The Classical Quarterly 69.1 107–118 © The Classical Association (2019)
doi:10.1017/S0009838819000533
107
ON NOT MISUNDERSTANDING OEDIPUS TYRANNOS*
How are we to understand what happens to Oedipus?1 What or who is the cause of the
terrible deeds—predicted by oracles to both Laius and Oedipus—that he has already
committed before the play begins and that are revealed in its course? The purpose of
the present essay, whose title alludes to a well-known article by E.R. Dodds,2 is to
draw attention to aspects of the play that have been ignored or explained away. To
give them their due it will be necessary to take issue with two views of Dodds (one
of which he owes to Wilamowitz) that I regard as mistaken. To argue against an article
that is more than fifty years old might be thought a pointless exhumation, but Dodds’s
highly influential formulations, I will argue, have caused what Sophocles wrote to be
either overlooked or misconstrued and are still causing misunderstanding in the second
decade of the present century. It is time these views were examined critically.3
A brief summary of Dodds’s article will suffice. Dodds considers three sorts of
answers made by Oxford Honours candidates to the question ‘In what sense, if in
any, does the Oedipus Rex attempt to justify the ways of God to man?’. The first
group of candidates thought the play showed that Oedipus’ suffering was deserved
punishment for his guilt or his faults of character. Dodds makes short work of this
moralizing interpretation. If Sophocles had meant for Oedipus’ grim fate to be seen
as deserved, he would have written the play differently.4
It is in reply to the second group that Dodds, I will argue, makes a mistake that has
bedevilled interpretation ever since. This group regards Oedipus Tyrannos (OT) as a
‘tragedy of destiny’: the play shows that ‘man has no free will but is a puppet in the
hands of the gods who pull the strings that make him dance’. If we take the image of
a puppet literally, a doll that has no life in it and whose limbs are moved by another,
this clearly describes a creature devoid of dramatic interest. But though human beings
can be manipulated in ways that are not so extreme, Dodds thinks that the literal
* I am grateful to Jenny March, Nicholas Lane and CQ’s anonymous referee for useful comments.
1
An earlier article of mine—‘The role of Apollo in Oedipus Tyrannos’, in J.R.C. Cousland and J.R.
Hume (edd.), The Play of Texts and Fragments: Essays in Honour of Martin Cropp (Leiden, 2009),
357–68—made a start on this theme. I have since realized that there is quite a bit more to be said.
2
E.R. Dodds, ‘On misunderstanding the Oedipus Rex’, G&R 13 (1966), 37–49 = The Ancient
Concept of Progress and Other Essays on Greek Literature and Belief (Oxford, 1973), 64–77 = M.J.
Obrien (ed.), Twentieth-Century Interpretations of Oedipus Rex: A Collection of Critical Essays
(Englewood Cliffs, NJ, 1968), 17–29.
3
There are some good remarks about incoherences in Dodds’s article in D. Cairns, ‘Divine and
human action in the Oedipus Tyrannus’, in D. Cairns (ed.), Tragedy and Archaic Greek Thought
(Swansea, 2013), especially 120–8. Some brief remarks in P.J. Finglass, Oedipus Tyrannus
(Cambridge, 2018), 70–6, citing Cairns (this note) and Kovacs (n. 1).
4
M. Lurje, Die Suche nach der Schuld: Sophokles’ Oedipus Rex, Aristoteles’ Poetik und das
Tragödienverständnis der Neuzeit (Munich, 2004), 1–225 documents the genesis of this view of
the play soon after the first printing of Aristotle’s Poetics. He also (at 255–77) notes its recrudescence
in the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
108
D AV I D KOVAC S
image of a puppet would describe an Oedipus who is manipulated by the gods. In order
to avoid making Oedipus a puppet, Dodds runs hard the other way and says that Apollo
does not cause what befalls Oedipus. ‘The gods know the future,’ says Dodds, ‘but they
do not order it: they know who will win the next Scotland and England football match,
but that does not alter the fact that the victory will depend on the skill, the determination,
the fitness of the players, and a little on luck.’5 But, as we will see, various kinds of
divine interference with the actions of human beings are a frequent theme in tragedy,
which makes the premise of Dodds’s argument doubtful. And OT in particular contains
quite a bit of language that suggests that such interference is going on here.
A third group of candidates argued that Sophocles is neither defending nor indicting
the gods but is a pure artist who intends to write a gripping play. Dodds replies that, if
Sophocles had wanted to sidestep the theological implications of his story, he would not
have had the Chorus in a famous stasimon raise the question of the existence of the gods
and ask why they should dance in their honour if their prophecies are not fulfilled.
Dodds propounds two theses, first that Sophocles ‘did not believe (or did not always
believe) that the gods are in any human sense “just”’; and second that ‘he did always
believe that the gods exist and that man should revere them’. In support of the first
proposition Dodds cites ‘the implicit evidence of the Oedipus Rex’ as well as the
more explicit comment on the injustice of the gods at the end of Trachiniae. But if
OT and Trachiniae show the gods to be unjust, that means that they have sent
undeserved misery on Oedipus and Heracles. Since Oedipus’ misery consists in his
having killed his father and married his mother, we must conclude that at this point
Dodds is prepared to entertain the idea that they caused him to do these things and
did not merely predict them. (The alternative, that they did not prevent what fate
decreed, does not indict them for injustice at all if Oedipus’ fate was unalterable or to
the same extent if it was alterable but not caused by the gods.) Dodds’s answer to
the third group thus stands in tension with his answer to the second since, if the gods
caused Oedipus to do these actions, he becomes, in Dodds’s own terms, a puppet.
We may allow ourselves to wonder whether the image of puppetry serves him well.
Let us return to Dodds’s reply to the second view. When he describes as a puppet any
character who is manipulated by a god, he implies that such manipulation is alien to
tragedy. But in fact gods do interfere with the actions of human beings in tragedy
and in more than one way. At the mild end of the spectrum they can create in someone
a momentary and natural emotion that will cause the performance of an action they want
to see performed: for example Apollo, as described at Ion 36–48, caused the Pythia to
feel pity for the exposed baby, so that instead of casting him out of the sanctuary she
raised him. Another possibility is for the gods to put persons in a position where
they are forced by circumstances to do something that will bring about their destruction,
as Agamemnon in Aeschylus is forced to kill his daughter Iphigenia and incur the
mortal enmity of Clytaemestra. At still other times the gods interfere with a person’s
organs of sense so that, for example, the principal character in Heracles thinks that
his own children are those of his enemy Eurystheus, and Agave in Bacchae thinks
that her son Pentheus is a lion. Still more invasive of the personality is Aphrodite’s
action in Hippolytus: she inspires Phaedra with a passion for her stepson, a passion
against which the unaltered part of her fights to the death. The extreme case is when
the gods inspire someone with a purpose he or she would ordinarily regard as impious,
5
Dodds (n. 2), 42, quoting A.W. Gomme.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
O N N OT M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G O E D I P U S T Y R A N N O S
109
as when Eteocles in Seven against Thebes is seized with the conscious desire to meet his
brother Polynices in battle and kill him. To regard as puppets all persons with whom the
gods interfere is to ignore the fact that such interference is allowed by tragic practice and
is compatible with our being emotionally engaged with them. In tragedy human beings
are in fact exposed to divine manipulation: complete personal autonomy is not the
default setting.
We thus cannot rule out on a priori grounds the idea that the gods or Apollo not only
predicted Oedipus’ actions but also caused them. What positive reasons do we have for
thinking that Apollo did so in our play? There are two kinds of reasons, specific
passages in the play and general considerations of mythical intelligibility.
APOLLO AT WORK IN THE PLAY
The text of the play as a whole is consistent with the intervention of Apollo in the life of
Oedipus. Tragedy has, as we have seen, no objection in principle to having the gods
interfere rather invasively, as with Eteocles and Phaedra. In the case of Oedipus,
there is no reason to think that his conscious purposes were supplanted by other,
god-sent, ones, as those of Eteocles apparently were, or that his affective life was altered
from without, as Phaedra’s was. The play suggests, rather, that all of Oedipus’ actions,
including the parricide and the incest with his mother, were perfectly free but that, in the
case of those two actions, Apollo tricked him into a situation where he unwittingly
carried out the god’s designs. Though Apollo’s intervention was less invasive than is
sometimes the case in tragedy, it was nevertheless an intervention.
The clearest indication that Apollo directed the events that precede the play’s action
occurs in the middle of the play. In the scene following his quarrel with Creon, Oedipus
gives Jocasta a summary of his life (774–827). He tells her that he was raised as the son
of Polybus, king of Corinth, and was quite happy with his lot until a doubt was raised
about his parentage: a man in his cups said he was not Polybus’ son. He resolved to go
to Delphi and ask the god who his parents were. At Delphi he put his question to the
god, but Apollo refused to answer it, most unusual behaviour for the oracle. Oedipus
says: ‘He sent me away unhonoured in what I had come for, but to me in my misery
he predicted other terrible things, that I was fated to lie with my mother and beget
offspring none can bear to see and that I would be my own father’s killer’ (788–93).
Notice what happens here: Apollo withholds information from Oedipus about his
parents, refuses to answer his enquiry at all; then, gratuitously, he gives him a prediction
that he will kill his father and marry his mother. He makes this prediction at the point
where it contributes to its own fulfilment. For even though Oedipus is in doubt (based
on the comment of the tipsy man) who his parents are, the foreseeable result of the
oracle is what actually happens: Oedipus resolves to avoid the only parents he knows
and never to return to Corinth. In consequence he takes the road out of Delphi leading
in the other direction, a road on which, as Apollo knows, Laius is travelling with his
entourage. The meeting at the crossroads is planned by Apollo. Laius, in an act of highhanded arrogance, tries to drive Oedipus from the road and aims a blow at his head with
a goad designed for controlling animals,6 and it is not in Oedipus’ nature to accept such
6
See Finglass (n. 3), on 806–9.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
110
D AV I D KOVAC S
an insult meekly.7 The rest follows naturally. They fight, and he kills Laius. When he
arrives at Thebes, he finds a city that has no king and is being terrorized by the
Sphinx. Clever man that he is, he solves her riddle and thereby wins the throne, with
which goes the hand of Jocasta in marriage. Oedipus’ narrative suggests that he was
deliberately set up to kill his father and marry his mother.
Consider also the prediction made to Laius. This too serves a function in helping to
bring about the parricide and the incest. Had Laius not received the warning he did and
had his son been raised by him and Jocasta, knowing them as his parents, the likelihood
of his killing his father would have been slight and the likelihood of his marrying his
mother virtually nil. But because of the oracle his parents gave him to a servant to
expose on Mount Cithaeron. The servant pitied the child and gave it to a Corinthian.
This allowed Oedipus to grow up in ignorance of his parentage and set him up for
two acts he never would have committed had he known his parents’ identity.
Apollo, then, engineered the parricide and the incest. And so when Jocasta says
(720–2) ‘Apollo neither caused him [the child] to become his father’s slayer nor caused
Laius to suffer at his son’s hands the terrible fate he feared’, she uses a form of speech
that implies that, had the prediction come true, Apollo would have been the cause of the
events he predicted. Her words suggest to the audience the view they are to take of what
has actually happened: Jocasta says that Apollo did not bring these actions about
because they never happened; but she is wrong about their never happening, and in
denying that Apollo acted to cause them she is also mistaken.
The same tale is told by Oedipus’ accusation of Apollo (1329–33) at a point where
all the facts are known and there are no more revelations to come: ‘It was Apollo, my
friends, Apollo, who wrought these my terrible miseries, though the hand that struck the
blow was none other than my own.’ (Oedipus’ statement is in response to the question
what god caused him to blind himself, and he replies that it was Apollo, using his
victim’s own hands. But ‘these my terrible sufferings’ also have in view the parricide
and the incest. Of these it is likewise true to say that Apollo caused them, using
Oedipus to carry them out.) In view of what has preceded it is simplest to suppose
that Oedipus means what he says and that Sophocles intends us to see that it is true.8
Another passage, as printed by almost all editors, contains a conjecture, but the
conjecture is virtually certain, and the passage is therefore relevant to the present
question. At 376–7 editors print Brunck’s οὐ γάρ ϲε μοῖρα πρόϲ γ’ ἐμοῦ πεϲεῖν,
which gives the sense ‘It is not fated for you [Oedipus] to be overthrown by me,
7
Compare the way Aphrodite in Hippolytus correctly estimates the way the humans in Trozen, both
royal and servile, will act. She knows that Phaedra will fight her love for Hippolytus with all her
might, deciding on death rather than adultery; that the Nurse, who cares about her but is without
her moral compass, will both worm the secret out of her and try to save her life by approaching
Hippolytus; that after her secret is out Phaedra will kill herself and incriminate Hippolytus; and
that Theseus, having read her suicide note, will invoke Poseidon’s curse.
8
Several scholars seem to treat it as a mere façon de parler. Thus R.C.T. Parker, ‘Through a glass
darkly: Sophocles and the divine’, in J. Griffin (ed.), Sophocles Revisited: Essays Presented to Sir
Hugh Lloyd-Jones (Oxford, 1999), 17 says: ‘The main reason why “it was Apollo” for Oedipus is
simply that, as no one could deny, what Apollo had decreed had come to pass.’ Since what ‘no
one could deny’ is that Apollo foretold Oedipus’ misery, I strongly suspect that Parker is using
‘decreed’ as a synonym for ‘predicted’. H.D.F. Kitto, Greek Tragedy (London, 19613), 182 likewise
implies that Apollo predicted but did not bring about the parricide and the incest. J.D. Mikalson,
‘Gods and heroes in Sophocles’, in A. Markantonatos (ed.), Brill’s Companion to Sophocles
(Leiden and Boston, 2012), 438 admits no more than the possibility of assigning an active role to
Apollo.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
O N N OT M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G O E D I P U S T Y R A N N O S
111
since Apollo, whose care it is to bring this about, is sufficient’. The reading of the
manuscripts, οὐ γάρ με μοῖρα πρόϲ γε ϲοῦ πεσεῖν, gives ‘It is not fated for me to be
overthrown by you’, irrelevant to the context, since Teiresias’ own fall is not the subject
under discussion. If the judgement of most editors is right here, Teiresias is another
witness for an Apollo who brings about what he predicts.
One other item in what precedes the opening of the play could also be explained as
Apollo-caused on the basis of parallels from tragedy. When Oedipus recounts (774–86)
how he came to Delphi, he says that it was because a chance event caused him to
wonder who his parents were, the remark of the drunken man at a banquet. If someone
in tragedy says that an event took place by chance or with no known cause, this is rarely,
if ever, the whole truth: such words are often a palpable suggestion by the dramatist that
the event was divinely caused.9 Though more naturalistic explanations might be available (for example gossip in the palace at Corinth), Sophocles’ audience may have
thought that drunkenness allowed this man to be the mouthpiece of a god (cf. Eur.
Bacch. 298–301) and to say something that was unknown to himself or to anyone in
Corinth except Polybus, Merope and the shepherd who gave Oedipus to them.
We may conclude that Apollo is behind Oedipus’ fate.10 To be sure, his intervention
is of a kind that leaves Oedipus’ actions free. Oedipus freely chooses to consult the
oracle, freely chooses to leave Corinth for good. These free decisions are made, however, on the basis of information supplied—in the one case this is clearly marked in
the text and in the other it is a reasonable conjecture—by Apollo, who is setting him
up for the encounter at the crossroads. We may call Oedipus a puppet if we like, for
Apollo has manipulated him.11 But ‘Oedipus would in that case be a puppet’ is no argument against a view of the action that is strongly suggested by the text of the play and is
congruent with tragic practice.12
9
See D.J. Mastronarde, Euripides: Phoenissae (Cambridge, 1994), on lines 33, 49 and 413 and
D. Kovacs, Euripides: Helen, Phoenician Women, Orestes (Cambridge, Mass., 2002), 209.
10
Cairns (n. 3), 137–8 says that there is ‘some purchase’ for the explanation of the role of Apollo I
put forth in 2009 (see n. 1 above), but that it is ‘insufficient’: about the parricide, incest and selfblinding he says that ‘those things are bound to happen. Apollo, we are encouraged to think, ensured
that they did, but also knew for certain that they would.’ I do not understand why Cairns feels obliged
to posit some kind of power external to Apollo that makes it certain these things would happen. He
cites nothing in the text to prove this claim. In the absence of such a passage, we are entitled to invoke
Occam’s razor and refuse to multiply entities without necessity.
11
Cairns (n. 3), 128 is clear that Apollo manipulates Oedipus, and his n. 35 says that this ‘simple
and incontrovertible point’ is ignored by what he calls ‘exclusively humanist interpretations’. His note
lists ten scholars who agree with him. Most have little to say about how Apollo operated. A. Cameron,
The Identity of Oedipus the King (New York and London, 1968) devotes a chapter (63–95) to the
immanence of Apollo in the action; B.M.W. Knox, Oedipus at Thebes: Sophocles’ Tragic Hero
and his Times (New Haven, 1957; repr. New York, 1971), 40 notes the effect of the oracle to
Oedipus on his subsequent action; R.D. Griffith, The Theatre of Apollo: Divine Justice and
Sophocles’ Oedipus the King (Montreal and Kingston, London, Buffalo, 1996), 42–3 is prepared
to see Apollo’s hand in the arrival of the Corinthian and in Oedipus’ being guided to Jocasta’s
body. There are similar remarks about Apollo’s actions, expressed with greater tentativeness than is
perhaps necessary, in S. Lawrence, ‘Apollo and his purpose in Sophocles’ Oedipus Tyrannus’,
Studia humaniora Tartuensia 9 (2008), 1–18. I have tried to offer further evidence for a point that
has often been controverted in the past, but also to examine more closely the how, to the extent
that Sophocles’ reticences allow.
12
O. Taplin, Sophocles: Oedipus the King and Other Tragedies (Oxford, 2015), 7, clearly
influenced by Dodds, writes that ‘humans in tragedy are not seen as puppets or some kind of “automata” acting out the determinations of higher powers’. His footnote 4 to this statement says: ‘Except
when they are maddened or possessed—the exception that proves the rule.’ But, as we have seen,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
112
D AV I D KOVAC S
But it is not only in what precedes the opening of the play that we can see Apollo in
action: he is still (I will argue) visibly at work in the play. The chief textual evidence for
this is to be found in two phrases in a passage (1255–62) of the speech of the Exangelos,
who describes how the entrance of Oedipus made it impossible for him and the other
servants to see how Jocasta died:
φοιτᾶι γὰρ ἡμᾶϲ ἔγχοϲ ἐξαιτῶν πορεῖν,
γυναῖκά τ’ οὐ γυναῖκα, μητρώιαν δ’ ὅπου
κίχοι διπλῆν ἄρουραν οὗ τε καὶ τέκνων.
λυϲϲῶντι δ’ αὐτῶι δαιμόνων δείκνυϲί τιϲ·
οὐδεὶϲ γὰρ ἀνδρῶν οἳ παρῆμεν ἐγγύθεν.
δεινὸν δ’ ἀύϲαϲ ὡϲ ὑφ’ ἡγητοῦ τινοϲ
πύλαιϲ διπλαῖϲ ἐνήλατ’, ἐκ δὲ πυθμένων
ἔκλινε κοῖλα κλῆιθρα κἀμπίπτει ϲτέγηι.
1255
1260
The Exangelos, of course, is not an accredited spokesman for the divine. But his
statements here differ in an important respect from a mere opinion with no evidentiary
value for the interpretation of the action: what he says is not an unsupported conjecture
but is based on the strong impression left by what he himself has seen. In the first of the
phrases printed in bold type (1258–9) the servant says the same thing positively and
negatively, namely that it was no human who showed Oedipus where to find Jocasta
but some divine power. The second (1260) states the servant’s impression that
Oedipus was moving under the guidance of someone unseen as he made his way to
the bedroom. Oedipus, of course, could have found Jocasta without supernatural guidance. But the fact that such guidance is unnecessary serves to underline the significance
of the fact that this minor person says that Oedipus was so guided. No member of
Sophocles’ original audience is likely to have dismissed this aspect of the Exangelos’
report as lacking in authority.13 We have here what looks like a veridical pronouncement
that a god guided Oedipus to Jocasta’s body. And so, when Oedipus emerges from the
palace blinded and says ‘It was Apollo, my friends, Apollo who accomplished these my
terrible, terrible sufferings, though the hand that struck the blow was none other than my
own’ (1329–32), we are entitled to suspect that in the play’s terms this is is no more than
the plain truth. Apollo in the past had led Oedipus by his subterfuges into committing
parricide and incest. Here in similar fashion he has guided him to the result, blindness,
that his spokesman Teiresias had predicted. We are not obliged to think (although it
would not be inconceivable in a tragedy) that Apollo moved Oedipus’ hands:
Oedipus later explains that he had his own reasons for putting out his eyes. But the
passage is indefinite and mysterious enough that I am prepared to countenance the
view, suggested by Taplin, that Oedipus is not fully the author of this action.14
madness or possession is merely one of several ways in which the gods interfere in tragedy. Dodds’s
misleading image of a puppet continues to do harm almost fifty years on.
13
Compare the way in which the Guard calls the dust storm that allows Antigone to approach
Polynices’ body undetected a θεία νόϲοϲ. R. Scodel, ‘Epic doublets and Polynices’ two burials’,
TAPA 114 (1984), 49–58 says that this remark is a way of suggesting in tragedy, where there is no
narrator, what can be described in an epic, the intervention of a god to conceal a mortal entrance
or exit. There is more to be said on the subject of utterances about the gods by minor characters. I
have discussed this topic in ‘The “grammar” of divine intervention in Greek tragedy’, Phasis 2–3
(2000), 224–7.
14
Taplin (n. 12), 7 n. 5.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
O N N OT M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G O E D I P U S T Y R A N N O S
113
WHAT IS THE ALTERNATIVE TO APOLLO?
In addition to the textual evidence cited above, there are more general reasons to favour
an Apollo who tricks Oedipus into ruining himself and his parents. Let us consider the
alternatives to this view. There are two, though arguably they come down to the same
thing. (1) Oedipus’ fall into misery was determined by an impersonal fate.15 Apollo
happened to know about this and prophesied to both Laius and his son what would
happen. But then (a) the two prophecies served no purpose (contrast the purposes served
on my interpretation by both oracles in bringing about their fulfilment); and (b) to put a
fate whose cause is utterly mysterious (as this would be) at the centre of a tragedy seems
both unsatisfying and anomalous. Furthermore (c) in tragedy moira is not an independent
agent but merely a way of talking about events retrospectively, emphasizing the divine
control of them. There are two instances of moira in the play, 376–7 and 711–14. In
both moira is merely a way of talking about what Apollo is going to bring about.
(2) Laius’ death and the misery of Oedipus and Jocasta have no real cause: they are
happenstance or coincidence.16 But to have something as momentous as parricide and
incest be simply a causeless brute fact seems contrary to the way in which stories are
handled in tragedy. Additionally, it is arguably not very satisfying. Just as important,
what is purely a matter of chance is not subject to prediction (as Jocasta correctly
notes at 977–8), and so Oedipus’ parricide and incest, if viewed as causeless events,
could not have been predicted by Apollo.17 The cost of ignoring or explaining away
the indications in the text that Apollo is responsible is narrative incoherence.
HOW MUCH PURE COINCIDENCE IS THERE IN THE PLAY?
We have seen that the meeting at the crossroads was no coincidence but was engineered
by Apollo. Can the other events that lead up to Oedipus’ ruin be similarly explained? As
it turns out, Sophocles has not explicitly linked all of them to Apollo (as will be noted
later, he is not as thorough as Euripides in this respect), but hints are offered for quite a
few of them, and it is arguable that the poet expected his audience to see that those that
are not explained are at least capable of explanation. My readers may find some of these
connections speculative. If so, they should also remember that these further points do
not undo the demonstration already made that Apollo’s influence on some of
Oedipus’ actions is rooted firmly in the text. I will first treat cases where parallels elsewhere in tragedy make it plausible to think that the audience was being invited to regard
an event as divinely caused.
(1) The Theban shepherd who was to have exposed Oedipus gives him to a
Corinthian shepherd out of pity (1178). We have seen a parallel at Ion 41–9 for pity
15
This is the view taken most recently by Woodruff in P. Meineck and P. Woodruff, Sophocles:
Oedipus Tyrannus (Indianapolis and Cambridge, 2000), xxvi–xxvii.
16
This appears to be the view of Taplin (n. 12), 9, who speaks of ‘the random vulnerability of
human fortune’ (emphasis mine). Taplin has a predecessor in A.J.A. Waldock, Sophocles the
Dramatist (Cambridge, 1951), 158, who says that ‘there is no meaning in the Oedipus Rex; there is
merely the terror of coincidence’. R. Scodel, Sophocles (Boston, 1984), 62 says: ‘An impression of
inevitable causality is joined with the terror of coincidence.’ On the following page she says: ‘In
the end, Apollo cannot be separated from the pattern of coincidence.’ But if random coincidence is
to blame, what role is there for either inevitable causality or Apollo?
17
This point is made by Cairns (n. 3), 123–4.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
114
D AV I D KOVAC S
deliberately inspired by Apollo. (2) The king of Corinth and his wife are childless. Ion
67–8 rather suggest that Apollo caused the marriage of Xuthus and Creusa to be unfruitful. (3) Oedipus says that he was happy in Corinth until a chance event occurred, the
utterance of the drunken man. As a result of this he goes to Delphi. We have noted
that, when someone in tragedy says that an event is mere happenstance or without
discernible cause, this often signals to the audience that it has on the contrary a divine
cause. (4) We are not told what caused Laius to go to Delphi on what proved to be his
last journey. At Eur. Phoen. 35–7 Laius consults Apollo about whether the exposed
child had died. We do not know why he went to Delphi in Aeschylus’ trilogy.18 The
exact means by which Apollo arranged that he was travelling from Thebes toward
Delphi at the same time Oedipus was travelling in the other direction are thus left
unspecified. That it was Apollo’s doing would nevertheless seem plausible to the
audience since the text shows the other participant in this meeting being sent to it by
the god. (5) At the beginning of the play Creon returns from Delphi with Apollo’s
answer to their query: to cure the plague the Thebans need to find the killer of Laius.
This sets the whole investigation in train and suggests that Apollo not only wished
Oedipus to commit the acts he predicted but also wished them to be discovered. (6)
The audience might have regarded the death of Polybus some days earlier than the day
of the play as the work of Apollo. The Corinthian at 961 says that small things may
bring about an old man’s death, and Apollo might have supplied the ‘small downturn’
that caused his death. If it happened of its own, there was time to engineer the plague.
That leaves the Sphinx and the plague. Nothing explicitly ties the Sphinx to Apollo.
As for the plague, the timing of its arrival, years after the death that supposedly caused
it, does not suggest the automatic operation of some kind of taint but the deliberate
action of a divinity. And anyone familiar with the first book of the Iliad knows that
Apollo can cause plague. In view of the number of events where Apollo is plausibly
seen to be at work, any audience member who thought about it might have concluded
that the god was either sole or joint cause of these two supernatural events. Euripides,
who was known in antiquity for his ϲαφήνεια, usually spells out any divine causation.19
Sophocles is often less explicit.
It would not be overly daring to conclude that none of the apparent coincidences on
which the plot of the play hinges is really a matter of chance. It will be recalled that
when she learns of Polybus’ death Jocasta concludes (977–8) that human life is ruled
by chance and no foreknowledge is possible. Her being proved wrong in thinking
that Polybus’ death refutes the idea of oracular truth does not prove that there is no
coincidence in the play. But it does suggest it.
Thomas Hardy wrote a sonnet called ‘Hap’, whose burden is that, while it is terrible
to suffer at the hands of a malignant divinity, it is in some ways worse to be the victim of
blind chance. I have the feeling that Sophocles would have agreed.
18
Finglass (n. 3), 33 discusses this question. As he says, nothing in OT connects the journey with
the threat posed by the Sphinx, but I do not feel that this possibility can be lightly eliminated.
19
Thus in Ion Hermes in the prologue spells out Apollo’s paternity, his sending of the baby Ion to
Delphi, his being raised by the Pythia owing to her god-inspired pity for him, and the Apollo-caused
childlessness of Creusa and Xuthus. Athena at the play’s end adds further explanation. Sometimes,
however, Euripides omits an explanation. In IT, for example, Athena at the end does not spell out
that the fit that seizes Orestes, causing his capture and bringing him face-to-face with his sister,
was the work of Apollo. (There is, however, a possibility that Orestes did so in the lacuna editors
mark after 1014: see the supplement in the Loeb edition.) The audience would probably have
concluded, if they thought about it, that the god’s hand was at work.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
O N N OT M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G O E D I P U S T Y R A N N O S
115
IF APOLLO RUINED OEDIPUS, WHY DID HE DO SO? AND WHY DOES NO
ONE EXPLAIN?
I have argued that the words of Teiresias (376–7), Jocasta (721–3), the Palace Servant
(1258–62) and Oedipus (787–97, 1329–33) are evidence that the audience are meant to
see Apollo as an active agent in the destruction of Oedipus both before the play began
and during its course. But we may still be puzzled when we consider that, when the truth
is known, Oedipus does not ask, nor does anyone venture to answer, the question why
the god ruined him. Parker20 notes that ‘the stricken Oedipus barely complains against
the gods, much though moderns have complained on his behalf’. But the whole thrust of
Parker’s article is that Sophocles is much less forthcoming about the gods (whose
workings the audience see ‘through a glass darkly’) than we might expect him to be.
The gods, when they appear, are ‘economical as to what they can or will reveal’, and
even when we take manteis and other authoritative figures into account, our attempts
to trace the gods’ justice are frustrated by the spareness of what we are told.
Parker devotes several pages (19–25) to the topic of theodicy in Sophocles. He notes
that the appearance of Heracles at the end of Philoctetes effaces ‘the impression of
divine indifference to human deserts’. In discussing the painful death of Heracles in
Trachiniae and the accusations it calls forth of Zeus’s indifference to the fate of his
son, he notes that Hyllus’ oblique hint at 1270 that the future may hold something
different for Heracles holds out hope that the justice of Zeus may be vindicated.21 He
indicates that the fate of Antigone has been regarded as posing ‘the acutest problem
of theodicy in all Sophocles’, but he lays more emphasis on the just punishment of
Creon than on the unjust death of Antigone.
As regards our play he says that the topic of theodicy would be ‘much more urgent’
(24) if Oedipus had made at 1329–32 (the ‘It was Apollo’ passage) the complaint he
utters (before the truth is known) at 813–29. But he does not explain why he thinks
that the question of divine justice is meant to have less urgency in this play. Possibly
it is no less urgent than in Trachiniae, but the poet is content, here as there, to remind
his audience, by means of slight hints, of what they know from elsewhere, leaving this
knowledge to do the work of explicit explanation by gods or their accredited spokesmen.
In fact, there are two hints that explain why Apollo acts as he does. Both connect
what befalls Oedipus with Apollo’s attempt to bring the line of Laius to an end. The
first is at 711–14, where Jocasta reports the oracle given to Laius.
χρηϲμὸϲ γὰρ ἦλθε Λαΐωι ποτ’, οὐκ ἐρῶ
Φοίβου γ’ ἀπ’ αὐτοῦ, τῶν δ’ ὑπηρετῶν ἄπο,
ὡϲ αὐτὸν ἥξοι μοῖρα πρὸϲ παιδὸϲ θανεῖν,
ὅϲτιϲ γένοιτ’ ἐμοῦ τε κἀκείνου πάρα.22
These lines mean that Laius was warned not to have a child with Jocasta. The inclusion
of his wife in the oracle means that what is envisaged is a legitimate heir: it is only
having such an heir to carry on his line that will have terrible consequences. A similar
20
Parker (n. 8), 24.
Parker (n. 8), 24 further suggests that Heracles’ sack of Oechalia, which he justified by a
fabricated excuse but actually committed out of a lust for Iole, may be an item supporting an ‘implicit
theodicy’.
22
‘An oracle once came to Laius—I will not say it was from Phoebus himself, but from his
servants—that it would be his destiny to die at the hands of any child that was born to me and him.’
21
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
116
D AV I D KOVAC S
version of the myth is visible in the oracle reported in Aeschylus’ Seven against Thebes.
There Apollo wants the Theban royal line to come to an end and so threatens Laius with
terrible consequences if he has an heir. We also have the claim of Eteocles (690–1), as
he goes off to meet his brother, that Apollo hates the race of Laius. We may conclude
that the consequences with which Laius is threatened are an inducement for him to bring
his dynasty to an end. Thus in both Aeschylus and Sophocles Apollo’s animus is
directed against Laius, not against Oedipus,23 who is hated only because he is Laius’
son and whose destruction is merely the result of Apollo’s making good on his threat.24
If this hint is to be evaluated as above, however, it is necessary to clear out of the way
an error that began at the end of the nineteenth century and is still being perpetuated into
the twenty-first. In an 1899 article Wilamowitz makes the claim that in Aeschylus and
Euripides the oracle to Laius is conditional and Laius can avoid the result if he simply
declines to have a child; whereas in Sophocles it is unconditional.25 If this were true, it
would mean that the oracle does not serve the purpose of encouraging Laius to die
without an heir: he could not be deterred from propagating his line by a prediction
that something bad would happen to him whatever he did. But Wilamowitz is mistaken:
his interpretation misconstrues the Greek of the only relevant passage, 711–14, quoted
above. The lines predict that any son born of Laius and Jocasta will commit parricide,
not that such a child will in fact be born. The optative γένοιτο is aorist, part of a
generalizing relative clause, not future, which a categorical prediction would require.26
23
Apollo, as we have seen, causes Oedipus to blind himself, which was not part of the prediction to
Laius. Does this indicate hostility to Oedipus himself? Perhaps it does, but this might be hostility
caused by his casting Teiresias’ blindness in his teeth. It is fitting that such an insult should be repaid
by a literal blindness that reflects Oedipus’ earlier inability to see the truth.
24
If we had the other two tragedies that accompanied Seven against Thebes we would presumably
know the reason for Apollo’s hostility. H. Lloyd-Jones, The Justice of Zeus (Berkeley and Los
Angeles, 19832), 120–2 thinks that Laius’ sin was his abduction of Chrysippus. This would have
brought on the punishment of the gods (in particular, it was a crime against Laius’ host). But since
we have no evidence clearly earlier that Euripides’ Chrysippus for the story, this is merely a plausible
guess. (A scholium on Eur. Phoen. 1760 cites a certain Pisander for this and other details of Theban
myth, but we do not know whether this is the early epic poet or someone much later.) As regards OT
there is a tantalizing hint in our only glimpse of Laius. Oedipus’ description of his behaviour at the
crossroads (804–9) reveals someone given to treating others with contempt (what Athenian law called
ὕβριϲ). This suggests that his sin lay in this area rather than in lust: cf. Trach. 280.
25
U. von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, ‘Excurse zum Oedipus des Sophokles’, Hermes 34 (1899),
55–80, at 55. The claim is repeated by Dodds (n. 2), 41. That Wilamowitz was in error was pointed
out by G. Perrotta, Sofocle (Messina and Florence, 1935), 203, and Lloyd-Jones (n. 24), 119–20, and
indeed he was rebutted in advance by Jebb in 1893. But we find it repeated by C. Segal, Oedipus
Tyrannus: Tragic Heroism and the Limits of Knowledge (New York, 1993), 28; Griffith (n. 11), 53
and n. 87; and (in the present century) Lurje (n. 4), 392; A.F. Garvie, The Plays of Sophocles
(London, 2005), 50; and F. Macintosh, Sophocles: Oedipus Tyrannus (Cambridge, 2009),
5. Cf. Scodel (n. 16), 6, who calls the oracle to Laius in Aeschylus a warning but that in
Sophocles ‘a neutral statement of fact’.
26
The grammar is correctly explained by J. Rusten, Sophocles: Oidipous Tyrannos (Bryn Mawr,
1990) and J.C. Kamerbeek, The Plays of Sophocles, Part IV: The Oedipus Tyrannus (Leiden,
1967): in historical-sequence oratio obliqua, generalizing subjunctives with ἄν are changed to
optatives without ἄν. The lines are correctly translated (‘his destiny would be to perish by the
hand of any child that would be born to him and me’) by R. Blondell, Sophocles’ King Oidipous
(Newburyport, Mass., 2002) and by Lawrence (n. 11), 3, but mistranslated in U. von
Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Griechische Tragödien Übersetzt I (Berlin, 1899); D. Grene, ‘Oedipus
the King’, in D. Grene and R. Lattimore, Sophocles I (Chicago, 1954) and still in the third edition
revised by M. Griffith and G.W. Most (Chicago and London, 2013); P. Mazon, Sophocle II (Paris,
1958); S. Berg and D. Clay, Sophocles: Oedipus the King (New York, 1978); Meineck and
Woodruff (n. 15); Taplin (n. 12) and many others.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
O N N OT M I S U N D E R S TA N D I N G O E D I P U S T Y R A N N O S
117
‘Any child born (ὅϲτιϲ γένοιτ’) of Laius and Jocasta will kill his father, etc.’ is merely
another way of saying ‘If a child is born to Laius and Jocasta, he will kill his father,
etc.’.27 The Sophoclean version, like the versions of Aeschylus and Euripides, leaves
Laius the option of having no heir.28
Once this mistake is corrected, it becomes clear that in all three tragic poets the
motive for the oracle is the same. There are in fact two motives. First, as already
noted, the prediction means that any child so born will be exposed and grow up in ignorance of his parents and thus capable of being tricked into committing these two crimes.
But a prior motive is hostility to Laius. In Aeschylus’ Seven against Thebes Eteocles
says that Apollo hates the race of Laius, that he wants to bring his dynasty to an end.
And so, if Laius because of the oracle had voluntarily had no children by Jocasta,
Apollo’s purpose would have been fulfilled. But in fact he does father a son, and the
son too begets children, so it is only in the third generation that the wiping out of
Laius’ line is accomplished in the mutual slaughter of Eteocles and Polynices.
The second hint is to be found near the end of the play at 1455–7:
καίτοι τοϲοῦτόν γ’ οἶδα, μήτε μ’ ἂν νόϲον
μήτ’ ἄλλο πέρϲαι μηδέν· οὐ γὰρ ἄν ποτε
θνήιϲκων ἐϲώθην, μὴ ’πί τωι δεινῶι κακῶι.
Oedipus has asked to be sent to Cithaeron, the place where his parents intended that he
should die, so that at long last their purpose might be fulfilled. ‘And yet’, he says, ‘this
much I know, that no sickness or any other thing will kill me. For I would not have been
preserved from death when I was perishing [that is, when I was to be exposed] if not for
some dreadful trouble (μὴ ’πί τωι δεινῶι κακῶι).’ We must regard it as certain that ἂν
… πέρϲαι (1455–6) refers to the future, since the surrounding lines refer to what will
happen to Oedipus; and that ἐπί τωι δεινῶι κακῶι also refers to something in the future.
It is, however, extremely unlikely that he is referring to sufferings of his own in the
future, for in that case he would be implying that his past sufferings were not a
δεινὸν κακόν. And indeed the man who has already suffered the utmost in woes
(1204–6, 1282–5, 1340–6, 1365–6) has no reason to think that another woe (and this
time a dreadful one!) still lies in his future. What is most likely is that ἐπί τωι δεινῶι
κακῶι means ‘for some terrible mischief’, that is, to cause it.29 This would be of a
27
There is no contradiction between this passage, construed as above, and 853–4, where no condition is mentioned, because the child in question is one already born, which means that the condition
has been fulfilled.
28
Finglass (n. 3), on 711–14, after agreeing with me that grammar ‘formally rules out’
Wilamowitz’s view, worries that no emphasis is placed on the conditionality of the oracle either by
grammar (there is only a single verb form to refute Wilamowitz) or context (nowhere is the possibility
raised that Laius could have avoided having children nor is there mention of a sin against Apollo). But
no emphasis is needed. Neither Sophocles nor his audience was aware of Wilamowtiz’s mistaken
view, and the poet had no need, when presenting the only version of the myth that extant tragedy
knows, to go out of his way to differentiate it carefully from a version no one would think of until
1899. All that is needed is a statement of the oracle that is consistent with the usual version (as
Sophocles’ is with γένοιτο). Siring a child need not involve a sin against Apollo if, as seems likely
for our play, the god issued a hypothetical imperative (‘If you wish to avoid death at your son’s hands,
do not procreate’) and not a categorical one. (But though Finglass [n. 3], on 1183–5 could be right in
asserting that Laius did not sin against Apollo, the fact that Sophocles has not emphasized this sin is
not proof positive in light of Sophocles’ reticences.)
29
This is the view of the prepositional phrase argued for in my ‘Do we have the end of Sophocles’
Oedipus Tyrannus?’, JHS 129 (2009), 66–8. A.H. Sommerstein, ‘Once more the end of Sophocles’
Oedipus Tyrannus’, JHS 131 (2011), 85–93, at 85 indicates his agreement. Finglass (n. 3) sees this
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533
118
D AV I D KOVAC S
piece with numerous other uses of ἐπί in this causative sense (see Ellendt’s Lexicon
Sophocleum, rev. H. Genthe [Berlin, 18722], 260 col. 2). What lies in the future for
Oedipus is precisely such an effect on others. He will curse his sons to divide their
inheritance with the sword, and the result will be the War of the Seven, one of the
two cataclysmic events that, according to Hesiod (Op. 161–5), brought to an end the
age of heroes (the other was the war at Troy). This will indeed be a δεινὸν κακόν.30
The hint here is borne out by what immediately follows: he tells Creon not to worry
about his sons, who will find a living wherever they are, which looks like an unconscious adumbration of Polynices’ living in Argos (his departure for Argos is mentioned
at the end of Stesichorus, fr. 97 F.). Then he mentions the pleasant table fellowship he
enjoys with his daughters. This would remind the audience of the unpleasant table
fellowship he had with his sons, who in the epic tradition angered their father by serving
him an inferior cut of meat and by using a table and a goblet he had forbidden them
to use.31
In Aeschylus this cursing of the sons is the final act in the extermination of Laius’
offspring. So this hint, like the hint implicit in the oracle, is about the destruction of
Laius’ line. Given Sophocles’ general reticence about the gods and their purposes,
this is perhaps enough to explain what Apollo is trying to do. The inexplicit way in
which it is handled is quite in Sophocles’ manner.
University of Virginia
DAVID KOVACS
[email protected]
as a meaning the audience will have heard, but thinks that Oedipus himself means his own future
sufferings. He does not say why it would be natural for a man who has already experienced the
ultimate in suffering to think that a δεινὸν κακόν lies in his future.
30
If we had no context, we might interpret μήτε μ’ ἂν νόϲον μήτ’ ἄλλο πέρϲαι μηδέν to mean that
Oedipus will not die at all, which would be an anticipation of what happens to him in Oedipus
Coloneus. But in view of the following explanatory sentence it seems better to paraphrase ‘I have
a strong intimation that nothing will kill me, for I am certain that I am destined to cause a dreadful
mischief. My life will be spared until I do that.’ (Oedipus does not say that nothing will kill him
on Cithaeron, since, on the view put forward here, he will not go to Cithaeron until he has cursed
his sons. After that, there is nothing to prevent his death.)
31
See Thebais, frr. 2–3 in M.L. West, Greek Epic Fragments from the Seventh to the Fifth
Centuries B.C. (Cambridge, Mass. and London, 2003), 44–7.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Virginia Libraries, on 26 Nov 2019 at 22:38:49, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838819000533