from the dogmata of the Cold War era, this observation is
just an observation and nothing else. No course corrections or sentimentalities are required here. For historical science, data can be
derived from this on the question of how an apparently historically
equivalent personality can be marginalized over decades by setting an
ideological focus. Internal Marxist debates showed long ago that, in
the case of Engels vs. Marx, there is no ›right‹ or ›wrong.‹ But in addition to this special situation, methodical-analytical approaches are
also appropriate for comparable ›twin pairs‹ in history: for example,
Romulus and Remus, Goethe and Schiller, or Liebknecht and Luxemburg. Almost always, one benefited from the other and outshone his
partner through his own growth — intentionally or unintentionally.
Final remarks
To take a step back, Marx position and ranking was, to a certain extent,
a conscious decision by Friedrich Engels himself, too. To name just
one example, Marx’s death in the year of 1883 should be mentioned
here. When he died, friends like Johann Philipp Becker (1809 – 1886)
wrote about him as »the mightiest head of our party.«25 But Engels
also put him on an indisputable podium. Instead of talking about
the loss of his friend, in his funeral speech, he regretted the loss of
his fellow combatant and spoke of him as the »greatest living thinker«: »Like Darwin with the law of the development of organic na25
Quoted in Hans Peter Bleuel, Friedrich Engels. Bürger und Revolutionär. Die zeitgerechte Biographie eines großen Deutschen (Bern / München: Scherz-Verlag, 1981),
359.
In the Shadow of Karl Marx
283
ture, Marx discovered the law of development of human history.«26
German Social Democrats, specifically August Bebel, asked Engels to
give up his British exile and come back to Germany. But he refused.27
Perhaps that would have been the moment when Engels could have
stepped out of the shadows to follow in the footsteps of his revered
friend. Instead, he devoted himself to the publication of the estate,
thereby increasing Marx’s later reputation.
In the first foreword to the 1883 German edition of the Communist Manifesto, which he signed alone, Engels wrote: »Unfortunately, I
have to sign the foreword to the current edition alone. Marx, the man
to whom the entire working class of Europe and America owes more
than anyone else — Marx lies in the Highgate cemetery, and the first
grass is already growing over his grave.« Then he put forward the basic ideas of the manifesto, which he had written together with Marx,
only to add: »This basic idea belongs only and exclusively to Marx. I
have said this many times, but it is necessary now to do it also before
the ›Manifesto‹ itself.«28 In the foreword to the English edition of 1888,
he reduced his performance in the manifesto even further: »Although
the ›Manifesto‹ was the work we both did, I feel obliged to state that
the basic idea at its core belongs to Marx.«29
A question might now arise as to why Engelsism never really developed alongside Marxism, especially in a positive connotation. Rudolf Walther knows the right answer when he writes about Engels
that »[t]he one who lived, thought, and wrote so freely was and is too
good for a church, a sect, or a party and all their Isms.«30 But apart
26
27
28
29
30
Quoted in ibid., 360.
Ibid., 362 – 363.
Friedrich Engels, »Vorwort zur deutschen Ausgabe1883,« in Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei, ed. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engel (Berlin: Karl-Dietz-Verlag,
1959), xvii-xviii.
Friedrich Engels, »Vorrede zur englischen Ausgabe von 1888,« in Manifest der
Kommunistischen Partei, ed. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engel (Berlin: Karl-DietzVerlag, 1959), xxiii.
Rudolf Walther, Aufgreifen, begreifen, angreifen. Historische Essays, Porträts, politische Kommentare, Glossen, Verrisse (Münster: Oktober Verlag, 2011), 232.
284
Riccardo Altieri
from that, the question about why Marx is clearly overrepresented on
the Internet, as he previously was in the literature, remains justified,
and we must also ask how Engels can be better served in the future.
If there were no answers to this, science would have no choice but to
agree with Engels in his humble judgment when he wrote to Eduard
Bernstein (1850 – 1932) while Marx was still alive, which he expressed
as follows: »I don’t understand how to be jealous of a genius; it is such
a thing of its own kind that we, who do not have it, know in advance
that it is unreachable for us.«31 The 200th birthday of Engels may at
least increase interest in the man, who was an important intellectual
not only following Marx, but next to him.
A judgment by Josef Stalin (1878 – 1953) that he expressed on Engels
should convince the last doubters, however, that the philosopher deserves to be put in the spotlight as an independent personality — and,
of course, in contrast to the dictator’s purge fantasies: »Even Engels
was not right about everything. It wouldn’t be a bad thing if we could
implicate Engels somewhere in Nikolai Bukharin’s (1888 – 1938) writing.«32 It is well-known what Stalin thought of Bukharin, although
his murder was a completely different way of removing someone from
the collective memory.
Works Cited
Berlin, Isaiah. Karl Marx. His Life and Environment. 4th ed. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2002 [1939].
Bleuel, Hans Peter. Friedrich Engels. Bürger und Revolutionär. Die zeitgerechte
Biographie eines großen Deutschen. Bern / München: Scherz-Verlag, 1981.
Boden, Michael A. »›The First Red Clausewitz‹: Friedrich Engels and Early
Socialist Military Theory, 1848 – 1870.« MA diss., U. S. Army Command
and General Staff College, 2001.
31
32
Quoted in Herres, Marx und Engels, 18.
Quoted in Alan Bullock, Hitler and Stalin: Parallel Lives (Toronto: McClelland &
Stewart, 1993), 402.
In the Shadow of Karl Marx
285
Brie, Michael. Sozialist-werden. Friedrich Engels in Manchester und Barmen,
1842 – 1845. Berlin: Rosa-Luxemburg-Stiftung, 2019.
Bullock, Alan. Hitler and Stalin: Parallel Lives. Toronto: McClelland &
Stewart, 1993.
Carver, Terrell. Friedrich Engels. His Life and Thought. New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 1990.
Dethmann, Adolf. »Der Rätegedanke als Staatstheorie und seine Keime in den
Schriften von Karl Marx und Friedrich Engels.« PhD thesis, Kiel, 1920.
Elbe, Ingo. »Die Beharrlichkeit des ›Engelsismus‹. Bemerkungen zum
›Marx-Engels-Problem‹«. In Marx-Engels-Jahrbuch 2007, edited by Beatrix
Bouvier et al., 92 – 105. München: Oldenbourg Akademie-Verlag, 2008.
—. Marx im Westen. Die neue Marx-Lektüre in der Bundesrepublik seit 1965.
Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 2008.
Engels, Friedrich. »Vorrede zur englischen Ausgabe von 1888.« In Manifest
der Kommunistischen Partei, edited by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels,
xix-xxv. Berlin: Karl-Dietz-Verlag, 1959.
—. »Vorwort zur deutschen Ausgabe von 1883.« In Manifest der Kommunistischen Partei, edited by Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, xvii-xviii. Berlin: Karl-Dietz-Verlag, 1959.
Erazo Heufelder, Jeanette. Der argentinische Krösus. Kleine Wirtschaftsgeschichte der Frankfurter Schule. Berlin: Berenberg-Verlag, 2017.
Eubanks, Cecil L. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. An Analytical Bibliography.
2nd ed. London / New York: Routledge, 2015 [1984].
Hagen, Kevin. »Sieger im Klassenkampf. Jahr für Jahr kassiert die linksextreme Splitterpartei MLPD riesige Summen von privaten Einzelspendern. Warum ist das so? Geschichten über das revolutionäre Erbe.« Spiegel
online, December 29, 2015. https://www.spiegel.de/politik/deutschland/
mlpd-die-grossspender-der-kommunisten-a-1069871.html.
Heinrich, Michael. »Engel’s Edition of the Third Volume of Capital, and
Marx’s Original Manuscript.« Science and Society 60, no. 4 (1995): 452– 466.
—. Karl Marx and the Birth of Modern Society: The Life of Marx and the
Development of His Work. Vol. I: 1818 – 1841. New York: Monthly Review
Press, 2018.
Herres, Jürgen. Marx und Engels. Porträt einer intellektuellen Freundschaft.
Stuttgart: Reclam, 2018.
Hirsch, Helmut. Friedrich Engels in Selbstzeugnissen und Bilddokumenten.
11th ed. Hamburg: Rowohlt, 1968.
286
Riccardo Altieri
Hoff, Jan. Marx global. Zur Entwicklung des internationalen Marx-Diskurses
seit 1965. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag, 2009.
Hollander, Samuel. Friedrich Engels and Marxian Political Economy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.
Hunt, Tristram. Marx’s General: The Revolutionary Life of Friedrich Engels.
New York: Metropolitan Books, 2009.
Krätke, Michael R. »Das Marx-Engels-Problem: Warum Engels das Marxsche ›Kapital‹ nicht verfälscht hat.« In Marx-Engels-Jahrbuch 2006, edited by Beatrix Bouvier et al., 142 – 170. München: Oldenbourg Akademie-Verlag, 2007.
Künzli, Arnold. Karl Marx. Eine Psychographie. Wien: Europa, 1966.
Liedmann, Sven-Eric. »Engelsismus.« In Historisch-Kritisches Wörterbuch des
Marxismus, vol. 3: Ebene — Extremismus, edited by Wolfgang Fritz Haug,
384 – 392. Hamburg: Argument-Verlag, 1997.
Marx, Karl and Frederick Engels. On the Paris Commune. 3rd ed. Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1980.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. Articles in the New American Cyclopaedia.
Edited by Hal Draper. Berkley, CA: Independent Socialist Press, 1969.
—. Die deutsche Ideologie. Edited by Harald Bluhm. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag,
2010 [1932].
Mayer, Gustav. Friedrich Engels. Eine Biographie. Erster Band: Friedrich Engels
in seiner Frühzeit. 2nd ed. The Hague: Springer Science+Business Media,
1934 [1920].
McLellan, David. Karl Marx: A Biography. 2nd ed. London: Macmillan, 1995.
Mehring, Franz: Karl Marx. The Story of His Life. Ann Arbor, MI: University
of Michigan Press, 1962 [1918].
Mescheryakov, Nicolai Leonidovich: The Life and Work of Karl Marx. Moscow /
Leningrad: Co-Operative Publishing Society of Foreign Workers in the
USSR, 1933.
Paler, Hein. Friedrich Engels — Der kreative Schatten. Norderstedt: Books on
Demand, 2020.
Paul, Hans-Holger. Marx, Engels und die Imperialismustheorie der II. Internationale. Hamburg: VSA-Verlag, 1978.
Rosdolsky, Roman. Friedrich Engels y el Problema de los Pueblos »sin Historia«.
La Questión de las Nacionalidades en la Revolution de 1848 – 1849 a la Luz de
la »Neue Rheinische Zeitung«. México City: Ediciones Pasado y Presente,
1980 [German 1964].
In the Shadow of Karl Marx
287
Schmitt, Richard. Introduction to Marx and Engels: A Critical Reconstruction.
2nd ed. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1997 [1987].
Sperber, Jonathan: Karl Marx: A Nineteenth-Century Life. New York / London:
Liveright Publishing Corp., 2013.
Stepanova, Yevgenia. Frederick Engels: A Short Biography. Moscow: Progress
Publishers, 1988 [1985].
Walther, Rudolf. Aufgreifen, begreifen, angreifen. Historische Essays, Porträts,
politische Kommentare, Glossen, Verrisse. Münster: Oktober Verlag, 2011.
Winters, Peter Jochen. »Ist die PDS am Ende?« In Zehn Jahre Deutsche Einheit. Eine Bilanz, edited by Wolfgang Thierse et al., 99 – 112. Opladen:
Leske + Budrich, 2000.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
Engels’s Perspective
Nuruddin Al Akbar
»But the necessity of authority, and of imperious authority at that,
will nowhere be found more evident than on board a ship on the
high seas. There, in time of danger, the lives of all depend on the
instantaneous and absolute obedience of all to the will of one.«
—Friedrich Engels1
»[T]here is no fixed and constant authority, but a continual exchange of mutual, temporary, and, above all, voluntary authority and
subordination.«
—Mikhail Bakunin2
»Today humanity faces an acute crisis not only due to the coronavirus, but also due to the lack of trust between humans. To defeat an
epidemic, people need to trust scientific experts, citizens need to trust
public authorities, and countries need to trust each other. [ …] In
this moment of crisis, the crucial struggle takes place within humanity itself. If this epidemic results in greater disunity and mistrust
among humans, it will be the virus’s greatest victory.«
—Yuval Noah Harari3
1
2
3
Friedrich Engels, »On Authority,« in The Marx-Engels Reader, ed. Robert C.
Tucker (New York: W. W. Norton, 1978), 732.
Mikhail Bakunin, »What is Authority?« The Marxists Internet Archive, accessed
April 1, 2020, https://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/bakunin/works/various/
authrty.htm.
Yuval Noah Harari, »In the Battle Against Coronavirus, Humanity Lacks Leadership,« Time, March 15, 2020, https://time.com/5803225/yuval-noah-harari-
290
Nuruddin Al Akbar
Introduction: Reading Engels in the Time
of the Coronavirus Outbreak
This study seeks to elaborate on the thoughts of Friedrich Engels
(1820 – 1895) about authority.4 This study is important because, traditionally, the name Engels tends to be considered »small« compared
to his colleague Karl Marx (1818 – 1883).5 Many of Marx’s ideas were
born together with Engels, such as the Communist Manifesto (1848), a
monumental work that raised Marx to the status of one of the world’s
leading thinkers that endures to this day.6 Another of Marx’s impressive works that is known to the world today, Das Kapital, also could
not have been born without the help of Engels.7 Marx is known as a
person who read more than he wrote.8 The reason is predictably that
Marx wanted his writing to be a work built on strong theoretical
and data foundations.9 However, Engels had another consideration,
4
5
6
7
8
9
coronavirus-humanity-leadership/.
In particular, the study considers his short writings entitled »On Authority« and
»Versus the Anarchists.« Although short, a lot of inspiration can be drawn from
the writings of Engels, primarily to help us understand contemporary phenomena such as the coronavirus outbreak.
Terrell Carver, Engels: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2003), vii.
Tristram Hunt, Marx’s General: The Revolutionary Life of Friedrich Engels (New
York: Holt Paperbacks, 2009), 1 – 2.
Even after the publication of Das Kapital, Engels was instrumental in introducing this book to a broad audience. For example, Engels wrote nine reviews about
Das Kapital that had a positive tone. Engels also became a supervisor in the translation of the book into English so that Marx’s work could gain a wider audience.
See Shlomo Avineri, Karl Marx: Philosophy and Revolution (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 2019), 144; Michael Charles Howard and John Edward King, A
History of Marxian Economics, vol. 1: 1883 – 1929 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989), 8.
Michael Evans, Karl Marx (London: Routledge, 2004), 47.
For example, Marx did not want to rush to complete the second volume because
he wanted to get accurate data about the latest developments that had occurred
in the UK related to the potential crisis of capitalism. See Bertell Ollman, Alienation: Marx’s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society (London: Cambridge University Press, 1971), 62.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
wherein the publication of Das Kapital — of which Marx planned to
publish six volumes — would not be finished if Marx read too much.
Because Marx used more and more of his time to read, to explore
particular topics, extra work was needed, and in the end, the writing
of Das Kapital continued to be delayed.10 Finally, thanks to Engels’s
insistence, Marx was able to complete the first volume of the original
six-volume plan that Marx envisioned.11 Engels was also instrumental
in editing Marx’s second and third volumes of Das Kapital, which
were left unfinished until the end of his life, and later, Engels chose
to publish them.12 In other words, Engels was a »big« intellectual, as
was his colleague Marx.13
However, it is unfortunate even long after his death, Engels’s name
is still positioned as a »complement« to the big-name Marx (even in the
academic world, his ideas are known as Marxism and not Engelsism14)
10
11
12
13
14
Even after the publication of the first volume, Marx felt that his work was still
not perfect. He stressed that he would revise his work if he found new findings
from the results of his research process and critical readings on various issues.
See Paul Prew, Tomás Rotta, Tony Smith and Matt Vidal, »The Enduring Relevance of Karl Marx,« in The Oxford Handbook of Karl Marx, ed. Tomás Rotta,
Tony Smith, Matt Vidal and Paul Prew (New York: Oxford University Press,
2019), 13.
William Otto Henderson, The Life of Friedrich Engels Volume II (London: Routledge, 1976), 399.
Lars Magnusson and Bo Stråt, A Brief History of Political Economy: Tales of Marx,
Keynes and Hayek (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2016), 10.
William Otto Henderson, The Life of Friedrich Engels Volume I (London: Frank
Cass, 1976), xi; Peter Singer, Marx: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2000), 59.
Regarding with the term Englelsism, it can be said that, there is a unique
tendency among some academics who seek to »purify« Marxism from Engels’s
influence. The attempt to »purify« Marxism was driven, for example, by their
suspicion of Engels, who was the editor of some of Marx’s works such as the
second and third volumes of Das Kapital. They feared that Engels’s subjective
interpretation influenced the originality of Marx’s work. In other words, there
was the potential for Marx’s ideas to be interfered with by Engels’s thought
as a thinker who had different ideas to Marx. So for these academics, further
studies must be conducted to clarify the influence of Engels on Marx’s work.
This trend is rather excessive, because Engels can be said to be a figure who
291
292
Nuruddin Al Akbar
so serious studies on him by academics are lacking.15 But now it is
undeniable that a new trend has also emerged. Many academics are
now interested in studying the figure and thought of Engels.16 This
new trend in studying Engels seriously is something to be celebrated
because, with the increasing number of academics involved, the in-
15
16
contributed to shaping Marx’s thinking, so it would be naive if they wanted to
erase the role of Engels in the formulation of Marxism. However, if the direction of this trend is to uncover the vital role of Engels in formulating Marxism,
then this tendency can be accepted. Marx and Engels must be appreciated as
intellectuals who both contributed to the creation of an original idea called
scientific socialism. See Carver, Engels, 12 – 13.
Terrell Carver is one of the academics who are aware of the lack of fascination
in the academic world with positioning Engels as a brilliant thinker. Even the
number of those who study him as a historical figure is relatively small. Carver
has tried to fill this academic vacuum by writing an introduction to placing
Engels as an independent thinker who deserves to be taken into account in the
academic world. See Carver, Engels, vii; Terrell Carver, Friedrich Engels: His Life
and Thought (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1990), xvi.
For example, two biographies of Engels written by two different authors appeared at not too distant times. The first book by John Green is titled Engels:
A Revolutionary Life and the second book written by Tristam Hunt is titled
Marx’s General: The Revolutionary Life of Friedrich Engels. Although they focus
more on the historical side of Engels and do not explicitly elaborate on his
thinking, both books got a warm appreciation from both contemporary socialists and non-Marxist academics. Interestingly, this appreciation was at the
same time their affirmation that Engels was a thinker who could not merely be
»reduced« to a subordination of Marx. Ian Angus, who wrote a review for the
Socialist Review, appreciates the books as works that fill the void in the study of
Engels. Angus even states that there have only been two biographical studies of
Engels in the 100 years since the death of the great thinker, namely the works
of Gustav Meyer (1936) and William Henderson (1976). The two works are
now out of print, so it is difficult for public audiences to access them. Angus
also encouraged a more serious study of Engels with an emphasis on the ideas
he generated, rather than merely studying the life of Engels. Likewise, Martin
Jacques — a non-Marxist academic — appreciated Hunt’s work as one that gave
readers a new insight into the life of Engels. Despite the scarcity of studies of
Engels, Hunt was able to show that he is a great thinker — equivalent to Marx.
See Ian Angus, »Two Accounts of Engels’s Revolutionary life,« Socialist Voice,
August 24, 2009: 28; Martin Jacques, »Marx’s Keeper,« The Guardian, May 2,
2009, https://www.theguardian.com/books/2009/may/02/frock-coated-engelshunt.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
293
formation discovered on the history of the life and intellectuality of
Engels that was previously unknown to the public will be priceless
treasure.17 The exploration of the life history of Engels is undoubtedly not only crucial for the academic world but also for the general public. This view is no exaggeration because, like Marx, Engels
was a man who walked in a critical tradition in which he was committed to developing the project of the emancipation of the people
from the various forms of oppression that enveloped them.18 This
study is expected to be a complement to previous works on Engels.
In other words, it is hoped that this work can become part of a new
trend of Engels studies. This work highlights Engels’s ideas about
authority, as he turned the debate about authority in an axiological
direction. For Engels, authority can be emancipatory but also can
be oppressive. Engels stated that if one negates the distinction between the two models of authority, then what happens is chaos because that authority is necessary, especially in emergencies. 19 This
study argues that Engels’s thought is relevant for understanding
contemporary phenomena, specifically those related to COVID19.20 This paper argues that the coronavirus outbreak is unique be17
18
19
20
J. S. McClelland, for example, underlines several of Engels’s intellectual works
in the context of the development of Marxism that might not have been previously realized by many parties. For example, according to McClelland, Engels
contributed to giving Marx knowledge about Feuerbach’s criticism of Hegel.
So it is not surprising that Marx’s critique of Feuerbach is printed along with
Engels’s work on Feuerbach (as an appendix). McClelland himself concluded
that Engels’s position was not subordinate but equivalent to Marx. See J. S.
McClelland, A History of Western Political Thought (London: Routledge, 1996),
574.
José Manuel Sánchez Bermúdez, The Neoliberal Pattern of Domination: Capital’s
Reign in Decline (Leiden: Brill, 2012), 87.
Engels, »On Authority,« 732; Friedrich Engels, »Versus the Anarchists,« in The
Marx-Engels Reader, ed. Robert C. Tucker (New York: W. W. Norton, 1978), 729.
The medical world gave this virus the name COVID-19 as an identity marker
to distinguish it from other types of coronavirus. When the term coronavirus is
used in this study, this refers to COVID-19, not to another type of coronavirus.
See Jianxing Yu, »Confronting and Governing the Public Health Emergency,«
Journal of Chinese Governance 5, no. 2 (2020): 137 – 139.
294
Nuruddin Al Akbar
cause it grew in the post-truth era,21 so it can be said that it is the
first post-truth outbreak of the 21st century.22
Furthermore, this study is considered even more important because although other works on Engels have begun to emerge, attempts
to contextualize the ideas of Engels with contemporary events can be
said to be very rare.23 Recall that in 2008 when the global economic
21
22
23
The term post-truth has become popular since it was named as the 2016 Word of
the Year by Oxford Dictionaries. Oxford Dictionaries defines post-truth as a condition in which objective factors influence public opinion less than emotions and
personal beliefs. Oxford Dictionaries‹ definition emphasizes the binary opposition between facts and opinions where subjective opinions have more of an effect
on people in the post-truth era. This study argues that post-truth is built on facts.
But it also agrees with Keyes‹ notion that there is a blur between fact and fiction.
That means that post-truth description is not merely an opinion, but the reality is
wrapped up in a story that tends to be fiction (or difficult to verify). Post-truth is
not only a matter of the decaying boundary between facts and opinions but also
its effect on society. It can be said that post-truth is almost sure to cause unrest,
fear, and panic for the public so they take actions that tend to be irrational. See
Kai Horsthemke, »›#FactsMustFall‹? — Education in a Post-Truth, Post-Truthful
World,« Ethics and Education 12, no. 3 (2017): 273 – 288; Scott Wilson, »Pre-Truth,
Post-Truth and the Present: Jacques Lacan and the Real Horror of Contemporary Knowledge,« in Post-Truth and the Mediation of Reality: New Conjunctures,
ed. Rosemary Overell and Brett Nicholls (Cham, Switzerland: Springer, 2020),
154; Lisa Portmess, »Post-Truth: Marcuse and New Form of Social Control,« in
America’s Post-Truth Phenomenon: When Feelings and Opinions Trump Facts and
Evidence, ed. C. G. Prado (Santa Barbara: Preager, 2018), 65.
Although not similar, there is a previous study conducted by Hakkı Taş in which
he tried to understand one particular event as a post-truth event. In his research,
Taş examines the failed coup that occurred on 15 July 2016 in Turkey as an example of a post-truth coup. Taş explicitly used the term »Turkey post-truth coup«
because the nature of the coup was filled with a variety of bombastic narratives
(about the Gulenist conspiracy), very little of which was supported by robust data.
The impact of the coup itself became a new marker for politics in Turkey, termed
by Taş as »new Turkey,« where, according to the author, the failed coup became
an excuse for Erdogan to strengthen his grip on the country by making himself
a hero who had succeeded in defeating foreign conspiracies (such as the US and
Germany were accused of being involved in) that had aimed at overthrowing him.
See Hakkı Taş, »The 15 July Abortive Coup and Post-Truth Politics in Turkey,«
Southeast European and Black Sea Studies 18, no. 1 (2018): 14 – 15.
An exception, for example, is the work of Michael Löwy, who tried to develop the tradition of eco-socialism. Interestingly, Löwy underlines Engels’s work,
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
295
crisis occurred, there was a strong attraction from academics — and
also from the public — to Marx’s ideas.24 The financial crisis that began in the US, where there was a problem of credit, eventually spread
widely and impacted various countries in the world.25 Some academics, for example, issued arguments that the global economic crisis was
following Marx’s thesis on the plight of capitalism26 where capitalism
tries to defend itself from a crisis by introducing several strategies, one
of which is through the credit system, to ensure the small bourgeoisie
does not collapse. But the effort of capitalism to maintain its existence ultimately has limitations. These limitations were reflected in
the occurrence of bad credit in the US, and finally, led to the crisis of
global capitalism.27 This study cannot elaborate the argument further
for reasons of space, but this does underline that Marx’s ideas have
been discussed again. Even at the grassroots level, the thoughts of
which sought to draw a link between the destruction of nature (forests in Cuba)
and the Spanish colonial capitalist production system that operates in the region.
Although, according to Löwy, Engels did not elaborate much on the linkage
between capitalism and environmental damage more systematically, Engels’s idea
could become a foundation for developing a Marxist analysis of current global
ecological damage. See Michael Löwy, »Marx, Engels, and Ecology,« Capitalism
Nature Socialism 28, no. 2 (2017): 16.
24 Slavoj Zizek, a well-known scholar who studies Lacanian philosophy, is one of
the academics who affirmed a new trend of intellectual and public excitement
about the ideas of political economy developed by Marx. Beyond academics
like Zizek, popular media also became involved in the trend; Time, for example,
released a special edition on February 2, 2009 with the provocative title »Global
financial crisis: What would Marx think?« See Christian Fuchs, »Dallas Smythe
Today — The Audience Commodity, the Digital Labour Debate, Marxist Political Economy and Critical Theory. Prolegomena to a Digital Labour Theory of
Value,« in Marx and the Political Economy of the Media, ed. Christian Fuchs and
Vincent Mosco (Leiden: Brill, 2016), 523.
25 Paul ›t Hart and Karen Tindall, »From ›Market Correction‹ to ›Global Catastrophe‹: Framing the Economic Downturn,« in Framing the Global Economic
Downturn: Crisis Rhetoric and the Politics of Recessions, ed. Paul ›t Hart and Karen
Tindall (Canberra: ANU E Press, 2009), 3.
26 Peter Hudis, Marx’s Concept of the Alternative to Capitalism (Leiden: Brill, 2012),
1 – 2.
27 Christian Fuchs, Digital Labour and Karl Marx (New York: Routledge, 2014), 13.
296
Nuruddin Al Akbar
Marx received much appreciation and became the basis of inspiration
for the emergence of the 2011 Occupy Wall Street movement in the
US.28 This took place in New York with people chanting the slogan,
»we are the 99 %.« This development means that Marx’s ideas have
been discussed again both in public and academic circles because his
ideas are considered relevant in reading contemporary phenomena.
A strong interest in Marx can be found again with the outbreak
of the coronavirus. For example, academics like David Harvey have
tried to apply Marx’s ideas to understand the origin of the coronavirus outbreak.29 Harvey’s analysis is in line with the big ideas developed by eco-Marxist exponents who are trying to develop a Marxist
analysis to see the link between capitalism and natural exploitation,
which leads to environmental damage.30 The difference is that Harvey specifically developed an argument about the connection between
capitalism, the exploitation of nature, and the emergence of the coronavirus.31 Harvey argued that nature became a kind of »iron cage« that
traps many dangerous viruses. However, the destruction of nature
28
29
Singer, Marx, 105.
Harvey, a contemporary Marxist geographer, analyzed the coronavirus outbreak
as an unintended consequence of a capitalist system that sought to turn nature
into mere industrial raw material. Harvey’s idea was in line with non-Marxist academics such as David Quammen, who believes that the disruption of ecosystems
by human activity causes viruses. According to Quammen, the viruses are then targeting humans as new hosts due to their lost ecosystems. See David Harvey, »Anti-Capitalist Politics in the Time of COVID-19,« Jacobin, March 20, 2020, https://
jacobinmag.com/2020/03/david-harvey-coronavirus-political-economy-dis
ruptions; David Quammen, »We Made the Coronavirus Epidemic,« The New
York Times, January 28, 2020, https://www.nytimes.com/2020/01/28/opinion/
coronavirus-china.html.
30 Bradley J. Macdonald, Performing Marx: Contemporary Negotiations of a Living
Tradition (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2006), 47 – 49.
31 In comparison, another famous scholar, Vandana Shiva argued similarly to Harvey. Although she did not explicitly base her writings on Marx’s ideas, Shiva
concluded that the coronavirus pandemic could not be separated from capitalistic logic, which sees nature as the raw material of production. Shiva presented
evidence that the Ebola outbreak also occurred due to deforestation. Shiva, as
an ecofeminist thinker, has made an argument for de-industrialization, especially for changes in the food system. See Vandana Shiva, »Ecological Reflections
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
297
and subsequent human contact with this damaged nature allows the
transfer of various viruses that were previously »isolated« from humans, one of which is the coronavirus.32
Another analysis was conducted by Martin Suryajaya,33 who tried
to underline the potential crisis of capitalism caused by the coronavirus.34 According to him, the coronavirus will encourage the creation
of the lumpenproletariat. Its emergence would happen as a natural
consequence of the policy that required the manufacturing industry
to lay off hard work to prevent the spread of the coronavirus. The
cessation of production for a long time will result in companies losing
money and going out of business. In his analysis, Suryajaya believes
this crisis will not only occur in the manufacturing industry but will
widen to a variety of other industries that cannot be based on working
from home, such as the entertainment industry. Along with the fall
of various industries, the monetary system may also be destroyed if
many people no longer invest their money but prefer to withdraw it
to guard against uncertain situations for a long time. In short, the
coronavirus outbreak has the potential to lead to a severe crisis of capitalism — although Suryajaya politely says that it is only a prediction
and will not necessarily occur.35
Unfortunately, amid the popularity of the name Marx, it can be
said there has been no serious effort from academics to elaborate Engels’s thought in context to understand the coronavirus outbreak — at
least, not as far as the search conducted by the author has shown.36
32
33
34
35
36
on the Coronavirus,« Medium, March 23, 2020, https://medium.com/postgrowth-institute/ecological-reflections-on-the-coronavirus-93d50bbfe9db.
Harvey, »Anti-Capitalist Politics.«
Martin Suryajaya is a young Indonesian thinker who is well known for his works
on Marxism.
Martin Suryajaya, »Membayangkan Ekonomi Dunia Setelah Korona Atau Cerita tentang Dua Virus,« MartinSuryajaya.com, March 30, 2020, https://www.
martinsuryajaya.com/post/membayangkan-ekonomi-dunia-setelah-korona.
Ibid.
There are various other critical analyses of the coronavirus outbreak with different
emphases. Take, for example, Yasraf Amir Pilliang, a famous Indonesian post-modern thinker, who took inspiration from Paul Virilio to put forward an argument
298
Nuruddin Al Akbar
Amid the scarcity of Engels studies, this article tries to contextualize
Engels’s ideas for a better understanding of the coronavirus outbreak.
Engels’s thoughts on authority are essential to counter the post-truth
tendencies that coincide with the global spread of epidemics.37 These
post-truth tendencies have caused severe problems for humanity because the anti-authority biases inherent in the post-truth era make
it difficult for humans to work together as a species to »wage war«
against the coronavirus.38 At the same time, Engels also contributed to
revealing another dangerous tendency where the anti-authority trend
is faced with the logic of traditional authority based on the spirit of
territorialism within the framework of the Westphalian state.39 The
37
38
39
for the de-globalization trend that occurred due to the outbreak. Other famous
academics such as Naomi Klein, also known as an anti-capitalist activist, tried to
see the outbreak as based on the ideas of shock doctrine and disaster capitalism.
She tried to explain the symptom of the return of elite characters in this outbreak
who manipulated people’s fears to pass unpopular policies (leading to widening
injustice, benefiting the elite, and harming ordinary citizens). Interestingly, Klein
concluded that we should be wary of elite discourse and that citizens would be
being selfish by staying quiet at home. Klein said we would never be safe if we did
not help our neighbors because without them (for example, those who carry out
the production process) our needs are also potentially in danger. The demands on
the elite to enforce a policy that will cover all parties then become an inevitability.
But once again, it needs to be emphasized that in the middle of an abundance of
weighty analyses, academics who refer to Engels to analyze the coronavirus outbreak critically have not yet been seen. See Yasraf Amir Pilliang, »Virus De-Globalisasi,« Kompas, March 30, 2020, https://kompas.id/baca/opini/2020/03/30/virusde-globalisasi/; Marie Solis, »Coronavirus Is the Perfect Disaster for ›Disaster Capitalism‹,« Vice, March 13, 2020, https://www.vice.com/en_uk/article/5dmqyk/naomiklein-interview-on-coronavirus-and-disaster-capitalism-shock-doctrine.
Engels, »Versus the Anarchists,« 729.
The post-truth narrative cannot be separated from the spirit of anti-authority,
especially authority in the mainstream sense (e. g. legal-formal authority). See
Gabriele Cosentino, Social Media and the Post-Truth World Order (Cham, Switzerland: Springer, 2020), 8 – 9; Steve Fuller, Post-Truth: Knowledge As A Power
Game (London: Anthem Press, 2018), 10.
Michael E. Clarke, Xinjiang and China’s Rise in Central Asia — A History (Abingdon: Routledge, 2011), 3; Kal Raustiala, Does the Constitution Follow the Flag?
The Evolution of Territoriality in American Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2009), 10.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
299
tendency of the return of authority in the Westphalian sense also
has the potential to cause various new problems. The conclusion
that Westphalian logic is problematic is not an exaggeration, given the nature of Westphalian authority, which emphasizes potential
territorial isolation (disengagement), hampering the possibility for
global cooperation.40 Furthermore, the application of a Westphalian
style of authority raises the risk of the presence of an authoritarian
state that considers that a single command lies in its hands and
potentially eliminates other ideas that are deemed not to be under
its command.41
On the other hand, the efforts to bring back Westphalian logic in
our era will also potentially strengthen anti-authority tendencies in
society. This trend, for example, is reflected in the Indonesian context
where local governments — even citizens at the local level — choose
to take actions that are different from the national government command line.42 This phenomenon happened because they feel that the
excessive domination of the central government is not followed by ef-
40
41
42
Interestingly, the WHO eventually revised the use of the term social distancing
and turned it into physical distancing. The reason, as stated by Maria van Kerkhove, an epidemiologist working at the WHO, is that efforts to build a feeling of
interconnection are essential for maintaining public mental health amid the epidemic. In other words, the WHO is aware that without robust global connectivity, efforts to fight the coronavirus will encounter major obstacles. See Harmeet
Kaur, »Forget ›Social Distancing.‹ The WHO Prefers We Call It ›Physical Distancing‹ Because Social Connections Are More Important Than Ever,« CNN, April
18, 2020, https://edition.cnn.com/2020/04/15/world/social-distancing-languagechange-trnd/index.html.
Florian Bieber, »Authoritarianism in the Time of the Coronavirus,« Foreign
Policy, March 30, 2020, https://foreignpolicy.com/2020/03/30/authoritarianismcoronavirus-lockdown-pandemic-populism/.
Jamal A. Nashr, »Tegal Lockdown karena Corona, Wali Kota: Tak Ditegur Mendagri,« Tempo, April 3, 2020, https://nasional.tempo.co/read/1327529/tegal-lock
down-karena-corona-wali-kota-tak-ditegur-mendagri; Irwan Syambudi, »Lockdown Mandiri ala Jogja: Ditolak Pemerintah, Diinginkan Warga,« Tirto, March
27, 2020, https://tirto.id/lockdown-mandiri-ala-jogja-ditolak-pemerintah-diing
inkan-warga-eH3o.
300
Nuruddin Al Akbar
fective policymaking in the face of the increasingly widespread coronavirus epidemic across Indonesian territory.43
This study will use the case of the global response to the coronavirus outbreak to elaborate on how the logic of anti-authority and authority in the traditional sense (Westphalian state) have emerged at the
same time. It seeks to reflect on the circumstances of China, the US,
Europe, Indonesia, and other cases deemed relevant. This study places
Engels’s thought as an analytical framework in which the coronavirus
outbreak is interpreted as a post-truth outbreak. To deal with the posttruth coronavirus outbreak, we must enter into the discussion of the
crisis of authority that has occurred globally, followed by efforts to find
a new form of authority that would have the function of liberating humans from the threat of a coronavirus outbreak. Without realizing the
importance of the axiological aspects of the existence of authority, as
stated by Engels, the world will have a hard time facing this pandemic.44 Furthermore, what happens by choosing a non-liberating form of
authority has the potential to give birth to new chaos amid humans‹
race to face the coronavirus, which can develop quickly and is also
known to be able to mutate. Without the search for accurate solutions
amid diminishing time, humans‹ existence as a species is at stake.
Contextualizing Engels’s Thought
in the Coronavirus Crisis
Before entering into the discussion of Engels’s idea of authority when
dealing with the coronavirus outbreak, we first need to understand
his idea in more detail. This discussion is also important because Engels’s idea of authority has been criticized by some academics and
43
44
The Jakarta Post, »COVID-19: Regions Start Locking Down as Govt Works on
Regulation,« The Jakarta Post, March 28, 2020, https://www.thejakartapost.com/
news/2020/03/28/covid-19-regions-start-locking-down-as-govt-works-on-regu
lation.html.
Engels, »On Authority,« 732; Engels, »Versus the Anarchists,« 729.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
301
contemporary anarchist writers who feel that Engels’s criticism of
anarchists is inappropriate.45 This study argues that Engels’s idea of
authority, raised in the nuance of the debate between Marxists and
anarchists, was not a misplaced criticism46 but rather a valid academic
criticism. Engels tried to direct the debate over authority to the axiological side, and it can be said that this axiological side did not receive
adequate discussion from anarchists.47
Although this study believes that Engels’s criticism of anarchists‹
positions can be justified, it must be acknowledged that anarchists‹
positions remained useful in the debate about the idea of authority.
Mikhail Bakunin’s (1814 – 1876) most important contribution to the
debate over authority was bringing it into the ontological domain.48
45
For example, academics such as Paul McLaughlin say that Marxist criticism of anarchists on authority is only based on prejudice, which tends to be simplistic and
inaccurate. Anarchists, who write on a number of websites using pen names like
Yuki, also say figures like Engels failed to understand the concept of anarchism
about authority. Another article called »An Anarchist FAQ« labelled Engels’s
criticism of anarchists non-fundamental, accusing Engels of being ignorant and
of not understanding what he criticized. See Paul McLaughlin, Anarchism and
Authority: A Philosophical Introduction to Classical Anarchism (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007), 12; Yuki, »The Semantical Issue Behind Engels’s »On Authority« and
How It Relates to Modern Day Anarchism,« The Anarchist Library, July 12, 2019,
https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/yuki-the-semantical-issue-behind-engelson-authority-and-how-it-relates-to-modern-day-anarchism#fn1; The Anarchist
FAQ Editorial Collective, »An Anarchist FAQ (09/17),« accessed April 1, 2020,
https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/the-anarchist-faq-editorial-collectivean-anarchist-faq-09-17.pdf.
46 Engels, »Versus the Anarchists,« 729.
47 Anarchists are more concerned with the ontological side of authority. See Saul
Newman, From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-authoritarianism and the Dislocation of
Power (Lanham: Lexington Books, 2001), 25 – 26; David W. Lovell, From Marx
to Lenin: An Evaluation of Marx’s Responsibility for Soviet Authoritarianism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 74.
48 It should be stated here that the views of famous thinkers such as Bakunin do
not necessarily »bind« anarchists in general. This tendency can be seen as a manifestation of a strong anti-authority tendency among anarchists. So the ideas
put forward by thinkers from Bakunin and Kropotkin to Proudhon cannot be
considered as ideas that are fully accepted and shape the face of the anarchist
movement as a whole. That is why it is also a question for academics and or anar-
302
Nuruddin Al Akbar
Bakunin’s argument is right when he mentions the destructive potential of an authority that is considered positive by the Marxist (e. g.
the concept of a proletarian state).49 Based on that concern, Bakunin
tried to formulate an alternative to reduce the destructive potential
of an authority. He then discusses a new form of authority based on
the idea of »voluntary« to minimize the form of authority that has
the potential to oppress individuals in the future.50 History proves
that deviations of authority, previously believed by Marxists to be a
liberating authority, occurred in the history of the Russian Revolution.51 The Russian Revolution experienced corruption, especially in
the Stalin era, which changed the proletarian state into a totalitarian
state by placing Stalin as the absolute ruler in that country.52
The synthesis of Engels’s and Bakunin’s thoughts is also relevant
if it is related to the discussion about the coronavirus outbreak. Before looking at the synthesis of Engels’s and Bakunin’s thoughts, it is
49
50
51
52
chist exponents who then blame Engels’s criticism of the anarchist movement by
describing the views of one of the leading anarchist thinkers, because it could be
that the ideas of the thinkers on which they base their arguments were not fully
agreed on by the anarchist movement in the days of Engels. See Richard T. De
George, »Anarchism and Authority,« Nomos 19 (1978): 92.
Feigan, »Marx’s »Dictatorship of the Proletariat,« Contemporary Chinese Thought
46, no. 2 (2015): 28.
Bakunin, »What is Authority?«
Leon Trotsky (1879 – 1940), one of the architects of the Russian Revolution, also
had concerns like Bakunin that the revolution could experience symptoms of
corruption. Trotsky saw that there was a potential similarity between the Russian
Revolution and the French Revolution, which, despite its noble goals, ultimately
led to the growth of the dictator Napoleon Bonaparte (1769 – 1821). Trotsky’s concern can be said to be reasonable. In the Stalin era, it seems that Russia turned
into a kind of new empire that had control over its satellite states in Eastern Europe. See Jay Bergman, The French Revolutionary Tradition in Russian and Soviet
Politics, Political Thought, and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019),
438 – 439.
An ironic historical fact is that Stalin (1878 – 1953), who had a major role in deviating the authority of the workers for his political interests, is an admirer of Engels’s
idea of authority — It is not surprising, then, that Stalin used Engels’ thought as
his main guide in arguing with anarchists. See Roland Boer, Stalin: From Theology
to the Philosophy of Socialism in Power (Singapore: Springer, 2017), 120.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
303
necessary to understand the nature of this post-truth era, which is
characterized by anti-authority.53 Why does a rejection of authority
symbolize post-truth? To grasp this, we must understand the nature
of post-truth and its effects on the global public. Post-truth, as emphasized by Oxford Dictionaries, is a marker of shifting public confidence from facts to personal opinions.54 The facts referred to here are
facts obtained from the empirical method.55 For example, statements
that the Statue of Liberty exists in the US can be empirically verified
by visiting the location of the statue. But there are also subjective interpretations of facts. Take, for example, the statement that the Statue
of Liberty is an icon of the US. A different approach must be taken
to verify this statement, because it cannot be checked empirically. The
way to validate this statement is to look at the collective imagination
of the global community. If it is proven that the citizens of the US
and the world have a relatively similar vision — that the building is an
icon of the US — , we can say that this statement can be declared valid. The subjective side of interpreting this reality is natural, related to
the symbolic side inherent in human beings.56 However, the personal
side of reality becomes problematic in the post-truth era due to the
construction of imagination related to one fact, which tends to spread
fear and excessive distrust of the »external world.«57
Take the example of the coronavirus, which first appeared in the
territory of China, as far as experts have been able to verify. However,
the presence of the virus in Wuhan was then given the subjective
53
54
55
56
57
Robert Farrow and Rolin Moe, »Rethinking the Role of the Academy: Cognitive Authority in the Age of Post-Truth,« Teaching in Higher Education 24, no. 3
(2019): 273.
Wilson, »Pre-truth, Post-truth and the Present,« 154.
Saulo de Freitas Araujo, »Truth, Half-Truth, and Post-Truth: Lessons from
William James,« Journal of Constructivist Psychology [online] (February 2020),
https://doi.org/10.1080/10720537.2020.1727390.
Ibid.
Frank Fischer, »Knowledge politics and Post-Truth in Climate Denial: On the
Social Construction of Alternative Facts,« Critical Policy Studies 13, no. 2 (2019):
134 – 135
304
Nuruddin Al Akbar
interpretation that the virus was a biological weapon belonging to
China that had leaked out.58 It is true that the virus initially spread
in the Wuhan region (which became the epicenter of the spread of
the virus).59 It is also a fact that there is a virus research laboratory in
Wuhan which has the official name of the Wuhan Institute of Virology.60 But it is become problematic when the events are arranged in
the framework of the narrative of
fear.61 The fear narrative is increasingly »convincing« by showing
images of the laboratory, the logo of which resembles that of the fictitious company »Umbrella Corporation« in the Hollywood films
and video games titled Resident Evil, which is responsible for releasing
viruses that turn humans into zombies. However, if one examines
the image critically, the image that appears »convincing« turns out to
be built on wild fantasies that are difficult to verify and some irrelevant data.62 The emergence of post-truth narratives that are difficult
to check, such as this case, quickly spread through social media and
58
BBC, »China coronavirus: Misinformation spreads online about origin and
scale,« BBC, January 30, 2020, https://www.bbc.com/news/blogs-trending-51271
037.
59 Huan Yang, Peng Bin and Alex Jingwei He, »Opinions from the Epicenter: An
Online Survey of University Students in Wuhan Amidst the COVID-19 Outbreak,« Journal of Chinese Governance 5, no. 2 (2020): 234 – 248; Yu, »Confronting
and Governing the Public Health Emergency,« 137 – 139
60 Emily Makowski, »Theory that Coronavirus Escaped from a Lab Lacks Evidence,« The Scientist, March 5, 2020, https://www.the-scientist.com/news-opinion/theory-that-coronavirus-escaped-from-a-lab-lacks-evidence-67229.
61 Molly Stellino, »Fact Check: Did the Coronavirus Originate in a Chinese Laboratory?« USA Today, March 22, 2020, https://www.usatoday.com/story/news/fact
check/2020/03/21/fact-check-did-coronavirus-originate-chinese-laboratory/288
1150001/.
62 The laboratory logo that is claimed to be similar to the Umbrella Corporation logo
is actually a logo of a laboratory in Shanghai named Shanghai Rulian Bao Hu San
Biotech. So it would be naive for the logo in Shanghai to be used as a justification
for the development of biological weapons in Wuhan. Further studies conducted
on the laboratory in Shanghai also found no indication of biological weapons
being developed. See Rachael Krishna, »This Company Is Based in Shanghai, not
Wuhan,« Full Fact, January 30, 2020, https://fullfact.org/online/wuhan-residentevil-coronavirus/.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
305
affect the public at large, which then causes mass fear. In this context, anxiety and, at the same time, hatred of China emerged.63 The
implications can be very complicated, such as the growth of racism
towards Chinese people, which led to efforts to blockade their territory to avoid the »threat« of China.64 From this explanation, we can
conclude that, starting with a post-truth narrative, it turns out to be
possible to influence global politics. We can also find that the panic
response is not much help because the coronavirus cannot be prevented from spreading globally just by closing off one particular territory.65 So, instead of the post-truth narrative contributing to saving the
world, it opens the way for the virus to develop more quickly because
China is left to struggle alone in facing the threat of the coronavirus.66 When China could no longer restrict the spread of the virus, it
quickly spread to various other parts of the world, breaking through
territorial boundaries that many imagined would be effective against
the global spread of the virus.67
Based on the example above, we can see several anti-authority tendencies arising from the post-truth narrative about China. If we look
at the WHO release, it is said that the spread of the virus should
63
Eoghan Macguire, »Anti-Asian Hate Continues to Spread Online Amid
COVID-19 Pandemic,« Al Jazeera, April 5, 2020, https://www.aljazeera.com/
news/2020/04/anti-asian-hate-continues-spread-online-covid-19-pandemic-200
405063015286.html.
64 Lauren Aratani, »Coughing while Asian‹: Living in Fear as Racism Feeds Off
Coronavirus Panic,« The Guardian, March 24, 2020, https://www.theguardian.
com/world/2020/mar/24/coronavirus-us-asian-americans-racism.
65 Lucy Budd and Stephen Ison, »Air Travel Restrictions Won’t Protect Us from the
Coronavirus,« The Jakarta Post, February 10, 2020, https://www.thejakartapost.
com/travel/2020/02/10/air-travel-restrictions-wont-protect-us-from-the-coronavirus.html.
66 James T. Areddy, »Amid Coronavirus, the World Closes Its Doors to China: ›I
Feel So Isolated‹,« The Wall Street Journal, February 18, 2020, https://www.wsj.
com/articles/amid-coronavirus-the-world-closes-its-doors-to-china-i-feel-so-iso
lated-11582060811.
67 Jessie Yeung, »A Global Coronavirus: Travel Bans, Face Masks, and Fear,« CNN,
February 27, 2020, https://edition.cnn.com/2020/02/27/world/gallery/coronavi
rus-prevention/index.html.
306
Nuruddin Al Akbar
not be used as a basis for racist action.68 However, WHO’s authorities have been ignored by a number of parties. For example, in some
European countries, there has been an increase in anti-Chinese sentiment. The rise of anti-Chinese sentiments in Europe is related to
the spread of the post-truth idea that ethnic Chinese, in general, are
»carriers« of the coronavirus.69 Likewise, global mistrust in the Chinese government authorities increased, which led to many countries
taking action to isolate China.70 Yet it was precisely the isolation of
China that essentially provided ample space for the coronavirus to
multiply. The virus is able to multiply quickly, and thus relying on
Chinese energy alone was not going to be enough to contain the
spread of the deadly virus. So it is not surprising that Xi Jinping continued to push for global cooperation rather than shut down and the
placing of suspicion on Chinese authorities.71 Antipathy toward Chinese authority and citizens does not provide much benefit in dealing
with the threat of the virus.72
This strong anti-authority tendency, inherent in the post-truth era,
is one of the reasons why the world has become so desperate while
68
69
70
71
72
Paula Larsson, »Anti-Asian Racism during Coronavirus: How the Language of
Disease Produces Hate and Violence,« The Conversation, March 31, 2020, https://
theconversation.com/anti-asian-racism-during-coronavirus-how-the-languageof-disease-produces-hate-and-violence-134496.
Kung Phoak, »Stop Prejudice, the Novel Coronavirus Has no Race,« The Jakarta
Post, February 22, 2020, https://www.thejakartapost.com/academia/2020/02/22/
stop-prejudice-the-novel-coronavirus-has-no-race.html.
Leslie Josephs, »China Grows Isolated as Airlines Cancel More than 50,000
Flights Amid Coronavirus Epidemic,« CNBC, February 6, 2020, https://www.
cnbc.com/2020/02/06/coronavirus-china-becomes-increasingly-isolated-as-air
lines-pull-out.html.
Stuart Lau and Owen Churchill, »Xi Jinping Urges ›Stronger International
Cooperation‹ and Quick Action to Fight Coronavirus Pandemic and Stave Off
Global Recession,« South China Morning Post, March 26, 2020, https://www.
scmp.com/news/china/politics/article/3077174/xi-jinping-urges-stronger-inter
national-cooperation-and-quick.
Mara Pillinger, »Virus Travel Bans Are Inevitable But Ineffective,« FP, February 23,
2020, https://foreignpolicy.com/2020/02/23/virus-travel-bans-are-inevitable-butineffective/.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
307
facing the coronavirus outbreak. This statement does not mean that
if this outbreak happened in the context of a »normal« era, the world
could quickly solve this problem. However, this post-truth situation
naturally complicates global cooperation.73 Global cooperation is the
key to fighting a pandemic that does not recognize territorial logic,
including gender and certain social classes. In other words, humans
are weakening their position amid the threat of this deadly plague
if they continue to maintain their anti-authority logic that impedes
global cooperation.74
However, it is also interesting to realize that the emergence of the
post-truth era also brought strong sentiments about restoring »traditional« authority.75 This desire for resurrecting »traditional« authority can be traced back to long before this outbreak began. There is
a growing trend in the academic world that seeks to resurrect »traditional« authority, such as the authority of scientists, as a solution
to the post-truth era.76 So what is happening today where there is a
desire to strictly re-enforce Westphalian territorial logic, is a manifestation of a long-standing desire to restore the »traditional« authority
that has been marginalized due to the rising tide of the post-truth era.
The desire to turn back history by positioning traditional authority
as an answer to overcoming the post-truth problem can be said to
be problematic. To say that there are problems inherent within the
desire to resurrect »traditional« authority is not an exaggeration because reality shows that the closing of borders between one country
and another does not prevent the spread of the virus in countries that
are trying to isolate themselves.77 In the context of finding solutions,
the synthesis of Engels’s and Bakunin’s ideas could be an alternative
73
74
75
76
77
Harari, »In the Battle Against Coronavirus.«
Ibid.
Fischer, »Knowledge Politics,« 135 – 136.
Ibid.
Noah Higgins-Dunn, »Travel Restrictions ›Irrelevant‹ if Coronavirus Becomes
a Pandemic, Top US Health Official Says,« CNBC, February 26, 2020, https://
www.cnbc.com/2020/02/26/fauci-travel-restrictions-irrelevant-if-coronavirusbecomes-a-pandemic.html.
308
Nuruddin Al Akbar
that transcends the »traditional« logic of territorialism and also offers
a form of authority that encourages human cooperation at all levels.78
Engels’s concept of authority cannot be separated from the prolonged
debate between Marxists and anarchists.79 Marx, who at that time
became an intellectual defender of Marxism, faced one of the giant
intellectuals of the anarchists, Bakunin.80 Both Marx and Bakunin believed that capitalism was an oppressive system, and they agreed that
revolution was the starting point for changing current harsh orders.81
But despite these similarities, both had different philosophical foundations that made them argue about some fundamental problems,
one of which is authority.82
Bakunin was an intellectual who grew up in a tradition of empiricism that recognizes the supremacy of experience over abstract
concepts.83 Bakunin was also an intellectual who was influenced by
the philosophy that emphasizes the idea of a »state of nature.«84 The
idea of a »state of nature« envisions a primitive human era that tends
to be good but then experiences degradation due to the concept of
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
This study agrees with Emma Woods that post-truth cannot be confronted by
reviving »traditional« authority but instead by devising a new form of authority that is more dynamic, open, and dialogic. Specifically, Woods believes that
scientific authority must be transformed in such a way as to make it more open
to public criticism. In line with Woods, this study believes that the authorities
based on Westphalian logic are not adequate to fight the coronavirus outbreak. A
new form of authority that is more nuanced in universal human interconnection
is needed, and this would also open up a broad range of movements for individuals that are needed to deal with the pandemic. See Emma Woods, »Science
Policy in a Post-Truth World,« in Risk and Uncertainty in a Post-Truth Society, ed.
Sander van der Linden and Ragnar E. Löfstedt (Abingdon: Routledge, 2019), 41.
Newman, From Bakunin to Lacan, 17.
Paul McLaughlin, Mikhail Bakunin: The Philosophical Basis of His Theory of Anarchism (New York: Algora Publishing, 2002), 96.
Eric Voegelin, From Enlightenment to Revolution (Durham: Duke University
Press, 1975), 201.
Newman, From Bakunin to Lacan, 17.
McLaughlin, Mikhail Bakunin, 113.
Barbara Goodwin, Using Political Ideas (Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd.,
2007), 133.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
309
organized society, especially in the era of capitalism.85 Interestingly,
Bakunin did not take the idea of »state of nature« wholeheartedly because he agreed with Marx that the fundamental phase of humanity
was a primitive society era where humans lived in communality but
still maintained their autonomy.86 Primitive society for Bakunin was
a society that naturally existed because individuals needed each other,
but in which there was no attempt by one party to dominate another.87
He believed that there was no domination in primitive communist society because there was no »external« authority capable of influencing
individual movements.88 Individual autonomy remains a fundamental
thing in Bakunin’s thought about freedom.89 For Bakunin, the ideal of
revolution is the desire to return man to his primitive state.90 From this
desire, it can be concluded that Bakunin considers that the concept of
authority is naturally problematic.91 The spontaneity of life and cooperation is the key and not the »imposed authority / external authority,«
which is the key to overcoming the problem of contemporary human
oppression.92 His view about the spontaneity of life makes Bakunin
and other anarchists uncomfortable with the concept of the proletarian dictatorship echoed by Marx.93
85
Samuel Rezneck, »The Political and Social Theory of Michael Bakunin,« The
American Political Science Review 21, no. 2 (1927): 280 – 281.
86 John Morrow, History of Western Political Thought (London: Red Globe Press,
2019), 91.
87 Rebecca A. Martusewicz, »›All this Boundless Multitude:‹ Rereading Mikhail
Bakunin for EcoJustice Education,« Educational Studies 48, no. 1 (2012): 1 – 2.
88 William L. Remley, Jean-Paul Sartre’s Anarchist Philosophy (London: Bloomsbury
Academic, 2018), 81 – 82.
89 McLaughlin, Anarchism and Authority, 19.
90 Leon P. Baradat, Political Ideologies: Their Origins and Impact (Abingdon: Routledge, 2016), 152.
91 Lawrence Wilde, Global Solidarity (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,
2013), 29.
92 Martin Phillip Johnson, The Paradise of Association: Political Culture and Popular
Organizations in Paris Commune of 1871 (Ann Arbor: The university of Michigan
Press, 1996), 278.
93 Lyman Tower Sargent, »Mikhail Bakunin (1814 – 76),« in Encyclopedia of Nineteenth-century Thought, ed. Gregory Claeys (Abingdon: Routledge, 2005), 32.
310
Nuruddin Al Akbar
Unlike Bakunin, Marx grew up in a Hegelian tradition.94 Marx
acknowledged that the primitive society era was a classless society.95
Still, according to dialectical law, there was a process of community
development that led to the idea of individual ownership.96 Historical movements continued until the era of capitalism, which for Marx
was an era of humans‹ exploitation of other humans.97 But unlike
Bakunin, Marx viewed capitalism as not entirely evil.98 Even Marx
saw the bourgeoisie as revolutionaries of his time99 because, at that
time, the worker was not in a state of being aware of his class consciousness.100 Capitalism, in its turn, will open the consciousness of
the working class because of the alienation effect produced by the
system.101 In the end, the workers will carry out a revolution and
then create a communist society, which is the end of the dialectics
of history.102
Unlike Bakunin’s position, Marx felt that history was moving forward and not backward.103 Marx also felt that because the foundation
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
Norman Levine, »Hegelian Continuities in Marx,« Critique 37, no. 3 (2009):
346 – 370.
Marian Sawer, Marxism and the Question of the Asiatic Mode of Production (The
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1977), 211 – 212.
Simon Clarke, Marx, Marginalism and Modern Sociology: From Adam Smith to
Max Weber (Aldershot: Macmillan Academic, 1991), 59.
William Clare Roberts, Marx’s Inferno: The Political Theory of Capital (Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 2017), 127.
Chilla Bulbeck, Re-orienting Western Feminisms: Women’s Diversity in a Postcolonial World (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 19.
R. J. Holton, The Transition from Feudalism to Capitalism (New York: St. Martin’s
Press, 1985), 189.
Elliott Johnson, David Walker and Daniel Gray, Historical Dictionary of Marxism (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 2014), 81.
I. Fetscher, »Karl Marx on Human Nature,« in Karl Marx’s Economics: Critical
Assessments, ed. John Cunningham Wood (London: Routledge, 1998), 220.
Fred Moseley and Tony Smith, »Introduction,« in Marx’s Capital and Hegel’s
Logic: A Reexamination, ed. Fred Moseley and Tony Smith (Leiden: Brill, 2014), 1.
Huaiyin Li, »Rewriting Modern Chinese History in the Reform Era: Changing
Narratives and Perspectives in Chinese Historiography,« in Marxist Historiographies: A Global Perspective, eds. Q. Edward Wang and Georg G. Iggers (Abingdon: Routledge, 2016), 95.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
was class consciousness, so the state could be used for the sake of class
struggle as well.104 Marx suggests that the state (which in the modern
framework is attached to formal legal authority) can be used for the
benefit of workers, especially in the transition to socialism.105 So even
though Marx does not explicitly elaborate on the concept of authority, he does not consider authority in the sense of »external authority«
to be a problem.106 Marx also stated that class consciousness needs to
be formed before the revolution.107 In other words, he considers the
idea of the »state of nature« that Bakunin believed was inaccurate because »naturally« they (the workers) did not have class consciousness,
so they had to become »aware« by learning.108 Unlike Marx, Bakunin
believed in spontaneity rather than the indoctrination of »abstract
concepts« by an external actor as the key to revolution.109
Engels entered the debate between Marxism and anarchism by
trying to strengthen the argument of Marxism.110 Engels also raised
the discussion about authority as a new academic debate. He felt that
if the issue of authority were not cleared up first, various discussions
about the revolution, the state, and so on would become endless de104 Newman, From Bakunin to Lacan, 27 – 28.
105 David Pavon-Cuellar, Marxism and Psychoanalysis: In or Against Psychology?
(Abingdon: Routledge, 2017), 71.
106 Paul Thomas, Karl Marx and the Anarchists (Abingdon: Routledge, 2010), 16.
107 Joseph M. Schwartz, The Permanence of the Political: A Democratic Critique of the
Radical Impulse to Transcend Politics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
1995), 150 – 152.
108 Timothy Messer-Kruse, The Haymarket Conspiracy: Transatlantic Anarchist Networks (Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 2012), 34.
109 Nathan Jun, »Anarchism and Just War Theory,« in Comparative Just War Theory:
An Introduction to International Perspectives, eds. Luis Cordeiro-Rodrigues and
Danny Singh (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2020), 23 – 24.
110 Engels’s analysis completes the position of Marx, who believes that it is not authority but an oppressive form of authority that must be rejected. Marx imagined that a new form of emancipatory authority would come along with the
proletarian revolution. The difference is that Marx talks about the future, while
Engels talks about the nature of authority by bringing it into the philosophical realm. See Peter Lamb, Marx and Engels’s Communist Manifesto (London:
Bloomsbury, 2015), 97.
311
312
Nuruddin Al Akbar
bate.111 For Engels, when discussing authority, we must speak in terms
of an axiological realm.112 Engels argued that authority could not be
reduced to merely a form of evil. An authority that has a liberating
vision is an authority worth supporting.113
Engels gave the simple example of a ship sinking in the middle of
an ocean.114 Without apparent authority, all the passengers on the ship
could drown.115 The authority, which has the function of liberating,
becomes crucial to ensure the safety of the ship’s passengers.116 So for
Engels, the discussion about authority must start from its function
and then discuss its form. This form adjusts according to the liberating function to be achieved. In the case of a ship that is threatened
with sinking, passenger survival is a fundamental idea that forms the
basis of the joint motion of the passengers. From the discovery of
this specific function, Engels gives the example that there must be
exceptional leadership that is obeyed by all passengers of the ship.117
Engels talked about someone who had sufficient leadership capacity
so that all passengers would not be in a panic and take various irrational actions, such as throwing themselves into the sea, which would
be an act of suicide. The existence of this one command is crucial to
regulating passenger movements. No passenger may act to violate his
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
Barry Hindess, »Socialism, Communism, Anarchism,« in Edinburgh Companion
to the History of Democracy, eds. Benjamin Isakhan and Stephen Stockwell (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2012), 350 – 351.
According to Herbert Marcuse (1898 – 1979), Engels did not want the abolition
of authority but to transform it into a democratic form. In other words, Engels
talks about the axiological realm where the purpose of authority is what must
be addressed rather than imagining authority as an evil concept, which then necessitates erasing the idea of authority. See Paul Blackledge, Friedrich Engels and
Modern Social and Political Theory (Albany: State University of New York Press,
2019), 147 – 148.
Engels, »On Authority,« 732 – 733.
Ibid, 732.
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
orders in order that all human resources on the ship can be utilized
optimally for the safety of all of them.118
The example used by Engels is interesting because it is related to
several dimensions, namely binding concepts together, leadership,
and obedience.119 Without these three dimensions of authority, we
can be sure the ship will sink. In other words, it is not spontaneity but
a rationally planned work (concept-based) that becomes important.120
Engels attempted to refute Bakunin’s position and those who agreed
with him by asserting that authority was a necessity if he wanted freedom or safety from danger.121
For Engels, authority is a matter of axiology. If authority is based
on the idea of liberating, then it becomes valid, but if it is not, then
it is rejected.122 From Engels’s explanation, it can also be drawn that
»shared concepts« are essential because these are the fundamental dimension of liberating authority.123 Based on these shared concepts, a
contextual strategy can be designed depending on the mission it intends to carry out.
Engels’s contribution to the debate over authority deserves appreciation. But the position of anarchists, especially Bakunin, is not
entirely wrong. Bakunin’s concept, which is based on spontaneity,
if used in the context of saving a ship from the possibility of sink118 Ibid.
119 The three dimensions of liberating authority are not explicitly stated by Engels
in his article, but are provided here to make it easier for the reader to understand
Engels’s explanation of the concept.
120 Lenin agreed to Engels’s idea of authority and tried to add his argument that
without centralized coordination and based on rational planning, it would be
impossible for a factory to produce, or for ships to sail smoothly at sea. In other
words, Lenin underlines the issue of rational planning and not spontaneity as the
key to the success of the workings of an order. See George G. Brenkert, Political
Freedom (London: Routledge, 1991), 166.
121 Daniel E. Saros, Information Technology and Socialist Construction: The End of
Capital and the Transition to Socialism (Abingdon: Routledge, 2014), 29.
122 Stanislaw Ehrlich, Pluralism On and Off Course (Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1982),
148.
123 Engels, »On Authority,« 732 – 733.
313
314
Nuruddin Al Akbar
ing, may end in chaos because there are no big ideas that frame the
movement of the passengers.124 However, the example given by Engels
about a single form of leadership that tends to be personalistic is an
unhealthy tendency.125 It could be said that Engels did not pay too
much attention to how a liberating idea, if wrongly applied, could
lead to disaster too.126 The ontological aspect of authority does not get
much attention from Engels.
Interestingly, anarchist thinkers like Bakunin elaborate on the
ontological side that was forgotten by Engels, so the ideas they put
forward deserve serious attention as well. Bakunin’s idea of »voluntary authority« and also the idea of the spontaneity of the masses
can be used as inspiration to develop Engels’s ideas.127 Contemporary
anarchist intellectuals have tried to further develop Bakunin’s ideas
about »voluntary authority« and also made efforts to maintain the
spontaneity of the masses within a broad framework of decentralized
networks.128
The concept of liberating authority developed by Engels coupled
with positive criticism from Bakunin about the »voluntary« side and
spontaneity can be synthesized in the context of being an alternative offer in the global war against the coronavirus. This study offers
the interpretation of a discursive form of authority so that the fundamental of authority is a shared idea that guides human motion.129
124 Ibid, 732.
125 Ibid.
126 In Bakunin’s thought, it is not justified to assume that there is an infallible authority on whom a person always relies. Bakunin proposed maintaining criticism
of authority, for example, by asking questions of different health experts and
thereby relate to the authority of health science as a whole so as not to rely on
just one expert’s opinion, which could be wrong. See Peter Marshall, Demanding
the Impossible: A History of Anarchism (Oakland: PM Press, 2010), 294.
127 Bakunin, »What is Authority?«
128 Jeff Shantz, Constructive Anarchy: Building Infrastructures of Resistance (Farnham:
Ashgate, 2010), 19.
129 The term discursive authority is inspired by Marcuse’s reading of Engels whereby
authority does not have to mean bad. Marcuse himself formulated the idea of
rational authority, which, according to him, was necessary to ensure the suffi-
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
315
The shared idea that was implied is the idea of human survival as a
species.130 The idea of humans as a species is crucial to be encouraged
because, in the context of the coronavirus outbreak, it is necessary
to realize that this virus is not targeting a particular country, gender,
civilization, race, or social class.131 Global collaboration must be built
on the idea of the unity of human beings as a species.132 The contextualization of strategies relevant to this post-truth era must be designed
from the idea that human beings must work together as a species.
This study argues network-based cooperation is a promising alternative.133 This collaborative network must also provide space for spon-
130
131
132
133
ciency of a civilization. Interestingly, the concept of rational authority developed
by Marcuse is one based on knowledge-based authority. This study considers that
knowledge-based authority necessitates an emancipatory discourse that could be
an ultimate reference to ensure the survival of the current human civilization
from its potential extinction due to the threat of the coronavirus outbreak. See
Christopher Holman, Politics as Radical Creation: Herbert Marcuse and Hannah
Arendt on Political Performativity (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2013), 83
Anna Carthaus, »Yuval Noah Harari on COVID-19: ›The Biggest Danger Is Not
the Virus Itself‹,« DW, April 22, 2020, https://www.dw.com/en/virus-itself-is-notthe-biggest-danger-says-yuval-noah-harari/a-53195552.
Zizek gives an interesting illustration that the ethics of global cooperation must
be encouraged, like the ethics of treating a soldier injured badly during a war.
Although he / she is unlikely to recover, maximum effort is made to help the
wounded soldier. Soldiers can be compared to humanity as a species that is at war
with the coronavirus. No matter the kind of soldier (or their background), they
must be saved because the existence of one soldier is crucial in the success of the
war against the coronavirus. See Slavoj Zizek, »Barbarism with a Human Face,«
Welt, March 19, 2020, https://www.welt.de/kultur/literarischewelt/article2068292
59/Slavoj-Zizek-on-Corona-Barbarism-with-a-Human-Face.html.
Yuval Noah Harari, »Yuval Noah Harari: The World After Coronavirus,« Financial Times, March 20, 2020, https://www.ft.com/content/19d90308-6858-11ea-a3
c9-1fe6fedcca75.
An interesting inspiration can be obtained from the work of Peter Kropotkin
(1842 – 1921), one of the leading anarchist thinkers besides Bakunin, who also
stressed the need to develop an organization with network characteristics. Kropotkin gave an example of a charity called the Royal National Lifeboat Institution, which is based on collective work but without the need for organizational
centrality. See Andrew Whitworth, Information Obesity (Oxford: Chandos Publishing, 2009), 141.
316
Nuruddin Al Akbar
taneous movements. Spontaneity does not mean that a person moves
at will without the guidance of one particular big idea (i. e. the survival of the human species).134 Spontaneity must be interpreted such
that there is room for each individual to develop their own methods
in the fight against the coronavirus.135 With the opening of the space
of spontaneity, various ideas that were previously unthinkable can be
raised.136 It is these creative ideas generated from various parties that
have significantly contributed to human survival on a macro level.137
134 The spontaneous movement of the masses must be framed together with one
big idea, namely the survival of humanity as a species. It is in this context that
the idea of authority must inevitably exist, but in the form formulated by Engels
and Marcuse, namely liberating discursive authority. See Engels, »On Authority,«
732; Holman, Politics as Radical Creation, 83.
135 In the language of Emma Goldman (1869 – 1940), an American anarchist, free
space must be provided so that individuals are allowed to »do it their own way.«
See Colin Ward, Anarchism: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 68.
136 Herbert Read (1893 – 1968), a British literary critic and also an anarchist, argued
that spontaneity is closely related to creativity. Using the framework of Fromm’s
psychology, Read stated that the effort to discipline spontaneity is what makes a
society »sick,« and to »make it healthy« again, spontaneity must be given a large
space so that a variety of creativity can be fostered. In the context of the war
against the coronavirus, if the authority that works tends to be monolithic, it has
the potential to destroy the brilliant ideas that are potentially emerging from the
community. See Carissa Honeywell, A British Anarchist Tradition: Herbert Read,
Alex Comfort and Colin Ward (New York: Continuum, 2011), 65.
137 According to Harari, global information sharing is vital to ensure the survival of
humanity. Harari exemplifies how it is crucial for every individual to have proper
scientific knowledge on how to prevent the transmission of the coronavirus so
that he can act appropriately. The problem for Harari that is happening right
now is the closure of information rather than information disclosure. If Harari
accuses, for example, some politicians of trying to block valid information from
spreading, it can also be added that the traditional authority model based on
territorialism is not conducive to the free flow of information globally. Instead,
the network model offered in this study can be an alternative to ensure that the
free flow of information can occur smoothly. The information in question is not
just related to technical information to prevent transmission of the coronavirus
but also inspirational information that can inspire people in various parts of the
world to be encouraged to carry out humanitarian actions. See the UNESCO
Courier, »Yuval Noah Harari: ›Every Crisis Is Also an Opportunity‹,« The UNES-
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
The logic of the collaborative network that gives room to spontaneity is also expected to reduce the post-truth effect because no
dominant authority is allowed in the logic of the network.138 In the
context of avoiding the dominance of one party, it is necessary to
contextualize the idea of Engels, especially on aspects of leadership
and obedience.139 This study argues that leadership is not necessarily
singular but can be plural.140 An essential component of leadership
also lies not in its command abilities but in the ability to inspire other
individuals.141 The redefinition of leadership as an entity that can be
a source of inspiration also changes the meaning of obedience. Obedience is not interpreted as blind submission but becomes the ability
to capture inspiration and give birth to positive new inspiration.142 So
in this leadership context, for example, the position of experts such
as the WHO is positioned as an essential source of inspiration on
how to fight viruses based on scientific methods.143 This inspiration
inspired some community members who then took the initiative to
produce masks and sell them cheaply to prevent a scarcity.144 Other
communities, such as religious or social movements, took the initiative to buy masks and distribute them to the poor so they could get
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
CO Courier, accessed April 30, 2020, https://en.unesco.org/courier/news-viewsonline/yuval-noah-harari-every-crisis-also-opportunity.
Bakunin, »What is Authority?«
Engels, »On Authority,« 732 – 733.
McLaughlin, Anarchism and Authority, 158; Joyce Rothschild and J. Allen Whitt,
The Cooperative Workplace: Potentials and Dilemmas of Organisational Democracy
and Participation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 16 – 17.
Nunzio Pernicone, Italian Anarchism, 1864 – 1892 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), 290.
Jeffrey Shantz and Dana M. Williams, Anarchy and Society: Reflections on Anarchist Sociology (Leiden: Brill, 2013), 45 – 56.
BBC, »Virus corona: Tips terlindung dari Covid-19 dan mencegah penyebaran
sesuai petunjuk WHO,« BBC, April 2, 2020, https://www.bbc.com/indonesia/
dunia-52127080.
Ahmad Sukirno, »Komunitas Difabel Boyolali Bikin Masker untuk Warga Miskin,« rri.co.id, April 8, 2020, http://rri.co.id/post/berita/816848/daerah/komuni
tas_difabel_boyolali_bikin_masker_untuk_warga_miskin.html.
317
318
Nuruddin Al Akbar
extra protection without spending money.145 Inspirational work based
on network logic, for example, has occurred in many parts of Indonesia. Similar work may also have occurred in many other countries.
What should be encouraged is to increase such inspirational work in
the future.
Conclusion: Engels’s Discursive Authority
or the Extinction of Humans as a Species
One conclusion that can be drawn from this study is the importance
to rethink the definition of authority to deal with the coronavirus
outbreak. Engels explained that authority was inevitable in ensuring
the survival of humanity. Without an acknowledgment of liberating
authority, this global coronavirus outbreak will spread without significant obstacles. The virus has become unstoppable due to the fertile
post-truth ground, which makes it difficult for humans to develop a
joint strategy that is effective in dealing with the coronavirus threat.
Post-truth narratives are built by manipulating the subjective side of
human beings in interpreting reality. The subjective side of humanity
is bombarded with narratives that are difficult to verify and often
contain disinformation. The attacks result in public panic and, at the
same time, reinforce a sense of distrust in all forms of authority.
What followed was a revival of extreme individualism that affected
not only individuals but also communities and even nation-states. It
is this extreme individualism that then leads to, for example, embarrassing events such as when the US was accused by some French and
German officials of stealing a shipment of masks bound for France
145 Muhammadiyah, »MCCC Denpasar Bagikan 1000 Masker Kepada Warga Kota
Denpasar,« Muhammadiyah, April 10, 2020, http://www.muhammadiyah.or.id/
id/news-18793-detail-mccc-denpasar-bagikan-1000-masker-kepada-warga-kotadenpasar.html; Makhfud Syawaludin, »NU Kabupaten Pasuruan Segera Bagikan
50 Ribu Masker Kain,« NU Online, April 11, 2020, https://www.nu.or.id/post/
read/118950/nu-kabupaten-pasuruan-segera-bagikan-50-ribu-masker-kain.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
319
and Germany amid the rise of the »global war for masks.«146 All countries try to prioritize themselves with irrational actions. So Engels’s
idea of liberating authority becomes a promising alternative to prevent the world from falling into chaos and global barbarism.
This concept of liberating authority offered by this study is an
idea developed by Engels (and also enriched by Bakunin’s ideas) is
authority in the discursive sense, not authority held by a particular
institution. Authority in the discursive sense must be interpreted as a
shared idea (big narrative) about the survival of humans as a species.
In other words, humanism became the highest authority in the war
against the coronavirus. Humanism here is not interpreted abstractly
but very specifically, namely as our survival as a species. It is this acceptance of the grand narrative of humanism that forms the foundation for building trust globally. The meaning of this kind of authority
will also prevent the accumulation of power in an institution such as
the ruling regime in a particular country, which tends to be corrupt.
The discursive authority will prevent the public from blind obedience to any form of »small« authority within its sphere. The public
will see the »small« authority, such as an expert organization like the
WHO, as one entity that has an essential role in leadership against the
coronavirus. But as necessary as the role of WHO leadership may be,
for example, it cannot hold leadership alone and must be helped by
other forms of leadership. In this new framework, everyone can and
must take a leadership role because without their contribution (in any
form), this global war will not be successful. Everyone can be likened
to musicians in a musical performance in which each person plays a
different role (producing different sounds through different musical
146 Tim Lister, Sebastian Shukla and Fanny Bobille, »Coronavirus Sparks a ›War
for Masks‹ as Accusations Fly,« CNN, April 3, 2020, https://edition.cnn.com/
2020/04/03/europe/coronavirus-masks-war-intl/index.html; Kim Willsher, Julian Borger and Oliver Holmes, »US Accused of ›Modern Piracy‹ After Diversion of Masks Meant for Europe,« The Guardian, April 4, 2020, https://www.
theguardian.com/world/2020/apr/03/mask-wars-coronavirus-outbidding-de
mand.
320
Nuruddin Al Akbar
instruments). But it is precisely from the variations in sounds that
cause a distinct beauty to arise and that makes music concerts meaningful. The unity of sound gives birth to musical tunes and makes the
audience feel comfortable.
Leadership here is not meant as a sign of dominance because leadership is not inherent but an action that can be done by anyone. So
we can say leaders like Duterte, who is threatening to shoot Filipinos
who protest against his lockdown policy, are unacceptable in this kind
of discursive authority scheme.147 Such an attitude does not give birth
to a positive impulse to further strengthen cooperation among Filipinos but rather weakens trust among them, especially toward their
government.
Engels’s thought about discursive authority could be a reasonable
solution and should be encouraged by academics as a new form of
global cooperation. Without a change on the paradigmatic side, we
are allowing the virus to win against humans. Take the lessons of China, for example, where an effort to concentrate authority in the central government in Beijing under Xi Jinping’s command ultimately
slowed down the detection and handling of the virus. Although China
has since halted the spread of the virus in the country, the distrust that
emerges from Chinese citizens has not stopped. Citizens‹ anger over
the death of doctor Li Wenliang, for example, is proof of the logic of
»traditional« authority, which had become the dominant paradigm in
China to stem the spread of the coronavirus, causing many problems.148
147 Yuki Tsang, »›Shoot Them Dead‹: Philippine President Duterte Warns Coronavirus Lockdown Violators,« South China Morning Post, April 2, 2020, https://www.
scmp.com/video/coronavirus/3078165/shoot-them-dead-philippine-presidentduterte-warns-coronavirus-lockdown.
148 BBC, »Li Wenliang: Coronavirus Death of Wuhan Doctor Sparks Anger,« BBC,
February 7, 2020, https://www.bbc.com/news/world-asia-china-51409801; Josephine Ma and Jun Mai, »Death of Coronavirus Doctor Li Wenliang Becomes
Catalyst for ›Freedom of Speech‹ Demands in China,« South China Morning Post,
February 7, 2020, https://www.scmp.com/news/china/politics/article/3049606/
coronavirus-doctors-death-becomes-catalyst-freedom-speech.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
President Xi was forced to go to Wuhan himself, which can be interpreted as an apology to its citizens.149
The application of the logic of »traditional« authority based on territorial logic is still affecting China — to a greater or lesser degree — since
the outbreak began to be controlled. Some residents — and also some
police — affected by territorial logic rejected the government’s attempt
to open the border between Wuhan (Hubei Province) and neighboring regions (e. g. Jiangxi Province).150 This event means that despite
the ongoing formation of a new consciousness based on the discursive
idea of human survival as a species (which gained momentum with
the »Wuhan Jiayou« phenomenon151), the new awareness process is
149 Simon Tisdall, »Covid-19 Is Exposing the Frailty in Autocrats and Democrats
Alike,« The Guardian, March 15, 2020, https://www.theguardian.com/commentis
free/2020/mar/15/covid-19-exposing-frailties-autocrats-democrats-alike-trumpxi-eu-un.
150 Lea Li, »Police, Public Clash as Border Reopens Between Coronavirus Epicentre
Hubei and Jiangxi Province,« South China Morning Post, March 29, 2020, https://
www.scmp.com/video/china/3077466/police-public-clash-border-reopens-be
tween-coronavirus-epicentre-hubei-and.
151 The phenomenon of »Wuhan Jiayou« is marked by Wuhan residents screaming from their apartment or residence, to which other residents respond with
replies containing a message of unity and cooperation. The term »Wuhan Jiayou« means »Wuhan residents, get excited.« It is a message to fellow Wuhan
residents to work together to get through the crisis. This moment of togetherness later inspired some Wuhan residents to document the event and spread
it via the Internet. Those who circulated it on the Internet can be said to have
performed a leadership function because they were trying to inspire the world
with the event they were experiencing in Wuhan. This message can be said to
affect many parties. Many countries are also encouraged to take part in helping
Wuhan and China overcome the coronavirus outbreak. The Chinese government also realized that their »traditional« way was not sufficient, even though
they continued to act according to the »old« logic. The Chinese government
then gave more leeway for the spirit of »Wuhan Jiayou« to be spread wider and
globally. It should be noted that several buildings in China turned on lights
to read »Wuhan Jiayou,« which then inspired others in other countries to do
the same. See Pythag Kurniati, »Bertemu Kapolri, Polisi Jambi yang Nyanyikan
Lagu Jiayou Wuhan Ditawari Sekolah Perwira,« Kompas, March 8, 2020, https://
regional.kompas.com/read/2020/03/08/13111271/bertemu-kapolri-polisi-jambiyang-nyanyikan-lagu-jiayou-wuhan-ditawari; Elsa Emiria Leba, »Semangat Be-
321
322
Nuruddin Al Akbar
not necessarily able to completely erase the logic of »traditional« authority based on distrust with other parties.
In conclusion, it seems no exaggeration that the world today is
faced with two choices, namely the discursive authority offered by
Engels or the »traditional« authority model based on the Westphalian
logic of territorialism that wants to place the state as the highest holder of control. The choice of »traditional« authority — which is still
the choice of many countries today — does not provide a meaningful
solution for humanity. The number of coronavirus patients globally is
not decreasing but continues to grow in an increasingly extraordinary
number. Not to mention the application of this kind of »traditional« authority, which has the potential to strengthen the proliferation
of post-truth narratives globally, because to strengthen the positions,
territorialism often requires justification from post-truth narratives.
This, for example, can be witnessed in the US, which continues to develop the idea of a »Chinese virus« conspiracy under Donald Trump’s
leadership.152 The development of post-truth narratives, in turn, complicates the situation, in which the US has become the non-Asian
region most severely affected by the coronavirus.153 This negative development means that the logic of territorialism that is trying to be
lum Padam, Wuhan Jiayou!« Kompas, February 1, 2020, https://kompas.id/baca/
internasional/2020/02/01/semangat-belum-padam-wuhan-jiayou/; Tresno Setiadi, »Kisah Mahasiswa di Wuhan Saat Virus Corona Merebak, Teriak ›Jiayou‹
dari Balik Jendela,« Kompas, February 17, 2020, https://regional.kompas.com/
read/2020/02/17/17033981/kisah-mahasiswa-di-wuhan-saat-virus-corona-mere
bak-teriak-jiayou-dari-balik?page=all.
152 Sabrina Tavernise and Richard A. Oppel, Jr., »Spit On, Yelled At, Attacked: Chinese-Americans Fear for Their Safety,« The New York Times, March 23, 2020,
https://www.nytimes.com/2020/03/23/us/chinese-coronavirus-racist-attacks.
html; BBC, »Coronavirus: Trump Attacks ›China-Centric‹ WHO Over Global
Pandemic,« BBC, April 8, 2020, https://www.bbc.com/news/world-us-canada-522
13439.
153 Nicole Chavez, Jason Hanna and Christina Maxouris, »US Coronavirus Cases Reach more than 101,000 as Reported Deaths Hit New Daily High,« CNN,
March 28, 2020, https://edition.cnn.com/2020/03/27/health/us-coronavirus-fri
day/index.html.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
323
maintained and even strengthened by post-truth narratives is leading
to an increasingly devastating humanitarian crisis.
Global barbarism seems to be the right term to refer to the current
global tendency in dealing with the coronavirus outbreak. Yet, at the
same time, world leaders such as German Chancellor Angela Merkel
have appealed for stronger global cooperation to face the coronavirus.154 But it seems that such appeals are mere rhetoric without any
real action as long as the logic of »traditional« authority is still entrenched in the minds of world leaders. Some netizens responded to
Merkel’s speech by posting images of burning European Union flags
(especially in Italy).155 The action illustrates the low public confidence
in Merkel’s rhetoric, especially among Italian citizens, who have suffered from one of the most severe outbreaks among EU countries.
Engels’s idea about authority is a reasonable choice to fill the
gap between the rhetoric of cooperation that is being discussed by
world leaders and the policies adopted by these leaders. At present,
humanity does not need authority, which results in a dualism between rhetoric and action. Humanity needs an authority that does
not discriminate between one country and another, between one
class and another, or between one civilization and another. Humans
need a form of authority that can unite them as one human species.
Not bound by boundaries that are confirmed by the old conception
of authority. This new conception of a discursive authority that can
unite humanity in the big idea as an endangered species needs to be
developed. The Engelsian concept (enriched by Bakunin’s ideas) is an
alternative offer that needs to be developed primarily by the academic
world in the hope that global efforts against the coronavirus outbreak
154 Eszter Zalan, »Merkel: Virus Is Biggest Challenge in EU History,« Euobserver, April
7, 2020, https://euobserver.com/coronavirus/148003; Ayhan Simsek, »Merkel:
Coronavirus Biggest Challenge in EU’s History,« Anadolu Agency, April 6, 2020,
https://www.aa.com.tr/en/europe/merkel-coronavirus-biggest-challenge-ineu-s-history/1794764.
155 Katya Adler, »Coronavirus Outbreak Eats into EU Unity,« BBC, April 3, 2020,
https://www.bbc.com/news/world-europe-52135816.
324
Nuruddin Al Akbar
will not move increasingly towards barbarism or, even more severely,
humans‹ extinction as a species on earth.
Works Cited
Adler, Katya. »Coronavirus outbreak eats into EU unity.« BBC, April 3, 2020.
https://www.bbc.com/news/world-europe-52135816.
Angus, Ian. »Two accounts of Engels’s revolutionary life.« Socialist Voice, August 24, 2009.
Aratani, Lauren. »›Coughing while Asian‹: living in fear as racism feeds off coronavirus panic.« The Guardian, March 24, 2020. https://www.theguardian.
com/world/2020/mar/24/coronavirus-us-asian-americans-racism.
Araujo, Saulo de Freitas. »Truth, Half-Truth, and Post-Truth: Lessons from
William James.« Journal of Constructivist Psychology [online] (February
2020). https://doi.org/10.1080/10720537.2020.1727390.
Areddy, James T. »Amid Coronavirus, the World Closes Its Doors to China:
›I Feel So Isolated‹«. The Wall Street Journal, February 18, 2020. https://
www.wsj.com/articles/amid-coronavirus-the-world-closes-its-doors-tochina-i-feel-so-isolated-11582060811.
Avineri, Shlomo. Karl Marx: Philosophy and Revolution. New Haven: Yale
University Press, 2019.
Bakunin, Mikhail. »What is Authority?« The Marxists Internet Archive, 1999.
https://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/bakunin/works/various/
authrty.htm.
Baradat, Leon P. Political Ideologies: Their Origins and Impact. Abingdon:
Routledge, 2016.
BBC. »Coronavirus: Trump attacks ›China-centric‹ WHO over global pandemic.« BBC, April 8, 2020. https://www.bbc.com/news/world-us-canada52213439.
—. »Li Wenliang: Coronavirus death of Wuhan doctor sparks anger.« BBC,
February 7, 2020. https://www.bbc.com/news/world-asia-china-51409801.
—. »China coronavirus: Misinformation spreads online about origin and
scale.« BBC, January 30, 2020. https://www.bbc.com/news/blogs-trend
ing-51271037.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
325
—. »Virus corona: Tips terlindung dari Covid-19 dan mencegah penyebaran
sesuai petunjuk WHO.« BBC, April 2, 2020. https://www.bbc.com/in
donesia/dunia-52127080.
Bergman, Jay. The French Revolutionary Tradition in Russian and Soviet Politics,
Political Thought, and Culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019.
Bieber, Florian. »Authoritarianism in the Time of the Coronavirus.« Foreign
Policy, March 30, 2020. https://foreignpolicy.com/2020/03/30/authori
tarianism-coronavirus-lockdown-pandemic-populism/.
Blackledge, Paul. Friedrich Engels and Modern Social and Political Theory. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2019.
Boer, Roland. Stalin: From Theology to the Philosophy of Socialism in Power.
Singapore: Springer, 2017.
Brenkert, George G. Political Freedom. London: Routledge, 1991.
Budd, Lucy and Stephen Ison. »Air travel restrictions won’t protect us from
the coronavirus.« The Jakarta Post, February 10, 2020. https://www.the
jakartapost.com/travel/2020/02/10/air-travel-restrictions-wont-protectus-from-the-coronavirus.html.
Bulbeck, Chilla. Re-orienting Western Feminisms: Women’s Diversity in a Postcolonial World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Carthaus, Anna. »Yuval Noah Harari on COVID-19: ›The biggest danger is
not the virus itself‹.« DW, April 22, 2020. https://www.dw.com/en/virusitself-is-not-the-biggest-danger-says-yuval-noah-harari/a-53195552.
Carver, Terrell. Engels: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2003.
—. Friedrich Engels: His Life and Thought. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1990.
Chavez, Nicole, Jason Hanna, and Christina Maxouris. »US coronavirus cases reach more than 101, 000 as reported deaths hit new daily high.« CNN,
March 28, 2020. https://edition.cnn.com/2020/03/27/health/us-coronavirus-friday/index.html.
Clarke, Michael E. Xinjiang and China’s Rise in Central Asia — A History.
Abingdon: Routledge, 2011.
Clarke, Simon. Marx, Marginalism and Modern Sociology: From Adam Smith
to Max Weber. Aldershot: Macmillan Academic, 1991.
Cosentino, Gabriele. Social Media and the Post-Truth World Order. Cham:
Springer, 2020.
De George, Richard T. »Anarchism and Authority.« Nomos 19 (1978): 91 – 110.
Ehrlich, Stanislaw. Pluralism On and Off Course. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1982.
326
Nuruddin Al Akbar
Engels, Frederick. »On Authority.« In The Marx-Engels Reader, edited by
Robert C. Tucker. New York: W. W. Norton & Company, Inc., 1978.
—. »Versus the Anarchists.« In The Marx-Engels Reader, edited by Robert C.
Tucker. New York: W. W. Norton & Company, Inc., 1978.
Evans, Michael. Karl Marx. London: Routledge, 2004.
Farrow, Robert and Rolin Moe. »Rethinking the role of the academy: cognitive authority in the age of post-truth.« Teaching in Higher Education 24,
no. 3 (2019): 272 – 287.
Feigan. »Marx’s ›Dictatorship of the Proletariat‹«. Contemporary Chinese
Thought 46, no. 2 (2015): 22 – 36.
Fetscher, Iring. »Karl Marx on Human Nature.« In Karl Marx’s Economics:
Critical Assessments, edited by John Cunningham Wood. London: Routledge, 1998.
Fischer, Frank. »Knowledge politics and post-truth in climate denial: on the
social construction of alternative facts.« Critical Policy Studies 13, no. 2
(2019): 133 – 152.
Fuchs, Christian. »Dallas Smythe Today — The Audience Commodity, the
Digital Labour Debate, Marxist Political Economy and Critical Theory.
Prolegomena to a Digital Labour Theory of Value.« In Marx and the
Political Economy of the Media, edited by Christian Fuchs and Vincent
Mosco. Leiden: Brill, 2016.
—. Digital Labour and Karl Marx. New York: Routledge, 2014.
Fuller, Steve. Post-Truth: Knowledge As A Power Game. London: Anthem
Press, 2018.
Goodwin, Barbara. Using Political Ideas. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd,
2007.
Harari, Yuval Noah. »In the Battle Against Coronavirus, Humanity Lacks
Leadership.« Time, March 15, 2020. https://time.com/5803225/yuval-noahharari-coronavirus-humanity-leadership/.
—. »Yuval Noah Harari: the world after coronavirus.« Financial Times, March
20, 2020. https://www.ft.com/content/19d90308-6858-11ea-a3c9-1fe6fedc
ca75.
Hart, Paul ’t and Karen Tindall. »From ›market correction‹ to ›global catastrophe‹: framing the economic downturn.« In Framing the Global Economic Downturn: Crisis Rhetoric and the Politics of Recessions, edited by
Paul ’t Hart and Karen Tindall. Canberra: ANU E Press, 2009.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
327
Harvey, David. »Anti-Capitalist Politics in the Time of COVID-19.« Jacobin,
March 20, 2020. https://jacobinmag.com/2020/03/david-harvey-corona
virus-political-economy-disruptions.
Henderson, William Otto. The Life of Friedrich Engels Volume I. London:
Frank Cass, 1976.
—. The Life of Friedrich Engels Volume II. London: Routledge, 1976.
Higgins-Dunn, Noah. »Travel restrictions ›irrelevant‹ if coronavirus becomes
a pandemic, top US health official says.« CNBC, February 26, 2020.
https://www.cnbc.com/2020/02/26/fauci-travel-restrictions-irrelevantif-coronavirus-becomes-a-pandemic.html.
Hindess, Barry. »Socialism, Communism, Anarchism.« In Edinburgh Companion to the History of Democracy, edited by Benjamin Isakhan and Stephen Stockwell. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2012.
Holman, Christopher. Politics as Radical Creation: Herbert Marcuse and Hannah Arendt on Political Performativity. Toronto: University of Toronto
Press, 2013.
Holton, R. J. The Transition from Feudalism to Capitalism. New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1985.
Honeywell, Carissa. A British Anarchist Tradition: Herbert Read, Alex Comfort
and Colin Ward. New York: Continuum, 2011.
Horsthemke, Kai. »›#FactsMustFall‹? — education in a post-truth, post-truthful world.« Ethics and Education 12, no. 3 (2017): 273 – 288.
Howard, Michael Charles and John Edward King. A History of Marxian Economics, Volume I: 1883 – 1929. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
1989.
Hudis, Peter. Marx’s Concept of the Alternative to Capitalism. Leiden: Brill,
2012.
Hunt, Tristram. Marx’s General: The Revolutionary Life of Friedrich Engels.
New York: Holt Paperbacks, 2009.
Jacques, Martin. »Marx’s keeper.« The Guardian, May 2, 2009. https://www.
theguardian.com/books/2009/may/02/frock-coated-engels-hunt.
Johnson, Elliott, David Walker, and Daniel Gray. Historical Dictionary of
Marxism. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 2014.
Johnson, Martin Phillip. The Paradise of Association: Political Culture and Popular Organizations in Paris Commune of 1871. Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press, 1996.
328
Nuruddin Al Akbar
Josephs, Leslie. »China grows isolated as airlines cancel more than 50, 000
flights amid coronavirus epidemic.« CNBC, February 6, 2020. https://
www.cnbc.com/2020/02/06/coronavirus-china-becomes-increasinglyisolated-as-airlines-pull-out.html.
Jun, Nathan. »Anarchism and Just War Theory.« In Comparative Just War
Theory: An Introduction to International Perspectives, edited by Luis Cordeiro-Rodrigues and Danny Singh. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield, 2020.
Kaur, Harmeet. »Forget ›social distancing.‹ The WHO prefers we call it
›physical distancing‹ because social connections are more important than
ever.« CNN, April 18, 2020. https://edition.cnn.com/2020/04/15/world/
social-distancing-language-change-trnd/index.html.
Krishna, Rachael. »This company is based in Shanghai, not Wuhan.« Full Fact,
January 30, 2020. https://fullfact.org/online/wuhan-resident-evil-corona
virus/.
Kurniati, Pythag. »Bertemu Kapolri, Polisi Jambi yang Nyanyikan Lagu Jiayou
Wuhan Ditawari Sekolah Perwira.« Kompas, March 8, 2020. https://
regional.kompas.com/read/2020/03/08/13111271/bertemu-kapolri-polisijambi-yang-nyanyikan-lagu-jiayou-wuhan-ditawari.
Lamb, Peter. Marx and Engels’s Communist Manifesto. London: Bloomsbury,
2015.
Larsson, Paula. »Anti-Asian racism during coronavirus: How the language of
disease produces hate and violence.« The Conversation, March 31, 2020.
https://theconversation.com/anti-asian-racism-during-coronavirushow-the-language-of-disease-produces-hate-and-violence-134496.
Lau, Stuart and Owen Churchill. »Xi Jinping urges ›stronger international
cooperation‹ and quick action to fight coronavirus pandemic and stave
off global recession.« South China Morning Post, March 26, 2020. https://
www.scmp.com/news/china/politics/article/3077174/xi-jinping-urgesstronger-international-cooperation-and-quick.
Leba, Elsa Emiria. »Semangat Belum Padam, Wuhan Jiayou!« Kompas, February 1, 2020. https://kompas.id/baca/internasional/2020/02/01/semangatbelum-padam-wuhan-jiayou/.
Levine, Norman. »Hegelian Continuities in Marx.« Critique 37, no. 3 (2009):
345 – 370.
Li, Huaiyin. »Rewriting Modern Chinese History in the Reform Era: Changing Narratives and Perspectives in Chinese Historiography.« In Marxist
Historiographies: A Global Perspective, edited by Q. Edward Wang and
Georg G. Iggers. Abingdon: Routledge, 2016.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
329
Li, Lea. »Police, public clash as border reopens between coronavirus epicentre Hubei and Jiangxi province.« South China Morning Post, March 29,
2020. https://www.scmp.com/video/china/3077466/police-public-clashborder-reopens-between-coronavirus-epicentre-hubei-and.
Lister, Tim, Sebastian Shukla, and Fanny Bobille. »Coronavirus sparks a ›war
for masks‹ as accusations fly.« CNN, April 3, 2020. https://edition.cnn.
com/2020/04/03/europe/coronavirus-masks-war-intl/index.html.
Lovell, David W. From Marx to Lenin: An Evaluation of Marx’s Responsibility
for Soviet Authoritarianism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984.
Löwy, Michael. »Marx, Engels, and Ecology.« Capitalism Nature Socialism 28,
no. 2 (2017): 10 – 21.
Ma, Josephine and Jun Mai. »Death of coronavirus doctor Li Wenliang becomes
catalyst for ›freedom of speech‹ demands in China.« South China Morning Post, February 7, 2020. https://www.scmp.com/news/china/politics/
article/3049606/coronavirus-doctors-death-becomes-catalyst-freedomspeech.
Macdonald, Bradley J. Performing Marx: Contemporary Negotiations of a Living Tradition. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2006.
Macguire, Eoghan. »Anti-Asian hate continues to spread online amid
COVID-19 pandemic.« Al Jazeera, April 5, 2020. https://www.aljazeera.
com/news/2020/04/anti-asian-hate-continues-spread-online-covid-19pandemic-200405063015286.html.
Magnusson, Lars and Bo Stråth. A Brief History of Political Economy: Tales of
Marx, Keynes and Hayek. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2016.
Makowski, Emily. »Theory that Coronavirus Escaped from a Lab Lacks Evidence.« The Scientist, March 5, 2020. https://www.the-scientist.com/newsopinion/theory-that-coronavirus-escaped-from-a-lab-lacks-evidence67229.
Marshall, Peter. Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism. Oakland:
PM Press, 2010.
Martusewicz, Rebecca A. »›All this Boundless Multitude:‹ Rereading Mikahail Bakunin for EcoJustice Education.« Educational Studies 48, no. 1
(2012): 1 – 4.
McClelland, J. S. A History of Western Political Thought. London: Routledge,
1996.
McLaughlin, Paul. Anarchism and Authority: A Philosophical Introduction to
Classical Anarchism. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2007.
330
Nuruddin Al Akbar
—. Mikhail Bakunin: The Philosophical Basis of His Theory of Anarchism. New
York: Algora Publishing, 2002.
Messer-Kruse, Timothy. The Haymarket Conspiracy: Transatlantic Anarchist
Networks. Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 2012.
Morrow, John. History of Western Political Thought. London: Red Globe Press,
2019.
Moseley, Fred and Tony Smith. »Introduction.« In Marx’s Capital and Hegel’s
Logic: A Reexamination, edited by Fred Moseley and Tony Smith. Leiden:
Brill, 2014.
Muhammadiyah. »MCCC Denpasar Bagikan 1000 Masker Kepada Warga
Kota Denpasar.« Muhammadiyah, April 10, 2020. http://www.muham
madiyah.or.id/id/news-18793-detail-mccc-denpasar-bagikan-1000masker-kepada-warga-kota-denpasar.html.
Nashr, Jamal A. »Tegal Lockdown karena Corona, Wali Kota: Tak Ditegur
Mendagri.« Tempo, April 3, 2020. https://nasional.tempo.co/read/1327529/
tegal-lockdown-karena-corona-wali-kota-tak-ditegur-mendagri.
Newman, Saul. From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-authoritarianism and the Dislocation of Power. Lanham: Lexington Books, 2001.
Ollman, Bertell. Alienation: Marx’s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society.
London: Cambridge University Press, 1971.
Pavon-Cuellar, David. Marxism and Psychoanalysis: In or against Psychology?
Abingdon: Routledge, 2017.
Pernicone, Nunzio. Italian Anarchism, 1864 – 1892. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1993.
Phoak, Kung. »Stop prejudice, the novel coronavirus has no race.« The Jakarta
Post, February 22, 2020. https://www.thejakartapost.com/academia/2020/
02/22/stop-prejudice-the-novel-coronavirus-has-no-race.html.
Pilliang, Yasraf Amir. »Virus De-Globalisasi.« Kompas, March 30, 2020. https://
kompas.id/baca/opini/2020/03/30/virus-de-globalisasi/.
Pillinger, Mara. »Virus Travel Bans Are Inevitable But Ineffective.« FP, February 23, 2020. https://foreignpolicy.com/2020/02/23/virus-travel-bansare-inevitable-but-ineffective/.
Portmess, Lisa. »Post-Truth: Marcuse and New Form of Social Control.« In
America’s Post-Truth Phenomenon: When Feelings and Opinions Trump
Facts and Evidence, edited by C. G. Prado. Santa Barbara: Praeger, 2018.
Prew, Paul, Tomás Rotta, Tony Smith, and Matt Vidal. »The enduring Relevance of Karl Marx.« In The Oxford Handbook of Karl Marx, edited by
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
Tomás Rotta, Tony Smith, Matt Vidal, and Paul Prew. New York: Oxford
University Press, 2019.
Quammen, David. »We Made the Coronavirus Epidemic.« The New York
Times, January 28, 2020. https://www.nytimes.com/2020/01/28/opinion/
coronavirus-china.html.
Raustiala, Kal. Does the Constitution Follow the Flag? The Evolution of Territoriality in American Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
Remley, William L. Jean-Paul Sartre’s Anarchist Philosophy. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2018.
Rezneck, Samuel. »The Political and Social Theory of Michael Bakunin.« The
American Political Science Review 21, no. 2 (1927): 270 – 296.
Roberts, William Clare. Marx’s Inferno: The Political Theory of Capital. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2017.
Rothschild, Joyce, and J. Allen Whitt. The Cooperative Workplace: Potentials
and Dilemmas of Organisational Democracy and Participation. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1989.
Sánchez Bermúdez, José Manuel. The Neoliberal Pattern of Domination: Capital’s Reign in Decline. Leiden: Brill, 2012.
Sargent, Lyman Tower. »Mikhail Bakunin (1814 – 76).« In Encyclopedia of
Nineteenth-century Thought, edited by Gregory Claeys. Abingdon: Routledge, 2005.
Saros, Daniel E. Information Technology and Socialist Construction: The End of
Capital and the Transition to Socialism. Abingdon: Routledge, 2014.
Sawer, Marian. Marxism and the Question of the Asiatic Mode of Production.
The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1977.
Schwartz, Joseph M. The Permanence of the Political: A Democratic Critique
of the Radical Impulse to Transcend Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995.
Setiadi, Tresno. »Kisah Mahasiswa di Wuhan Saat Virus Corona Merebak,
Teriak »Jiayou« dari Balik Jendela.« Kompas, February 17, 2020. https://
regional.kompas.com/read/2020/02/17/17033981/kisah-mahasiswa-diwuhan-saat-virus-corona-merebak-teriak-jiayou-dari-balik?page=all.
Shantz, Jeff. Constructive Anarchy: Building Infrastructures of Resistance. Farnham: Ashgate, 2010.
Shantz, Jeffrey and Dana M. Williams. Anarchy and Society: Reflections on
Anarchist Sociology. Leiden: Brill, 2013.
331
332
Nuruddin Al Akbar
Shiva, Vandana. »Ecological Reflections on the Coronavirus.« Medium,
March 23, 2020. https://medium.com/post-growth-institute/ecologicalreflections-on-the-coronavirus-93d50bbfe9db.
Simsek, Ayhan. »Merkel: Coronavirus biggest challenge in EU’s history.«
Anadolu Agency, April 6, 2020. https://www.aa.com.tr/en/europe/merkelcoronavirus-biggest-challenge-in-eu-s-history/1794764.
Singer, Peter. Marx: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2000.
Solis, Marie. »Coronavirus Is the Perfect Disaster for ›Disaster Capitalism‹«.
Vice, March 13, 2020. https://www.vice.com/en_uk/article/5dmqyk/naomiklein-interview-on-coronavirus-and-disaster-capitalism-shock-doctrine.
Stellino, Molly. »Fact check: Did the coronavirus originate in a Chinese
laboratory?« USA Today, March 22, 2020. https://www.usatoday.com/
story/news/factcheck/2020/03/21/fact-check-did-coronavirus-originatechinese-laboratory/2881150001/.
Sukirno, Ahmad. »Komunitas Difabel Boyolali Bikin Masker untuk Warga
Miskin.« rri.co.id, April 8, 2020. http://rri.co.id/post/berita/816848/daerah/
komunitas_difabel_boyolali_bikin_masker_untuk_warga_miskin.html.
Suryajaya, Martin. »Membayangkan Ekonomi Dunia Setelah Korona Atau
Cerita tentang Dua Virus.« MartinSuryajaya.com, March 30, 2020. https://
www.martinsuryajaya.com/post/membayangkan-ekonomi-duniasetelah-korona.
Syambudi, Irwan. »Lockdown Mandiri ala Jogja: Ditolak Pemerintah, Diinginkan Warga.« Tirto, March 27, 2020. https://tirto.id/lockdown-mandiriala-jogja-ditolak-pemerintah-diinginkan-warga-eH3o.
Syawaludin, Makhfud. »NU Kabupaten Pasuruan Segera Bagikan 50 Ribu
Masker Kain.« NU Online, April 11, 2020. https://www.nu.or.id/post/read/
118950/nu-kabupaten-pasuruan-segera-bagikan-50-ribu-masker-kain.
Taş, Hakkı. »The 15 July abortive coup and post-truth politics in Turkey.«
Southeast European and Black Sea Studies 18, no. 1 (2018): 1 – 19.
Tavernise, Sabrina and Richard A. Oppel, Jr. »Spit On, Yelled At, Attacked: Chinese-Americans Fear for Their Safety.« The New York Times, March 23, 2020.
https://www.nytimes.com/2020/03/23/us/chinese-coronavirus-racistattacks.html.
The Anarchist FAQ Editorial Collective. »An Anarchist FAQ (09 / 17).« Accessed April 1, 2020. https://theanarchistlibrary.org/library/the-anarchistfaq-editorial-collective-an-anarchist-faq-09-17.pdf.
Post-Truth Coronavirus Outbreak
333
The Jakarta Post. »COVID-19: Regions start locking down as govt works
on regulation.« The Jakarta Post, March 28, 2020. https://www.thejakarta
post.com/news/2020/03/28/covid-19-regions-start-locking-down-asgovt-works-on-regulation.html.
The UNESCO Courier. »Yuval Noah Harari: ›Every crisis is also an opportunity‹«. Accessed April 30, 2020. https://en.unesco.org/courier/newsviews-online/yuval-noah-harari-every-crisis-also-opportunity.
Thomas, Paul. Karl Marx and the Anarchists. Abingdon: Routledge, 2010.
Tisdall, Simon. »Covid-19 is exposing the frailty in autocrats and democrats
alike.« The Guardian, March 15, 2020. https://www.theguardian.com/
commentisfree/2020/mar/15/covid-19-exposing-frailties-autocrats-demo
crats-alike-trump-xi-eu-un.
Tsang, Yuki. »›Shoot them dead‹: Philippine President Duterte warns coronavirus lockdown violators.« South China Morning Post, April 2, 2020. https://
www.scmp.com/video/coronavirus/3078165/shoot-them-dead-philip
pine-president-duterte-warns-coronavirus-lockdown.
Voegelin, Eric. From Enlightenment to Revolution. Durham: Duke University
Press, 1975.
Ward, Colin. Anarchism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
Whitworth, Andrew. Information Obesity. Oxford: Chandos Publishing, 2009.
Wilde, Lawrence. Global Solidarity. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,
2013.
Willsher, Kim, Julian Borger, and Oliver Holmes. »US accused of ›modern piracy‹ after diversion of masks meant for Europe.« The Guardian, April 4, 2020. https://www.theguardian.com/world/2020/apr/03/
mask-wars-coronavirus-outbidding-demand.
Wilson, Scott. »Pre-truth, Post-truth and the Present: Jacques Lacan and the
Real Horror of Contemporary Knowledge.« In Post-Truth and the Mediation of Reality: New Conjunctures, edited by Rosemary Overell and Brett
Nicholls. Cham: Springer, 2020.
Woods, Emma. »Science Policy in a Post-Truth World.« In Risk and Uncertainty in a Post-Truth Society, edited by Sander van der Linden and
Ragnar E. Löfstedt. Abingdon: Routledge, 2019.
Yang, Huan, Peng Bin, and Alex Jingwei He. »Opinions from the epicenter:
an online survey of university students in Wuhan amidst the COVID-19
outbreak.« Journal of Chinese Governance 5, no. 2 (2020): 234 – 248.
334
Nuruddin Al Akbar
Yeung, Jessie. »A global coronavirus: Travel bans, face masks, and fear.« CNN,
February 27, 2020. https://edition.cnn.com/2020/02/27/world/gallery/
coronavirus-prevention/index.html.
Yu, Jianxing. »Confronting and Governing the Public Health Emergency.«Journal of Chinese Governance 5, no. 2 (2020): 137 – 139.
Yuki. »The semantical issue behind Engels’s »On Authority« and how it relates
to modern day anarchism.« The Anarchist Library, July 12, 2019. https://
theanarchistlibrary.org/library/yuki-the-semantical-issue-behind-engelson-authority-and-how-it-relates-to-modern-day-anarchism#fn1.
Zalan, Eszter. »Merkel: Virus is biggest challenge in EU history.« Euobserver,
April 7, 2020. https://euobserver.com/coronavirus/148003.
Zizek, Slavoj. »Barbarism with a Human Face.« Welt, March 19, 2020. https://
www.welt.de/kultur/literarischewelt/article206829259/Slavoj-Zizek-onCorona-Barbarism-with-a-Human-Face.html.
Engels as Course Reading
in the 21st Century History Classroom
Alexander Maxwell
This chapter examines Friedrich Engels’s Condition of the Working
Class in England (1845)1 as a course reading for first-year university
students. Its narrative is essentially autobiographical. I describe my
personal motives to the text when I first thought to assign it in a
»Modern Europe« survey course, student reactions, and how student
reactions affected subsequent iterations of the first-year survey. As it
happens, my students, mostly millennials, responded more favorably
to the text than I had expected. Their enthusiasm ultimately inspired
me to reevaluate Engels’s continued relevance in the 21st century.
An autobiographical narrative, perhaps, should begin with an autobiographical sketch. I was born in Los Angeles, spent most of my
high school years in Southern California, and did my undergraduate degree at the University of California, Davis. For this degree, I
spent two years as an exchange student in Germany. I found life
in Central Europe congenial. While in Germany, I studied Czech
and after graduating moved to Prague to teach English as a Second Language (ESL). I have since lived, worked or studied in several
Central European towns, including Bratislava, Budapest, Bucharest,
and Erfurt. When I did my history Ph.D, I wrote my thesis on Slovak history. After finishing my doctorate, I found short-term jobs
in Wales and Nevada, and eventually landed a permanent position
at Victoria University of Wellington, New Zealand. I am happily
1
Friedrich Engels, Die Lage der arbeitenden Klasse in England (Leipzig: Otto
Wigand, 1845); first English translation by Florence Kelley Wyschnewetzky, The
Condition of the Working Class in England in 1844 (New York: John W. Lovell,
1887).
336
Alexander Maxwell
settled in New Zealand, but when I feel homesick, I feel homesick
for Central Europe.
Neither my adolescence in Southern California nor my undergraduate education provided any particular emphasis on the works of
Karl Marx or Friedrich Engels. I was assigned some Marx to read in
an excellent undergraduate course called »European Intellectual History,« but my strongest memory of reading Marx as an undergraduate
is a metaphor comparing economic progress to »that hideous, pagan
idol who would not drink the nectar but from the skulls of the slain.«2
At 18, I found Marx’s prose pleasingly dramatic. As far as I remember,
I did not read any Engels as an undergraduate.
Nor did my formative experiences in the ruins of the Soviet Empire encourage a serious study of Marxism. On the contrary: conversations I had in the former Eastern bloc after the fall of the Berlin Wall encouraged a contemptuous attitude. I treated the failure
of the Soviet system as self-evident, and the collapse of the Soviet
system as a boon to humanity. During the early 1990s, I was not
alone treating the Soviet Union’s failure as a definitive repudiation
of Marxism. My atheism repelled me from American conservatism
and I usually took leftist positions on cultural issues like gay rights,
but as a young man I accepted market economics, regularly read The
Economist, and basically approved of how Tony Blair changed the
British Labour party.
My graduate training, furthermore, did not lead me to the Marxist
classics. I specialized in the origins of nationalism. The 19th century
may be the century in which Engels lived, but most East-Central
European historiographies also remember it as the era of so-called
»national awakening.« I wrote my master’s thesis on national awakening in North Macedonia, my doctoral thesis on national awakening
in Slovakia, my second book on clothing and national awakening,
2
Karl Marx, »The Future Results of British Rule in India,« New-York Daily Tribune, August 8, 1853, cited in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Collected Works
(New York: International Publishers, 1979), 222.
Engels as Course Reading in the 21st Century History Classroom
337
and my third book on national awakening in Hungary.3 I have also
published several works on nationalism theory.4 The nationalist ideologies and nationalist activism that interest me tend to come from the
middle classes, they do not reflect the struggles of workers or proletarians. Nationalism, as I study it, belongs to intellectual and cultural
history: it is rather removed from the social or economic history that
interested Marx and Engels.
Scholars influenced by the thought of Marx and Engels have admittedly made several outstanding contributions to nationalism theory. Austrian Social Democratic politician and Marxist theorist Otto
Bauer (1881 – 1938) wrote an excellent overview of how nationalist politics developed in Habsburg Austria.5 Bauer particularly influenced the
3
4
5
Alexander Maxwell, Choosing Slovakia: Slavic Hungary, the Czech Language and
Unintended Nationalism (London: I. B. Tauris, 2009); Alexander Maxwell, Patriots Against Fashion: Clothing and Nationalism in Europe’s Age of Revolutions
(London: Palgrave, 2014); Alexander Maxwell, Everyday Nationalism in Hungary
(Berlin: De Gruyter Oldenbourg, 2019).
Alexander Maxwell, »Primordialism for Scholars Who Ought to Know Better:
Anthony D. Smith’s Critique of Modernization Theory,« Nationalities Papers
(published online March 2020), DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/nps.2019.93; Alexander Maxwell and Molly Turner, »Nationalists Rejecting Statehood: Three
Case Studies from Wales, Catalonia, and Slovakia,« Nations and Nationalism,
(published online December 2019), DOI: 10.1111/nana.12577; Alexander Maxwell, »›Supplicant Nationalism‹ in Slovakia and Wales: Polyethnic Rights During
the Nineteenth Century,« Central Europe 16, no. 1 (2018): 29 – 50; Alexander
Maxwell, »Nationalism as Classification: Suggestions for Reformulating Nationalism Research,« Nationalities Papers 46, no. 4 (2018): 539 – 555; Alexander Maxwell, »Nationalism and Sexuality,« in The Wiley Blackwell Encyclopedia of Gender
and Sexuality Studies, ed. Nancy Naples (Oxford: Wiley Blackwell, 2016), vol. 4,
1741 – 1744; Alexander Maxwell, »Typologies and Phase Theories in Nationalism Studies: Hroch’s A-B-C Schema as a Basis for Comparative Terminology,«
Nationalities Papers 38, no. 6 (2010): 865 – 880; Alexander Maxwell, »Multiple
Nationalism: National Concepts in 19th Century Hungary and Benedict Anderson’s ›Imagined Communities‹,« Nationalism and Ethnic Politics 11, no. 3 (2005):
385 – 414.
Otto Bauer, Die Nationalitätenfrage und die Sozialdemokratie (Vienna: Ignaz
Brand, 1907); available in English as The Question of Nationalities and Social
Democracy (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2000).
338
Alexander Maxwell
Czech scholar Miroslav Hroch,6 author of the influential Social Preconditions of National Revival in Europe, the first work I read in graduate school.7 I was ultimately more impressed by the British Marxist
historian Benedict Anderson (1936 – 2015), whose Imagined Communities has become a classic in the field.8 The influential historian Eric
Hobsbawm (1917 – 2012) also wrote from a Marxist perspective.9 These
scholars persuaded me that nationalism arises from social transformations that are not really captured by the phrase »industrial revolution,«
but can, for want of a better term, be summarized as »modernization.«
Yet if Marxist nationalism scholars influenced my understanding of
how nationalism arises, they neither inspired me to read Marx and
Engels nor much influenced my political stances. I found their work
interesting despite rather than because of their Marxism.
When I started designing undergraduate course syllabi, in short, I
had no special desire to assign Engels, or indeed any Marxist classics.
American conservatives often express suspicion of »Marxist professors,« as John Wilson documented in his analysis of »the conservative
attack on higher education.«10 While I would certainly have failed any
conservative purity test, I doubt anybody actually claiming to be a
Marxist would acknowledge me as espousing any flavor of Marxism.
My first chance to teach the modern Europe survey came in 2006.
I won a one-year temporary teaching fellowship at the University of
6
7
8
9
10
Miroslav Hroch, »Learning from Small Nations, Interview,« New Left Review 58
(2009): 43.
Miroslav Hroch, Die Vorkämpfer der nationalen Bewegung bei den kleinen Völkern
Europas: Eine vergleichende Analyse zur gesellschaftlichen Schichtung der patriotischen Gruppen (Prague: Charles University, 1968); available in English as Social
Preconditions of National Revival in Europe: A Comparative Analysis of the Social
Composition of Patriotic Groups Among the Smaller European Nations (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1985).
Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread
of Nationalism (London: Verson, 1983).
Eric Hobsbawm, Nations and Nationalism since 1780: Programme, Myth, Reality
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
John Wilson, The Myth of Political Correctness: The Conservative Attack on Higher
Education (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1995), 10 – 11.
Engels as Course Reading in the 21st Century History Classroom
339
Nevada, Reno. The main theme of the course, as I taught it, was
the rise of nationalist politics. Skeptical of textbooks but encouraged
to use one, I chose Mark Kishlansky’s Sources of the West: Readings
in Western Civilization, an anthology of bite-sized excerpts from various primary sources. I felt some moral pressure to select readings
from Kishlansky’s textbook wherever possible so that students would
get value for their textbook purchase. The course contained fourteen
weeks; I gave two lectures each week. In week 8, I discussed Marxism
in a grab-bag lecture that also covered Darwin, secularization, and
suffragism. For that week, I assigned as course reading Kishlansky’s
excerpt from Condition of the Working Class in England.11
Several considerations led me to assign Engels, rather than any
other sources found in Kishlansky. I started from the pedagogical
assumption that students in Nevada might struggle to understand
the appeal of socialism to historical actors. Given my own politics, I
was hardly hoping that my course lectures and course readings would
convert students to Marxist politics, but hoped to persuade students,
some of whom I assumed would be strongly anti-Communist, that
Marxism, socialism, and communism arose in response to pressing
social problems. Kishlansky also offers an excerpt from the Communist Manifesto,12 but Engels’s detail-oriented description of urban
squalor seemed more likely to help conservative or unworldly middle-class American students appreciate the suffering caused by the
industrial revolution.
I felt some trepidation about how the class would respond to Engels. Teaching in a state that had just helped re-elect George W. Bush,
I worried that some conservative students might refuse on principle to
11
12
Friedrich Engels, »The Condition of the Working Class in England (1845),« excerpt in Sources of the West: Readings in Western Civilization, vol. 2, eds. Mark
Kishlansky, Patrick Geary and Patricia O’Brien (New York: Longman: 2006),
reading 103.
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, »The Communist Manifesto,« excerpt in: Sources of the West: Readings in Western Civilization, vol. 2, eds. Mark Kishlansky, Patrick Geary and Patricia O’Brien (New York: Longman: 2006), reading 112.
340
Alexander Maxwell
read anything by a Communist icon. I also feared that Engels might
strike them as dreary. So, for my 2006 course, I assigned two other
course readings to accompany Engels: Kishlansky’s excerpt from Beatrice Webb’s Women and the Factory Acts (1896), and a short excerpt
from Coventry Patemore’s poem »Angel of the House« (1854).13 The
Webb text illustrates how socialist activists tried to improve the lives
of working class women. Patemore’s ode to bourgeois domesticity, I
hoped, would strikingly contrast with working-class concerns. Viewing working class suffering through the lens of gender would also
speak to the feminist themes of the lecture, and perhaps the poem,
which I thought fascinating, would compensate for a course reading I
personally had not found particularly interesting.
My 2006 students in Nevada did not respond to these course readings as I anticipated. Patemore’s poem left them wholly cold, and they
did not want to discuss any gender issues. Instead, they wanted to
discuss Engels! They immediately understood and appreciated precarity as a social problem, they reacted with fascination to Engels’s
description of working-class squalor. One student decided to change
the topic of his research essay so as to study Engels more carefully. I
had wholly misjudged student reactions.
I remembered student enthusiasm for Engels when designing another modern Europe survey after my arrival in New Zealand. In
2008, shortly after joining the faculty of Victoria University of Wellington, a senior colleague and I created lectures for a team-taught
course, given over a twelve-week semester. There were two lectures
a week, and after the first week, students also attended a weekly »tutorial« (discussion section). I still taught my half of the course as the
rise of nationalism, but the different teaching circumstances required
13
Beatrice Webb, »Women and the Factory Acts (1896)« excerpt in Sources of the
West: Readings in Western Civilization, vol. 2, eds. Mark Kishlansky, Patrick Geary
and Patricia O’Brien (New York: Longman: 2006), reading 120; »The Angel of
the House,« excerpt from Bernie Heidkamp, Genders and Identities in the Poetry of Walt Whitman (1997). Accessed March 25, 2020. https://whitmanarchive.
org/archive1/classroom/student_projects/bernie/patmore.html.
Engels as Course Reading in the 21st Century History Classroom
341
several innovations. In Wellington, for example, faculty routinely
compile their own books of readings instead of using a textbook, I
thus gained more freedom to choose whatever reading best served my
pedagogical aims.
My colleague and I chose to devote the eleven weekly tutorials
to the in-depth discussion of primary sources, which encouraged us
to find a single text. Kishlansky’s brief excerpts would no longer be
appropriate: we needed something longer. When selecting readings,
my colleague and I both prioritized exposing students to canonical
texts, echoing the spirit of a so-called »great books« course. Marxism,
socialism, and communism have been important forces in world history and educated people should have some idea what they are about.
Engels’s The Condition of the Working Class in England surely qualifies
as one of the »great books.« So, however, would several works by the
even more famous Karl Marx. Browsing anthologies of Marxist classics for a suitable reading, I looked first for something written by
Marx.
In the end, however, I again chose Engels’s Condition of the Working Class in England. Marx’s Capital proved much too long and complex for a first-year modern Europe survey, and I found no suitably
self-contained excerpts. I more seriously considered a chapter from
the Communist Manifesto. The book as a whole seemed too long for
one week’s course reading; students who have to read more than 40
pages tend not to be prepared for class discussion, but the individual chapters are about the right length. The opening chapter, »Bourgeois and Proletarians,« nicely outlines the Marxist theory of history.
The stirring bit about proletarians having nothing to lose but their
chains, however, comes from the end of the final chapter, »Position of
the Communists in relation to the various existing Opposition Parties.« This last chapter, however, opens by expressing support for the
Chartists in England, Agrarian reformers in America, Social Democrats in France, the Radicals in Switzerland, and the 1846 uprising in
Kraków. I feared first-year students in New Zealand would be overwhelmed if the course reading began with a long list of unfamiliar
342
Alexander Maxwell
political parties. I remembered how positively students in Nevada had
responded to Engels, so I stuck with that.
Since I needed a lengthier reading, I also properly read Engels for
the first time. The book proved more engaging than Kishlansky’s excerpts had led me to believe. Engels describes hunger, streets, houses,
furniture, clothing, and toilets: everything is immediate and concrete.
Engels mentions several place names that students in New Zealand
do not know, such as Benthal Green and »the famous rookery of
St. Giles,«14 but the point comes through even if readers are not familiar with English geography. My favourite passage from the whole work
occurs in the chapter »the Great Towns,« in which Engels describes a
traveler arriving in London by ship. The sight of the Thames packed
with tall-masted ships, Engels tells his readers, »is so vast, so impressive, that a man cannot collect himself but is lost in the marvel of England’s greatness before he sets foot upon English soil.«15 The passage
illustrates an enthusiasm for progress I expected students would find
surprising, and its eloquence also captured my imagination.
In the end, therefore, my senior colleague and I assigned Engels for
tutorial discussion. The accompanying lecture remained a grab-bag of
19th-century social movements, covering socialism alongside secularism, racial »science,« anti-Semitism, and suffragism. I extended the
bit on socialism, transcribing key passages from the Communist Manifesto onto PowerPoint slides. My colleague and I did not teach the
tutorials ourselves, but indirect feedback from postgraduate student
tutors was positive. In New Zealand, as in Nevada, students liked
reading Engels.
Ten years later, I am teaching still another first year Modern Europe survey. The course is still team taught, but my senior colleague
has left the department and been replaced by a junior colleague. I am
still a scholar of nationalism and I still dwell primarily on the rise of
nationalism in the course narrative overall. Nevertheless, my lectures
14
15
Friedrich Engels, Condition of the Working Class in England (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1993), 41, 39.
Ibid., 36.
Engels as Course Reading in the 21st Century History Classroom
343
now depict socialism as a serious if ultimately unsuccessful alternative
to national movements. I still show excerpts from the Communist
Manifesto on PowerPoint slides, but in the relevant lecture Marx no
longer shares space with secularism or suffragism. I instead depict
utopian socialism, Marxism, and anarchism as social consequences
of the industrial revolution. The lecture also links more directly with
subsequent lectures on 20th-century communism.
In the meantime, I have also acquired a deeper understanding of
the history of socialism. Preparing lectures for a different course, I
read biographies of Marx, Vladimir I. Lenin (1870 – 1924) and Leon
Trotsky (1879 – 1940), which in turn inspired me to broader reading
about the First and Second International, as well as the history of
anarchism. My deeper understanding in turn informed my first-year
lectures. To demonstrate the internationalist scope of the First International, for example, I made a PowerPoint slide depicting on a
map the location of active correspondents in the first half of 1866;
to construct the map I went through the minutes from the First
International.16
In the most recent version of the syllabus, last taught in 2018, I
have also further expanded the Engels content. As in my 2008 course,
students are supposed to discuss the »The Great Towns« in the tutorial meetings for week eight. As in the past, students find the reading
engaging, and tutors describe it as one of the more successful tutorials.
Students like reading Engels! The 2018 course, furthermore, requires
students to buy a cheap paperback edition of Condition of the Working Class in England and write a short essay about it. Students have
two options for their essay on Engels. Both options require students
to analyze his text in light of another course reading, chosen so as to
minimize the chance that an online essay mill will have an essay ready
to download.
16
The General Council of the First International, 1864 – 1866, The London Conference
1865, Minutes (Moscow: Progress, 1964).
344
Alexander Maxwell
The first essay option asks students whether the political system
described in the 1789 »Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen,« a founding constitutional document from the French Revolution, provides the necessary means to address the injustices Engels
outlines. Students generally answer in the negative: they do not think
that a »democratic« government is sufficient to curb the excesses of
the industrial revolution. Our students mostly come from the comfortable middle classes; I am not sure whether they realize that their
skepticism implies a radical rejection of parliamentary democracy.
The second essay option asks students to compare the living conditions Engels describes with those depicted in Slavenka Drakulić’s
How We Survived Communism and Even Laughed, an extremely readable memoir of socialist Yugoslavia.17 Student opinion on this question is more evenly divided: some emphasize differences, others stress
similarities. Several students compare Drakulić’s description of shoddy Yugoslav housing to their own student accommodation in Wellington. (Rental housing in New Zealand is shockingly poor overall).18
Over the course of my career, therefore, Engels has steadily grown
in importance. Initially assigned as only in the form of a brief excerpt,
Engels’s Condition of the Working Class in England has fifteen years
later become a staple course reading in my »Modern Europe« survey.
As a course reading, the text has proved much more successful than
I had expected. Indeed, it may be the only course reading I assign in
which students get more out of the reading than I do. Indeed, looking
back, my own inability to predict the appeal of Engels may be the
most interesting feature of the story.
17
18
Slavenka Drakulić, »On Doing Laundry,« in How We Survived Communism and
even Laughed (New York: Vintage, 1987), 43 – 54.
Philippa Howden-Chapman et al., »Tackling Cold Housing and Fuel Poverty in
New Zealand: A Review of Policies, Research, and Health Impacts,« Energy Policy 49 (2012): 134 – 142; Elinor Chisholm and Kimberley O’Sullivan, »Using Twitter to Explore (Un)Healthy Housing: Learning from the # Characterbuildings
Campaign in New Zealand,« International Journal of Environmental Research and
Public Health 14, no. 11 (2017): 1424.
Engels as Course Reading in the 21st Century History Classroom
345
My inability to anticipate the appeal of Engels could have any
number of causes, but a difference in social origins seems unlikely.
I resemble most of my students in that I enjoy white privilege in a
settler society. Polynesian students attend Victoria University of Wellington, and students of color attended the University of Nevada at
Reno, but such students have not been strongly represented in the
first year »Modern Europe« survey. The students in my courses probably boast from more diverse class backgrounds, but my downwardly
mobile middle-class upbringing has not created any noticeable cultural differences between me and my students.
My students, however, are much more concerned about their own
economic prospects than I had been at their age. I grew up in the final
years of the Keynesian consensus. As a child, I did not know what I
wanted to be »when I grew up,« but I feared boring, meaningless work
more than unemployment and poverty. Nor did I question whether
I could afford university, I assumed a way would somehow be found.
My confidence was not entirely misplaced. My father paid the loan I
took out for my undergraduate degree, and I won fellowships for my
graduate study. University history teaching jobs are hard to find and I
did not have a proper job until I was thirty-eight years old, but I got
one in the end, even if I had to move to a distant country that I had
never previously visited. Thanks to some combination of perseverance and good fortune, things worked out for me in the end.
The students I teach, by contrast, are coming of age in an era of
neoliberalism, and experience the precarity that neoliberalism implies.
Since several authors have ably documented the overall trend toward
economic insecurity in recent decades,19 I will here consider only the
cost of university tuition. I began my undergraduate degree in the
19
Loïc Wacquant, Punishing the Poor: The Neoliberal Government of Social Insecurity (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2009); Rob Lambert and Andrew
Herod, eds. Neoliberal Capitalism and Precarious Work: Ethnographies of Accommodation and Resistance (Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2016);
Sanford Schram, The Return of Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity, Occupy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015).
346
Alexander Maxwell
1987 / 8 school year, and taught my first Modern Europe survey in
Nevada in 2005 / 6. During that time, the cost of American university education at a four-year institution, adjusted for inflation, has
more than doubled, rising from US$ 9,223 in 1987 / 8 to US$ 21,281
in 2005 / 6 (in constant 2016 / 7 dollars).20 The situation aspiring students face in New Zealand is not nearly so dire, but the trend is
moving in the same direction. In 2000, the median total student debt
upon graduation was NZ$ 2,360, but in 2016, the most recent year
for which figures are available, the median total student debt was
NZ$ 18,650.21 The erosion of the welfare state is a global process, affecting both Nevada and New Zealand.
Declining economic opportunity has led to a general divergence
in political opinions. Economic precarity, Ruth Milkman argues,
has contributed to »a new political generation« more open to socialist thinking.22 A 2019 Gallup survey found, for example, that 49 %
of Millennials have a positive view of »Socialism,« as compared to
39 % of my own generation, and 32 % of Baby Boomers. The same
poll found millenials relatively disenchanted with »Capitalism.«23
This generational shift has caused anxiety among existing elites: the
Washington Post, for example, published an alarmist editorial under
the headline »Millennials have a higher opinion of socialism than
20
21
22
23
»Table 330.10: Average Undergraduate Tuition and Fees and Room and Board
Rates … Selected Years, 1963 – 64 through 2016 – 17,« National Center for Education Statistics (2017). Accessed January 24, 2020. https://nces.ed.gov/programs/
digest/d17/tables/dt17_330.10.asp.
»Median Annual Amount Borrowed and Median Student Loan Leaving Balance,«
data table available at »Affordability of Tertiary Education to Students,« Ministry of Education, New Zealand Government (2020). Accessed January 24, 2020.
https://www.educationcounts.govt.nz/statistics/indicators/main/family-andcommunity-engagement/1999.
Ruth Milkman, »A New Political Generation: Millennials and the Post-2008
Wave of Protest,« American Sociological Review 82, no. 1 (2017): 1 – 31.
Lydia Saad, »Socialism as Popular as Capitalism Among Young Adults in U. S.,«
Gallup, October 1 – 13, 2019. Accessed January 24, 2020. https://news.gallup.com/
poll/268766/socialism-popular-capitalism-among-young-adults.aspx.
Engels as Course Reading in the 21st Century History Classroom
347
of capitalism.«24 I suspect that New Zealand students sympathetic to socialism, if confronted with the Washington Post’s anxieties,
would respond much as New Zealand Green MP Chlöe Swarbrick
responded to a parliamentary heckler: »OK Boomer.«25
Perhaps, then, my students like reading Engels because they find
him relevant to their lives. Engels shines a spotlight on precarity, and
that speaks to their anxieties about their own futures. He also provides a scathing and timeless critique of establishment hypocrisy, for
example, in his memorable denunciation of those »charitable out of
self-interest,«26 and I think students respond to that, as well. Most
importantly, he frames inequality and poverty as injustices deserving
remedy.
One could, of course, over-state Engels’s relevance to millennial
concerns. Millennials are supposedly the first generation of »digital
natives,« and since Engels did not anticipate the internet, he has little
to say about its dilemmas. Millennials are also concerned about the
environmental crisis. I struggle to see Engels as a pioneering environmentalist, even if, as Ted Benton rightly observed, »Engels makes
links between the environmental conditions and health of the industrial working population on the one hand, and their working conditions and class relations on the other.«27 Even Engels’s analysis of
industrial capitalism, furthermore, provides few answers to Lenin’s
famous question »What is to be done?«28 Engels calls for dramatic
changes to the structure of society without divisively spelling out
24
25
26
27
28
Catherine Rampell, »Millennials Have a Higher Opinion of Socialism than of
Capitalism,« Washington Post, February 6, 2016.
Dan Satherley, »›OK Boomer‹: World Reacts to NZ Politician Chloe Swarbrick’s
Use of Meme in Parliament,« Newshub, November 7, 2019. Accessed January
24, 2020. https://www.newshub.co.nz/home/politics/2019/11/ok-boomer-worldreacts-to-nz-politician-chloe-swarbrick-s-use-of-meme-in-parliament.html.
Engels, Condition of the Working Class, 283 – 284.
Ted Benton, »Engels and the Politics of Nature,« in Engels Today, ed. Christopher
Arthur (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 1996), 68.
Vladimir I. Lenin, Chto dělat’? Nabolěvshie voprosy nashego dvizhenije (Stuttgart:
Dietz, 1902); see also »What is to be Done?« in Collected Works (Moscow: Foreign
Languages Publishing House, 1961), vol. 5, 347 – 530.
348
Alexander Maxwell
what exactly those changes ought to be. Identifying problems is easier
than finding solutions. Students presumably would not respond as
well to the book if it confronted them with concrete policy proposals.
Students nevertheless engage so deeply with Engels that I have in
turn found myself drawn to more closely his ideas in my middle age.
If a relatively privileged youth explains why I was unable to predict
Engels’s appeal when I started teaching, reading Engels with multiple
cohorts of undergraduate students has helped me see the power and
relevance of his thought in the 21st century. My economic opinions
have also shifted leftwards: I no longer read The Economist, even if I
still do not make a very good Marxist. The work of Engels, mediated
through the appreciative eyes of my undergraduate students, played a
role in shaping my political views.
Works Cited
»Affordability of Tertiary Education to Students,« Ministry of Education, New
Zealand Government (2020). Accessed January 24, 2020. https://www.
educationcounts.govt.nz/statistics/indicators/main/family-and-commu
nity-engagement/1999.
Anderson, Benedict. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and
Spread of Nationalism. London: Verson, 1983.
Bauer, Otto. Die Nationalitätenfrage und die Sozialdemokratie. Vienna: Ignaz
Brand, 1907.
—. The Question of Nationalities and Social Democracy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2000.
Benton, Ted. »Engels and the Politics of Nature.« In Engels Today, ed. Christopher Arthur, 67 – 93. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 1996.
Chisholm, Elinor and Kimberley O’Sullivan. »Using Twitter to Explore (Un)
Healthy Housing: Learning from the # Characterbuildings Campaign
in New Zealand.« International Journal of Environmental Research and
Public Health 14, no. 11 (2017): 1424.
Drakulić, Slavenka. How We Survived Communism and even Laughed. New
York: Vintage, 1987.
Engels as Course Reading in the 21st Century History Classroom
349
Engels, Friedrich. Die Lage der arbeitenden Klasse in England. Leipzig: Otto
Wigand, 1844.
—. The Condition of the Working Class in England in 1844, transl. by Florence
Kelley Wyschnewetzky. New York: John W. Lovell, 1887.
—. Condition of the Working Class in England. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1993.
Hobsbawm, Eric. Nations and Nationalism since 1780: Programme, Myth,
Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.
Howden-Chapman, Philippa et al., »Tackling Cold Housing and Fuel Poverty in New Zealand: A Review of Policies, Research, and Health Impacts.«
Energy Policy 49 (2012): 134 – 142
Hroch, Miroslav. Die Vorkämpfer der nationalen Bewegung bei den kleinen
Völkern Europas: Eine vergleichende Analyse zur gesellschaftlichen Schichtung der patriotischen Gruppen. Prague: Charles University, 1968.
—. »Learning from Small Nations, Interview.« New Left Review 58 (2009):
41 – 59.
—. Social Preconditions of National Revival in Europe: A Comparative Analysis
of the Social Composition of Patriotic Groups Among the Smaller European
Nations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.
Kishlansky, Mark, Patrick Geary and Patricia O’Brien Sources of the West:
Readings in Western Civilization, vol. 2. New York: Longman: 2006.
Lambert, Rob and Andrew Herod, eds. Neoliberal Capitalism and Precarious
Work: Ethnographies of Accommodation and Resistance. Cheltenham, UK:
Edward Elgar Publishing, 2016.
Lenin, Vladimir I. Chto dělat’? Nabolěvshie voprosy nashego dvizhenije. Stuttgart: Dietz, 1902.
—. Collected Works, vol. 5. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House,
1961.
Marx, Karl and Friedrich Engels. Collected Works. New York: International
Publishers, 1979.
Maxwell, Alexander. Choosing Slovakia: Slavic Hungary, the Czech Language
and Unintended Nationalism. London: I. B. Tauris, 2009.
—. Everyday Nationalism in Hungary. Berlin: De Gruyter Oldenbourg, 2019.
—. »Nationalism and Sexuality.« in The Wiley Blackwell Encyclopedia of Gender and Sexuality Studies, ed. Nancy Naples (Oxford: Wiley Blackwell,
2016), vol. 4, 1741 – 1744.
350
Alexander Maxwell
—. »Multiple Nationalism: National Concepts in 19th Century Hungary and
Benedict Anderson’s ›Imagined Communities‹.« Nationalism and Ethnic
Politics 11, no. 3 (2005): 385 – 414.
—. »Nationalism as Classification: Suggestions for Reformulating Nationalism Research.« Nationalities Papers 46, no. 4 (2018): 539 – 555.
— and Molly Turner, »Nationalists Rejecting Statehood: Three Case Studies
from Wales, Catalonia, and Slovakia.« Nations and Nationalism, (published online December 2019), DOI: 10.1111/nana.12577
—. Patriots Against Fashion: Clothing and Nationalism in Europe’s Age of Revolutions. London: Palgrave, 2014.
—. »Primordialism for Scholars Who Ought to Know Better: Anthony D.
Smith’s Critique of Modernization Theory.« Nationalities Papers, (published online March 2020), DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/nps.2019.93.
—. »›Supplicant Nationalism‹ in Slovakia and Wales: Polyethnic Rights
During the Nineteenth Century.« Central Europe 16, no. 1 (2018): 29 – 50.
—. »Typologies and Phase Theories in Nationalism Studies: Hroch’s A-B-C
Schema as a Basis for Comparative Terminology.« Nationalities Papers 38,
no. 6 (2010): 865 – 880.
Milkman, Ruth. »A New Political Generation: Millennials and the Post-2008
Wave of Protest.« American Sociological Review 82, no. 1 (2017): 1 – 31.
Rampell, Catherine. »Millennials Have a Higher Opinion of Socialism than
of Capitalism.« Washington Post, February 6, 2016.
Saad, Lydia. »Socialism as Popular as Capitalism Among Young Adults in
U. S.« Gallup, October 1 – 13, 2019. Accessed January 24, 2020. https://
news.gallup.com/poll/268766/socialism-popular-capitalism-amongyoung-adults.aspx.
Satherley, Dan. »›OK Boomer‹: World Reacts to NZ Politician Chloe Swarbrick’s Use of Meme in Parliament.« Newshub, November 7, 2019. Accessed January 24, 2020. https://www.newshub.co.nz/home/politics/2019/
11/ok-boomer-world-reacts-to-nz-politician-chloe-swarbrick-s-use-ofmeme-in-parliament.html.
Schram, Sanford. The Return of Ordinary Capitalism: Neoliberalism, Precarity,
Occupy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2015.
»Table 330.10: Average Undergraduate Tuition and Fees and Room and
Board Rates … Selected Years, 1963 – 64 through 2016 – 17,« National Center for Education Statistics (2017). Accessed January 24, 2020. https://nces.
ed.gov/programs/digest/d17/tables/dt17_330.10.asp.
Engels as Course Reading in the 21st Century History Classroom
The General Council of the First International, 1864 – 1866, The London Conference 1865, Minutes. Moscow: Progress, 1964.
Wacquant, Loïc. Punishing the Poor: The Neoliberal Government of Social Insecurity. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2009.
Wilson, John. The Myth of Political Correctness: The Conservative Attack on
Higher Education. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1995.
351
Contributors
Riccardo Altieri is PhD student at the University of Potsdam, Germany.
Nuruddin Al Akbar is a PhD student at the Department of Politics
and Government, Faculty of Social and Political Sciences, Universitas
Gadjah Mada, Indonesia.
Vitor Bartoletti Sartori is Professor at the Federal Universiy of Minas
Gerais, Brazil.
Jia Feng is Associate Professor at the School of History and Culture,
Shandong University, Jinan, China.
Frank Jacob is Professor of Global History at Nord Universitet, Norway.
David Pavón-Cuéllar is Professor of Marxism, Social Psychology
and Psychoanalysis at the State University of Michoacán (Universidad
Michoacana de San Nicolás de Hidalgo, Morelia, Mexico).
Maria Rosário de Carvalho is a Professor at Universidade Federal
da Bahia, in Brazil, and a research productivity fellow at the National
Council for Scientific and Technological Development (CNPq).
Gottfried Schweiger works at the Centre for Ethics and Poverty Research of the University of Salzburg. His interests lie primarily in
354
Contributors
the field of political philosophy on issues of poverty, childhood, migration and justice. He runs the popular German philosophy blog
www.praefaktisch.de and is co-editor of the open access Zeitschrift für
Praktische Philosophie.
Renildo Souza is Professor of Political Economy at the Federal University of Bahia, Brazil.
Vincent Streichhahn is PhD student at Halle University, Germany.
Gilmar Visoni-Alonzo is Professor of History at CUNY’s Queensborough Community College, New York, USA.
Alexander Maxwell is senior lecturer at Victoria University of Wellington, New Zealand, where he also runs the Antipodean East European Study Group. He has published widely on East European history, nationalism theory, and history pedagogy.
Henrique Wellen is Professor at the Federal University of Rio Grande
do Norte, Brazil.