The Journal of Value Inquiry (2005) 39: 169–181
DOI: 10.1007/s10790-006-8394-4
C
Springer 2006
Utilitarianism with a Human Face
BERNWARD GESANG
Philosophisches Institut der Universität Düsseldorf, Universitätsstr. 1,
40255 Düsseldorf, Germany; e-mail:
[email protected]
1. Utilitarianism: An Inhumane Calculus?
Utilitarians are said to sacrifice the interests of individuals for a greater collective good, to threaten human rights and scorn justice. Utilitarianism is a
monistic ethical theory with just one ultimate value, the maximization of
happiness. Such monism is criticized for having absurd and inhumane moral
consequences. Many people do not deny that happiness is important, but most
people do not believe that happiness is the only thing that matters. This criticism is plausible. Utilitarianism starts with basic intuitions that are widely
accepted, but it ends up absolutist, which leads to conflicts. In one respect,
such conflicts are welcome to a utilitarian who seeks to oppose accepted conservative intuitions with the voice of reason. However, many utilitarians take
confrontation too far. There are already resources available for a more humane
utilitarianism that are worthy of development.1 They might help to temper the
provocations of some utilitarians and to bring us closer to common sense.
We need a greater correspondence between utilitarianism and common
sense to gain a more humane utilitarianism. Ethics cannot be radically
revolutionary.2 The so-called revolutionists emphasize that ethics is normative and that it cannot be its task to affirm the existing egoistic ethos. The
so-called conservatives argue that revolutionary ethics will never be realized
because only philosophers understand and believe in it. We seek to steer a
middle course between pure conservatism and revisionism that is compatible
with the fundamental concept of utilitarianism that means justified by a gain
of utility. It is too easy to disregard this centerpiece of utilitarianism and just
to add some arbitrary modifications, justified by conventional morality.
As a starting point, every utilitarian bases his decisions on the interests or
happiness of everyone affected, in a neutral balancing of happiness. For a more
humane utilitarian, it is worth considering that, e.g., people who demonstrate
against abortion are also affected by the abortion debate. Their vital interests
are touched by abortion or infanticide rules. Some of them even make it their
170
BERNWARD GESANG
aim in life to campaign against such rules, but many utilitarians forget their
so-called external preferences while balancing happiness. There are arguments for an integration of external preferences in utilitarianism. This makes
utilitarianism humane because humaneness is in part definable in terms of
its relation to the enlightened moral convictions of the majority of people.
The convictions create external preferences and the preferences reflect the
current concept of humaneness in a society. As a result, the external preferences of the majority of people and humaneness are linked and utilitarianism and the moral convictions of the majority are also coupled. Therefore,
utilitarianism cannot be a revolutionary ethics in the sense defined above because the majority convictions about morals have influence on the utilitarian
calculus.
2. Criticism on the Use of External Preferences: Formal Arguments by
Dworkin and Harsanyi
Criticisms have been raised against this idea that are worthy of consideration.
In this section, formal arguments by Ronald Dworkin and John Harsanyi are
discussed. Dworkin seeks to show that utilitarianism is a failure because it
has to include external preferences that lead to absurd consequences. But the
consequences are not given. Dworkin’s criticism is based on the distinction
between internal, or as he calls them personal, and external preferences.3 This
distinction is made clearly by Christoph Fehige and Ulla Wessels:
External preferences, i.e., preferences whose content entails the existence
or non-existence, or the satisfaction or frustration, of other people’s preferences . . . can be moral, benevolent, altruistic preferences, or immoral,
malevolent, anti-social . . . preferences or mixtures of these.4
We can distinguish preferences that refer only to the personal wealth of an
individual and preferences that are related to other people as well. The type
of relationship is probably not only causal because many private preference
realizations have causal effects on others, perhaps unintentionally. Instead,
it must be based on intending the well-being or harming of others. Unless
this was the case, nearly all preferences would be external. Harsanyi takes up
Dworkin’s distinction and illustrates it as follows:
Thus my personal interests include my economic assets, . . . the benefit
of being alive, . . . my health, . . . my friendships, etc. I have no ‘personal
interest’ in my neighbour’s joining a particular church, even if I would
strongly prefer his doing so – unless his doing so would yield my prestige
. . . or would provide other personal benefits for me.5
UTILITARIANISM WITH A HUMAN FACE
171
Dworkin and Harsanyi try to show that a utilitarian is in trouble when he
includes external preferences in his measurement of utility, and they think
he cannot avoid this. The main justification given by Dworkin and Harsanyi
for the accusation of external preferences is the injury of the impartiality
postulate. Harsanyi and Dworkin regard the inclusion of external preferences
as an injury of the principle of equality, which says that everyone counts as
one, no one for more than one. Dworkin explains himself, using the example
of a swimming pool, the construction of which was supported by many nonswimmers out of sympathy:
If the altruistic preferences are counted, the result will be a form of double
counting: Each swimmer will have the benefit not only of his own preference, but also of the preference of someone else who takes pleasure in his
success.6
Harsanyi agrees with him. Are they right? We should distinguish a formal
and a material point. An injury of the formal impartiality postulate exists
when specific individuals count extra. In this formal sense, the impartiality
postulate is not injured by the counting of external preferences. An individual
does not count for more just because he is the particular individual he is.
In Dworkin’s example, all swimmers could profit from external preferences,
and the same holds true in every relevantly similar situation. People affected
by certain external preferences are considered twice in a way and counted
twice because of these preferences. That does not change the fact that we can
claim in a clear and understandable sense that everyone counts the same. The
preferences of minorities affected by so-called prejudices are not disregarded.
They are considered as before and then weighted according to their intensity.
Also, the external preferences of members of these minorities are considered,
so there is no procedural unfairness. No one is counted twice because the
internal preferences of Arthur and the supporting external preferences of Jane
and Jill are still preferences of different people, each of which still counts as
one. The interests of Arthur, Jane, and Jill are different, each is an individual
interest with similar content, and every interest counts as one, whose weight
is only adjusted according to its intensity.
In any case, the core of Dworkin’s objection is not directed at formal impartiality but at material egalitarianism.7 Dworkin speaks explicitly of an
unfairness that arises through the unavoidable consideration of external preferences in utilitarianism.8 Material fairness, the lack of which Dworkin actually criticizes, only takes place in utilitarianism when we include the external
preferences. Additionally, we can turn the reproach of injuring the equality
postulate against Dworkin. If we consider external preferences to be independent preferences, then we do not treat every interest the same way if
the external preferences are abandoned.9 All classical utilitarians went about
172
BERNWARD GESANG
their calculations in the same way, considering all interests equal, and that
seems to be reasonable for every ethics based on interests. Exceptions from
this principle of equal consideration have not been well justified until now.
It goes against the logic of utilitarianism to acknowledge bad preferences or
unauthorized welfare, which are only bad and unauthorized in the light of
commonsense morality.
3. Criticism on the Use of External Preferences: They are Irrational
A utilitarian therefore has to include in his calculations the interests of parties
who are not directly affected. He cannot simply discard them as irrational. But
this seems to be the standard reaction of many utilitarians. According to them,
most external preferences are irrational because they are motivated, e.g., by
religion or metaphysics. This allows them to be rejected. Rationality standards
could be used as a filter with which we could exclude certain preferences
as irrelevant. It may sometimes be correct to label external preferences as
irrational in a special sense, but this does not mean that they should not
be considered. In order to understand this, we must clarify the definition of
rational interests.
A utilitarian can insist on the rationality of interests, but only in a narrow
internal sense. Justifiably, nearly all utilitarians start from the idea that in
the ideal case only enlightened preferences should be counted.10 This means
that, in the ideal case, preferences are tested. In the test procedure developed
by Richard Brandt, it is relevant, e.g., whether the different preferences of a
person are consistent with one another and whether they are based on correct
factual assumptions.11 According to this procedure, one of Jim’s preferences is
internally irrational precisely when Jim would not have this preference under
ideal conditions of information. This measure of rationality is internal and
not related to rationality in the light of modern science, since Jim himself is
the authority who decides the rationality of his preferences. A preference is
internally rational if Jim still holds it after Brandt’s test, where Jim has received
all the relevant information. This is independent from the question of whether
Jim’s preference is rational according to the external rationality standards
of scientists. Jim is not in any way dominated by external standards. Instead,
Brandt’s test simply guarantees that the factual preferences of Jim are not based
on carelessness, a mood, or a mistake. It should not be assumed that all factual
wishes of Jim can be disregarded or that the only relevant wishes are those
that Jim would have in an ideal, perhaps unachievable, informational situation.
However, it is reasonable to give more weight to wishes for which there are
fewer indications that they would be rejected by the desiring individual himself
after Brandt’s test.
This is the reason why a desiring individual should accept a rationality
filter for his preferences at all. Internal rationality affects the interests of every
UTILITARIANISM WITH A HUMAN FACE
173
actor, since otherwise he would often not reach his goals. No actor prefers
that. Consequently, Brandt’s test should be part of the internal rationality
measure of every actor, since we would not be able to get anywhere without
a minimum of information and consistency. The lower the internal rationality
level, the higher the later tendency for frustration. That is why every actor has
at least a latent preference for internal rationality. A utilitarian can use such
as preference to legitimize the application of the internal rationality measure.
In contrast, external irrationality need not lead to frustration. People with
mythical conceptions of the world can be happy. They have false convictions, according to our common scientific external rationality standards, since
they incorrectly explain facts about the world they live in. However, the lack
of external rationality need not result in frustration. In the sense of internal rationality, enlightened wishes have a higher non-frustration potential for
their possessor than does unenlightened wishes. In exceptional circumstances,
somebody can be very happy with illusions and even happier if he were to
have enlightened wishes. In any case, for a decision maker in a case of conflicting interests, who has to weight wishes of differing enlightenment levels,
there is something to be said for weighting enlightened wishes more heavily.
A utilitarian seeks to maximize happiness and avoids producing frustration.
Internal rationality is a question of degree, since our information is never
perfect. We may ask how much internal enlightenment is necessary in order
to give full weight to a wish. There are no clear general criteria for this, but
a decision about this is not completely arbitrary. With the justified internal
rationality postulate, a utilitarian only seeks to guarantee that the information
about preferences available before his decision is really a hint to the later
satisfaction of the person who holds the preferences. Consequently, someone
with such preferences must have as much information as necessary to avoid
future frustrations. In concrete decision-making situations, it can often be assessed whether or not this is the case. This relevance standard can be useful
when analyzing some examples, as we will see later. An external rationality standard is introduced by many utilitarians when they view the interests
of anti-abortionists as irrational. Whether interests are based on false religious grounds or other convictions is a question of external rationality and is
therefore irrelevant for a utilitarian. A utilitarian might be able to convince individual people by using external rationality standards. He should even try to
do so, especially as some external rationality deficits can lead to frustrations
in the long run. However, as long as his external standards do not become
internal standards of the affected party, they remain irrelevant.
4. Criticism on the Use of External Preferences
To regard external preferences might lead to new problems with respect to
morality and humanity. It may be, e.g., that a large number of people reject
174
BERNWARD GESANG
foreign people. We may wonder if we have to allow for anti-liberal intolerance
because it is based on external preferences that are admissible, and we may
ask if external preferences that are bad in terms of the common-sense morality
are to be counted. Peter Vallentyne, e.g., thinks that every welfarist ethics has
to include a “welfare authorization standard” that allows for “discounting”
of suspect external preferences.12 Here, a utilitarian has to clear away fears.
We can respond to an opponent of foreigners using different tools, which
characterize the position of humane utilitarianism.
First, we can regard rationality deficits. We could doubt whether somebody
who seeks to limit the number of his foreign neighbors just because they are
foreigners is really internally rational. Perhaps he does not realize what this
would mean for foreigners or he has displaced the consequences. Perhaps he
would regret his decision sometime in future, when he gets to know a foreigner
and his perspective changes. If considerable doubts arise as to whether or
not the opponent of foreigners has thoroughly concerned himself with the
consequences, we can either make him do this. Alternatively, we might not
count his preference at all, or only in a limited way, in accordance with its
enlightenment level. We can, furthermore, question the internal rationality of
some interests of citizens within states that do not have freedom of the press
and that have an education system based on indoctrination.
For example, if a survey were taken in which the majority of the Cubans
people were against personal autonomy and freedom of speech as a component of a good life, this decision could perhaps be set aside on the basis of
suspected internal irrationality. If people are indoctrinated by their education
and are subject to a media that is not free, then it must be doubted whether the
convictions that they have developed are mainly internally enlightened. The
majority of the Cubans perhaps have not put their minds to the formation of
their own opinions, since they do not reflect the mechanisms of a totalitarian
education system. In addition, the majority of Cubans perhaps do not know all
the relevant facts about leading an autonomous life. They are not extensively
informed either by their education system or by the media, and therefore they
are not in a position to compare lifestyles. Pluralism and freedom of speech
could be necessary conditions for the existence of internally rational preferences, since the preference holder lacks highly relevant information without
them. This standard is only founded in internal rationality. It is not supposed
to fall into moral absolutism, which requires everyone to follow infallible
universal reason that has the authority to correct the preferences of those who
are not yet fully enlightened. The welfare of the Cubans is concerned, if they
behave not internally rational, as it was argued.
But we must ask ourselves, if the comparison of lifestyles counts as relevant
information for the Cubans in this example. We can test the relevance standard
from the last section. The suppression of knowledge about liberal ways of life
is not possible on a long-term basis in an informed age. In the foreseeable
UTILITARIANISM WITH A HUMAN FACE
175
future, the Cubans could receive information about autonomous ways of life.
The preferences they had against autonomy might then reveal themselves
as suboptimal, resulting in frustration. This shows that the opportunity to
compare information with other cultures is relevant for the Cubans, since it
enhances their internal rationality. States or cultures that do not guarantee
conditions of plurality and freedom of speech cannot be held up to argue
against a consensus of enlightened cultures about the relevance of autonomy
and the human rights connected with it. We could demonstrate this to the
Cubans people using their own value standards, since they also accept the
value of internal rationality as a general condition of successful actions. These
arguments help a utilitarian in the problematic area of human rights and justice,
and they offer a reply to the objection that utilitarianism is unable to protect
minorities against anti-liberal preferences.
After regarding rationality deficits, we can next look at preference education, change, and substitution to cope with the opponents of foreigners. A
utilitarian should sometimes work toward the construction of an ideal preference situation.13 He looks for maximal utility values. When a minority is
sacrificed for the majority, there are many people who might profit from this
and some who suffer violently. It is worth striving for an ideal preference
situation in which all would prosper because nobody has an interest in sacrificing the minority. The utility would be greater here, in any case, than if
we have to override highly intense interests of minorities. Because of this,
there is always an incentive to strive for the realization of an ideal preference
situation without victims. It does not matter which arrangements promise to
increase utility. As long as there are victims in the arrangements, they can
be improved by sparing them. Victims suffer, and suffering always lowers the
level of happiness.
There are many ways a utilitarian might further ideal preference situations.
He might not let really bad preferences arise, or he can bring good preferences into existence. That is called preference education. He can change
existing preferences what we call preference change, or he can offer holders
of preferences a substitution for the fulfilment of their preference, the so-called
preference substitution.
Here is an example of preference education. Overall satisfaction would be
larger if there were no preferences against foreigners because the preferences
had been prevented from arising at the development stage. There would be
no reason to restrict the number of foreigners in the neighborhood of our
opponent, and no one would suffer.
Here is an example of preference change. The Romans enjoyed attending
games in which gladiators were killed. If the Romans were content with chariot
races, they would have the same, or at least only a little less, satisfaction. The
amount of satisfaction for gladiators, however, would be considerably higher,
so the overall level of satisfaction would rise. We could achieve this by offering
176
BERNWARD GESANG
only chariot races and hoping that the Romans get used to it and dispense with
their old bloodthirsty preferences.
Here is an example of preference substitution. Let us suppose that the bad
preferences of the Romans remain unchanged but that we offer a substitute
to them which they prefer as much as the satisfaction of the bad preferences.
This substitute, a new toga every year, will make them just as happy as the
games would have. Then we only have to compare the costs of the substitute
and the utility for the gladiators. The substitute is not allowed to be too expensive. Preference substitution is a borderline case of preference change. Since
“preference change” is the established term, it will be used as a general term
that also covers substitution and development.
A utilitarian can criticize every restriction of liberty or distraction from
human rights as ethically imperfect, as there are victims. But endeavors to
change preferences have factual limits. For anthropological reasons, preferences are not randomly changeable or capable of substitution, and the costs
of substitutes are sometimes too high. Nevertheless, there is often a strong
incentive to take pains to achieve a preference change. Generally, sacrifice
of minorities brings sorrow into the world. Therefore, in a utilitarian-guided
education, we would fight against such preferences. Here utilitarianism and
common sense meet.
If we change preferences, we do not injure the autonomy of people whose
preferences will be changed. Recall the example of the gladiator games. A
utilitarian Caesar only imposes restrictions on freedom to act if he allows
only chariot races in Rome. He has no direct control of the preferences of
the Romans. Their preferences would hopefully become newly conditioned
on their own. The development of new preferences remains an autonomous
process. There are incentives for new preferences, e.g., the offer of chariot
racing, but whether an individual adopts such preferences remains for him an
autonomous decision. His thoughts and feelings are still free.
Every preference change has associated costs and underlying empirical
obstacles. This is why attempts to change existing preferences should only be
taken into consideration if the existing preferences would be very damaging
for some affected parties. In such cases, attempts are not only desirable but
necessary.
5. Two Further Instruments of Humane Utilitarianism
A third instrument of a humane utilitarian is the maintenance of long-term
overall interests and structural rationality. Were we to give way to the demands
of opponents of foreigners, then we might have to allow all other similar antiliberal demands in other areas. The possibility of a slippery slope effect would
be opened. If that was to happen, society would be changed in a lasting way.
UTILITARIANISM WITH A HUMAN FACE
177
We could turn into an anti-liberal society, which would, for the overwhelming
majority of citizens, be a sensational and undesirable change. As long as the
majority of citizens find such a society undesirable, a utilitarian can reject the
wishes of the anti-liberals, as long as there is sufficient evidence to suggest
that a slippery slope effect is not wholly unlikely. Here, the long-term interest
of the majority counts far more than the interests of a few anti-liberals. Also,
the exclusive comparison of the interests of the opponents of foreigners and
the foreigners themselves is an inappropriate abridgement of the issue, since
it does not embrace all relevant dimensions. A humane utilitarian will, in
every case, pay attention to all the interests of everyone involved, to ensure
that everything is considered. Therefore, a utilitarian should not carry out
single, act-by-act utility maximizations. Instead, he should ensure structural
rationality and start from an anticipation of the long-term overall interest.
A humane utilitarian does not start with act-by-act maximization, but with
a kind of maximization that evaluates the end result of a chain of actions.14
Consequently, a utilitarian can accept some practices as legitimated, even
if they lead to suboptimal results in individual cases. A utilitarian is not a
slave to an abridged calculation procedure. He can freely decide what the
most useful action is from a final perspective, all things considered. Actby-act maximizations have the problem of structural rationality. People who
maximize in this way do not anticipate the final result of the combined effects
of the single optimizations, neither on a diachronic nor on a synchronic level.
Single acts are optimized in an uncoordinated manner, and complex beneficial
action aggregates are not realized by act-by-act maximization. A utilitarian
must optimize chains of actions and complex action systems.
The fourth instrument of a humane utilitarian is the consideration of all
external preferences. When most people in a society tolerate or even love foreigners and reject anti-liberalism, then their preferences can take priority over
the preferences of the anti-liberals who oppose foreigners. This opposition
may sometimes be rejected even when the anti-liberal preferences outnumber
the preferences of the foreigners. If the preferences of the opponents of foreigners are to count, then the preferences of the opponents of the opponents
must also count. A utilitarian must proceed in exactly the same way with
problems of justice. Next to the preferences of the people primarily affected,
he must count the internally rational external preferences of the citizens for
fairness and justice. Here a utilitarian could appeal to the preferences of many
people for a fair national and global order, which is rooted in the sense of
justice described by John Rawls.15 This sense is one of the strongest moral
feelings that people have. We can, e.g., observe that even small children seem
to have a great sensitivity to unfairness, as is evident in the crying of children
over an unjust division of cake. A majority of enlightened people wish for a
fair world. We can see this in the regular outrage that arises in anti-utilitarian
thought experiments in which an innocent individual is sacrificed for the
178
BERNWARD GESANG
benefit of others, thereby realizing an extremely unfair division of utility. The
existence of these external justice preferences is, alongside the respective
internal interests, a strong grounding for a utilitarian defence of justice.
6. Should a Utilitarian Eliminate Some Humane External Preferences?
Some people have argued that if we all became utilitarians and agreed that utility maximization and not justice matters, our sense of justice would disappear.
Justice then would not be one of our preferences anymore and consequently
would not have to be considered. Perhaps we have to work toward a preferential change of this type and thereby work against some of the external
preferences that secure the coupling of utilitarianism with everyday intuition
and the humanity of utilitarianism. This argument is not effective. For us, it is
a de facto increase of utility if things are distributed in a fair way. An unfair
world angers us, and a fair world makes us at least a little happier. News programs play upon these emotions every evening. Justice is a type of utility in
utilitarianism, since it promotes the satisfaction of many preferences. Perhaps
we achieve more utility without fairness preferences. But a preference change
that rids us of our sense of justice is impossible because it attacks our anthropological substance. Furthermore, it would be wholly groundless, since
preference changes are only sensible for preferences that are substantially
damaging. The sense of justice is valuable in society. Fairness is useful from
the point of view of structural rationality because it preserves social peace,
but it must be confessed that in certain cases justice can diminish utility.
We can differentiate between the aspects of our existing inclination for
justice that are useful and that are not. Some people may argue that we should
attempt to institute preference change to rid ourselves of useless external
preferences. The suggestion here is that preference changes are easily effected.
However, they are complex undertakings, which only make sense in cases
of extreme utility burdens through external preferences. Furthermore, they
are not always successful, since they require much effort and high costs.
Preference changes are an emergency brake in extreme situations and not an
instrument of regular conflict resolution. Even so, in some extreme cases,
utilitarians should take trouble to change some external preferences that may
have guaranteed the humanity of utilitarianism until now. But a utilitarian does
not lose his humanity even in these cases. When the efforts of a utilitarian
are really successful and a preference change takes place, then he has also
shifted the concept of humanity. There is hardly anyone left who takes the old
position on what is humane, since the preferences and intuitions have changed.
The changes of convictions and of preferences are coupled. Some preferences
can only change if the convictions have changed first. If the old convictions
remain, they would contribute to produce preferences that exclude a successful
UTILITARIANISM WITH A HUMAN FACE
179
preference change. A conflict of utilitarianism and everyday intuitions is not
a difficulty in such cases, since a utilitarian position would be remain humane
insofar as it accorded with the new everyday intuitions.
7. The Limits of Influence of External Preferences
The intuitions of the majority do not amount to the entire morality. We can
criticize them, e.g., with rationality demands, and we can refer to internal
preferences. Additionally, we might demand an avoidance of victims in every preference change and thereby a protection of minority interests, which
would improve the utility balance in every case if it is realizable. Nevertheless, the intuitions of the majority are a considerable part of morality and are
reflected in humane utilitarianism. A problem arises for anyone who seeks to
separate moral norms from rational empirical interests and keep the norms,
whatever preferences might be. Our morality is, however, an inter-subjective
construction, which derives from convictions of individuals and not from eternal values. Morality is coupled with enlightened empirical interests. If there
were not such a coupling, we would have to assume that something could be
immoral, yet be preferred by all human beings or that something could be
moral, yet be preferred by nobody at any time. When we believe that values
depend on the interests of individuals, then values are always connected with
the informed empirical value judgements of people. States of affairs have
worth through the satisfaction they generate.16 According to this view, a liberal or just society which satisfied nobody would have no value. If we claim
the opposite, then we must defend, e.g., a strong form of moral realism, which
contains values that exist independently from all subjectivity and that have
normative power for subjects. This meta-ethical position is highly implausible. The coupling of norms and empirical interests is legitimate. As long as
external preferences exist, a utilitarian has to take them into consideration.
But if they lead to unwelcome long-term effects, if they are irrational, if they
can easily be changed into better preferences, or if they are outweighed by
other external preferences, their influence can at least be diminished. Their
strength has to be compared with that of the internal preferences. The arguments of the opponent of foreigners must pass these standards. People who
have reservations about the application of external preferences should remind
themselves that the preferences are going to be weaker as a general rule than
the direct, vehement interest of minorities in survival or freedom. As a general rule, our internal preferences for our own life, sustenance, and health
are much more intense than the preferences we have about other people. The
influence of external preferences is self-regulated. External preferences can
only be influential in the described critical cases if very many enlightened
and intense external preferences exist, otherwise they would not be able to
180
BERNWARD GESANG
override the vehement internal interests of minorities. Therefore, influential
external preferences mirror broad majority convictions, and this is a desired
quality, if we seek to bring utilitarianism closer to common sense. The enlightened intuitions of the broad majority determine our concept of humanity
at least in part, and especially influential external preferences must be broad
majority preferences, produced under the contribution of intuitions and convictions. This is the reason why influential enlightened external preferences
and humanity are coupled. At the same time, the intuitive moral standards of
our Western democracies might be dominating, if we include external preferences in our calculations. The preferences that are generated there are most
likely internally enlightened, since a principle of pluralistic education and
freedom of press and speech exist in such states. Preferences that were developed in non-democratic systems, e.g., fanatical external preferences, would
often conflict with rationality, as they are introduced by indoctrination. Brandt
distinguished between artificial wishes, which result from imitation of other
people, and authentic wishes. Only authentic wishes will survive cognitive
psychotherapy, and that will be an obstacle for fanaticism and similar preferences often seen in non-democratic systems.17 Yet, in each case, we have
to collect indications of the enlightenment level of the preferences as far as
possible, and we cannot always disregard preferences from non-democratic
systems wholesale.
Notes
1. See Peter Railton, Facts, Values, And Norms (Cambridge, England: Cambridge University
Press, 2003), pp. 151–186; John Stuart Mill, “Utilitarianism,” in J.M. Robson, et al., eds.,
Collected Works of John Stuart Mill (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1962), p. 10;
Nicolas Rescher, Distributive Justice (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Co., 1966).
2. See Brad Hooker, Ideal Code, Real World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp.
9–15. Also see David Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (Cambridge,
England: Cambridge University Press, 1989), pp. 122–143.
3. Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2002),
p. 17.
4. Christoph Fehige, Ulla Wessels, Preferences (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1998), p. xxvi.
5. John Harsanyi, “Problems with Act-Utilitarianism and with Malevolent Preferences,” in
N. Fotion and D. Seanor, eds., Hare and Critics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988),
p. 97.
6. See Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth & Co., 1977) pp.
234–235.
7. See Herbert L.A. Hart, “Between Utility and Rights,” Columbia Law Review, 79 (1979),
p. 843.
8. See Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, pp. 235–236.
9. Richard M. Hare (1998), “Preferences of Possible People,” in C. Fehige and U. Wessels,
eds., Preferences, p. 247.
10. See James Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), pp. 13–15.
UTILITARIANISM WITH A HUMAN FACE
181
11. See Richard Brandt, A Theory of the Right and the Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1979).
12. See Peter Vallentyne, “The Problem of Unauthorized Welfare,” Nous 25 (1991), pp. 295,
299.
13. See Richard M. Hare, Moral Thinking (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981), Section
2.8.
14. See Jonathan Dancy, Moral Reasons (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), p. 247.
15. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971).
16. See Bernward Gesang, “Der Nutzenbegriff des Utilitarismus,” Erkenntnis 52 (2000).
17. See Richard Brandt, A Theory of the Right and the Good, pp. 116–118.
18. I would like to extend many thanks to an anonymous referee and Thomas Magnell.